Corps-Sujet, The Lived Body Is Not A Functional Machine That Elicits An Appropri
Corps-Sujet, The Lived Body Is Not A Functional Machine That Elicits An Appropri
Corps-Sujet, The Lived Body Is Not A Functional Machine That Elicits An Appropri
E M B O D I M E N T A N D E X I S T E N C E : M E R L E AU - P O N T Y
A N D T H E L I M I T S O F N AT U R A L I S M
ABSTRACT
93
A-T. Tymieniecka (ed.), Analecta Husserliana CIV, 93–104.
© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2009
94 P E T E R R E Y NA E RT
N AT U R A L I S M
EXAMPLE: PERCEPTION
T H E B O DY A N D T H E S Y M B O L I C F U N C T I O N
and more precisely kinaesthesia, the sensation of movement. Only the combi-
nation of kinaesthetic and tactile sensations, whereby as Husserl showed the
second kind of sensation is motivated by the first, generates this perception
of the rectangular form. One can generalize this finding into the principle: No
perception without movement.
The idea that the perceiver is an embodied subject governing over her body
as a freely moveable organ of perception was first formulated by Husserl.
(Husserl, Hua I, p. 128; Hua IV, p. 145; Hua VI, pp. 220–221) Merleau-Ponty’s
phenomenology of perception can be considered as a further development of
this analysis of embodied existence. To be embodied means to situate one-
self in a specific environment, to engage in a particular situation. The world
is for instance visible, can be manipulated etcetera, because I am embodied.
Perception has its origin in the vital bond between the perceiver, his body and
the world. I perceive, I am sensitive to colours and other sensible qualities,
because my body has an original pact with empirical reality. Sensation is a
natural co-existence and communion with this reality. (communion, connatu-
ralité, Merleau-Ponty, 1945, p. 370) This follows from my bodily constitution.
Consequently, my natural affinity with the world has to be understood as an
impersonal, anonymous pact (on perçoit). Perception is not the result of a con-
scious, intentional act, but is naturally mine. The perceiving “corps-sujet” is
a natural self (moi naturel, Merleau-Ponty, 1945, p. 250). Sensibility occurs
in the margin of my personal live, since I’ve always been an embodied self
that sides with the world. Vision is a capacity that is naturally directed at,
attuned to a visual field. My organism is originally a pre-personal belonging
to the world; it is anonymous and exists in an impersonal mode. (l’anonymat
de notre corps, Merleau-Ponty, 1945, p. 101) Merleau-Ponty calls this kind of
embodiment the normal, habitual or customary body, and he distinguishes it
from the actual body a person lives. A person who suffers phantom-pain in an
amputated limb neglects this amputation, and returns to the habitual body. The
person refuses to acknowledge the actuality of the mutilated body. According
to Merleau-Ponty, this is neither a conscious nor an unconscious mental act.
But this pain can’t have a simple physiological explanation either, since the
physical cause is literally absent. In the case of the lived body, we are con-
fronted with a third term, the so-called existential attitude, which supersedes
the dichotomy of the physical and the psychical. “To refuse the mutilation is
an attitude of our existence.” (Merleau-Ponty, 1945, p. 102)
This lived body is not experienced as an object, nor does it simply function
as a cause of sensations. Psychology elucidates bodily experience in terms of
a body schema, which means that we have at every moment a global, prac-
tical and implicit notion of our proper body, of its posture and its relation to
other objects. My body appears as an attitude towards the world, in relation
EMBODIMENT AND EXISTENCE 99
of the moving body, one also presumes that different, complementary perspec-
tives of the same object are possible. From my own point of view, I am present
in and to the world which is the horizon of my perception, and which as such
founds my particular perspective of it. It wouldn’t make sense to speak of my
particular view on the world, if this completed world weren’t implied by my
proper perspective. (Merleau-Ponty, 1945, p. 380) So situated perception and
particular point of view mutually co-found each other. The totally given object
correlates with my movement, and the specific position I have at this moment
can only be identified as a particular view of the object when it is presumed to
be more than the object of this actual perspective. The natural world is the hori-
zon of all horizons. To perceive means to engage in the present a multitude of
future possible perceptions, which the future cannot guarantee. In this respect,
one must understand the object as the target of a bodily teleology. (Merleau-
Ponty, 1945, p. 373) It is the correlate of a practical and horizon-like synthesis.
(Merleau-Ponty, 1945, p. 376)
Temporality is the original essence of being embodied. Time does not
belong to the objective world, because past and future do not exist (any-
more or not yet). They are both a dimension of our subjective presence in
the world. Merleau-Ponty underlines the priority of the present wherein past
and future appears. He refers to Husserl’s analysis of internal time conscious-
ness, who understands retention and protention as the conscious modes of past
and future, to illustrate this embeddednes of past and future in the present.
Time consciousness is a condition of possibility of the subject’s life. Time
is in that sense a transcendentale. Perception for instance is only possible
when the perceptual presence of the perceived object is sustained by a past
and directed at a future. Embodied existence is this openness towards other
temporal dimensions, which emanate from the present, but also give it its sig-
nification as now. A momentary snapshot of a perceived object is necessarily
integrated in a series of experiences which are directed at a presumptively
future appearing object that confirms the past experiences of it. So embod-
ied perception presupposes temporality, this mode of existence is necessarily
temporal. (Merleau-Ponty, 1945, p. 483) Temporality is openness, and pre-
cisely this characteristic founds meaning and significance. The significance
of the perceived object is precisely that it is only one aspect of a complete
object, which appears as goal at the horizon of perception. This sense-giving
openness, which coincides with temporality, is the functioning intentionality,
another name for embodied existence.
The object is more than the correlate of an actual perception, because it is
also perceived as really transcending embodied perception. It appears as exist-
ing in the world, which presupposes a completed synthesis, which is actually
EMBODIMENT AND EXISTENCE 103
REFERENCES
Gallagher, Shaun and Zahavi, Dan, The Phenomenological Mind (London: Routledge, 2008)
Hurley Susan, Consciousness in Action (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1998)
Husserl, Edmund, Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philoso-
phie. Zweites Buch: Phänomenologische Untersuchungen zur Konstitution. Ed. M. Biemel,
Husserliana vol. 4 (Den Haag, Martinus Nijhoff, 1952)
Husserl, Edmund, Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie.
Drittes Buch: Die Phänomenologie und die Fundamente der Wissenschaften. Ed. M. Biemel,
Husserliana vol. 5 (Den Haag, Martinus Nijhoff, 1953)
Husserl, Edmund, Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale
Phänomenologie. Eine Einleitung in die phänomenologische Philosophie. Ed. W. Biemel,
Husserliana vol. 6 (Den Haag, Martinus Nijhoff, 1954)
Husserl, Edmund, Phänomenologische Psychologie. Vorlesungen Sommersemester 1925. Ed.
W. Biemel, Husserliana vol. 9 (Den Haag, Martinus Nijhoff, 1962)
Husserl, Edmund, Zur Phänomenologie der Intersuhjektivitüt. Texte aus dem Nachlaß. Erster Teil:
1905–1920. Ed. I. Kern, Husserliana vol. 13 (Den Haag, Martinus Nijhoff, 1973)
Kanizsa, Gaetano, “Margini quasi-percettivi in campi con stimolazione omogenea,” Rivista di
Psicologia 49:1, (1955), pp. 7–30.
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, Phénoménologie de la Perception (Paris: Gallimard, 1945)
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, Signes (Paris: Gallimard, 1960)
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, La Prose du Monde (Paris: Gallimard, 1969)
Noë, Alva, Action in Perception (Cambridge MA: MIT Press, 2004)