Voegelin On Hegel's Sorcery

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 35
At a glance
Powered by AI
The document discusses the critiques and influences of Strauss, Voegelin and Arendt on American political thought. The three emigres critically analyzed modern culture and social sciences in America.

Strauss, Voegelin and Arendt were critical of the neutral, value-free approach of social sciences in America. They argued that it imposed a moral/political vocabulary and obscured the human condition through lack of plurality.

Voegelin believed that postwar academic disciplines in the US were influenced by German intellectuals who brought modernist, bankrupt ideas. He also criticized the 'influx of functional illiterates' in academic positions in the 1950s-60s.

Interwar German-Speaking Emigres

and American Political Thought:


Strauss, Voegelin, and Arendt

Peter Graf Kielmansegg, Horst Mewes, and Elisabeth Glaser-


Schmitt (eds.), Hannah Arendt and Leo Strauss: German Emigres
and American Political Thought After World War II (New York:
Cambridge University Press, 1995) 208 pages. (Referred to as
GE)
Ted V. McAllister, Revolt Against Modernity: Leo Strauss, Eric
Voegelin, and the Search for a Postliberal Order (Lawrence:
University Press of Kansas, 1996) 323 pages. (Referred to as
RAM)

odern intellectual traditions associated with the Enlighten-


M ment project have become self-undermining, thus leading to
a loss of a widely shared orientation in nature, politics, and history.
Contemporary Western culture may very well be without sufficient
cognitive resources for the achievement of personal integrity and
political order. Can we foster and secure public life in a post-
Enlightenment and post-traditional culture?
Three great interwar German-speaking emigres-Leo Strauss,
Eric Voegelin and Hannah Arendt-have brilliantly and durably
influenced American political thought and have sought a way out of
the modern predicament. The two books under review demonstrate
that Strauss, Voegelin, and Arendt as peregrine furthered pro-
found-yet quite different-interpretations of the American politi-
cal experience. Their flight from National Socialism brought with
them distinctive cognitive resources which led them to critique
American political science and political practice as well as to offer
philosophic alternatives to the self-undermining movements of
contemporary individualism, materialism, and scientism. These
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 297

peregrini were not flatterers of the American regime; they were


friendly critics. They would become especially severe critics of
American social science, viewing this discipline's ambition as impos-
ing upon human beings a moral, political, and social vocabulary
completely neutral in tone. The state of American social science is
emblematic of the crisis of modernity in that we have lost faith in
reason's ability to validate our highest aims.
For Eric Voegelin, postwar academic disciplines in the United
States were strongly influenced by "German intellectuals who
emigrated to America" bringing with them neo-Hegelian "ideolo-
gies, methodologies...phenomenologies, hermeneutic profundities,
and so on." This migration coincided with the "populist expansion of
the universities, accompanied by the inevitable inrush of functional
illiterates into academic positions in the 1950's and 60's." For
Voegelin, the social sciences and the humanities in America have
produced an intellectual climate that is centered on imported
modernist ideas that are bankrupt and derivative of European
versions of those ideas debated at the turn of the century. "Today,"
states Voegelin, "the academic world is plagued with figures who
could not have gained public attention in the environment of the
Weimar Republic."'
For Arendt, the "prediction and control" talk in political science
is a dark comedy, both foolish and frightening. Until we are made
predictable and controllable, human action cannot be predicted or
controlled. Arendt claims quite directly that facts fail to determine
the laws that explain them:
The perplexity is that the particular incident, the observable
fact or single occurrence of nature, or the reported deed and
event of history, have ceased to make sense without a universal
process in which they are supposedly embedded; yet the
moment man approaches this process in order to escape the
haphazard character of the particular, in order to find meaning,
order and necessity, his effort is rebutted by the answer from
all sides: any order, any necessity, any meaning you wish to
impose will do.
298 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER

Social science theories in the United States "cancel each other


out," and this is so "because they can all be consistently proved."
Because history does not precisely repeat itself, no controlled
experiments are possible. The difficulty lies directly with the plural-
ity of the human condition; plurality is irreducible given the many
versions of historical truth and the "unprecedented" events of each
era.' American social science in the 1950s and 1960s, like older
metaphysical systems, tended to obscure the human capacity to
break with the past and develop something new. As David Luban
puts it, "Arendt finds such a view of social science silly, misguided,
and dangerous."3
For Strauss, American behavioral science is oblivious to the
nihilism at its heart. In the insouciant world of the political science
profession, political scientists were fiddling while Rome (American
liberal democracy) was burning. The dominance of positivism,
historicism, and dogmatic atheism within the political science pro-
fession creates a dilemma for most of its members. While they
remain liberal, they do so despite the apparent inconsistency be-
tween their value neutrality and their liberal convictions. Strauss
argued that although value neutrality implies "that before the
tribunal of reason all values are equal," most modem liberal political
scientists assume that "the rational society will be egalitarian or
democratic and permissive or liberal: the rational doctrine regard-
ing the difference between facts and values rationally justifies the
preference for liberal democracy-contrary to what is indicated by
the distinction itself." 4 The feckless modem political scientist has no
criterion for distinguishing specious from genuine claims upon
political sympathy because the fact-value distinction subjects such
persons to the kind of moral suasion which consists of little more
than direct appeals to sympathetic emotions. The political science
profession contributes to a public discourse that is unable to say no
by appeal to high principle and appreciate that any political order
must establish a hierarchy of values that represses some values so
that others may flourish.
Strauss was critical of the seeming refutation of biblical faith
which pervades the modem political science profession. Most in the
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 299

profession have rested their political teachings on a "dogmatic


exclusion" of the possibilities of biblical faith and an unreflective
assumption that social life does not require belief in, and worship of,
God or gods.
Given the above characterizations of the dominant
"progressionist" wing of American social science by our three
emigres, we can certainly appreciate why they have exercised very
little influence on the practice of political science. Though Strauss,
Voegelin, and Arendt have different philosophical positions them-
selves, they all present methods and inquiries that separate them
from the "mainstream" practitioners of the profession. They are a
clear example of the enormous chasm that still exists between the
practitioners of political philosophy and the practitioners of political
science in the American regime. What accounts for the extraordi-
nary influence of these three peregrini in furthering distinctive
interpretations of American political philosophy while being thor-
oughly rejected by the behaviorists and radical historicists?
Hannah Arendt and Leo Strauss: German Emigres and Ameri-
can Political Thought After World War II (GE) seeks to link the
German-Jewish emigration after 1933 and the development of
political philosophy in the United States as a single topic. The book
is based on a conference at the University of Colorado exploring
Arendt's and Strauss's intellectual citizenship of two worlds-
belonging fully to neither.

I.
Focusing first on GE, I intend to explore at length Jurgen Gebhardt's
outstanding chapter, "Leo Strauss: The Quest for Truth." Gebhardt,
a non-Straussian, demonstrates both an acute textual analysis of and
an irenic openness to the challenge of Strauss's scholarship. He
begins his study of Strauss as an emigre scholar with John G.
Gunnell's critical account of the original intentions of Strauss,
Voegelin, and Arendt to bring with them to the United States the
"myth of the tradition"-a "Europeanized theory in the United
States." Political theory, for them, was "a response to a crisis, as a
diagnosis of disorder and a critique of contemporary politics...a
300 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER

search for a truth of political order and human nature, and...the


construction of a vision of a new political society." The idea of
political theory became institutionalized, academic, and depart-
mentalized (GE, 82). The academic activity of political theory
alienated itself from political science and politics, becoming a
curiosity in the academic world. Gebhardt agrees with Gunnell that
Leo Strauss's project of a philosophical inquiry into politics, though
well-organized with a routinized system of teaching and research-
ing, is "apparently lost" on the professional practitioner of political
science. Gebhardt is also sympathetic to Harry V. Jaffa's criticism of
Strauss's former students for hailing the establishment of an award
honoring Leo Strauss by the American Political Science Association
"for the recognition it has given to political philosophy ` as one of the
important traditions within the discipline.- For Jaffa, this language
is absurd in the implication that political philosophy was "one of
many" subdivisions or branches of political science. For Jaffa,
political philosophy as practiced by Strauss is to guide all other
practical sciences-it is the very foundation of the science of politics,
not a designated sub-field. Jaffa, as one of Strauss's early students at
the New School for Social Research, doubts whether political
philosophy should be reconciled with the institutional realities and
the practice of professional political science at all (GE, 84).
Gebhardt is convinced that Strauss does represent a "European-
ized political theory in the United States" emphasizing the enduring
crisis of the West. The persistence of the crisis required that the
quest for truth be continued even if it does not promise answers and
solutions; such a quest does bring humanizing qualities that make up
the good life. Gebhardt quite correctly presents Strauss as obliged
to ask persistently the question untouched by the modern sciences,
namely how should human beings live because "modern western
man no longer knows what he wants" and "he no longer believes that
he can know what is good and bad, what is right and wrong" (GE, 87).
For Strauss, as for Jaffa, political philosophy correctly understood is
not to be considered an "academic pursuit," but should be viewed
as a cultural enterprise concerned with the principles of societal
order. According to Gebhardt, then, Strauss's project assumes "that
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 301

sociocultural crises and the ensuing social problems are rooted in the
intellectual and spiritual life of society" (GE, 87). Gebhardt views
Strauss's quest for truth within the context of Strauss's specific
cultural interpretation of the modern crisis-a "notion, of the
cultural crisis [which] was characteristic of the German intellectual
community, the `mandarin intellectuals. - Fritz Ringer defines
them, in terms of an ideal type, the German cultural and social elite
which owes its status primarily to educational qualifications, rather
than to the hereditary rights or wealth (GE, 87-88). They were
guided by the concepts of Wissenschaft and Bildung, which pre-
sented higher learning in terms of the quest for truth and self-
cultivation and the development of a university-trained cultural
elite. Gebhardt maintains that Strauss's personal style and intellec-
tual perspective "reflect the habitudes and the intellectual vision of
the German mandarins" ( GE, 88). Although Strauss began his
scholarly life at Jewish institutes in Germany outside of the univer-
sity, his style in which he later taught in the United States, the way
he asserted his authority and his notion of spiritual elevation
achieved through learning, had a great deal in common with the
German mandarins. Alfons Sollner presents Strauss as a very Ger-
man figure, "a charismatic representative of Teutonic learnedness,"
a representative of the nineteenth-century German tradition of a
highly elevated aristocracy of scholars of imperious manner (GE, 6).
Whether Strauss truly fits this model can be answered only by the
few who knew him well.
Gebhardt is convinced that much of the controversy that sur-
rounded Strauss and his students had to do with the exotic, German
mandarin flavor of his work, which "was met with enthusiasm as well
as disgust" ( GE, 89).
What, according to Gebhardt, is the greatness or distinctiveness
of Strauss's learning? It centers on "the problem of the true philoso-
pher," as Gebhardt puts it. Once Strauss contemplates a return to
pre-modern philosophy, "a new understanding of philosophizing
under modem conditions comes into sight: the ascent from the
second unnatural cave of the modern worldview to the primary
natural cave of the City by means of historical learning" (GE, 96).
302 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER

Gebhardt, in support of this view, quotes from a generally unknown


early review by Strauss in the Deutsche Literaturzeitung, no. 52,
(December 27, 1931):
Bearing in mind the classic representation of the natural
differences involved in philosophizing, in other words, the
Platonic allegory of the cave, one can say that today we are in
a second much deeper cave than the fortunate ignorant per-
sons with which Socrates was concerned. We need history first
of all to reach the cave from which Socrates can lead us to the
light. We need preparatory instruction-something the Greeks
didn't need-that is, precisely learning by reading ( GE, 96).
The problem of the true philosopher becomes centered on the
return to premodern rationalism, with the reopening of the quarrel
between the ancients and the moderns and the discovery of the
potential of philosophy, that is Platonic philosophy, found in medi-
eval Islamic and Jewish rationalism. The medieval Muslim, Farabi,
becomes Strauss's exemplary model of a true Platonist-he is not
concerned with the historical (accidental truth); he is primarily
interested in the philosophic (essential) truth. Gebhardt quotes
Strauss stating, "only because public speech demands a mixture of
seriousness and playfulness, can a true Platonist present the serious
teaching in a historical, and hence, playful garb" (GE, 97). To qualify
as a true Platonist, one must meet a decisive criterion in that there
exists "his private, and truly original and individual understanding of
the necessary anonymous truth" (GE, 97). Is this a self-description
of Strauss? For Gebhardt this might be part of the truth of what
Strauss was about. Strauss's self-characterization of his vocation was
that of scholar who leads us back to our natural ignorance of the
common-sense world, and "who retrieves us from the lapsed world
of modern rationalism, from the `second unnatural' cave" (GE, 97).
We must gain a reading knowledge of the languages used by the
great minds in order to be able to listen to them. The scholar
prepares the way to philosophizing. Strauss prepares the way for
true historical reflection-a nonhistoricist approach to understand-
ing the great thinkers of the past in order to overcome the limitations
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 303

of modernity. Modernity cannot be overcome by modern means or


subjectivism. The instruments of natural reason have, to some
extent, been lost, and we have to learn them from the ancients.
Historical objectivity brings about a profound intellectual change in
the scholar himself. Once the scholar has led us from the second,
"unnatural" cave to the cave of natural understanding, the philoso-
pher can take over.
Gebhardt views Strauss as a critic of the modern world (the
second, unnatural cave) where there is no seriousness or morality-
a world of divertissement ( GE, 102). It is a world where humans
abdicate their humanity and the quest for the right, the good, and the
just. True philosophizing involves the restitution of the political-
the strict separation of philosophy and social opinion-which is the
precarious balance between the few persons who are able to pursue
the philosophical life and the many people leading a life of the
normal citizen. Though philosophy ultimately transcends political
opinion and is transhistorical and transpolitical, it presupposes the
political ( GE, 103). Gebhardt appropriately emphasizes Strauss's
most significant teaching, that only when modern man becomes
aware of his habitation in the second, unnatural cave and the self-
destructive power of modern rationalism can a way be paved for
reinstating the City. An ennobled liberal democracy is Strauss's best
possible regime under present circumstances. The best regime is
dependent on the city-state-the polls interpreted by Plato and
Aristotle which is surveyable, urban, moral, serious, based on
agriculture, in which the gentry rule. For Strauss this "is morally-
politically the most reasonable and most pleasing" (GE, 104). These
political teachings of Strauss, the Jewish German-American manda-
rin and emigre, are an exotic and fascinating plant indeed trans-
planted to an American soil, which can be referred to as "applied
Enlightenment" in crisis.
Robert B. Pippin in his chapter, "The Modern World of Leo
Strauss," claims that Strauss produced a "complex and multifront
attack" on the insufficiencies of modernity and America. The "at-
tack" by Strauss created a distinctly contentious audience in the
United States. This fascination with Strauss is the result of the
304 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER

rediscovery of the "problem of modernity," which includes doubts


about the benefits of technological mastery, the eclipse of public
reliance on religion, and the greater role of enlightened self-interest
in the formation of a polity (GE, 139).
Pippin provides a close textual analysis and critique of Strauss's
"wave hypothesis"-the modern experiment has occurred in three
waves-an instauration begun mainly by Hobbes, a first "crisis"
diagnosed by Rousseau, and a second "crisis" diagnosed by Nietzsche
and continuing in our times. Pippin argues that Strauss's interpre-
tation of the second wave or first crisis "misinterprets and underval-
ues the alternatives presented by German thinkers so influenced by
Rousseau, the German Idealists: especially Kant, Fichte and Hegel"
( GE, 140). Pippin disagrees with Strauss's reasons for claiming that
this tradition must result in the self-undermining of historicism that
intensifies rather than resolves the "modern crisis." For Pippin there
is no fatal aporia within modernity ultimately revealed by Nietzsche.
Pippin concentrates on Strauss's second wave or "first crisis" of
the common theme of freedom in modernity and movement from
the liberation of the passions to "absolute freedom." Pippin argues
that the best Strauss text to use to examine Strauss's interpretation
of this movement is his account of Rousseau in Natural Right and
History. Strauss claims that Rousseau appeals from both the modern
state to the classical city "and almost in the same breath...from the
classical city to the `man of nature,' the prepolitical savage." For
Pippin this means that Strauss produces a picture of Rousseau as a
confused writer who shifts back and forth between two directly
opposed positions ( GE, 154). This has produced a view of freedom
with historical positive results-a wholly modern notion of virtue-
man is virtuous only as self-determining and respect should be given
only for what we have done or made. But what we feel is our own
might not genuinely to be our own, might actually be the product of
the desires of others. A goal I posit to be worthy might not truly
express "me." With such worries, the "natural" in all the senses
involved is "lost" according to Strauss. Pippin suspects that Strauss's
characterization of Rousseau as primarily concerned with the self-
conscious and natural refugee from civil society reveals his clear
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 305

pessimism that a modern, virtuous commonwealth can be estab-


lished "without reference to man's nature" (GE, 156-157). Pippin is
not convinced that this tradition ends in a kind of aporia. Pippin
seeks to show that Rousseau's appeal to autonomy, and the necessar-
ily accompanying "unavailability" of any politically relevant appeal to
nature, "is more thoroughly and consistently motivated in Rousseau
than Strauss allows for, and generates a far more powerful legacy in
later philosophy than the romantic, `natural' sentiments (or classicist
nostalgia) pointed out by Strauss" ( GE, 159). Pippin seeks to
demonstrate, though quite sketchily, in this particular chapter, that
the second modern "wave" has not yet peaked or dissipated.
Horst Mewes, in "Leo Strauss and Martin Heidegger: Greek
Antiquity and the Meaning of Modernity," begins by noting that at
one point in Strauss's life he felt compelled to take an "explicit" stand
toward Heidegger. Strauss, when a young student, was deeply
impressed by Heidegger's "seriousness, profundity, and concentra-
tion in the interpretation of philosophic texts" (GE, 105). Gradually,
Strauss was to become aware of "the breadth of the revolution of
thought" prepared by Heidegger. Like Heidegger, Strauss was to
recognize the self-destructive nature of modern rationality and the
philosophical limits of modern science's claim to master nature-
indicative of a "crisis of the West."
Mewes does identify a significant divergence of positions be-
tween Strauss and Heidegger as to how to overcome the crisis by
returning to Greek philosophy. Their understandings and interpre-
tations of Greek philosophy were profoundly different; Strauss's life
work consisted in a "return to classical political philosophy [Mewes's
emphasis], while according to Strauss, Heidegger never believed in
the possibility of an ethic," and "left no room for political philosophy
in this thought" (GE, 105). Strauss was to view Heidegger's despi-
cable sympathies with the Nazi movement not simply as a personal
flaw, but rather in "their intimate connection with the core of his
philosophic thought." The lack of a political philosophy in Heidegger
goes to the very core of his project.
Mewes provides us with a highly incisive discussion of Strauss's
view that Heidegger's understanding of being differs fundamentally
306 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER

from that of both Plato and Aristotle. For Plato and Aristotle "to be
in the highest sense means to be always," while for Heidegger, "to
be in the highest sense means to exist, that is to say, to be in the
manner in which man is" (GE, 106). Heidegger's "return" to the
ancients is grounded in the radical spirit of modernity and the
disposition of the historicism of human existence. For Strauss, it is
crucial to understand ancient Greek philosophers as they had
understood themselves. Strauss considered Heidegger to be correct
in perceiving that there was something concealed to us moderns in
the origins of Western philosophy. However, Heidegger failed to
identify what was actually hidden, namely the radical division
between the philosophers and the non-philosophers. Heidegger
had focused on the pre-Socratics, rather than on Aristophanes,
Xenophon, and "the Socratic turn." For Strauss, Heidegger failed to
appreciate the poetic character of Platonic philosophy and its
political roots. Heidegger did not recognize the capacity of the
philosopher to transcend in thought his time and place; he could not
see the anger traditional authorities express against the philosopher
who challenges their love of their own. Nor could he see the
importance of the precautions the philosopher must take not to
arouse that anger. Strauss, then, considered Heidegger to be a
failure in not paying attention to the truly "original" relationship or
tension between philosophy and politics. Mewes's analysis of Strauss's
view of Heidegger's project becomes especially acute when he states
that Heidegger's failure to recognize the fundamental dualisms in
human nature-reason and revelation, the philosopher and the non-
philosopher, speech and deed, thought and action, and therefore
the limits of progress-led Strauss away from Heidegger and toward
the view that the philosopher must temper his philosophical mania.
Mewes makes it quite clear that to read Strauss is to understand well
the exceedingly high price Heidegger paid for explaining dualism in
being itself rather than viewing the "fate" of Western civilization as
the offspring of a "fundamental dualism in man." Strauss refused to
follow Heidegger and acknowledged the direct relationship be-
tween Heidegger's philosophy and his "resoluteness" which, ac-
cording to Strauss, leads in "a straight line...to his siding with Nazis
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 307

in 1933." What Strauss "could not stomach" was Heidegger's own


seeming inability to recognize that he actually had a moral teaching
based on his "radical historicism. Mewes's chapter allows us to
explore more cogently the contrasting responses of Heidegger and
Strauss to the challenges of philosophy and politics and to see more
clearly exactly what the philosophy has to do with the philosopher
(GE, 116-120).
Alfons Miner's contribution is a decent overview of Strauss's
thought that unfortunately is riddled with groundless characteriza-
tions of Strauss's project. Miner's piece is representative of many
misrepresentations of Strauss's writings and career. It might be
useful to cite a few of S611ner's characterizations of Strauss: his way
of thinking could be called "ultraconservative"-"a term which will
have to be defined more clearly" (which Sollner does not do); he
offers a "fundamentalist interpretation of the crisis of his time"; his
high point in a "condemnatory method of interpretation was reached
in his Thoughts on Machiavelli in which long passages" read almost
like an exercise in "intellectual exorcism," in which the dichotomous
worldview of McCarthyism, that is, of the Cold War, an idiosyncratic
apocalyptic gesture, at no time unfamiliar to Strauss, "overlap and
even reinforce each other momentously"; and his position was finally
"ultraconservative" "insofar as it took offense at all modern regimes"
(GE, 121, 132-133). These characterizations of Strauss's work are
not helpful in illuminating Strauss's teachings, and contrast sharply
with the immensely stimulating and irenic contributions of Gebhardt
and Mewes.
Timothy Fuller's "Reflections on Leo Strauss and American
Education" offers a very thoughtful and nuanced examination of
Strauss's role in contributing to the debates over American educa-
tion. Fuller notes quite appropriately that in our post-World War era
of educational specialization it is difficult to sustain collegiality and
conversationality. There may well be a great deal of choice in
education, but choice for what end? This deeply concerned Strauss.
Liberals had to make a choice between exploring natural right and
the uninhibited cultivation of individuality and diversity. For Strauss,
they chose the latter.
308 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER

Fuller is convinced that Strauss's critical view of contemporary


educators' insistence "that every comprehensive view is relative to a
specific perspective, or that all comprehensive views are mutually
exclusive and none can be simply true" is not only extraordinarily
prophetic, but also has created a major impact on the American
political science profession. His prophecy and the distinctive voice
are quite real; his impact on the political science profession is much
more problematic.
Fuller cites Strauss's Natural Right and History (1953) as an
"important harbinger" of the revival of interest in the study of
political philosophy. Fuller is quite right to state that interest in
political thought has increased. Yet one must also recognize the fact
that there is a "babel" of voices in the profession that is mostly
historicist and dogmatically atheist in orientation and that, more-
over, Strauss's work and career have elicited ferocious animosity and
demonization by such diverse personages as Sheldon Wolin, Stephen
Holmes, Shadia Drury, and Brent Staples in his editorial in The New
York Times.
Fuller emphasizes that liberal education in a liberal democracy
can engender modesty in things political and boldness in things
philosophical by its constant intercourse with the greatest minds.
Liberal learning contradicts the prejudices of the modern demo-
cratic culture. Liberal education is an act of retrieval of the conver-
sations of the greatest minds and recreates in ourselves a dialogue
that is often suppressed in the democratic ambience (GE, 76). Fuller
gets Strauss's position quite right when he states that:
When Strauss says he is critical of democracy because a friend
to it, he means to say that democracy should be praised for its
virtues and challenged on its vices. Unfortunately, there is a
democratic tendency to want simply to be praised, or worse,
flattered, and that, in effect, is likely to mean being praised for
its faults or excesses. The diversity of human goods is real.
Thus, the appearance of excellence or greatness in our midst
should be responded to so as to appropriate its contribution
opportunely, not vilified because it embarrasses a concealed
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 309

desire for a diversity that is actually a uniformity (GE, 7


footnote 15).

Fuller concludes by claiming that Strauss argues in favor of an


education challenging democracy rather than education for democ-
racy. We are called on to question the vast achievements of the
scientific-technological culture and egalitarianism as a vision of
order of human relationships. Education confronting democracy
would be showing how the Enlightenment project contributes to a
darkening in which "mass taste precludes holding anyone in particu-
lar responsible in any meaningful way.... Everyone and no one is
responsible for our situation" (GE, 80). We must fortify ourselves to
elevate the sense of being responsible-politically, living moder-
ately between natural right and history and, philosophically think-
ing, boldly pursuing the fundamental problems of the greatest
minds.
Hannah Arendt's influence as an emigre on American political
thought in GE is the subject of three contributions. They focus on
her theory of democracy and her classical conception of politics as
the basis for critiquing contemporary democratic republics.
Helmut Dubiel offers an astute overview of some of the major
themes of "public freedom" and the "founding act" that make up
Arendt's contribution to political theory in "Hannah Arendt and the
Theory of Democracy: A Critical Reconstruction." Dubiel considers
it important to explore the putative tension that exists between her
theory of decline from the politics of Greek antiquity to the politics
of modern republics and her analysis of contemporary American
society. He thinks that this tension, after some reflection, loses some
of its starkness (GE, 12).
Dubiel presents Arendt's model of modern politics in an illumi-
nating fashion-the social contract model (political authority that
demands subordination along with a pragmatic obedience) and a
communicative concept of political power that is represented in the
American founding. The American founding included a document
establishing political authority along with "the communicative en-
ergy that went into the document during the process of discussion
310 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER

prior to its codification" (GE, 19). For Dubiel her discussion of


contemporary American issues did not basically contradict her
model of the American founding. In her discussion of contemporary
civil disobedience, for example, she distinguishes it from violence
and views civil disobedience as one possible way in which every new
generation and every new individual can recreate the conditions for
the creative political activity of the founding act; especially when
"the majority occludes access to the political realm, they now have
the task of insisting, by means of symbolic political practices, upon
open access to the political sphere" ( GE, 22). Dubiel considers
Arendt to be ever the Aristotelian, in that she sees an inner
connection between the political character of human existence and
the ability to coordinate plans for action by means of speech-
including symbolic speech. Politics so conceived, says Dubiel,
excludes violence. As Arendt puts it, "violence is itself incapable of
speech." The state should only employ violence to protect the
communicative modus operandi of the political sphere.
Dubiel also addresses Arendt's famous classical division be-
tween the political and social spheres. In Arendt's view, the political
decline most characteristic of modern societies takes place when
politics becomes the instrument to realize "the social." Dubiel takes
Arendt's conception of politics absent of specific social regulation,
abandoning the social sphere to self-regulation, to be quite devoid
of particular purpose and incompatible with the essential nature of
democratic politics. This leads Dubiel to be somewhat sympathetic
to the view that Arendt is a "conservative utopian" or a "political
antimodernist" ( GE, 11).
In "The Questionable Influence of Arendt (and Strauss),"
George Kateb critically assesses Arendt's and Strauss's contribu-
tions to American democratic theory. For Kateb, "both radiate
disapproval of modern democracy" (GE, 29). He states "that anyone
committed to modem democracy should resist the influence of
these German-American philosophers while not being totally im-
pervious to it" (GE, 29). Kateb argues that Arendt's and Strauss's
love of ancient Greece was mediated by German philosophy, which
placed them against modern democracy. Arendt, he muses, might
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 311

be a more "serious enemy of modern democracy" than Strauss. Her


critique is decidedly political without the cultural pessimism and
"snobbism" of Strauss. While Arendt celebrates Athenian participa-
tory democracy as a critique of modem democratic practice, Strauss
recovers the ancient political philosophy of Plato and Aristotle,
which provides, among other things, the basis for a critique of the
modem historical relativization of beliefs and principles.
Kateb certainly recognizes that the matter of Arendt and democ-
racy is indeed complex. Arendt wants politics in a democracy to be
the monopoly of the admirable-the ones who want to "count and
be counted upon," those who refuse the delight of passivity or
pleasures or private pursuits (GE, 31). In On Revolution she
theorizes that Jefferson's ward governments "would spell the end of
general sufferage as we understand it; for only those who as
voluntary members of an `elementary republic' have demonstrated
that they care for more than their private happiness and are con-
cerned about the state of the world would have a right to be heard
in the conduct of the business of the republic" (GE, 31). Kateb
argues that Arendt is fully aware that she writes as a European
coming to America as an adult living spiritually at a distance from her
new home. American theorists, says Arendt herself, cannot take
European theory unreserved, not even hers.
Even though she is often inspired in interpreting democratic
political action at its best, Kateb continues to argue that "her
influence is not at all to the good" (GE, 35). Her influence is
especially regrettable on interconnected matters of modem consti-
tutional representative democracy and the role of genuine political
action. Kateb takes her to task for her view of modern constitutional
representative democracy as simply grounded in "self-preservation"
or self-interest. Such a system is vastly more complex than that. The
psychological benefits of being included as equal citizens seems to
elude her. Kateb states rather sarcastically that "it is not wise...for us
to imitate her onesidedness: We do not have her genius to excuse us"
(GE, 37). More to the point, Kateb concludes that Arendt is a great
and valuable writer in the fields of moral psychology, but her thought
trains "must be refracted and resisted by us if they are to bestow their
312 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER

benefits" (GE, 38).


Kateb proceeds to comment on Strauss's relation to modern
democracy. He raises a crucial question, namely, Are rules of textual
interpretation serving, if only indirectly, a particular political inten-
tion? Kateb works with the assumption that Strauss's rules of
interpretation as well as his political orientation give "power to his
readings." Kateb concludes that "a case could be made for saying that
Strauss's strategy of reading is not merely at the service of some local
or contemporary conservatism; rather-and far more important-it
is at the service of an inveterate antidemocratic outlook, an authori-
tarian antidemocratic position." For Kateb, though Strauss may
formally state that he is a friend and ally of democracy, he is "at most
a reluctant and disdainful supporter; a tactical supporter" ( GE, 39).
Kateb would like to demystify Strauss's antidemocratic myths of the
Founding Fathers, political authority, the need for divine or meta-
physical authentication for morality or systems of gentlemanly virtue
and popular discipline "in which full discretionary permissiveness
for `statesman' is joined to rigid moral constraints for the `masses-
(GE, 41). Kateb considers Strauss's promotion of "the so-called
classical position in the modern age to be an attempt to improve
modern democracy by viewing it in the light of Plato's and Aristotle's
ideal conceptions" (GE, 41). Kateb categorically berates Strauss for
being remiss for ignoring the writings of Emerson, Thoreau, and
Whitman as well as American democratic practice and modern
democratic practice with the possible exception of Weimar. Kateb
does admit that there are statements in Strauss's writings that are
positive about democracy, such as that only democracy among the
i mperfect polities as a matter of principle tolerates and encourages
philosophy. Kateb, once again, raises the right question: Was Strauss
trying with the statement "to strengthen democracy by avoiding
flattery and inducing democrats to undergo an ascesis that would
make them better democrats?" (GE, 43). If this was Strauss's
strategy, states Kateb, it miscarried. Those who were influenced by
Strauss, even when they write about the creation and meaning of
American constitutional democracy, are "...literal and artificial au-
thoritarian antidemocrats..." (GE, 43). Kateb's harsh conclusion is
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 313

that Strauss instructed those influenced by him to preserve the


American polity, yet "the tendency of their work is to misrepresent
it and spread dislike of it." Kateb now clearly places himself in the
coterie of Drury, Wolin, Burnyeat, Holmes, and others who wish to
demonize the Straussians as an antidemocratic cult bent on under-
mining American democratic traditions and practices.
I conclude this review of Kateb's discussion of Strauss with two
comments by Horst Mewes in the Roundtable Discussion section of
GE. These comments respond to Kateb's and S~llner's biting
remarks about Strauss and liberal democracy. Mewes makes the
following critical point:
Strauss saw reflected in [the American] founding act his
relation between philosophy and politics. It was precisely the
constant references to human nature in terms of the signifi-
cance of checks and balances that one finds in the Federalist
Papers and in all the correspondence surrounding the found-
ing act. [Also] we have, I think, gotten the overall impression
that he [Strauss] is not a genuine democrat.... Strauss repre-
sented a type [of democracy], and that is the type of the
Federalist's democratic republic. The type of democracy that
is essentially based on a representative republic governed by an
elected, natural aristocracy of merit. Now I regard that to be a
genuine type of democracy in the self-understanding of the
founders. Whether it is or not, he is providing the most
profound theory at the moment that is available for that type of
democracy. Now, the fact that this is an extremely unpopular
type of democratic theory right now is more than obvious. It is
quite clearly a perfectionist theory, as it provides a theory of
human excellence. I completely agree with Robert Pippin that
after building this edifice Strauss does not provide the tools for
the most profound answers to the relation between natural
consciousness, modern science, post-Kantianism, etc., and
one can hardly blame him for that" (GE, 189).
Ernest Volbrath's "Hannah Arendt: A German-American Jewess
Views the United States-and Looks Back to Germany" appreciates
314 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER

the influence of Arendt's refugee experience on her view of the


United States' political system. Though she would level harsh
criticism against specific political practices, Arendt remained in
fundamental agreement with the principles and practices of the
founding of the Constitution. She regularly contrasted, and some-
times tried to "even reconcile, the principles of the American
political system, with European, above all German, traditions" (GE,
45).
Volbrath claims that Arendt's clear-cut distinction between a
sphere of the political and an area of the societal is actually taken
from German experience-the difference between her position and
the German experience is that she never identified the political
sphere with the state. This gave her an opportunity "to distinguish
"
between what is authentically political and what is not (GE, 46).
This gave her a criterion by which to critique the perversity of politics
present in totalitarian domination.
In order to find adequate political categories, Arendt turned to
the Greek origins of the political. She knew too well that a simple
renewal of the polis was doomed to fail under the conditions of the
modern age. What could be renewed was Greek politeia, its
politicality, so to speak. Arendt found this politicality in the founding
of the American republic, wherein one could hope for the preserva-
tion of the public realm, and of political freedom along with the
minimum of social justice without which citizenship is impossible
(GE, 52-55). This type of thinking hardly existed in the tradition of
German culture with the exception of Kant's Critique of Judgment.
According to Volbrath, Arendt was not able to see a truly new
foundation for the postwar German Federal Republic. "She mea-
sured this against her understanding of the innovative spirit of the
American Republic" (GE, 58).
GE is an enormously rich commentary on the emigre experience
of Leo Strauss and Hannah Arendt as they theorized in a world
between German culture and philosophy and the modern American
regime. Most of the chapters will be of great value to those who are
open to their profound challenge.
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 315

II.

Ted. V. McAllister's Revolt Against Modernity (RAM) is a lucid and


powerful account of the crisis of modernity as understood by Leo
Strauss and Eric Voegelin. McAllister is concerned with Strauss's
and Voegelin's revolt against modernity-a revolt against modern
rationality, political orthodoxies and ideologies, scientism, and the
human drive for mastery of the environment. In an important way,
one can immediately focus on Strauss's and Voegelin's revolt against
modernity by identifying their common rejection of scientism or
positivism. For Voegelin, a close reading of Weber reinforced his
animus toward modern social science in that Weber restricted the
role of the scientists to an exploration of cause and effect, which
amounted to the method dictating the subject. Voegelin wanted the
realm of science to be much broader and applied to all areas of
human experience. For Strauss, positivism or social science grounded
in the fact/value dichotomy undermines beliefs necessary for politi-
cal and social order.
McAllister argues that Voegelin's and Strauss's critique of
positivism involved a great issue of which positivism formed a part
nothing less than the fate of civilization (RAM, 80). "Both men
played important roles in the development of a conservative intellec-
tual movement born in the 1950s" (RAM, 9). McAllister, unlike
many other commentators on their work, realizes fully that applying
the conservative label presents special problems. Voegelin objected
to the label "conservative" because it tended to "flatten" out "his
work" and to be used to buttress a political persuasion he did not
openly share. To be sure, Voegelin rejected ideological thinking in
any form. Strauss could never be classified as a Burkean conservative
traditionalist which, for him, would certainly smack of historicism.
Yet, according to McAllister, "Strauss...invited an appropriation of
his work by those who misunderstood him" (RAM, 9).
McAllister does consider Strauss and Voegelin to be conserva-
tives in one important sense-they were antimodernist. Voegelin
can be called conservative because of his "chronic concern for order,
or the search for order, or the experience of order" (RAM, 10).
316 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER

Strauss's emphasis upon "nature" may appear to undermine order


resting upon convention, habit, or prescription. Strauss's teaching
concerning "nature" actually serves a conservative function of un-
dermining historicist or relativist arguments against normative social
'
order. For McAllister, "his motivations were nothing if not conser-
vative."' Though Voegelin and Strauss do not fit perfectly the ideal
conservative type as do Russell Kirk or Robert Nisbet, "their
philosophical assumptions closely resemble those of traditionalist
conservatives" (RAM, 13). With their rejection of modernity, Strauss
and Voegelin were to produce a critique of the modern world that
conservatives primarily relied upon to develop their specific attacks
on contemporary social ills (RAM, 13). McAllister is making two
separate claims: (1) Strauss and Voegelin present a critique of
modernity that contributes to a postliberal political order and (2) that
many contemporary conservatives ground their sociopolitical criti-
cism "primarily" on Strauss's and Voegelin's work. I consider
McAllister to be very successful in providing support for the first
claim, while his second claim must be viewed as highly problematic
and unproven.
McAllister graces the reader with a beautifully crafted and
illuminating discussion of Strauss's reading of Machiavelli and
Voegelin's reading of Hegel as a way toward understanding their
critiques of modernity. These discussions are among the most lucid,
concise and nuanced accounts of Strauss on Machiavelli and Voegelin
on Hegel available in print.
For McAllister, it was Strauss's intention to recover the "sur-
prise" of Machiavelli, to see once again Machiavelli as innovator, to
go beyond the pallor and see the "evil." Machiavelli has so corrupted
moderns that they can no longer capture his "creative if demonic
genius" (RAM, 95). Machiavelli is viewed by Strauss as an Averroist-
interested in Christianity only as a political force. Machiavelli
reduces God to a symbol equivalent tofortuna (or chance) and to a
foe that must be conquered (RAM, 100-101). Machiavelli's great
innovation was to loose human behavior from the coercive dictates
of a god or gods, undermining as well the classical belief in the
teleology of nature, replacing both with a world in which humans
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 317

must live with "chance understood as a non-teleological necessity


which leaves room for choice and prudence and therefore chance
understood as the cause of simply unforeseeable accidents" (RAM,
102). Machiavelli's new modes and orders threatened not only
Christianity but also classical political philosophy and in the process
challenges the reader to face or recover the "permanent problems."
McAllister manages to capture the larger flow of Thoughts on
Machiavelli when he states that:
The connections Strauss made between Machiavelli and the
moderns who swallowed him whole merge with rarely matched
Straussian clarity in the concluding pages of Thoughts on
Machiavelli. Humans moved out of a universe of necessity into
a realm of godlike freedom, with their desires positing ends
and their evolving science employed in the discovery or cre-
ation of means appropriate to those ends. In due course Hitler
posited the ends, ratified by the support of the German
population, and science and philosophy supplied the means.
What was `the final solution' but a rational method of achieving
a political goal? (RAM, 105).
Ultimately, Strauss intended to present more than a work on
Machiavelli. Strauss was to show that moderns follow Machiavelli
without knowing it, moderns lack Machiavelli's own full horizon that
he had inherited from the ancients and that "moderns may be
Machiavellian more than disciples of Machiavelli" (RAM, 107).
Most importantly, Strauss was to address the issue of the modern's
lost access to "fundamental experiences" or lack of recognition of the
"permanent problems." For McAllister, Strauss contrasts the per-
manent problems with the problem of Machiavelli. Machiavelli
produces a constriction of the horizon. "The permanent problems,"
for Strauss, "concern the irremovable tensions between politics and
philosophy, between practical matters and theory, between is and
ought" (RAM, 109). Machiavelli placed philosophy in the service of
politics and eliminated theory and the universal good from the
political equation. Machiavelli solved a problem "at the expense of
ignorance concerning the highest excellence open to humans as
318 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER

individuals and as part of a political order" (RAM, 109). Though


humans could now in godlike terms posit their own goals, they would
also become like animals in losing sight of the noble, the excellent,
the good.
McAllister most appropriately emphasizes Strauss's character-
ization of the United States as an example of a non-Machiavellian
order because it included in its founding strong premodern teach-
ings that enabled it to sustain a tradition of justice and freedom and
to reaffirm the ideals of its society against the backdrop of particular
failures. America has been, and Strauss ominously warns must
continue to be, a society that escapes the restrictions caused by
substituting instrumental reason or method-driven science for theo-
retical questions about the good and the just. As McAllister puts it,
for Strauss, "in the United States, techne (technique or instrumental
reason) had not entirely overtaken theory" (RAM, 109). McAllister
helps the reader appreciate why Strauss and Voegelin are so severely
critical of American social sciences' emphasis on techne, which has
led to the forgetting of the fact that the United States was "founded
in explicit opposition to Machiavellian principles."
There is an existential issue involved in Voegelin's reading of
Hegel, according to McAllister; it involves a characterization of
Hegel as modernity's paradigmatic man. Voegelin saw Hegel's
intellectual project as a "revolt against the Christian reliance in a
world-transcendent God by bringing God to earth in the mode of
becoming and as immanent in history," thereby allowing for human
mastery of their human world and fate (RAM, 110). In due course,
according to Voegelin, God must be murdered to make way for
human creativity and domination. While for Strauss the problem
with modernity was purely philosophical (Machiavelli's new science
of philosophy in competition with ancient science and philosophy),
for Voegelin the problem was the recurrence of a spiritual disease
requiring a return to the true science of the soul and order.
McAllister's examination of Voegelin on Hegel centers on his
lengthy essay "On Hegel: A Study in Sorcery." Voegelin makes his
critical point in the title, namely that there is a magical component
of modernity. Gnostics expect to achieve a transformed humanity
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 319

through magic. A belief in the magical ability ("metastasis" was


Voegelin's word) to change reality animated all gnostic thinkers,
especially modern gnostics who emphasized revolution. Magicians
or sorcerers are frauds or swindlers using tricks. Hegel is a magician
and Voegelin exposes his tricks (RAM, 128).
Voegelin certainly recognized Hegel's brilliance. Yet Voegelin
characterizes him as deforming reality as a divided self, a tortured
soul. Hegel cannot gain the stature of his true self under God, which
produces "the darkness of this existential deficiency" upon which
"rises the libido dominandi and forces him into the imaginative
construction of a false self as a messias of the new age" (RAM, 128).
Since no person could actually become a god or alter his nature,
Hegel must "eclipse" reality and construct a "second reality." Voegelin
understands Hegel to see himself as the new Christ, the locus of
spiritual energy that inaugurates a new age. The philosopher no
longer limits himself to the search for wisdom (which recognizes
human limitation ) but seeks to use the symbol "science" to acquire
a peculiarly modern magic. Voegelin's Hegel is intensely jealous of
Napoleon passing through Hegel's town. Voegelin exposes Hegel's
tricks, which served as expressions of his self-deification. The most
important of these was a circularity of language. "The game was
rigged, you can't win once you let yourself be sucked into accepting
Hegel's language" (RAM, 130). Hegel replaces Jesus by bringing the
fullest revelation in which spirit and flesh become one. This is a
second reality created by Hegel, which is ill-fit to the human
condition in the metaxy which is the actual in-between tensioned
field between God and man, the divine and the mundane. Diseased
souls who accept this second reality become most violent in their
efforts to realize goals posited by the sorcerer's ideological deforma-
tion of reality. McAllister puts Voegelin's prescription quite simply
when he states that "only a return to the balanced consciousness and
an acceptance of the reality of the metaxy can deliver us from the
violence and disorder of modernity" (RAM, 131).
Strauss's profound analysis of Machiavelli's project and Voegelin's
profound analysis of Hegel's project were both, to be sure, highly
controversial. Each of them would provide Strauss and Voegelin
320 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER

with a firm foundation, along with other studies, for their critiques
of modern liberalism.
For Strauss, American liberalism originally was grounded in two
faiths-modern and premodern-drawing sustenance from mod-
ern natural rights theory and also from premodern beliefs in the
Christian God and classical republican virtues. In effect, "unalien-
able rights were lodged in a larger framework that shaped the range
of appropriate uses of these freedoms (RAM, 162). Strauss, from the
vantage point of 1950, began to see a great change in which the
United States was moving toward a German type of relativism. With
the growth of prestige of an American social science, with its
characteristic fact/value distinction, American social scientists would
greatly influence the society to see humans as motivated by urges and
aspirations with no natural right. This is the crisis of liberal democ-
racy-to be wedded to ideals that are no longer defensible as good.
Even modern natural right, shorn of religious support, leads to
relativism. McAllister strongly emphasizes Strauss's view of the
pernicious role social science plays in our liberal democracy, as we
have also discussed above. McAllister rightly focuses on Strauss's
analysis of the modern understanding of nature, which leads to the
elevation of certain areas of knowledge as being useful for control-
ling or manipulating nature-including human nature. Yet science
alone cannot address "the question of how this power ought to be
used" (RAM, 163). As the premodern elements in the American
regime diminish in the postwar period, and the prestige and
influence of modern social science is enhanced, the United States
would be left with unlimited modern natural right, escalating
demands for greater and greater freedom, and a politics primarily
grounded in the will to power. Like Weimar, we seem to be
experiencing a growing inability to identify and defend our highest
principles (RAM, 166).
Strauss and Voegelin both view modern humanity as having lost
access to a wisdom that insists on evaluating the use of knowledge in
terms of proper ends. Unlike Strauss, Voegelin argues that the
human horizon, which naturally includes the apperception of the
mysterious ground of human existence, suffered an artificial con-
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 321

striction in which modern humans have lost access to the actual


ordering principles inherent in the reality of which they form a part.
This artificial constriction produces for Voegelin the danger of
modern liberalism, which is "the defense of the private good as the
greatest good," as McAllister puts it (RAM, 170).
Although, Voegelin rarely comments on the current conditions
of the spiritual bankruptcy of modern liberalism, McAllister co-
gently demonstrates that a close reading of certain essays by Voegelin,
especially "The German University and the Order of German
Society: A Reconsideration of the Nazi Era," will lead to much
insight about Voegelin's view of the modern expressions of that
bankruptcy. Like Strauss, Voegelin found the Weimar and Nazi past
to be illuminating for contemporary liberal public life in general.
What is required in studying Weimar, Nazism, and the German
University is a "critical history" requiring those who pursue it to have
a balanced consciousness. Modern liberal democracies tend to
accept an individualistic ethic emphasizing one's uniqueness, el-
evating the private character of one's existence which tends to
replace virtue, duty, or citizenship with freedom and originality.
Universities no longer play the role of guardian and dispenser of the
knowledge needed for rational public deliberation (RAM, 173).
Modern education is not concerned with building character or
orienting people to the nature of human reality as experienced by
spiritually sensitive people. With this loss, a vacuum is created
which the modern gnostics can exploit. "Those who have lost sight
of the divine ground but who cannot believe in these `second
realities' are unable to respond" (RAM, 172). For Voegelin most
intellectual leaders in postwar Germany and the West generally are
spiritually incapable of understanding his critique. McAllister once
again makes the correct point that "Voegelin must remain on the
intellectual margins as long as his apperception of this larger context
of human existence remains unbelievable to the larger intellectual
community" (RAM, 172).
Despite the intellectual blindness around him, Voegelin still
wrote with some hope that we can develop and teach a spiritually
differentiated language that could counter such deformed language
322 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER

symbols as the subject/object dichotomy. This development is


crucial if we are to resist the language of "values" and "value-free
science." A few contemporary Germans, though, could understand
what Voegelin meant when he ended his German lecture with the
example of the watchman who speaks God's words even though few
will respond (Ezek. 33:7-9). In order to reach them Voegelin "had
to create a new symbolic structure representing the noetic structure
of existence while exposing the untrue structure and motivations of
ideologies" (RAM, 173).
McAllister points quite properly to the affinities of Strauss's and
Voegelin's diagnoses of the crisis of the West. Their answers to the
crisis point in different, but by no means opposite, directions.
McAllister devotes a chapter to Strauss "the philosopher" and
Voegelin "the mystic."
Strauss's subtle understanding of the paradoxical nature of the
relationship between the philosopher and the social order, in which
the commands of the law and the philosophic quest to replace
opinion with knowledge produce an obvious tension. The philoso-
pher is "something of an outsider," such as the condition of a Jewish
philosopher in a Christian society (RAM, 178). It was this "prob-
lem"-the quarrel between Jerusalem and Athens-that was to
dominate Strauss's project throughout his career.
McAllister gives the reader a scrupulous discussion of the key
texts that relate to the Jerusalem and Athens quarrel and Strauss's
view that the Jewish problem is the most manifest symbol of the
human problem insofar as it is a social or political problem (RAM,
178). For Strauss, "the political dependence [of Jews] was also
spiritual dependence" (RAM, 180). The Jewish problem was more
than a political problem; it could be addressed only as a socio-
religious matter. Strauss argues that a regime that ignores the
religious roots of conventional morality is vulnerable or spiritually
weak. The Jewish problem appeared insoluble, because one must
belong to a particular society. One must embrace one's community.
A Jew must "return" to the Jewish faith and to the Jewish way of life.
McAllister characterizes Strauss's own response to this situation as
"ambiguous" because Strauss was a zetetic philosopher skeptical
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 323

about all beliefs yet open to the possibility of truth who, nonetheless,
did call for a return to the ancient faith for the Jew (RAM, 182). This
discussion of the Jewish problem, for Strauss, in the works of
Spinoza, Herman Cohen, and Franz Rosenzweig focuses on the
question of the relationship between orthodoxy and philosophy.
The discussion emphasizes the appropriate moral posture that
"prevents modern intellectuals from seeing clearly," according to
McAllister's interpretation of Strauss's project (RAM, 181). The
term for this moral posture, absent in these modern intellectuals, is
"intellectual probity," which appreciates the impossibility of dis-
proving revelation, seeks to understand revelation as believers
understood it, and recognizes the danger of undermining religious
beliefs through mockery. The Enlightenment thinkers "embraced
their own epistemology with such tenacity that they eliminated all
room for revelation" (RAM, 182). Strauss, in these terms, held up
orthodoxy as an intellectually defensible alternative. McAllister
claims that for Strauss, orthodoxy "serves a vital need" (RAM, 182).
McAllister describes Strauss's call for "return" as "oblique." For
many, the law is really no more, God is dead, and we find ourselves
in the sub-cave. Without the law, though, morality fades, political
order is precarious, and no specific transcendent morality can be
championed. Strauss's examination of Maimonides' prophetology
led him to conclude that Moses had seen reality beyond the cave
using his "imagination" as philosopher and prophet to see the
general theory and the particular political order. He was not the
traditional or conventional prophet; he was a gifted philosopher.
Men as social beings need such prophets to give the law, which
"must be of a sort that directs fractious human natures toward
communal harmony," according to McAllister's characterization of
Strauss (RAM, 202). The prophet is the founder of a society
dedicated to human perfection, which is, by the way, philosophy.
Moses, by providing the "divine" law, addressed the practical
philosophical needs. All subsequent philosophers should defer to
the law giver-a social order "requires a normative order that
supersedes individual conceptions of right and wrong and that binds
a people together in a common goal or purpose" (RAM, 203). The
324 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER

few must instruct the many about proper beliefs concerning heav-
enly matters, which will then allow the philosopher to interpret and
reinterpret the literal meaning of the legal text. The Torah is
enormously flexible, which allows the philosopher, even commands
him, to freely interpret the established legal foundation. This is
medieval "enlightened" reason, which rejects efforts to reshape the
world radically in contradistinction to modern "enlightened" reason,
which reversed the priority of medieval Islamic and Jewish rational-
ism-the superiority of theory over practice-and sought to recon-
struct the world. The modern enlightenment claimed that knowl-
edge and reason could replace superstition and faith as the compass
of human action. The many must be liberated from orthodox
religion. Freedom of thought was possible for the many, not just the
few. The many would be cut off from their moral roots subsequently
producing alienated and egoistic creatures. As McAllister puts it,
Strauss saw the many as gravitating toward "mass movements others
to crass consumerism, but whichever way they went, the normative
order fell apart. Not reason but passion ruled" (RAM, 204). Strauss,
states McAllister, sought "to secure a rationale for other people to
reconstruct [to return to] an old one [the insights and enlightened
reason of Farabi and Maimonides]" (RAM, 204).
Strauss's "return " to Maimonides eschewed metaphysical ques-
tions and emphasized moral-political matters. Strauss and
Maimonides as philosophers were not truly concerned with the
"source" of the law. Strauss knew enough about the life of the
philosopher to recognize the need for political philosophy (RAM,
205).
Strauss also "returns" to, or reconstructs, the Platonic concept of
philosophy, which is centered on the question of how one should
live; philosophy is a way of life rather than a rigid set of doctrines. For
Strauss, genuine philosophers live with a "mania" or existential
imperative that turns to "nature" as a means to understand the whole
without appeal to authority and with agnosticism concerning which
claims about god or the gods to believe. For Strauss, the philosopher
lives in between relativism and orthodoxy. Strauss remained in the
human realm, leaving others to examine divine things.
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 325

Those who pursue philosophy, in "Platonic" terms, are con-


cerned with "permanent problems." They begin in wonder and
doubt, refuse to accept hearsay or authority, and begin to pursue
their own investigation of conflicting opinions. This may produce a
synthesis that partly purifies opinions of their conventional proper-
ties. An ascent may take place not producing complete knowledge,
but an understanding of the permanent problems and the range of
answers available to human beings. The philosopher annoys the
citizens of the city and is endangered. The Platonic philosopher
learns to become the political philosopher (RAM, 216). The Platonic
Socrates, then, "must have moved to a greater concern for, and
awareness of, souls and their natures" (RAM, 216). This awareness
implicates the political by leading to Socrates' accommodating
himself to the city. For Strauss, Platonic political philosophy emerges
as an astute presentation of philosophy as well as a philosophy of
politics.
Strauss's own great work of political philosophy is Natural Right
and History. McAllister centers his attention on Strauss's discussion
of Platonic political philosophy. The conclusion drawn about the
Platonic conception of the philosopher is that he must concern
himself with the health of the city, which is coeval with the health of
philosophy. Cities cannot promote the skeptical life and survive.
Laws are dependent upon some myth about the nature of reality and
right and wrong. Political questions are always moral and religious.
Liberal democracies, which can be friendly to philosophy, cannot
long survive if they are actually grounded in the pursuit of idiosyn-
cratic individual happiness alone. Without a social myth, society,
whether liberal democratic or not, will slowly lose the means of
protecting itself (RAM, 220). Strauss wanted to "breathe new life
into the quest for transhistorical truth about natural right" in order
to secure a political and moral center as well as revive a "defensible
religious faith," according to McAllister, because Strauss recognized
that political societies depended upon some metaphysical construc-
tion. Strauss respected religious faith in terms of its political utility,
in terms of the respectable people who possess such faith, and in
terms of the natural or common-sense experience of the world which
326 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER

is bound up in religious/mythological expressions of reality. Modern


atheistic dogmatism, as expressed by historicists and positivists, has
to be attacked by Strauss, according to McAllister, if the damage
done to the cause of faith is to be repaired in the interest of true
enlightenment as best understood by the premodern Islamic and
Jewish philosophers. McAllister characterizes Strauss as a "conser-
vative" in a special sense. He lived the life of the mind in search of
enlightenment-of the truths locked away in great books. McAllister
states that "Strauss was forced to speak to his society because
Heidegger could not. Strauss felt compelled to answer Heidegger's
silence" (RAM, 221). We might also add that Strauss felt compelled
to speak to a civil society that was deeply undermined by a social
science that "fiddles while Rome burns. " Pathetically, the political
science discipline does not even realize that it is fiddling and that
Rome is burning. He is a conservative in the sense that he calls for
a return to the problems, alternatives, vital tensions, and guiding
principles found in the quarrel of philosophy and biblical religion,
the quarrel of the ancients and the moderns, and the quarrel of
philosophy and poetry. Such a "return" could restore the social
vitality of the United States and the West (RAM, 221). McAllister is
correct to apply the label "conservative" to Strauss if we understand
it to mean that Strauss was deeply concerned with both the revival
of religious education of the people and of liberal education of the
representatives of the people.
McAllister refers to Voegelin as the mystic whose philosophical
investigations were concerned with the individual soul and the
understanding of consciousness. His work was indeed "unfashion-
able" (RAM, 222). The mysteries of humans, society, history, and
God rest in the depths of the human soul. Order and disorder are
attunement to, or alienation from, the truths apperceived in the soul.
Voegelin's historical analysis "sought to recapture the experience
that created the symbols of order that, for him, constituted history"
(RAM, 224). For Voegelin there is a historical "reality" that allows
communication across huge cultural divides. Plato's experiences
could make sense only when they engender a "responsive experi-
ence" in us. What is required, according to Voegelin, is an openness.
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 327

What is the universal experience resting beneath the historically


conditioned veneer of the spiritual struggle of Moses or Plato?
McAllister alerts us to the fact that Voegelin's use of conscious-
ness "most nearly parallels Heidegger's Dasein as the place in being
where being becomes aware of itself (a process Voegelin called
`luminosity')" (RAM, 232). The specter of Heidegger haunts all
three of the peregrine discussed in this review essay. Voegelin's
understanding of consciousness is not that of a relationship, but as
a participation event. "Humans learn about the story in which they
discover themselves only from the perspective of participants"
(RAM, 232). The luminous discovery identifies a part of reality in
which "the knower and the known move into tensional poles in a
consciousness we call luminous as far as it engenders symbols which
express the experience of its own structure" (RAM, 234). For both
Strauss and Voegelin, Plato stands at the beginning of a search often
"derailed" by modernity.
Voegelin appropriates from Plato the symbol and word metaxy
-meaning "in-between"-as peculiar to the human condition. We
participate in both immanent reality and transcendent reality in
which the philosophers among us search (zetema) for the ground of
existence. The mutual attraction of the human nous and the divine
nous produces consciousness. The experiences of Moses and Plato
are "equivalent" and rest on a theophanic ground even if they expose
different dimensions of the common experienced reality. "In sharp
contrast to Strauss," states McAllister, "Voegelin did not juxtapose
faith and reason, nor did he suggest that they were complementary
faculties. Faith and reason belong together as part of the same
experience" (RAM, 248).
There is no history without God, according to Voegelin. How-
ever, the mystery-human interaction with the divine-cannot be
penetrated by a set of doctrines about the nature of God. Voegelin
considered himself, when asked, to be a pre-Nicean Christian. His
prime concern was the reification of the history of Christian sym-
bols. The problem with modern civilization is that it has inherited
and reified the earlier symbols of differentiated consciousness that
found its synthesis in Christianity. Those earlier symbols have lost
328 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER

their transparency to truth and have become deformed. The conse-


quence of this deformation is a "bastardized set of ideas" and gnostic
ideologies. These ideas do not rest upon an experiential base nor do
they orient individuals or societies to being (RAM, 254). Individuals
who cannot live in-between in the pole of reality beyond human
control (libido dominandi) select from any array of ideas or ideolo-
gies. For Voegelin, modern political science rests, as well, upon an
anti-metaphysical bias springing from a lust for power and control in
which there is a virtual eclipse of the transcendent pole of reality and
a reification of immanent reality. Losing access to the metaxy,
modem political scientists could not conceive of a right order. They
talk instead of "values." Cut off from participation in the metaxy,
there can be no adjudication (RAM, 258-59). Consequently, a
deformed political science can offer no resistance to the develop-
ment of the most monstrous ideologies. McAllister is convinced that
Voegelin believed that America and the West could not last long in
a world of epiphenomenal "values" and with such a minimalist
conception of the good. An understanding of the good that is "larger
than collective individual goods...requires an understanding of con-
sciousness that enlarges the realm of human participation to include
the divine pole of reality" (RAM, 259). As McAllister puts it, Voegelin
did not call for any old God-as Strauss came close to advocating-
but for the mysterious God beyond existence whose revelations are
revelations of mystery. Politics is equally dangerous with reified gods
or with no god at all (RAM, 250). This statement gives us a most
felicitous summary of Voegelin's approach to a new science of
politics along with an ungracious swipe at Strauss's approach to God.
Perhaps McAllister and others would do well to consider Strauss's
most revealing and subtle lecture, now published, "Why We Remain
Jews: Can Jewish Faith and History Still Speak to Us?" 5
McAllister in his conclusion reveals the strengths and weak-
nesses of his work. He demonstrates admirably Strauss's and
Voegelin's search for a normative order, finding few definitive
answers, yet shaping intellectually the few people who pursue the
search. By attracting some who are open to the possibility of truth
they help save philosophy and perhaps even serve society. These
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 329

approaches to the soul as a natural hierarchy of parts or the ordered


soul in the metaxy are certainly timeless. I am not convinced,
however, that many politically oriented conservatives such as liber-
tarians, the religious right, supply-side economists, or even most
traditionalists have been profoundly influenced by Strauss or
Voegelin. Both strongly objected to being labeled conservative or
traditionalist and for good reason. Both of these German emigres
could not uncritically accept market ideologies, the prestige of
American social science, or political or religious orthodoxies. Strauss
and Voegelin would also become very ambivalent about America's
particular traditions of individualism, scientism, and egalitarianism.
The philosopher and the mystic, each pursuing his own search,
would provide us with cognitive resources that could be used
against modem social science for the achievement of personal
wholeness and social coherence. Their legacy is best understood as
propaedeutic. What finally mattered most to both of them was to
serve as guides for the perplexed in modern times-to attract a few
to pursue the search for wisdom, to get the many to consider putting
their lives in the service of common ideals and to see their private
concerns as part of something larger and more significant. Leo
Strauss and Eric Voegelin both brilliantly struggled with the
question that Friedrich Nietzsche posed around the turn of the last
century:
And now the myth-less man remains eternally hungering
among all the bygones, and digs and grubs for roots, though he
has to dig for them even among the remotest antiquities. The
stupendous historical exigency of the unsatisfied modern
culture, the gathering around one of the countless other
cultures, the consuming desire for knowledge-what does all
this point to, if not to the loss of myth, the loss of the mythical
home, the mythical source.'

Kenneth L. Deutsch
State University of New York-Geneseo
330 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER

NOTES
1. Quotations from Voegelin are cited in Marion Montgomery,
The Men I Have Chosen for Fathers: Literary and Philosophical
Passages (Columbia: University of Missouri Press, 1990), pp. 138-
39.
2. Quotations from David Luban, "Explaining Dark Times:
Hannah Arendt's Theory of Theory" in Lewis P. Hinchman and
Sandra K. Hinchman (eds.), Hannah Arendt: Critical Essays (Al-
bany: SUNY Press, 1994), pp. 86-87.
3. Ibid., p. 86.
4. Herbert J. Storing (ed.), Essays in the Scientific Study of
Politics (New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston, 1962), p. 221.
5. Kenneth L. Deutsch and Walter Nicgorslā (eds.), Leo Strauss:
Political Philosopher and Jewish Thinker, (Lanham: Rowman and
Littlefield Pubs., 1994), p. 52.
6. Friedrich Nietzsche, The Birth of Tragedy, trans. Hausmann
(Edinburgh, Scotland: Foulis, 1910), p. 175.

You might also like