Voegelin On Hegel's Sorcery
Voegelin On Hegel's Sorcery
Voegelin On Hegel's Sorcery
I.
Focusing first on GE, I intend to explore at length Jurgen Gebhardt's
outstanding chapter, "Leo Strauss: The Quest for Truth." Gebhardt,
a non-Straussian, demonstrates both an acute textual analysis of and
an irenic openness to the challenge of Strauss's scholarship. He
begins his study of Strauss as an emigre scholar with John G.
Gunnell's critical account of the original intentions of Strauss,
Voegelin, and Arendt to bring with them to the United States the
"myth of the tradition"-a "Europeanized theory in the United
States." Political theory, for them, was "a response to a crisis, as a
diagnosis of disorder and a critique of contemporary politics...a
300 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER
sociocultural crises and the ensuing social problems are rooted in the
intellectual and spiritual life of society" (GE, 87). Gebhardt views
Strauss's quest for truth within the context of Strauss's specific
cultural interpretation of the modern crisis-a "notion, of the
cultural crisis [which] was characteristic of the German intellectual
community, the `mandarin intellectuals. - Fritz Ringer defines
them, in terms of an ideal type, the German cultural and social elite
which owes its status primarily to educational qualifications, rather
than to the hereditary rights or wealth (GE, 87-88). They were
guided by the concepts of Wissenschaft and Bildung, which pre-
sented higher learning in terms of the quest for truth and self-
cultivation and the development of a university-trained cultural
elite. Gebhardt maintains that Strauss's personal style and intellec-
tual perspective "reflect the habitudes and the intellectual vision of
the German mandarins" ( GE, 88). Although Strauss began his
scholarly life at Jewish institutes in Germany outside of the univer-
sity, his style in which he later taught in the United States, the way
he asserted his authority and his notion of spiritual elevation
achieved through learning, had a great deal in common with the
German mandarins. Alfons Sollner presents Strauss as a very Ger-
man figure, "a charismatic representative of Teutonic learnedness,"
a representative of the nineteenth-century German tradition of a
highly elevated aristocracy of scholars of imperious manner (GE, 6).
Whether Strauss truly fits this model can be answered only by the
few who knew him well.
Gebhardt is convinced that much of the controversy that sur-
rounded Strauss and his students had to do with the exotic, German
mandarin flavor of his work, which "was met with enthusiasm as well
as disgust" ( GE, 89).
What, according to Gebhardt, is the greatness or distinctiveness
of Strauss's learning? It centers on "the problem of the true philoso-
pher," as Gebhardt puts it. Once Strauss contemplates a return to
pre-modern philosophy, "a new understanding of philosophizing
under modem conditions comes into sight: the ascent from the
second unnatural cave of the modern worldview to the primary
natural cave of the City by means of historical learning" (GE, 96).
302 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER
from that of both Plato and Aristotle. For Plato and Aristotle "to be
in the highest sense means to be always," while for Heidegger, "to
be in the highest sense means to exist, that is to say, to be in the
manner in which man is" (GE, 106). Heidegger's "return" to the
ancients is grounded in the radical spirit of modernity and the
disposition of the historicism of human existence. For Strauss, it is
crucial to understand ancient Greek philosophers as they had
understood themselves. Strauss considered Heidegger to be correct
in perceiving that there was something concealed to us moderns in
the origins of Western philosophy. However, Heidegger failed to
identify what was actually hidden, namely the radical division
between the philosophers and the non-philosophers. Heidegger
had focused on the pre-Socratics, rather than on Aristophanes,
Xenophon, and "the Socratic turn." For Strauss, Heidegger failed to
appreciate the poetic character of Platonic philosophy and its
political roots. Heidegger did not recognize the capacity of the
philosopher to transcend in thought his time and place; he could not
see the anger traditional authorities express against the philosopher
who challenges their love of their own. Nor could he see the
importance of the precautions the philosopher must take not to
arouse that anger. Strauss, then, considered Heidegger to be a
failure in not paying attention to the truly "original" relationship or
tension between philosophy and politics. Mewes's analysis of Strauss's
view of Heidegger's project becomes especially acute when he states
that Heidegger's failure to recognize the fundamental dualisms in
human nature-reason and revelation, the philosopher and the non-
philosopher, speech and deed, thought and action, and therefore
the limits of progress-led Strauss away from Heidegger and toward
the view that the philosopher must temper his philosophical mania.
Mewes makes it quite clear that to read Strauss is to understand well
the exceedingly high price Heidegger paid for explaining dualism in
being itself rather than viewing the "fate" of Western civilization as
the offspring of a "fundamental dualism in man." Strauss refused to
follow Heidegger and acknowledged the direct relationship be-
tween Heidegger's philosophy and his "resoluteness" which, ac-
cording to Strauss, leads in "a straight line...to his siding with Nazis
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 307
II.
with a firm foundation, along with other studies, for their critiques
of modern liberalism.
For Strauss, American liberalism originally was grounded in two
faiths-modern and premodern-drawing sustenance from mod-
ern natural rights theory and also from premodern beliefs in the
Christian God and classical republican virtues. In effect, "unalien-
able rights were lodged in a larger framework that shaped the range
of appropriate uses of these freedoms (RAM, 162). Strauss, from the
vantage point of 1950, began to see a great change in which the
United States was moving toward a German type of relativism. With
the growth of prestige of an American social science, with its
characteristic fact/value distinction, American social scientists would
greatly influence the society to see humans as motivated by urges and
aspirations with no natural right. This is the crisis of liberal democ-
racy-to be wedded to ideals that are no longer defensible as good.
Even modern natural right, shorn of religious support, leads to
relativism. McAllister strongly emphasizes Strauss's view of the
pernicious role social science plays in our liberal democracy, as we
have also discussed above. McAllister rightly focuses on Strauss's
analysis of the modern understanding of nature, which leads to the
elevation of certain areas of knowledge as being useful for control-
ling or manipulating nature-including human nature. Yet science
alone cannot address "the question of how this power ought to be
used" (RAM, 163). As the premodern elements in the American
regime diminish in the postwar period, and the prestige and
influence of modern social science is enhanced, the United States
would be left with unlimited modern natural right, escalating
demands for greater and greater freedom, and a politics primarily
grounded in the will to power. Like Weimar, we seem to be
experiencing a growing inability to identify and defend our highest
principles (RAM, 166).
Strauss and Voegelin both view modern humanity as having lost
access to a wisdom that insists on evaluating the use of knowledge in
terms of proper ends. Unlike Strauss, Voegelin argues that the
human horizon, which naturally includes the apperception of the
mysterious ground of human existence, suffered an artificial con-
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 321
about all beliefs yet open to the possibility of truth who, nonetheless,
did call for a return to the ancient faith for the Jew (RAM, 182). This
discussion of the Jewish problem, for Strauss, in the works of
Spinoza, Herman Cohen, and Franz Rosenzweig focuses on the
question of the relationship between orthodoxy and philosophy.
The discussion emphasizes the appropriate moral posture that
"prevents modern intellectuals from seeing clearly," according to
McAllister's interpretation of Strauss's project (RAM, 181). The
term for this moral posture, absent in these modern intellectuals, is
"intellectual probity," which appreciates the impossibility of dis-
proving revelation, seeks to understand revelation as believers
understood it, and recognizes the danger of undermining religious
beliefs through mockery. The Enlightenment thinkers "embraced
their own epistemology with such tenacity that they eliminated all
room for revelation" (RAM, 182). Strauss, in these terms, held up
orthodoxy as an intellectually defensible alternative. McAllister
claims that for Strauss, orthodoxy "serves a vital need" (RAM, 182).
McAllister describes Strauss's call for "return" as "oblique." For
many, the law is really no more, God is dead, and we find ourselves
in the sub-cave. Without the law, though, morality fades, political
order is precarious, and no specific transcendent morality can be
championed. Strauss's examination of Maimonides' prophetology
led him to conclude that Moses had seen reality beyond the cave
using his "imagination" as philosopher and prophet to see the
general theory and the particular political order. He was not the
traditional or conventional prophet; he was a gifted philosopher.
Men as social beings need such prophets to give the law, which
"must be of a sort that directs fractious human natures toward
communal harmony," according to McAllister's characterization of
Strauss (RAM, 202). The prophet is the founder of a society
dedicated to human perfection, which is, by the way, philosophy.
Moses, by providing the "divine" law, addressed the practical
philosophical needs. All subsequent philosophers should defer to
the law giver-a social order "requires a normative order that
supersedes individual conceptions of right and wrong and that binds
a people together in a common goal or purpose" (RAM, 203). The
324 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER
few must instruct the many about proper beliefs concerning heav-
enly matters, which will then allow the philosopher to interpret and
reinterpret the literal meaning of the legal text. The Torah is
enormously flexible, which allows the philosopher, even commands
him, to freely interpret the established legal foundation. This is
medieval "enlightened" reason, which rejects efforts to reshape the
world radically in contradistinction to modern "enlightened" reason,
which reversed the priority of medieval Islamic and Jewish rational-
ism-the superiority of theory over practice-and sought to recon-
struct the world. The modern enlightenment claimed that knowl-
edge and reason could replace superstition and faith as the compass
of human action. The many must be liberated from orthodox
religion. Freedom of thought was possible for the many, not just the
few. The many would be cut off from their moral roots subsequently
producing alienated and egoistic creatures. As McAllister puts it,
Strauss saw the many as gravitating toward "mass movements others
to crass consumerism, but whichever way they went, the normative
order fell apart. Not reason but passion ruled" (RAM, 204). Strauss,
states McAllister, sought "to secure a rationale for other people to
reconstruct [to return to] an old one [the insights and enlightened
reason of Farabi and Maimonides]" (RAM, 204).
Strauss's "return " to Maimonides eschewed metaphysical ques-
tions and emphasized moral-political matters. Strauss and
Maimonides as philosophers were not truly concerned with the
"source" of the law. Strauss knew enough about the life of the
philosopher to recognize the need for political philosophy (RAM,
205).
Strauss also "returns" to, or reconstructs, the Platonic concept of
philosophy, which is centered on the question of how one should
live; philosophy is a way of life rather than a rigid set of doctrines. For
Strauss, genuine philosophers live with a "mania" or existential
imperative that turns to "nature" as a means to understand the whole
without appeal to authority and with agnosticism concerning which
claims about god or the gods to believe. For Strauss, the philosopher
lives in between relativism and orthodoxy. Strauss remained in the
human realm, leaving others to examine divine things.
Interwar German-Speaking Emigres 325
Kenneth L. Deutsch
State University of New York-Geneseo
330 THE POLITICAL SCIENCE REVIEWER
NOTES
1. Quotations from Voegelin are cited in Marion Montgomery,
The Men I Have Chosen for Fathers: Literary and Philosophical
Passages (Columbia: University of Missouri Press, 1990), pp. 138-
39.
2. Quotations from David Luban, "Explaining Dark Times:
Hannah Arendt's Theory of Theory" in Lewis P. Hinchman and
Sandra K. Hinchman (eds.), Hannah Arendt: Critical Essays (Al-
bany: SUNY Press, 1994), pp. 86-87.
3. Ibid., p. 86.
4. Herbert J. Storing (ed.), Essays in the Scientific Study of
Politics (New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston, 1962), p. 221.
5. Kenneth L. Deutsch and Walter Nicgorslā (eds.), Leo Strauss:
Political Philosopher and Jewish Thinker, (Lanham: Rowman and
Littlefield Pubs., 1994), p. 52.
6. Friedrich Nietzsche, The Birth of Tragedy, trans. Hausmann
(Edinburgh, Scotland: Foulis, 1910), p. 175.