Unit 1. Law and Morality-Hart & Fuller
Unit 1. Law and Morality-Hart & Fuller
Unit 1. Law and Morality-Hart & Fuller
Natural law theory holds that along with the positive law there exist
certain ideal principles or values to which the positive law should
correspond if it is to be regarded as genuine law. Thus, while positivism
holds that to be valid law, all that is required is that it should issue from
a competent legislator after following the prescribed process, natural
law theory requires in addition that such law, to be valid, must conform
to some ideal principle (which may emanate from morality, reason,
God, or some other such source).
The "debate" began when Hart published his Holmes Lecture (entitled
Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals) delivered at Harvard
Law School in April 1957 and published in Harvard Law Review in 1958.
The reply was given by Fuller in his article "Positivism and Fidelity to
Law - A reply to Prof. Hart", also published in 1958 in Harvard Law
Review.
Hart's rejoinder was in his book The Concept of Law, to which Fuller
replied in the rst edition of his book The Morality of Law. To this Hart
gave his reply in 1965 in Harvard Law Review. Fuller replied in the
Second (Revised) Edition of The Morality of Law, published in 1969.
This ding-dong, inconclusive series of repartees and rejoinders led
Cotterrell to remark in his book The Politics of Jurisprudence:
Dynamic positivism certainly supports Hart's view that Nazi laws were
also laws (though wicked laws). But the reasons which dynamic
positivism gives are deeper and more consistent than those of Hart.
The wife's defence was that her husband had committed an o ence
under a Nazi statute of 1934. Post-war Germany, however, held the
wife liable.
Hart argued that the decision of the court was wrong, as the Nazi law of
1934 was a valid law (as it satis ed his "rule of recognition"), whereas
Fuller contended that the Nazi regime was so "lawless" that nothing
therein could qualify as law.
The basic principle of Nazi law was laid down in the Enabling Act of July
12, 1934 passed by the German Reichstag which amended the German
Constitution by permitting Hitler to issue decrees inconsistent with the
Constitution, including decrees passing the budget, making treaties,
and even amending the Constitution. As declared by Goering to the
Prussian prosecutors on July 12, 1934 "The Law and the will of the
F hrer are one".
The nature of Nazi justice has been described in William Shirer's The
Rise and Fall of the Third Reich, under the heading "Justice in the Third
Reich" (at p. 369). Nazi racial laws regarded Jews as inferior beings and
treated them inhumanly. There was total arbitrariness and terror
during Hitler's rule; the Gestapo being empowered to arrest, torture or
even kill any person without any charge or trial. Ultimately 6 million
Jews were murdered in gas chambers, apart from the other atrocities
committed by the Nazis.
Hart is right, Nazi laws were certainly laws, but such laws were wholly
inconsistent with the mode of production in industrial society (which
stage Germany had reached long before Hitler came to power), and
with the social relations engendered by such a mode of production.
Hitler's regime in fact could not have lasted long, as it was based on
features which disrupt industrial society e.g. arbitrariness and terror. In
fact Hitler's regime would have collapsed much earlier than it did had it
not received the support of Chamberlain and Daladier.
Hitler turned the German economy into a war economy1. Massive
rearmament could only lead to a parasitic economy relying on wars of
conquest, slave labour and stolen goods (from conquered countries).
The anxiety of natural law thinkers like Fuller is that unless Nazi laws
are treated as non-laws, those who perpetrated atrocities under the
Nazi regime could escape punishment.
But where does morality come from? It arises from the mode of
slavery (except stoics like Seneca, who were really on the fringe of
ancient Roman society, and not in its mainstream, and really belonged
intellectually to the subsequent Christian era). But today everyone
regards slavery as immoral. Thus any law which re ects the social
relationships of a slave society or feudal society will today be regarded
as immoral or unjust.
The Nazi regime was certainly immoral, but it was immoral because it
was totally inconsistent with the mode of production of modern
industrial society and the social relations and values which such a
society engenders. Unless one grasps this point clearly the Hart-Fuller
debate will go on endlessly.
Once this basic concept is grasped, all the talk of Fuller (and even Hart)
that there must be a "minimum degree" of morality in law in order that
it may qualify as law goes up in smoke.
Are we then to de ne law as a set of rules made for the smooth running
of society at a particular stage of historical development in conformity
with the mode of production of that stage?
The di culty with this de nition is that it does not take note of the fact
that the law often lags behind social development (as happened in pre-
revolutionary France or pre-revolutionary Russia). There can be
reactionary laws which throw society backwards. Also, as dynamic
positivism advocates, laws can be ahead of social development in order
to guide society forward.
* Mention has been made of this debate in the author's book Law in the
Scienti c Era, at p. 65 of that book. The history of the "debate" is
mentioned in the Revised Edition of Fuller's book The Morality of Law
(in Chapter V, "A Reply to Critics"). Return to Text
** This theory has been propounded by the writer in his book Law in
the Scienti c Era published by Universal Law Publishing Co. Pvt. Ltd.,
Delhi. Return to Text
1. See William Shirer's Rise and Fall of the Third Reich, under the
heading "The Economy of the Third Reich", at p. 357. Return to
Text
Fuller, in this regard is unclear about whether, for Hart, the distinction
between ‘what is’ and ‘what ought to be’ really is about morality. While
Hart consists ‘what ought to be’, from a natural law perspective - to
conserve a precious moral principle, Fuller says ‘what ought to be’ is
about preserving the delity towards law itself and not about
preserving a precious moral principle. He suggests that legal positivists
are moralizing the nature of morality when in fact, the moral input into
the legal system is already there in the positivists, when we see that the
attempt to internally reconcile, all legal principles is seen as a value
delity to the law. That value is the value outside of the legal system to
which a legal system necessarily references to.
A discussion, which began in the late 1950s between Hart and 9.1 Occasion of
Fuller, highlights some of the fundamental differences between the debate
the legal positivists and advocates of natural law. Essays by
Hart and Fuller, which appeared in the Harvard Law Review
1958, set out their reactions to certain events in Germany
following the end of the Second World War, which appeared
to revive the question of the links between law and morality.
Fuller took the general view that law and morality must not be
separated and that a law which is totally divorced from morality
ceases to be ‘law’. Hart insisted that the law is the law even
though it may not satisfy the demands of morality.
Law under the National-Socialist régime in Germany (1933– 9.2 Background to the
45) was put totally to the service of the dictatorship. The debate (1): German
German Criminal Code was amended in 1935 so as to introduce law during the era
the concept of ‘healthy popular feeling’ as a factor in the of dictatorship
determination of ‘criminality’. Punishment could be inflicted:
‘on any person who commits an act declared by the
law to be punishable, or which, in the light of the
basic purpose of the criminal law and according to
healthy popular feeling, deserves to be punished. If
there is no specific criminal law applying directly to
such an act, it is to be punished according to
whatever law in its basic purpose best applies to it.’
In similar vein, a regulation of 1936 effectively placed the 9.3 Background to the
German secret police above the law: no court was permitted to debate (2): German
interfere with that organisation’s operations. The result was law during the
that law became the willing servant of a tyranny. post-war period
9.4 The case of the Hart drew attention to the prosecution in 1949 of a German
wife-informer woman by a West German court on a charge (under the German
Criminal Code of 1871) of ‘depriving a person illegally of his
freedom’. It was alleged that during the war she had denounced
her husband, in pursuance of a personal grudge, under a statute
of 1934, for having criticised Hitler’s conduct of the war. The
husband was tried under laws of 1934 and 1938 and sentenced
to death, that sentence being commuted to service on the
Russian front. The wife’s defence was the ‘legality’ of her action;
her husband’s behaviour had contravened a law which was
valid at the time of the denunciation. She was found guilty, the
court stating that the statute under which her husband had been
sentenced was ‘contrary to the sound conscience and sense of
justice of all decent human beings’. (It should be noted that
there is a dispute as to the precise facts of the case: see Validity
of Judicial Decisions by Pappe (23 MLR 260). But the dispute does
not alter the essence of the debate.)
For a consideration by the House of Lords of Nazi race laws,
see Oppenheimer v Cattermole (1976), in which Lord Cross noted
that ‘legislation which takes away without compensation from
a section of the citizen body singled out on racial grounds all
their property…and deprives them of their
citizenship…constitutes so grave an infringement of human
rights that the courts of this country ought to refuse to recognise
it as a law at all.’
9.5 Hart opens The German court’s decision was interpreted by Hart (writing
the debate in 1958) as favouring natural law doctrine and as opposing
positivism. He took issue with Radbruch’s new stance and its
effect upon German legal thought.
Hart sympathised with Radbruch’s support for a revision of
German attitudes concerning the relationship between State
power and law.
9.5.1 The law is the law Hart insisted, however, that the law is the law, and that it remains
law even though it might not meet the demands of external moral
criteria. If a law be considered so evil that it ought not to be
obeyed, this is a separate, though worthy and relevant, issue. In
Positivism and The Separation of Law and Morals (1958), he wrote:
ItmustbestressedthatHartisnotshowinganysympathywhatsoever
with Nazi law of the 1930s. (He refers in the 1958 article to Nazi 9.5.2 A confusion of the
Germany as ‘a Hell created on earth by men for other men.’) He real issue
is pointing out that the advocates of natural law appear to be
confusing the real issue. The 1934 statute was a valid law, and it
is not possible to deny this. Its inherent evil, and how one ought
to react to this, are separate—but very important—issues. It is
confusing to say of a law that, because it rests on a stratum of
evil and results in atrocities, it is not, therefore, a law.
Law must possess certain characteristics if it is to be classified 9.6.1 The necessity of inner
correctly as ‘law’; the most important characteristic is ‘inner morality of law
morality’ which must command respect. Where there is no such
morality in an enactment there is no law. The ‘tinsel of the legal
form’ with which the Nazis sought to disguise evil required to
be analysed for what it really was.
Hart failed to realise, according to Fuller, that under the Nazi
regime, nothing existed to which the title of ‘law’ might be applied
correctly.
Fuller saw the essence of the lawlessness of the dictatorship 9.6.2 Lawlessness
exemplified in the retroactive decree by which Hitler validated exemplified
92 Jurisprudence
9.6.3 Positivism basically Fuller widens the attack and argues against the basic theory of
flawed positivism:
‘I do not think it is unfair to the positivistic
philosophy to say that it never gives any coherent
meaning to the moral obligation of fidelity to law…
The fundamental postulate of positivism—that law
must be strictly severed from morality—seems to
deny the possibility of any bridge between the
obligation to obey law and other moral obligations.’
‘As we seek order, we can meaningfully remind
ourselves that order itself will do us no good unless
it is good for something. As we seek to make our
order good, we can remind ourselves that justice
itself is impossible without order, and that we must
not lose order itself in the attempt to make it good.’
In the chapter on ‘Law and Morals’ (in The Concept of Law) Hart 9.8 The minimum
concedes that there are ‘certain rules of conduct which any content of
social organisation must contain if it is to be viable’; further, natural law
such rules may be considered as constituting a common
universal element in law within societies. The ‘human
condition’ suggests certain basic characteristics which
necessitate the creation of rules so as to protect persons and
property and to insist upon the keeping of promises.
• Human vulnerability
We are occasionally prone to, and normally vulnerable to,
bodily attack. The use of violence must, therefore, be
restricted.
• Approximate equality This makes obvious ‘the necessity
for a system of mutual forbearance and compromises which
is at the base of both legal and moral obligation’.
• Limited altruism ‘Human altruism is limited in range and
intermittent, and the tendencies to aggression are frequent
enough to be fatal to social life if not controlled.’
• Limited resources We need food, clothes and shelter, but
they are scarce. A minimal form of the institution of property
‘and the distinctive kind of rule which requires respect for
it’ are needed.
• Limited understanding and strength of will Sanctions are
required as a guarantee that persons who would usually obey
rules must not be sacrificed to those who will not. ‘What reason
demands is voluntary co-operation in a coercive system.’
These are ‘simple truisms’ which disclose ‘the core of good sense
9.8.1 Core of good sense in
in the doctrine of natural law’. It is upon their recognition and
natural law
understanding that human beings and the world they inhabit
will retain their ‘salient characteristics’.
In The Morality of Law (1963), Fuller intensified and expanded 9.9 Fuller’s response
his attack on Hart’s position. In the book he gives a detailed
exposition of the ‘morality’ which must characterise an
acceptable legal system. It is important to note that in spite of
Fuller ’s concern for morality, he does not personally accept all
the doctrines associated with classical natural law. He rejects
the Christian approach to natural law, does not accept concepts
of ‘absolute values’ and ‘natural rights’, and places no value
on the religious interpretation of ‘nature as the grand legislator’.
Fuller’s espousal of natural law reflects his basic belief that law
is a collaborative effort to aid in the satisfying of mankind’s
common needs. Each rule of law has a purpose related to the
94 Jurisprudence
9.10 The ‘internal Eight qualities which, according to Fuller, must be present in a
morality’ of law legal system if it is to deserve to command allegiance from
citizens, are enumerated as follows:
• Laws must be in existence: they must not ‘exist’ merely as ad
hoc settlements of disputes.
• Laws must be promulgated publicly: they must be made
known to persons who will be bound by them.
• Laws must not be retroactive: they must not affect adversely
persons who relied upon the law as it was.
• Laws must be intelligible and clear.
• Laws must be internally consistent through time, ie, they
must not change so that citizens are unable to orient their
actions by them.
• Laws must be free from contradictions.
• Laws must not require the impossible.
• Laws must be administered so that there is no failure of
congruence between the rules as promulgated and their
administration in practice.
9.10.1 Criticism of Fuller’s Some critics, such as Friedmann, have noted that, in fact, Fuller’s
desiderata desiderata could have been used to ‘approve’ of the Nazi legal
regime, which complied with each of the above requirements,
save, perhaps, that calling for public promulgation.
9.11 Fuller and the Given the principles which constitute the external and internal
‘lawless regime’ morality of a regime, Fuller goes on to declare that any departure
from them is an affront to the dignity of the citizen as a
responsible agent. How ought citizens (including judges and
lawyers) to react to a regime which ignores these principles as
and when it wishes? How ought individuals to behave when
The Hart-Fuller Debate 95
the legal regime under which they live assists in the systematic
denial of rights to groups of citizens?
Questions of law and morality must not—indeed, cannot—be 9.11.2 Questions of law and
separated, particularly on the basis of the arguments enunciated morality inseparable
by Hart.
D’Amato (Jurisprudence (1984)) suggests that an answer to
the Hart-Fuller controversy must be found in moral, not legal,
philosophy: ‘Unless they are infused with basic, normative
concepts, present legal theories cannot resolve such issues’.
(Note Dworkin’s argument that ‘jurisprudential issues are at
their core issues of moral principle, not legal fact or strategy’.)
Both Hart and Fuller are united in their abhorrence of the Nazi 9.12 The main issues
regime and in their approval of efforts to cleanse the succeeding in the debate: a
regime from its past taint. They are separated, however, by basic brief recapitulation
disagreement on the relationship of law and morality. For Hart,
the immorality of a law cannot constitute the basis of a denial
that it is, and will continue to be, law until properly repealed.
For Fuller, the immorality of a law, vitiates, or destroys, its right
to be called ‘law’. Specifically, a law founded upon a denial of
the principles of the ‘inner morality of the law’ is not entitled
to any respect: it is mere evil disguised by the language,
ceremonies and formalities associated with rational law. Hart
answers that morality is not law, and must not seek, therefore,
to supplant it. Fuller retorts that law and morality cannot be
separated, and a law that flies in the face of morality is no law.
Critics have suggested that, by its very nature, the Hart-Fuller 9.13 An inconclusive
debate was doomed to inconclusiveness. Terms such as ‘justice’, debate
‘morality’, ‘law’, which were fundamental to the discussion
were not defined. There appeared to be little ‘give and take’ in
the discussions. The questions which prompted the debate
remain. Societies continue to exist and prosper (in a sense)
96 Jurisprudence
Although Hart was sympathetic to the attempts of the German Hart opens the debate
legal system to cast aside all remnants of the dictatorship period,
nevertheless, he argued, law remains law even though it does
not meet the requirements of morality.
Whether a bad law (such as that allowing the denunciation
of the husband) ought to be obeyed is a significant, but entirely
separate, question.
Hart, Fuller claimed, was in error. A law must possess certain Fuller’s response
characteristics if it is to be classified correctly as ‘law’. There
was nothing in the legal system of the dictatorship which
remotely resembled true law.
Hart’s error arose from the general positivist position which
demanded a separation of law from questions of morality.
Hart responded by stressing his belief that ‘law’ and ‘morality’ Hart and the
were not interchangeable terms, so that one should not impugn ‘minimum content of
a law solely on the grounds of its lack of morality. natural law’
Hart suggested that the ‘human condition’ necessitated the
creation of minimum rules designed to protect persons,
property and rights created by promises. The ‘human condition’
revealed vulnerability, approximate equality, limited altruism,
scarce resources and a general, limited understanding and
strength of will. It was the recognition of these matters which
formed the core of good sense in the doctrine of natural law.
Fuller’s response Fuller argued further that a legal system must aim at the
subjection of human conduct to the governance of rules.
Law must have its own ‘internal morality’. It must be more
than the mere ad hoc settling of disputes; it must not be
retroactive; it must be intelligible, free from contradictions, must
not require the impossible and must produce congruence of its
declared aims and the actions of administrators.
The dictatorship in Germany had produced an essentially
‘lawless’ regime which had forfeited any right to expect
allegiance from its citizens.
Hart’s arguments illustrate the results of attempting to
separate law from morality.
An inconclusive In spite of Hart’s nod in the direction of ‘the core of good sense’
debate in the natural law, the parties to the debate remain widely
separated. For Hart it is the confusion of ‘law’ with ‘morality’
which blurs the fundamental issue: law remains law until
repealed or otherwise replaced. Fuller sees this as an inevitable,
and regrettable, result of positivist doctrine; for him man-made
law which lacks an inner morality has no claim to be recognised
as ‘true law’.
It has been suggested that the inconclusive nature of the
debate followed inevitably from a failure to define terms such
as ‘law’, ‘morality’, ‘lawlessness’.