Martinez Marzoa - Space and Nomos
Martinez Marzoa - Space and Nomos
Martinez Marzoa - Space and Nomos
any location of the limits of this space itself and thus bursts the community
whose statute should have been established. Another way to say the same
thing: regular interchange within the community (‘‘you are you, I am I,’’
‘‘this is this, that is that,’’ the distance which makes this be this and that be
that) presupposes a community, so the fact that there are binding contents,
binding things, so also the fact that the interchangeability is not general
(i.e., that things are not exchangeable for other things without limitations
as to the type of things), and so on: this history has already been related.
When I said above space as indifference to the limits began to be valid
with the Hellenistic epoch, this ‘‘began to be valid’’ was a way to refer to the
situation that results from this bursting of the polis which I have just said is
the consequence of the fact polis itself. When immediately after that I said
space as indifference as to the limits belongs to the notion of validity itself
(of being) just in the Modern Ages, I meant that, in order to understand
certain things Schmitt seems to take for granted, we must assume a situa-
tion in which not only has that community ‘‘burst,’’ but also basic supposi-
tions operate that positively involve the absence of any community, namely
that there is, at least as ruling tendency, what we call the ware,2 the thing
as exchangeable for other things without limitation as to the type of things,
which, tautologically, can occur about a thing only in the case it occurs about
every thing; this, as we have already said, implies the absence of binding
contents. The concept of ware in this sense involves the whole structure we
call civil society, and thus it is this structure that I have meant when I spoke
of basic position of space as indifference to the limits.
So something we have found as consequent expression of the civil society
(the nominal definition of ‘‘right’’ alluded to above, which actually expresses
the system of one’s not belonging to any community) seems to be the same
thing as the prospect we had found on developing (the contradiction of )
Schmitt’s scheme of the jus publicum Europaeum. This seems to give the
alleged definition of right a very central position, perhaps in the sense that
a certain structure, which makes a situation intelligible, at the same time
generates the means of challenging this situation itself; in other words: that
the formula we have presented as a nominal definition of right, this formula
whose semantic development is the system of guarantees of the political
and civil liberties, at the same time as it expresses the nature of civil society
also lays the ground for criticism about it. Criticism always consists in show-
ing that civil society itself does not comply with that formula. I will not
argue whether political power today is a unique and global entity, nor how
much this has to do with one’s not belonging to any community; what I say
is that the wrong lies not in uniqueness or global character, but in the fact
that this power, in its global doing, is no system of guarantees of political
and civil liberties but a tyranny; consistent criticism is based on this, not on
reference to particular communities. As to particular communities, if they
can do without denying others equal liberty, from this it follows by mere
logic that they entirely can do on the mere basis of the individual rights and
liberties of the individuals who will participate.
The nominal definition of ‘‘right’’ we have made use of is Kant’s concept of
right,3 including that no moral superiority can be alleged in judicial or politi-
cal questions, because Kant derives his concept of right from the consider-
ation that the object of moral judgment (tautologically) cannot be modified
by material coaction, which, as there is always material coaction, makes
it necessary to find a basis for the distinction between legitimate and ille-
gitimate material coaction, a basis which, for the reason we have adduced,
cannot be moral. It appeared to us that the way in which Schmitt’s concep-
tion conduces to what initially could be taken for its contrary is the abstract
character of his concept of the political entity or political community—the
fact that, as a matter of general principles, it must remain undecided which
types of links determine that something will or will not be a political com-
munity. In fact, this is a way (and it is Schmitt’s way) to acknowledge that
there are no obligatory contents (and thus no qualified boundaries) any-
more, which perhaps implies placing the underlying idea of right in the
region of the absence of community (so in the ‘‘Kantian’’ region).
Notes
1 Carl Schmitt, Der Begriff des Politischen (1932; Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 1987).
2 See my articles ‘‘Estado y legitimidad’’ and ‘‘Estado y pólis,’’ in Los filósofos y la política, ed.
M. Cruz (Madrid: Fondo de Cultura Económica, 1999), 85–115.
3 My interpretation of Kant’s philosophy has been developed in other publications. A re-
cent summary is my article ‘‘Reconsideración del concepto de ética autónoma,’’ in La
ortiga 33–35 (2002): 35–45.