The Clinical Application of Gene Editing: Ethical and Social Issues

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 14

Perspective

For reprint orders, please contact: [email protected]

The clinical application of gene editing:


ethical and social issues
Kelly E Ormond*,1 , Yvonne Bombard2,3 , Vence L Bonham4 , Lily Hoffman-Andrews5 ,
Heidi C Howard6,7 , Rosario Isasi8 , Kiran Musunuru9 , Kirsten A Riggan10 , Marsha Michie‡ ,11
& Megan Allyse‡ ,12
1
Department of Genetics & Stanford Center for Biomedical Ethics, Stanford University School of Medicine, Stanford, CA 94305,
USA
2
Institute of Health Policy, Management & Evaluation, University of Toronto; Li Ka Shing Knowledge Institute of St Michael’s
Hospital, Toronto, ON, Canada
3
Li Ka Shing Knowledge Institute of St Michael’s Hospital, Toronto, ON, Canada
4
Social & Behavioral Research Branch, National Human Genome Research Institute, NIH, Bethesda, MD 20892, USA
5
Penn Center for Inherited Cardiac Disease, Penn Medicine, Philadelphia, PA 19104, USA
6
Centre for Research Ethics & Bioethics, Uppsala University, Uppsala, Sweden
7
Society & Ethics Research, Connecting Science, Wellcome Genome Campus, Cambridge, UK
8
Dr J T Macdonald Foundation Department of Human Genetics, Institute of Bioethics & Health Policy, University of Miami Miller
School of Medicine, Miami, FL 33136, USA
9
Department of Medicine, Perelman School of Medicine at the University of Pennsylvania, PA 19104, USA
10
Biomedical Ethics Research Program, Mayo Clinic, Rochester, MN 55905, USA
11
Department of Bioethics, Case Western Reserve University School of Medicine, Cleveland, OH 44106, USA
12
Biomedical Ethics Research Program & Center for Individualized Medicine, Mayo Clinic, Rochester, MN 55905, USA
*Author for correspondence: [email protected]

Authors contributed equally

Gene-editing techniques have progressed rapidly in the past 5 years. There are already ongoing human
somatic gene-editing clinical trials for multiple diseases. And there has been one purported scenario of
human germline gene editing in late 2018. In this paper, we will review the current state of the technology,
discuss the ethical and social issues that surround the various forms of gene editing, as well as review
emerging stakeholder data from professionals, the ‘general public’ and individuals and families dealing
with genetic diseases potentially treatable by gene editing.

First draft submitted: 31 December 2018; Accepted for publication: 2 May 2019; Published online:
23 July 2019

Keywords: clinical trials • CRISPR • ethics • gene editing • genome editing • germline gene editing • professional
attitudes • public attitudes • somatic gene editing • stakeholder research

For nearly 40 years, scientists and clinicians have aspired to treat genetic conditions in humans by altering genes
or gene expression. While there were a number of attempts at early stage clinical trials [1], gene therapy approaches
in the 1980’s and 1990’s were ultimately unsuccessful due to challenges in delivering functioning genes to the
intended organ system and achieving sufficient gene expression for clinical impact. Only a few Phase III human
clinical trials were initiated, with one ultimately ending in the death of a participant, Jesse Gelsinger, in 1999 [2]. In
tandem to these developments, the international gene therapy policy framework has also evolved and streamlined,
shifting the research context from an exceptional approach to the one governing general biomedical research [3–5]. In
addition, across the world, somatic gene therapy in the clinical context continues to adopt a distinctive regulatory
framework specially tailored for advance innovative therapies. This approach in many jurisdictions has created in
turn an accelerated approval process and a new category for product classification such as the advanced therapy
medicinal products or similar category adopted in Europe, the USA, Japan and Korea.
The past 5–7 years have brought significant progress in both gene therapy and ‘gene-editing’ tools, including
zinc finger nucleases (ZFNs); transcription activator-like effector nucleases (TALENs) and clustered regularly
interspaced short palindromic repeats (CRISPR) [6,7]. Such tools have become increasingly more efficient and
technically easier to use [8], leading some to believe that they are ready for clinical translation in humans. By 2018,

10.2217/pme-2018-0155 
C 2019 Future Medicine Ltd Per. Med. (2019) 16(4), 337–350 ISSN 1741-0541 337
Perspective Ormond, Bombard, Bonham et al.

several preliminary human somatic gene therapy trials, to treat hemoglobinopathies, hemophilia and lysosomal
storage diseases such as MPS1, had been approved by regulatory agencies in the USA and Europe (e.g., LentiGlobin
TDT for β-thalassemia, Luxturna for inherited retinal disease due to RPE65 mutations) [9–12].
Germline gene-editing research in animals has already moved forward [13–15] and has transformed the way in which
researchers make genetically modified animal models. While many countries have laws, professional guidelines or
funding restrictions that limit or forbid human germline gene editing [16,17], a few have approved embryo research
programs. For example, the Niakan laboratory in the UK was approved in early 2016 by the Human Fertilisation
and Embryology Authority (HFEA) to do in vitro embryo research [18], and the Mitalipov laboratory in the USA
published a paper describing in vitro human embryo editing in August 2017 [19]. Nevertheless, the world was
shocked in November 2018 when He Jianku announced that he performed germline gene editing of the CCR5
gene in two recently born twins [20], particularly given that it appears the prospective parents may not have provided
informed consent.
This paper will review the technical background of gene editing, as well as the ethical and policy issues that
underlie it. We will describe research our teams and others are currently doing to address these ethical and policy
issues, and propose key areas of research and policy work that are required before any further clinical translation of
gene editing, particularly germline gene editing.

Technical background
Gene editing in humans can occur at various stages of the lifecourse: ‘somatic’ gene editing can occur during a
pregnancy or after birth, while ‘germline’ gene editing takes place with germ cells (egg or sperm) or single-cell
embryos (zygote). Somatic and germline gene editing differ with respect to the proportion of the body’s cells that
are edited. Somatic gene editing would typically affect a subset of cells, often confined to a single organ (e.g, blood,
liver, muscle). Somatic gene editing could occur either in an ex vivo manner, with re-introduction into the body after
treatment of targeted cells, or in vivo, where the editing tools are delivered directly into a patient’s body. Germline
gene editing would theoretically affect all of the cells in the person that arises from the edited germ cell or embryo,
including that person’s germ cells (except in cases of unintended mosaicism, where only a subset of the body’s cells
might be edited). Critically, germline edits would therefore be likely to propagate into future generations. Fetal
somatic gene editing would represent a unique scenario in that it is intended to alter a subset of cells, like somatic
gene editing, but because treatment occurs during fetal development, the hope would be that intervention can
ameliorate or even prevent genetic conditions. However, fetal gene editing raises concerns regarding impacts on
maternal health and the uncertainties of editing cells during crucial early development stages.
While all three types of gene editing have demonstrated feasibility in mammals [21–23], each has unique technical
challenges in humans. Data on the potential risk of ‘off-target mutations’, mutations that occur at genomic sites
other than the desired target site and therefore might introduce new disease risks (e.g., cancer), remain unclear.
‘On-target mutations’, or large insertions/deletions and complex rearrangements to the genomic site of interest, can
also occur at the target site and potentially affect genes other than the target. It is also possible that even successful
editing at the target site might confer undesirable consequences. For instance, the CCR5 gene may confer resistance
to the HIV virus but is thought to also confer greater susceptibility to West Nile virus and influenza [24,25]. There
are complex considerations to be made in balancing the potential benefits against several possible harms.
Germline gene editing presents additional unique challenges. If gene editing succeeds in only editing some of the
embryo’s cells but not others, the embryo will be mosaic, which not only limits the potential therapeutic benefits but
also potentially introduces unanticipated harms; using mosaic embryos of any kind in fertility procedures is highly
controversial [26]. Many authors have pointed out the availability of other options for a healthy and biologically
related child, including standard in vitro fertilization (IVF) coupled with preimplantation genetic testing that could
identify embryos unaffected by the disease of concern [27]. There are only a few, very rare scenarios that would
preclude any possibility of an unaffected and biologically related child using already available methods.
These scientific and technical challenges are likely to be surmountable given the rapid pace of progress in the
gene editing field. Somatic gene editing in adults has already moved into clinical trials; in January 2018, the NIH
launched the Somatic Cell Genome Editing research program to remove the barriers in implementing somatic
gene editing into clinical care [28]. The Somatic Cell Genome Editing initiative includes improving current delivery
mechanisms, gene editors and assays for testing the safety and efficacy of gene-editing tools. With this program,
NIH hopes to accelerate the field and to expedite the translation of gene-editing treatments into meaningful clinical
applications [29]. Sickle cell disease, in particular, has been recognized as a promising target for both gene therapy

338 Per. Med. (2019) 16(4) future science group


The clinical application of gene editing: ethical & social issues Perspective

Table 1. Ethical issues with gene editing.


General (across all types) • Unknown risks of harm and unintended consequences of the technology
• Challenge of defining acceptable uses and medical conditions (including nonmedical or enhancement uses, medical
tourism and biohacking)
• Human subjects protection regulation and oversight
• Inclusion of stakeholders’ views in policy making
• Addressing justice, solidarity and equity of access to successful technologies
Germline • The impact on future generations
• Legal and funding bans or moratoria on germline gene editing in many jurisdictions
• Issues in preclinical embryo research, including the large number of research embryos needed and protection for
research donors
• The need for international consensus on oversight of germline gene-editing clinical trials
Somatic: prenatal (in utero) • The need for physical intervention and potential harm to the pregnancy and/or the mother
• Concerns about research to validate interventions, particularly given that these are often historically vulnerable
populations
Somatic: childhood or adulthood • Historical research misconduct and issues in vulnerable populations with no other treatment options
• Pediatric concerns around potential developmental impact

and gene editing [30,31]; in September 2018 the National Heart, Lung, and Blood Institute (NHLBI) of the NIH
announced new initiative to help speed the development of genetic therapeutic cures for sickle cell disease (SCD).

Social & ethical implications


Beyond the scientific and technical challenges, there are complicated social, ethical and policy questions, which
we summarize in Table 1. All of these issues vary by cultural, social and political contexts, including religious
perspectives on gene modification, assisted reproductive technologies and abortion; legal policies regarding fetal
and embryo research and abortion; social attitudes toward disability and social inclusion; economic contexts of
healthcare provision and social welfare programs; the political and social status of pregnant women, children and
people with disabilities; and issues around a child’s autonomy and right to an open future. It also bears repeating
that somatic gene editing differs from germline and fetal gene editing in the potential to affect other individuals
besides the intended patient, whether currently living or in the future.

The critical value of stakeholder research & engagement


There are numerous policy and professional guidance statements that we are aware of around the appropriate use
of gene-editing technologies in humans [32–39] and we have summarized some of the key concepts they express
in Tables 2 & 3. These statements generally share a call for research on stakeholder views, especially patient and
disability groups, prior to the clinical translation of gene editing in order to contribute to set research priorities
and to inform the development of related policy and regulatory approaches. For example, the European Society of
Human Genetics states: “particularly for the purposes of gene editing, we consider SEED (Stakeholder engagement,
education and dialogue) a way to try to ensure that decisions on a subject that is filled with uncertainties, and
could have important implications for society for generations to come, is not left in the hands of a few. We want to
underline the need for: lay publics to be informed to support transparency; lay publics to be educated to support
autonomy and informed opinion/decision making; different voices and concerns to be heard and considered
through ongoing dialogue to help ensure that no one stakeholder group pursue their interests unchecked” [40]. But
what does this really mean? Who does it include? Why do it? And how do we ensure that the expectations, interests
and priorities of a diverse public are implemented in policy setting, particularly around germline gene editing.
In formulating any health policy, engagement with end users such as patient/family stakeholder and broader
citizenry is increasingly seen as critical, and is frequently required or legislated by many health policy bodies [41].
Formats for collecting such data can vary significantly, which may bias the data and make findings difficult to
generalize. And the impact varies based on who is requesting the engagement – patient or public engagement
inputs requested by a Ministry of Health, for example, are likely to have more of an impact on policies since they
are commissioned by a decision maker than those initiated by researchers or foundations or other nondecision
makers [42]. It is also worth noting that often what is labeled ‘stakeholder engagement’ is, in fact, efforts at ‘public
education’ or top-down efforts to build support for an existing research plan or policy, rather than the kinds of
collaborative and informed deliberation. For example, a recent review found that even the more robust attempts
at stakeholder engagement commonly found in HIV research have tended toward ‘researcher-driven, top-down
methods’, and toward early stage clinical trials rather than later stages with potentially more translational impact [43].

future science group www.futuremedicine.com 339


Perspective Ormond, Bombard, Bonham et al.

Table 2. Key terms in policy calls for ‘public’ engagement.


Dialog Activities, strategies and methods should support dialog or engagement that is:
• open or transparent
• urgent and/or ongoing
• responsible
• participatory, inclusive or democratic
• global (beyond local borders)
Objectives Activities, strategies and methods should have as overarching goals to:
• promote advocacy
• stimulate communication, discussion or debate
• educate or inform the target audience(s)
• provide advice, serve as a mechanism for consultation and/or support decision-making processes
• build (societal) consensus
• empower stakeholder(s) engagement and influence in decision-making processes
• facilitate issue identification (scientific, socio-ethical impact, etc.) and assessment (risks, scope, safety)
• support governance mechanisms (e.g., ethics oversight)
• inform policy-making efforts
• review effects of extant policy or its absence (e.g., impact of bans, restrictions, moratoria)
• build trustworthiness
Participants/target audience Actors and target audience(s) in/for engagement efforts are:
• stakeholders
• ‘lay’, ’general’ public or citizens
• community (national and global)
• society (e.g., local and international)
• patients
• research subjects/participants
• caregivers and members of affected families
• scientists and academics (individuals and professional organizations)
• government (national, policymakers) and governance bodies (e.g., licensing authorities and ethics review
committees)
• funding agencies (private and governmental)

Table 3. Common themes in international and professional guidelines.


Scientific integrity and strength Translation should be based only on robust, reproducible, scientific studies that demonstrate safety and efficacy
Clinical need Gene-editing technologies should be used to target disease and improve human health. Conditions that have valid
and effective medical interventions should not take priority
Precautionary approach Translation should move in a measured, conservative manner that builds on previous successes
Justice In both clinical targets and access to treatment, translation should work to address equity and reduce health
disparities
Human subjects protection Existing bioethical principles and frameworks should be observed at all times to protect the autonomy of patients,
research participants and families
Public engagement The direction and pace of translation should be the ongoing subject of widespread engagement with stakeholder
groups and publics

Collaborative efforts are more laborious and time consuming but result in more fully incorporating stakeholder
perspectives. Additional challenges include identifying appropriate stakeholder groups, the reality that stakeholder
interests will never fully align, and developing decision-making processes that balance and synthesize these divergent
– even conflicting – interests.
When thinking about which conditions warrant gene editing, issues of disability and identity are important
to consider. Members of the disability community have raised concerns about technologies to prevent the birth
of children with disabilities (such as prenatal testing and preimplantation genetic diagnosis) and even ‘cures’ or
treatments for some disabilities (such as cochlear implants; e.g. [44–52]). They believe that these technologies express
and perpetuate negative attitudes toward people with disabilities: rather than accepting people with difference,
medicine focuses on making them ‘more normal’. Indeed, particularly reproductive approaches have been criticized
for trying to eliminate traits that are a source of positive value and identity for many and constitute a form of
human diversity [53]. Studies show that members of the general public and healthcare professionals underestimate
the quality of life of people with disabilities compared with how they and their families report it, underscoring the
importance of involving stakeholders with disabilities in research and policymaking [54–60].
Finally, we argue that conducting stakeholder research improves the research process and the quality of published
research by impacting legitimacy, transparency and the quality of the policy decision [41,61–65]. Specifically, it

340 Per. Med. (2019) 16(4) future science group


The clinical application of gene editing: ethical & social issues Perspective

promotes a sense of inclusion and trustworthiness among and between stakeholders, which can help address
the historic problem of recruiting underserved or under-represented populations (both in terms of ethnicity, for
example, in the US communities participating in sickle cell research, as well as communities of rare disease and
individuals with disability potentially treated by gene editing). It can also impact approaches to consent, and
improve clinical uptake because the relevant patient populations have been included in the development of new
treatments from early in the process.

Voices of stakeholders
In response to the call for stakeholder data about attitudes toward gene editing, our various research groups have
been involved in survey, interview and focus group data collection to document the attitudes of scientists, clinicians,
the general public and patient/family stakeholder groups toward the various types of gene editing. Below, we will
summarize the currently published data and some of our own work that is pending publication.

Attitudes of scientists & clinicians


The earliest studies of stakeholder views began by assessing the knowledge and attitudes of scientists and clinicians,
due to their greater background knowledge of gene editing. Armsby et al. [66] presented work at the 2016 American
Society of Human Genetics meeting on a survey that assessed attitudes of members of various genetics professional
organizations across the globe. Five hundred respondents represented clinicians (56%), clinical lab (7%) and research
scientists (30%), and Ethical, Legal, and Social Implications (ELSI) researchers and educators (5%) covering all
continents. A second publication surveyed 300 scientists and physicians attending a cardiology professional society
meeting in 2017 [67]. Both studies found high levels of support for somatic gene-editing research and clinical
translation (as high as 70–85% depending on the specific scenarios), but lower support for germline gene-editing
research and its clinical translation. In both studies, scientists and clinicians were significantly more supportive of
therapeutic treatments (e.g., of physical or intellectual disability) in both somatic and germline settings than they
were of enhancement treatments (e.g., improving appearance, physical abilities or cognitive abilities). Researchers
also addressed whether concepts of severity influenced attitudes, although they examined it in slightly different
ways. Armsby [66] found that penetrance, age of onset, impact of condition on lifespan and degree of impairment
influenced hypothetical support, but overall prevalence of a condition did not. Musunuru et al. [67] found that
the severity of the condition being treated by germline gene editing influenced the level of support, and that 61%
found it acceptable to use germline gene editing to have a healthy biological child when there is no other means
to do so (i.e., severe genetic disorder), but fewer (45%) found it acceptable to reduce the risk of having a serious
medical condition during the lifetime.
Persaud et al. found that physicians who care for individuals with SCD [68], stressed the importance of discussing
the range of therapeutic options available both within, and outside of the gene-editing research trials, as well as
clearly explaining the purpose of Phase I clinical trials, and the implications and limitations, of participation.
“A patient needs to know that gene therapy may cure you only if you do it at birth. If you wait until you have
already suffered a stroke, renal disease, whatever. . . even if you have gene therapy, this is not going to reverse
the damage that has already occurred.” (Physician [68]).
Last, participants urged researchers to act in a manner sensitive to the fraught past between the SCD patient
community and researchers.
“I feel like we have one shot with this community. If things wane and we can’t maintain whatever is the
production of the cure, then will they have something else that they can move forward with?” (Physician [68]).

‘Public’ attitudes toward gene editing


Recent studies have begun to address views toward somatic and germline gene editing by the general public and
various citizen constituencies thereof. In 2016, the Pew Research Center surveyed approximately 2500 US adults;
in 2017 [69], the National Academies of Science and National Academies of Medicine surveyed 1600 US adults [38];
and in 2018 yougov.com surveyed approximately 5000 UK adults [70]. Studies in China and Japan have also assessed
public support for theoretical applications of gene-editing technologies [71,72]. In considering the results, however,
it is critical to take into account that such studies may be biased by how the technology and its implications are
described by the media and/or the survey tool itself and the prior knowledge (or lack thereof ) that participants have.
Prior studies in the USA have found limited understanding of genetic science and related concepts [73], although

future science group www.futuremedicine.com 341


Perspective Ormond, Bombard, Bonham et al.

CRISPR and related technologies are both too new to have been included in such studies and also have generated
considerable media hype that has likely changed public understandings in unknown ways. To our knowledge none
of the currently published studies of the general public have taken a deliberative approach where individuals were
educated over a period of time and subsequently evaluated as to their attitudes. Each study also used slightly
different wording, which can make comparisons challenging.
Despite these challenges, a key, and somewhat surprising, finding is that members of these general publics appear
to have similar levels of acceptance toward both hypothetical somatic and germline gene editing: generally around
60–70% acceptance levels for therapeutically focused gene editing [38,69]. The major distinctions appear to lie in
the intended uses of the gene editing (e.g., a therapeutic approach compared with nonmedical or enhancements).
For example, the Pew study found that 72% supported germline gene editing for treatment of a serious disease a
baby would have at birth; 60% for reduction of risk of a serious disease that could occur over the lifetime; and 19%
for use in making a baby more intelligent [69]. The UK study found that 83% would support gene editing if ‘you
were carrying genes for a genetic disorder and ran the risk of passing them on to future children’ but only 23%
supporting using it to ‘make your future children more intelligent’ and 12% supported it to ‘change your future
children’s appearance’ [70].
Finally, in a qualitative study designed to elicit views on gene editing in human embryos and somatic gene
therapy, focus group participants in the upper midwest of the USA showed results consistent with broader public
assessments [74]. Focus group participants were generally supportive of the use of gene editing to prevent or treat
serious or life-threatening congenital or adult-onset disease but were more ambivalent about using gene editing
to treat multifactorial diseases that could potentially be treated through lifestyle changes. Most opposed using
gene editing for nonmedical or enhancement purposes, such as selecting for superficial traits (eye or hair color) in
offspring. Participants expressed hope that gene-editing interventions could be used to treat serious, progressive
diseases that may potentially impact themselves or their families.
“Things that are life threatening diseases, I would attack those first. And things that are not so. . . It would be
nice if my child had blue eyes, or something, I’d say, let’s not mess with that.”
“I can see this if it was able to work and they could figure out how to do it, it could be a huge thing for
Alzheimer’s. . . Also, Parkinson’s.” [74]
Participants also expressed concerns that this technology could have unforeseen consequences to human health
or could be misused. Some participants feared vulnerable patients could be exploited by unethical scientists or
physicians, stressing the need for oversight as this technology is implemented.
“I think with the testing (germline gene editing) there can be some side effects that might be undesirable and
might be causing some other problems that might even be worse than what you’re dealing with” [74].
While it was evident that focus group participants had limited knowledge about genetics and/or the methodology
of gene editing, the ethical concerns expressed by participants reflect the published literature cited above on attitudes
in the general public, as well as the ongoing discussions by academic, industry and government stakeholders [74].

Common themes about gene editing across different disease group stakeholders
Within our various research teams, we have conducted surveys, interviews and focus groups that queried various
patient and family stakeholder groups about their attitudes toward gene editing. Thus far, this has included parents
of children with Down syndrome (DS [75]; qualitative work is ongoing, and includes comparisons to parents of
children with more medically serious aneuploidies such as trisomy 13 and 18), adults with inherited eye disorders
such as Leber congenital amaurosis (LCA) or retinitis pigmentosa [76], and adults and parents of children with
SCD [68]. Our work has thus far focused on conditions where gene-editing trials seemed imminent and on areas of
genetic disease that represent a range of features and, in some ways, identify stakeholder populations where a sense
of community or identity has been documented in the literature.
Despite the differences in age of onset, clinical presentation and overall severity of physical and intellectual
impairment involved with these conditions, we have identified a number of themes that appear to be crossing
multiple populations: qualified optimism about the potential of gene editing; conceptual similarities and differences
with previous interventions; a weighing of potential risks and benefits; the social implications of gene editing
including impacts on self identity, acceptance and inclusion; and justice and access. Participants also express

342 Per. Med. (2019) 16(4) future science group


The clinical application of gene editing: ethical & social issues Perspective

unanswered questions they have about gene-editing technologies, including the unknown harms and concerns
about the newness of treatments.

Qualified optimism about the potential of gene editing


Overall, a majority of participants across all our studies [68,75–77], demonstrated qualified optimism about the use
of gene editing as a promising (and sometimes overdue) treatment, though it often came with expressions of worry
or frustration. Individuals with inherited eye disease and parents of children with Down syndrome showed a mix
of optimism and caution. For example, parents of people with DS were more divided over the acceptability of
fetal gene editing to silence the extra chromosome 21, with half stating they would support such a therapy and
a little less than half opposed to this intervention [75]. Some parents of people with DS expressed optimism that
an intervention could improve their child’s neurocognition or reduce the physical symptoms of DS. Parents who
were hypothetically supportive of in utero chromosome silencing identified the potential increase in cognition as
an important benefit, as they believed it would enable their child to more fully integrate into society and gain
independence [77].
“I adore so many qualities about my daughter but if there was opportunity to improve cognition which would
lead to more independence and confidence I would do it”: Parent of a child with DS [77].
However, parents of people with DS were divided on what they considered to be the most appropriate therapeutic
target of a genetic intervention. Many parents expressed that they were more concerned with reducing the impact of
physical health conditions associated with DS (such as, for example, congenital heart defects) than they were about
improving their child’s neurocognition [77]; these themes are borne out in our ongoing qualitative research [78].
“If I had to choose between typical IQ and typical physical condition. . . I would choose the healthy body”:
Parent of a child with DS [77].
For people with inherited eye conditions, enthusiasm for the prospect of gene editing varied with attitudes toward
their own visual condition, with some blind adults very enthusiastic due to their perception of blindness being
highly negative in their lives, and others who were less troubled by their blindness feeling more neutral toward the
idea of curing it. However, these latter individuals were often excited about the possibility of gene-editing treatment
for other conditions that they felt were painful or life threatening [76].
The potential stage or timing of treatment was another area where we saw cautious optimism from multiple
stakeholder populations [68,74,76]. For example, families of people with DS expressed that a somatic gene-editing
intervention, even during a pregnancy may be too late to have a significant impact on the cognitive phenotype of
Down syndrome [77]. For people with retinal dystrophies, participants voiced awareness that the timing of a somatic
gene therapy intervention could make a big difference in effectiveness – both in terms of amount of vision restored
and ability to adapt to vision – but some balanced this with concerns about the ability of minors to consent to such
interventions, and of sighted adults to competently make these decisions for blind children [76].
“I think because parents know so little about blindness and generally have never met a blind person who was
living successfully they’re awash in ignorance and fear. And they’re going to do what the doctors tell them, and
doctors are no better informed than parents about reality of life as a blind person. So they’re not going to get . . .
what I might consider to be good information” [76].

Conceptual differences & similarities with previous interventions


Some observers of the gene-editing debate have argued that assigning too much ethical weight to gene editing, as
opposed to the other alternative treatments and lifestyle approaches that can be tried, amounts to a form of genomic
exceptionalism. Especially in somatic applications, one could argue that there is little difference between a gene-
editing application and a novel drug. Indeed, the US FDA regulates them in the same way. Even fetal applications
may have material parallels in the expansion of prenatal surgeries to address structural abnormalities in the developing
fetus. In both cases, there are strong models to suggest that the intervention can be effective, at least in some cases,
but also significant known risks to both mother and fetus, often in the form of miscarriage or preterm birth. Even
embryonic and germline interventions, though most commonly agreed upon in terms of ethical challenges, may
have some parallels in the early days of in vitro fertilization and cryopreservation. Although not technically gene
editing, modern-assisted reproductive procedures can involve considerable manipulation of gametes and embryos,

future science group www.futuremedicine.com 343


Perspective Ormond, Bombard, Bonham et al.

manipulations that, at least in the early days, might well have had considerable unintended consequences. In our
research, both parents and affected individuals grapple with the fact that whether an intervention involves gene
editing materially affects their willingness to accept it on behalf of themselves and their children. Prenatal and
pediatric interventions also share complex moral questions about the role of parenting and what the duties of a
future or current parent are to their offspring. One parent of a child with DS recalled, “having a son who went
through heart surgery, the doctor explained chasing perfection can do more damage than help. Basically leave well enough
alone.”

Weighing of potential risks & benefits


All the participant groups we assessed stressed that no matter how great the potential benefits of any suggested
intervention were, the risks may make it not worth it. Participants often focused in on potential treatment risks,
including the concept of unintended negative effects and unknown impact [68,77].
“Injecting genes is in my opinion too far. Genetically modifying human beings, and without any knowledge of
long-term effects? Nope”: Parent of a child with DS [77].
“I’m really talking about changing someone’s DNA. There is always that unintended consequence. You do A,
but with the unknown potential?”: Parent of a child with SCD [68].
Participants also stressed the remaining uncertainty about what the risks and benefits entail, and were able to
articulate trade offs that they were and were not willing to make. Many parents indicated their support would
depend upon the level of risk involved [68,77], particularly, if there were any chance it could potentially exacerbate
disease severity [68,76]. Or would only partially impact their medical condition [76].
“The question I think for me would ultimately come down to a lot of details. One is the cost, another is
the treatment procedures. The risk, the downside risks as well as the upside potential. And then whether it’s
something I’d have to do repeatedly, or is it like this one time thing . . . Because I do have some vision at this
point in time, if there’s a risk I could lose what I have, that would be a factor . . . And if we’re talking about
only a marginal increase in my vision . . . then I might be much less inclined than if we’re talking about a large
enough increase . . . that it would have a meaningful impact on the functional utility of the vision I have”:
Patient with LCA [76].
The genetic nature of proposed interventions was, however, specifically mentioned in terms of its impact on
reproductive choice and future offspring [68].

Social implications of gene editing: self identity, acceptance & inclusion


The expressivist arguments described above were articulated by participants across all our studies thus far. For
example, many persons with visual impairments and parents of children with DS described a high quality of life
and opposed the medicalization of their difference [76,79].
“Every single thing I was told has been wrong. My daughter is smart, is competent, independent”: Parent of
child with DS [79].
“I personally wouldn’t choose blindness as an early priority for this technology . . . I would be much more excited
about something that could prevent or treat breast cancer, for example . . . .”: Patient with LCA [76].
A very interesting theme emerged in several interviews of individuals who themselves had a genetic condition,
around identity as it relates to impairment and the potential impact of gene-editing technologies:
“I’ve already lived some of my life and I enjoyed it pretty damn good. And as I said, I love everything about it.
And what if we gave that chance to an embryo and we didn’t give them retinitis pigmentosa and maybe their
life wasn’t wonderful and great and we took away that retinitis pigmentosa . . . I’m not saying that it would
have been, but . . . what I’m saying is that I don’t think it’s really truly up to us to decide that”: Participant
with retinitis pigmentosa [76].
There were some respondents who worried treatments and technology created false hopes and delayed adjustment:

344 Per. Med. (2019) 16(4) future science group


The clinical application of gene editing: ethical & social issues Perspective

“I really worry about this sort of chimera of hope that we’re going to fix all these blind people and give them
sight and it leads people to go through life waiting for cure rather than living a life. . . . and it just seems to be
so stultifying, so ultimately emotionally damaging”: Patient with LCA [76].
Participants in several stakeholder groups [76] raised global issues around how gene-editing treatments could impact
on evolution, both scientifically and socially, and the negative impact of losing heterogeneity in society, a sort of
‘counter-eugenic logic’ (Garland–Thomson, 2012). Parents of children with DS stressed the unique contributions
of their child to society, including their role in teaching others tolerance and inclusivity, and others articulated that
the burden should be on society to become more inclusive of those with intellectual or other disabilities, not to
treat or cure the phenotypes [76,79].
“We have been so blessed by him (son with DS) exactly the way he is. A world without Down syndrome seems
sad too”: Parent of a child with DS [79].
“I just don’t want people to think, oh my goodness, don’t worry blind people, so what if the unemployment rate
amongst blind people is 70% . . . now with gene editing, all the blind people will be able to see and now they’ll
be able to be employed . . . society is going to think, oh no need to make accessibility our prime focus or making
accommodations . . . because there will be no more blind people”: Participant with retinitis pigmentosa [76].
Interestingly, concerns about how the widespread adoption of gene editing may impact the disability community
were a theme also spontaneously brought up by general public focus group participants. These participants stressed
the societal benefits of diversity and the lessons that can be learned from the inclusion and acceptance of disabled
people.
“Maybe having people with disabilities teaches the rest of us more compassion or gives us more diversity in our
community to give us a better perspective on what the variation in life is all about”: Public participant [74].
Finally, some participants, both members of the general public [74] and individuals with blindness [76] expressed
fear that parents could be socially or financially pressured into accepting gene editing for their child’s condition
through the denial of social services or insurance coverage if genetic intervention is declined.
“If you don’t get your embryo fixed, you can’t get paid for the expenses. I think it’s a way off but it could happen”:
Public participant [74].

Social implications of gene editing: justice & equity


The principle of ‘fairness’ is a core ethical and health equity principle to guide implementation of gene-editing
research and clinical treatment. The National Academy of Science (NAS) report [38] describes fairness as the
principle that ‘requires like cases be treated alike, and that risks and benefits be equitably distributed (distributive
justice). Responsibilities that flow from adherence to this principle include equitable distribution of the burdens
and benefits of research; and broad and equitable access to the benefits of resulting clinical applications of human
genome editing’ [38].
Equity and fairness was a dominant theme expressed by patients and families of individuals with sickle cell [68]
and inherited blindness [76]:
“If this treatment becomes available to the public, will it be available to everyone equally? I am not rich, but I
qualify. I have sickle cell. I struggle with it daily”: Patient with SCD [68].
“The people who are left behind would be the people in the lower socioeconomic echelons. . . a lot of the impetus
for developing technology that blind people can use and the impetus for fighting for laws and fighting for rights
has come from people who have education, who have been raised to feel empowered and articulate. And who’ve
had families who have been able to push for them. So if those people all disappear, who’s going to fight for
everybody else? They’re going to be forgotten”: Participant with LCA [76].
The stakeholders in several studies questioned who will actually benefit from the gene editing. For example, the
global burden of SCD is not in the USA and Europe, but primarily in sub-Saharan Africa and India. It is estimated
that between 300,000 and 400,000 babies are born with SCD each year [80].
“Because it’s a minority illness, it doesn’t get the consideration that it should” [68].

future science group www.futuremedicine.com 345


Perspective Ormond, Bombard, Bonham et al.

Conclusion
Gene-editing technologies are rapidly moving toward clinical incorporation without clear knowledge of the potential
benefits and harms. As the scientific research moves forward, parallel stakeholder research is critical in building
trustworthy and transparent research agendas, and in developing national and international policies that reflect key
priorities and concerns of stakeholders.

Future perspective
As novel gene-editing technologies move closer and closer to the clinic and the potential to treat genetic disease
somatically and through germline editing approaches, many ethical, policy and translational challenges remain. As
scientific and social science researchers, we must continue to identify relevant ethical questions from the perspective
of a broad range of stakeholder groups, and to do so in parallel with clinical trials (moving beyond the thus
far hypothetical assessments). We must also encourage ongoing engagement among biological scientists, patient
advocates, and bioethics and humanities researchers with the skills and experience to conduct healthcare policy
research. Several observers have called for novel approaches to building broader and more inclusive collaborations
that take into account the complex ethical, social and legal implications of these burgeoning technologies [81].
At the same time, there are lessons to be learned from the clinical translation of science and technology in
the past. There are some public health processes in place for translating genetic technologies (e.g., Evaluation of
Genomic Applications in Practice and Prevention [EGAPP]). In particular, the precautionary role of patient and
bioethics stakeholders may be compromised if they are viewed as being too embedded in the translational process,
to the point where translational determinism – the idea that any form of successful translation is a necessary and
a priori good – sets in, in which case they are often criticized for being co-opted. All stakeholders – researchers,
clinicians, advocates, and health services and policy scholars – must remain aware that the prospect of saving lives
and removing disease burden can override more precautionary approaches to scientific discovery and public health.
The example of He Jiankui, who has claimed that his controversial application of embryonic gene editing was
justified in the service of eliminating the HIV virus, is a stark example of how scientific ambition and a narrow
focus on genetics as ‘the answer’ can lead to undesirable outcomes [82].
A typical normative approach is to call for public or stakeholder engagement so that policy decisions can reflect
societal interests and values. These policies often emanate from national or international professional organizations
or funding agencies and are seldom incorporated into laws or governmental regulations [35,83]. As such, these policies
are usually nonbinding and legally unenforceable. In addition, they frequently fail to establish a concrete mechanism
for implementation, or even to resolve differing views from different stakeholder populations. Yet the influence
of such recommendations should not be underestimated. Acknowledging the role of public engagement in the
deliberate policy-making process creates normative responsibilities for those in charge, making them accountable
for potential inaction. Equally important is the role that funders and professional organizations play as agents for
policy transfer: these institutions provide a mechanism for the development and dissemination of best practices
and exert pressure on other stakeholders, including governments, to act accordingly.
One of the challenges in moving forward is arriving at an ethical policy decision. To do so, we must bridge
the chasm between descriptive ethics (i.e., what people believe should be done) and normative ethics (i.e., what
ethical principles oblige), perspectives that are sometimes considered irreconcilable [84]. However, using patient or
public engagement methods in systematic and robust studies to elicit ethical values can be a first step toward such
bridging. Empirical evidence from patient/public engagement can be used to excavate core values or principles,
which can in turn be used to formulate concrete policies. Thus, patient/public engagement approaches to explore
ethical issues can identify values and positions of communities, clarify meanings and perspectives of stakeholders,
and ultimately portray the full complexity of the issues to enhance decision making and policy development.

Acknowlegments
The authors would like to acknowledge work by A Persaud (Social and Behavioral Research Branch, National Human Genome
Research Institute), A Armsby and E Snure (Stanford MS Human Genetics and Genetic Counseling program).

Financial & competing interests disclosure


M Allyse is supported by NIH grant K01HG009542. Y Bombard is supported by a New Investigator Award from the Canadian
Institutes of Health Research. VL Bonham is supported by Division of Intramural Research, National Human Genome Research
Institute ZIAHG200394. HC Howard is supported by the Swedish Research Council grant 2017-01710. The authors have no other

346 Per. Med. (2019) 16(4) future science group


The clinical application of gene editing: ethical & social issues Perspective

relevant affiliations or financial involvement with any organization or entity with a financial interest in or financial conflict with the
subject matter or materials discussed in the manuscript apart from those disclosed.
No writing assistance was utilized in the production of this manuscript.

Author contributions
All authors contributed in conceptualization, review and editing. KE Ormond prepared the original draft.

Executive summary
Background
• There are several currently used gene-editing techniques including clustered regularly interspaced short
palindromic repeats, transcription activator-like effector nucleases and zinc finger nucleases.
• Somatic gene-editing clinical trials have already begun in humans for several diseases, with more set for 2019.
• Germline gene editing has been performed in animals, and there are publications on human in vitro studies.
Human germline gene editing was reported in November 2018, but has not yet been published in a peer
reviewed setting.
Technical background
• Safety and effectiveness data are still limited for all types of gene editing in humans.
Stakeholder research
• Research has addressed hypothetical attitudes toward somatic and germline gene editing in various professional
groups, general publics (typically without deliberative education), and family and individuals faced with specific
genetic diseases.
Common themes
• Common themes that arise in the available patient/family stakeholder research include: qualified optimism
about the potential of gene editing; conceptual similarities and differences with previous interventions; a
weighing of potential risks and benefits; the social implications of gene editing including impacts on self identity,
acceptance and inclusion; and justice and access.

References
Papers of special note have been highlighted as: • of interest; •• of considerable interest
1. Gene Therapy Clinical Trials Worldwide. www.abedia.com/wiley/phases.php
2. Sibbald B. Death but one unintended consequence of gene-therapy trial. CMAJ 164(11), 1612 (2001).
3. Carvalho M, Martins AP, Sepodes B. Hurdles in gene therapy regulatory approval: a retrospective analysis of European marketing
authorization applications. Drug Discov. Today 24(3), 823–828 (2018).
4. Carvalho M, Sepodes B, Martins AP. Regulatory and scientific advancements in gene therapy: state-of-the-art of clinical applications and
of the supporting European regulatory framework. Front. Med. 4, 182 (2017).
5. Halioua-Haubold C-L, Peyer JG, Smith JA et al. Regulatory considerations for gene therapy products in the US, EU, and Japan. Yale J.
Biol. Med. 90(4), 683–693 (2017).
6. Kim J-S. Genome editing comes of age. Nat. Protoc. 11(9), 1573–1578 (2016).
7. Carroll D. Genome editing: past, present, and future. Yale J. Biol. Med. 90(4), 653–659 (2017).
8. Dunbar CE, High KA, Joung JK, Kohn DB, Ozawa K, Sadelain M. Gene therapy comes of age. Science 359(6372), eaan4672 (2018).
9. A safety and efficacy study of TALEN and CRISPR/Cas9 in the treatment of HPV-related cervical intraepithelial neoplasial (2017).
https://clinicaltrials.gov/ct2/show/NCT03057912
10. NY-ESO-1-redirected CRISPR (TCRendo and PD1) edited T cells (NYCE T cells) (2018).
https://clinicaltrials.gov/ct2/show/NCT03399448
11. Ascending dose study of genome editing by the zinc finger nuclease (ZFN) therapeutic SB-318 in subjects with MPS I (2016).
https://clinicaltrials.gov/ct2/show/NCT02702115
12. A study to assess the safety, tolerability, and efficacy of ST-400 for treatment of transfusion-dependent β-thalassemia (TDT) (2018).
https://clinicaltrials.gov/ct2/show/NCT03432364?term=genome+editing&rank=6
13. Geurts AM, Cost GJ, Freyvert Y et al. Knockout rats via embryo microinjection of zinc-finger nucleases. Science 325(5939), 433 (2009).
14. Yang H, Wang H, Shivalila CS, Cheng AW, Shi L, Jaenisch R. One-step generation of mice carrying reporter and conditional alleles by
CRISPR/Cas-mediated genome engineering. Cell 154(6), 1370–1379 (2013).
15. Liu H, Chen Y, Niu Y et al. TALEN-mediated gene mutagenesis in rhesus and cynomolgus monkeys. Cell Stem Cell 14(3), 323–328
(2014).

future science group www.futuremedicine.com 347


Perspective Ormond, Bombard, Bonham et al.

16. Isasi R, Knoppers BM. Oversight of human inheritable genome modification. Nat. Biotechnol. 33(5), 454–455 (2015).
• Discusses international legal and regulatory issues around genome modification of various types.
17. Regulation (EU) No 536/2014 of the EUROPEAN parliament and of the council of 16 April 2014 on clinical trials on medicinal
products for human use, and repealing directive 2001/20/EC.
https://ec.europa.eu/health/sites/health/f iles/f iles/eudralex/vol-1/reg 2014 536/reg 2014 536 en.pdf
18. Expert reaction to HFEA granting first UK licence for use of genome editing techniques on human embryos, Science Media Centre.
www.sciencemediacentre.org/expert-reaction-to-hf ea-granting-first-uk-licence-for-use-of -genome-editing-techniques-on-human-em
bryos/
19. Ma H, Marti-Gutierrez N, Park S-W et al. Correction of a pathogenic gene mutation in human embryos. Nature 548, 413–419 (2017).
20. AP News. Chinese researcher claims first gene-edited babies (2018). www.apnews.com/4997bb7aa36c45449b488e19ac83e86d
• Breaking news story about the Chinese germline gene-editing situation in November 2018.
21. Wang H, Yang H, Shivalila CS et al. One-step generation of mice carrying mutations in multiple genes by CRISPR/Cas-mediated
genome engineering. Cell 153(4), 910–918 (2013).
22. Ding Q, Strong A, Patel KM et al. Permanent alteration of PCSK9 with in vivo CRISPR-Cas9 genome editing. Circ. Res. 115(5),
488–492 (2014).
23. Rossidis AC, Stratigis JD, Chadwick AC et al. In utero CRISPR-mediated therapeutic editing of metabolic genes. Nat. Med. 24(10),
1513–1518 (2018).
24. Lim JK, Murphy PM. Chemokine control of west Nile virus infection. Exp. Cell Res. 317(5), 569–574 (2011).
25. Falcon A, Cuevas MT, Rodriguez-Frandsen A et al. CCR5 deficiency predisposes to fatal outcome in influenza virus infection. J. Gen.
Virol. 96(8), 2074–2078 (2015).
26. Ethics Committee of the American Society for Reproductive Medicine. Transferring embryos with genetic anomalies detected in
preimplantation testing: an Ethics Committee opinion. Fertil. Steril. 107(5), 1130–1135 (2017).
27. Lander ES. Brave new genome. N. Engl. J. Med. 373(1), 5–8 (2015).
28. NIH. NIH to launch genome editing research program (2018).
www.nih.gov/news-events/news-releases/nih-launch-genome-editing-research-program
29. Perry ME, Valdes KM, Wilder E, Austin CP, Brooks PJ. Genome editing to ‘re-write’ wrongs. Nat. Rev. Drug Discov. 17(10), 689–690
(2018).
30. Ribeil J-A, Hacein-Bey-Abina S, Payen E et al. Gene therapy in a patient with sickle cell disease. N. Engl. J. Med. 376(9), 848–855 (2017).
31. Demirci S, Uchida N, Tisdale JF. Gene therapy for sickle cell disease: an update. Cytotherapy 20(7), 899–910 (2018).
32. Canadian Institutes of Health Research. Human germline gene editing: points to consider from a Canadian perspective (2016).
www.cihr-irsc.gc.ca/e/documents/sce human germline gene editing en.pdf
33. Hellenic National Bioethics Commission. Recent developments in human genome modification: genome editing (2016).
www.bioethics.gr/images/pdf/GNOMES/OPINION gene%20editing Final EN.pdf
34. Science Council of Japan. Genome editing technology in medical sciences and clinical applications in Japan (2017).
www.scj.go.jp/ja/inf o/kohyo/pdf/kohyo-23-t251-1-en.pdf
35. Ormond KE, Mortlock DP, Scholes DT et al. Human germline genome editing. Am. J. Hum. Genet. 101(2), 167–176 (2017).
• American Society of Human Genetics (ASHG) Germline Gene Editing Professional Society statement 2017, with many
international organizations signing on in support.
36. ACMG Board of Directors. Genome editing in clinical genetics: points to consider – a statement of the American College of Medical
Genetics and Genomics. Genet. Med. 19, 723–724 (2017).
37. Nuffield Council on Bioethics. Genome editing: an ethical review (2016).
http://nuff ieldbioethics.org/project/genome-editing/ethical-review-published-september-2016
38. National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine. Human Genome Editing: Science, Ethics, and Governance. The National
Academies Press, WA, USA (2017). www.nap.edu/catalog/24623/human-genome-editing-science-ethics-and-governance
•• Major organizational statement from the US National Academies about both somatic and germline gene editing, including ethics.
39. Juengst ET, Henderson GE, Walker RL et al. Is enhancement the price of prevention in human gene editing? CRISPR J. 1(6), 351–354
(2018).
40. Howard HC, van El CG, Forzano F et al. One small edit for humans, one giant edit for humankind? Points and questions to consider for
a responsible way forward for gene editing in humans. Eur. J. Hum. Genet. 26(1), 1–11 (2018).
• European Society of Human Genetics (ESHG) professional statement about gene editing from the EU 2018.
41. Bombard Y, Abelson J, Simeonov D, Gauvin F-P. Eliciting ethical and social values in health technology assessment: a participatory
approach. Soc. Sci. Med. 73(1), 135–144 (2011).

348 Per. Med. (2019) 16(4) future science group


The clinical application of gene editing: ethical & social issues Perspective

42. Abelson J, Bombard Y, Gauvin F-P, Simeonov D, Boesveld S. Assessing the impacts of citizen deliberations on the health technology
process. Int. J. Technol. Assess. Health Care 29(3), 282–289 (2013).
43. Day S, Blumberg M, Vu T, Zhao Y, Rennie S, Tucker JD. Stakeholder engagement to inform HIV clinical trials: a systematic review of
the evidence. J. Int. AIDS Soc. 21(Suppl. 7), e25174 (2018).
44. Asch A, Wasserman D. Reproductive testing for disability. In: The Routledge Companion to Bioethics. Arras JD, Fenton E, Kukla
R (Eds). Taylor and Francis, NY, USA (2015).
45. Chen EA, Schiffman JF. Attitudes toward genetic counseling and prenatal diagnosis among a group of individuals with physical
disabilities. J. Genet. Couns. 9(2), 137–152 (2000).
46. Parens E, Asch A. Disability rights critique of prenatal genetic testing: reflections and recommendations. Ment. Retard. Dev. Disabil. Res.
Rev. 9(December 2002), 40–47 (2003).
47. Mand C, Duncan R, Gillam L, Collins V, Delatycki M. Clinical ethics: genetic selection for deafness: the views of hearing children of
deaf adults. J. Med. Ethics 35(12), 722–728 (2009).
48. Boardman FK. The expressivist objection to prenatal testing: the experiences of families living with genetic disease. Soc. Sci. Med. 107,
18–25 (2014).
49. Bryant L, Hewison JD, Green JM. Attitudes towards prenatal diagnosis and termination in women who have a sibling with Down’s
syndrome. J. Reprod. Infant Psychol. 23(2), 181–198 (2005).
50. Crouch RA. Letting the deaf be deaf reconsidering the use of cochlear implants in prelingually deaf children. Hastings Cent. Rep. 27(4),
14–21 (1997).
51. Hahn HD, Belt TL. Disability identity and attitudes toward cure in a sample of disabled activists. J. Health Soc. Behav. 45(4), 453–464
(2004).
52. Check Hayden E. Should you edit your children’s genes? Nature News 530(7591), 402 (2016).
53. Skotko BG. With new prenatal testing, will babies with Down syndrome slowly disappear? Arch. Dis. Child. 94(11), 823–826 (2009).
54. Skotko BG, Levine SP, Goldstein R. Self-perceptions from people with Down syndrome. Am. J. Med. Genet. A 155A(10), 2360–2369
(2011).
55. Skotko BG, Levine SP, Goldstein R. Having a son or daughter with Down syndrome: perspectives from mothers and fathers. Am. J.
Med. Genet. A 155A(10), 2335–2347 (2011).
56. Skotko BG, Levine SP, Goldstein R. Having a brother or sister with Down syndrome: perspectives from siblings. Am. J. Med. Genet.
A 155A(10), 2348–2359 (2011).
57. Boardman FK, Young PJ, Griffiths FE. Impairment experiences, identity and attitudes towards genetic screening: the views of people
with spinal muscular atrophy. J. Genet. Couns. 27(1), 69–84 (2018).
58. Goering S. ‘You Say You’re Happy, but. . . ’: contested quality of life judgments in bioethics and disability studies. J. Bioeth. Inq. 5(2-3),
125–135 (2008).
59. Crocker TF, Smith JK, Skevington SM. Family and professionals underestimate quality of life across diverse cultures and health
conditions: systematic review. J. Clin. Epidemiol. 68(5), 584–595 (2015).
60. Albrecht GL, Devlieger PJ. The disability paradox: high quality of life against all odds. Soc. Sci. Med. 48(8), 977–988 (1999).
61. Abelson J, Giacomini M, Lehoux P, Gauvin F-P. Bringing ‘the public’ into health technology assessment and coverage policy decisions:
from principles to practice. Health Policy 82(1), 37–50 (2007).
62. Goodman MS, Sanders Thompson VL. The science of stakeholder engagement in research: classification, implementation, and
evaluation. Transl. Behav. Med. 7(3), 486–491 (2017).
63. Israel BA, Schulz AJ, Parker EA, Becker AB. Review of community-based research: assessing partnership approaches to improve public
health. Annu. Rev. Public Health 19, 173–202 (1998).
64. Eder MM, Evans E, Funes M et al. Defining and measuring community engagement and community-engaged research: clinical and
translational science institutional practices. Prog. Community Health Partnersh. 12(2), 145–156 (2018).
65. Corbie-Smith G, Wynn M, Richmond A et al. Stakeholder-driven, consensus development methods to design an ethical framework and
guidelines for engaged research. PLoS ONE 13(6), e0199451 (2018).
66. ASHG Press: Survey results: genetics specialists’ views on genome editing (2017). www.ashg.org/press/201710-geneticist-views.shtml
67. Musunuru K, Lagor WR, Miano JM. What do we really think about human germline genome editing, and what does it mean for
medicine? Circ. Cardiovasc. Genet. 10(5), pii: e001910 (2017).
• Early stakeholder work on how clinicians and clinician scientists view gene editing.
68. Persaud A, Desine S, Blizinsky K, Bonham VL. A CRISPR focus on attitudes and beliefs towards somatic genome editing from
stakeholders within the sickle cell disease community. Genet. Med. doi:10.1038/s41436-018-0409-6 (2018) (Epub ahead of print).
• Early stakeholder research on a condition, sickle cell disease, where gene-editing trials are about to begin (and gene therapy trials
are ongoing).

future science group www.futuremedicine.com 349


Perspective Ormond, Bombard, Bonham et al.

69. Pew Research Center: Internet, science & tech. Public views of gene editing for babies depend on how it would be used (2018).
www.pewinternet.org/2018/07/26/public-views-of -gene-editing-for-babies-depend-on-how-it-would-be-used/
70. YouGov. Most Brits say gene editing to reduce risk of disease should be allowed (2018).
https://yougov.co.uk/topics/science/articles-reports/2018/10/10/most-brits-say-gene-editing-reduce-risk-disease-sh
71. Uchiyama M, Nagai A, Muto K. Survey on the perception of germline genome editing among the general public in Japan. J. Hum.
Genet. 63(6), 745–748 (2018).
72. McCaughey T, Budden DM, Sanfilippo PG et al. A need for better understanding is the major determinant for public perceptions of
human gene editing. Hum. Gene Ther. 30(1), 36–43 (2018).
73. Hurle B, Citrin T, Jenkins JF et al. What does it mean to be genomically literate?: National Human Genome Research Institute meeting
report. Genet. Med. 15(8), 658–663 (2013).
74. Riggan KA, Sharp RR, Allyse M. Where will we draw the line? public opinions of human genome editing. Qual. Health
Res. doi:10.1177/1049732319846867 (2019) (Epub ahead of print).
75. Michie M, Allyse M. Gene modification therapies: views of parents of people with Down syndrome. Genet. Med. 21, 487–492 (2019).
• Early stakeholder research on how parents of children with Down syndrome think about potential gene-editing therapies.
76. Hoffman-Andrews L, Mazzoni R, Pacione M, Garland-Thomson R, Ormond KE. Attitudes of people with inherited retinal conditions
toward gene editing technology. Mol. Genet. Genomic Med. doi: 10.1002/mgg3.803 (Epub ahead of print).
77. Riggan KA, Nyquist C, Michie M, Allyse M. Evaluating the risks and benefits of genetic and pharmacology interventions for Down
syndrome. AJIDD (In Press).
78. Snure E, Deutich N, Michie M, Riggan K, Allyse M, Ormond K. Attitudes towards gene editing technologies in parents of people with
trisomy 21. Poster presented at: American College of Medical Genetics and Genomics Conference Seattle. WA, USA (2019).
79. Allyse M, Nyquist C, Simonson G, Michie M. Gene therapy for congenital genetic conditions: views of parents. Poster presented at:
American College of Medical Genetics and Genomics Conference NC, USA (2018).
80. Piel FB, Hay SI, Gupta S, Weatherall DJ, Williams TN. Global burden of sickle cell anaemia in children under five, 2010–2050:
modelling based on demographics, excess mortality, and interventions. PLoS Med. 10(7), e1001484 (2013).
81. Jasanoff S, Hurlbut JB, Saha K. CRISPR democracy: gene editing and the need for inclusive deliberation. Issues Sci. Technol. 32(1),
25–32 (2015).
82. Cyranoski D, Ledford H. How the genome-edited babies revelation will affect research. Nature (2018).
www.nature.com/articles/d41586-018-07559-8
83. Isasi R, Kleiderman E, Knoppers BM. Editing policy to fit the genome? Framing genome editing policy requires setting thresholds of
acceptability. Science 351(6271), 337–339 (2016).
84. Kenny N, Giacomini M. Wanted: a new ethics field for health policy analysis. Health Care Anal. 13(4), 247–260 (2005).

350 Per. Med. (2019) 16(4) future science group

You might also like