Chesterton Essays

Download as txt, pdf, or txt
Download as txt, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 143

THE COMMON MAN

by
G. K. Chesterton
First Published 1950
By Sheed And Ward, Inc.
New York
THE COMMON MAN
A MIDSUMMER NIGHT'S DREAM
ON READING
MONSTERS AND THE MIDDLE AGES
WHAT NOVELISTS ARE FOR
THE SONG OF ROLAND
THE SUPERSTITION OF SCHOOL
THE ROMANCE OF A RASCAL
PAYING FOR PATRIOTISM
THE PANTOMIME
READING THE RIDDLE
A TALE OF TWO CITIES
GOD AND GOODS
FROM MEREDITH TO RUPERT BROOKE
THE DANGERS OF NECROMANCY
GIOTTO AND ST. FRANCIS
THE NEW GROOVE
THE REAL DR. JOHNSON
RABELAISIAN REGRETS
THE HOUND OF HEAVEN
THE FRIVOLOUS MAN
TWO STUBBORN PIECES OF IRON
HENRY JAMES
THE STRANGE TALK OF TWO VICTORIANS
LAUGHTER
TALES FROM TOLSTOI
THE NEW CASE FOR CATHOLIC SCHOOLS
VULGARITY
THE REVIVAL OF PHILOSOPHY--WHY?
VANDALISM
ELIZABETH BARRETT BROWNING
THE ERASTIAN ON THE ESTABLISHMENT
THE END OF THE MODERNS
WALTER DE LA MARE
THE MEANING OF METRE
CONCERNING A STRANGE CITY
THE EPITAPH OF PIERPONT MORGAN
THE NEW BIGOTRY
BOOKS FOR BOYS
THE OUTLINE OF LIBERTY
A NOTE ON NUDISM
CONSULTING THE ENCYCLOPAEDIA
IF I HAD ONLY ONE SERMON TO PREACH
IF DON JOHN OF AUSTRIA HAD MARRIED MARY QUEEN OF SCOTS
THE COMMON MAN
The explanation, or excuse, for this essay is to be found
in a certain notion, which seems to me very obvious, but which I
have never, as it happens, seen stated by anybody else. It happens
rather to cut across the common frontiers of current controversy.
It can be used for or against Democracy, according to whether that
swear-word is or is not printed with a big D. It can be connected,
like most things, with religion; but only rather indirectly
with my own religion. It is primarily the recognition of a fact,
quite apart from the approval or disapproval of the fact.
But it does involve the assertion that what has really happened,
in the modern world, is practically the precise contrary of what is
supposed to have happened there.
The thesis is this: that modern emancipation has really been
a new persecution of the Common Man. If it has emancipated anybody,
it has in rather special and narrow ways emancipated the Uncommon Man.
It has given an eccentric sort of liberty to some of the hobbies
of the wealthy, and occasionally to some of the more humane
lunacies of the cultured. The only thing that it has forbidden is
common sense, as it would have been understood by the common people.
Thus, if we begin with the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries,
we find that a man really has become more free to found a sect.
But the Common Man does not in the least want to found a sect.
He is much more likely, for instance, to want to found a family.
And it is exactly there that the modern emancipators are quite
likely to begin to frustrate him; in the name of Malthusianism
or Eugenics or Sterilisation or at a more advanced stage of progress,
probably, Infanticide. It would be a model of modern liberty to tell
him that he might preach anything, however wild, about the Virgin Birth,
so long as he avoided anything like a natural birth; and that
he was welcome to build a tin chapel to preach a twopenny creed,
entirely based on the text, "Enoch begat Methuselah", so long
as he himself is forbidden to beget anybody. And, as a matter
of historical fact, the sects which enjoyed this sectarian freedom,
in the seventeenth or eighteenth centuries, were generally founded
by merchants or manufacturers of the comfortable, and sometimes
of the luxurious classes. On the other hand, it is strictly
to the lower classes, to use the liberal modern title for the poor,
that such schemes as Sterilisation are commonly directed and applied.
It is the same when we pass from the Protestant world of
the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries to the Progressive
world of the nineteenth and twentieth. Here the form of freedom
mostly claimed, as a boast and a dogma, is the freedom of the Press.
It is no longer merely a freedom of pamphlets but a freedom of papers;
or rather, it is less and less a freedom at all, and more and
more a monopoly. But the important point is that the process,
the test and the comparison are the same as in the first example.
Modern emancipation means this: that anybody who can afford
it can publish a newspaper. But the Common Man would not want
to publish a newspaper, even if he could afford it. He might want,
for instance, to go on talking politics in a pothouse or the parlour
of an inn. And that is exactly the sort of really popular talk
about politics which modern movements have often abolished:
the old democracies by forbidding the pothouse, the new dictatorships
by forbidding the politics.
Or again, it is the boast of recent emancipated ethics and politics
not to put any great restraints upon anybody who wants to publish
a book, especially a scientific book, full of psychology or sociology;
and perhaps unavoidably full of perversions and polite pornography.
As that modern tendency increased, it was less and less likely
that the police would interfere very much with a man publishing
the sort of book that only the wealthy could publish with sumptuous
artistic plates or scientific diagrams. It is much more probable,
in most modern societies, that the police would be found interfering
with a man singing a song, of a coarse and candid description,
bawling out a ballad of the grosser sort, or even using the more
restrained medium of prose with a similar lack of restraint.
Yet there is a great deal to be said for song, or even speech,
of the old ribald sort, as compared with writing of the new sort,
when it is at once analytic and anarchic. The old obscenity had
a gusto and a great virility even in its violence, which is not
easily rendered in a diagram or a table of statistics and the old
was always normal and never had any of the horrors of abnormality.
The point is that, here again, the Common Man does not generally want
to write a book, whereas he may occasionally want to sing a song.
He certainly does not want to write a book on psychology or sociology--
or to read, it. But he does want to talk, to sing, to shout, to yell
and howl on due and suitable occasions; and, rightly or wrongly,
it is when he is thus engaged that he is much more likely to fall
foul of a policeman than when he is (as he never is) writing a
scientific study of a new theory of sex. The upshot of uplift,
in the modern sense, is the same in practice as in the previous examples.
In the actual atmosphere of the age, men will still be arrested
for using a certain kind of language, long after they cannot be
arrested for writing a certain kind of literature.
It would be easy to give other examples; but these contemporary
examples are already too continuous to be a coincidence.
It is equally true, for instance, that the liberating movement of
the eighteenth century, the life in the American and French Revolutions,
while it did really vindicate many virtues of republican
simplicity and civic liberty, also accepted as virtues several
things that were obviously vices: that had been recognised
as vices long before, and are now again beginning to be recognised
as vices so long afterwards. Where even ambition had once been
a pardonable vice, avarice became an utterly unpardonable virtue.
Liberal economics too often meant merely giving to those already
rich the liberty to grow richer, and, magnificently granting
to the poor the permission to remain rather poorer than before.
It was much more certain that the usurer was released to practise usury
than that the peasant was released from the practices of the usurer.
It was much more certain that the Wheat Pit was as big as the
Bottomless Pit, than that the man who grew wheat would ever be found
anywhere except at the bottom.
There was a sense in which "liberal economics" were a proclamation
of freedom, for the few who were rich enough to be free.
Nobody thought there was anything queer about talking of prominent
public men "gambling" in the Wheat Pit. But all this time,
there were laws of all kinds against normal human gambling; that is,
against games of chance. The poor man was prevented from gambling,
precisely because he did not gamble so much as the rich man. The beadle
or the policeman might stop children from playing chuck-farthing;
but it was strictly because it was only a farthing that was chucked.
Progress never interfered with the game of chuck-fortune,
because much more than a farthing was being chucked.
The enlightened and emancipated age especially encouraged those
who chucked away other people's fortunes instead of their own.
But anyhow, the comparison remains continuous and clear.
Progress, in the sense of the progress that has progressed since
the sixteenth century, has upon every matter persecuted the Common Man;
punished the gambling he enjoys and permitted the gambling
he cannot follow; restrained the obscenity that might amuse
him and applauded the obscenity that would certainly bore him;
silenced the political quarrels that can be conducted among men
and applauded the political stunts and syndicates that can only be
conducted by millionaires; encouraged anybody who had anything to say
against God, if it was said with a priggish and supercilious accent;
but discouraged anybody who had anything to say in favour of Man,
in his common relations to manhood and motherhood and the normal
appetites of nature. Progress has been merely the persecution
of the Common Man.
Progress has a hagiology, a martyrology, a mass of miraculous legends
of its own, like any other religion; and they are mostly false and belong
to a false religion. The most famous is the fancy that the young and
progressive person is always martyred by the old and ordinary person.
But it is false. It is the old and ordinary person who is almost
always the martyr. It is the old and ordinary person who has
been more and more despoiled of all his old and ordinary rights.
In so far as this progress progresses, it is far more likely that six
million men will be forbidden to go to sleep, because six men say
that certain breathing exercises are a substitute for slumber,
than that any of the six million somnambulists will wake up sufficiently
to clout the six men over their highbrowed but half-witted heads.
There is no normal thing that cannot now be taken from the normal man.
It is much more likely that a law will be passed to forbid the eating
of grain (notoriously the parent of poisons like beer and whisky)
than that it will be even faintly suggested, to men of that philosophy,
that the economic evil is that men cannot grow grain, and that
the ethical evil is that men are still despised for growing it.
Given the purely progressive principle, and nothing else as a guide
to our future, it is entirely possible that they may be banged
or buried alive for growing it. But of course, in a scientific age,
they will be electrocuted--or perhaps only tortured by electricity.
Thus far my thesis is this: that it is not the Uncommon Man who
is persecuted; but rather the Common Man. But this brings me into
direct conflict with the contemporary reactions, which seems to say,
in effect, that the Common Man had much better be persecuted.
It is quite certain that many modern thinkers and writers honestly feel
a contempt for the Common Man; it is also quite certain that I myself
feel a contempt for those who feel this contempt. But the actual
issue must be faced more fully; because what is called the reaction
against democracy is at this moment the chief result of democracy.
Now on this quarrel I am democratic, or at least defiant of the attacks
of democracy. I do not believe that most modern people have seen
the real point of the advantage or disadvantage of popular rule;
and my doubt can be very largely suggested and summarised under this
title of the Common Man.
To put it briefly; it is now the custom to say that most modern
blunders have been due to the Common Man. And I should like to point
out what appalling blunders have in fact been due to the Uncommon Man.
It is easy enough to argue that the mob makes mistakes; but as a fact
it never has a chance even to make mistakes until its superiors
have used their superiority to make much worse mistakes. It is easy
to weary of democracy and cry out for an intellectual aristocracy.
But the trouble is that every intellectual aristocracy seems to
have been utterly unintellectual. Anybody might guess beforehand
that there would be blunders of the ignorant. What nobody could
have guessed, what nobody could have dreamed of in a nightmare,
what no morbid mortal imagination could ever have dared to imagine,
was the mistakes of the well-informed. It is true, in a sense,
to say that the mob has always been led by more educated men.
It is much more true, in every sense, to say that it has always
been misled by educated men. It is easy enough to say the cultured
man should be the crowd's guide, philosopher and friend.
Unfortunately, he has nearly always been a misguiding guide,
a false friend and a very shallow philosopher. And the actual
catastrophes we have suffered, including those we are now suffering,
have not in historical fact been due to the prosaic practical
people who are supposed to know nothing, but almost invariably
to the highly theoretical people who knew that they knew everything.
The world may learn by its mistakes; but they are mostly the mistakes
of the learned.
To go back no further than the seventeenth century, the quarrel
between the Puritans and the populace was originally due
to the pride of a few men in being able to read a printed book,
and their scorn for people who had good memories, good traditions,
good stories, good songs, and good pictures in glass or gold
or graven stone, and therefore had less need of books.
It was a tyranny of literates over illiterates. But it was
the literates who were narrow, sullen, limited and often oppressive;
it was the illiterates who were, at least relatively, gay and free
and fanciful and imaginative and interested in everything.
The Uncommon Men, the elect of the Calvinist theory, did undoubtedly lead
the people along the next stretch of the path of progress; but what it
led to was a prison. The book-reading rulers and statesmen managed
to establish the Scottish Sabbath. Meanwhile, a thousand traditions,
of the sort they would have trampled out, yet managed to trickle
down from the medieval poor to the modern poor, and lingering as
legends in countless cottages and farmhouses, were collected by Scott
(often repeated orally by people who could not read or write)
to combine in the construction of the great Scottish Romances,
which profoundly moved and partly inspired the Romantic Movement
throughout the world.
When we pass to the eighteenth century, we find the same part played
by a new and quite contrary party; differing from the last in everything
except in being the same sort of rather dried up aristocracy.
The new Uncommon Men, now leading the people, are no longer Calvinists,
but a dry sort of Deists drying up more and more like Atheists;
and they are no longer pessimists but the reverse; only their
optimism is often more depressing than pessimism. There were
the Benthamites, the Utilitarians, the servants of the Economic Man;
the first Free-Traders. They have the credit of having first made
clear the economic theories of the modern state; and the calculations
on which were mainly based the politics of the nineteenth century.
It was they who taught these things scientifically and systematically
to the public, and even to the populace. But what were the things,
and what were the theories? Perhaps the best and broadest of them
was a most monstrous and mythical superstition of Adam Smith;
a theological theory that providence had so made the world that men
might be happy through their selfishness; or, in other words,
that God would overrule everything for good, if only men could
succeed in being sufficiently bad. The intellectuals in this
epoch taught definitely and dogmatically that if only men would
buy and sell freely, lend or borrow freely, sweat or sack freely,
and in practice, steal or swindle freely, humanity would be happy.
The Common Man soon found out how happy; in the Slums where they
left him and in the Slump to which they led him.
We need not continue, through the last two centuries, all the tale
of the frenzy and folly inflicted by the fickleness of the educated
class on the relative stability of the uneducated. The fickle
intellectuals next rushed to the other extreme, and became Socialists,
despising small property as they had despised popular tradition.
It is quite true that these intellectuals had a lucid interval in which
they proclaimed some primary truths along with many priggish falsehoods.
Some of them did rightly exalt liberty and human dignity
and equality, as expressed in the Declaration of Independence.
But even that was so much mishandled that there is now a disposition
to deny the truth along with the falsehood. There has been a reaction
against Democracy; or, in plain words, the prigs are now too bored
even to go on with their normal routine about the Common Man;
the familiar routine of oppressing him in practice and adoring
him in theory.
I do not adore him, but I do believe in him; at least I believe
in him much more than I believe in them. I think the actual history
of the relations between him and them, as I have narrated it,
is enough to justify my preference. I repeat that they have had
all the educational advantages over him; they have always led him;
and they have always misled him. And even in becoming reactionaries,
they remain as raw and crude as when they were revolutionaries.
Their anti-democracy is as much stuffed with cant as their democracy.
I need only allude to the detestable new fashion of referring to ordinary
men as morons. First, it is pedantry, the dullest form of vanity;
for a moron is only the Greek for a fool; and it is mostly sham pedantry,
for most of those who mention morons hardly know they are talking Greek,
still less why on earth they should. It also involves this moral evil:
that a man who says that men are mostly fools knows at least
that he has often made a fool of himself; whereas the morons are
thought of like monkeys; as if they were a fixed tribe or caste.
The Common Man may well be the victim of a new series of tyrannies,
founded on this scientific fad of regarding him as a monkey.
But it is doubtful whether he can be much more persecuted for having
the instincts of a moron, than he has already been for having
the instincts of a man.
A MIDSUMMER NIGHT'S DREAM
The greatest of Shakespeare's comedies is also, from a certain
point of view, the greatest of his plays. No one would maintain
that it occupied this position in the matter of psychological
study if by psychological study we mean the study of individual
characters in a play. No one would maintain that Puck was
a character in the sense that Falstaff is a character, or that
the critic stood awed before the psychology of Peaseblossom.
But there is a sense in which the play is perhaps a greater triumph
of psychology than Hamlet itself. It may well be questioned whether
in any other literary work in the world is so vividly rendered
a social and spiritual atmosphere. There is an atmosphere in Hamlet,
for instance, a somewhat murky and even melodramatic one, but it
is subordinate to the great character, and morally inferior to him;
the darkness is only a background for the isolated star of intellect.
But A Midsummer Night's Dream is a psychological study,
not of a solitary man, but of a spirit that unites mankind.
The six men may sit talking in an inn; they may not know each other's
names or see each other's faces before or after, but night or wine
or great stories, or some rich and branching discussion may make
them all at one, if not absolutely with each other, at least
with that invisible seventh man who is the harmony of all of them.
That seventh man is the hero of A Midsummer Night's Dream.
A study of the play from a literary or philosophical point of view
must therefore be founded upon some serious realisation of what this
atmosphere is. In a lecture upon As You Like It, Mr. Bernard Shaw
made a suggestion which is an admirable example of his amazing
ingenuity and of his one most interesting limitation. In maintaining
that the light sentiment and optimism of the comedy were regarded
by Shakespeare merely as the characteristics of a more or less
cynical pot-boiler, he actually suggested that the title "As You Like It"
was a taunting address to the public in disparagement of their taste
and the dramatist's own work. If Mr. Bernard Shaw had conceived
of Shakespeare as insisting that Ben Jonson should wear Jaeger
underclothing or join the Blue Ribbon Army, or distribute little
pamphlets for the non-payment of rates, he could scarcely have conceived
anything more violently opposed to the whole spirit of Elizabethan
comedy than the spiteful and priggish modernism of such a taunt.
Shakespeare might make the fastidious and cultivated Hamlet,
moving in his own melancholy and purely mental world,
warn players against an over-indulgence towards the rabble.
But the very soul and meaning of the great comedies is that of an
uproarious communion between the public and the play, a communion
so chaotic that whole scenes of silliness and violence lead us
almost to think that some of the "rowdies" from the pit have climbed
over the footlights. The title "As You Like It", is, of course,
an expression of utter carelessness, but it is not the bitter
carelessness which Mr. Bernard Shaw fantastically reads into it;
it is the god-like and inexhaustible carelessness of a happy man.
And the simple proof of this is that there are scores of these genially
taunting titles scattered through the whole of Elizabethan comedy.
Is "As You Like It " a title demanding a dark and ironic
explanation in a school of comedy which called its plays "What
you Will", "A Mad World, My Masters", "If It Be Not Good,
the Devil Is In It", "The Devil is an Ass", "An Humorous Day's Mirth",
and "A Midsummer Night's Dream"? Every one of these titles is flung
at the head of the public as a drunken lord might fling a purse
at his footman. Would Mr. Shaw maintain that "If It Be Not Good,
the Devil Is In It", was the opposite of "As You Like It",
and was a solemn invocation of the supernatural powers to testify
to the care and perfection of the literary workmanship?
The one explanation is as Elizabethan as the other.
Now in the reason for this modern and pedantic error lies the whole
secret and difficulty of such plays as A Midsummer Night's Dream.
The sentiment of such a play, so far as it can be summed up at all,
can be summed up in one sentence. It is the mysticism of happiness.
That is to say, it is the conception that as man lives upon
a borderland he may find himself in the spiritual or supernatural
atmosphere, not only through being profoundly sad or meditative,
but by being extravagantly happy. The soul might be rapt
out of the body in an agony of sorrow, or a trance of ecstasy;
but it might also be rapt out of the body in a paroxysm of laughter.
Sorrow we know can go beyond itself; so, according to Shakespeare,
can pleasure go beyond itself and become something dangerous and unknown.
And the reason that the logical and destructive modern school,
of which Mr. Bernard Shaw is an example, does not grasp this
purely exuberant nature of the comedies is simply that their
logical and destructive attitude have rendered impossible the very
experience of this preternatural exuberance. We cannot realise
As You Like It if we are always considering it as we understand it.
We cannot have A Midsummer's Night Dream if our one object in life
is to keep ourselves awake with the black coffee of criticism.
The whole question which is balanced, and balanced nobly and fairly,
in A Midsummer Night's Dream, is whether the life of waking,
or the life of the vision, is the real life, the sine qu? non of man.
But it is difficult to see what superiority for the purpose of judging
is possessed by people whose pride it is not to live the life of
vision at all. At least it is questionable whether the Elizabethan
did not know more about both worlds than the modern intellectual;
it is not altogether improbable that Shakespeare would not only have
had a clearer vision of the fairies, but would have shot very much
straighter at a deer and netted much more money for his performances
than a member of the Stage Society.
In pure poetry and the intoxication of words, Shakespeare never rose
higher than he rises in this play. But in spite of this fact,
the supreme literary merit of A Midsummer Night's Dream is
a merit of design. The amazing symmetry, the amazing artistic
and moral beauty of that design, can be stated very briefly.
The story opens in the sane and common world with the pleasant
seriousness of very young lovers and very young friends.
Then, as the figures advance into the tangled wood of young troubles
and stolen happiness, a change and bewilderment begins to fall on them.
They lose their way and their wits for they are in the heart
of fairyland. Their words, their hungers, their very figures
grow more and more dim and fantastic, like dreams within dreams,
in the supernatural mist of Puck. Then the dream-fumes begin
to clear, and characters and spectators begin to awaken together
to the noise of horns and dogs and the clean and bracing morning.
Theseus, the incarnation of a happy and generous rationalism,
expounds in hackneyed and superb lines the sane view of such
psychic experiences, pointing out with a reverent and sympathetic
scepticism that all these fairies and spells are themselves
but the emanations, the unconscious masterpieces, of man himself.
The whole company falls back into a splendid human laughter.
There is a rush for banqueting and private theatricals, and over all
these things ripples one of those frivolous and inspired conversations
in which every good saying seems to die in giving birth to another.
If ever the son of a man in his wanderings was at home and
drinking by the fireside, he is at home in the house of Theseus.
All the dreams have been forgotten, as a melancholy dream remembered
throughout the morning might be forgotten in the human certainty
of any other triumphant evening party; and so the play seems
naturally ended. It began on the earth and it ends on the earth.
Thus to round off the whole midsummer night's dream in an eclipse
of daylight is an effect of genius. But of this comedy,
as I have said, the mark is that genius goes beyond itself;
and one touch is added which makes the play colossal.
Theseus and his train retire with a crashing finale, full of humour
and wisdom and things set right, and silence falls on the house.
Then there comes a faint sound of little feet, and for a moment,
as it were, the elves look into the house, asking which is the reality.
"Suppose we are the realities and they the shadows." If that ending
were acted properly any modern man would feel shaken to his marrow
if he had to walk home from the theatre through a country lane.
It is a trite matter, of course, though in a general criticism
a more or less indispensable one to comment upon another point
of artistic perfection, the extraordinarily human and accurate
manner in which the play catches the atmosphere of a dream.
The chase and tangle and frustration of the incidents and personalities
are well known to every one who has dreamt of perpetually falling
over precipices or perpetually missing trains. While following
out clearly and legally the necessary narrative of the drama,
the author contrives to include every one of the main peculiarities of
the exasperating dream. Here is the pursuit of the man we cannot catch,
the flight from the man we cannot see; here is the perpetual returning
to the same place, here is the crazy alteration in the very objects
of our desire, the substitution of one face for another face,
the putting of the wrong souls in the wrong bodies, the fantastic
disloyalties of the night, all this is as obvious as it is important.
It is perhaps somewhat more worth remarking that there is about this
confusion of comedy yet another essential characteristic of dreams.
A dream can commonly be described as possessing an utter discordance
of incident combined with a curious unity of mood; everything changes
but the dreamer. It may begin with anything and end with anything,
but if the dreamer is sad at the end he will be sad as if by prescience
at the beginning; if he is cheerful at the beginning he will be cheerful
if the stars fall. A Midsummer Night's Dream has in a most singular
degree effected this difficult, this almost desperate subtlety.
The events in the wandering wood are in themselves, and regarded
as in broad daylight, not merely melancholy but bitterly cruel
and ignominious. But yet by the spreading of an atmosphere as
magic as the fog of Puck, Shakespeare contrives to make the whole
matter mysteriously hilarious while it is palpably tragic,
and mysteriously charitable, while it is in itself cynical.
He contrives somehow to rob tragedy and treachery of their
full sharpness, just as a toothache or a deadly danger from a tiger,
or a precipice, is robbed of its sharpness in a pleasant dream.
The creation of a brooding sentiment like this, a sentiment not merely
independent of but actually opposed to the events, is a much greater
triumph of art than the creation of the character of Othello.
It is difficult to approach critically so great a figure as that of
Bottom the Weaver. He is greater and more mysterious than Hamlet,
because the interest of such men as Bottom consists of a rich
subconsciousness, and that of Hamlet in the comparatively superficial
matter of a rich consciousness. And it is especially difficult in
the present age which has become hag-ridden with the mere intellect.
We are the victims of a curious confusion whereby being great is
supposed to have something to do with being clever, as if there
were the smallest reason to suppose that Achilles was clever,
as if there were not on the contrary a great deal of internal
evidence to indicate that he was next door to a fool. Greatness is
a certain indescribable but perfectly familiar and palpable quality
of size in the personality, of steadfastness, of strong flavour,
of easy and natural self-expression. Such a man is as firm as a tree
and as unique as a rhinoceros, and he might quite easily be as
stupid as either of them. Fully as much as the great poet towers
above the small poet the great fool towers above the small fool.
We have all of us known rustics like Bottom the Weaver, men whose
faces would be blank with idiocy if we tried for ten days to explain
the meaning of the National Debt, but who are yet great men,
akin to Sigurd and Hercules, heroes of the morning of the earth,
because their words were their own words, their memories their
own memories, and their vanity as large and simple as a great hill.
We have all of us known friends in our own circle, men whom the
intellectuals might justly describe as brainless, but whose presence
in a room was like a fire roaring in the grate changing everything,
lights and shadows and the air, whose entrances and exits were in some
strange fashion events, whose point of view once expressed haunts
and persuades the mind and almost intimidates it, whose manifest
absurdity clings to the fancy like the beauty of first-love,
and whose follies are recounted like the legends of a paladin.
These are great men, there are millions of them in the world,
though very few perhaps in the House of Commons. It is not in
the cold halls of cleverness where celebrities seem to be important
that we should look for the great. An intellectual salon is merely
a training-ground for one faculty, and is akin to a fencing class
or a rifle corps. It is in our own homes and environments,
from Croydon to St. John's Wood, in old nurses, and gentlemen
with hobbies, and talkative spinsters and vast incomparable butlers,
that we may feel the presence of that blood of the gods.
And this creature so hard to describe, so easy to remember,
the august and memorable fool, has never been so sumptuously painted
as in the Bottom of A Midsummer Night's Dream.
Bottom has the supreme mark of this real greatness in that like
the true saint or the true hero he only differs from humanity
in being as it were more human than humanity. It is not true,
as the idle materialists of today suggest, that compared to the majority
of men the hero appears cold and dehumanised; it is the majority
who appear cold and dehumanised in the presence of greatness.
Bottom, like Don Quixote. and Uncle Toby and Mr. Richard Swiveller
and the rest of the Titans, has a huge and unfathomable weakness,
his silliness is on a great scale, and when he blows his own trumpet
it is like the trumpet of the Resurrection. The other rustics in
the play accept his leadership not merely naturally but exuberantly;
they have to the full that primary and savage unselfishness,
that uproarious abnegation which makes simple men take pleasure
in falling short of a hero, that unquestionable element of basic
human nature which has never been expressed, outside this play,
so perfectly as in the incomparable chapter at the beginning
of Evan Harrington in which the praises of The Great Mel are
sung with a lyric energy by the tradesmen whom he has cheated.
Twopenny sceptics write of the egoism of primal human nature;
it is reserved for great men like Shakespeare and Meredith to detect
and make vivid this rude and subconscious unselfishness which is
older than self. They alone with their insatiable tolerance
can perceive all the spiritual devotion in the soul of a snob.
And it is this natural play between the rich simplicity of Bottom
and the simple simplicity of his comrades which constitutes
the unapproachable excellence of the farcical scenes in this play.
Bottom's sensibility to literature is perfectly fiery and genuine,
a great deal more genuine than that of a great many cultivated
critics of literature--"the raging rocks, and shivering
shocks shall break the locks of prison gates, and Phibbus'
car shall shine from far, and make and mar the foolish fates",
is exceedingly good poetical diction with a real throb and swell
in it, and if it is slightly and almost imperceptibly deficient
in the matter of sense, it is certainly every bit as sensible
as a good many other rhetorical speeches in Shakespeare put into
the mouths of kings and lovers and even the spirits of the dead.
If Bottom liked cant for its own sake the fact only constitutes
another point of sympathy between him and his literary creator.
But the style of the thing, though deliberately bombastic and ludicrous,
is quite literary, the alliteration falls like wave upon wave,
and the whole verse, like a billow mounts higher and higher
before it crashes. There is nothing mean about this folly;
nor is there in the whole realm of literature a figure so free
from vulgarity. The man vitally base and foolish sings
"The Honeysuckle and the Bee"; he does not rant about "raging rocks"
and "the car of Phibbus". Dickens, who more perhaps than any
modern man had the mental hospitality and the thoughtless wisdom
of Shakespeare, perceived and expressed admirably the same truth.
He perceived, that is to say, that quite indefensible idiots
have very often a real sense of, and enthusiasm for letters.
Mr. Micawber loved eloquence and poetry with his whole immortal soul;
words and visionary pictures kept him alive in the absence of food
and money, as they might have kept a saint fasting in a desert.
Dick Swiveller did not make his inimitable quotations from Moore and
Byron merely as flippant digressions. He made them because he loved
a great school of poetry. The sincere love of books has nothing to do
with cleverness or stupidity any more than any other sincere love.
It is a quality of character, a freshness, a power of pleasure,
a power of faith. A silly person may delight in reading
masterpieces just as a silly person may delight in picking flowers.
A fool may be in love with a poet as he may be in love with a woman.
And the triumph of Bottom is that he loves rhetoric and his own
taste in the arts, and this is all that can be achieved by Theseus,
or for the matter of that by Cosimo di Medici. It is worth remarking
as an extremely fine touch in the picture of Bottom that his literary
taste is almost everywhere concerned with sound rather than sense.
He begins the rehearsal with a boisterous readiness, "Thisby,
the flowers of odious savours sweete." "Odours, odours," says Quince,
in remonstrance, and the word is accepted in accordance with
the cold and heavy rules which require an element of meaning in a
poetical passage. But "Thisby, the flowers of odious savours sweete",
Bottom's version, is an immeasurably finer and more resonant line.
The "i" which he inserts is an inspiration of metricism.
There is another aspect of this great play which ought to be
kept familiarly in the mind. Extravagant as is the masquerade
of the story, it is a very perfect aesthetic harmony down to such
coup-de-ma?tre as the name of Bottom, or the flower called Love
in Idleness. In the whole matter it may be said that there
is one accidental discord; that is in the name of Theseus,
and the whole city of Athens in which the events take place.
Shakespeare's description of Athens in A Midsummer Night's Dream is
the best description of England that he or any one else ever wrote.
Theseus is quite obviously only an English squire, fond of hunting,
kindly to his tenants, hospitable with a certain flamboyant vanity.
The mechanics are English mechanics, talking to each other with
the queer formality of the poor. Above all, the fairies are English;
to compare them with the beautiful patrician spirits of Irish legend,
for instance, is suddenly to discover that we have, after all,
a folk-lore and a mythology, or had it at least in Shakespeare's day.
Robin Goodfellow, upsetting the old women's ale, or pulling
the stool from under them, has nothing of the poignant
Celtic beauty; his is the horse-play of the invisible world.
Perhaps it is some debased inheritance of English life which makes
American ghosts so fond of quite undignified practical jokes.
But this union of mystery with farce is a note of the medieval English.
The play is the last glimpse of Merrie England, that distant
but shining and quite indubitable country. It would be difficult
indeed to define wherein lay the peculiar truth of the phrase
"merrie England", though some conception of it is quite
necessary to the comprehension of A Midsummer Night's Dream.
In some cases at least, it may be said to lie in this, that the
English of the Middle Ages and the Renaissance, unlike the England
of today, could conceive of the idea of a merry supernaturalism.
Amid all the great work of Puritanism the damning indictment
of it consists in one fact, that there was one only of the fables
of Christendom that it retained and renewed, and that was
the belief in witchcraft. It cast away the generous and wholesome
superstition, it approved only of the morbid and the dangerous.
In their treatment of the great national fairy-tale of good
and evil, the Puritans killed St. George but carefully preserved
the Dragon, And this seventeenth-century tradition of dealing
with the psychic life still lies like a great shadow over England
and America, so that if we glance at a novel about occultism we
may be perfectly certain that it deals with sad or evil destiny.
Whatever else we expect we certainly should never expect to find
in it spirits such as those in Aylwin as inspirers of a tale of
tomfoolery like the Wrong Box or The Londoners. That impossibility
is the disappearance of "merrie England" and Robin Goodfellow.
It was a land to us incredible, the land of a jolly occultism where
the peasant cracked jokes with his patron saint, and only cursed
the fairies good-humouredly, as he might curse a lazy servant.
Shakespeare is English in everything, above all in his weaknesses.
Just as London, one of the greatest cities in the world, shows more
slums and hides more beauties than any other, so Shakespeare alone
among the four giants of poetry is a careless writer, and lets us
come upon his splendours by accident, as we come upon an old City
church in the twist of a city street. He is English in nothing
so much as in that noble cosmopolitan unconsciousness which makes him
look eastward with the eyes of a child towards Athens or Verona.
He loved to talk of the glory of foreign lands, but he talked
of them with the tongue and unquenchable spirit of England.
It is too much the custom of a later patriotism to reverse this
method and talk of England from morning till night, but to talk
of her in a manner totally un-English. Casualness, incongruities,
and a certain fine absence of mind are in the temper of England;
the unconscious man with the ass's head is no bad type of the people.
Materialistic philosophers and mechanical politicians have certainly
succeeded in some cases in giving him a greater unity. The only
question is, to which animal has he been thus successfully conformed?
ON READING
The highest use of the great masters of literature is not literary; it is
apart from their superb style and even from their emotional inspiration.
The first use of good literature is that it prevents a man from
being merely modern. To be merely modern is to condemn oneself
to an ultimate narrowness; just as to spend one's last earthly
money on the newest hat is to condemn oneself to the old-fashioned.
The road of the ancient centuries is strewn with dead moderns.
Literature, classic and enduring literature, does its best work
in reminding us perpetually of the whole round of truth and balancing
other and older ideas against the ideas to which we might for a moment
be prone. The way in which it does this, however, is sufficiently
curious to be worth our fully understanding it to begin with.
From time to time in human history, but especially in restless
epochs like our own, a certain class of things appears.
In the old world they were called heresies. In the modern world
they are called fads. Sometimes they are for a time useful;
sometimes they are wholly mischievous. But they always consist
of undue concentration upon some one truth or half-truth. Thus it
is true to insist upon God's knowledge, but heretical to insist on it
as Calvin did at the expense of his Love; thus it is true to desire
a simple life, but heretical to desire it at the expense of good
feeling and good manners. The heretic (who is also the fanatic)
is not a man who loves truth too much; no man can love truth too much.
The heretic is a man who loves his truth more than truth itself.
He prefers the half-truth that he has found to the whole truth
which humanity has found. He does not like to see his own precious
little paradox merely bound up with twenty truisms into the bundle
of the wisdom of the world.
Sometimes such innovators are of a sombre sincerity like Tolstoi,
sometimes of a sensitive and feminine eloquence like Nietzsche,
and sometimes of an admirable humour, pluck, and public spirit like
Mr. Bernard Shaw. In all cases they make a stir, and perhaps found
a school. But in all cases the same fundamental mistake is made.
It is always supposed that the man in question has discovered a new idea.
But, as a fact, what is new is not the idea, but only the isolation
of the idea. The idea itself can be found, in all probability,
scattered frequently enough through all the great books of a more
classic or impartial temper, from Homer and Virgil to Fielding
and Dickens. You can find all the new ideas in the old books;
only there you will find them balanced, kept in their place,
and sometimes contradicted and overcome by other and better ideas.
The great writers did not neglect a fad because they had not thought
of it, but because they had thought of it and of all the answers
to it as well.
In case this point is not clear, I will take two examples,
both in reference to notions fashionable among some of the more
fanciful and younger theorists. Nietzsche, as every one knows,
preached a doctrine which he and his followers regard apparently as
very revolutionary; he held that ordinary altruistic morality had been
the invention of a slave class to prevent the emergence of superior
types to fight and rule them. Now, modern people, whether they agree
with this or not, always talk of it as a new and unheard-of idea.
It is calmly and persistently supposed that the great writers of the past,
say Shakespeare for instance, did not hold this view, because they
had never imagined it; because it had never come into their heads.
Turn up the last act of Shakespeare's Richard III and you will
find not only all that Nietzsche had to say put into two lines,
but you will find it put in the very words of Nietzsche.
Richard Crookback says to his nobles:
Conscience is but a word that cowards use,
Devised at first to keep the strong in awe.
As I have said, the fact is plain. Shakespeare had thought of Nietzsche
and the Master Morality; but he weighed it at its proper value
and put it in its proper place. Its proper place is the mouth of a
half-insane hunchback on the eve of defeat. This rage against the weak
is only possible in a man morbidly brave but fundamentally sick;
a man like Richard, a man like Nietzsche. This case alone ought
to destroy the absurd fancy that these modern philosophies are modern
in the sense that the great men of the past did not think of them.
They thought of them; only they did not think much of them.
It was not that Shakespeare did not see the Nietzsche idea;
he saw it, and he saw through it.
I will take one other example: Mr. Bernard Shaw in his striking
and sincere play called "Major Barbara", throws down one of
the most violent of his verbal challenges to proverbial morality.
People say, "Poverty is no crime." "Yes," says Mr. Bernard Shaw,
"poverty is a crime, and the mother of crimes. It is a crime
to be poor if you could possibly rebel or grow rich.
To be poor means to be poor-spirited, servile or tricky."
Mr. Shaw shows signs of an intention to concentrate on
this doctrine, and many of his followers do the same.
Now, it is only the concentration that is new, not the doctrine.
Thackeray makes Becky Sharp say that it is easy to be moral
on £1,000 a year, and so difficult on £100. But, as in the case
of Shakespeare I have quoted, the point is not merely that Thackeray
knew of this conception, but that he knew exactly what it was worth.
It not only occurred to him, but he knew where it ought to occur.
It ought to occur in the conversation of Becky Sharp; a woman
shrewd and not without sincerity, but profoundly unacquainted
with all the deeper emotions which make life worth living.
The cynicism of Becky, with Lady Jane and Dobbin to balance it,
has a certain breezy truth. The cynicism of Mr. Shaw's Undershaft,
preached alone with the austerity of a field preacher, is simply not
true at all. It is simply not true at all to say that the very poor
are as a whole more insincere or more grovelling than the very rich.
Becky's half-truth has become first a crotchet, then a creed,
and then a lie. In the case of Thackeray, as in that of Shakespeare,
the conclusion which concerns us is the same. What we call
the new ideas are generally broken fragments of the old ideas.
It was not that a particular notion did not enter Shakespeare's head;
it is that it found a good many other notions waiting to knock
the nonsense out of it.
MONSTERS AND THE MIDDLE AGES
I do not remember to have read anywhere an adequate and comprehensive
account of the fabulous monsters so much written of in the Middle Ages.
Such studies as I have seen suffered from the three or four strange
and senseless blunders which throttle all our thought on such subjects.
The primary blunder, of course, is that comic one to which students
like Mr. Frazer have lent, or rather pawned, their authority.
I mean the absurd notion that in matters of the imagination men
have any need to copy from each other. Poems and poetic tales tend
to be a little alike, not because Hebrews were really Chaldeans,
nor because Christians were really Pagans, but because men
are really men. Because there is, in spite of all the trend
of modern thought, such a thing as man and the brotherhood of men.
Anyone who has really looked at the moon might have called the moon
a virgin and a huntress without ever having heard of Diana.
Anyone who had ever looked at the sun might call it the god
of oracles and of healing without having heard of Apollo.
A man in love, walking about in a garden, compares a woman to a flower,
and not to an earwig; though an earwig also was made by God, and has
many superiorities to flowers in point of education and travel.
To hear some people talk, one would think that the love of flowers
had been imposed by some long priestly tradition, and the love
of earwigs forbidden by some fearful tribal taboo.
The second great blunder is to suppose that such fables, even when they
really are borrowed from older sources, are used in an old tired and
customary spirit. When the soul really wakes it always deals directly
with the nearest things. If, let us say, a man woke up in bed from
a celestial dream which told him to go on painting till all was blue,
he would begin by painting himself blue, then his bed blue, and so on.
But he would be using all the machinery that came to hand;
and that is exactly what always happens in real spiritual revolutions.
They work by their environment even when they alter it.
Thus, when professors tell us that the Christians "borrowed"
this or that fable or monster from the heathens, it is as if people
said that a bricklayer had "borrowed" his bricks from clay,
or a chemist had "borrowed" his explosives from chemicals;
or that the Gothic builders of Lincoln or Beauvais had "borrowed"
the pointed arch from the thin lattices of the Moors.
Perhaps they did borrow it, but (by heaven!) they paid it back.
Five or six other similar errors need not detain us now.
For upon these two rests the essential error about, let us
say, unicorns; which, after all, is our chief affair in life.
The mystical monsters talked of in the Middle Ages had most of them,
no doubt, a tradition older than Christianity. I do not admit
this because many of the most eminent authorities would say so.
As Swinburne said in his conversation with Persephone, "I have
lived long enough to have known one thing"; that eminent men mean
successful men, and that successful men really hate Christianity.
But it is evident from the general tradition of life and letters.
I think that someone in the Old Testament says that the unicorn
is a very difficult animal to catch; and certainly it has not been
caught yet. If nobody has yet said that in this case "unicorn"
must mean rhinoceros, somebody soon will, but it shall not be I. But
though it is probably true that many of these medieval monsters
were of pagan origin, this truth, which is always repeated,
is far less startling than another truth that is always ignored.
The monster of the pagan fables was always, so far as I can see, an emblem
of evil. That is to say, he was really a monster; he was abnormal;
or as Kingsley put it in those fine and highly heathen hexameters:
Twi-formed strange, without like, who obey not the
golden-haired rulers.
Vainly rebelling, they rage till they die by the swords of
the heroes.

Sometimes the monster, once killed, could be used to kill other monsters;
as Perseus used the Gorgon to kill the dragons of the sea.
But this is a mere accident of material. I can imagine,
in the same way, that if I could put the head of a folk-lore
professor on the end of a stick, in the French Revolutionary manner,
it might serve very excellently as a heavy wooden club for beating
in the heads of other and less hardened folk-lore professors.
Or, again, the hydra, which grew two heads for every one that was
cut off, might have been praised as an emblem of branching evolution
and the advantage of an increasing population. But, as a fact,
the hydra was not praised. He was killed, amid general relief.
The minotaur might have been admired by moderns as the meeting-place
of men and animals; the chimera might have been admired by moderns
as an instance of the principle that three heads are better than one.
I say that the hydra and chimera might have been admired by moderns.
But they were not admired by ancients. Among the pagans the grotesque,
fabulous animal was thought of only as something you ought to kill.
Sometimes it killed you, like the sphinx; but even when it had done that,
you did not really love it.
Now the case of the reappearance of such unearthly animals after Europe
became Christendom is the thing I have never seen properly described.
In one of the oldest of the legends of St. George and
the Dragon, St. George did not kill the Dragon, but led it captive
and sprinkled it with holy water. Something of the same sort
happened to that whole department of the human mind which creates
violent and unnatural images. Take the griffin for example.
In our time the griffin, like most other medieval symbols,
has been made a mean and farcical thing for fancy-dress balls:
in twenty pictures from Punch, for instance, we can see the griffin
and the turtle as supporters of the civic arms of London.
For the modern "citizen" the arrangement is excellent; the griffin,
which eats him, does not exist; the turtle, which he eats,
does exist. But not only was the griffin not always trivial,
but he was not always even bad. He was a mystical incorporation
of two animals held wholly sacred: the lion of St. Mark,
the lion of generosity, valour, victory; the eagle of St. John,
the eagle of truth, of aspiration, of intellectual liberty.
Thus the griffin was often used as the emblem of Christ;
as combining the eagle and the lion in that mysterious and
complete compound in which Christ combined the divine and human.
But even if you thought of the griffin as good, you were not less
afraid of him. Perhaps more.
But the strongest case is that of the unicorn, which I intended
to figure prominently in this article but which seems to have evaded
my thought in a most miraculous manner, and which up to this time I seem
to have practically omitted. He is a terrible creature, the unicorn;
and though he seems to live rather vaguely in Africa, I could never be
surprised if he came walking up one of the four white roads that lead
to Beaconsfield; the monster whiter than the roads, and his horn
higher than the church spire. For all these mystical animals were
imagined as enormously big as well as incalculably fierce and free.
The stamping of the awful unicorn would shake the endless deserts
in which it dwelt; and the wings of the vast griffin went over
one's head in heaven with the thunder of a thousand cherubim.
And yet the fact remains that if you had asked a medieval man what
the unicorn was supposed to mean, he would have replied "chastity".
When we have understood that fact we shall understand a great many
other things, but above all the civilisation out of which we come.
Christianity did not conceive Christian virtues as tame, timid,
and respectable things. It did conceive of these virtues as vast,
defiant, and even destructive things, scorning the yoke of this world,
dwelling in the desert, and seeking their meat from God.
Till we have understood that no one will really understand even
the "Lion and the Unicorn" over a pastry cook's shop.
WHAT NOVELISTS ARE FOR
A long time ago, when I happened to be living in Rye in Sussex, I had
the honour of being visited by two very distinguished men; they were
both Americans, indeed, they were brothers; but the type of their
success seemed oddly different. One was Henry James, the novelist,
who lived next door; the other was William James, the philosopher,
who had just crossed the Atlantic and seemed as breezy as the sea.
In fact, there was an almost fantastic contrast between the two men:
the one so solemn about social details often considered trivial;
the other so hearty about abstract studies generally considered dry.
Henry James talked about toast and teacups with the impressiveness
of a family ghost; while William James talked about the metabolism
and the involution of values with the air of a man recounting his
flirtations on the steamer. But though I had and have the greatest
possible regard for them both, I cannot but think that a certain
relative completeness, and incompleteness, in the contrast between
them reveals a certain truth about two different types of letters.
I was recently rereading one of the late Harvey Wickham's exceedingly
clever studies of modern thought; including the study of William James.
I think the critic was mainly just about the philosophy, but not quite
just about the philosopher. I do not myself think that Pragmatism
can ever stand up as a serious rival to the permanent philosophy
of Truth and the Absolute. But I do think that William James
did really stand up as a rattling good fighter and cleaner-up
of the particular sort of solemn nonsense most current in his time.
He may have only indirectly served the cause of belief in belief.
But he did a lot to serve the cause of unbelief in unbelief;
a very wholesome object. But that is not my main point. It seems to me
that where William James failed was exactly where Henry James succeeded;
in making a whole scheme out of fine shades and doubtful cases.
Now that can be done with a novel; for it only claims to be exceptional.
It cannot be done with philosophy; for it must claim to be universal.
Pragmatism fails because it is a cosmos made out of odds and ends.
But stories are better for being made out of odds and ends; especially if
the ends are very odd. Recalling at random some Henry James stories,
there was one about an intelligent youth who unaccountably became a sort
of tame cat in the house of a couple of rich but unspeakably dull people.
But it is not because he is a snob or a plate-licker; but because
he is really touched by a devotion and delusion of the old couple,
about their dead daughter, whose life they continue in a sort
of waking dream, in which the young man figures as her lover.
It is beautifully and delicately done; and it does not seem impossible.
Now if we apply to this any moral philosophy on earth,
however modern, however mad, we shall all shrink from laying it
down as a general rule that young men ought to cadge on old men,
that they ought to encourage delusions; that this ménage is a model
for the normal home. But that is exactly what a novelist is for.
He is not bound to justify human beings, but only to humanise them.
It is for him and not the philosopher to deal with all this chapter
of accidents; in which "things work out differently in practice".
William James's mistake was that he did not put his notions into novels,
like his brother; where such opportunism is quite appropriate.
He tried to make a cosmic system out of these accidents
and this opportunism; and the system is not systematic.
The comparison carries a faint hint that novelists may be some
use after all.
THE SONG OF ROLAND
MOST OF us remember reading, in the school histories
of our childhood, that at the Battle of Hastings Taillefer
the Jongleur went in front of the Norman Army, throwing his sword
in the air and singing the Song of Roland. They were naturally
histories of a very Victorian sort, which passed lightly over
the Roman Empire and the Crusades on the way to serious things,
such as the genealogy of George I or the administration of Addington.
But that one image emerged in the imagination as something alive in its
dead surroundings; like finding a familiar face in a faded tapestry.
The song he sang was presumably not the noble and rugged
epic which Major Scott Moncrieff has done so solid and even
historic a service to letters in rendering in its entirety.
The Jongleur must at least have selected extracts or favourite passages,
or the battles would have been unduly delayed. But the tale has
the same moral as the translation; since both have the same inspiration.
The value of the tale was that it did suggest to the childish mind,
through all the deadening effects of distance and indifference, that a man
does not make such a gesture with a sword unless he feels something,
and that a man does not sing unless he has something to sing about.
Dull avarice and an appetite for feudal lands do not inspire
such jugglery. In short the value of the tale was that it
hinted that there is a heart in history, even remote history.
And the value of the translation is that if we are really to learn
history we must, in a double sense of the word, learn it by heart.
We must learn it at length and as it were at large; lingering over
chance spaces of contemporary work, for love of its detail,
and one might almost say for love of its dullness. Even a random
reader like myself, only dipping here and there into such things,
so long as they are really things of the period, can often learn
more from them than from the most careful constitutional digests
or political summaries by modern men more learned than himself.
A modern man, educated on the modern histories, may find here
the things he does not expect. I have here only space for
one example, out of many that I could give to show what I mean.
Most of the stock histories tell the young student something of
what Feudalism was in legal form and custom; that the subordinates
were called vassals, that they did homage, and so on.
But they do it somehow in such a way as to suggest a savage
and sullen obedience; as if a vassal were no more than a serf.
What is left out is the fact that the homage really was homage;
a thing worthy of a man. The first feudal feeling had something
ideal and even impersonal, like patriotism. The nations were not
yet born; and these smaller groups had almost the soul of nations.
The reader will find the word "vassalage" used again and again on a note
which is not only heroic but even haughty. The vassal is obviously
as proud of being a vassal as anybody could be of being a lord.
Indeed the feudal poet uses the word "vassalage" where a modern
poet would use the word "chivalry". The Paladins charging
the Paynim are spurred on by vassalage. Turpin the Archbishop
hacks the Moslem chieftain rib from rib; and the Christians,
beholding his triumph, cry aloud in their pride that he has shown
great vassalage; and that with such an Archbishop the Cross is safe.
There were no Conscientious Objections in their Christianity.
This is a type of the truths that historical literature ought to make
us feel; but which mere histories very seldom do. The one example
I have already given, of the Jongleur at Hastings, is a complexity
of curious truths that might be conveyed and which very seldom are.
We might have learned, for instance, what a Jongleur was;
and realised that this one may have had feelings as deep and fantastic
as the Jongleur celebrated in the twelfth-century poem, who died
gloriously of dancing and turning somersaults before the image
of Our Lady; that he was of the trade taken as a type by the mystical
mirth of St. Francis, who called his monks the Jugglers of God.
A man must read at least a little of the contemporary work itself before
he thus finds the human heart inside the armour and the monastic gown;
the men who write the philosophy of history seldom give us
the philosophy, still less the religion, of the historical characters.
And the final example of this is something which is also illustrated
by the obscure minstrel who threw up his sword as he sang
the Song of Roland, as well as by the Song of Roland itself.
Modern history, mainly ethnological or economic, always talks of a thing
like the Norman adventure in the somewhat vulgar language of success,
but it is well to note, in the real Norman story, that the very bard
in front of their battle-line was shouting the glorification of failure.
It testifies to a truth in the very heart of Christendom that
even the court poet of William the Conqueror was celebrating
Roland the conquered.
That high note of the forlorn hope, of a host at bay and a battle against
odds without end, is the note on which the great French epic ends.
I know nothing more moving in poetry than that strange and unexpected end;
that splendidly inconclusive conclusion. Charlemagne, the great
Christian emperor, has at last established his empire in quiet,
has done justice almost in the manner of a day of judgment, and sleeps
as it were upon his throne with a peace almost like that of Paradise.
And there appears to him the angel of God crying aloud that his
arms are needed in a new and distant land, and that he must take
up again the endless march of his days. And the great king tears
his long white beard and cries out against his restless life.
The poem ends, as it were with a vision and vista of wars against
the barbarians; and the vision is true. For that war is never
ended which defends the sanity of the world against all the stark
anarchies and rending negations which rage against it for ever.
That war is never finished in this world; and the grass has hardly
grown on the graves of our own friends who fell in it.
THE SUPERSTITION OF SCHOOL
It is an error to suppose that advancing years bring
retrogressing opinions. In other words, it is not true that men growing
old must be growing reactionary. Some of the difficulties of recent
times have been due to the obstinate optimism of the old revolutionary.
Magnificent old men like Kropotkin and Whitman and William Morris
went to their graves expecting Utopia if they did not expect Heaven.
But the falsehood, like so many falsehoods, is a false version
of a half-truth. The truth, or half-truth, is not that men must
learn by experience to be reactionaries; but that they must learn
by experience to expect reactions. And when I say reactions I
mean reactions; I must apologise, in the world of current culture,
for using the word in its correct sense.
If a boy fires off a gun, whether at a fox, a landlord or a
reigning sovereign, he will be rebuked according to the relative
value of these objects. But if he fires off a gun for the first
time it is very likely that he will not expect the recoil, or know
what a heavy knock it can give him. He may go blazing away through
life at these and similar objects in the landscape; but he will be
less and less surprised by the recoil; that is, by the reaction.
He may even dissuade his little sister of six from firing off one of
the heavy rifles designed for the destruction of elephants; and will
thus have the appearance of being himself a reactionary. Very much
the same principle applies to firing off the big guns of revolution.
It is not a man's ideals that change it is not his Utopia that is altered;
the cynic who says, "You will forget all that moonshine of idealism
when you are older", says the exact opposite of the truth. The doubts
that come with age are not about the ideal, but about the real.
And one of the things that are undoubtedly real is reaction:
that is, the practical probability of some reversal of direction,
and of our partially succeeding in doing the opposite of
what we mean to do. What experience does teach us is this:
that there is something in the make-up and mechanism of mankind,
whereby the result of action upon it is often unexpected, and almost
always more complicated than we expect.
These are the snags of sociology; and one of them concerned
with Education. If you ask me whether I think the populace,
especially the poor, should be recognised as citizens who can
rule the state, I answer in a voice of thunder, "Yes". If you ask
me whether I think they ought to have education, in the sense
of a wide culture and familiarity with the classics of history,
I again answer, "Yes". But there is, in the achievement
of this purpose, a sort of snag or recoil that can only be
discovered by experience and does not appear in print at all.
It is not allowed for on paper, even so much as is the recoil of a gun.
Yet it is at this moment an exceedingly practical part of
practical politics; and, while it has been a political problem
for a very long time past, it is a little more marked (if I may stain
these serene and impartial pages with so political a suggestion)
under recent conditions that have brought so many highly respectable
Socialists and widely respected Trade Union officials to the front.
The snag in it is this: that the self-educated think far too much
of education. I might add that the half-educated always think
everything of education. That is not a fact that appears on
the surface of the social plan or ideal; it is the sort of thing
that can only be discovered by experience. When I said that I wanted
the popular feeling to find political expression, I meant the actual
and autochthonous popular feeling as it can be found in third-class
carriages and bean-feasts and bank-holiday crowds; and especially,
of course (for the earnest social seeker after truth), in public-houses.
I thought, and I still think, that these people are right on a vast
number of things on which the fashionable leaders are wrong.
The snag is that when one of these people begins to "improve himself"
it is exactly at that moment that I begin to doubt whether it
is an improvement. He seems to me to collect with remarkable
rapidity a number of superstitions, of which the most blind
and benighted is what may be called the Superstition of School.
He regards School, not as a normal social institution to be fitted
in to other social institutions, like Home and Church and State;
but as some sort of entirely supernormal and miraculous
moral factory, in which perfect men and women are made by magic.
To this idolatry of School he is ready to sacrifice Home and
History and Humanity, with all its instincts and possibilities,
at a moment's notice. To this idol he will make any sacrifice,
especially human sacrifice. And at the back of the mind,
especially of the best men of this sort, there is almost always
one of two variants of the same concentrated conception:
either "If I had not been to School I should not be the great man I
am now", or else "If I had been to school I should be even greater
than I am". Let none say that I am scoffing at uneducated people;
it is not their uneducation but their education that I scoff at.
Let none mistake this for a sneer at the half-educated; what I dislike
is the educated half. But I dislike it, not because I dislike education,
but because, given the modern philosophy or absence of philosophy,
education is turned against itself, destroying that very sense of
variety and proportion which it is the object of education to give.
No man who worships education has got the best out of education;
no man who sacrifices everything to education is even educated.
I need not mention here the many recent examples of this monomania,
rapidly turning into mad persecution, such as the ludicrous persecution
of the families who live on barges. What is wrong is a neglect
of principle; and the principle is that without a gentle contempt
for education, no gentleman's education is complete.
I use the casual phrase casually; for I do not concern myself
with the gentleman but with the citizen. Nevertheless, there is
this historic half-truth in the case for aristocracy; that it
is sometimes a little easier for the aristocrat, at his best,
to have this last touch of culture which is a superiority
to culture. Nevertheless, the truth of which I speak has
nothing to do with any special culture of any special class.
It has belonged to any number of peasants, especially when they
were poets; it is this which gives a sort of natural distinction
to Robert Burns and the peasant poets of Scotland. The power which
produces it more effectively than any blood or breed is religion;
for religion may be defined as that which puts the first things first.
Robert Burns was justifiably impatient with the religion he inherited
from Scottish Calvinism; but he owed something to his inheritance.
His instinctive consideration of men as men came from an
ancestry which still cared more for religion than education.
The moment men begin to care more for education than for religion
they begin to care more for ambition than for education.
It is no longer a world in which the souls of all are equal before heaven,
but a world in which the mind of each is bent on achieving unequal
advantage over the other. There begins to be a mere vanity in being
educated whether it be self-educated or merely state-educated. Education
ought to be a searchlight given to a man to explore everything,
but very specially the things most distant from himself.
Education tends to be a spotlight; which is centred entirely on himself.
Some improvement may be made by turning equally vivid and perhaps
vulgar spotlights upon a large number of other people as well.
But the only final cure is to turn off the limelight and let him
realise the stars.
THE ROMANCE OF A RASCAL
It was Thackeray, I think, somewhere in the dizzy mazes of his
Roundabout Papers, who made a remark which throws some light on
literary fashions and the fate of Smollett's Peregrine Pickle.
He described very vividly the fervour he felt as a boy for the
Waverley Novels; and how those great romances filled the boyhood
of those, like himself, who were to make the literature of that
most romantic epoch which we call in England the Victorian era.
He adds an interesting comment to this effect: "Our fathers used
to talk about Peregrine Pickle, telling us (the sly old boys)
that it was capital fun. But I think I was rather bewildered by it."
That, I fear, may be the immediate effect upon many either
of Thackeray's period or even of our own period, where it has
inherited the great literary tradition, which many learnt in youth
from Thackeray, and which Thackeray learnt in youth from Scott.
Most of those who grew up under such standards of fiction,
as did the present writer, may be disposed to say at first
that they find Smollett's novel rather bewildering. Not quite
so bewildering as some of the most modern novels, of course.
But many people seem to have a singular literary test, by which they
like being bewildered by a new book, but dislike being bewildered
by an old one. As I shall point out presently, this is very
largely because the new book is not so new as it pretends to be.
And the old book is not so very old, as the real stages of history go.
In short, the real moral of all these things is the astonishing
rapidity with which moods and standards change and change again;
often changing back from the third condition to the first.
There is nothing so mystifying as the rapidity with which new literary
methods harden, except the brittleness with which they break.
Each traveller who turns the corner thinks it will lead him into a
straight road of progress; but really it leads him, in about ten minutes,
to another corner which turns into another and equally crooked road.
The point about a book like Peregrine Pickle can be fixed
fairly precisely, by considering what are the changes that separated
him from Thackeray, or that separate Thackeray from us.
In that little phrase from the Roundabout Papers there are,
to begin with, some interesting and even amusing points.
For instance, we are always told that the Victorian parent, or, even more,
the early nineteenth-century parent, was a Puritan who forbade his
family the idle as well as the improper forms of light literature;
a Heavy Father who sat very heavily even on ordinary love-stories
or romantic plays. Even so eighteenth-century a type as Macaulay
identified the opinion of most sober and responsible parents with so
extraordinary a parent as Sir Anthony Absolute in the comic play.
"A circulating library is an evergreen tree of diabolical knowledge."
Even a modern so steeped in the eighteenth century as Mr. Max Beerbohm
has described the typical papa of a generation that might well
have been that of Thackeray's papa, as a gloomy and ponderous
person who talked to his children about nothing but Hell.
Surely that one little glimpse from Thackeray's own essays might
lead one to guess that there is something wrong in all this.
It is difficult to imagine the Puritan papa, who commonly talked
about Hell, winding up with a recommendation to read Peregrine Pickle.
It is difficult to suppose that a race of Sir Anthony Absolutes,
disapproving of all novels, would have gone out of their way
to select this novel, out of all earthly novels, on the ground
that it was "capital fun". The parent must have been a very sly old
boy indeed if he really thrust Peregrine Pickle on the attention
of a little boy, whose head was full of ideals of chivalry,
like those of Quentin Durward and Ivanhoe.
The truth is that the elements were too mixed, and, above all,
the fashions too fugitive, for any of these generalisations.
Men who lose traditions abandon themselves to conventions;
but the conventions are more fleeting than fashions. There were
papas who would have been almost as much shocked at their daughters
reading Pride and Prejudice as at their reading Peregrine Pickle.
But they were the papas and not the grand-papas. There was
a sort of household where Hell was the brightest topic of chat;
but it was not the old-fashioned household but rather
the new-fashioned household. It came in with the Methodists,
who were regarded as innovators and rebels. That episode of
extreme severity, which was the beginning of the highly expurgated
Victorian fiction, need not here be traced to its historical causes.
Broadly speaking, it came from the rapid increase of wealth and power
among the Nonconformists of the north, who vetoed the frankness
both of the old gentry and the old peasantry of the south. The point
here is that the work of these Puritans, from Lancashire or Yorkshire,
was so very rapidly done that men forgot that it was so very recent.
All this has to be understood before anybody, looking back through
the nineteenth century, can do justice to the work of Smollett.
The point of it is that not only did the changes come, but each
generation accepted them as if they had always been unchangeable.
Thus, in the case just mentioned, Thackeray began to write novels
long after Dickens; he was still an artist, or art student,
when he offered to illustrate Pickwick. Dickens, in the flood
of his popularity that followed Pickwick, had already accepted
and popularised what we call the Victorian conventions.
This has been somewhat harshly expressed by Mr. Aldous Huxley when
he said that a writer like Dickens writes as if he were a child,
while a writer like Smollett writes as if he were a grown man.
But indeed there is a considerable link between a writer like Smollett
and a writer like Aldous Huxley. For the road has taken another
sharp turn backwards; and the interlude of Victorian innocence is
again out of sight. There is one instance of this, which dominates
and largely explains the whole story of Peregrine Pickle.
When Thackeray called Vanity Fair "a novel without a hero",
or even when he made the relatively realistic Pendennis a novel
with a rather unheroic hero, he was doubtless by that time
so accustomed to Victorian fiction as to feel that he was doing
something new, and even "cynical". For Victorian fiction had already
returned to the old romantic idea that the hero should be heroic,
even if it did not understand him so well as did the old romances.
Nicholas Nickleby vanquishes Squeers as St. George vanquishes the dragon;
and John Ridd is a knight without fear or reproach, like Ivanhoe.
But in fact Thackeray was only slightly reacting towards what had
been universal in the time of that sly old boy, his papa.
All novels like Peregrine Pickle, all novels up to the time
of Pickwick, were written frankly on a far more cynical convention:
that the hero should not be heroic. The enterprising Mr. Pickle
is certainly not heroic. He is many things that are good;
not only brave, but often warm-hearted and considerate; and, above all,
capable of recognising better men than himself. But, for the rest,
by Victorian and even by normal standards, he is simply a coarse
and rapacious rascal; nor does Smollett really pretend that he is
anything else. This tendency to follow with delight the tricks
and triumphs of somebody little better than a swindler comes from
the historical origin of this type of story, which began in what is
called the picaresque novel. It is the romance of a wanderer,
apt to turn from the romance of a peddler to that of a highway robber.
It is a curious coincidence that Smollett translated Gil Blas,
in which this new cynical romance made its first triumph; and also
translated Don Quixote, in which the road was cleared for it by the rout
of the old romances which had made their heroes impossibly heroic.
But about this sort of rambling tale, of the Romance of a Rascal,
there are certain modern misunderstandings to be avoided.
It would be complete misunderstanding of men like Tobias Smollett
to suppose that because the heroes are immoral the authors
are even unmoral. It is a peculiar characteristic of all that
stalwart school, which represented this picaresque element in
England that they do believe in heroism for anybody except heroes.
Both in Fielding and Smollett and others we find a sort of fixed habit
of thought, by which virtue is represented, and is even preached,
and is often preached vehemently and in terms of authority;
but never by the principal character, who is a young man of the world
apparently not expected either to preach it or to practise it.
Parson Adams is a serious picture of a good man, and Joseph Andrews
is only a bad joke; but Joseph gives his name to the book.
Fielding is more concerned with Tom Jones than with Alworthy;
but be agrees with Mr. Alworthy and not with Tom Jones.
And if anyone wishes to note exactly how this habit expresses
itself in Smollett, let him turn to the typical scene in
which Peregrine Pickle provokes a duel with Mr. Gauntlet.
By all possible standards Peregrine is to behave like a vulgar
and low-minded cad, actually sneering at the poverty of the soldier
whom he has insulted, and being ignominiously defeated by the man
he has so coarsely despised. Certainly no Victorian romancer
would have dragged his hero through the mud of such a meeting.
And yet the whole incident brings out in glowing colours all that is
really good and lovable about Peregrine Pickle. He does vividly
realise that the other man is more virtuous than himself; he acts
as impetuously on the moral as on the immoral impulse;. he apologises
after defeat, which is more difficult than apologising before it.
In other words, Mr. Gauntlet, like Parson Adams, stands for something
fixed and recognised; a virtue which the other characters venerate
even while they violate. In this incident Peregrine is represented
in the course of an hour or so as behaving almost incredibly badly
and then almost incredibly well; and yet it is quite credible.
Why do we thus feel that there is something solid in it after all?
First, no doubt, because Smollett was a real novelist,
and the character of Peregrine Pickle was a real character.
He does convey what later sentiment would have called the contradiction:
that Peregrine was a scoundrel, but a warm-hearted scoundrel; that lie
was very near to being a swindler, but always an impetuous swindler.
But it is due, almost as much, to the sense of firmness produced
by the fact that vice and virtue are still treated as facts.
Our sense of sincerity is founded on the fact that Tobias Smollett,
as well as Peregrine Pickle, did really believe in right and wrong,
and thought the principal character wrong and the secondary
character right.
It is here that we find the chief difference between old writers
like Smollett and many modern writers who set themselves
successfully to produce the same convincing smell of dirt,
the same unmistakable ugliness in the details of life,
the same slippery and sometimes slimy irresponsibility about sex,
the same heroic persistency in avoiding heroism. The difference
is that Smollett's hero, or villain, does know exactly where he is
in the moral world, even if it is where he ought not to be.
The modern adventurer of the same type occupies all his adventures
in trying to discover where he is. He is not so much breaking
laws with bravery and cunning, as trying to learn the laws,
with constant bewilderment and despair. Virtue does not rebuke him;
the best that can be said for him is that vice generally bores him.
Therefore he is not wholly successful in copying the older writers
in their two gifts of lucidity and grossness; because he lacks
the third angle of the triangle: their confidence.
Considered as a series of chapters, Peregrine Pickle is simply a chapter
of accidents. Curiously enough the splash it made in its own day,
especially in the sparkling world of wit and fashion, was almost entirely
due to what almost anybody would now call the dullest part of the book.
The insertion called "Memoirs of a Lady of Quality" was supposed
to have some scandalous allusiveness to aristocratic society at
the time; but it is not typical of the author, or even of the book.
Nor can we in practice class this patchy and parenthetical style
with the similar irregularity of a book like Pickwick. Most people,
at least most mature people, have read Pickwick. Comparatively few,
even among the most aged people, have read Peregrine Pickle.
There cannot be very many sly old boys still going about the street,
and advising modern youth to read it and find it capital fun.
To many it must now be introduced as a new book rather than an old one;
and the method of approach is sharply divergent. In writing of Dickens,
we are writing for our fellow Dickensians, and can prove any point
or illustrate any theory by examples they know as well as we.
I do not think it is unfair to say that if I were to begin by referring
the average reader to the well-known attitude of Mr. Metaphor,
or the incident of Mr. Hornbeck, he would hardly be so suddenly
illumined as by a reference to Mr. Stiggins or Mr. Weller.
In cases like this, where an historic work by a man of genius is not
now widely popular, or in immediate contact with the reading public,
the cause and the problem can almost always be found in certain
changes of taste which, rapid as they are, do correspond
largely to changes of ideas. A man who opens Peregrine Pickle
must not expect what he gets from a good Victorian novel,
or a good modern novel; and only by some explanation of principles
can he ever discover that it may contain things quite as good.
It is well, therefore, to emphasise some general qualities that are
even better. The novel of Smollett's time was better than the novel
of the Victorian time, in so far as it recognised more clearly
that good and evil exist and are entangled even in the same man.
The novel of Smollett's time was better than the novel of our own time,
in so far as it recognised that, even when they are entangled in
the same man, they can still be distinguished and are very different,
and at war till death.
PAYING FOR PATRIOTISM
Somebody was recently remonstrating with me in connection with certain
remarks that I have made touching the history of English misgovernment
in Ireland. The criticism, like many others, was to the effect
that these are only old unhappy far-off things and battles long ago;
that the present generation is not responsible for them;
that there is, as the critic said, no way in which he or I could
have assisted or prevented them; that if anyone was to blame,
he had gone to his account; and we are not to blame at all.
There was mingled with his protest, I think, a certain suggestion
that an Englishman is lacking in patriotism when he resurrects
such corpses in order to connect them with crime.
Now the queer thing is this: that I think it is I who am standing
up for the principle of patriotism; and I think it is he who is
denying it. As a matter of fact, I am one of the few people left,
of my own sort and calling, who do still believe in patriotism;
just as I am among the few who do still believe in democracy.
Both these ideas, were exaggerated extravagantly and,
what is worse, erroneously, or entirely in the wrong way,
during the nineteenth century; but the reaction against them
today is very strong, especially among the intellectuals.
But I do believe that patriotism rests on a psychological truth;
a social sympathy with those of our own sort, whereby we see our own
potential acts in them; and understand their history from within.
But if there truly be such a thing as a nation, that truth is
a two-edged sword, and we must let it out both ways.
Therefore I answer my critic thus. It is quite true that it
was not I, G. K. Chesterton, who pulled the beard of an Irish
chieftain by way of social introduction; it was John Plantagenet,
afterwards King John; and I was not present. It was not I,
but a much more distinguished literary gent, named Edmund Spenser,
who concluded on the whole that the Irish had better be exterminated
like vipers; nor did he even ask my advice on so vital a point.
I never stuck a pike through an Irish lady for fun, after the siege
of Drogheda, as did the God-fearing Puritan soldiers of Oliver Cromwell.
Nobody can find anything in my handwriting that contributes
to the original drafting of the Penal Laws; and it is a complete
mistake to suppose that I was called to the Privy Council when it
decided upon the treacherous breaking of the Treaty of Limerick.
I never put a pitchcap on an Irish rebel in my life; and there was
not a single one of the thousand floggings of '98 which I inflicted
or even ordered. If that is what is meant, it is not very difficult
to see that it is quite true.
But it is equally true that I did not ride with Chaucer to Canterbury,
and give him a few intelligent hints for the best passages
in The Canterbury Tales. It is equally true that there was
a large and lamentable gap in the company seated at the Mermaid;
that scarcely a word of Shakespeare's most poetical passages
was actually contributed by me; that I did not whisper to him the
word "incarnadine" when he was hesitating after "multitudinous seas";
that I entirely missed the opportunity of suggesting that Hamlet
would be effectively ended by the stormy entrance of Fortinbras.
Nay, aged and infirm as I am, it were vain for me to pretend that I lost
a leg at the Battle of Trafalgar, or that I am old enough to have seen
(as I should like to have seen), ablaze with stars upon the deck
of death, the frail figure and the elvish face of the noblest
sailor of history.
Yet I propose to go on being proud of Chaucer and Shakespeare and Nelson;
to feel that the poets did indeed love the language that I love
and that the sailor felt something of what we also feel for the sea.
But if we accept this mystical corporate being, this larger self,
we must accept it for good and ill. If we boast of our best,
we must repent of our worst. Otherwise patriotism will be a very
poor thing indeed.
THE PANTOMIME
Mr. Maurice Baring, the chief Puppet-Master of the Puppet-Show
of Memory, has included in a recent reprint, I am glad to see,
an item that I have loved long since and lost awhile, in the form
of a scene from the old Drury Lane sort of Harlequinade,
recast in the manner of the mystical plays of Maeterlinck.
It was probably written when Maeterlinck was very much the fashion,
and when people had long been saying that the Harlequinade was
hopelessly old-fashioned. In one sense it would be difficult to say
which of the two is more old-fashioned now. But, to judge by current
criticism and conversation, there are many who remember Pantaloon
and Harlequin who hardly even remember Pélleas and Mélisande. It
is a queer thing to note the extent to which the world has become
silent about Maeterlinck; though it may be the more impressive
to the remaining followers of so eloquent an admirer of silence.
Whatever be the cause, it certainly was not that his work was devoid
of a very individual imaginative quality. Personally, I should guess
that he had shared the fate of many modern attempts to refound mysticism
on something less real rather than something more real than this world.
But the matter only arises here in relation to this little literary
jest about the Pantomime, which I always felt to be one of Mr. Baring's
most charming fancies. Of course it is a very good burlesque
of Maeterlinck; it is also in a sense a very good burlesque of
the Pantomime; and the latter is the more delicate achievement.
Every healthy person wishes to make fun of a serious thing;
but it is generally almost impossible to make fun of a funny thing.
But in this case the notion of fun or burlesque must not be confused
in either case with any idea of hostility, or even of satire.
Parody does not consist merely of contrast; at its best it rather
consists of a superficial contrast covering a substantial congruity.
The bitter sort of burlesque may exist, and have a right to exist;
but it is doubtful whether in this particular form the bitterest
is the best. The one sort of parodist will naturally parody the sort
of style he dislikes. But the other sort of parodist will always
prefer to parody the style he likes. I remember in my boyhood,
when Swinburne was our (rather too bubbly) champagne, I for one wrote
almost as many conscious travesties of Swinburne as unconscious
copies of him.
Now in this case of the Pantomime the paradox has a sort of moral.
For I know that the real reason why I return with unwearied
joy to Mr. Baring's little Maeterlinckian Harlequinade is
because the atmosphere of the harlequinade really was for me,
if not exactly Maeterlinckian, at least in some mysterious
sense mystical. I need not dwell on the points in the parody
which were witty considered as contrasts as well as coincidences.
The policeman repeats at intervals, like the tolling of a funeral bell
(a lost and wandering bell attached to no church and uttering in
its hollow throat an awful agnosticism), "It was not on my beat."
The Pantaloon, one of the shivering old men of Maeterlinck,
babbles not of green fields but of grey and ghostly sausages, as of
things he will never find, or is not certain that he ever did find.
But my point here is that, in spite of the comic contrast
between the hilarity of the Pantomime and the hopelessness
of the Maeterlinckian atmosphere, there really is something that,
for me at least, melts the two into a sort of mystical unity; so that
the top-heavy house of the Harlequinade is even here like my home.
For I am quite certain, as a fact of psychology, that I did
even in childhood regard the knockabout part of the Pantomime
with its pokers and sausages, as being none the less a poetical
part of the Pantomime; and as unmistakably within the frontiers
of fairyland as the palace of the Fairy Queen. Never on earthly
anvil, never in earthly fireplace, did that red poker gleam:
never those clattering milkcans brim with an earthly cream.
The Policeman was perfectly right about both scenes and in both senses.
He was not on his beat. He was a stray and estranged policeman;
a policeman stolen by the fairies; a constable wandering
far away from his constabulary duties, if he ever had any.
The joke depended on the very Victorian accident that the costume
of a London policeman seemed both commonplace and comic;
and yet, although he was comic, he was not really commonplace.
He was not merely befooled but bewitched; and his blue uniform
revisited the glimpses of a blue moon. Still, it is curious to
reflect how completely different the whole drama would have seemed
if he had been any sort of foreign gendarme, with a cocked hat
and a sword.
Now my interest in the matter is this; that I know many will say
that this sense of glamour is an effect of distance, like the colour
of blue hills or crimson clouds; and that in this romantic aspect it
is only a puppet-show of memory. They would say that I saw it in this
mystical manner through the intervening veils of time, through the mists
of Maeterlinck, through the mockeries of Mr. Baring, and, above all,
through that depth of delicate melancholy with which the remote
past is remembered. But I am certain that this is not so.
Apart from the fact that the memory of childish joys does not
make me melancholy (it is perhaps a fine shade of theology)
and apart from the fact that I suspect that Mr. Baring himself
remembers the thing very much as I do, I am quite sure that I
am remembering a reality that was real then as well as now.
You could as soon persuade me that the taste of toffee was an
illusion that only came to me in later years, or that I think
I liked roast chestnuts then only because I like them now,
as convince me that I did not have, even as a child, an overwhelming
impression that this farcical world was fantastic, not merely
in the sense of being comic, but also in the sense of being mystic.
Though the scene might superficially seem completely constructed out
of objects made as much as possible prosaic, I had an instant inward
certainty that they were all poetic. The sky above those staggering
chimneys was not the sky above the chimneys in the street outside;
its stars would have been strange stars; for I had looked
round another corner of the cosmos. To wander in the streets
of that strange town would have been as unearthly an experience
as to wander in the Blue Forest round Bluebeard's Sapphire Palace,
or along the Golden Orange-Groves in the gardens of Prester John.
Not verbally, but quite vividly, I knew then, exactly as I know now,
that there is something mysterious and perhaps more than mortal
about the power and call of imagination. I do not think this early
experience has been quite rightly understood, even by those modern
writers who have written the most charming and fanciful studies
of childhood; and I am not so presumptuous as to think that I can
scientifically succeed where I think they have somehow vaguely failed.
But I have often fancied that it might be worth while to set down
a few notes or queries about this difficult and distant impression.
For one thing, the ordinary phrases used about childish fancies
often strike me as missing the mark, and being in some subtle way,
quite misleading. For instance, there is the very popular phrase,
"Make-believe." This seems to imply that the mind makes itself
believe something; or else that it first makes something and then
forces itself to believe in it, or to believe something about it.
I do not think there is even this slight crack of falsity in the crystal
clearness and directness of the child's vision of a fairy-palace--
or a fairy-policeman. In one sense the child believes much less,
and in another much more than that. I do not think the child
is deceived; or that he attempts for a moment to deceive himself.
I think he instantly asserts his direct and divine right to enjoy beauty;
that he steps straight into his own lawful kingdom of imagination,
without any quibbles or questions such as arise afterwards out of false
moralities and philosophies, touching the nature of falsehood and truth.
In other words, I believe that the child has inside his head
a pretty correct and complete definition of the whole nature
and function of art; with the one addition that he is quite
incapable of saying, even to himself, a single word on the subject.
Would that many other professors of aesthetics were under
a similar limitation. Anyhow, he does not say to himself,
"This is a real street, in which mother could go shopping."
He does not say to himself, " This is an exact realistic copy
of a real street, to be admired for its technical correctness."
Neither does he say, "This is an unreal street, and I am drugging
and deceiving my powerful mind with something that is a mere illusion."
Neither does he say, "This is only a story, and nurse says
it is very naughty to tell stories." If he says anything,
he only says what was said by those men who saw the white blaze
of the Transfiguration, "It is well for us to be here."
This is the beginning of all sane art criticism: wonder combined
with the complete serenity of the conscience in the acceptance
of such wonders. The purity of the child largely consists in its
entire absence of morality in the sense of Puritan morality,
and all the modern and muddled moralities that have sprung from it,
scientific and provincial and equivocal, especially the confusions
about different meanings of words like "fact" and "fable" and falsehood.
The problem is very close to the real problem about images.
A child knows that a doll is not a baby; just as clearly as a real
believer knows that a statue of an angel is not an angel.
But both know that in both cases the image has the power of both
opening and concentrating the imagination. Stevenson, whom I
shall always count a fountain of fine inspiration, and certainly
a man gifted with the eye that sees the daydreams of childhood
in broad daylight, was nevertheless not quite sound on this example,
possibly because he was not quite sound on the other.
He talks too often of the child having his head in a cloud
of confusion and indifference to fact or fancy. I believe that
our difficulty with the child has the directly opposite cause.
It comes because the child is perfectly clear about the difference,
not only between truth and falsehood but between fiction and falsehood.
He understands the two essential types of truth: the truth of the mystic,
which turns a fact into a truth where it should be turned into a truth,
because the alternative is a triviality; and the truth of the martyr,
which treats a truth as a fact, where it should be treated as a fact,
because the alternative is a lie. In other words, the child knows
perfectly well without being told the difference between saying
he has seen the policeman cut in two in the pantomime, and saying
he has seen his little brother break the jug in the nursery,
when he really broke it himself. It is we who have grown confused
about these categories, and cannot realise the swiftness and clarity
with which the child accepts what we call the convention of art.
Looking at the street down which the clown pursues the policeman
with a poker he would never dream of saying in the ordinary sense,
indeed he would never dream of saying at all, "That is a real street."
But still less would he ever dream of saying, "That is an unreal street."
He has a better understanding of dreams--and visions.
In the case of the Pantomime there is one plain fact which clenches
this conviction for me. I know I knew that the scenery and costume
were "artificial", because I deeply rejoiced that they were artificial.
I liked the notion that things were made of painted wood or plastered
by hand with gold and silver. These were the vestments and ornaments
of the ritual; but they were not the rite, still less the revelation.
I liked the magic-box called a stage, because there, for some reason,
the light that never was on sea or land was on paint and paste-board.
But I knew perfectly well that it was paint and paste-board.
It would be impossible for anybody not to know that who had
a toy-theatre of his own. In the Pantomime of my childhood,
with its somewhat simpler scenery, there were tricks of mere stage
carpentry which I enjoyed as much as if I were working them myself.
There was one way of representing tossing waves, by rank behind
rank of escaloped blue walls as groundpieces, moved in opposite
directions so that the crests seemed to cross and dance.
I knew how it was done, because my father did it himself before my
very eyes, in my own toy-theatre at home. But it gave me such ecstasy
that even now when I think of it for an instant my heart leaps up
like the wave. I knew it was not water, but I knew it was sea;
and in that flash of knowledge I had passed far beyond those who suffer
the fixed and freezing illusion, uttered by the pessimistic poet,
that "the sea's a lot of water that happens to be there."
In imagination there is no illusion; no, not even an instant of illusion.
For no split second even then did I believe that people
had cut in two a live man--even if he was only a policeman.
If I had believed it, I should have felt very different.
What I felt was that it was right; that it was a good and enlarging
and inspiriting thing to see; that it was an excellent thing
to look down on the strange street where such things could be seen;
in short, I could say then, with a quite undivided mind, that it
was a very good Christmas present to go to the Pantomime.
READING THE RIDDLE
An infinite number of years ago, when I was the chief weakness
of a publisher's office, I remember that there was issued
from that establishment a book of highly modern philosophy:
a work of elaborate evolutionary explanation of everything and nothing;
a work of the New Theology. It was called "The Great Problem Solved"
or some such title. When this book had been out for a few
days it began to promise an entirely unexpected success.
Booksellers sent to ask about it, travellers came in and asked for it,
even the ordinary public stood in a sort of knot outside the door,
and sent in their bolder spirits to make inquiries.
Even to the publisher this popularity seemed remarkable; to me
(who had dipped into the work, when I should have been otherwise employed)
it appeared utterly incredible.
After some little time, however, when they had examined
"The Great Problem Solved", the lesser problem was also solved.
We found that people were buying it under the impression that it
was a detective story. I do not blame them for their desire,
and most certainly I do not blame them for their disappointment.
It must have exasperated them, it would certainly infuriate me,
to open a book expecting to find a cosy, kindly, human story about
a murdered man found in a cupboard, and find instead a lot of dull,
bad philosophy about the upward progress and the purer morality.
I would rather read any detective book than that book.
I would rather spend my time in finding out why a dead man was
dead than in slowly comprehending why a certain philosopher had
never been alive.
But this little incident has always stuck to me as a symbol of
what is really wrong with modern popular religion. Why is a work
of modern theology less startling, less arresting to the soul,
than a work of silly police fiction? Why is a work of modern theology
less startling, less arresting to the soul than a work of old theology?
When those unfortunate clients bought "The Great Problem Solved",
perhaps it was inevitable that they should feel slightly cooled
and lowered in their vitality; perhaps no philosophical work can
really be so good as a good detective story. But at any rate
there need not have been such an absolute abyss between them.
People need not have felt that they had paid for the most
exciting kind of book and got the least exciting kind of book.
It cannot be right that religion should be the dullest of subjects.
There must be something wrong if the most important human business
is also the least exciting. There must be something wrong if
everything is not interesting.
A man called Smith goes out for a walk, and stops by a bookstall,
where he sees a book called "The Great Problem Solved". If Smith
finds that this book solves a problem in crime, he is entranced.
If Smith finds that it solves a problem in chess, he is interested.
If Smith finds that it solves the problem in the last issue of Answers,
he is genuinely excited. But if Smith finds that it solves the problem
of Smith, that it explains the stones under his feet, and the stars
over his head, that it tells him suddenly why it really is that he likes
chess or detective stories, or anything else; if I say, Smith finds
that the book explains Smith--then we are told he finds it dull.
It may be a democratic prejudice, but I do not believe this.
I think that Smith likes modern chess problems more than modern
philosophical problems for the very simple reason that they are better.
I think he likes a modern detective story better than a modern religion
simply because there are some good modern detective stories and no
good modern religions. In short, he buys "The Great Problem Solved"
as a police novel, because be knows that in a police novel, in some
shape or form, the great problem will be solved. And he does not buy
it as a book of modern philosophy, because he knows that in a book
of modern philosophy, the great problem will certainly not be solved.
This title as the title of a police romance is a sensation,
but as the title of a metaphysical work it is a swindle.
Those early friends of mine bought the book when they thought that it
solved the mystery of Berkeley-square, but dropped it like hot bricks
when they found that it professed only to solve the mystery of existence.
But if those people had really believed for a moment that it did solve
the mystery of existence they would not have dropped it like hot bricks.
They would have walked over hot bricks for ten miles to find it.
That forgotten book may stand as a type of all the new
theological literature. What is wrong with it is not that it
professes to state the paradox of God, but that it professes to state
the paradox of God as a truism. You may or may not be able to reveal
the divine secret; but at least you cannot let it leak out.
If ever it comes, it will be unmistakable, it will kill or cure.
Judaism, with its dark sublimity, said that if a man saw God
he would die. Christianity conjectures that (by an even more
catastrophic fatality) if he sees God he will live for ever.
But whatever happens will be something decisive and indubitable.
A man after seeing God may die; but at least he will not be
slightly unwell, and then have to take a little medicine and then
have to call in a doctor. If any of us ever do read the riddle,
we shall read it in brutal black and blazing white, exactly as we
do read the riddle of some sixpenny mystery of murder. If we ever
do find the solution, we shall know that it is the right solution.
This dark and drastic quality there has been certainly in all
real religions. The ordinary detective story has one deep quality
in common with Christianity; it brings home the crime in a quarter
that is unsuspected. In any good detective story the last shall
be first and the first shall be last. The judgment at the end of any
silly sensational story is like the judgment at the end of the world;
it is unexpected. As the sensational story always makes the apparently
blameless banker, the seemingly spotless aristocrat, the author
of the incomprehensible crime, so the author of Christianity told
us that in the end the bolt would fall with a brutal novelty,
and he that exalted himself would be abased.
The actual records of great religions are so terribly
theatrical that Mr. Bernard Shaw recently said that the story
of the Crucifixion in the Gospels was too dramatic to be true.
This is sufficiently characteristic of the Fabian political philosophy,
which has never lived in the heart of any heroic politics.
The story of Danton and Robespierre (to take an accidental example)
with its "speeches", "eternal daring", "If we do this our names
are never forgotten among men", "The blood of Danton chokes you",
"There is a God"--shows what men do say. These things were said,
and said suddenly, because the heart of man was high.
When man is at his utmost he is in a state indescribable;
he tells the truth or dies.
It is not in your lot or mine to live in a great or an ecstatic age.
Men talk of the noise and unrest of our age; but I think that all that age
is really very sleepy; all the wheels and the traffic send one to sleep.
The shrieking pistons and the shattering hammers are one enormous
and most soothing lullaby. But even in our quiet life I think
we can feel the great fact that is the core of all religion.
However quiet may be the skies, or however cool the meadows,
we always feel that if we did know what they meant the meaning
would be something mighty and shattering. About the weakest weed
there is still a sensational difference between understanding
and not understanding. We stare at a tree in an infinite leisure;
but we know all the time that the real difference is between
a stillness of mystery and an explosion of explanation.
We know all the time that the question is whether it will always
continue to be a tree or turn suddenly into something else.
A TALE OF TWO CITIES
A Tale of Two Cities was written in the later part of Dicken's
literary development, and in one respect stands absolutely alone
among all his works. It is, I think, the one solitary instance,
from which a critic in distant days could possibly deduce that this
very great literary man had ever read any literature at all.
This generalisation may be subject to certain partial modifications,
to be considered when we consider the course of his life; but as a
matter of proportion, which is the essential of truth, it is true.
In a thousand ways, ranging from the most depressing destitution
to the most pantomimic parade and luxury, Dickens showed that he had
studied life, and could turn life into literature. In a thousand moods,
ranging from the rankest vulgar farce to the most stagey and
melodramatic morality, he showed that he had within himself the powers
and passions and appetites to stock the whole world with stories.
But very seldom indeed, in enjoying the world of Dickens, do we
feel that there was really any writer but Dickens in the world.
Like all very creative men, he unfixes the dates of history,
and stands as a sort of immortal anachronism. It is sometimes with a
sort of start that we remember that his Hogarthian farce and tragedy
went on long after Keats had written "La Belle Dame Sans Merci"
and well into the time when Tennyson was writing the poems
of his best period, which was his Pre-Raphaelite period.
Dickens, in practice and in private life, was a very great admirer
of Tennyson. Forster, his biographer, says that his literary
tastes touching his contemporaries varied very much, but that
he never failed in his admiration of Tennyson. But I do not
honestly believe that anybody could guess, from any printed word--
from the first words about Mr. Pickwick and Mr. Blotton of Aldgate,
to the last broken and doubtful sentences that hint at the identity
of Datchery or the destruction of Drood--that Dickens had taken
any particular pleasure in "The Lady of Shalott", or "Sir Galahad".
It is partly a tribute to the strength of Dickens that his mind was
so teeming with images that he never needed to borrow mere ideas.
It is partly, also a real weakness in his position, that he had
never valued the great culture of the past, and therefore could
not fully understand its developments all around him in the culture
of the present. But, for good or evil, it is true that in
ninety-nine cases out of a hundred nobody (to use a popular phrase)
ever made a bulge in Dickens; nobody even made a dent in him.
He remained, with all his gifts and glories, solidly and almost
insolently himself. The one example, among all works of his authorship,
in which we feel even faintly the presence, or perhaps the shadow,
of another author, is A Tale of Two Cities; and that other author
is Thomas Carlyle.
As I have said, the normal human conditions necessary to his
normal human life, involved some modification of this statement.
He was very largely what is called a self-taught man, which means
that be was taught, not by himself, but by other people;
by other people acting as they really act in the real world,
and not as they pose before pupils they are paid to teach.
His domestic circumstances from the first were very insecure,
so that he saw more of books than of school-books; he learned more
from tattered volumes left about in a tavern than from grammars
provided primly in an educational establishment. But it is quite
true that among the tattered volumes in the tavern, or elsewhere,
there were some with titles not yet entirely forgotten: titles like
Robinson Crusoe and Tom Jones and Roderick Random and Tristram Shandy.
In this sense it is true that he, like every other human being who ever
wrote or even read, owed something to what had already been written.
And indeed the great comic classics, which were the glory of
eighteenth-century England, did leave a certain trend or track
in his mind, which is an utterly trackless waste as regards all
the things that anybody could ever have tried to teach him in school.
It is evident, however, from the very nature of the story itself,
that school in his case must have been almost as intermittent as truancy.
Charles Dickens was born in Portsea, adjoining Portsmouth,
in 1812, and was promptly carried away from it at the age of two.
He then became a Londoner for a few years, equally infantile;
and then his wandering family settled down in Chatham, which was about
the nearest approach it ever made to settling down anywhere. Thus we
find first the two facts, that are both determining and important:
one, that his family was one of very varied economic fortunes,
such as leads to frequent change of abode, and has indeed made the modern
poorer middle class almost as nomadic as Arabs; and the other,
that such background as a child of genius will always feel and value
(if he has half a chance to do it) was for Charles Dickens,
to the day of his death, the great roads of Kent that go down to Dover;
and the gardens and hopfields and the towers of Rochester Cathedral.
In so far as he had any traditions, that was his traditional environment;
just as in so far as he had any culture, it was that of the great
comic novelists of England a hundred years before. He was so far
traditional by instinct that he never forgot either of the influences;
he named one of his sons after Henry Fielding; and, when he came
to comfort and affluence, he made his home on Gad's Hill,
on that great Kentish road where Falstaff had played the glorious
fool long ago.
The private life of Dickens, however, is of little importance
to the outline of criticism here involved, and is indeed
in its own nature somewhat irrelevant and accidental.
Its chief tragedy was almost an accident, and its premature close
was a sort of defeat brought about by an excess of triumphs.
It is well known that in his early youth, while he was still
a parliamentary reporter living in London after his boyhood
in Chatham, he married the daughter of one of his literary patrons
named Hogarth, and that by a long process of disagreement,
about which critics can always disagree, he came to be alienated
from his wife; though, curiously enough, remaining on terms of
perfectly sober and fraternal friendship with one of her sisters.
There is no need to pronounce upon a problem which was really
kept private, by the not undignified prejudice of the Victorian time;
it is enough to say that no very grave charge was ever brought against
either party by any of the small group of people who knew the truth.
It is more relevant here to remark that at almost the same moment
as his marriage occurred his first and perhaps most triumphant
entry into literature. His first book, commonly called Pickwick
or the Pickwick Papers, is supreme among his works in many ways,
but especially in the way here in question: that it is a
purely personal creation and owes nothing to any other book.
It is all the more amusing to remember that a spiteful attempt
was made by some of his enemies to suggest that it owed
everything to its original illustrator, an artist named Seymour,
who drew spirited sporting sketches of the sort then fashionable.
It is a peculiarly false insinuation, in a literary sense.
For it is the whole point of Pickwick that its rush of inspiration
not only leaves Seymour's first ideas behind, but leaves Dickens'
first ideas quite as far behind. We might say that the whole
point of Pickwick is that it does not stick to the point;
or at least that the point is not Pickwick, in the sense of the
President of the Pickwick Club. The best things in Pickwick have
nothing to do with the principal characters, still less with the
preliminary chapters, and least of all with the early illustrations.
It is an exceptional case in which the story grows better the more
it strays from the story. Dickens did not preserve this limpid
and perfect liberty in his later stories. He produced better novels,
but never so good a book. Still, we can say of the ensuing series
of books that, whatever else they were, they were not bookish.
They showed Dickens interested in different things, but never
any other authors influencing Dickens. Thus, in his next book
Oliver Twist, which he seemed resolved to make as grim and lurid
as Pickwick had been gay and luminous, he was in fact protesting
against many social evils, which had already produced noble protests
from great men of that age. The workhouse he hated had been hated
as healthily by Cobbett or by Hood, by Cartwright or by Carlyle.
But nobody could say that one word of Oliver Twist sounds as if it
were suggested by the style of Cobbett or by the style of Carlyle.
Nicholas Nickleby and Martin Chuzzlewit show him even more
obviously walking down his own street, in some ways even a narrow
and Cockney street; the same applies to The Old Curiosity Shop;
and, though Barnaby Rudge is a sort of experiment in the way
of a historical novel, it is not much more really historical
than the Old Curiosity Shop or its Wardour Street curiosities.
Dombey and Son has the same now established balance of perfect
comedy and rather imperfect melodrama; and though David Copperfield
strikes far deeper, and releases a much finer spring of inspiration,
it is even more personal than the rest. Dickens has found a new
source of inspiration, but not by reading anybody else's book;
rather by reading his own diary. The same statement applies to that
fine book, Great Expectations, and a much sharper social criticism,
still extorted by contemporary facts rather than contemporary culture,
appears in the unconscious or unclassifiable Socialism of Hard Times.
It mixes his own observations less with mere fancies than did
his first protest in Oliver Twist; but it is always his own
observations and nobody else's. There is little to vary this
verdict in the other two novels of Bleak House and Little Dorrit.
It is only when we come to the book which is here specially
in question, A Tale of Two Cities, which appeared in 1859, that we
have anything like the particular impression of which I speak;
that Dickens has felt the pressure of an imaginative atmosphere outside
his own bursting sufficiency and energy, that energy from whose
centrifugal fury all fancies but his own had been spurned away.
This compact and competent, and some would say conceited, sense of
self-expression does in A Tale of Two Cities, for the first time,
seem to admit something external, something that might be called
an echo. Indeed, in one way, it might be called the echo
of an echo. It is Carlyle's French Revolution rather than
Michelet's French Revolution; in other words, it is not entirely
or exactly the French Revolution of the French Revolutionists.
Dickens does tend to neglect, as Carlyle did tend to neglect,
the extent to which the revolutionists themselves regarded it
not as an explosion of unreason, or even an explosion of passion,
but as an inevitable explosion of reason. They themselves
might almost have said that the explosion was an explanation;
as is the explosion that occurs during a chemical lecture.
Carlyle, who had laboriously studied all the documents and historical
literature of the French Revolution, never quite understood this.
It is small blame by comparison to Dickens, who had never studied
any documents or any history or any literature, or hardly any books
except his own, if he did not understand it either. But he had studied
one book, and that was Carlyle's book; and the shadow of that luminous
but lurid cloud lies over the whole landscape and scenery of his story.
It is very difficult to define or prove these merely atmospheric things.
A short if clumsy way of putting it is to compare the general tone
of Dickens towards the mere notion of a mob, as it is in Barnaby Rudge,
with his tone towards such a mob in A Tale of Two Cities.
The comparison, of course, is not quite fair. Even a man so little
in touch with history as he, could tell that the second was more
historic than the first; that the second was at least an outbreak
of liberty, by comparison with an outbreak of bigotry. But there
is more in the contrast than that; we feel that he could never have
taken a Gordon Rioter seriously, even if he had liked him, as he did
so often seem to like his most ludicrous and indefensible characters;
as the reader does really, in a way, like Sim Tappertit.
He did not like Madame Defarge, but he did take her seriously.
If she had occurred in Barnaby Rudge, she would have been a vulgar
villainess; as she occurred in A Tale of Two Cities, she is a Fate.
In other words, there is not only a romantic but a mystical element
that has entered the story; and though Dickens was in one sense
always a romantic, he was certainly never a mystic. In some sense
the comparison involves a paradox. Carlyle, as a reactionary,
declared that the mob, being made of most men, was made mostly of fools.
But Carlyle also allowed for a mystical suggestion that the folly
of men was the wisdom of God. Dickens, as a radical, regarded the mob,
in so far as it meant most ordinary men, as being composed of
reasonable and responsible citizens, whose votes were all valuable
and whose intellects were all capable of benefiting by education
and discussion. But, in practice, when Dickens did see a mass
of men in any sort of elemental disorder, acting in anger or by some
accident lawless or unlettered, he was deeply disgusted in every
corner of his compact and sensible intelligence, and hated that
very wildness which Carlyle half admired. Dickens felt like this,
for instance, towards the sprawling licence and spasmodic ferocity
of the more wild and western elements of the American Republic.
He would, if subjected to the real experience, have been quite as much
horrified by the ferocious pugnacity and spontaneous militarism
of the mob of the French Republic. Nevertheless, the Carlylean sense
of a sort of savage symbolism in the great struggles of history does
make the atmosphere of this book, or perhaps of half this book,
different from the whole bulk of his other books.
Perhaps it is really impossible for any good citizen to write A Tale
of Two Cities. He will always see one from the outside and the other
from the inside; and the line of relative reality and unreality in this
case runs fairly clear. Thus the description of the old-fashioned
London bank is unmistakably written by the old London Dickens.
The story of the sacrifice of Sydney Carton, though genuinely touching
and nobler especially as compared with some of the Dickensian melodramas,
is still in a sense a London melodrama, with the larger background
of a Paris tragedy. The hero is being heroic for private reasons;
whereas nobody understands or does justice to the French Revolution,
who forgets that half its leaders lost their heads by really
being heroic for public reasons. It is easy enough to make fun
of their classical rhetoric about Brutus who killed his sons,
or Timoleon who killed his brother; but it is not so easy to deny that,
if they had too much of this notion of sacrificing private good
to public good, we have far too much of the corruption and cowardice
that comes of sacrificing public good to private good. The ideals
for which that war was waged were insufficient but largely just;
and it is curious and rather moving to note that the author is so far
exalted by the atmosphere that he turns in the end to an older and
in truth a larger ideal, which exists before and after and affirms
the same justice in public and in private life. I know nothing
in all the works of this man of genius which is, in the true sense,
so imaginative as that last strange voice, coming from nowhere,
those great timeless words put into the mouth of no mortal character,
spoken suddenly as by a trumpet out of the empty sky, between the
click of the knitting-needles and the crash of the guillotine:
"I am the Resurrection and the Life . . ."
GOD AND GOODS
It is often noted, and generally truly enough, that Bolshevism
is necessarily connected with atheism. It is not so much realised,
perhaps, that atheism is now under an increasing necessity
of connecting itself with Bolshevism. For Bolshevism is at
least partly positive, even if it is largely destructive.
And the history of the purely negative notion, of an abstract attack
on religion, has been in this respect a rather curious history.
Taken as a whole, indeed it is at once melancholy and comic.
Those who in modern times have tried to destroy popular religion,
or a traditional faith, have always felt the necessity of offering
something solid as a substitute. The queer part of it is that they
have offered about a dozen totally different things; some of them
entirely contradictory things; that the promises perpetually varied,
and only the negative threat remained the same.
Just before the French Revolution, among the first eighteenth-century
philosophers, it was generally assumed that Liberty was not merely
a good thing, but the one and only origin of all good things.
The man living according to Nature, the Natural Man or the Noble Savage,
would find himself immediately free and happy so long as he never went
to church, and was careful to cut the parish priest in the street.
These philosophers soon discovered, what the parish priest could
have told them at the start, that it is rather more difficult to be a
happy animal, than to be a happy man. Indeed, a man cannot be an animal
for the same reason that he cannot be an angel; because be is a man.
But for some time the philosophers who did not believe in God,
whom they regarded as a myth, managed to believe in Nature without
realising that she is a metaphor. And they assured those whom they
waved on to the burning down of churches, that after that they
would be eternally happy in their fields and gardens.
Then after the political revolution came the industrial revolution;
and with it an enormous new importance attached to science.
The amiable atheists went back to the people, smiled at them,
coughed slightly, and explained that it was still necessary
to burn down churches, but that a slight error had been made
about the substitute for churches. The second atheist philosophy
was founded, not on the fact that Nature is kind, but on the fact
that Nature is cruel; not that fields are free and beautiful,
but that scientific men and industrialists are so energetic,
that they will soon cover all the fields with factories and warehouses.
Now there was a new substitute for God; which was gas and coal
and iron and the privilege of turning wheels in order to work
these substances. It was now positively stated that economic liberty,
the freedom to buy and sell and hire and exploit, would make
people so blissfully happy that they would forget all their dreams
of the fields of heaven; or for that matter of the fields of earth.
And somehow that also has been a little disappointing.
Two Earthly Paradises had collapsed. The first was the natural
paradise of Rousseau; the second the economic paradise of Ricardo.
Men did not become perfect through being free to live and love;
men did not become perfect through being free to buy and sell.
It was obviously time for the atheists to find a third inevitable
and immediate ideal. They have found it in Communism.
And it does not trouble them that it is quite different
from their first ideal and quite contrary to their second.
All they want is some supposed betterment of humanity
which will be a bribe for depriving humanity of divinity.
Read between the lines of half a hundred new books--outlines of popular
science and educational publications on history and philosophy--
and you will see that the only fundamental feeling in them is
the hatred of religion. The only positive thing is negative.
But they are forced more and more to idealise Bolshevism,
simply because it is the only thing left that is still new enough
to be offered as a hope, when every one of the revolutionary hopes
they have themselves offered has in its turn become hopeless.
FROM MEREDITH TO RUPERT BROOKE
The title of the Age of Reason has been given to the eighteenth century,
though the typical eighteenth-century man who invented it probably
meant it as a prophetic and optimistic description of the nineteenth
century or the twentieth century. Certainly if Thomas Paine
had foreseen the actual nineteenth century, he would have called
it the Age of Romanticism. If he had foreseen the actual
twentieth century, he would have called it the Age of Nonsense,
the Age of Unreason, especially in the departments originally
identified with rationalism, such as the department of science.
To him Einstein would have been merely a contradiction
in terms and Epstein a disease afflicting bronze and marble.
It is therefore not altogether misleading to measure modern developments,
for good or evil, as from a sort of datum line of simple or
self-evident rationality to be found in the eighteenth century.
Whatever else is false, it is false to say that the world has
increased in clarity and intelligibility and logical completeness.
Whatever else is true, it is true to say that the world has grown
more bewildering, especially in the scientific spheres supposed to be
ruled by law or explained by reason. The simplification of the older
rationalists may have been, and indeed was, an over-simplification.
But it did simplify and it did satisfy; above all, it satisfied them.
It would not be altogether unfair to say that it filled them
not only with satisfaction but with self-satisfaction. And,
as historical divisions are never clean-cut, this rationalistic
self-satisfaction descended in part to their children; in many ways
it may be found pervading the nineteenth century, and, in the case
of some rather old-fashioned persons, even our own century.
Nevertheless, the nineteenth century was very different;
and the Victorian Age was vividly different. And it was different
from the eighteenth century chiefly in this: that the old clarity
of rationalism and humanitarianism was more and more coloured
and clouded by certain waves of specially modern imagination
or hypothesis or taste and fancy. These new notions had been
unknown in the Age of Reason and even in the Age of Revolution.
These sentiments had never disturbed the generalisations of Jefferson
and the Jacobins any more than they had disturbed the doctrines
of Johnson and the Jacobites. These sentiments colour everything
in the Victorian Age, and they must be understood before attempting
any survey of it.
It is generally difficult to illustrate this truth without being
involved in a discussion about religion. But there is, as it happens,
another outstanding example, which does not directly involve
any interest in religion. I mean the enormous interest in race.
That would alone be enough to stamp the nineteenth century
as something sharply different from the eighteenth century.
That would alone be enough to mark off the Victorian from the older
Georgian frame of mind. In the eighteenth century, both the
reactionaries and the revolutionaries inherited the ancient religious
and philosophic habit of legislating for mankind. A man like Johnson
thought of men everywhere as under certain religious conditions,
though he thought them happier under conditions of subordination.
A man like Jefferson thought of men everywhere as under certain
moral conditions, though he thought them happiest in a condition
of equality. A man like Gibbon might doubt both the moral systems
of Johnson and Jefferson. But it never occurred to Gibbon
to explain the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire by exalting
the Teuton as such against the Latin as such, or vice versa.
Gibbon had religious prejudices, or, if you will, irreligious prejudices.
But the notion of having racial prejudices in a quarrel between
some brutal Vandal or Visigoth and some petty Byzantine official
would have seemed to him as nonsensical as taking sides among
Chinese tongs or Zulu tribes. Similarly, the eighteenth-century
Tories were traditional but not tribal. Even a man as late
as Metternich, while he might be on the watch against French
atheism or even Russian orthodoxy disturbing the Austrian Empire,
would have troubled his head very little over the fact that
the Austrian Empire contained a mixture of Teutons and Slavs.
The rise of this romance of race, or, as some would say, of this
science of race, was one of the distinct and decisive revolutions
of the nineteenth century, and especially of the Victorian Age.
It will be well to mark in what way these colossal clouds of historical
imagination or theory actually coloured or discoloured the dead daylight,
which an earlier rationalism thought to have dawned upon the world.
In the case of Victorian literature, perhaps it is best tested
by noting how it affected even the Victorians who might have been
expected to escape its effect. Carlyle was not merely affected by it
we might almost say that he was made by it. Anyhow, he was inspired
and intoxicated by it; he was at once overwhelmed and made overwhelming.
All his history and philosophy was full of this one idea: that all
that is good in our civilisation comes, not from the older civilisation,
but from a yet older thing that might be called a benevolent barbarism.
All light as well as fire, all law as well as liberty,
was supposed to be derived from a sort of ethnic energy originally
called Germanic, afterwards more prudently called Teutonic; and now,
with almost an excess of caution, called Nordic. The merits of this
racial theory, as against the old Roman theory, of European culture,
are difficult to discuss without trenching on controversial themes.
Personally I should say that when certain European provinces broke
with the Roman tradition, they set up certain Puritan theologies
of their own, which could not last, or at any rate have not lasted.
Anyhow, it is curious that in each of these provinces the place
of both the new and the old religion has really been taken by a stark
and rather narrow national pride. The Prussian is more proud of being
a Prussian than of being a Protestant, in the sense of a Lutheran.
The Orangeman is more proud of being what he calls an Ulsterman
than of being a Calvinist, in the sense of studying the strict
Calvinist theology. And even in England, where the atmosphere
was more mild and the elements more mixed, the same type of intense
insular self-consciousness has in some degree developed; and it has
been not untruly said that patriotism is the religion of the English.
In any case, to take the same test, an Englishman is normally
more proud of being an Englishman than of being an Anglican.
It was therefore not unnatural that when these lands, that were the
extinct volcanoes of the great Puritan fire, sought for a more modern
and general bond of association, they should seek it in that sort
of pride in the race, which is the extension of the pride in the tribe.
It is right to say that there is much in the idea of race that stirs
the imagination and lends itself to the production of literature.
The ideal of race, like the ideal of religion, has its own symbols,
prophecies, oracles and holy places. If it is less mystical,
it is equally mysterious. The riddle of heredity, the bond of blood,
the doom which in a hundred human legends attends certain houses
or families, are things quite sufficiently native to our nature to lend
a sincerity to the sense of national or even international kinship.
Many may quite honestly have felt that race was as religious as religion.
But one thing it certainly was not. It was not as rational as religion.
It was not as universal or philosophical as religion. At its best it
involved a sort of noble prejudice; and its romanticism clouded the old
general judgments upon men as men, whether dogmatic or democratic.
Carlyle was the most romantic of all these romantic Victorian writers,
and largely owed to this his predominance in the romantic Victorian age.
But his popular champions, like Froude and Kingsley, were even
more romantic; though in the case of Kingsley the romancing was really
honest romancing, while in the case of Froude (I cannot but think)
the word romancing is something of a euphemism.
Only, as I have said, the way in which this racial romance penetrated the
Victorian culture can best be seen, not in an obvious case like Carlyle,
but in much more remote cases like Matthew Arnold or Meredith.
To take the latter case first: George Meredith was in one sense
an entirely international intellectual; a Liberal humanist; a true
child of the French Revolution, which he celebrated in sumptuous odes.
But he illustrates the indirect effect of the racial craze,
which is that the other side often accepted the distinction.
Not only did the Teutonist talk about being a Teuton, but the Celt
talked about being a Celt. A great mass of Meredith's social
judgment is modified, and, to my taste, a little falsified,
by his insistence on setting the Saxon against the Celt, when he has
to set the Englishman against the Irishman or the Welshman.
He often satirised in the Englishman exactly what the Teutonist
praised in the Englishman; and it was often something that the
Englishman does not happen to possess. So in the other case:
Matthew Arnold made himself specially and supremely the apostle
of a cosmopolitan culture; he did a vast amount of real good
by insisting on the truism that England is a part of Europe.
He was at his best in a contempt for the contempt that was felt
for Frenchmen or Irishmen or Italians. But he could not bring
himself to treat them simply as Frenchmen or Irishmen or Italians.
He was affected by the universal fashion of ethnology and worried
by the racial generalisations. When he talked what was relatively
excellent sense about the senseless treatment of Ireland, he thought of
such things too much as Celtic Studies and too little as Irish Studies.
He also tried to explain the English faults as part of "the
German paste in us", and wasted on anthropology what was meant
for the study of mankind. We might take a third example.
William Morris was on one side a Communist and almost bound
to be an internationalist; he was on the other side a medievalist,
appealing to that ancient beauty that belonged to all Europeans alike.
But he was encumbered with a clumsy desire to be Saxon, to treat
English as if it were merely the rudimentary language of the Angles;
and moved his admirer, Stevenson, to an intense irritation by
writing "whereas" when he only meant "where".
I have mentioned this particular Victorian fashion, the racial
theory of history, as a primary and prominent thing, because it
is not generally mentioned at all. We are so accustomed,
in reading modern records of recent or ancient things, to gain
an impression of an ever-expanding world, called in the only too
typical Victorian expression, "the thoughts of men being widened
by the process of the suns", that we often forget the many periods
when the world contracted into a new narrowness or exclusiveness,
or the thoughts of men visibly shrank and shrivelled under some fresh
influence of isolation or distinction. This was certainly true of
the tribalism and imperialism that the nineteenth century developed,
out of a romance of races, as compared with the first revolutionary
generalisations about the human race. The fact is plain,
for instance, in the story of the first revolutionary experiment--
the American Republic. In the time of Jefferson, many of those
who held slaves disapproved of slavery; many of those who approved
of slavery did not specially approve of it as negro slavery.
The notion of the negro as something peculiarly perilous or
pestilent is not an ancient prejudice but a very recent and largely
anthropological fashion. It is akin to all that dates from Darwin;
and the popularisation by Huxley of an almost pessimistic type
of evolution. Modern Southerners are much more hostile to negroes
than they were when they owned slaves. As there rose recently
in America the anthropological theory that the negro is only an ape,
so there rose recently in Europe the anthropological notion that
the Pole is only a Slav, or that the Irishman is only a Celt.
People were so proud of discovering these larger groups that they
failed to notice that they are really looser groups. They belonged
to what the eminent Victorian truly called the fairy-tales of science.
They had neither the precision that belongs to doctrinal
definition nor the practicality that belongs to daily experience.
In religion and morals we all really know what we mean by a man,
and in the stress of real life we all really know what we mean
by an Irishman. It is by no means certain that we all know
what we mean by a Celt. Hence something large and imaginative,
but formless and partly imaginary, began to spread over popular
sentiment with the spread of popular science. It was darker and more
dubious than either the humanitarianism of the eighteenth century
or the nationalism of the nineteenth. It was not so clean-cut;
indeed I will venture to say that it was not so clean.
It was mixed with the mud and mist, the chaotic clay and cloud,
of primitive and even bestial beginnings; it had only vague
visions of barbaric migrations and massacres and enslavements.
It started all our recent preference for the prehistoric to the historic.
All this must be remembered as an influence overshadowing the second
half of the nineteenth century, because it eventually took a more
pointed and controversial form which involved not only materialism
but pessimism. The earlier rationalists may or may not have
been materialists; but they certainly were not pessimists.
They were, I admit, rather exaggerated and excessive optimists.
It is none the less curious that the general revolutionary tradition,
of revolt and criticism of conditions, which began with the philosophy
of Rousseau, should have ended with the philosophy of Thomas Hardy.
So much for one side of this later Victorian change.
But the mere mention of Hardy and the realistic rebels will
remind us that it had another side, which was a very good side.
Probably speaking, it consisted in turning the attention
from purely political wrongs to fundamental economic wrongs.
In this also Carlyle, who belongs to the earlier period,
continues to colour and even control the destinies of the later.
In the matter of dates Carlyle and Macaulay covered the same period.
In the matter of destinies they lived in two different centuries.
Macaulay was, for good and evil, entirely a man of the
eighteenth century. He was a Whig as Fox had been a Whig;
a patriot as Pitt had been a patriot; a Protestant as any Erastian
latitudinarian Georgian parson had been a Protestant; a logician
as Dr. Johnson was a logician; a historian as Gibbon was a historian.
Carlyle, who had brought into history the doubtful romance of blood,
also brought into politics the very real tragedy of bread.
He stands at the beginning of all the best efforts of the later
Victorians to face the problems of labour and hunger that had
developed in the depths of the new industrial civilisation.
With the great exception of Cobbett, who had stood apart and alone,
misunderstood and abused by all parties, it is fair to say that
Carlyle started much of the merely social unrest of conscience
which has modified the evils of the later nineteenth century.
It is needless here to weigh the evil against the good;
or to discuss how much of a certain disinterested dignity,
in the old Republicans, was lost in his practical and impatient
clamour for captains and for kings. It is only necessary to insist
on the reality of the contrast and the change. Grattan, a great
and typical orator of the eighteenth-century ideal, had said
that the Irishman might go in rags, but he must not go in chains.
Ruskin and the social reformers reversed the principle,
until some of the extreme Socialists, like the Marxian Communists,
are now inclined to say that a man must go in chains so that he may
not go in rags.
Ruskin was the heir and representative of Carlyle in this later
and better Victorian development. It is unnecessary to react
against romanticism to such an extent as a recent critic,
who summed up Ruskin in a book on the Victorians by saying that at
least his economics were all scientifically sound though he could
not write for toffee. He certainly could not write in that stately
modern style in which toffee figures as the prize of writing.
When the critic suggests that he could not write, it merely means
that the critic does not like that particular sort of writing,
which proves rather the limitations of the critic than the incapacities
of the writer. Ruskin certainly wrote poetical prose, which may
not for the moment be fashionable in an age of prosaic poetry.
But to say that it is not good poetical prose is simply
to be ignorant of the varied possibilities of good writing.
It is also true that what he did he overdid, which is largely true
of the whole of this highly coloured and romantic final development
of Victorianism. Even those few who deliberately tried to correct it
by understatement managed somehow to overstate their understatement.
Matthew Arnold deliberately endeavoured to introduce a French
classical balance and critical detachment into English letters.
The consequence was that he was called a prig, which was unjust but
not unthinkable; whereas no Frenchman reading Saint-Beuve ever thought
of thinking that he was a prig. Walter Pater wished to create an art
criticism more detached than that of Ruskin; but he did in fact manage
to create the impression of being artificial as well as artistic.
It was very difficult to be classic in the later Victorian atmosphere.
There was a romantic unrest about it, so that even the umpires
were competitive and combative. The loss of a natural repose,
in Latin logic or French clarity, was one of the penalties of parting
with the spirit of the eighteenth century. Another mark of it was
the growth of an intellectual individualism which expressed itself,
not only in being outré, but actually in being obscure.
Browning and Meredith were among the very greatest of Victorians;
and over both of them brooded that cloud I have described as coming
up to over-shadow the epoch; and though it was coloured gorgeously
like a cloud of sunset, it none the less came between many people
and the sun.
George Meredith largely stood alone; but he stood as it were
representing many others who had also a taste for standing alone.
All this last phase is full of men whom it is interesting
to remember and yet very easy to forget. It was because of the
individualistic isolation of their talents and even their topics.
An example is Richard Jefferies, who was "The Gamekeeper At Home";
or T. E. Brown, who made a niche for himself that is somehow
at once obscure and popular: or William de Morgan, who with
English eccentricity took up literature as a hobby for old age.
The danger of all grouping is that we may miss too many of these men
who did not fit into groups. Nevertheless, there are two or three
groups which may be said to bulk biggest in the period--the period
after the triumph of Tennyson and Browning in poetry, or Dickens
and Thackeray in fiction. First there appears, primarily through
the influence of Ruskin, what was called the Pre-Raphaelite Group;
which began with a Ruskinian version of Christian medievalism and
shaded off into later forms of aestheticism, not to say Paganism.
The leader, who was also the link, was Rossetti, who accepted with
delight the medieval pattern, but blazoned it with bolder and warmer
colours than some of the literal Pre-Raphaelites would have approved.
With him went his sister Christina, who was medieval in the more
orthodox sense; and, in a manner very much his own, William Morris,
who made the medieval form the expression of modern discontents
and social ideals, instead of Christina Rossetti's religious ideals.
The queer transition of the Pre-Raphaelites from a revival of
Christianity to a revival of Paganism is complete in the poet Swinburne,
who belonged to the set, yet had little in common with the sect.
That it had Ruskin at one end and Swinburne at the other illustrates
how loose a thing a group is, especially in English literature.
Swinburne had three phases; one in which he wrote the best
poetry in the worst spirits, or mood or frame of mind for his
beautiful boyish singing is not merely in praise of Paganism,
but definitely of Pessimism. There is a second period when his
spirits are a little better and his poetry a little worse;
the period of his political enthusiasm for United Italy and
Victor Hugo and the resounding qualities of the word Republic.
There is, unfortunately, a third period, in which he imitated
himself and did it badly. But the point to seize is that, in his
great hour, Swinburne was a spell; he held people like a magic flute,
till they forgot that there was any other melody in the world.
It is thoroughly typical of such glamours that there has been a violent
and very unreasonable reaction against his unreasonable power.
With him and Walter Pater the movement ends in its last pagan phase;
save perhaps for the queer aestheticism that later became a decadent
dandyism in Oscar Wilde.
But already new groups were making this one look old.
One was what may be called the Picaresque or Adventurous Group,
but may be more recognisable as the group of Stevenson and Henley.
Both for good and evil, they reacted into a robust blood-and-thunder
literature, which, in the case of Stevenson, who was not only
the greater but much the more amiable and balanced of the two,
was as blameless as it was bloody. There was, however, a dangerous
double use of the very word "blood". And, quaintly enough, the more
dubious element is to be found rather in blood than in bloodshed.
The blood that spatters the pages of Treasure Island can only
promote a respect for the real virtues of courage or loyalty.
The blood that is not shed at all, but remains in the human body,
was used to encourage a respect for the real vices and weaknesses of pride
and racial contempt. For one important point about this group is this:
that through them, or some of them, there came into full power
and possession that curious religion of Race, which I have described
as developing from Teutonic sources a little time before. It is not
to be confused with patriotism or the unselfish love of one's country.
It is a mere pride in being oneself of a certain real or imaginary
race or stock. The Frenchman loves France as if she were a woman;
the Nordic Man merely loves himself for being a Nordic Man.
This weakness did to some extent spoil the spirited attempt
of Henley and his school of masculine critics; I mean their
very just attempt to show that letters should be red-blooded,
as against the green-blooded pessimism of the decadents.
But whatever their weaknesses, they did fill the age with a new change
and stir, and gave to the pessimists something which if not a cure,
was at least an antidote and a counter-irritant. The earliest
and best work of Mr. Rudyard Kipling came to them like a new breath
of prophecy and promise; Sir Henry Newbolt supported the chorus
with two or three of the very finest modern English lyrics.
There was a general fashion of patriotic poetry, as well as of
Jingo journalism--in verse or otherwise. It was the only point
on which that strongest and most virile of the pessimists,
the Shropshire Lad, could be moved for a moment to a slightly
blasphemous cheerfulness. John Davidson, a dark Scot in a dark
and even dim state of revolt against everything, also was ready
to follow the flag and revolt against everything except the Empire.
The point of all this is not that patriotism revived,
for the older poets and critics took patriotism for granted:
but that the special type of tribal imperialism sprang out of that
rather barbaric root of Race, already noted as a romance of science,
which reacted against the rationalism of the Revolution.
Fortunately, from the same Stevenson and Henley stock of ideas,
came another idea that also filled the age. It came from Stevenson
alone, as distinct from Newbolt, Henley, Kipling and the rest,
and may be called the cult of the child, but especially of the boy.
It would be putting it too harshly, perhaps, to say that Stevenson
wanted to go on playing at robbers; whereas Henley and the Imperialists
wanted to be robbers. Anyhow, Stevenson saw the fun of what he was
doing when be made the child say that he was the captain of a tidy
little ship; whereas it is, I believe, the inscrutable fact that
Henley did not see any fun in what he was doing when he adjured
John Bull to "Storm along, John", and assured that public character
that the whole world would soon be his own. Through Stevenson's
truly magic lantern, which he described in The Lantern-Bearers,
there shone a true reillumination of the mystical melodrama of childhood.
And in that light many followed to the same sort of fairyland;
notably Sir James Barrie, who introduced a sort of irony into fairyland.
He continued what may be called the Stevensonian stereoscopic view;
the looking at the same object in a double fashion, with the eye
of the adult and of the child. But it was mostly through a string
of accidental friendships that this fantastic element was connected with
the more realistic of the robust school, though of course there were many
brilliant individuals who could only be placed with or near that group.
Thus Joseph Conrad, though a Pole, was connected with it by his
record of hard or violent adventure at sea; and Mr. John Masefield,
though he wrote later and longer poems of rural sport or religion,
began with rousing sea songs of the buccaneers.
Already, however, a new voice had been heard, and a new influence
balanced or rebuked an influence like that of Kipling; and it was
a voice from a more remote elfland than the elfland of Peter Pan.
Stevenson himself said that he had twice in poetry heard a new note
or a unique and arresting voice: once when he read Love In A Valley
by George Meredith; and once again when he read some verses
called The Lake Island of Innisfree by William Butler Yeats.
Yet it is worth remarking that there still remained this curious
persistence of the romance of race, even in what was so naturally
hostile to the popular romance of the Anglo-Saxon race.
The appearance of a new cultural nucleus in Dublin, while it derived
something from the Pre-Raphaelites, and therefore something from
the Victorians, was so far Victorian in this special respect, that it
managed to get entangled like all the rest with an ethnological term:
the term "Celtic". It did not even substitute the old Irish term
"Gaelic". It is true that Mr. Yeats himself, the founder of the school
and one of the first poets of recent times, did not really base his
own case on anthropology, but rather on history and (very rightly)
even more on legend. But it marks the racial influence already
described that the word "Celtic" stuck to the movement, which was really
a revival of remote legend and a gentle heathenism of the hills.
It also explains why there was some reaction against it even in its
own home. There are many who came not to care very much about
the Celtic Twilight, who have lived to see the Irish Dawn.
About this time, or a little later, in England, there appeared
a group formally called Minor Poets; though one of them was certainly
a Major Poet. He was classed at the time with John Davidson and
Sir William Watson, both of them very genuine poets in their own style;
and there is some charming lyricism in their contemporaries,
Norman Gale and Richard le Gallienne. Two other writers of fine verse
really belong to this period: Ernest Dowson and Lionel Johnson.
But I think it fair to say that Francis Thompson, thus classed
as one of them, was of another and altogether higher class.
He owed something to Coventry Patmore, one of the most
really original Victorians, and something to Alice Meynell,
a woman who was a poet (not a poetess) of the sort that women
were least supposed to be; an intrinsically intellectual poet.
But even of these friends he was free; with all the freedom of a
creative and supremely productive or fertile genius. His imagery
was so imaginative as to be almost crowded; and, in a different sense
from the more analytical Victorians, dark with excess of light.
Because he was Catholic many would expect him to be Gothic;
but there was something in his exuberance that resembled rather
the very best of the Baroque.
The necessity of marking the period by moods has led us here to mark it
too exclusively by poets, who are the only permanent record of moods.
It need not be said that work of another and what some think a more
solid sort had been going forward in those last years; some of it
very solid indeed, certainly in the best and perhaps also in the more
questionable sense. Fiction, for instance, had followed other guides
besides romance. The immense influence of Thomas Hardy was there;
with his strong sense of the truth of the earth, as also of the tragedy
of the dust. It had set many able men working in a mine of realism.
The two ablest and most typical in this tradition were Arnold Bennett
and John Galsworthy. If I do not speak here at length of men
of genius like H. G. Wells and Bernard Shaw, it is because they
are in a sense the opening of another world, and are most vividly
lit up by the glare of the Great War and the existing social perils;
and these things really mark the close of the period. For an appalling
apocalypse came upon all life, and therefore upon all literature;
and the most fitting emblems of such splendour and terror,
and the arts of peace torn across, and youth going to its death singing,
remain with the last few poems of Rupert Brooke.
THE DANGERS OF NECROMANCY
We often lament that the world is divided into sects, all with
different narrow ideas. The real trouble is that they all have
different broad ideas. It is when it comes to being broadminded
that they are most narrow, or at any rate most different.
It is their generalisations that cut across each other.
The Buddhist believes he is broadminded when he says that all efforts
at personal achievement and finality, east or west, Christian or Buddhist,
are equally vain and hopeless. But I think that is a narrow negation,
sprung from special spiritual conditions in Upper India.
A modern agnostic thinks he is broadminded when he says that all
religions or revelations, Catholic or Protestant, savage or civilised,
are alike mere myths and guesses at what man can never know.
But I think that is a narrow negation, sprung from special spiritual
conditions in Upper Tooting. My idea of broadmindedness is to sympathise
with so many of these separate spiritual atmospheres as possible;
to respect or love the Buddhists of Tibet or the agnostics of Tooting
for their many real virtues and capacities, but to have a philosophy
which explains each of them in turn and does not merely generalise
from one of them. This I have found in the Catholic philosophy;
but that is not the question here, except in so far as there is,
I think, just this difference: that the largeness of the other
schemes is an unreal largeness of generalisation, whereas the
largeness of our scheme is a real largeness of experience.
Anybody can say that all Africans are black, but it is not the same
as having a wide experience of Africa.
This difference about the obvious in generalisation struck
me sharply, and with some amusement, in a debate on Spiritualism
in the Daily News. A well-known secularist said that it is all
very well to say that scientific men and intelligent people
accept Spiritualism; but (he added, as with a sort of hiss)
remember that wise men for ages actually accepted Witchcraft.
He returned more than once to this biting and blasting word;
and the argument obviously was, "Modern spirit-rapping by men like Lodge
may look very plausible and scientific; but a ghastly fate awaits you;
you will be the derision of history; you will be compared to the brutal,
brainless, bestially ignorant people who believed in Witchcraft.
Ha, ha, how will you like that?"
Now all this makes me smile in a sad but broad-minded manner.
Because it seems to me to be quite the other way. I am not by any
means certain, one way or the other, that there is really such a
thing as Spirit-rapping. I am absolutely certain that there is such
a thing as Witchcraft. I impute a belief in it to common sense,
to experience and the records of experience, and to a broad view
of humanity as a whole. I impute disbelief in it to inexperience,
to provincial ignorance, to local limitations, and all the vices
that balance the virtues of Tooting. Common sense will show that
the habit of invoking evil spirits, often because they were evil,
has existed in far too vast a variety of different cultures,
classes and social conditions to be a chance piece of childish credulity.
Experience will show that it is not true that it disappears
everywhere before the advance of education; on the contrary,
some of its most evil ministers have been the most highly educated.
Record will show that it is not true that it marks barbarism rather
than civilisation; there was more devil-worship in the cities of Hannibal
and Montezuma than among the Esquimaux or the Australian bushmen.
And any real knowledge of modern cities will show that it is going
on in London and Paris today.
The truth is that the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries had
their little local limitations, which are already breaking down.
Wishing to expel the superhuman and exalt the human, they grossly
simplified the human. The great Huxley (on whose name be praise)
said in the innocence of his heart, "It may be doubted if any man
ever really said, 'Evil, be thou my good.'" He could not believe
that any scepticism could touch common morality, by which he really
meant Christian morality. But such innocence is also ignorance.
Nothing is more certain than that certain highly lucid,
cultivated and deliberate men have said, "Evil, be thou my good";
men like Gilles de Rais and the Marquis de Sade. Please God they
repented in the end, but the point is that they did pursue evil;
not pleasure, or excess of pleasure, or sex or sensuality, but evil.
And it is quite certain that some pursued it beyond the bounds
of this world; and called evil forces from beyond. There is very
good evidence that some of them got what they asked for.
Now a Catholic starts with all this realistic experience of humanity
and history. A Spiritualist generally starts with the recent
nineteenth-century optimism, in which his creed was born,
which vaguely assumes that if there is anything spiritual,
it is happier, higher, lovelier and loftier than anything we yet know;
and so opens all the doors and windows for the spiritual world
to flow in. But we think this is just as simple an ignorance
as if an eighteenth-century sentimentalist, reading into Rousseau
a notion that savage man is like Adam in Eden, had gone to live in the
Cannibal Islands to be surrounded with happiness and virtue. He would
be surrounded, perhaps, but in a more bodily and unpleasant sense.
One sentimental fashion may assume there are no cannibals;
another optimistic fashion that there are no devil-worshippers--
or no devils. But there are. That is the fact of experience
that is the key to many mysteries, including the mysterious policy
of the Roman Catholic Church.
GIOTTO AND ST. FRANCIS
St. Francis of Assisi has been for ages a popular saint;
in our own age he has for the first time been in some danger
of being a fashionable saint. That sort of distinction of
the drawing-rooms, which is said to have been a temptation rejected
by many saints in their lifetime, which is certainly a peril
besetting most popular preachers all their lives, has come at
last to this popular preacher six hundred years after his death.
It is natural that artists should be interested in the poet who was
practically the founder of medieval and therefore of modern art.
And it is only too true that, wherever we admit the artist, it is very
difficult to exclude the aesthete. This sort of light literary fuss,
though often sincere as a sentiment and even valuable as a tribute,
is the very opposite of that sort of solid and traditional popularity
which St. Francis had among countless generations of peasants.
There is something about peasant traditions, and even about
peasant legends, which knows how to keep close to the earth.
It is a mark of true folklore that even the tale that is evidently
wild is eminently sane. We see this in the most extravagant stories
of the saints, if we compare them with the extravagant theories
of the sophists and the sentimentalists. Take, for instance,
that most beautiful attribute for which St. Francis is rightly loved
throughout the modern world: his tenderness towards the lower animals.
It is illustrated in medieval folklore by fancies but not by fads.
It is impossible to imagine any fable more fabulous, in the sense
of fantastic and frankly incredible, than the story of St. Francis
making a business bargain with a very large and dangerous wolf;
drawing up a legal document with carefully numbered promises
and concessions from the party of the first part and the party
of the second part; the wild beast solemnly lodging a legal
affidavit by the number of times he nodded his head.
And yet there is in that fairy-tale a rustic and realistic sagacity
that comes from real relations with animals, and is therefore perhaps
called by the picturesque name of horse-sense. It was not written
by the modern monomaniac animal-worshipper. It is a pleasant story
because the saint is considering the peasants as well as the wolf.
St. Francis was not the sort of man to agree with the hypothetical
Hindoo who would be slowly devoured by a Bengal tiger, and remain
in a state of philosophical absent-mindedness, because tigers are quite
as cosmic as Hindoos. The Christian common sense of St. Francis,
even in this wild fable, seized on the vital fact; that men must
be saved from wolves as well as wolves from hunger, or even more so,
and that this could only be done by some sort of definite arrangement.
And it does put its finger upon the difficulty; in the absence
of communication and therefore of contract between men and beasts.
It realises that a moral obligation must be a mutual obligation.
St. Francis contemplating the mountain wolf, hits on the same point
as Job contemplating the monstrous Leviathan: "Will he make
a pact with thee?" That is a sort of solid popular instinct,
which was never lost by the really popular saint, in spite of anything
which strangers might stare at as his antics or his agonies.
Men remembered that he had been a good friend to them as well as to
birds and beasts; and the fact is still apparent in the most remote
and extravagant rumours of him. It is in this that he differs from some
of the rather unbalanced and unnatural humanitarians of modern times.
As a matter of fact, St. Francis does not by any means stand alone among
medieval or other saints in this protest and protection of animals
against men; though he probably does stand alone in his poetical
and imaginative power of stamping the memory of it in picturesque
images on the popular mind. Some of the greatest medieval priests
long before St. Francis, St. Anselm, for instance, were famous
for demanding kindness to the brute creation; many of them, St. Hugh
of Lincoln, for instance, had an even more eccentric taste in pets;
for St. Hugh, instead of preaching to the birds, seems to have
allowed a large bird to accompany him everywhere like a curate.
But what is notable about this medieval theory of mercy is something
ultimately mild and reasonable, however freakish was its expression;
a comprehension of the common needs of common people, and a
humanitarianism that did not exclude humanity. In that sense,
it is the modern age that is the age of fanatics.
This fact of St. Francis becoming a modern fashion, after having
been for so long a medieval tradition, might well arouse in his
real admirers a fear of his cult becoming merely artistic in
the sense of merely artificial. And yet, in spite of one or two
incongruous interventions, this has not really taken place.
It is perhaps the highest tribute to the truth and sincerity
of St. Francis that even now he can keep his simplicity in the face
of fashionable admiration; as the Franciscan in the story kept
the fashionable crowd at a distance by playing antics on a seesaw.
And this remarkable escape from the suffocation of sophistication is
nowhere better expressed than in what still remains, even to the eye
of the traveller--the naked nobility of his native town.
A traveller at all experienced in the ways of travellers, not to say
of trippers, will approach the steep city of Assisi with some
feelings of doubt and even of fear. He will know that the modern
discovery of the medieval saint may yet be followed by disasters,
more subtle than those which superstition has traced in the modern
disinterment of the Egyptian king. He will know that there are things
to which guide-books are not the best guides; which are seen better
by solitary pilgrims than by sociable tourists; and, without any sort
of superiority let alone misanthropy, he will have had experience already
of places which crowds of visitors have made less worth visiting.
He will know that quarrels not untouched by quackeries have insulted
the great silence of Glastonbury; he will know that there is some
truth in the report that a bustle of sight-seeing and a bawling for
baksheesh has spoiled for many the spiritual adventure of Jerusalem.
Knowing how many aimless aesthetes, how many irresponsible intellectuals,
how many mere sheep of show and fashion follow this track through Italy,
he may well fear to find obliterated the ancient simplicity of Assisi.
But when he sees it, if I may answer for at least one among many
such travellers, he will receive what I can only describe as a cool
shock of consolation.
The city is founded upon a rock; the city is a rock; and it is too
simple for anybody to spoil. It has proved practically impossible
to paint or gild or pad or upholster or even to scratch that rock.
In the main lines of it an austerity alone remains in the memory;
and even the beauty of the milder landscape is itself austere.
There may be, indeed there is, the usual accumulation in corners
of the popular trinkets or traditional toys of devotion, which some
people are so unfortunately fastidious as to resent; but that is
not the sort of peril of which I am thinking, even from the point
of view of those who would admit it to be in other ways perilous.
It is not a question of any abuses among the ignorant or the innocent
who look up to the saint; it is a question of the condescending culture
that looks down to him; not a matter of importing idolatry into the
institution of a patron saint; but a matter of patronising the patron.
And though multitudes in this rather snobbish state of mind must have
passed through so established a station of the Italian pilgrimage,
they have not in fact left any trail behind them, as they have
in so many similar places; the hills have forgotten them and their
personalities have passed away with the smell of their petrol.
St. Francis is still left alone with his own friars and mostly
with his own friends; and especially with that great first friend
who was his interpreter to the expanding civilisation that came
after him; the friend who could express in images what Francis
himself had always felt as imagery, or what we call imagination;
the painter who translated the poet--Giotto.
The advance of art criticism is a continual retreat; it would seem
in some strange manner destined to march perpetually backwards into
older and older periods. At the beginning of the nineteenth century
the critics had finally accepted the normality of the Ancient Greeks.
By the end of the nineteenth century the critics were already inaugurating
the novelty of the Ancient Egyptians. We must all, by this time,
be familiar with expressions of admiration for the art of the Caveman,
scrawled in rock and red ochre with an unmistakable spirit and
even distinction of draughtsmanship; the cult of the prehistoric
which has given a new meaning to the cult of the Primitives.
It will soon seem perfectly natural to be talking about the modernised
and decadent sophistication of the Second Stone Age as compared
with the rich but well-balanced civilisation of the First Stone Age.
The further we go back to explore, the more we find that is
really worth exploring; and the nearer we are to the real
primitive man, the further we are from the ape or even the savage.
This being true even of the tremendous scope of the whole history
of the human tribe, it is not to be wondered at that men have made
the same discovery about the high and complex culture of Christendom.
The spotlight of artistic interest and concentration has been
steadily travelling backwards ever since I was a child.
I can remember faintly that in my first years it was still felt as
something of a paradox to maintain that the quaintness of Botticelli
could be taken as seriously as the solid finish of Guido Reni;
that Ruskin was still a revolutionist for preferring the dayspring
of the Renaissance in the fourteenth century to the dregs
of the Renaissance in the eighteenth. Even as late as that,
for most people, Giotto was still not so much a Primitive
as a primitive man. He was a sort of savage who had done some
service by discovering that it was possible to scratch something
resembling a rudimentary human figure on the walls of his cave.
For most people all serious art still lay between Raphael and Reynolds.
As I grew up, the Ruskinian revolution prevailed, and most men came
to realise that Giotto was a great painter; but even those men
generally regarded him as the first great painter. But now, in yet
more recent times, the artists are yet more like archaeologists,
in the sense of going back to what is yet more archaic.
The change that has passed over the most recent phase of art
criticism can be sufficiently suggested by this one case of Giotto.
I referred somewhere, in the Ruskinian manner, to Giotto as the figure
who stands at the beginning of Christian art. One of the most
creative of modern sculptors, whom many would call a medievalist,
wrote to assure me that Giotto stands at the end of Christian art;
with something like a broad hint that Giotto brought it to an end.
The spotlight has moved further back, and is now illuminating
what even Ruskin and the romantic medievalists would have regarded
as a desert of dead and barbaric formalism; the true Dark Ages.
Our Progressives are now bound with golden chains to the
decline of Byzantium, rather than to the rise of Florence.
It is quaint to think how little harm a blundering nickname need
do in the long run. All the admirers of Gothic call it Gothic,
though it was originally meant to stamp it as barbaric. And all
the admirers of Byzantine call it Byzantine; though the very adjective
is already in use as a symbol of stiff degradation and decline.
The new theories about rhythm and design have done justice to the old
pictures which the romantics regarded merely as diagrams or patterns.
The change from Cimabue to Giotto is at least not so certainly
an unmixed improvement as it appeared to the Victorian medievalists.
There is, as it were, a new school of Pre-Raphaelites, who are not
only pre-Raphael, but pre-Giotto. The shining figure of the shepherd
no longer stands against a background of black and barbarous darkness;
but in a sort of double light, in itself involving some of these
subtler problems of balance and recurrence; having on his right hand
the wide white daybreak of Rome and Assisi and Paris and all the West,
and on his left the long and gorgeous golden sunset of the great
city of Constantine.
But in truth this double light may make for a better enlightenment,
both about Giotto and his master St. Francis. The two artistic movements,
coming one after the other, have between them done some justice
to two halves of medieval history, and an earlier and a later period
of Christendom, both of which had been underrated and misunderstood.
There is a sort of mathematical beauty in the harshness of Byzantine
art which is only beginning to be understood; but there is none
the less another and livelier kind of beauty in the more humanised art
of the later Middle Ages; something suggestive of a moment when a dead
design comes to life, or a pattern begins to move, or even to dance.
Some humorist wrote a work called "The Loves of the Triangle",
and a mystical theologian might find in it a profound significance
touching the loves of the Trinity. In other words, the old abstract
expression of divine beauty was the expression of a truth, but the other
truth of its expression in the concrete was none the less true.
Now what is true of the early abstract art and the humanistic
revolution of Giotto, is equally true of the abstract theology
and the humanistic revolution of Francis. Some modern writers
on the first Franciscans talk as if Francis was the first to invent
the idea of the Love of God and the God of Love; or at least was
the first to go back and find it in the Gospels. The truth is that
anybody could find it in any of the creeds and doctrinal definitions
of any period between the Gospels and the Franciscan movement.
But he would find it in the theological dogmas as he would find
it in the Byzantine pictures, drawn out in stark and simple lines
like a mathematical diagram, asserted with a sort of dark clarity
for those who can appreciate the idea of logical content and balance.
In the sermons of St. Francis, as in the pictures of Giotto,
it is made popular by pantomime. Men are beginning to act it as in
a theatre, instead of representing it as in a picture or a pattern.
Thus we find that St. Francis was in many ways the actual founder of
the medieval miracle play; and there is all this suggestion of a stiff
thing coming to life in the tale of his contact with the Bambino,
illustrated in one of Giotto's designs. And thus we find in Giotto
himself a quality unique and hardly to be repeated in history.
It is a sense, not only of movement, but of the first movement.
There is still something in his figures that suggests that they
are like the pillars of a church moved by the spiritual earthquake
of a divine visitation, but even so moved slowly and with a sort
of reluctant grandeur. The figures are still partly architectural
while the faces are alive with portraiture. This first moment
of motion has much to do with that sense of morning and youth
which so many admirers of medievalism have felt, and which I shall
continue to feel, with all respect to the medievalist sculptor.
Nothing is nearer to the nerve of primal wonder, which is the soul of
all the arts, than that strange saying of the blind man in the Gospels,
that when he was half awakened to sight, he saw "men as trees walking."
There is something about the figures of Giotto that suggests men
as trees walking. The Byzantine School will not permit me to say that
before his eyes were thus opened, the artist had been wholly blind.
But I will still maintain that there was something like a miracle,
in the transition from treating trees as tracery and men as trees,
to the realisation of the new shock of liberation; and how,
at the word of God, they could arise and walk.
And here again we strike the parallel between the artist and the saint.
The followers of St. Francis were, above all things, men who could walk.
Many of them even walked with that sort of dazed unfamiliarity
and doubtful balance, being suddenly robbed by a whirlwind of all
the props of property. But they walked, because a new spirit
of walking, and even of wandering, had entered into the static
scheme of medieval Christianity; just as a new spirit of gesture
and drama had entered into the static scheme of decorative art.
The difference between the Friars and the Monks was, after all,
that the Friars now walked like men where the Monks had once stood
like statues. I mean nothing but admiration for the Benedictine monks,
as for the Byzantine mosaics: or, for that matter, the grand
and almost grim rationality of the great abstract dogmas.
But there had come upon these flat and spacious things,
carved in stone or ordered like statues, a new depth or dimension;
a new quality of drama and motion. The popular propaganda of
St. Francis, throwing thousands of wandering friars out into roads
of the world, was the beginning of what we call the modern spirit;
the spirit of romance and experiment and earthly adventure.
For once a modern phrase which is much misused, may be rightly used.
The Benedictines were, in the exact sense, an Order; as the plan
of a cathedral is an Order. The Franciscans were, in the exact sense,
a movement. Historically, perhaps, the most interesting of the great
pictures by Giotto which are displayed in the Upper Church of Assisi,
is that which commemorates the famous dream of the great Pope Innocent
the Third; in which he saw the strange beggar, from whom he had
almost turned away in the street, upholding the whole toppling
load of St. John Lateran, and indeed, in a larger symbolism,
the whole load of St. Peter and the Church founded on a rock.
More than one historian has suggested that, humanly speaking, it was
St. Francis who prevented all Christendom from coming to an end under
the double destructive drive and drag of Islam without and the pessimist
heresies within. This particular picture is also worth noting,
as a perfect example of that solidity which marked the simplicity
of the medieval mind. Modern writers have referred often enough
to medieval dreams and dark clouds and dim mystical fancies.
But in fact the medievals never dealt in these things,
even where they would have been justified in dealing in them.
There is scarcely any modern of any school, who could deliberately draw
a picture of a vision in the watches of the night, especially a vision
so very visionary, so transcendental and so tremendously symbolic,
as that of an unknown saint upholding a universal church, without bringing
into the picture some shadow of unreality, or remoteness, of a lurid halo
of the preternatural; at least of mystery and the tints of twilight.
But the medieval dream is more solid than the modern reality.
The medieval artist has dealt with it with a directness which
belongs to the vigorous realism of innocence and of childhood;
the sort of actuality which has been wholly untouched by the many
sorts of scepticism which masquerade as mysticism. The dream is
full of something very extraordinary, something which did indeed,
for those who can understand it, shine on the evil and the good
throughout the epoch that we call the Dark Ages: broad daylight.
In another sense, however, the spirit illuminating these great
medieval designs is not so much generally the spirit of daylight
as in a rather curious and peculiar sense, the spirit of daybreak.
Of that highly medieval design it is true to say something of what
Keats said of the highly classical design of his Grecian Urn.
It is a sort of immortal moment of morning, and that which is
a mere transition in time fixed as an absolute for eternity.
We are so accustomed, in modern times, to think in terms of what we
call progress, that we seldom admit, except in a poetical parenthesis,
that there is such a thing as a perfect moment which is better
than what comes after, as well as better than what went before.
Yet it might well be maintained that art in all its history
had no better moment, either before or after, than this
in which all that was good in the old framework and formalism
still remained with the upstanding strength of a great building,
but in which there had already entered that rush of life
and growth, which had turned it into something like a forest,
without having as yet turned it into anything like a jungle.
The naturalistic spirit of the nineteenth century, when it first began
to understand the genius of Giotto or St. Francis, as interpreted
by the talent of Ruskin or of Renan, was bound to fasten especially
on the fanciful and charming episode of the Sermon to the Birds.
For that generation was less concerned about the preservation of
churches and more about the preservation of birds, even if it were
in the equivocal sense of the preservation of game. It would be easy
to illustrate the whole development, we might even say, the whole
ascent and descent, under the emblem or example of the bird. The birds
of the primal and symbolic epoch were simplified and somewhat terrible:
as in the Eagle of the Apocalypse or the Dove of the Holy Ghost.
All other birds in the Byzantine scheme would have been as abstract
and typical as the birds of an Egyptian hieroglyphic. The birds
of the later realistic epoch, when the painters of the nineteenth
century had brought to the last perfection, or the last satiety,
the studies of optics or of physics begun in the sixteenth, might well
have been a most detailed and even bewildering display of ornithology.
But the birds to whom St. Francis preached, in the vision of the
thirteenth-century art, were already birds that could fly and sing,
but not yet birds that could be shot or stuffed; they had ceased
to be merely heraldic without becoming merely scientific.
And as, in all studies of St. Francis, we always return to that
great comparison which he at once denied with all his humility
and desired with all his heart, we may say that they were not wholly
unlike those strange birds in the legend, which the Holy Child
pinched into shape out of scraps of clay, and then started into life
and swiftness with a clap of His little hands.
THE NEW GROOVE
The Poet Tennyson, like a true Victorian, must have written
a good many of his poems in the train; travelling by railroad being
the chief invention and institution of his age. Indeed he confesses
to have written the poem of Lady Godiva while waiting for the train;
and to judge by the careful construction of the blank verse the train
must have been very late. But there are other Tennysonian lines which
Tennyson would seem to have written while he was asleep in the train.
They have that peculiar mixture of jumble and jingle familiar
to those who go to sleep in trains and only feel the metallic rhythm
of the wheels mingling with the most shapeless and senseless dreams.
It was at some such moment of profound slumber that Lord Tennyson
composed the more progressive and prophetic portions of Locksley Hall;
and this is clearly proved by the convincing, nay, damning, fact that
one of the lines does really and truly run:
Let the great world spin for ever down the ringing grooves of change.

Psychologists will be interested in the curious displacement of words


and disorder of ideas, which is characteristic of sentences invented
in a dream. To the ordinary waking intelligence the words would appear
to have no meaning. Grooves do not change; they do not necessarily ring;
they do not even ring the changes. But, just as a sleeper in a
railway-carriage will murmur, in the shock of awakening, some sentence
betraying a secret he would probably have concealed if awake;
as that he is travelling first-class with a third-class ticket,
or that the corpse of a creditor is concealed under the seat--
so Tennyson, in this very extraordinary line of verse, did really
betray the secret, and even the crime, of his own intellectual
world and most of the world that has come after it.
For what is the matter with most of what calls itself the modern
mind is simply grooves; and our habit of being content in
the grooves, because we are told that they are grooves of change.
And it is, as I say, a revealing fact that even when the modern poet
wishes to describe change, even when he wishes to glorify change,
he does still instinctively describe it as a groove.
This is a mark that has been left on very much of the modern world,
ever since the beginning of the mechanical and industrial epoch.
But it had its first and clearest form in this fixed conception
of travelling by rail. It may be specially noted that we speak
of the modern mind being in a groove rather than in a rut.
A rut was a term commonly used of a cart-track; in the simple times
when we did not put the cart before the horse. When a living thing
went before us there was something of doubt or adventure or hesitation
in the tracks it made for itself, even if they became grooves for others.
There were strange curves in his course who hitched his wagon even
to a horse, and who had not yet given up horses for horsepower.
There were sometimes very wild and fantastic tracks in his,
who hitched his wagon to a star. But, apart from all such figures
or fancies, the essential peculiarity of the groove is that there can
be nothing new about it except that it may take us to new places,
or possibly take us past new places, at an entirely new rate of speed.
That is the essential of what I mean by the modern groovings;
that its only form of progress is going quicker and quicker along
one line in one direction. It has not the curiosity to stop,
nor the adventurous courage to go backwards.
Let us take, for the sake of clarity, this familiar case of the
railway-train. A history of the locomotive steam-engine has often
been presented in all its stages of improvement; the evolution
of the modern train from the first clumsy models of Puffing Billy.
But the engine did not produce anything but faster and faster engines;
and the vital point is that nobody ever expected that it would.
Nobody, even in a flight of fancy, wondered whether it would develop
in any other direction, except the direction of its own groove.
For instance, nobody ever suggested that it might develop its own
type of architecture, so that the building of cars or carriages
should be like the building of temples or town-halls. Yet there
might perfectly well have been four or five schools of architecture
for the designing of trains, as there are for the designing of temples.
It would be a pleasing fancy if the architectural style of the train
varied according to the country it was crossing or visiting.
The Pennsylvania Railway Station in New York is a noble and serious
piece of architecture; and it is really a sort of salute to
the great city of Philadelphia towards which its gates are set.
It might quite well have fallen out that what was done for
the station could be done for the steam-engine; and the very
design and colour of the vehicle vary according to whether it
was going to the old French cities or the Red Indian plains;
to the snows of Alaska or the orange-groves of Florida.
Indeed I think there would have been much poetic symbolism in a
hundred forms, probably guarded by rituals and dedicated to gods
or patron saints, if it had so happened that the steam-engine
was discovered by ancient Greeks or medieval Christians,
and not by the Philistines of the Victorian time. But the point
is here that nobody ever thought of such things; and certainly
nobody thought of testing the progress of the train by such tests.
There was only one test of the train and that was the test of the groove;
of the smoothness of the groove; of the straightness of the groove;
of the swiftness with which it travelled along the groove.
There was something, in the tone of the whole thing, that prevented
even mere fancy from breaking away in any other direction;
or wondering, even vainly, if it could ever carry a castle like an
elephant or a figurehead like a ship.
Now, in spite of the wildest claims to independence,
the intellectual life of today still strikes me as being
mainly symbolised by the train or the track or the groove.
There is any amount of fuss and vivacity about certain fixed fashions
or directions of thought; just as there is any amount of rapidity
along the fixed rails of the railway-track. But if we begin
to think about really getting off the track, we shall find that.
what is true of the train is equally true of the truth.
We shall find it is actually harder to get out of the groove,
when the train is going fast, than when the train is going slowly.
We shall find that rapidity is rigidity; that the very fact of some
social or political or artistic movement going quicker and quicker
means that fewer people have the courage to move against it.
And at last perhaps nobody will make a leap for real intellectual liberty,
just as nobody will jump out of a railway-train going at eighty
miles an hour. This seems to me the primary mark of what we
call progressive thought in the modern world. It is in the most
exact sense of the term limited. It is all in one dimension.
It is all in one direction. It is limited by its progress.
It is limited by its speed.
I have said that it has not the curiosity to stop. If the train-dwellers
were really travellers, exploring a strange country to make discoveries,
they would always be stopping at little wayside stations.
For instance, they would always be stopping to consider the curious
nature of their own conventional terms; a thing which they
never do, by any chance. Their catchwords are regarded solely
as gadgets or appliances for getting them where they are going to;
they never cast back a thought upon where the catchword comes from.
Yet that is exactly what they would do if they were really thinking,
in any thorough and all-round sense. Of course it will be understood,
touching these intellectual fashions, that great masses,
probably the mass of mankind, never travel on the train at all.
They remain in their villages and are much happier and better;
but they are not regarded as the intellectual leaders of the time.
What I complain of is that the intellectual leaders can only
lead along one narrow track; otherwise known as "the ringing
groove of change". Take, in this matter of current phrases,
the example of the controversy about advanced and futuristic art.
I do not mean to consider the art but to consider the controversy;
as illustrating what has been said about the advisability of stopping
and the stupidity of the non-stop train.
Now although, of course, the actual masses are quite unconverted
to Picasso or Epstein, yet the terms of controversy, the only tags
of argument known to the newspapers, the only familiar and almost
popular sophistries outside mere popular abuse, are on the side
of the new schools. I mean that modern men are not familiar
with the rational arguments for tradition; but they are familiar,
and almost wearily familiar, with the rational arguments for change.
Whichever side may be really right in the question of art
(which obviously depends largely on the particular artists),
the whole modern world is verbally prepared to regard the new
artist as right and the old artist as wrong. It is prepared
to do so by the whole progressive philosophy; which is often
rather a phraseology than a philosophy. The language which comes
most readily to everyone's mind is the language of innovation;
but it is a language that is rather exercised than examined.
For instance, it is probable that more people are even now acquainted with
the poems of Mr. W. B. Yeats than with the poems of Miss Edith Sitwell.
But many, many more people understand what Miss Sitwell means, when she
simply says that she is criticised in her day as Keats was criticised
in his day, than could possibly understand what Mr. Yeats means,
when he says that nothing quite new can be used in poetry;
or that innocence is only born out of ceremony and custom.
For the former argument is a familiar argument of all modern
progressives and reformers; the latter sayings are very
profound sayings of a man who really thinks for himself.
I agree that in many other things, and especially in the best
examples of her poetry, Miss Sitwell also can think for herself.
I only say that this particular argument ("John the Baptist was
laughed at and I am laughed at"; "Galileo was disbelieved and I
am disbelieved")--this particular argument is part of the regular
recognised bag of tricks of reformers and revolutionists;
it is a part of the very old apparatus of the New Movement.
Now if we apply this, for instance, to the quarrels about
painting or sculpture we shall find the same situation:
that, whichever side is right, the whole apparatus of modern
talk favours the idea that the new thing is always right.
There are a definite selection of phrases used, but not often examined.
For instance, should any Philistine faintly protest against
Helen of Troy being sculptured with a head of the exact shape
of the Great Pyramid, or Titania with a figure following the grand
simple lines of the hippopotamus at the zoo, or even perhaps his own
favourite daughter presenting herself to the public in the appealing
and even touching condition of having her nose and eyelids cut off--
whenever such a criticism is heard, whether it be right or wrong,
it will be answered with the precision of clockwork, by a phrase
to the effect that some people want art to be "pretty-pretty". Now
the first act of any independent mind will be to criticise this criticism;
and especially to feel a curiosity about the curious form of it.
Why does everybody say, "pretty-pretty"? Why not say that some people
do not like what is "ugly-ugly", or possibly what is "beastly-beastly"?
What is the meaning of this weird repetition, like a recurring decimal?
If you have the sort of independent curiosity that stops at
wayside stations, if (in short) you are not merely in a hurry to get
to the fashionable terminus, you may well pause upon a phrase like that,
not without profit. You will perceive that the phrase is, in fact,
a rather pathetic attempt to reproduce the wondering exclamation
of a child. And that would be alone enough to destroy the argument.
For a child has a very sound sense of wonder at what is really wonderful;
and by no means merely a vulgar and varnished taste in what is
conventionally beautiful. The thing that a genuine child might
call "pretty-pretty" is not the soapy portrait of a débutante
or an upholstered group of a royal family; it is much more likely
to be a flash of red fire or the strong colours of a great garden
flower or something that really is elemental and essential;
something in its way quite as "stark" (as our dear friends
would say) as the Great Pyramid or the great pachyderm.
Children are not snobs in art any more than in morals. And if they
often have also a pleasure in things that are really "pretty",
in the sense of a graceful girl by Greuze or a cloud of pink blossom
in spring, it is simply because there is a perfectly legitimate
place in art for what is pretty; and it is not in the least
disposed of by jabbering the same word twice over and calling
it "pretty-pretty". Anyhow, the more supercilious moderns make
a bad blunder in imputing childishness in defence of some things
that could only be defended as being in the higher sense childish.
It was Cezanne himself who said, "I am trying to recover the direct
vision of a child."
It is the same with all the cant phrases already in circulation,
for the purpose of defending any eccentricity, even before it exists.
Thus everybody is familiar with the phrase that art is
not photography, and that only photography is required
to be realistic. Everybody is familiar with the phrase,
and nobody is familiar with the holes or errors in the phrase.
As a matter of fact nothing is less realistic than photography.
At the very start it is cut away from all reality exactly as marble
sculpture is cut away from reality, by being conventionally colourless;
by divorcing the great optical union of colour and form.
But it is not really realistic even about form. The thing it
does reproduce more or less realistically is light and shade,
and the light often falsifies the form and always falsifies the colour.
If we want true form it must be drawn for us more or less
abstractedly by a draughtsman; and when it is so drawn by Leonardo
or Michelangelo, it cannot be dismissed as photographic, any more
than as "pretty-pretty". The modern artist may have his own reasons
for drawing legs as if they were bolsters or sausages; but that does
not make the strong sweeping lines, of sloping bone or gripping muscle,
in a great Florentine drawing, a dull mechanical reproduction,
valuable only as the vulgar snapshot of a trivial fact.
Those lines are strong and beautiful, as the lines of waterfall and
whirlpool are beautiful. In fact, they are exactly like the beautiful
abstract forms, which the modern artist would like to invent--
if he could.
I have taken only this one type, of the talk about new schools of art,
to illustrate what I mean by saying that the world is in such
a hurry to be new that it does not even pause upon the truths
of the new school, let alone of the old. Of the million men
and women who have heard those two phrases, how many have heard
any phrases out of the opposite phraseology and philosophy?
I mean any which offer a philosophical defence of the other philosophy?
Of all those who have been told (somewhat needlessly)
that Epstein does not profess to be pretty, how many have heard
that case for civilisation, in which its very strength is shown
in being able to rear and poise and protect prettiness?
The very cyclopean massiveness of the foundations of the city
is best proved in the fact that no earthquake can shake the ivory
statuette upon the pedestal or the china shepherdess upon the shelf.
How many have considered the more ancient argument, of a culture that
is sufficiently athletic to be elegant? Or, to take another example,
how many have understood the scientific and psychological arguments
for antiquity itself? Of all those who can recall being told
to admire a modern picture, merely because it is even more unlike
life than a photograph, or being told to admire modern poetry,
for no reason whatever except that it is more prosaic than slang--
of all those, how many even remember the sound remark made long ago
by Oliver Wendell Holmes; that the grand Latin poets actually grow
grander by being quoted again and again; that the words actually
grow together with time, as do the sections of a seasoned violin?
I am not saying that the truth is all on the side of tradition;
I am only saying that the publicity is all on the side of innovation.
Until the recent rise of the Humanist group in America,
hardly anybody, even of the educated classes, possessed even
the vocabulary for a defence of tradition. The very words in use,
the very structure of the sentences, the ordinary tone of the whole
public Press, prevented me from using the real and reasonable
arguments against mere novelty. England, strangely enough,
has even less of a working Humanist vocabulary than America.
Here also working journalistic ethics have been too much cut
down and simplified to a few crude ideas, of commercial activity
or continuous reform. I shall be completely misunderstood if I am
supposed to be calling for a return ticket to Athens or to Eden;
because I do not want to go on by the cheap train to Utopia.
I want to go where I like. I want to stop where I like.
I want to know the width as well as the length of the world;
and to wander off the railway-track in the ancient plains of liberty.
THE REAL DR. JOHNSON
It is possible that there are still people in England who do not adore
Dr. Johnson. These persons must be removed, if possible, by persuasion.
A short and plain attempt to persuade them must take precedence
of subtler questions in every discussion of the great man.
Now this old and superficial misunderstanding of Johnson
(now nearly extinct) expresses itself in two main popular notions--
that he was pedantic and that he was rude. He occasionally was rude;
he never was pedantic. He was probably the most unpedantic man
that ever lived; certainly you and I are much more pedantic
than Dr. Johnson. For pedantry means the worship of dead words;
and his words, whether long or short, were always alive.
He played long words and short words against each other with impromptu
but infallible art. I am far from books, and I quote from memory,
but I think that a Scotchman, vexed at the ritual jeers of Johnson
against his country, said: "Do you remember that God made Scotland?"
Johnson replied promptly: "Sir, you are to remember that he made it
for Scotchmen." Then, after a pause, he said in grave meditation:
"Comparisons are odious; but God made hell." Now the vague popular
opinion of Johnson would concentrate on long words like "comparisons"
and "odious", and retain the impression that he was pedantic.
It would be just as easy to concentrate on words like "hell"
and give the impression that he was vulgar. The only true way
of testing the matter is to look at the whole sentence and ask
oneself if there is a single word, long or short, out of its place.
Johnson was the reverse of pedantic, for he used long words only where
they would be effective. Generally it came to this, that he spoke
pompously when Boswell spoke flippantly and flippantly when Boswell
spoke pompously--a very sound rule. When Boswell confronted him
with the brute facts of a lonely tower and a baby, he answered,
with distant dignity: "Sir, I should not much like my company."
But when Boswell justified some morally backsliding bishop or vicar
with that elaborate hash of sophistry and charity which is still used
to excuse the rich, Johnson answered him with a few short words,
so full of Christianity and common sense that I should not be allowed
to print them.
The charge of rudeness is much more real; but about this also an
impression still surviving requires a great deal of correction.
Taken in conjunction with the charge of pedantry, it has created
the image of a bullying schoolmaster, a superior person who thinks
himself above good manners. Now Johnson was sometimes insolent,
but he was never superior. He was not a despot, but exactly
the reverse. It was his sense of the democracy of debate that made
him loud and unscrupulous, like a mob. It was exactly because
he thought the other men as clever as himself that he sought
in desperate cases to bear them down by clamour. Everyone knows
the brilliant description of him by one of his best friends:
"If his pistol misses fire he knocks you down with the butt of it."
But few realise that this is the act of a simple and heroic fellow
fighting against a superior force. Johnson was a man of great animal
impulsiveness and of irregular temper, but intellectually he was humble.
He always went into every conflict with the idea that the other man
was as good as he was, and that he might be defeated. His bellowings
and bangings of the table were the expressions of a fundamental modesty.
We can feel this element, I think, in everything he said, down to
those last awful words upon his death-bed, when he spoke of Burke,
the one man who had really excited and arrested him, "If I saw him
now it would kill me." His fate in these respects has been strange.
He has been called the pedant par excellence because he was
the one thoroughly unpedantic person of a pedantic age.
He has been called a conversational tyrant, because he was the one
man of his mental rank who was ready to argue with his inferiors.
On the one hand it is often said that he translated English
into Johnsonese. But let it be remembered that he was the only man
of his time who could translate Johnsonese back into English.
Half a hundred critics in that age might have said of a play, "It does not
possess sufficient vitality to preserve it from putrefaction", but only
Johnson could have said also, "It has not wit enough to keep it sweet."
There were numerous great men in the eighteenth century who kept a club
or court of dependents, where they had things entirely their own way.
I need not prove the point; the greatest satirist of that age has
made the image immortal.
Like Cato gave his little Senate laws, And sat attentive to
his own applause.
But Johnson was the reverse of attentive to people who were
applauding him. Johnson was furiously deaf to people who were
contradicting him. So far from being a stately and condescending
king like Atticus, Johnson was a kind of Irish member in his
own Parliament. All these are but broken and incidental examples;
everything about the man rang of reality and honour; he never thought
he was right without being ready to give battle; he never thought
he was wrong without being ready to ask pardon. We have all heard
enough to fill a book about Dr. Johnson's incivilities. I wish they
would compile another book consisting of Dr. Johnson's apologies.
There is no better test of a man's ultimate chivalry and integrity
than how he behaves when he is wrong; and Johnson behaved very well.
He understood (what so many faultlessly polite people do not understand)
that a stiff apology is a second insult. He understood that
the injured party does not want to be compensated because he has
been wronged; he wants to be healed because he has been hurt.
Boswell once complained to him in private, explaining that he did
not mind asperities while they were alone, but did not like to be
torn to pieces in company. He added some idle figure of speech,
some simile so trivial that I cannot even remember what it was.
"Sir," said Johnson, "that is one of the happiest similes I
have ever heard." He did not waste time in formally withdrawing
this word with reservations and that word with explanations.
Finding that he had given pain, he went out of his way to give pleasure.
If he had not known what would irritate Boswell, he knew at least what
would soothe him. It is this gigantic realism in Johnson's kindness,
the directness of his emotionalism, when he is emotional,
that gives him his hold upon generations of living men.
There is nothing elaborate about his ethics; he wants to know whether
a man, as a fact, is happy or unhappy, is lying or telling the truth.
He may seem to be hammering at the brain through long nights of noise
and thunder, but he can walk into the heart without knocking.
RABELAISIAN REGRETS
There has arisen in our time an extraordinary notion that there is
something humane, open-hearted or generous about refusing to define
one's creed. Obviously the very opposite is the truth. Refusing to
define a creed is not only not generous, it is distinctly mean.
It fails in frankness and fraternity towards the enemy.
It is fighting without a flag or a declaration of war.
It denies to the enemy the decent concessions of battle;
the right to know the policy and to treat with the headquarters.
Modern "broad-mindedness" has a quality that can only be called sneakish;
it endeavours to win without giving itself away, even after it has won.
It desires to be victorious without betraying even the name
of the victor. For all sane men have intellectual doctrines
and fighting theories; and if they will not put them on the table,
it can only be because they wish to have the advantage of a fighting
theory which cannot be fought.
In the things of conviction there is only one other thing besides
a dogma, and that is a prejudice. If there is something in your
life for which you will hold meetings and agitate and write letters
to the newspaper, but for which you will not find the plain
terms of a creed, then that thing is properly to be described
as a prejudice, however new or noble or advanced it may seem to be.
But indeed I think that when these ages are seen in proper perspective,
men will say that the chief mark of the end of the nineteenth
century and the beginning of the twentieth was the growth of vast
and victorious prejudices. I give, in passing, some instances
of what I mean. Thus, for instance, it is a brave and logical
creed which declares, like Mahomet and some modern Puritans,
that the drinking of fermented liquor is really wrong.
But the modern world has not adopted this clear creed and never will.
What it has done has been to spread everywhere a strong but vague
prejudice against certain forms of drinking, particularly those
adopted by the poor. We have not made it wicked to drink ale,
but we have made it slightly disreputable to go into a public-house.
In other words, we have made it slightly disreputable, if you
drink ale, to be poor or to be sociable. What it comes to is this:
that any one wishing to sneer at me can get a laugh by saying I am
a beer-drinker, but he will not commit himself to the statement
that the thing that he has sneered at is wrong. He may hit me,
because he is appealing to a prejudice; but I may not hit him
because he is not appealing to a creed. He will not set anything
up for me to hit. He wants, somehow or other, to avoid calling
liquor wrong and yet to call me wrong for touching liquor.
This is not latitudinarianism; it is ordinary human cowardice.
There are a great many other instances which could be given.
For instance, fashionable opinion does not actually declare
(as do, I believe, certain Eastern religions) that ablutions and
bodily cleanliness are primary things, above even ordinary morals;
but it does create a loose popular impression that it has scored
off a personality or a nation more by saying that it is dirty
than by saying that it is avaricious or timid or unchaste.
No new creed is preached about cleanliness, but a strong
sentimental emphasis and partiality is attached to the thing,
making it more important than other things. Of course cleanliness
is only made so very important at present because it happens to be
a thing quite easy for the rich and very difficult for the poor.
My only concern here, however, is to point out the method by which it
has been made important; never by explaining or defining its importance,
as in a creed; always by assuming its importance, as in a prejudice.
I have no space to go at length into other examples, but the reader can
easily put the cases to himself; and he can employ this general test:
that in the case of half the most typical movements of the last
thirty years, nobody can say how or when they really began.
In no barbaric twilight or tangled forest or confusion of the dark ages
did huge forces ever come so silently or secretly into the world as they
come to-day. No one knows or can name the real beginning of Imperialism
or of the popularity of the Royal Family (a thing quite recent yet
quite untraceable), or of the taking for granted, in so many minds,
of the materialist philosophy or of the practical imposition of
teetotalism as a discipline on the Nonconformist public ministry.
These things come out of the night and are formless even when they
are forming everything else.
But discussions on the subject of the Censor and other theatrical problems
have brought before the public a supreme instance of what I mean.
We have been asked for the hundredth time to find some solution of
that problem of the combination in art of truth with sexual modesty;
and the result of considering this has been that we find ourselves
face to face with a profound and most important change in public
opinion on this subject; a change that has been going on,
perhaps, for the last twenty years, perhaps ever since the coming
of the Puritans; but a change which is, at any rate, of the utmost
import to the wholesomeness of ethics, and a change which has
proceeded in the same powerful silence as the growth of a tree.
It is this difference between new English and old English ethics
in the matter of verbal delicacy of which I wish to speak here.
The subject is difficult, it is even emotional and painful;
and I think it will do no harm to begin with some of the general
human principles of the problem, even if they are as old and obvious
as the alphabet.
There is not really much difference of opinion among normal men
about the first principles of decency in expression. All healthy men,
ancient and modern, Western and Eastern, hold that there is in sex
a fury that we cannot afford to inflame; and that a certain mystery
must attach to the instinct if it is to continue delicate and sane.
There are people, indeed, who maintain that they would talk
of this topic as coldly or openly as of any other; there are
people who maintain that they would walk naked down the street.
But these people are not only insane people, they are in the most emphatic
sense of the word stupid people. They do not think; they only point
(as children do) and say "Why?" Even children only do it when they
are tired; but exactly this tired quality is most of what passes
in our time not only for thought but for bold and disturbing thought.
To ask, "Why cannot we discuss sex coolly and rationally anywhere?"
is a tired and unintelligent question. It is like asking, "Why does
not a man walk on his hands as well as on his feet?" It is silly.
If a man walked systematically on his hands, they would not be hands,
but feet. And if love or lust were things that we could all discuss
without any possible emotion they would not be love or lust, they would
be something else--some mechanical function or abstract natural duty
which may or may not exist in animals or in angels, but which has
nothing at all to do with the sexuality we are talking about.
All the ideas of grasp or gesture, which to us make up the meaning
of the word "hand", depend upon the fact that hands are loose
extremities used not for walking on but for waving about.
And all that we mean when we speak of "sex" is involved in the fact
that it is not an unconscious or innocent thing, but a special
and violent emotional stimulation at once spiritual and physical.
A man who asks us to have no emotion in sex is asking us to have
no emotion in emotion. He has forgotten the subject-matter
with which he deals. He has lost the topic of the conversation.
It may be said of him, in the strict meaning of the words,
that he does not know what he is talking about.
And if men have never doubted that there should be a decorum
in such things, neither have they ever doubted that that decorum
might be carried much too far; that courage and laughter
and wholesome truth might be sacrificed to the proprieties.
So far, I say, humanity is essentially unanimous. It is in the
discussion as to which thing shall be suppressed and which permitted,
in the selection of the more harmless from the more harmful
types of candour, that we begin to find the difference between
different civilisations and different religions among men.
And it is exactly upon the point of such a difference as this
that I wish to speak here. Among other societies and ages
our own society and age has made a choice in this matter.
We have said, substantially by a general feeling, that one kind
of expression shall be allowed and another rendered impossible.
We have chosen, and I think we have chosen wrong.
Before going deeper into this most difficult subject there is
at least one general statement to be made. The evil of excess
in this matter really consists of three quite separate evils.
Verbal impropriety or excess can spring from three quite
different motives, three quite different states of mind,
which have really very little to do with each other.
It is necessary to unpick these three strands before we go any further.
Ordinary popular discussion of the problem always hopelessly mixes
them up. Briefly, they may be stated thus: impropriety arises
either from a really vicious spirit, or from the love of emphasis,
or from the love of analysis.
The first can be dismissed with brevity and with relief. There is such
a thing as pornography; as a system of deliberate erotic stimulants.
That is not a thing to be argued about with one's intellect,
but to be stamped on with one's heel. But the point about it
to be noted for our purpose is that this form of excess is separated
from the other two by the fact that the motive of it must be bad.
If a man tries to excite a sex instinct which is too strong already,
and that in its meanest form, he must be a scoundrel.
He is either taking money to degrade his kind or else he is acting
on that mystical itch of the evil man to make others evil,
which is the strangest secret in hell.
But when we come to the two motives of emphasis and of analysis,
it is essential to observe that in both cases the motive
may be beautiful, even when the result is most disastrous.
The motive for impropriety arising out of emphasis can be best
illustrated by a comparison with the habit of swearing.
Swearing is, of course, the strongest possible argument for
the religious view of life. A man cannot satisfactorily affirm
anything about this world except by getting out of this world.
The things commonly called fables are so true that they alone can
give final ratification even to the things commonly called facts.
A man in Balham cannot even call his dog a good dog without
summoning to his aid either the angels or the devils.
The Balhamite, like the Roman, if he cannot bend the gods will
move Acheron; but he never thinks of trying to move Balham.
Religion is his only resort for purposes of real emphasis;
and often, even when he is attacking religion, his instinctive
way of attacking it is to say that it is a damned lie.
The most natural way of talking is the supernatural way of talking.
And indeed this may be considered a good working test for all
modern fads and philosophies which pretend to be religions.
The new faiths founded on evolution or an impersonal ethic are
always claiming, that they also can produce holiness; and no Christian
has any right in Christian charity to deny that possibility.
But if the question really is whether the things in question are
religions in the sense that Christianity or Mohammedanism are religions,
then I should suggest a different test. I should not ask whether
they can produce holiness, but whether they can produce profanity.
Can any one swear by ethics? Can any one blaspheme evolution?
Many men now hold that a mere adoration of abstract morality or goodness
is the core and sole necessity of religion. I know many of them;
I know that their lives are noble, and their intellects just.
But (I say it with respect and even hesitation) would not their
oaths be a little mild? I do not mean that they ought to swear,
or that anybody ought to swear, I mean that if it comes to swearing
one can see in such a competition the vast difference in actuality
between the new sham religion which talks about the holiness within,
and an old practical religion which worshipped a real holiness without.
You can see the difference in the weakness of the oaths
considered as literature. The man of the Christian Churches said
(occasionally), "Oh, my God!" The man of the ethical societies says
(presumably), "Oh, my goodness!"
It is generally true, I say, that the whole circle of this physical
universe does not contain anything strong enough for the purposes
of a man who really means what he says; even about a small dog.
Yet there is one exception to this generalisation. There is one thing
which belongs to this world, but which is yet so fierce and startling,
so full of menace and ecstasy, that it seems at times to partake
of the character of miracle. This thing is the thing called sex;
and on this also from time to time the man with the small dog in Balham
will call in his dire need. Men used to swear by their heads;
they still in a manner swear by their bodies. Sex is actual
enough to swear by. To take but one coarse democratic test,
people scribble about it on walls as they do about religion.
Nobody ever scribbled on a wall about ethics. Above all,
the language of sex can be used as a kind of violent invocation;
a reinforcement of common words by the strongest words.
I will not pause here to ask the reason of this; whether saying "damn"
and saying other things unprintable have something to do
with the fact that sex is the great business of the body,
and salvation the great business of the soul. It is enough to say
that any one can read the thing I mean and any one can hear it.
He can read the thing best perhaps in Aristophanes or in Rabelais.
He can hear the thing best in the street outside.
But though he can find it in the street outside, he cannot
find it in any of the books or newspapers sold in the street.
There is no law against indecent ideas; but there is a quite
efficient and practical law against indecent words.
Slowly throughout the eighteenth century word after word was
dropped until by the Victorian time it was insisted that no
coarse phrases should be used even in defending coarseness.
I am myself under the limitations of this very local prejudice.
I am compelled to prove my case in many pages because I
have to talk as one talks in a respectable magazine.
I could prove my case in ten minutes if I could talk as two
respectable married men really talk on the top of an omnibus.
It is sufficient, however, to put the matter thus: When a navvy
uses what is called obscene language it is almost always to express
his righteous disgust at obscene conduct. And here the navvy
is at one with all the most really masculine poets or romancers;
he is at one with Rabelais, with Swift, and even with Browning.
Browning uses a foul metaphor to express the foulness of those who
profess sympathy with human sorrows merely out of their own morbidity.
You can find the phrase in "At the Mermaid." Browning uses
the same foul metaphor to express the foulness of those who cannot
understand a man's prompt grasp of the presence of a good woman.
You can find the phrase in the speech of Capponsacchi.
In short, the emphatic use of sexual language has this great advantage
that it is commonly used purely in the interests of virtue.
The virtuous cabman may (and does) call a man a blank, in a state
of furious and innocent horror at the idea of any one being a blank.
But this is not true in the case of the third impulse to indecorum.
The third impulse is that which I have called the analytical;
the mere curiosity of the mind about how the relations of the sexes
are to be considered and classified. This covers all that we now
call the Problem Play, and all that we associate with the realistic
and psychological novel, and all the millions of proposals for
the rearrangement of marriage. The dialogue in The Little Eyolf
horrified many people; but it did not contain a single coarse word.
Mr. George Moore, Mr. Richard Le Gallienne, and the lady called
"Victoria Cross" have in turn been accused of being needlessly daring;
but not one of them dare use words straight out of Bunyan or the Bible.
The analytic indecency is now more free than it ever was among free men.
The emphatic indecency is more stifled than it ever was among free men;
more stifled than it ever was among slaves.
I am not concerned here to deny that the modern fashion of
analysing sex is in general a good thing. Certainly there is
grossly too much hypocrisy about sex; not in the English people,
but in the literature and journalism which the English people,
for some incomprehensible reason, permit to speak for them.
There is no hypocrisy on the top of an English omnibus; but I warmly
agree that there is really too much hypocrisy in the front page
of an English newspaper, or within the covers of an English book.
Let us agree that Ibsen had a right to suggest that marriage is an
unpleasant fact as well as a pleasant one; that as well as the more
chivalrous side of sex which is exaggerated by the Victorian poets,
there is also the realistic and scientific side of sex, which was
exaggerated by the old monks. Let me concede altogether and at once
the fact that the modern tendency to dissect sex and to subdivide it,
to put it into pigeon-holes, is a just and necessary measure.
I will not even say here that the tendency has gone too far.
But I will say this: what will you do if it does go too far?
Suppose you wake up some fine morning and find indecencies
which are quite ludicrous being taken quite seriously.
Suppose you find certain sins put in a pigeon-hole when they ought
to be put in a dust-hole. Suppose that after twenty years of scientific
study you find that you have all the dirty jokes back again, the only
difference being that you must enjoy them without laughing at them.
Suppose, in short, that you are confronted with the exasperating
spectacle of people chewing sins, instead of spitting them
out of their mouths like their fathers; what will you do then?
How will you express your feelings if you are faced with that
horrible fashion of taking sex seriously--of which the true name is
Phallic Worship? I know what you will do: you will call upon the shades
of Rabelais and Fielding to deliver you out of that foul idolatry;
and perhaps the English people will answer you and speak.
It is common enough to talk of the English people speaking;
but if ever they do speak they will speak as Rabelais spoke,
and as English cabmen speak now.
THE HOUND OF HEAVEN
"The Hound of Heaven", the greatest religious poem of modern times
and one of the greatest of all times, was produced under certain peculiar
historical conditions, which accentuate its isolation. To begin with,
the religious poem is a religious poem, not only in what we should
call the real sense, but in what some would call the limited sense.
The word "religion" is used in these days in an expansive or
telescopic fashion, sometimes inevitable, sometimes nearly intolerable.
It is used of various realms of emotion or spiritual speculation
more or less lying on the borders of religion itself; it is
applied to other things that have nothing to do with religion;
it is applied to some things that are almost identical with irreligion.
But the line between legitimate and illegitimate expansion of a word
is so difficult to draw, that there is little to be gained by questioning
it except that mere quarrel about a word that is called logomachy.
There always are some confusions about a definition or exceptions
to a rule. The great principle that Pigs is Pigs does not
dispose entirely of the existence of pig-iron, or of cannibals
calling a man a long pig. We all know the plain practical man,
the sceptic in the crowd, the atheist on the soap-box, who boasts
that he calls a spade a spade, and generally calls it a spyde.
But even he may have to deal with the learned and sophisticated man,
who will prove to him, that even in the case of the ace of spades
which he planks down in playing poker, the spade is not really
a spade; being derived from the Spanish espada, a sword.
If once we begin to quibble and quarrel about what words ought to mean
or can be made to mean we shall find ourselves in a mere world
of words, most wearisome to those who are concerned with thoughts.
For the latter it will be enough to realise that there certainly was
and is a certain thing, to which our fathers found it more practical
to attach and limit the name of religion; that they recognised
that the thing had many forms, and that there were many religions;
but that they were equally certain of what things were not religions,
including much that modern moralists call a wider religious life.
They recognised a Protestant religion and a Catholic religion,
and probably thought one or other of them true; they recognised
a Mohammedan religion, even if they thought it false; they recognised
a Jewish religion, which had once been true and by a sort of
treason had become false; and so on. But they did not recognise
a religion of Humanity; or a "religion of the Life Force":
or a religion of creative evolution; or a religion which has
the object of ultimately producing a god who does not yet exist.
And the distinction is better preserved by noting these examples
than by an attempt to fix the elusive evasions of the verbal
sophists of today.
What we mean when we say that "The Hound of Heaven" is a real
religious poem is simply that it would make no sense if we supposed
it to refer to any of these modern abstractions, or to anything
but a personal Creator in relation to a personal creature.
It may be, and indeed is, a generous and charitable mood to look
out on all the multitudes of men with sympathy and social loyalty.
But it was not the multitudes of men that were pursuing
the hero of this poem "down the nights and down the days".
It may be a good thing for men to look forward to mankind
someday producing a superior being, thousands of years hence,
who will be like a god compared with the common mass of men.
But it was not some superior person born a thousand years hence, who drove
the sinner in this story from refuge to refuge. He was not running
away from the Life Force, from a mere summary of all natural vitality,
which would be expressed equally in the pursued or the pursuer.
For it requires quite as much Life Force to run away from anybody
as to run after anybody. He was not swiftly escaping from a slow
adaptive process called evolution, like a man pursued by a snail.
He was not alarmed at a gradual biological transformation,
by which a Hound of Heaven might be evolved out of a Hound of Hell.
He was dealing with the direct individual relations of God and Man,
and the story would be absolutely senseless to anybody who thought
that the service of Man is a substitute for the service of God.
This is where the practical habit of speech, among our religious
ancestors of all religions, proves its validity and veracity.
Francis Thompson was a Catholic, and a very Catholic Catholic.
In some aspects of art, poetry and pomp, the Catholic is more akin to
the pagan; in some aspects of philosophy and logic (though this is little
understood), he has more sympathy with the sceptic or the agnostic.
But in the solid central fact of the subject or subject-matter he is
still something utterly separate from sceptics and even from pagans;
and all Christians have their part in him. A perfectly simple and
straightforward member of the Salvation Army knows what "The Hound
of Heaven" is about, even if he knows it better without reading it,
and would recognise its central theology as promptly as the Pope.
But the mere humanist, the mere humanitarian, the universal aesthete,
the patroniser of all religions, he will never know what it is about,
for he has never been near enough to God to run away from Him.
Now the next point of interest is that this poem of purely
personal religion, so directly devotional, so dogmatically orthodox,
appeared at a time when it might least be expected, and at the end
of an historical process that might have seemed to make it impossible.
The nineteenth century had been, at least on the surface, one triumphal
procession of progress, away from these theological relations,
which were accounted narrow, towards ideals of brotherhood or natural
living which seemed to be more and more broad. We might say
that the poets had led the procession, for even at the beginning
of the nineteenth century Shelley and Landor and Byron and Keats had
moved in various ways towards a pantheistic paganism; and the tendency
was continued by Victor Hugo in Europe and by Walt Whitman in America.
There were, of course, continual cross-currents and confusions.
Even an appeal to pantheism is something like an appeal to theism,
and it was difficult to imitate the pagans without discovering,
like St. Paul, that they were very religious. The contradiction
came out quaintly in the case of Swinburne, who was always trying
to prove that he was an atheist by invoking about ten different
gods in a style exactly copied from the Old Testament.
Roughly speaking, however, I myself remember fairly well the curious
cultural conditions in which the genius of Francis Thompson arose;
for, though I was a boy at the time, a boy can sometimes absorb
the atmosphere of a society, with the same subtle subconscious
instinct with which a child can absorb the atmosphere of a house.
I read all the minor poets; and it was specially an age of minor poets.
The curious thing is that Francis Thompson was considered,
criticised, appreciated or admired as one of the minor poets.
I can remember Mr. Richard Le Gallienne, who is one of the survivors
of that epoch, defending himself with spirit, but with a certain air
of audacity, against the charge of fulsome exaggeration in saying
that there was in the poems of this Mr. Thompson an Elizabethan
richness and sometimes almost a Shakespearian splendour.
Mr. Le Gallienne was quite right; but the main point is that his defence
was a general defence of minor poets, and of this poet as a minor poet.
It had hardly occurred to the world in general that Francis Thompson
was a major poet; we might almost say a major prophet.
There was in all that world of culture an atmosphere of paganism
that had worn rather thin. But hardly anybody thought that
the future of poetry could be anything but a future of paganism.
It was then, in the slowly deepening silence, as in the poem
of Coventry Patmore, that there was first heard, afar off,
the baying of a hound.
That is the primary point about the work of Francis Thompson;
even before its many-coloured pageant of images and words.
The awakening of the domini canes, the Dogs of God, meant that
the hunt was up once more; the hunt for the souls of men;
and that religion of that realistic sort was anything but dead.
In Patmore's poem the dog is "an old guard-hound"; and we may say,
without irreverence, that the first impression or lesson was that there
is life in the old dog yet. In any case, it was an event of history,
as much as an event of literature, when personal religion returned
suddenly with something of the power of Dante or the Dies Irae,
after a century in which such religion had seemed to grow more weak
and provincial, and more and more impersonal religions appeared
to possess the future. And those who best understand the world
know that the world is changed, and that the hunt will continue
until the world turns to bay.
THE FRIVOLOUS MAN
By one of those queer associations that nobody can ever understand,
a large number of people have come to think that frivolity has
some kind of connection with enjoyment. As a matter of fact,
nobody can really enjoy himself unless he is serious.
Even those whom we commonly regard as belonging to the butterfly
classes of society really enjoy themselves most at the crises
of their lives which are potentially tragic. Men can only enjoy
fundamental things. In order to enjoy the lightest and most flying
joke a man must be rooted in some basic sense of the good of things;
and the good of things means, of course, the seriousness of things.
In order to enjoy even a pas de quatre at a subscription dance a man
must feel for the moment that the stars are dancing to the same tune.
In the old religions of the world, indeed, people did think
that the stars were dancing to the tunes of their temples;
and they danced as no man has danced since. But thorough enjoyment,
enjoyment that has no hesitation, no incidental blight, no arri?re pensée,
is only possible to the serious man. Wine, says the Scripture,
maketh glad the heart of man, but only of the man who has a heart.
And so also the thing called good spirits is possible only
to the spiritual.
The really frivolous man, the frivolous man of society, we all know,
and any of us who know him truthfully know that if he has
one characteristic more salient than another it is that be is
a pessimist. The idea of the gay and thoughtless man of fashion,
intoxicated with pagan delights, is a figment invented entirely
by religious people who never met any such man in their lives.
The man of pleasure is one of the fables of the pious.
Puritans have given a great deal too much credit to the power which
the world has to satisfy the soul; in admitting that the sinner is gay
and careless they have given away the strongest part of their case.
As a matter of fact, Puritanism commonly falls into the error
of accusing the frivolous man of all the wrong vices.
For instance, it says (and it is a favourite phrase) that the frivolous
man is "careless". In truth the frivolous man is very careful.
Not only does he spend hours over dressing and similar technical matters,
but a great part of his life is passed in criticising and discussing
similar technical matters. At any odd hour of the day we may find
him talking about whether one man has the right kind of coat
or another man the wrong kind of dinner-service; and about these
matters he is far more solemn than a Pope or a General Council.
His general air about them might be described as rather sad than serious,
as rather hopeless than severe. Religion might approximately be defined
as the power which makes us joyful about the things that matter.
Fashionable frivolity might, with a parallel propriety, be defined
as the power which makes us sad about the things that do not matter.
Frivolity has nothing to do with happiness. It plays upon the surface
of things, and the surface is almost always rough and uneven.
The frivolous person is the person who cannot fully appreciate
the weight and value of anything. In practice he does not appreciate
even the weight and value of the things commonly counted frivolous.
He does not enjoy his cigars as the gutter boy enjoys his cigarette;
he does not enjoy his ballet as the child enjoys "Punch and Judy".
But, in fairness to him, it must be admitted that he is not alone
in being frivolous: other classes of men share the reproach.
Thus, for instance, bishops are generally frivolous, moral teachers
are generally frivolous, statesmen are generally frivolous,
conscientious objectors are generally frivolous. Philosophers and
poets are often frivolous; politicians are always frivolous.
For if frivolity signifies this lack of grasp of the fullness and the
value of things, it must have a great many forms besides that of mere
levity and pleasure-seeking. A great many people have a fixed idea
that irreverence, for instance, consists chiefly in making jokes.
But it is quite possible to be irreverent with a diction devoid
of the slightest touch of indecorum, and with a soul unpolluted
by a tinge of humour. The splendid and everlasting definition of real
irreverence is to be found in that misunderstood and neglected
commandment which declares that the Lord will not hold him guiltless
that taketh His name in vain. This again is supposed vaguely to have
some connection with buffoonery and jocularity and play upon words.
But surely that is not the plain meaning of the phrase.
To say a thing with a touch of humour is not to say it in vain.
To say a thing with a touch of satire or individual criticism is not
to say it in vain. To say a thing even fantastically, like some
fragment from the scriptures of Elfland, is not to say it in vain.
But to say a thing with a pompous and unmeaning gravity;
to say a thing so that it shall be at once bigoted and vague;
to say a thing so that it shall be indistinct at the same moment
that it is literal; to say a thing so that the most decorous listener
shall not at the end of it really know why in the name of all
things you should have said it or he should have listened to it--
this is veritably and in the weighty sense of those ancient Mosaic
words to take that thing in vain. The Name is taken in vain
many times more often by preachers than it is by secularists.
The blasphemer is, indeed, fundamentally natural and prosaic,
for he speaks in a commonplace manner about that which he believes
to be commonplace. But the ordinary preacher and religious orator
speaks in a commonplace manner about that which he believes
to be divine.
This is the breach of one of the Commandments; it is the sin against
the name. Take, if you will, the name wildly, take it jestingly,
take it brutally and angrily, take it childishly, take it wrongly;
but do not take it in vain. Use a sanctity for some strange or new
purpose and justify that use; use a sanctity for some doubtful
and experimental purpose and stake your act on your success;
use a sanctity for some base and hateful purpose and abide the end.
But do not use a sanctity for no purpose at all; do not talk about Christ
when you might as well talk about Mr. Perks; do not use patriotism
and honour and the Communion of Saints as stopgaps in a halting speech.
This is the sin of frivolity, and it is the chief characteristic
of the great majority of the conventionally religious class.
Thus we come back to the conclusion that real seriousness is
at a discount alike among the irreligious and the religious,
alike in the worldly and in the unworldly world.
TWO STUBBORN PIECES OF IRON
In discussing such a proposal as that of the co-education of
the sexes it is very desirable first of all to realise clearly
what it is that we want the thing to do. The thing might be upheld
for quite opposite reasons. It might be supposed to increase
delicacy or to decrease it. It might be valued because it was
a sphere for sentiment or because it was a damper for sentiment.
My sympathies would move me in a discussion entirely according
to what difference its upholders thought it would make.
For myself, I doubt whether it would make much difference at all.
Everyone must agree with co-education for very young children; and I
cannot believe that even for elder children it would do any great harm.
But that is because I think the school is not so important as people think
it nowadays. The home is the really important thing, and always will be.
People talk about the poor neglecting their children; but a little boy
in the street has more traces of having been brought up by his mother
than of having been taught ethics and geography by a pupil teacher.
And if we take this true parallel of the home we can see,
I think, exactly what co-education can do and what it cannot do.
The school will never make boys and girls ordinary comrades.
The home does not make them that. The sexes can work together in a
school-room just as they can breakfast together in a breakfast-room;
but neither makes any difference to the fact that the boys go off
to a boyish companionship which the girls would think disgusting,
while the girls go off to a girl companionship which the boys would
think literally insane. Co-educate as much as you like, there will
always be a wall between the sexes until love or lust breaks it down.
Your co-educative playground for pupils in their teens will not be
a place of sexless camaraderie. It will be a place where boys go
about in fives sulkily growling at the girls, and where the girls
go about in twos turning up their noses at the boys.
Now if you accept this state of things and are content
with it as the result of your co-education, I am with you;
I accept it as one of the mystical first facts of Nature.
I accept it somewhat in the spirit of Carlyle when somebody told him
that Harriet Martineau had "accepted the Universe", and he said,
"By God, she'd better." But if you have any idea that co-education
would do more than parade the sexes in front of each other twice
a day, if you think it would destroy their deep ignorance of each
other or start them on a basis of rational understanding, then I
say first that this will never happen, and second that I (for one)
should be horribly annoyed if it did.
I can reach my meaning best by another route. Very few people ever
state properly the strong argument in favour of marrying for love
or against marrying for money. The argument is not that all lovers
are heroes and heroines, nor is it that all dukes are profligates
or all millionaires cads. The argument is this, that the differences
between a man and a woman are at the best so obstinate and
exasperating that they practically cannot be got over unless there
is an atmosphere of exaggerated tenderness and mutual interest.
To put the matter in one metaphor, the sexes are two stubborn pieces
of iron; if they are to be welded together, it must be while they are
red-hot. Every woman has to find out that her husband is a selfish beast,
because every man is a selfish beast by the standard of a woman.
But let her find out the beast while they are both still in the story
of "Beauty and the Beast". Every man has to find out that his wife
is cross--that is to say, sensitive to the point of madness:
for every woman is mad by the masculine standard. But let him find
out that she is mad while her madness is more worth considering
than anyone else's sanity.
This is not a digression. The whole value of the normal relations
of man and woman lies in the fact that they first begin really to
criticise each other when they first begin really to admire each other.
And a good thing, too. I say, with a full sense of the responsibility
of the statement, that it is better that the sexes should misunderstand
each other until they marry. It is better that they should not
have the knowledge until they have the reverence and the charity.
We want no premature and puppyish "knowing all about girls".
We do not want the highest mysteries of a Divine distinction
to be understood before they are desired, and handled before
they are understood. That which Mr. Shaw calls the Life Force,
but for which Christianity has more philosophical terms,
has created this early division of tastes and habits for that
romantic purpose, which is also the most practical of all purposes.
Those whom God has sundered, shall no man join.
It is, therefore, a question of what are really the co-educators' aims.
If they have small aims, some convenience in organisation,
some slight improvement in manners, they know more about such things
than I. But if they have large aims, I am against them.
HENRY JAMES
An artist who is at once individual and complete attracts a type
of praise which is a sort of disparagement; and even those who
overrate him underrate him. For the tendency is always to insist
on his art; and by art is often meant merely arrangement.
Because a very few colours can be harmoniously arranged in a picture,
it is implied that he has not many colours on his palette.
And as a study by Henry James was often in its tones something of a
nocturne in grey and silver, even his eulogists managed to imply something
slight or even thin about his work. Before attempting to touch upon
what was really peculiar in the tone of it, it is necessary to correct,
and even to contradict, this tenuous impression by the reminder
of what he had in common with other great writers. For Henry James
must be considered as a great man of letters; and the greatness
itself is something which existed in geniuses utterly unlike him.
It might seem startling and even comic to compare him to Dickens or even
to Shakespeare; but what makes him great is what makes them great,
and what alone can make a literary man in the ultimate sense great.
It is ideas; the power of generating and making vivid an incessant
output of ideas. It is untrue to say that what matters is quality
and not quantity. Most men have made one good joke in their lives;
but to make jokes as Dickens made them is to be a great man.
Many forgotten poets have let fall a lyric with one really
perfect image; but when we open any play of Shakespeare, good or bad,
at any page, important or unimportant, with the practical certainty
of finding some imagery that at least arrests the eye and probably
enriches the memory, we are putting our trust in a great man.
We are taking at random from a whole store of what are truly
to be called great inventions when we think of Mrs. Todgers'
wooden leg, or Mr. Fledgby's nose, or Mr. Pecksniff's pinions,
or Mr. Swiveller's double-bedded room.
And wide as the distance may seem, it is true, in exactly the same sense,
that we are taking at random from a treasury of unique inventions when we
think of any two or three of the numberless new ideas of Henry James;
of the two people who grew afraid of the mystical coincidence of
never meeting; of the man who ceased to exist when he was left alone;
of the mysterious unity that ran through all a writer's books
like "the figure in the carpet"; of the pearls that were counted
false for purposes of respectability and real for purposes of sale;
of the sudden supernatural calm created like a garden in the skies
by the breakdown of the brain at its busiest; of the wife
who would not justify herself to her husband because his whole
life was in his chivalry; and so on through a thousand more.
Such an idea, though it may be as delicate as an atmosphere,
is nevertheless as precise as a pun. It cannot be a coincidence;
it is always a creation. He has been attacked for making a great
deal of small things; but most of those who attacked him were making
a great deal of large nothings. The point that is important
about him is not whether the things with which he dealt were
as small as some think them, or as large as he could make them;
whether it was a fine shade in vulgarity or an occult tenacity of vice;
whether it was the restless ten minutes of a visitor coming
too early, or the restless ten years of a lover moved too late.
The point is that the things were things; that we should have lost
them if he had not given them; that no mere perfections of prose
would have been a substitute for them; in short, that he never wrote
about nothing. Each small notion had the serious thing called value--
like a jewel, or, like what is both smaller and more valuable
than a jewel, a seed.
His greatness is the greatest thing about him, therefore, and it
is of a kind with that of other creative men. But when this
large and rather neglected aspect has first been allowed for,
it is possible to consider him as a peculiar and fastidious writer.
Certainly his work is of a sort to which it is difficult to do justice
amid the pulsation of the direct public energies with which most of us
who are at all public-spirited feel ourselves concerned today.
We should need to be at leisure in those large and vague spaces
of gardens and great neglected houses which are the background
of so many of his spiritual dramas, to grow fond of the fine shades
of a whole science of shadows and slowly appreciate the multitudinous
colours of what seems at first monochrome. Some of his finest
stories were ghost stories; and one must be alone to meet a ghost.
And yet even the phrase I use indicates its own limitations,
for no one seized more swiftly than Henry James the greatness of this
awful time, in which we have to think even of ghosts in crowds.
He had always been in his innermost being a mystic, and the dead were
near to him; and he rose more magnificently, perhaps, than any other
to that hour in which the dead were so living and so near to us all.
A unique purity and disinterestedness had always attended his pen,
and he had the reward of it in realising moral proportion.
He had never failed to see small things; nor did he fall into
the more modern and enlightened error of failing to see big ones.
He had no difficulty in adjusting his subtlety to the stupendous
simplicity of a war for justice; his brain, like a Nasmyth hammer,
had not unlearnt in a long course of tapping how to fall and shatter.
That he should feel the prodigy of the Prussian insult to mankind
will only surprise those who have read him superficially;
or perhaps only read his more superficial sketches. He by no means
exhibits manners as more than morals; though he may exhibit manners
as more than many would think them. In a story like The Turn
of the Screw he has rather the character of a divine detective.
The woman who probes the stagnant secret of the depraved boy
and girl is resolved to forgive and, therefore, unable to forget.
She is a kind of inquisitor; and her morality is altogether
of the old thorough and theological sort. It is a summons to
repent and die, rather than a vague capacity to die and repent.
And when at the last the deliverance of the boy's soul seems
to be delayed by the appearance at the window of his evil genius,
"the white face of the damned", it is perhaps the one place
in all modern literature where that monosyllable is not a joke.
And it is strongly significant that men of any belief and no belief
have universally fallen back on such phraseology to find terms
for the sneering savagery of the present enemy of Christendom.
Honest grey-haired atheists are found judging the Prussian upon
the paradoxical principle that there may be heaven, there must be hell.
And the nations can find nothing but the language of demonology
to describe a certain poison of pride, which is none the less
a tyranny because it is also a temptation.
Henry James always stood, if ever a man did, for civilisation;
for that ordered life in which it is possible to tolerate
and to understand. His whole world is made out of sympathy;
out of a whole network of sympathies. It is a world of wireless
telegraphy for the soul; of a psychological brotherhood
of men of which the communications could not be cut.
Sometimes this sympathy is almost more terrible than antipathy;
and his very delicacies produce a sort of promiscuity of minds.
Silence becomes a rending revelation. Short spaces or short
speeches become overweighted with the awful worth of human life.
Minute unto minute uttereth speech, and instant unto instant
showeth knowledge. It is only when we have realised how perfect
is the poise of such great human art that we can also realise
its peril, and know that any outer thing which cannot make it must
of necessity destroy it.
It has been customary to talk of Henry James's American origin
as something almost antagonistic to the grace and rarity of his art.
I am far from sure that this is not to miss a fine and serious strain
in it. There is an element of idealism in the American tradition,
which is very well typified in the sincere and sometimes exaggerated
external deference to women. This particular sort of purity
in the perceptions, very marked in him, he had originally owed,
I think, to something other than the more mellow and matured European
life in which he came afterwards to take his deepest pleasures.
The older civilisation gave him the wonderful things he wanted;
but the wonder was his own. His attitude in private life
remains for anyone who has seen it as something infinitely
higher than politeness; an attitude towards things,
and something that can only be called an impersonal reverence.
Despite all their modernism, some of his love stories have a
dignity that might be dressed in the clothes of an antique time.
They should have moved upon high-terraced lawns among great and
gentle ladies, and their squires who were something more than gentlemen.
As Mr. Yeats says somewhere:
There have been lovers whose thought love should be So much compounded
of high courtesy, That they would sigh and quote with learned looks
Precedents out of beautiful old books.

The books of Henry James will always be beautiful; and I believe


they are young enough to be old.
THE STRANGE TALK OF TWO VICTORIANS
The Faith always returns in a counter-attack; and it is generally
not only a successful attack but almost always a surprise attack.
Here more than anywhere it is the unexpected that happens;
the religion supposed to be rotting away slowly in unlettered peasantries
was found present in pressing numbers in the new industrial towns;
the creed compassionately tolerated in a few old sentimentalists
is today making converts among the young almost entirely of
the hard-headed logicians.
But this tendency to a reconciliation with intellectuals,
once regarded as a reconciliation with irreconcilables, has produced,
among other queer points in the position, this fact; that the newest
group consists rather too much of those who are in a position to teach,
while there is not yet a sufficient crowd, or larger public,
of those who are in a position to learn. There is, for instance,
a huge mass of material in Catholic history for very good novels or plays;
and there are a considerable proportion of Catholics capable of
writing them; but there is not yet a sufficient number of ordinary
readers capable of reading them, in the sense of understanding them.
This is especially true of the high historic quality of irony.
An Englishman realising the real religious history of his country
constantly comes upon small social and political episodes, of which
the irony is as grand as Greek tragedy; and then he remembers most of
the other Englishmen, and has to own that it would be Greek to them.
The very ironic point which gives him grim gratification would
be quite pointless, because the public at large would probably take
the suggestion quite seriously and never even see the joke.
So, till very lately at least, the public hardly saw the joke
of talking about the Virgin Queen or the Glorious Revolution.
You cannot have drama without a public; you cannot have irony
without an instructed public.
I was wondering the other day whether anybody had thought
of a play, or rather a scene, which could be a very fine scene
written by anybody well read in eighteenth-century England.
It might be called "Five Irishmen."
Seated round a table in a coffeehouse (but conspicuously not drinking
coffee) would be Goldsmith, an old Tory almost a Jacobite; Sheridan,
a younger Whig almost a Jacobin; Burke, a Whig more alarmist than
any Tory about disturbing the balance of the British Constitution
(which he had largely made up out of his own highly imaginative head);
Grattan, a Whig orator also, but native to the Irish Parliament;
and (if he could be dragged in somehow) somebody more dangerous,
like Lord Edward of Tone, foreshadowing the Irish Rebellion.
All these men were Protestants. All, either in their own persons
or through their families, could be traced back in some way
to the time when it seemed that the heart of Ireland was broken;
and for a man who did not abandon the Faith there was no normal
hope on earth.
I think somebody could make a fine study, in several stages,
of how layer after layer began to crack and that awful forbidden
ancestral Thing rose slowly to overshadow them like a ghost.
They would begin decorously, of course, probably discussing
Catholic Emancipation with cold pagan liberality; and the wine
and the words and the Irish passion for personal recrimination,
and especially for family reminiscence, would bring strange things
spouting from the depths; and through a wild scene I actually seemed
suddenly to hear the high voice of Sheridan, shrill with intoxication,
crying out some taunt: "Have ye forgotten that, O'Bourke?" And then
I remembered that an audience in a London theatre would probably make
nothing of the notion of that great eternal Thing terribly returning;
because any number of them do not know that it is eternal and hardly
that it is great.
In Edith Sitwell's very graceful sketch of Queen Victoria, I came
on another quaint little drama, which in this case would be
a duologue. Also, in this case, the thing really happened.
It is there described briefly and impartially; but anyone
knowing persons and period can easily understand and expand it;
and to me it is enormously amusing; amusing and also enormous.
It has exactly that grim Greek irony of the contrast between great
things known and the greater thing that is not known. It was
a discussion, and even a dispute between two very eminent Victorians.
It was concerned with the news of the proclamation of the dogma
of the Immaculate Conception.
They were both good men; they were both men of the first prominence
in the public eye. Both had the finest culture of the Protestant;
both had a faint streak of the prig; but both had a warmth of generous
conviction for their own favourite causes; neither certainly was a fool;
neither was a No-Popery man in the narrow and vulgar sense;
both believed themselves flooded with the full daylight of the age
of enlightenment and liberty; and, at the same time, both had
hobbies and intelligent interests that might soften them toward
older religious traditions.
One was a great reader of the Fathers and the first devotional literature;
the other had a genuine taste in what was still often regarded
as the childish cheap jewellery of medieval painting.
One was a High Churchman of the Oxford Movement; the other was a
liberal Lutheran. One was the great Gladstone; the other was Albert,
the Prince Consort.
The two men talked and disagreed. They sharply disagreed.
The point on which they disagreed was extraordinary.
But it was not a hundredth part as extraordinary as the part on
which they agreed.
Mr. Gladstone was greatly grieved because he had found
the Prince Consort in a state of indecent hilarity, he thought,
over the news about the Immaculate Conception. Indecent hilarity
is not a vice conspicuously staining Prince Albert's name, any more
than Gladstone's; two more solemn disputants would be hard to find.
But Prince Albert was the more cheerful, because (he said in effect)
it is always a good thing when an evil system tottering to its fall,
does some one wildly insane and frantic act of arrogance;
which will quite certainly bring it to a final crash.
Rome had staggered along somehow till now; but, obviously, Rome would
never have a leg to stand on after this.
But Mr. Gladstone (of the Oxford Movement) could not join in this
simple German triumph over the disaster and disgrace that had at last
destroyed the Eternal City. In those deep tones of reproach he could
command so well, he rebuked the Prince for his insensibility to this
blasting and blackening of a name that had meant so much in history;
no Christian, he felt, could be insensible to the utter downfall
of so large a section of the Christian world. He meant it. He was
tremendously upset about it. He returned to the subject afterwards;
repeatedly imploring Prince Albert to drop at least one tear upon
the ruins of St. Peter's, now lying as desolate as Stonehenge.
But the Prince also was firm; and remained in his somewhat rare
state of high spirits over the news that the unduly protracted
business was finished; and the Pope had done himself in at last.
And all this was because--of what? Because one more crown had been
added to that tower of crowns that crowd after crowd, city after city,
nation after nation, age after age, have reared higher and higher on the
image which is of all others most strongly based and founded and built,
as regards this earth, in the affection of the universal people.
And Prince Albert, with his unselfish labours for the education
of the working classes, and Gladstone, with his confident appeal
to the great heart of the people, understood so little of what that
crown and image really meant to millions of ordinary poor people,
in all the countrysides and cities of half the world, that they
actually expected that it would be dethroned like a tyranny,
for this last toppling insolence in the demands of a tyrant.
The one extraordinary thing on which these extraordinary
men agreed, it seems, was that the decision would be unpopular.
... One of Belloc's Ballades had a refrain chiefly remembered
by the Envoi, which ran:
Prince, is it true that when you met the Czar
You said that English people think it low
To coax to life a half-extinct cigar?
Good Lord, how little wealthy people know!

Anyhow, the one assumption shared by these admirable public men seems
to have been wrong somewhere. Apple-women did not rush madly out
of church; seamstresses in garrets did not dash their little images
of Mary to the ground, on learning that she was named Immaculate.
Four years after these potentates had their regrettable difference,
while the Bishop still frowned and the parish priest feared to believe,
little knots of poor peasants began to gather round a strange
starved child before a crack in the rocks, from whence was to spring
a strange stream and almost a new city; the rocks she had heard
resound with a voice crying, "I am the Immaculate Conception. . . ."
"Good Lord, how little wealthy people know!"
LAUGHTER
If we in any sense propose for discussion the subject of Laughter,
we shall normally notice that our neighbours receive it in one
of two ways. Either they laugh, which is perhaps the best thing
they could do with a proposal for the analysis of laughter;
since practice is better than precept; and anyone sitting down,
as I do here, to write a whole article on this subject is a very proper
object for the derision of mankind. But if they have sense enough
to laugh, they will also probably have sense enough to go away;
the colloquy will be cut short and exhibit only the kind of wit
which is identified with brevity.
If, on the other hand, we mention Laughter to them and they
do not laugh, what they always do is this; to twist their silly
faces into expressions of ferocious gravity and gloom and begin
to talk about Primitive Psychology, and the automatic reflexes
of Pithecanthropus; and after a month or two of this cheery little chat,
they practically always bring out the result (which is an unmistakable
sign and a symptom of their dying minds) that "laughter is,
after all, founded on some form of the instinct of cruelty".
The whole being a neat and polished exposition of the great modern habit
of being as unscientific as possible in the use of scientific words.
They have not yet proved that there is any instinct of cruelty,
any more than there is an instinct of chewing glass.
Some lunatics do chew glass; even some eminent men have done it;
I think the famous Sir Richard Grenville had the habit.
Some men have a perversion called cruelty; but if primitive men
develop a talent for humour from a perversion of cruelty, it is quite
as difficult to explain how they developed the perversion as how they
developed the talent. We might as well explain the beginning
of poetry by saying that Pithecanthropus was addicted to cocaine.
The whole thing is one of those impudent insinuations of popular science,
quite unsupported by serious science, but having a very strong
moral or anti-moral motive; to suggest by innumerable irresponsible
hints that human beings owe everything to semi-human beings called
primitive men; and that these were utterly degraded creatures,
dwelling in a darkness of hatred and fear.
On the face of it, all this theory of laughter is laughable.
Anybody can make a child laugh by some simple inversion
or incongruity; such as putting spectacles on the teddy bear.
Are we asked to believe that a dark troglodyte stirs in the cave
of the infant's skull, and takes pleasure in torturing the teddy
bear with unfamiliar optical conditions; or fiendishly rejoices in
the agony of an aged uncle when temporarily deprived of his goggles?
The sort of literature at which children really laugh is the
simplest sort of nonsense like "the cow jumped over the moon".
Are we to suppose children lie awake and laugh to think of the long
and chilly journey of the lost quadruped, in the cold altitudes wholly
unsuited to warm-blooded mammals? It is obvious that the mind is amused
with incongruity, when there is no direct or indirect idea of discomfort.
Why it is amused with incongruity is indeed a very deep question,
and we shall get no further with such questions until we
adopt a totally different attitude to the whole story of man;
until we have the patience to respect a great many of the mysteries
as mysteries, and wait for an explanation which really explains;
instead of jumping at any explanation that merely explains away.
But I suspect it will be found connected with the idea of human
dignity rather than indignity; and rather related to the strangeness
of man on this strange earth, than to the mere dull brutalities
connecting him with the dull mud.
It is not surprising that an age exhibiting this monstrous spectacle,
of men being sombre and pessimistic about the origin of Laughter,
should also exhibit some loss of the simpler sort of laughter in its
literature and art. And I fancy even those who might claim that we
produce more humour would admit that we produce less laughter.
But the poison of the anti-human heresy I have mentioned works back
in a curious fashion into the practice of those who have heard the theory;
and the ideas of cause and effect act and react on each other.
It may be that only in a dry age could pedants be found to trace back
all mirth to malignity; it may be that the atmospheric suggestion
of that origin has made the mirth less mirthful, and more dry if not
more malignant. But certainly, at the best, the tendency of recent
culture has been to tolerate the smile but discourage the laugh.
There are three differences involved here. First, that the smile can
unobtrusively turn into the sneer; second, that the smile is always
individual and even secretive (especially if it is a little mad),
while the laugh can be social and gregarious, and is perhaps
the one genuine surviving form of the General Will; and third,
that laughing lays itself open to criticism, is innocent and unguarded,
has the sort of humanity which has always something of humility.
The recent stage of culture and criticism might very well be
summed up as the men who smile criticising the men who laugh.
We may read in any current novel, "Grigsby stroked his chin and
smiled a rather superior smile." We seldom read, even in a novel,
"Grigsby flung back his head and howled at the ceiling with a
slightly superior laugh." The moment Grigsby abandons himself
so far as to laugh he has lost something of that perfect superiority
of the Grigsbys, for which they are famous in fashionable circles,
and for which so many of their fellow-creatures would love to kick them,
as old Weller kicked Mr. Stiggins. For it is a complete mistake
to suppose that there is less cruelty since we abandoned the good old
custom of kicking Mr. Stiggins. The only difference is that it is
Mr. Grigsby who is allowed to be cruel; because of the lack of simpler
and humbler men to enjoy the innocent pleasure of kicking him.
In the mind of Mr. Grigsby, at that exquisite moment when he smiles,
there is infinitely more cruelty, in the sense of mere malice,
than there was in the mind of Weller when he applied the boot,
or Dickens when he wrote the book. The chief mark of the most
modern change in the world is that milder social manners do not go
with warmer social feelings. The chief fact we have to face today
is the absence of even that amount of democratic comradeship which
was involved in coarse laughter or merely conventional ridicule.
The men of the older fellowship may have sometimes unjustly
disliked a scapegoat or an alien, but they liked each other
much more than a good many literary men now like each other.
It is obvious in a thousand ways that there was more communal sentiment,
or if you will sentimentality, in the camps where Bret Harte's
ruffians brandished bowie-knives and revolvers, or in the public-house
cellar where Mr. Bardell was knocked on the head with a quart pot,
than in many a modern intellectual circle in which the soul
is at last finally isolated, like the heads in hell held apart
in their rings of ice. Therefore, in this modern conflict
between the Smile and the Laugh, I am all in favour of laughing.
Laughter has something in it in common with the ancient winds
of faith and inspiration; it unfreezes pride and unwinds secrecy;
it makes men forget themselves in the presence of something greater
than themselves; something (as the common phrase goes about a joke)
that they cannot resist. The saint is he who enjoys good things and
refuses them. The prig is he who despises good things and enjoys them.
But when he hears a really good thing, which he really enjoys,
then he can no longer despise it. On that awful and apocalyptic occasion,
he does not smile; he laughs.
TALES FROM TOLSTOI
In one sense there is a real and actual law of progress by which we
grow simpler as we grow more civilised, for the more we scan and study
the phenomena around us the more they tend to unify themselves
with the power behind them, and the whole of existence thus seen
for the first time seems something of an entirely new shape and colour,
a fresh and surprising thing. And all the great writers of our
time represent in one form or another this attempt to re-establish
communication with the elemental or, as it is sometimes more roughly
and fallaciously expressed, to return to nature. Some think
that the return to nature consists in drinking no wine ; some think
that it consists in drinking a great deal more than is good for them.
Some think that the return to nature is achieved by beating swords
into ploughshares; some think it is achieved by turning ploughshares
into very ineffectual British War Office bayonets.
It is natural, according to the Jingo, for a man to kill other people
with gunpowder and himself with gin. It is natural, according to
the humanitarian revolutionists, to kill other people with dynamite
and himself with vegetarianism. It would be too obviously Philistine
a sentiment, perhaps, to suggest that the claim of either of these
persons to be obeying the voice of nature is interesting when we
consider that they require huge volumes of paradoxical argument to
persuade themselves or anyone else of the truth of their conclusions.
But the giants of our time are undoubtedly alike in that they
approach by very different roads this conception of the return
to simplicity. Ibsen returns to nature by the angular exterior
of fact, Maeterlinck by the eternal tendencies of fable.
Whitman returns to nature by seeing how much he can accept,
Tolstoi by seeing how much he can reject.
Now, this heroic desire to return to nature is, of course,
in some respects, rather like the heroic desire of a kitten to return
to its own tail. A tail is a simple and beautiful object, rhythmic in
curve and soothing in texture; but it is certainly one of the minor
but characteristic qualities of a tail that it should hang behind.
It is impossible to deny that it would in some degree lose
its character if attached to any other part of the anatomy.
Now, nature is like a tail in the sense that it is vitally important
if it is to discharge its real duty that it should be always behind.
To imagine that we can see nature, especially our own nature,
face to face is a folly; it is even a blasphemy. It is like
the conduct of a cat in some mad fairy tale who should set out
on his travels with the firm conviction that he would find his
tail growing like a tree in the meadow at the end of the world.
And the actual effect of the travels of the philosopher
in search of nature when seen from the outside looks very like
the gyrations of the tail-pursuing kitten, exhibiting much
enthusiasm but little dignity, much cry and very little tail.
The grandeur of nature is that she is omnipotent and unseen, that she
is perhaps ruling us most when we think that she is heeding us least.
"Thou art a God that hidest Thyself," said the Hebrew poets.
It may be said with all reverence that it is behind a man's back
that the spirit of nature hides.
It is this consideration that lends a certain air of futility even
to all the inspired simplicities and thunderous veracities of Tolstoi.
We feel that a man cannot make himself simple merely by warring
on complexity; we feel, indeed, in our saner moments that a man
cannot make himself simple at all. A self-conscious simplicity
may well be far more intrinsically ornate than luxury itself.
Indeed, a great deal of the pomp and sumptuousness of the world's
history was simple in the truest sense. It was born of an almost
babyish receptiveness; it was the work of men who had eyes to wonder
and men who had ears to hear.
King Solomon brought merchant men
Because of his desire
With peacocks, apes and ivory,
From Tarshish unto Tyre.
But this proceeding was not a part of the wisdom of Solomon;
it was a part of his folly--I had almost said of his innocence.
Tolstoi, we feel, would not be content with hurling
satire and denunciation at "Solomon in all his glory".
With fierce and unimpeachable logic he would go a step further.
He would spend days and nights in the meadows stripping the shameless
crimson coronals off the lilies of the field.
Any collection of Tales from Tolstoi is calculated to draw particular
attention to this ethical and ascetic side of Tolstoi's work.
In one sense, and that the deepest sense, the work of Tolstoi is,
of course, a genuine and noble appeal to simplicity. The narrow
notion that an artist may not teach is pretty well exploded by now.
But the truth of the matter is that an artist teaches far more
by his mere background and properties, his landscape, his costume,
his idiom and technique--all the part of his work, in short,
of which he is probably entirely unconscious, than by the elaborate
and pompous moral dicta which he fondly imagines to be his opinions.
The real distinction between the ethics of high art and the ethics
of manufactured and didactic art lies in the simple fact that
the bad fable has a moral, while the good fable is a moral.
And the real moral of Tolstoi comes out constantly in his stories,
the great moral which lies at the heart of all his work,
of which he is probably unconscious, and of which it is quite
likely that he would vehemently disapprove. The curious cold white
light of morning that shines over all the tales, the folklore
simplicity with which "a man or a woman" are spoken of without
further identification, the love--one might almost say the lust--
for the qualities of brute materials, the hardness of wood,
and the softness of mud, the ingrained belief in a certain ancient
kindliness sitting beside the very cradle of the race of man--
these influences are truly moral. When we put beside them
the trumpeting and tearing nonsense of the didactic Tolstoi,
screaming for an obscene purity, shouting for an inhuman peace,
hacking up human life into small sins with a chopper, sneering at men,
women, and children out of respect to humanity, combining in one
chaos of contradictions an unmanly Puritan and an uncivilised prig,
then, indeed, we scarcely know whither Tolstoi has vanished.
We know not what to do with this small and noisy moralist who is
inhabiting one's corner of a great and good man.
It is difficult in every case to reconcile Tolstoi the great artist
with Tolstoi the almost venomous reformer. It is difficult to believe
that a man who draws in such noble outlines the dignity of the daily
life of humanity regards as evil that divine act of procreation
by which that dignity is renewed from age to age. It is difficult
to believe that a man who has painted with so frightful an honesty
the heartrending emptiness of the life of the poor can really grudge
them every one of their pitiful pleasures from courtship to tobacco.
It is difficult to believe that a poet in prose who has so powerfully
exhibited the earth-born air of man, the essential kinship of a human
being with the landscape in which he lives, can deny so elemental a virtue
as that which attaches a man to his own ancestors and his own land.
It is difficult to believe that the man who feels so poignantly
the detestable insolence of oppression would not actually, if he had
the chance, lay the oppressor flat with his fist. All, however,
arises from the search after a false simplicity, the aim of being,
if I may so express it, more natural than it is natural to be.
It would not only be more human, it would be more humble of us to be
content to be complex. The truest kinship with humanity would lie
in doing as humanity has always done, accepting with a sportsmanlike
relish the estate to which we are called, the star of our happiness,
and the fortunes of the land of our birth.
THE NEW CASE FOR CATHOLIC SCHOOLS
Any amount of nonsense has been talked about the need of novelty,
and in that sense there is nothing particularly meritorious about
being modern. A man who seriously describes his creed as Modernism
might just as well invent a creed called Mondayism, meaning that
he puts special faith in the fancies that occurred to him on Monday;
or a creed called Morningism, meaning that he believed in the thoughts
that occurred to him in the morning but not in the afternoon.
Modernity is only the moment of time in which we happen to find ourselves,
and nobody who thinks will suppose that it is bound to be superior,
either to the time that comes after it or to the time that went before.
But in a relative and rational sense we may congratulate ourselves
on knowing the news of the moment, and having realised recent facts
or discoveries that some people still ignore.
And it is in that sense that we may truly call the fundamental
concept of Catholic Education a scientific fact, and especially
a psychological fact. Our demand for a complete culture, based on its
own philosophy and religion, is a demand that is really unanswerable,
in the light of the most vital and even the most modern psychology.
For that matter, for those who care for such things, there could
hardly be a word more modern than atmosphere.
Now, so long as they are engaged in doing anything whatever except
arguing with us, our modern and scientific friends are never
tired of telling us that education must be treated as a whole;
that all parts of the mind affect each other; that nothing is too
trivial to be significant and even symbolic; that all thoughts can
be coloured by conscious or unconscious emotions; that knowledge can
never be in watertight compartments; that what may seem a senseless
detail may be the symbol of a deep desire; that nothing is negative,
nothing is naked, nothing stands separate and alone.
They use these arguments for all sorts of purposes, some of them
sensible enough, some of them almost insanely silly; but this is,
broadly speaking, how they argue. And the one thing they do not
know is that they are arguing in favour of Catholic education,
and especially in favour of Catholic atmosphere in Catholic schools.
Perhaps if they did know they would leave off.
As a matter of fact, those who refuse to understand that Catholic
children must have an entirely Catholic school are back in the bad
old days, as they would express it, when nobody wanted education
but only instruction. They are relics of the dead time when it
was thought enough to drill pupils in two or three dull and detached
lessons that were supposed to be quite mechanical. They descend
from the original Philistine who first talked about "The Three R.s";
and the joke about him is very symbolic of his type or time.
For he was the sort of man who insists very literally on literacy,
and, even in doing so, shows himself illiterate.
They were very uneducated rich men who loudly demanded education.
And among the marks of their ignorance and stupidity was the particular
mark that they regarded letters and figures as dead things,
quite separate from each other and from a general view of life.
They thought of a boy learning his letters as something quite
cut off, for instance, from what is meant by a man of letters.
They thought a calculating boy could be made like a calculating machine.
When somebody said to them, therefore, "These things must be
taught in a spiritual atmosphere", they thought it was nonsense;
they had a vague idea that it meant that a child could only do
a simple addition sum when surrounded with the smell of incense.
But they thought simple addition much more simple than it is.
When the Catholic controversialist said to them, "Even the alphabet
can be learnt in a Catholic way", they thought he was a raving bigot,
they thought he meant that nobody must ever read anything but
a Latin missal.
But he meant what he said, and what he said is thoroughly
sound psychology. There is a Catholic view of learning the alphabet;
for instance, it prevents you from thinking that the only thing
that matters is learning the alphabet; or from despising better people
than yourself, if they do not happen to have learnt the alphabet.
The old unpsychological school of instructors used to say:
"What possible sense can there be in mixing up arithmetic
with religion?" But arithmetic is mixed up with religion,
or at the worst with philosophy. It does make a great deal
of difference whether the instructor implies that truth is real,
or relative, or changeable, or an illusion. The man who said,
"Two and two may make five in the fixed stars", was teaching arithmetic
in an anti-rational way, and, therefore, in an anti-Catholic way.
The Catholic is much more certain about the fixed truths than about
the fixed stars.
But I am not now arguing which philosophy is the better;
I am only pointing out that every education teaches a philosophy;
if not by dogma then by suggestion, by implication, by atmosphere.
Every part of that education has a connection with every other part.
If it does not all combine to convey some general view of life,
it is not education at all. And the modern educationists,
the modern psychologists, the modern men of science, all agree
in asserting and reasserting this--until they begin to quarrel
with Catholics over Catholic schools.
In short, if there is a psychological truth discoverable by human reason,
it is this; that Catholics must either go without Catholic
teaching or possess and govern Catholic schools. There is a case
for refusing to allow Catholic families to grow up Catholic,
by any machinery worth calling education in the existing sense.
There is a case for refusing to make any concessions to Catholics
at all, and ignoring their idiosyncrasy as if it were an insanity.
There is a case for that, because there is and always has been
a case for persecution; for the State acting on the principle that
certain philosophies are false and dangerous and must be crushed
even if they are sincerely held; indeed that they must be crushed,
especially if they are sincerely held.
But if Catholics are to teach Catholicism all the time,
they cannot merely teach Catholic theology for part of the time.
It is our opponents, and not we, who give a really
outrageous and superstitious position to dogmatic theology.
It is they who suppose that the special "subject" called theology
can be put into people by an experiment lasting half an hour;
and that this magical inoculation will last them through a week
in a world that is soaked through and through with a contrary
conception of life.
Theology is only articulate religion; but, strange as it seems
to the true Christians who criticise us, it is necessary to have
religion as well as theology. And religion, as they are often obliging
enough to remind us when this particular problem is not involved,
is a thing for every day of the week and not merely for Sunday
or Church services.
The truth is that the modern world has committed itself to two totally
different and inconsistent conceptions about education. It is always
trying to expand the scope of education; and always trying to exclude
from it all religion and philosophy. But this is sheer nonsense.
You can have an education that teaches atheism because atheism is true,
and it can be, from its own point of view, a complete education.
But you cannot have an education claiming to teach all truth,
and then refusing to discuss whether atheism is true.
Since the coming of the more ambitious psychological education,
our schools have claimed to develop all sides of human nature;
that is, to produce a complete human being. You cannot do this
and totally ignore a great living tradition, which teaches that a
complete human being must be a Christian or Catholic human being.
You must either persecute it out of existence or allow it to make
its own education complete.
When schooling was supposed to consist of spelling, of counting
and making pothooks and hangers, you might make out some kind
of case for saying that it could be taught indifferently by a
Baptist or Buddhist. But what in the world is the sense of having
an education which includes lessons in "citizenship", for instance;
and then pretending not to include anything like a moral theory,
and ignoring all those who happen to hold that a moral theory
depends on a moral theology.
Our schoolmasters profess to bring out every side of the pupil;
the aesthetic side; the athletic side; the political side, and so on;
and yet they still talk the stale cant of the nineteenth century
about public instruction having nothing to do with the religious side.
The truth is that, in this matter, it is our enemies who are
stick-in-the mud, and still remain in the stuffy atmosphere
of undeveloped and unscientific education; while we are,
in this at any rate, on the side of all modern psychologists
and serious educationists in recognising the idea of atmosphere.
They sometimes like to call it environment.
VULGARITY
Vulgarity is one of the great new modern inventions;
like the telephone or the wireless set. It may be plausibly
maintained that the telephone is less of an instrument of torture
than the thumbscrew or the rack, and in the same way that other ages
had other vices that were worse than this new or modern vice.
As we may find fanciful sketches of aeroplanes in the sketchbooks
of Leonardo da Vinci, or speculations very near to modern physics
in the philosophers of ancient Greece, so we may find here and
there in history a hint or foreshadowing of the great and golden
vision of vulgarity that was later to burst on the world.
We may find it in the smell of Punic plutocracy that stank in
the nostrils of Greeks and Romans, or in a certain touch of bad
taste in an aesthete like Nero.
Nevertheless, the thing is so new that the new world has not
yet really found a name for it, but has had to borrow a rather
misleading name, which is really the Latin word for something else.
So we have to go on using the Greek name of amber as the only name
of electricity because we have no notion what is the real name
or nature of electricity. And so we have to go on using the Latin
word vulgus, which only meant the common people, to describe something
that is not particularly common among the common people.
Indeed, through long stretches of human history, and over wide spaces
of the habitable globe, it is very uncommon among the common people.
Farmers living by long agricultural traditions, peasants in normal
villages, even savages in savage tribes, are hardly ever vulgar.
Even when they massacre and enslave, even when they offer human
sacrifice or eat human flesh, they are hardly ever vulgar.
All travellers attest to the natural dignity of their carriage
and the ceremonial gravity of their customs. Even in the more
complex modern cities and civilisations the poor as such are
not particularly vulgar.
No; there is a new thing, which really needs a new name, and still more,
a new definition. I do not say I can define vulgarity; but, having just
been reading a modern book about love, I feel inclined to throw
out a few suggestions.
In so far as I can get near to its essence, it consists largely
of two elements, which I should describe as facility and familiarity.
The first means that a man does really, as the phrase goes, "gush";
that is, his self-expression flows without effort, selection or control.
It does not come from him like picked and pointed words, passing through
an articulate organ; it simply streams from him like perspiration.
He need never stop explaining himself, for he understands neither
himself nor the limits of explanation. He is the sort of man who
understands women; he is the man who can always get on with the boys;
he finds it easy to talk, easy to write, easy to speak in public,
for his own self-satisfaction carries with it a sort of huge cloud
and illusion of applause.
And the second element is familiarity, which, if understood,
would be called profanity. Horace spoke of the "profane vulgar",
and it is true that this familiarity is the loss of holy fear
and a sin against the mystical side of man. In practice
it means handling things confidently and contemptuously,
without the sense that all things in their way are sacred things.
Its most recent mode is the readiness to write torrents of tosh
on either side of any serious subject, for you hardly ever get real
vulgarity on a frivolous subject.
The point is that the fool is so subjective that it never occurs to him
to be afraid of the subject. For instance, he can be a Pagan fool,
as well as a Puritan fool, in the debate on modern morals;
but in the first case there will be torrents of tosh about love
and passion and the right to live and in the other, exactly similar
torrents of tosh about Christian manhood and healthy boyhood and noble
motherhood and the rest. The trouble is that they are so infernally
familiar with these things.
Never do you find that note in a real lover writing of the woman
he loves or in a real saint writing of the sin he hates.
Both say the right thing, because they would rather say nothing at all.
THE REVIVAL OF PHILOSOPHY--WHY?
The best reason for a revival of philosophy is that unless a man
has a philosophy certain horrible things will happen to him.
He will be practical; he will be progressive; he will
cultivate efficiency; he will trust in evolution; he will do the work
that lies nearest; he will devote himself to deeds, not words.
Thus struck down by blow after blow of blind stupidity and random fate,
he will stagger on to a miserable death with no comfort but a series
of catchwords; such as those which I have catalogued above.
Those things are simply substitutes for thoughts. In some cases
they are the tags and tail-ends of somebody else's thinking.
That means that a man who refuses to have his own philosophy will not even
have the advantages of a brute beast, and be left to his own instincts.
He will only have the used-up scraps of somebody else's philosophy;
which the beasts do not have to inherit; hence their happiness.
Men have always one of two things: either a complete and conscious
philosophy or the unconscious acceptance of the broken bits of
some incomplete and shattered and often discredited philosophy.
Such broken bits are the phrases I have quoted: efficiency and evolution
and the rest. The idea of being "practical", standing all by itself,
is all that remains of a Pragmatism that cannot stand at all.
It is impossible to be practical without a Pragma. And what would
happen if you went up to the next practical man you met and said
to the poor dear old duffer, "Where is your Pragma?" Doing the work
that is nearest is obvious nonsense; yet it has been repeated
in many albums. In nine cases out of ten it would mean doing
the work that we are least fitted to do, such as cleaning the windows
or clouting the policeman over the head. "Deeds, not words"
is itself an excellent example of "Words, not thoughts".
It is a deed to throw a pebble into a pond and a word that sends
a prisoner to the gallows. But there are certainly very futile words;
and this sort of journalistic philosophy and popular science almost
entirely consists of them.
Some people fear that philosophy will bore or bewilder them;
because they think it is not only a string of long words,
but a tangle of complicated notions. These people miss
the whole point of the modern situation. These are exactly
the evils that exist already; mostly for want of a philosophy.
The politicians and the papers are always using long words.
It is not a complete consolation that they use them wrong.
The political and social relations are already hopelessly complicated.
They are far more complicated than any page of medieval metaphysics;
the only difference is that the medievalist could trace out the tangle
and follow the complications; and the moderns cannot. The chief
practical things of today, like finance and political corruption,
are frightfully complicated. We are content to tolerate them
because we are content to misunderstand them, not to understand them.
The business world needs metaphysics--to simplify it.
I know these words will be received with scorn, and with gruff
reassertion that this is no time for nonsense and paradox;
and that what is really wanted is a practical man to go in and
clear up the mess. And a practical man will doubtless appear,
one of the unending succession of practical men; and he will
doubtless go in, and perhaps clear up a few millions for himself
and leave the mess more bewildering than before; as each of the
other practical men has done. The reason is perfectly simple.
This sort of rather crude and unconscious person always adds
to the confusion; because he himself has two or three different
motives at the same moment, and does not distinguish between them.
A man has, already entangled hopelessly in his own mind,
(1) a hearty and human desire for money, (2) a somewhat priggish
and superficial desire to be progressing, or going the way the world
is going, (3) a dislike to being thought too old to keep up
with the young people, (4) a certain amount of vague but genuine
patriotism or public spirit, (5) a misunderstanding of a mistake
made by Mr. H. G. Wells, in the form of a book on Evolution.
When a man has all these things in his head, and does not even attempt
to sort them out, he is called by common consent and acclamation
a practical man. But the practical man cannot be expected to improve
the impracticable muddle; for he cannot clear up the muddle in his
own mind, let alone in his own highly complex community and civilisation.
For some strange reason, it is the custom to say of this sort
of practical man that "he knows his own mind". Of course this
is exactly what he does not know. He may in a few fortunate cases
know what he wants, as does a dog or a baby of two years old;
but even then he does not know why he wants it. And it is the why
and the how that have to be considered when we are tracing out
the way in which some culture or tradition has got into a tangle.
What we need, as the ancients understood, is not a politician
who is a business man, but a king who is a philosopher.
I apologise for the word "king", which is not strictly necessary
to the sense; but I suggest that it would be one of the functions
of the philosopher to pause upon such words, and determine their
importance and unimportance. The Roman Republic and all its citizens
had to the last a horror of the word "king". It was in consequence of this
that they invented and imposed on us the word "Emperor". The great
Republicans who founded America also had a horror of the word "king";
which has therefore reappeared with the special qualification
of a Steel King, an Oil King, a Pork King, or other similar monarchs
made of similar materials. The business of the philosopher is not
necessarily to condemn the innovation or to deny the distinction.
But it is his duty to ask himself exactly what it is that he or others
dislike in the word "king". If what he dislikes is a man wearing
the spotted fur of a small animal called the ermine, or a man having
once had a metal ring placed on the top of his head by a clergyman,
he will decide one way. If what he dislikes is a man having vast
or irresponsible powers over other men, he may decide another.
If what he dislikes is such fur or such power being handed on from father
to son, he will enquire whether this ever occurs under commercial
conditions today. But, anyhow, he will have the habit of testing
the thing by the thought; by the idea which he likes or dislikes;
and not merely by the sound of a syllable or the look of four
letters beginning with an "R".
Philosophy is merely thought that has been thought out.
It is often a great bore. But man has no alternative,
except between being influenced by thought that has been thought
out and being influenced by thought that has not been thought out.
The latter is what we commonly call culture and enlightenment today.
But man is always influenced by thought of some kind, his own
or somebody else's; that of somebody he trusts or that of somebody
he never heard of, thought at first, second or third hand;
thought from exploded legends or unverified rumours; but always
something with the shadow of a system of values and a reason
for preference. A man does test everything by something.
The question here is whether he has ever tested the test.
I will take one example out of a thousand that might be taken. What is
the attitude of an ordinary man on being told of an extraordinary event:
a miracle? I mean the sort of thing that is loosely called supernatural,
but should more properly be called preternatural. For the word
supernatural applies only to what is higher than man; and a good many
modern miracles look as if they came from what is considerably lower.
Anyhow, what do modern men say when apparently confronted with
something that cannot, in the cant phrase, be naturally explained?
Well, most modern men immediately talk nonsense. When such a thing
is currently mentioned, in novels or newspapers or magazine stories,
the first comment is always something like, "But my dear fellow,
this is the twentieth century!" It is worth having a little training
in philosophy if only to avoid looking so ghastly a fool as that.
It has on the whole rather less sense or meaning than saying, "But my
dear fellow, this is Tuesday afternoon." If miracles cannot happen,
they cannot happen in the twentieth century or in the twelfth.
If they can happen, nobody can prove that there is a time when they
cannot happen. The best that can be said for the sceptic is that
he cannot say what he means, and therefore, whatever else he means,
he cannot mean what he says. But if he only means that miracles
can be believed in the twelfth century, but cannot be believed in
the twentieth, then he is wrong again, both in theory and in fact.
He is wrong in theory, because an intelligent recognition
of possibilities does not depend on a date but on a philosophy.
An atheist could disbelieve in the first century and a mystic
could continue to believe in the twenty-first century.
And he is wrong, in fact, because there is every sign of there being
a great deal of mysticism and miracle in the twenty-first century;
and there is quite certainly an increasing mass of it in the twentieth.
But I have only taken that first superficial repartee because
there is a significance in the mere fact that it comes first;
and its very superficiality reveals something of the subconsciousness.
It is almost an automatic repartee; and automatic words are of some
importance in psychology. Let us not be too severe on the worthy
gentleman who informs his dear fellow that it is the twentieth century.
In the mysterious depths of his being even that enormous ass does actually
mean something. The point is that he cannot really explain what he means;
and that is the argument for a better education in philosophy.
What he really means is something like this, "There is a theory
of this mysterious universe to which more and more people were in fact
inclined during the second half of the eighteenth and the first
half of the nineteenth centuries; and up to that point at least,
this theory did grow with the growing inventions and discoveries
of science to which we owe our present social organisation--
or disorganisation. That theory maintains that cause and effect
have from the first operated in an uninterrupted sequence like a
fixed fate; and that there is no will behind or within that fate;
so that it must work itself out in the absence of such a will,
as a machine must run down in the absence of a man. There were more
people in the nineteenth century than in the ninth who happened
to hold this particular theory of the universe. I myself happened
to hold it; and therefore I obviously cannot believe in miracles."
That is perfectly good sense; but so is the counter-statement;
"I do not happen to hold it; and therefore I obviously can
believe in miracles."
The advantage of an elementary philosophic habit is that it
permits a man, for instance, to understand a statement like this,
"Whether there can or can not be exceptions to a process depends
on the nature of that process." The disadvantage of not having it
is that a man will turn impatiently even from so simple a truism;
and call it metaphysical gibberish. He will then go off and say:
"One can't have such things in the twentieth century"; which really
is gibberish. Yet the former statement could surely be explained to him
in sufficiently simple terms. If a man sees a river run downhill
day after day and year after year, he is justified in reckoning,
we might say in betting, that it will do so till he dies.
But he is not justified in saying that it cannot run uphill,
until he really knows why it runs downhill. To say it does so by
gravitation answers the physical but not the philosophical question.
It only repeats that there is a repetition; it does not touch the deeper
question of whether that repetition could be altered by anything
outside it. And that depends on whether there is anything outside it.
For instance, suppose that a man had only seen the river in a dream.
He might have seen it in a hundred dreams, always repeating itself
and always running downhill. But that would not prevent the hundredth
dream being different and the river climbing the mountain;
because the dream is a dream, and there is something outside it.
Mere repetition does not prove reality or inevitability.
We must know the nature of the thing and the cause of the repetition.
If the nature of the thing is a Creation, and the cause of
the thing a Creator, in other words if the repetition itself
is only the repetition of something willed by a person, then it
is not impossible for the same person to will a different thing.
If a man is a fool for believing in a Creator, then he is a fool
for believing in a miracle; but not otherwise. Otherwise, he is
simply a philosopher who is consistent in his philosophy.
A modern man is quite free to choose either philosophy.
But what is actually the matter with the modern man is that he does
not know even his own philosophy; but only his own phraseology.
He can only answer the next spiritual message produced by
a spiritualist, or the next cure attested by doctors at Lourdes,
by repeating what are generally nothing but phrases; or are,
at their best, prejudices.
Thus, when so brilliant a man as Mr. H. G. Wells says that such
supernatural ideas have become impossible "for intelligent people",
he is (for that instant) not talking like an intelligent person.
In other words, he is not talking like a philosopher;
because he is not even saying what he means. What he means is,
not "impossible for intelligent men", but, "impossible for
intelligent monists", or, "impossible for intelligent determinists".
But it is not a negation of intelligence to hold any coherent
and logical conception of so mysterious a world. It is not a
negation of intelligence to think that all experience is a dream.
It is not unintelligent to think it a delusion, as some Buddhists do;
let alone to think it a product of creative will, as Christians do.
We are always being told that men must no longer be so sharply divided
into their different religions. As an immediate step in progress,
it is much more urgent that they should be more clearly and more
sharply divided into their different philosophies.
VANDALISM
Vandalism is of two kinds, the negative and the positive;
as in the Vandals of the ancient world, who destroyed buildings,
and the Vandals of the modern world, who erect them. A long
procession of those typically modern thinkers, who are too tired
to think, has already left behind a trail or tradition of language;
by which it is vaguely suggested that whatever is constructive
is good and only what is destructive is bad. Anyone wishing
to lose himself in mazes of such logic, or rather illogicality,
may put to himself some particular proposition; as that it is
good to construct a stake, with faggots, for burning a man alive,
and yet bad to destroy a growing plantation or cut down trees,
which is the only possible way of doing it. But in the particular
case of Vandalism, it is very specially necessary to remember
that the real argument is all the other way. Of two bad things,
it is better to be the barbarian who destroys something, which for
some reason he dislikes or does not understand, and who may yet
sincerely like other things that he does understand, rather than to be
the vulgarian who erects something exactly expressive of what he likes;
and in that act rears a colossal image of the smallness of his soul.
Destructive Vandalism, though a very great evil at the present time,
and indeed through all history, has not been in all history so bad
as it is now; and certainly not so bad as many more constructive
things that exist now.
It is important to remember that there are two kinds of
mere destructiveness; neither on the noblest level of human culture,
but neither on the most ignoble. First, of course, the Vandal
may be the Iconoclast. He may destroy certain artistic creations
because they are really opposed to his moral convictions.
Thus a Puritan fanatic from America might conceivably think himself
commanded by the Lord to dynamite Westminster Abbey, because it
is full of idols; that is of images with a religious character.
Curiously enough, he would be half right. It is full of idols;
but they are not images of a religious character. Anybody can
see at a glance that medieval figures of saints and angels
are not worshipped; for the perfectly simple reason that they
are themselves represented in the act of worshipping. But the
eighteenth-century statues of statesmen and generals really are idols.
They are manifestly set up, not to the glory of God, but to the glory
of the men there represented; who are to be directly worshipped
for their own sake; as the Pagans worshipped demigods and heroes.
Lord Polkerton and Admiral Bangs are not themselves represented
in the act of worshipping; but in the act of being worshipped.
For the eighteenth century, which has been called the Age of Reason,
was the real Age of Idolatry. This, however, is a parenthesis.
The point is that the American fanatic would be a much finer fellow
than the American chain-store man who finds half London in the chains
of his cheap and tawdry stores. If the dynamite of the Iconoclast
caved in the whole front of Westminster Abbey, I should be far
less horrified than I am at a project of a Yankee shopkeeper for
building a tower with bells, taller than Westminster Cathedral.
It is curious to reflect on the few stray nerves of criticism and
sensibility that still remain. I fancy that if an American erected
immediately opposite Windsor Castle, on the other side of the river,
another castle of exactly the same castellated form and plan,
only a little bigger (being made of cheap and rotten material)
and then flew the flag of his own ancient family in direct defiance
of the personal flag of the King, there would be a good many people
in society who would tell the American, however rich he was,
that this was going a bit too far. Which shows how much safer it
is to insult religion than to insult royalty.
Secondly, in the great moral philosophy of being fair to Vandals,
we must remember that there is a certain element in life which
has even a right to its place in life, though that place may
not always be easy to find, without displacing better things.
We talk of positive and negative, of creation and destruction;
but in a sense the association is incorrect. Destruction is
not negation; at least it is not always and of necessity negation.
There is a positive pleasure in destruction, which can be harmless
and is certainly real. It is innocent, for it is felt strongly
by children when they first tear up paper or break sticks.
But I trust that few of us have so entirely lost our innocence,
as to be unable to drink deep joy from smashing up the happy home.
Breathes there a man with soul so dead that he has never,
when standing in a respectable parlour, felt a wild desire
to seize a pot and plant and send it crashing through the bow
windows into the front-garden or the street? These things are
not entirely to be sterilised; these things also are from God.
It is all explained in a ballade which my friends and I composed
years ago, after I had shattered a great tumbler all over the carpet.
It has the refrain: "I like the noise of breaking glass."
And though I should not like the glass of Chartres Cathedral to be
broken merely to gratify this taste, I can imagine two types of human
beings who might break it and remain human. A lunatic might do it
because he thought it unChristian to make pictures of the life of Christ;
and a boy might do it because he liked the noise of breaking glass.
So much for the defence of the more dignified Vandal--the Destroyer.
But the new sort of Vandal is much more indefensible.
The crude creative Vandal is much more of a pestilence and a peril.
There is more to be said for the conqueror, who makes a solitude
and calls it peace, than for the other who makes a pandemonium
and calls it progress. For he brands upon the eye in memory
the positive and vivid picture of his own meanness and stupidity.
The barbarians who laid waste the world may have prevailed in so far
that some good things were forgotten, but they did not insist
that their own base and barbarous things should be remembered.
But that is exactly what the "constructive" vulgarian does.
That is exactly what the Modern Vandal does. It is a gloomy pleasure
to think that if a dissolving civilisation brings in forces more
like those of the Ancient Vandals, if vagabond tribes from Asia or
Eastern Europe drift in with the old-world, animal, almost automatic
destructiveness of the Huns or the Bashi-Bazouks, they at least
will wreck and ruin all the new Civilisation without any pretence
of reconstructing it; and that towering and glaring flats, or long
leagues of flashy glass shop-windows, will lie in rubbish-heaps
side by side with better things.
ELIZABETH BARRETT BROWNING
Mrs. Browning was a great poet, and not, as is idly and vulgarly supposed,
only a great poetess. The word poetess is bad English, and it conveys
a particularly bad compliment. Nothing is more remarkable about
Mrs. Browning's work than the absence of that trite and namby-pamby
elegance which the last two centuries demanded from lady writers.
Wherever her verse is bad, it is bad from some extravagance of imagery,
some violence of comparison, some kind of debauch of cleverness.
Her nonsense never arises from weakness, but from a confusion of powers.
If the phrase explain itself, she is far more a great poet than she
is a good one.
Mrs. Browning often appears more luscious and sentimental than
many other literary women, but this was because she was stronger.
It requires a certain amount of internal force to break down.
A complete self-humiliation requires enormous strength,
more strength than most of us possess. When she was writing
the poetry of self-abandonment she really abandoned herself with
the valour and decision of an anchorite abandoning the world.
Such a couplet as--
Our Euripides, the human,
With his dropping of warm tears.
gives to most of us a sickly and nauseous sensation.
Nothing can be well conceived more ridiculous than Euripides going
about dropping tears with a loud splash, and Mrs. Browning coming
after him with a thermometer. But the one emphatic point about this
idiotic couplet is that Mrs. Hemans would never have written it.
She would have written something perfectly dignified,
perfectly harmless, perfectly inconsiderable. Mrs. Browning was
in a great and serious difficulty. She really meant something.
She aimed at a vivid and curious image, and she missed it.
She had that catastrophic and public failure which is as much
as a medal or a testimonial, the badge of the brave.
In spite of the tiresome half-truth that art is unmoral,
the arts require a certain considerable number of moral qualities,
and more especially all the arts require courage. The art
of drawing, for example, requires even a kind of physical courage.
Any one who has tried to draw a straight line and failed knows that
he fails chiefly in nerve, as he might fail to jump off a cliff.
And similarly all great literary art involves the element
of risk, and the greatest literary artists have commonly been
those who have run the greatest risk of talking nonsense.
Almost all great poets rant, from Shakespeare downwards.
Mrs. Browning was Elizabethan in her luxuriance and her audacity,
and the gigantic scale of her wit. We often feel with her as we
feel with Shakespeare, that she would have done better with half
as much talent. The great curse of the Elizabethans is upon her,
that she cannot leave anything alone, she cannot write a single
line without a conceit:
And the eyes of the peacock fans
Winked at the alien glory,
she said of the Papal fans in the presence of the Italian tricolour.
And a royal blood sends glances up her princely eye to trouble.
And the shadow of a monarch's crown is softened in her hair,
is her description of a beautiful and aristocratic lady.
The notion of peacock feathers winking like so many London urchins is
perhaps one of her rather aggressive and outrageous figures of speech.
The image of a woman's hair as the softened shadow of a crown
is a singularly vivid and perfect one. But both have the same
quality of intellectual fancy and intellectual concentration.
They are both instances of a sort of ethereal epigram.
This is the great and dominant characteristic of Mrs. Browning,
that she was significant alike in failure and success.
Just as every marriage in the world, good or bad, is a marriage,
dramatic, irrevocable, and big with coming events, so every one
of her wild weddings between alien ideas is an accomplished fact
which produces a certain effect on the imagination, which has for
good or evil become part and parcel of our mental vision for ever.
She gives the reader the impression that she never declined a fancy,
just as some gentlemen of the eighteenth century never declined a duel.
When she fell it was always because she missed the foothold,
never because she funked the leap.
"Casa Guidi Windows" is, in one aspect, a poem very typical
of its author. Mrs. Browning may fairly be called the peculiar
poet of Liberalism, of that great movement of the first half
of the nineteenth century towards the emancipation of men from
ancient institutions which had gradually changed their nature,
from the houses of refuge which had turned into dungeons,
and the mystic jewels which remained only as letters.
It was not what we ordinarily understand by revolt. It had no hatred
in its heart for ancient and essentially human institutions.
It had that deeply conservative belief in the most ancient
of institutions, the average man, which goes by the name of democracy.
Their ideal, like the ideal of all sensible people, was a chaotic
and confused notion of goodness made up of English primroses
and Greek statues, birds singing in April, and regiments being cut
to pieces for a flag. They were neither Radicals nor Socialists,
but Liberals, and a liberal is a noble and indispensable lunatic
who tries to make a cosmos of his own head.
Mrs. Browning and her husband were more liberal than most Liberals.
Theirs was the hospitality of the intellect and the hospitality
of the heart, which is the best definition of the term.
They never fell into the habit of the idle revolutionists
of supposing that the past was bad because the future was good,
which amounted to asserting that because humanity had never made
anything but mistakes it was now quite certain to be right.
Browning possessed in a greater degree than any other man the power
of realising that all conventions were only victorious revolutions.
He could follow the medieval logicians in all their sowing of the wind
and reaping of the whirlwind with all that generous ardour which is due
to abstract ideas. He could study the ancients with the young eyes
of the Renaissance and read a Greek grammar like a book of love lyrics.
This immense and almost confounding Liberalism of Browning doubtless
had some effect upon his wife. In her vision of New Italy she went back
to the image of Ancient Italy like an honest and true revolutionist;
for all true revolutions are reversions to the natural and the normal.
A revolutionist who breaks with the past is a notion fit for an idiot.
For how could a man even wish for something which he had never heard of?
Mrs. Browning's inexhaustible sympathy with all the ancient and essential
passions of humanity was nowhere more in evidence than in her conception
of patriotism. For some dark reason, which it is difficult indeed
to fathom, belief in patriotism in our day is held to mean principally
a belief in every other nation abandoning its patriotic feelings.
In the case of no other passion does this weird contradiction exist.
Men whose lives are mainly based upon friendship sympathise
with the friendships of others. The interest of engaged couples
in each other is a proverb, and like many other proverbs sometimes
a nuisance. In patriotism alone it is considered correct just
now to assume that the sentiment does not exist in other people.
It was not so with the great Liberals of Mrs. Browning's time.
The Brownings had, so to speak, a disembodied talent for patriotism.
They loved England and they loved Italy; yet they were the very
reverse of cosmopolitans. They loved the two countries as countries,
not as arbitrary divisions of the globe. They had hold of the root
and essence of patriotism. They knew how certain flowers and birds
and rivers pass into the mills of the brain and come out as wars
and discoveries, and how some triumphant adventure or some staggering
crime wrought in a remote continent may bear about it the colour
of an Italian city or the soul of a silent village of Surrey.
THE ERASTIAN ON THE ESTABLISHMENT
Dean Inge is so obviously the most acute, the most cultivated
and the most individual of the sceptical school which he represents,
that there is sometimes inevitably an appearance of singling
him out, when the singularity is only due to his own distinction.
It is due, if we must put it more roughly, to there being so
very few intellectuals of that school who are worth answering.
I have often myself, perhaps, put it more roughly than I intended;
but the double duty involved presents a problem not easily solved.
The trouble is that he is really in such a false position
that the true statement of it sounds itself like a taunt.
Yet it may not be meant for a taunt, but only for a truth.
His own position certainly does not seem as false to him as it
does to us; but to excuse it requires a long explanation which is
impossible in so short an expression. For instance, he wrote
the other day a severe condemnation of those of the Anglican
clergy who favour the Disestablishment of the Church of England.
It may seem curt to retort, as I should be first inclined to do,
that the Dean naturally hesitates to sever the one very slender
strip of red tape that still connects him with Christianity.
Yet it is quite true; and it is not necessarily merely hostile.
To understand the curious case of Dean Inge, in a spirit of
Christian charity, we must leave for the moment all questions
of creed and definition and call up another image before the mind.
It is the image that was in the mind of Matthew Arnold when he openly
said that, being almost an agnostic himself, he yet wished to preserve
the institutions of religion, and especially the literature of religion;
that he found these best preserved in the Church of England
and advised nobody to leave it. We must call up the image of a
historic hierarchy of priests who are also professors, and whose
main business is scholarship and the study of letters; it was not
for nothing that both Arnold and Inge had connections with Oxford.
Most of such men would probably be Christian in hereditary sentiment
and subject-matter; but their Christianity would not, so to speak,
be the point. We can even imagine the institution better if we
think of it as a Confucian rather than a Christian foundation.
The idea of it is a classical culture that is undisturbed. But it has
this further essential point; that if its traditions and rites must
be undisturbed, so also must its doubts and negations be undisturbed.
It must be so traditional that a sceptic is safe there.
Something like this may really have existed in Chinese and other
pagan parallels. Something like it probably did exist among
the last pagan priests of antiquity. A jolly old heathen Flamen
or Pontifex Maximus did not want to be disturbed in explaining away
the gods to his friends; and certainly did not want to make himself
responsible for drawing the exact line between truth and fable
in the metamorphoses of Ovid or the genealogies of Jupiter.
And something of the same sort did exist in the Academic Anglicanism
of the Erastian age in England, when scholarly Whigs and rather
worldly bishops quoted indifferently Horace and Augustine and Gibbon
over the nuts and wine. That is the Establishment which Dean Inge
really likes to see established; that is the civilised institution
which he does really and sincerely believe to be a good thing;
a traditional home of learning and liberal education, though mainly
for the few; a thing that to the outer world shall be as authoritative
as the medieval abbots, but in its inner life be as casual as
the Greek philosophers; a thing that need not exclude the heretical,
but does exclude the ignorant; a thing that can admit all questions
so long as it is never questioned itself.
Now a cultural tradition of that kind can have many marks of dignity
and national value; and a man may without absurdity or falsity
wish to preserve it as a national thing. But there are a number
of conditions to be remembered, which Dean Inge now seems continually
to forget. For one thing, the nation must continue in the same
mood of respect towards the college of professors, or whatever
it is to be called. The modern mood is changing very rapidly;
and I think it would be an exaggeration to say that all England
is now filled with an affection and veneration for Dons.
Another difficulty is that whatever this sort of Chinese synod can do,
it cannot exist side by side with a real and passionate religion.
It was defeated by the Christians at the end of the Roman era.
It was defeated even by the Methodists at the end of the
eighteenth century. It is often quoted of poor Charles II
that he said that Puritanism was no religion for a gentleman.
It is not so often added that he also said that Anglicanism was no
religion for a Christian.
This, I fancy, is what the Dean really means; and it explains why be
is at once such a conservative and such an iconoclast; such a sceptic
and such a Tory. It is not, of course, in so many words what he says.
When driven to defend his bunch of bigwigs, with their libraries
and endowments, he characteristically takes an old book out of those
dusty shelves, and quotes from Burke the thesis that the Church was
only the State seen in one light and the State was only the Church
seen in another light. Burke always struck me as, of all men,
the man with the most imaginative and the most utterly unreal mind.
Even as he uttered such a phrase, he must have known that the Church
was packed with people who did not believe in it, and that
the leaders of the State had almost ceased to pretend to do so.
All the time, it is worth remarking, Burke was gravely discussing
the admission to the Church of Dissenters whose whole enthusiasm
was admittedly concerned with making their Calvinist God if possible
more of a devil than he was before. He knew the world around him
was crowded with such fanatics and with such blasphemers; and yet
he could bring himself to imagine that the actual secular condition
of all England was the Church of Christ, if one only slightly shifted
one's point of view. But it was rather odd to maintain this even
in Burke's time; it is perfectly crazy to maintain it in our time.
Dean Inge admits, that two great calamities might really ruin his plan,
and make the position of the Church of England impossible.
But he thinks that neither is likely enough to be worth considering.
One is--what would happen if a large body of England really
abandoned Christianity? The other is what would happen if England
went over to Rome? The answer to both these impossibilities
is very simple. It is that the second might happen any day,
and the first has happened already.
Of course it is possible to play an endless game with the word "Christian"
and perpetually extend its epoch by perpetually diminishing its meaning.
By the time that everybody has agreed that being a Christian only
means thinking that Christ was a good man, it will indeed be true
that few persons outside lunatic asylums can be denied the name
of Christian. But it is really a mere alteration in the meaning
of a word that prevents us saying frankly that a great mass,
probably a majority, of our modern people are Pagans.
Many of them make a mock of standards of family piety or public
dignity that were generally accepted by the Pagans. But most of them,
if they have any religion at all, have a religion of pantheism or pure
ethics which most of the great Christian characters of history,
Catholic or Protestant would have instantly stamped as pagan.
If you had asked Wesley, or Swedenborg, or Dr. Johnson, or Baxter,
or Luther, they would have called the modern mood heathen
more promptly, if possible, than would Bossuet or Bellarmine.
If it is true that the Church is simply the religion of the State,
we have got precious near to saying that it is simply the irreligion
of the State.
There was a bitter and cynical man (also, I am sure, an Oxford man)
who said, "The Church of England is our last bulwark
against Christianity". This is quite unjust as a description
of the Church of England. But it is not altogether unjust
as a description of Dean Inge. What is really at the back of his
mind is this image of a great academic and cultural tradition,
established as a national need but not specially as a spiritual need.
It is to have religious texts--to criticise; religious ceremonial--
to reform slightly and rather pompously from time to time;
a sort of assumption on religion, in the sense that it could not
tolerate the horrors of anything like the Russian denial of religion.
But all through, it will be subject to one unmistakable test.
It can coexist with Doubt; but it cannot coexist with Faith.
At the end of his article, Dean Inge tries to toss aside as impertinent
the term Erastianism; the term is too obviously true not to irritate.
But in any case he absurdly underrates its meaning at the moment.
It is not a question of whether those who form a nation by being
Englishmen could in the abstract form a religion by being Anglicans.
It is a question of whether a Church which does at least exist,
with some who belong to it and some who do not belong to it,
should be ruled by those who do not belong to it.
Erastianism exists today in the perfectly practical sense
that any Jew, Holy Roller or Hyde Park atheist may dictate
what that Christian Church shall do on any matter whatever,
however intimate and sacred. Bradlaugh was a Member of Parliament;
he might well have become a Cabinet Minister and appointed Bishops.
Mr. Saklatvala was a Socialist leader and might quite well
be a Labour Minister, with a majority in the House and might
by Act of Parliament make the Prayer Book anything he chose.
That is State Establishment, as now universally understood;
that is what Dean Inge desires and presumably defends; or must set
about the delicate task of defending.
THE END OF THE MODERNS
All schools of thought, moderate or revolutionary or reactionary,
are agreed that the future is full of new possibilities or perils,
that the various forms of revolt in art or thought are the
beginning of big changes, and especially that certain geniuses,
creative or destructive, have opened the gates of a new world.
The Communist may think they are the gates of heaven,
or the Conservative that they are the gates of hell. But both
substantially agree that they mark not only the end of the world,
but the beginning of another world. The modern writers who have been
hailed alternatively as dynamic or demoniac are, for good or evil,
but the forerunners of others yet more dynamic or more demoniac.
Both sides are heartily agreed about this; and I have the misfortune
to disagree with both of them.
I think the first fact about what may roughly be called Futurism is that
it has no future. It has still a very lively and interesting present.
Indeed, it has already a picturesque and romantic past. The life
of D. H. Lawrence, for instance, has already become a mere legend,
which might be of any antiquity; and the romantic and rather
sentimental glamour that has already gathered about him is now quite
as distant and diffused as that which gathered round Byron or Burns.
As for the present, no period could be entirely dull when
Mr. Aldous Huxley was writing in it; but it is significant to notice
what he writes. In Brave New World he shows that however grimly
he may enjoy the present, he already definitely hates the future.
And I only differ from him in not believing that there is any such
future to hate.
I take these two names as typical of what has been called
in the last decade modernity or revolt; but the thesis I would
seriously suggest covers something larger and perhaps simpler.
The revolutionary elements in our epoch do not mark the beginning,
but the end, of an epoch of revolution. I should hesitate to describe
a number of distinguished and often honest literary gentlemen as Dregs;
or I would have given that short and convenient title to this article.
I prefer to put the same meaning, or even the same metaphor,
into the words of a revolutionary poet (whose present unpopularity
is enough to show how insecure is the future of revolutionary poetry)
and while I drink to the memory of Lawrence or the health of Huxley,
murmur the words:
All thine the last wine that I pour is
The last in the chalice I drain.
That will suggest the same idea in less offensive language.
In short, it is doubtless true, in the words of Mr. Jefferson Brick
(that pioneer of revolt), that the Libation of Freedom must
sometimes be quaffed in Blood; but whether it be in blood or wine,
that cup is very nearly dry.
My reason for thinking this has nothing to do with likes or dislikes
or the wish being father to the thought; it is the sort of logic
that is more like mathematics or chess. To almost all the modern
moral and metaphysical systems, as stated by the moderns themselves,
I should be content to add the comment, "Mate in three moves."
That is, these thinkers have landed themselves in positions which are
already doomed by the laws of thought; or, to change the mathematical
to the military figure, their positions are outflanked, their
communications cut and their ammunition very obviously running short.
In many cases, their form of revolt is one that can only be a sort
of temporary formation.
Merely to explain what I mean, I will take an extremely crude and
even clumsy example first. It does not touch the more distinguished
types I have mentioned; but it does show in a very clear and plain
shape the sense in which such things are intrinsically fugitive.
I mean what may be called the literary use of blasphemy. Earlier, when
the spirit of revolt was younger, it was used by some men of genius;
by Swinburne, in whose work it seems now to have entirely lost its sting.
Recently a modern writer, actually appointed to make a special study
of Swinburne, asked wearily how anybody could get excited about
the verses which said that the Galilean also would go down to the dead.
It also disturbed the fine literature and very confused cosmic
philosophy of Thomas Hardy, who tried to say (at the same time)
that God did not exist, and that He ought to be ashamed of existing;
or possibly that He ought to be ashamed of not existing.
This irritable profanity, which is already rather stale among
cultivated people, is apparently still quite fresh to the Communists;
but that is because Bolshevist Russia is the most backward State
in Europe. It is even said that attempts were made to print atheistic
assertions on match-boxes and sell them in England as propaganda.
If it is true, they must have a very queer idea of England,
to suppose that its somewhat too inert populace could be roused
to universal civil war by bad language printed on a match-box.
But the only point here is that this sort of bad language,
like all bad language, necessarily weakens itself by use.
The literature of atheism is bound to fail, exactly in proportion
as it succeeds. The Bolshevists have not merely tried to abolish God,
which some think a trick needing some ingenuity. They have tried
to make an institution of the abolition of God; and when the God
is abolished, the abolition is abolished. There can never be any
future for the literature of blasphemy; for if it fails, it fails;
and if it succeeds, it becomes a literature of respectability.
In short, all that sort of effect can only be an instantaneous effect;
like smashing a valuable vase that cannot be smashed again.
The heaven-defying gesture can only be impressive as a last gesture.
Blasphemy is by definition the end of everything, including
the blasphemer. The wife of Job saw the common sense of this,
when she instinctively said, "Curse God and die." The modern poet,
by some thoughtless oversight, so often neglects to die.
This is a very crude and popular instance; but it exactly defines
what I mean when I say that all these death-dealing dynamic motions
carry the seeds of their own death. And when we turn to the more
subtle and suggestive writers, such as those I have named,
we shall find that this is exactly their own condition.
They are not opening the gates either of heaven or hell;
they are in a blind-alley, at the end of which there is no door.
They are always philosophising and they have no philosophy.
They have not reached that reality, that reason of things, or even
that fully realised unreason of things, for which they are obviously
and indeed avowedly seeking. But, what is here more to the point,
they do not (like the old revolutionists) even know the direction
in which they are to seek it. They have failed to discover,
not only any purpose in the world, but even any purpose in the will.
They are witty, brilliant and fashionable bankrupts.
They have come to an end; and they have not come to an End.
The earlier rebels were happy in being pioneers of the actual
forward movements of their time; as Walt Whitman, axe in hand,
walked before the actual march of industrial democracy.
But Mr. Aldous Huxley can hardly be roused by the word Democracy.
D. H. Lawrence, on the other hand, could be roused by
the word Industrialism.
So far as that is concerned, the case is simple enough. Lawrence, whom so
many moderns have made a sort of test of modernity, was in fact in violent
revolt against anything and everything that can be called modern.
He did not merely hate industrial machinery and the servile
society it has produced. He hated practically all the effects
of science and public education and even political progress.
All that is very right and proper; but he also hated intellectualism
along with industrialism; though why anybody should think
industrialism particularly intellectual, I cannot imagine.
But he was perfectly right in his revolt against these things;
only they are all in their very nature modern or very recent things.
He himself was in favour of very ancient things, and notably of one of
the most ancient things on the earth, the worship of the earth itself;
the Great Mother: Demeter. But he could not, by his own admission,
even do this, without almost literally cutting off his own head.
It may be regarded, in a thinker, as at least equivalent
to cutting his own throat. He confessed himself, in effect,
that he could only worship Demeter from the neck downwards.
He could only do it by setting the subconsciousness against
the consciousness, or in other words, the dreams against the daylight.
It is surely a remarkable gospel for an age of realism.
In a famous passage he wrote, "In my dark heart gods are,"
but added that in his "white mind" they were not, having been
washed or whitewashed out by elementary education. But the modern
educated mind is not white; it is only pale.
The point is that from every point of view, ancient or modern,
his solution is not a solution. A man cannot leave his head at home
and send his body dancing through the world and doing as it likes;
and there is no earthly reason for supposing that it will do
what it ought, from a modern or any other point of view.
For instance, if it fancies food, it will steal, and it will steal
quite as readily from Communist Stores as from private houses.
This is not the beginning of a new life; a gorgeous jungle opening
before man as a sort of Mowgli. It is the end of an utterly
impossible argument, which cannot be carried any further.
A man wallowing in the earth with the animals would not be an animal.
He would only be a lunatic; which is the exact opposite of an animal.
There was no way out of the intellectual or anti-intellectual
impasse into which Lawrence had got himself; except the third road
which he never thought of . . . possibly because it leads to Rome.
If mere rationalism is insufficient, we must get above the reason
and not below it. The direct appeal to Nature is utterly unnatural.
I admit it was weakly conceded by the Pantheists of the first
revolutionary phase; now very remote; and many who would
pass for pious accepted it. Professor Babbitt has pointed
out some of the dangerous concessions in Wordsworth.
Another even more orthodox writer expressed the error of that period.
He said that we must rise through Nature up to Nature's God.
He was wrong. We must descend from God down to God's Nature.
Nature is only right when seen in the light of the highest right;
whether it be, as some Humanists would say, in the mind of Man,
or as Christians would say, in the mind of God. But they really believe
in their God; and Lawrence did not really believe in his Goddess.
He passionately disbelieved in everything, except something
in which he could not really believe.
Mr. Aldous Huxley, whom I have taken as the other outstanding
talent of that time, sees this impossibility and avoids it.
But he can only avoid it by cutting down his own standard to
something so thin that it can hardly stand. In one of his novels
a character sums up much of the general teaching of the author,
by saying that Man must not hope to be either an animal or an angel.
He adds, significantly, that it is a tight-rope sort of business.
Now walking on a tight-rope is both difficult and dangerous;
and the author makes the good life really more difficult than it is
for an ascetic. He has not only to avoid being an animal, but he must
guard against any unlucky accident that might turn him into an angel.
That is, he is forbidden to have the enthusiasms and spiritual
ambitions that have sustained the saints, and yet he has got to
become in cold blood something much more exceptional than a saint.
Nobody asks such a realist as Mr. Huxley to idealise the real.
But such a realist must surely know that human nature cannot show,
at every instant, the valour and vigilance of a spiritual
tight-rope walker, cannot suffer more for this ideal than all
the heroes, and yet be forbidden even to idealise its own ideal.
The plan of life is simply obviously unworkable; where the plans
of the wildest mystics and martyrs have proved workable.
I say that I do not abhor these men as the first figures
of an advancing anarchist army. On the contrary, I admire
these men as the last figures of a defeated anarchist army.
I take these two original and forcible writers as types of many others;
but the point is that they are not, like the anarchists of history,
at the head of an army marching in a determined direction.
That is exactly what they are not. Lawrence rushed out against
almost everything; Huxley, being more sensitive, recoils from
almost everything. But, however valuable be the vivid description
of the one or the sharp criticism of the other, they are not
valuable as guides; and certainly not as guides to a revolution.
They had not the simplification given either by religion or irreligion.
There was something grand about D. H. Lawrence groping blindly
in the dark; but he really was in the dark, not only about the Will
of God, but about the will of D. H. Lawrence. He was ready
to go anywhere; but he did not really know where to go next.
Aldous Huxley is ideally witty; but he is at his wit's end.
Now of course there are numberless copyists and followers calling
themselves revolutionary, who would say that they knew where to go;
simply because they are content with some conventional word
like Communism. For Communism is almost the same word as convention;
it means people getting "together", and nothing else.
But that very fact illustrates what I say, when I say
that the army is short of ammunition and the end is near.
When the great democratic movement began, it was supported by real
democratic emotions. Only Comradeship can be the soul of Communism;
for otherwise it has no soul. But the more we note the actual temper
of the new rebels, the more we shall note that all that is gone.
The men who call themselves Communists are not Comrades.
Their tone is bitterly individualistic, and bitterly critical.
When Walt Whitman looked at a crowd, it is really true to say
that he loved the crowd. When a modern poet, imitating the free
verse of Whitman (which was the least free thing about him),
describes a crowd, it is always to describe his disgust with the crowd.
They have none of the natural sentiments that would correspond with
their unnatural dogmas. In other words, the army is short of powder,
short of passion, short of the primary impulses that make such an
army act. For they are not a vanguard advancing, they are the end
of a revolutionary adventure, both for good and evil, which began
more than a hundred years ago; and they are fighting the rearguard
action of a retreat. Liberty, Equality and Fraternity really meant
something to the emotions of those who first used the phrase.
But Fraternity is the last emotion anyone is likely to find in an acrid
article or poem by a modern rebel; Liberty is lost in both systems,
old and new; and Equality only remains in the form of a dull
attempt at uniformity, copied from that very mechanical capitalism
which the rebels would reject.
Along with those who accept the thing as a label, or hope
fallaciously that they may accept it as a fashion, there are some
who accept it in a more noble but very negative way; for the very
reasons I have urged in this article. I mean that they accept
it desperately, as the only way out of an intellectual impasse.
It is not too much to say that Mr. Middleton Murry accepts
Soviets with the gestures of a great heathen accepting suicide.
He seems to exult in the thought of it being the end of everything,
or at least the end of nearly everything he likes. That is yet
another example of the psychology I have attempted to describe;
the psychology of men who have come to the end. I do not want to confuse
this distinct impression with jaded journalistic talk about pessimism.
People will call Mr. Aldous Huxley a pessimist; in the sense of one
who makes the worst of it. To me he is that far more gloomy character;
the man who makes the best of it. He gives the best advice he can;
in conditions of converging impossibility. I do not write
here in a hostile spirit about any of these recent realistic
or revolutionary writers; on the contrary, I sincerely sympathise
with them, because, unlike the earlier revolutionists, they know they
are in an intellectual hole. Doubtless, there are thousands of gay
and buoyant innovators, who are not intelligent enough to know it.
But the same plan of defeat is spread over the whole situation.
It can be seen, for instance, in the thousands of thoughtless "sexual"
novels, the writers of which are evidently unconscious that they have
got into a logical contradiction about the whole position of sex.
They inherit the notion that sex is a serious crux and crisis;
for indeed this is necessary to the very nature of a novel.
In this they are living on the last legacy of Romanticism;
which, in its turn, was living on the last legacy of religion.
But their new and simple philosophy teaches them that sex is
only the sort of necessity that is also a triviality; that sex
is no more crucial than smoking. So that the modern novelist,
torn between two ideas, has to attempt to write a story about a man
who smokes twenty cigarettes and tries to think that each of them
is a crisis. In all these things there is an intellectual tangle;
the sort of thing that eventually tightens and throttles.
Of this sort of philosopher it is exactly and literally true
to say that, if you give him rope enough, he will hang himself.
It is consoling to reflect that suicide holds a sublime place
in his philosophy.
WALTER DE LA MARE It has not always been sufficiently understood
that a critic of poetry should be a poetical critic.
Literary history is littered with the disasters of good critics
who become bad critics, merely by colliding with good poets.
But one of the first facts which a good poetical critic will realise,
is one which the poet of necessity realises: the limitation of language,
and especially the poverty and clumsiness of the language of praise.
There is hardly any praise of poets that does not sound
as if they were all the same sort of poets, and this is true
even when the praise is intended to say precisely the opposite.
Thus the habit of calling somebody "unique" has become universal,
and we may insist that a man is original, and still leave the impression
that originality is about as rare as original sin.
But this difficulty applies in a special way to Mr. Walter de la
Mare and his poetry, because the common poetical terms of praise for
that poetry are also applied to a totally different sort of poetry.
He stands very close, in time and place and appearance,
to a group of writers, most of them good writers and some of them
great writers, from whom he is really quite free and distinct.
Only the epithets applied to him are also applied to them.
When we say that he is a dreamy and fantastic poet, an interpreter
of elfland, a singer of strange rhymes that have a witchery
and wild charm for children, and the rest, we are driven to use
a number of terms that have now become a little trite, perhaps,
as applied to other talented persons who are utterly different.
The fountains, the foundations, the primary principles of
imagination and the view of life, are really quite different
in a man like Mr. de la Mare from all that they are, let us say,
in a man like Sir James Barrie or a man like Mr. A. A. Milne.
This, I need hardly say, has nothing to do with depreciating
these authors, but only with appreciating each author for his own sake.
Yet there is a sort of tangle of tradition, and a recognised
traffic in certain subjects, which may well confuse a modern
reader about all this sort of literature of fancy. For instance;
we might start by saying that the tradition of Treasure Island
and its pirates was continued in Peter Pan and its pirates.
We might say that the elvish children of Peter Pan were
continued in the elvish children of When We Were Very Young.
And then we might imagine vaguely that all this sort of thing,
the bottle of rum and the crocodile's dinner and the king's breakfast,
were all somehow stuffed or stirred up together in a hotch-potch called
Peacock Pie. But this is to miss the whole point about the poet,
and especially where he is rather more than a poet. It would be easy
to link him up with the tradition of Treasure Island; for he has
himself written a very fascinating fantasia about Desert Islands.
But the association would be an error, for he has not really laid
up for himself treasure in the same sort of treasure islands.
There is really a sort of dynasty, a Scottish dynasty, of Stevenson
and Barrie. But it descended on the infantile side to Scots like
Kenneth Graham and on the manly, or at least boyish side to Scots
like John Buchan. It has nothing to do with Walter de la Mare;
because his philosophy is different. One way of putting it would
be to say that, poetic as are the fairy-tales of the Scots,
they are the fairy-tales of the Sceptics. The fairy-tales
of de la Mare are not those of the Sceptic but of the Mystic.
Take the primary idea with which all the best work for imaginative
infancy, as supplied by Stevenson and Barrie, really began.
It began with an idea which is called "make-believe". That is,
strictly speaking, it is written by men who do not believe;
and even written for children who do not believe;
children who quite logically and legitimately make believe.
But de la Mare's world is not merely a world of illusion;
it is in quite another sense a world of imagination. It is a real
world of which the reality can only be represented to us by images.
De la Mare does not, in the material sense, believe that there is
an ogre who crawls round houses and is turned back by the influence
of the Holy Child; any more than Barrie believes that there is
an immortal little boy who plays physically in Kensington Gardens.
But de la Mare does believe that there is a devouring
evil that is always warring with innocence and happiness;
and Barrie does not believe that innocence and happiness go on
having an uninterrupted legal occupation of Kensington Gardens.
Stories of the school of Peter Pan are radiant and refreshing dreams;
but they are dreams. They are the dreams of somebody taking
refuge from real life in an inner life of the imagination;
but not necessarily of somebody believing that there is also
a larger universal life corresponding to that imagination.
The first is a fabulist but the second is a symbolist; as if we
were to compare the talking animals of La Fontaine with the typical
animals of Blake. Blake (though certainly mad in a quiet way)
probably did not believe that golden lions and tigers walked
about on the hills of Albion; and La Fontaine did not believe
that garrulous lions engaged in chatty conversation with foxes.
But Blake did believe that certain tremendous truths, only to be shown
under the types of golden lions, were really true; and, what is
most important of all, were not only within him, but beyond him.
So the conversation of Mr. Milne's funny little pigs and bears is
as delightful as La Fontaine, and only deceptive in the same sense as
La Fontaine. That is to say, it is not false, because it is fictitious;
or what was called fabulous. But the rhymes of the Mad Prince,
though they would be called fantastic, are not merely fabulous.
The Mad Prince, like the Mad Poet, in the person of poor Blake, is,
after all, something essentially different from The Mad Hatter.
There are hollow undertones in his queer questions, about green grass
for graves, which do really re-echo from things deep and secret
as the grave.
Many who remember the apparently nonsensical nursery rhymes which
figure among Walter de la Mare's verses for children may imagine
that I am drawing a fine distinction; but it is not a distinction
of degree but of direction. The parrot and the monkey who attended
the dwarfs on the Isle of Lone, may seem quite as disconnected from
normal natural history as the owl and the pussy-cat who went to sea.
But there remains a real distinction, outside all natural history,
between unnatural history and supernatural history. Mr. de la Mare's
parrots and monkeys are as symbolical as the strange beasts in the Book
of Apocalypse. Only they are symbolical in a sense that means something
better than the allegorical. Symbolism is superior to allegory,
in so far that the symbol exactly fits; and there is therefore no
superfluous explanation that needs to pass through ordinary language,
or need be, or indeed can be, translated into other words.
If a parrot only means speech, or a monkey only means mischief
(as he generally does) then nothing beyond pictorial elegance
is gained by not dealing directly with mischief, or speaking
plainly about speech. And the mere allegory never gets beyond
a pictorial elegance, adorning what might well be unadorned.
But the great mystic can sometimes present to us a purple parrot
or a sea-green monkey, in exactly such a manner as to suggest
submerged or mysterious ideas, and even truths, that could not
possibly be conveyed by any other creature of any other colour.
The meaning fits the symbol and the symbol the meaning; and we cannot
separate them from each other, as we can in the analysis of allegory.
And there is a side of spiritual life, so to speak, which might well
be represented by sea-green monkeys, whose colouring is not merely
arbitrary colouring like that of the mysterious monsters in that admirable
but purely nonsensical rhyme about the Jumblies, whose heads were
green and whose hands were blue. The colour scheme here is pleasing,
but it is no disrespect to the great Mr. Lear of the Nonsense Rhymes,
to say that his cosmic philosophy would not have been convulsed
even if their hands had been green and their heads had been blue.
Walter de la Mare's nonsense is never nonsensical in that sense.
If his monkey is sea-green, it is for some reason as deep
and significant as the sea; even though he cannot express it
in any other way except by patient and uncomplaining greenness.
And he would never mention even a green weed, a dock or nettle in a ditch,
without meaning it to bear the same witness in the same way.
It is the first paradox about him that we can find the evidence of his
faith in his consciousness of evil. It is the second paradox that we
can find the spiritual springs of much of his poetry in his prose.
If we turn, for instance, to that very powerful and even terrible
short story called Seaton's Aunt, we find we are dealing directly
with the diabolic. It does so in a sense quite impossible in all
the merely romantic or merely ironic masters of that nonsense that is
admittedly illusion. There was no nonsense about Seaton's Aunt.
There was no illusion about her concentrated and paralysing malignity;
but it was a malignity that had an extension beyond this world.
She was a witch; and the realisation that witches can occasionally exist
is a part of Realism, and a test for anyone claiming a sense of Reality.
For we do not especially want them to exist; but they do.
Now the wonderland of the other charmers of childhood consists
entirely of things that we want to exist or they want to exist.
Whether they are of the older English or Victorian school of
Lewis Carroll and Lear, or of the later Scottish school of Stevenson
and Barrie, their whole aim is to create a sort of cosmos within
the cosmos, which shall be free from evil; a crystal sphere
in which there shall be no cracks or flaws or clouds of evil.
Peter Pan is a wonderful evocation of the happy daydreams of childhood.
There is plenty of fighting and ferocity; because fighting
and ferocity are among the very happiest dreams of a really
innocent and Christian childhood. But Captain Hook the Pirate
is not really wicked; he is only ferocious; which, after all,
it is his simple duty as an honest and industrious pirate to be.
But there are rhymes, even nursery rhymes, of Walter de la Mare in which
the shiver is a real shiver, not only of the spine but of the spirit.
They have an atmosphere which is not merely thrilling, but also chilling.
They lay a finger that is not of the flesh on a nerve that is
not of the body; in their special way of suggesting the chill
of change or death or antiquity. To do this was against the whole
purpose and origin of the fairyland of the later Victorians.
Like all literature, it cannot really be understood without reference
to history; and, like all history, it cannot really be understood
without reference to religion. As scepticism gradually dried up
the conventional religion of the English, and even of the Scotch,
poetic and humane spirits turned more and more to the construction of an
inner world of fancy, that should be both a refuge and a substitute.
William Morris, one of the most large and humane of these later
Victorians, admitted it in acknowledging the purely decorative
vision in his own work:
So with this earthly Paradise it is,
If you will read aright and pardon me
Who strive to build a shadowy isle of bliss
Midmost the beating of the steely sea.

And it is the irony of the case that these men, who were rationalists
and realists about the real world, were for that very reason resolved
to be radiant optimists when once they were inside the city of dreams
which was their city of refuge. The pessimists insisted on having
happy dreams; the sceptics insisted on having omnipotent drugs.
But the mystic does not deal in dreams but in visions; that is,
in things seen and not seeming. The mystic does not desire drugs
but the drinking of that wine that wakes the dead; different in nature
from any opiate that soothes the living.
In short, we may say that the early twentieth century presented two
movements towards the fanciful or fantastical, and away from the merely
rational or material: a centripetal movement and a centrifugal movement.
The one spiritual spiral worked inwards, towards the secret
subjective dreams of man; the other worked outwards towards
the spiritual powers or truths that seemed beyond the reach of man.
The new world made by the first was the great, glowing, iridescent bubble
of the Barrie daydream; the world revealed by the second was that world
of strange skies, at the ends of the earth and the corners of the sea,
that appears in the far-off flashes of the de la Mare imagination.
We might say shortly that Stevenson and Barrie could produce grisly
buccaneers dripping with gore without frightening the children;
whereas de la Mare could produce pollarded willows or whitewashed
barns with an imminent risk of frightening the children, and even
the grownup people. But it is only fair to say that there is a
subtlety only possible to the first method, as well as a subtlety
possible to the second. It is, as has been already suggested,
the subtlety of an irony which at once accepts and discounts illusion.
It is the whole point of the best work of Barrie, for instance,
that somebody is deceiving himself, but also that somebody is
looking on at somebody who is deceiving himself; and if they are
both deceiving themselves, so much the better for the third person
who is looking on from a third angle. Much of this sort of work
is like a world of mirrors reflected in mirrors; the reduplication
of reflection; the shadow of a shade. To name but one instance:
a fairy-tale palace is itself only a fancy; but the court scene
in A Kiss for Cinderella is not merely the fairy-tale fancy,
but a child's fancy about the fancy. This sort of intensive
imaginative delicacy is in theory a thing of infinite possibilities;
and this does belong to the merely subjective school of symbolism.
But what I have called the truly symbolic school of symbolism does still
belong altogether to another and, I cannot but think, a larger world.
It is all that world of the powers and mysteries beyond mankind which
even the sceptic would consent to cover with the celebrated label:
"Important, If True". Perhaps as good an example as can be found is
in that truly extraordinary sketch by de la Mare called "The Tree".
I can imagine multitudes of quite intelligent people totally
unable to make head or tail of it. It is concerned with a fruit
merchant and his brother, who was an artist, and with a Tree,
which is talked of in a manner utterly indescribable; as if it were
not only more important than anything, but were outside the world.
Now Barrie might have dealt admirably with a theme like that;
and probably made the human comedy clearer. But the difference
is precisely this. Even the reader who cannot understand anything
else about de la Mare's story does definitely understand this:
that somehow the fruit merchant was wrong, and the artist was right;
and, above all, the Tree was right. Now if Barrie had told the tale,
he would have taken a gentle pride in leaving us in doubt on that
very point; of suggesting that the sceptic might be the sane man,
and the Tree might be a delusion. But the Tree is not a delusion.
THE MEANING OF METRE
Did Bret Harte imitate Swinburne? Or (more pleasing thought)
did Swinburne imitate Bret Harte? Did Swinburne wrestle in spirit
with the admirable poem called "The Heathen Chinee", and then start up
from his reading inspired and inflamed to write the great Greek tragedy
of "Atalanta in Calydon"? To some academic and pedantic minds I know
that this will not appear an exact literary comparison; though it
covers a small point that may be called a curiosity of literature.
To them it will sound as if I suggested that John Ruskin was
merely a plagiarist of Josh Billings. Anyhow, it is a rather
curious coincidence that there is one particular poetical metre,
consisting of a quatrain and one long line at the end,
which is found nowhere else in all literature, so far as I know,
except in the finest and most tragic chorus of Swinburne's Atalanta
and in the poem of the Heathen Chinee. It would be possible
to get quite a pleasing poetical effect by interleaving the verses
of the one with the verses of the other and thus producing a complete
and continuous poem, all to the same beautiful tune and combining
(as only the greatest masterpieces can do) the qualities of
the humanist and the humorist; the elements of the grave and gay.
There is no space here to weave the whole of the two narratives together;
but a verse or two will show that they move with the same melody
in the same metre.
0 would that with feet
Unsandaled, unshod,
Over-bold, over-fleet,
I had swum not nor trod
From Arcadia to Calydon northward a blast of the envy
of God.
Which expressions are strong,
Yet would feebly imply
Some account of a wrong
Not to call it a lie
That was worked upon William my pardner, and the same
being W. Nye.

It may be urged maliciously, by the unmelodious, that the identity


is a mere accident of arrangement on the page; since the long line
could be divided or the short lines linked up. But this is not true.
That last long rolling line is really unique, like a wave sweeping
away all that went before. And the moral is that metre is not
artificial but elemental; it is smooth like Niagara. That long
rushing line does express the sea-worship of Swinburne; that long
meandering line does express the detached lucidity of Truthful James.
Since then, writers have broken writing to bits to make it explosive.
The other Truthful James--I allude to Henry James--began it
with a shower of commas; the more modern poets are quite capable
of keeping the commas and leaving out the words. Others would make
an explosion, or at least a noise, by some line like, "Burst. Blast.
Burst-Blast back-blasted. Bang!" But it is not really even so noisy
as a line like, "Where the thundering Bosphorus answers the thunder
of Pontic seas"; because it somehow suggests, not a natural noise that
cannot be stopped, but an artificial noise that actually is stopped,
if only by full stops. Metre is more natural than free verse;
because it has more of the movement of nature, and the curves
of wind and wave.
CONCERNING A STRANGE CITY
Everyone has his own private and almost secret selection among
the examples of the mysterious power of words, the power which a certain
verbal combination has over the emotions and even over the soul.
It is a commonplace that literature sometimes has a charm, not merely
in the sense of the charm of a woman, but of the charm of a witch.
Historical scholars question how the ignorant imagination
of the Dark Ages distorted the poet Virgil into a magician;
and one answer to the question, possibly, is that he was one.
Theologians and philosophers debate about the inspiration of scripture;
but perhaps the most philosophical argument, for certain scriptural
sayings being inspired, is simply that they sound like it.
The great lines of the poets are like landscapes or visions;
but the same strange light can be found not only in the high places
of poetry but in quite obscure corners of prose. And, in my own
personal case, there are no words in literature that more directly
produce this indescribable effect than a few that appear,
almost accidentally, in one episode of Malory's romance of Arthur.
They occur in one of the visions of Sir Galahad; or it may be
Sir Percivale, for the rest of the scene has rather faded from my memory,
save for the constellation of words that shines in the midst of it.
But I think that St. Joseph of Arimathea shows the knight a vision
of a veiled object; presumably the Holy Grail. And he adds
the sentence: "But you shall see it unveiled in the city of Sarras,
in the spiritual place."
The soul of this, of course, escapes analysis; but for all that,
an attempt at analysis has certain aspects of interest.
I can only express what I mean by saying that it is the finite
part of the image that really suggests infinity. Most worthy
and serious people, instead of saying the spiritual place,
would say the spiritual world. Some dismal and disgusting people,
instead of saying the spiritual place, would say the spiritual plane.
And the immediate chill and disenchantment of these changes is due to a
vague but vivid sense that the spiritual thing has become less real.
A world sounds like an astronomical diagram, and a plane sounds
like a geometrical diagram; and both these are abstractions.
But a place is not an abstraction, but an actuality.
And the writer not only says definitely that it is a place,
but he gives it a definite name like the name of a place.
Sarras is not an abstraction; it is not even an allegory.
It is not even as if he had said the City of Heaven or the City
of Paradise. These, though not unreal, are at least universal.
But the name given has identity, which is something much more
intense than universality. Sarras only means Sarras, as Sarum only
means Sarum, or (for that matter) as Surbiton only means Surbiton.
But the very fact that we have never heard of it before, and that
it is never mentioned again, that it is referred to in passing
and without explanation, gives a curious intensity to the hint
of something at once distant and definite. The spiritual thrill
is all in the idea that the place is a place, however spiritual;
that it is some strange spot where the sky touches the earth,
or where eternity contrives to live on the borderland of time and space.
I wish there were a real philosophy of comparative religion,
and one that was not full of inhuman nonsense. I wish it did
not tend to one particular trick of unreason, as for instance
when Mr. Wells says that the Christian sacrament of bread
and wine was a break-back to primitive blood sacrifices.
Or sometimes a man will say that the feeling about a Madonna is only
the revival of the worship of Isis, or that the idea of St. Michael
smiting Satan is the same as that about Mithras who slew a bull.
Now there are many other more historical objections to this sort
of thing, but my primary objection to it is that it not only puts
the cart before the horse, but gives me directions for finding my own
horse in my own stable, by looking for a primitive Mycenaean chariot
of which no traces remain. Instead of explaining x by saying it is
equal to 5, it undertakes to explain 5 by saying it is equal to x.
It is as if a man said, "You may not be aware that your feelings
about your wife are best described as those of the Missing Link at
the sight of an oyster shell." I know what a Christian feels about
the idea that Michael smote a rebel angel. I do not in the least know
what a Mithraist felt about the idea that Mithras killed a bull.
It may really have been something like the Christian feeling,
for all I know; it may also have been the worst sort of heathen feeling,
for all I know. But to have the thing that I do know explained
to me by the thing that I don't know, is like nonsense out of Alice
in Wonderland. It is offering something inexplicable to explain
something that needs no explanation. I cannot tell whether
anybody really felt anything about Isis comparable to what men
feel about Mary; if anybody did, I am sure I congratulate him.
But I decline to have my own feelings revealed to myself, in the light
of some remote alleged feelings that no man alive has ever felt.
But though there is this abyss of agnosticism between dead faiths
and living ones, and between religions that are experienced and
religions that are only explored, it might be possible to establish
some human connection if the people who did it were more human.
If they took the simple things that really are similar, instead of merely
trying to assimilate the civilised things to the barbaric things,
they might really bridge some of those abysses in the name
of the brotherhood of men. If they were not so anxious to say
that the sacrament and the sacrifice were both cannibal orgies
(which is nonsense) they might say that they were both sacrifices,
and had something to do with the philosophy of sacrifice,
which is sense. And then, instead of having less respect for
the Christians, we might have more respect for the cannibals.
If they were not so anxious to compare the Virgin to a heathen goddess,
they might possibly compare them both to a human mother, and at
least get near to something human, if not to something divine.
And in the same way, if they were not so eager to compare a shrine
or a sacred soil to fetishism and taboo, they might get some sort
of glimpse of what all men mean by making a deity local, or talking
of a spiritual place.
At least in the mind of man, if not in the nature of things,
there seems to be some connection between concentration and reality.
When we want to ask, in natural language, whether a thing
really exists or not, we ask if it is really "there" or not.
We say "there", even if we do not clearly understand where.
A man cannot enter a house by five doors at once; he might do it
if he were an atmosphere; but he does not want to be an atmosphere.
He has a stubborn subconscious belief that an animal is greater than
an atmosphere. In proportion as a thing rises in the scale of things,
it tends to localise and even narrow its natural functions.
A man cannot absorb his sustenance through all his pores
like a sponge or some low sea-organism; he cannot take
in an atmosphere of beef or an abstract essence of buns.
Any buns thrown at him, as at the bear at the zoo, must be
projected with such skill as to hit a particular hole in his head.
In nature, in a sense, there is choice even before there is will;
the plant or bulb narrows itself and pierces at one place rather
than another; and all growth is a pattern of such green wedges.
But however it be with these lower things, there has always been
this spearlike selection and concentration in man's conception
of higher things. And compared with that there is something
not only vague but vulgar in most of the talk about infinity.
The pantheist is right up to a certain point, but so is the sponge.
Both vitally and verbally, this infinity is the enemy of all that
is fine. Such philological points are sometimes more than mere
pedantries or mere puns. And it is more than a pedantic pun to say
that most things that are fine are finite. We testify to it when we
talk of a beautiful thing having refinement or having finish.
It is brought to an end like the blade of a beautiful sword;
not only to its end in the sense of its cessation but to its
end in the sense of its aim. All fine things are in this
sense finished, even when they are eternal. Poetry is committed
to this concentration fully as much as religion; for fairyland
has always been as local, one might say as parochial, as Heaven.
And if religion in the recognised sense were removed tomorrow,
the poets would only begin to act as the pagans acted.
They would begin to say, "Lo, here", and "Lo, there", from the
incurable itch of the idea that the something must be somewhere,
and not merely anywhere. Even if it were in some sense found to be
in everything, it would still be in everything and not merely in all.
And if men did indeed seek the secret in primitive sacrifices,
it was a secret and not a superficiality like fetish-worship. If
they did indeed look for it behind the veil of Isis, it was a secret
and not a platitude like nature-worship. And if indeed it is better
sought in another fashion, it will be a secret, and therefore a
real revelation, for those who see it unveiled in the city of Sarras,
in the spiritual place.
THE EPITAPH OF PIERPONT MORGAN
It is obvious enough that whitewashing a man is quite the opposite
of washing him white. The curious thing is that people often
try to whitewash a man, and fail, when it might be possible
to wash him, and to some limited extent, succeed. The real story,
if the culprit only had the courage to tell it, would often be
much more human and pardonable than the stiff suspicious fiction
that he tells instead. Many a public man, I fancy, has tried
to conceal the crime and only succeeded in concealing the excuse.
Many a man has sought to bury the sin and only buried the temptation.
Suppose that Nelson had covered his relations with Lady Hamilton
so discreetly that he left about his movements only a vague suspicion
that he had a wife in every port. We should think him a far worse
man than we think him, knowing the whole truth. Suppose Parnell
had kept his secret so well that his disappearances were put down to
an unmarried man's most vulgar and purchased type of vice, instead of
an unmarried man's comparatively pardonable fault of infatuation.
That great man would seem far less great to us than he does now.
In our craven commercial public life there are not many of the Parnell
or Nelson sort: but even among our lords and millionaires there
are men, I dare say, who are less despicable than they look.
If we had the key of their souls we might come upon virtues
quite unexpected--or at least upon vices more generous.
In many a complex human scandal, I fancy, the first real slander
is the acquittal.
But there is another form of this dehumanising defence:
and that is the defence of the dead. The idea of observing restraint,
if not respect, in speaking of the recently departed rests
on a human instinct altogether deep and free: but in modern
practice it is turned exactly the wrong way. A dead man should
be sacred because he is a man--perhaps a man for the first time.
A baby says he is a man; a boy often thinks he is a man; a man
takes for granted he is a man, and often finds out his mistake.
Perhaps one never knows what being a man means until the instant
of death. Perhaps in a very manly and even military sense all
life is a learning to die. If I were asked to say something
by the grave of a man like Pierpont Morgan, I would say:
"I will not remember his name. He has fought the great unequal fight;
and is of more value than he was."
Now turn to the modern newspaper method; the method of weak whitewash.
The Christian Commonwealth is a paper with a perfectly genuine,
though hazy and patronising, concern for social improvement.
Its intentions are certainly not servile, though I think its upshot
would be. But it feels as we all do, that the day after poor
Morgan's death is not the time for kicking his corpse about:
so, being modern, it contrives to speak well of him in the following
extraordinary fashion. "It is easy to denounce the methods by which
such men amass their vast fortunes, but, making every allowance
for the injury done to individuals by the often ruthless methods
such men adopt to gain their ends, the great fact stands out,
that they are the human agents working out certain economic movements.
. . . These men are helping to prepare industry for a new form of control
and ownership. In the transition stage they amass huge fortunes
for themselves, and ruin many who are too weak to withstand them,
but it is doubtful if the sum of their harmful inflections is as
great as the evils in the same period caused by the great number
of small competing capitalists."
I shall have much to say of this as a social doctrine in a moment.
At the start I am only concerned with it as an epitaph.
In the mere matter of respect for the dead, I say this. I am ready
to pass the grave of Morgan in a decent silence, as a Christian grave.
The Christian Commonwealth can only think of sacrificing a thousand
slaves upon it, as if it were a pagan and prehistoric grave.
For to justify or palliate the capitalist today is to sacrifice
a thousand slaves. My epitaph on Morgan need not even contain
his name; I would write over his grave what I would over my own,
"Have mercy upon us, miserable sinners." But just think how the
Christian Commonwealth epitaph reads, merely as an epitaph! "Sacred to
the Memory of J. Pierpont Morgan: Who, By Methods Peculiarly Easy
to Denounce, Amassed a Large Fortune. Having a Preference
for Ruthless Methods For the Gaining of His Ends, He Selected
for Ruin Such Persons as Were Too Weak To Withstand Him.
He Thus Became The Human Instrument of An Economic and Inhuman Movement.
He Also Formed Trusts. For of Such is the Kingdom of Heaven."
That is the amount of tenderness for the terrible dead that can
be reached in the modernist manner. The sacred death is forgotten,
but the profane life is excused.
And now for the excuse. In order to write a polite paragraph
about a poor old man whose only superiority over any of us
is that he has passed what we all must fear, this paper digs up
the dusty and discredited rubbish of Bellamy: and maintains
the proposition that millionaires bring us nearer to Socialism.
The obvious deduction for a Socialist is that he ought to be,
in every hour and instant, on the side of the millionaires.
No man's wage must be increased by a penny, no man's working day
must be shortened by an hour; for this might delay the swift,
sweet process by which the whole earth will soon be owned by its
six most unscrupulous inhabitants. Then we shall get Socialism.
I don't see why. I never did. But it is self-evident that,
if this is the case, every capitalist must be exalted and every
workman brought low. The whole argument means nothing unless it
means that the rich had better smash us all as soon as possible.
There are some who doubt this concept. I am one of them.
We say it would not have been Napoleon's best policy to wait till
the Allies had conquered him utterly, so that he might only have to
write one letter, asking them to give him back the whole of Europe.
We say, in our simple way, that it would not have been wise in Montenegro
to wait till all the Moslems in Asia were marching upon them;
so as to abolish Islam in one well-expressed proclamation.
We entertain similar doubts about the sanity of making capitalists
stronger than any of the past emperors of this earth, and then asking
them to hand over the only thing for which they have lost their souls.
The final fact is that anyone who subscribes to this epitaph must league
himself with the forces of evil until something like the Last Judgment.
He must not merely give up Socialism, which is a doctrine.
He must also give up Social Reform--which is a dissipation.
He must not only abandon the duty of helping the poor;
he must even tear from his heart the pleasure of tormenting them.
I see that one paper (the name of which I forget) has even
addressed an open letter to me on this matter, asking whether
any of my words (which, I sadly confess, have been many) have born
any fruit in practice--by which, of course, it means Westminster.
Well, I am afraid I must confess that my efforts have been barren,
that I have brought forth no fruit fit for the field of social reform.
In all the most powerful modern movements I have been impotent.
I have never segregated anybody, or tortured anybody,
or unsexed anybody, or buried anybody alive--to my knowledge.
I am not a philanthropist. I do not think any words of mine have
led to one single man being kept in prison beyond his lawful term.
I doubt if I have succeeded in adding a single lash to the torture
at the triangles. I question whether I have succeeded in deducting
so much as a penny from the tiny fortunes of grooms and housemaids.
I have cropped no hair off the heads of other people's daughters.
I have drawn no blood from poorer men's backs. My claim
to be a Progressive is gone for ever; and I know it well.
But I am not quite so bitterly opposed to all possible Social Reform
as the Christian Commonwealth is. I agree that men like Morgan
should be pardoned. I even agree that, for purposes of debate,
men like Morgan should be excused. But I shall deny till death
and damnation that men like Morgan should be encouraged.
And if that epitaph does not mean that men like Morgan should
be encouraged, it means nothing whatever.
THE NEW BIGOTRY
I notice with some amusement, both in America and English literature,
the rise of a new kind of bigotry. Bigotry does not consist in a man
being convinced he is right; that is not bigotry, but sanity.
Bigotry consists in a man being convinced that another man must
be wrong in everything, because he is wrong in a particular belief;
that he must be wrong, even in thinking that he honestly believes
he is right. The last occasion is one applied mostly to literature
and the ability of literary men. And it is all the more like the old
bigotry because it is in opposition to it.
We all know what used to happen sometimes in the Puritan period;
or the more critical classicism of the eighteenth century.
A young idealistic poet would write a copy of verses; mostly verses
somewhat in this style:
O'er rushing waterfall and verdant grove
The languid moonlight throws a light of love.
The poet was considered quite respectable; perhaps the poem was even
a prize poem. Then it was discovered that the poet, when slightly drunk,
had expressed doubts about the exact date of the Book of Habakkuk.
There was a terrible scandal; the youth was hurled from his
college as an atheist; and then the learned critics went back
and looked at his poem with a new darkling and suspicious eye.
The "rushing waterfall", after all, had a very revolutionary sound
and hinted at pantheistic anarchy. The phrase "languid moonlight"
was an appeal to all the most profligate passions. "Light of love"
was a term notoriously of loose significance.
Today it is just the opposite; only equally bigoted.
A young idealistic poet, full of the new visions of beauty,
writes verses appropriate to such vision; as, for instance:
Bug-house underbogies belch daybreak back-firing.
Daylight's a void-vomit; steadying legs to stump.

And all the young critics know he is all right; he has got cosmic rhythm;
he is a regular guy.
And then a horrid whisper goes round that he was seen outside an
Episcopal Church near Vermont. The whole horrid truth is soon known.
He has admitted to a newspaper man that he believes in God.
Then the young critics go back gloomily and stare at his poetry;
and, strangely enough, see for the first time that there was something
awfully old-fashioned in saying "daylight" when Binx might have
said "sky-blank"; and, after all, bogies are just the sort of thing
Episcopalians are forced by their bishops to believe in.
This, though some of the worst examples have occurred in England,
is a strictly correct biography of a man of genius who has come to us
from America--Mr. T. S. Eliot. It would be an exaggeration to say
that Mr. Eliot was expelled from Harvard for being a High Churchman,
as Shelley was expelled from Oxford for being an atheist.
Mr. Eliot's character was not blasted by a religion until later
in life, and after he had said all that can be said for modern
scepticism and despair.
But this makes it all the funnier. An English critic actually
accused him of asking us "to believe the unbelievable".
Whatever is the sense of calling a thing unbelievable when a man
like Eliot already believes it. The author of The Waste Land
knows all there is to know about scepticism and pessimism;
why not admit that his beliefs are beliefs, and go back to a proper
criticism of his literature?
BOOKS FOR BOYS
A recent correspondence upon what is called pernicious literature has
given rise to several declarations to the effect that the popular
literature which is sold to boys in our day is greatly inferior
to that of two or three decades ago. At first sight a reflective
person might be inclined to suggest that perhaps there were more
psychological elements involved in that far-off boyish enjoyment,
and in that, as in many other instances of our youthful pleasures,
we were not so much enjoying the stories as enjoying ourselves.
It is at least possible that the laudator temporis acti of whom
we are speaking would regard the actual task of reading through
those lost romances very much in the same way that he would regard
the action of a waiter in a restaurant who brought him fourteen
penny buns and a plate of bull's-eyes.
The mental digestion of boys is as strong as their physical digestion.
They do not heed the cookery of art any more than the art of cookery.
They can eat the apples of the tree of knowledge, and they can eat
them raw. It is a great mistake to suppose that boys only read
boyish books. Not only do they privately revel in their sisters' most
sentimental novels, but they absorb cartloads of useless information.
One boy in particular, with whose career from an early age we have
the best reasons for being familiar, used to read whole volumes
of Chamber's Encyclopaedia, and of a very musty and unreliable
History of English Trade. The thing was a mere brute pleasure
of reading, a pleasure in leisurely and mechanical receptiveness.
It was the sort of pleasure that a cow must have in grazing
all day long.
But when all allowance has been made for the omnivorousness of youth,
we incline to think that there is probably a considerable amount
of truth in the idea that boys' books have to some extent degenerated.
They have degenerated probably for the reason that all forms
of art degenerate, because they are despised. Probably they
were less despised in the days when they still had upon them,
as it were, the glamour of the great masters of historical romance.
The spirit of Scott and Ainsworth and Fenimore Cooper remained
in them even if it was only the reflection of a hundred reflections
and each in a distorting mirror.
No one will ever understand the spirit at the back of popular
and juvenile literature until he realises one fact, that a large
amount of it is the result of that enthusiasm of the young reader
which makes him wish to hear more and more about certain heroes,
and read more and more of certain types of books. He dowers
the creatures of fiction with a kind of boyish immortality.
He is not surprised if Dick Deadshot or Jack Harkaway renews
his youth through a series of volumes which reaches further than
the length of the Encyclopaedia Britannica. These books have
the vital philosophy of youth, a philosophy in which death does
not exist, except, indeed, as an external and picturesque incident
which happens to villains.
The serious student of this class of books and papers will go on
to observe that a very large mass of such works has arisen directly
out of the interest taken in some of the creations of great masters.
An irresponsible writer for boys early in the century continued
the adventures of Pickwick. An interminable book of Oriental
adventure which we read in our boyhood was avowedly a supplement
to the Arabian Nights, and mingled Aladdin, Sinbad, and Ali Baba
in one inexhaustible tale. To take a more vulgar example,
it is said that "Ally Sloper" is simply an infinitely degraded
version of Mr. Micawber; the literary zoologist will trace
the same rudimentary organs, the hat, the tie, and the bald head.
All this amounts to one of the great laws of the question,
the fact that the youthful mind takes hold of certain figures,
insists upon them, tears them, as it were, out of the covers of the story,
and could follow their adventures in any number of day dreams.
Hence one of the essential qualities of this cheap literature--
its astonishing voluminousness. A library keeping a record of it
would need a dome vaster than the Bodleian.
From this, as we have said, it may be inferred that there is likely enough
to have been some decadence of late years, since we are becoming further
and further removed from the great historical novelists, who left a kind
of glow upon all historic fiction. New literary fashions have arisen,
but they are scarcely likely to be imitated in the literature of boys.
No publisher has yet brought out with gaudy-coloured illustrations
"The Further Adventures of Jude the Obscure". No penny dreadfuls have
been devoted to what eventually happened to Pelleas and Melisande.
And in this manner we reach once more the inevitable conclusion
about debased forms of art; that they are debased because they
are not respected. Everything in the world, from a child to a form
of fiction, will be bad until we consent to treat it as good.
And of all forms of literature in the world, the one most
grossly neglected, from an artistic point of view, is the boys'
book of adventure.
It is a very peculiar fact, that while the educated middle-class at
the present day expends infinite money and trouble upon surrounding
the child with the noblest works of art and literature, the boy is in this
matter treated as if he were a half-witted and inconsiderable savage.
The wretched infant of four years old is expected to drink in
the verses of Stevenson and the decorative curves of Walter Crane.
But when he has imbibed this atmosphere, when his aesthetic hunger
has by hypothesis been aroused, when his mind has developed with
the rapid development of boyhood, he is suddenly put off with books
and papers which are not literature at all. A child's love for what is
pretty is sedulously cultivated as the dawn of an aesthetic sense,
but no one seems to realise that a boy's love of adventure is
another aesthetic sense quite equally noble and appropriate.
A child's love of colour is treated as a spiritual thing,
a sort of hint of heaven, but a boy's love of adventure is spoken
of as if it were a mere brute appetite, excusable in a growing lad.
If a child says, "I like the pretty flowers", he is applauded for his
poetic instinct, but if a boy says, "I like a story about pirates",
he is treated as if he had asked for another slice of pork.
As long as this view continues there can be no worthy school
of adventurous fiction. It must be realised that both the child's
love of the pretty and the boy's love of the bold are sound
and admirable artistic instincts. Neither of them shows that the
individual is a cherub who cannot be long for this world, but both
of them show that he is a well-equipped and healthy human soul.
The child in the fairy-tale is canonised for running after a butterfly.
The boy in the penny dreadful is denounced for running away to sea.
But the sea is more beautiful than any butterflies.
If, then, we are agreed that the first need of the problem is
to understand once and for all that the love of adventure is not
a temporary savagery to be satisfied, but an essential artistic
tendency to be crowned and brought to consummation, it cannot
but seriously affect our view of boys' literature as a whole.
We want to realise that the instinct of day dream and adventure is
a high spiritual and moral instinct, that it requires neither dilution
nor excuse, that it has been the mother of all great travellers and
missionaries and knights errant and the patroness of all the brave.
The one essential of a writer for boys is that he should not write
down to them. He should rather write up, arduously and reverently,
as well he may, to the mysterious spirit of youth.
THE OUTLINE OF LIBERTY
There is a quality needed today for the spread of all truth,
and especially religious truth, which is very simple and vivid,
but which I find it very difficult to fit with a word.
So many words have become catchwords.
I suppose that our critics, in their learned way, would have recourse
to the little-known Greek word paradox, if I were simply to say
that they are not quite broad-minded enough to be Catholics.
In their own jargon, being broad-minded so often means being blank-minded.
If I were to say that they suffer from a lack of imagination,
they might suppose (heaven help them) that I meant that what we
believe is all imaginary. Nor indeed do either of these two terms
define the definite thing I intend. It would be nearer the mark
if I said that they cannot see all round a subject; or that they
cannot see anything against the background of everything else.
The learned man, of what I may call the Cambridge type, is like a man
who should spend years in making a minute ordnance map of the country
between Cork and Dublin, and never discover that Ireland is an island.
It is not a question of understanding something difficult.
It is rather a question of opening the mind wide enough to understand
something easy. It is not to be attained by years of labour;
it is more likely to be attained in a moment of laziness;
when the map-maker who has long been poring over the map with his nose
close to Cork, may lean back for a moment and suddenly see Ireland.
It is much more difficult to get such men to lean back for a moment
and see Christendom.
The Catholic Church is always being defined in terms of the particular
quarrel that she happens to have with particular people in a
particular place. Because the Protestant sects in Northern Europe,
for one or two centuries, disapproved of rosaries and incense
and candles and confessional boxes, there was a widespread
impression that Roman Catholics were simply people who liked
confessional boxes and candles and incense and rosaries.
But that is not what a Manichee or a Moslem or a Hindoo or an ancient
Greek philosopher would say about Roman Catholics.
Buddhists have incense; Moslems have something very like rosaries;
and hardly any healthy heathen human being on earth could conceive
why anybody should have any particular hatred of candles.
Buddhists would say that Catholics were people who insisted
on a personal God and personal immortality. Moslems would say
that Catholics were people who believed that God had a Son
who assumed human form, and who did not think it idolatrous
that He should afterwards assume pictorial or sculptural form.
Every group in the world would have its own angle or aspect;
and the Protestant would hardly recognise the same object which
he had only considered in his own aspect.
Nevertheless, each of these, taken in itself, is in a sense narrow;
and to dwell upon it narrows the issue. What we want is to have
some general impression of the whole background of humanity,
especially of heathen humanity, against which we can see the outline
of the object, as, in the map of Ireland, the island is seen
against the sea.
Now the real background of all that human heathenry is rather a
grey background. There are particular patches, which happen to be close
to us in place and time, which have been freshly painted in various ways.
So freshly painted that nobody knows yet how long the colours
will last. As the Imperialists wanted to paint the map red,
so the Internationalists and Idealists now want to paint the map pink.
But none of them has painted half so much of the map anything as they,
in their optimism, have sometimes supposed. And even in the areas
where a sort of official optimism prevails, as in parts of America,
there is a great deal more of the old ordinary melancholy of men than
anyone could gather from newspaper headlines or political programmes.
And I believe that the most general philosophy of men left to themselves,
and perhaps the most practical illustration of the Fall of Man,
is a vague impression of Fate.
If a man will really talk to the poor, in almost any country, I think
he will generally find that they are either Christians or fatalists.
This fatalism is more or less varied or complicated, of course,
in various places by various mythologies or philosophies.
It will generally be found that the mythology is a sort of poetry,
embodying a worship of the wild forces of nature; a nature-worship
which, when broken up, is called polytheism, and, when united,
is called pantheism. But there is sometimes very little left
of theism in pantheism.
Then there are whole districts where there is true theism
which is, nevertheless, permeated with a mood of fatalism.
That, I suppose, is true at least of large areas of Islam.
Then there are what may be called the philosophies of resignation,
which probably cover equally large areas of the ancient
civilisation of Asia.
We need not insist here on any controversial points against or even
about these things. But I take it as certain that all those notes
of recurrence and cosmic rhythm, and a cycle beginning and ending
with itself, which repeat themselves so frequently in connection with
Buddhism and Brahminism and Theosophy, are in a general sense allied
to an almost impersonal submission to an ultimately impersonal law.
That is the tone of the whole thing; and, as I have said,
the tone or tint of it strikes us as rather grey; or at least,
neutral and negative.
It is the same with almost all we know of the pagan myths and metaphysics
of antiquity. It is a modern slander on pagans to represent paganism
as almost identical with pleasure. But anyhow, nobody acquainted
with the great Greek and Latin literature, even in the smallest degree,
will ever dream of identifying paganism with optimism.
It would at least be a great deal nearer the truth to say that there,
as everywhere else, the fundamental character of paganism is pessimism.
But in any case, it can quite fairly be said that it is fatalism.
Upon this grey background there is one splash or star of silver or gold;
a thing like a flame. It is quite exceptional and extraordinary.
Of its many extraordinary characters, this is perhaps the chief;
that it proclaims Liberty. Or, as the only true meaning of that term,
it proclaims Will. In a strange voice, as of a trumpet from heaven,
it tells a strange story, of which the very essence is that it
is made up of Will, or of a free divergence of Wills.
Will made the world; Will wounded the world; the same Divine Will gave
to the world for the second time its chance; the same human Will can for
the last time make its choice. That is the real outstanding peculiarity,
or eccentricity, of the peculiar sect called Roman Catholics.
And if anyone objects to my limiting so large a conception to
Roman Catholics, I willingly agree that there are many who value
it so much that they obviously ought to be Roman Catholics.
But if anyone says that it is not in fact and history bound up
with the Faith of Roman Catholicism, it is enough to refer him
to the history and the facts.
Nobody especially emphasised this spiritual liberty until
the Church was established. People began instantly to question
this spiritual liberty, when the Church began to be broken up.
The instant a breach, or even a crack, had been made in the dyke
of Catholicism, there poured through it the bitter sea of Calvinism,
or in other words, of a very cruel form of fatalism.
Since that time, it has taken the much duller form of Determinism.
This sadness and sense of bondage is so general to mankind that it
immediately made its appearance, when the special spiritual message
of liberty was silenced or interrupted anywhere. Wherever that
message is heard, men think and talk in terms of will and choice;
and they see no meaning in any of the philosophies of fate,
whether desperate or resigned.
It is idle to talk to a Catholic about optimism or pessimism;
for he himself shall decide whether the universe shall be, for him,
the best or the worst of all possible worlds. It is useless to tell
him that he might be more at one with the universal life as a Buddhist
or a pantheist; for he knows that, in that sense, he might be more
at one with the universal life as a turnip or a tree. It is his
whole hope and glory that he is not at one with the universal life;
but stands out from it, an exception and even a miracle.
There is a great passage in the "Paradiso" of Dante, which I wish I
knew enough Italian to appreciate or enough English to translate.
But I would commend it to those who may fancy that my emphasis
on this exceptional quality is a mere modern whitewashing of a
medieval superstition; and especially to those who have been
taught in laborious detail, by learned and very stupid historians,
to regard medievalism as narrow and enchained. For it runs
roughly like this:
The mightiest gift that God of his largesse Made in creation,
perfect even as He, Most of His substance, and to Him most dear,
He gave to the Will and it was Liberty.

A NOTE ON NUDISM
There is one little habit of some of the most intelligent modern
writers against which I should like to protest. It consists
of flatly refusing to state somebody else's opinion as it stands;
and consider it on its own merits. The modern writer must always
assume that it is a choice between his own extreme opinion and
something at the other extreme. I found a curious example in a very
excellent book by Miss Cicely Hamilton called Modern Germanies.
She was referring to the sect of the Nudists, who have revived
the ancient heresy of the Adamites and go about without any clothes,
taking themselves very seriously; as if nakedness were a new invention.
I think Miss Hamilton really hesitated a little, being moved by her
instincts as a civilised person to laugh, and by her instincts
as a progressive person to applaud. What then does she do?
She immediately repeats the old story that in Paul et Virginie,
the very artificial sentimental novel of the eighteenth century,
the heroine is drowned because she refuses to take off her clothes.
She then adds that "if she has to choose" between Virginie and some German
flapper who finds it more comfortable to have no clothes to flap, she will
choose the latter. But, first of all, why should she "have to choose"?
Why should she not consider Nudism on its own merits; and the normal
view of clothes, among sane people, also on its own merits?
If I have to judge a drunkard, I will judge him without dragging
in the comparison of a mad fakir who deliberately died of thirst
in the desert. If I have to judge a miser, I will call him a miser;
despite the possible existence of an insane and intoxicated nobleman
in Vienna, who poured ten thousand gold coins down a drain.
I cannot see why Miss Hamilton should call in one extravagance
merely to justify another.
Next, if she really does suppose that normal, traditional or Christian
morality are represented by Virginie, she is probably quite wrong.
Most Christian authorities would say that her notion of sacrifice
came very near to the sin of suicide. For Paul et Virginie was
not written in a Christian period but in a very pagan period,
when pre-Revolutionary France was in love with the pagan Stoics
who did not disapprove of suicide. The story itself is largely
founded on an old classical romance. It cannot be taken as typical
of modern Christianity, or even of medieval Christianity.
It is only fair to remember that in this sense Virginie is a
heathen heroine; and Godiva was a Christian heroine.
Lastly, I am not sure I should choose the German flapper,
even if I were driven to the choice. We may think a sacrifice
is made to a mistaken code of honour; but there is the sacrifice;
and there is the honour. We have no reason to suppose that
the Nudist even knows what we mean by honour. We know nothing
about her, except that she does not know what we mean by dignity.
As a plain piece of practical psychology, I think it extremely
likely that the poor mistaken maiden, who would die for her dignity,
would also die for her country, would die for her friends,
would die for her faith or promise, or any worthy obligation.
We know nothing about the other woman, except that (like the pig
and other animals), she feels more comfortable without clothes.
It seems to me an insufficient basis for moral confidence.
CONSULTING THE ENCYCLOPAEDIA
The Historical Student will raise his refined eyebrows if I say
that a Catholic is an Encyclopaedist. The name of Encyclopaedism
was given in the eighteenth century to the most coldly eager of
the enemies of Catholicism. And even now it is generally believed
that we bow submissively before the storm of the ephemeral Encyclical,
but dare not open the scientific and solid Encyclopaedia--
which, by the way, is generally at any given moment much more out
of date than the Encyclical.
It is none the less true that the Catholic Church presents itself,
though on a higher plane and plan, in a certain double character to which
perhaps the nearest natural parallel is the use of an encyclopaedia.
For it is the test of a good encyclopaedia that it does two rather
different things at once. The man consulting it finds the thing he wants;
he also finds how many thousand things there are that he does not want.
It advises the particular man upon his particular problem,
though it were quite a private problem, almost as if it were giving
private advice. And the man must be so far touched to some tinge
of healthy humility, if it be only the admission that he does
not know everything, and must seek outside himself for something.
Even if he is so ill-advised as to consult a medical work of reference
for the proper proportions of hyoscine for the poisoning of an aunt,
he must be so far in a pious and respectful attitude and accepting
something upon a sort of authority.
I remember a man who told me he never accepted anything on any
sort of authority; I also remember asking him whether he ever
consulted Bradshaw, or whether he insisted on travelling by every
train first, to see whether it was safe to travel by it.
The journey itself might be highly private, the visit to the aunt
almost pressingly private, but he would not evolve a railway train
entirely out of his private judgment.
But a work of reference works in another way also. It reminds
the traveller in the train that there are a good many other trains
full of travellers. It reminds the neoethical nephew that there
are a good many different words in the dictionary. In his search
for hyoscine he will pass carelessly over the honey of Hymettus,
and think it needless to dwell on the life of Heliogabalus or the science
of hydraulics. And thus he will learn the same lesson in another way;
the somewhat difficult lesson that he is nobody except himself.
Those two discoveries commonly combine in a conversion;
and this is perhaps the most workable framework in which to state
the two chief elements of my own. There was first the relation
of Catholicism to my own original and personal problem; and there
was a second rather curious and illuminating illustration of the
necessity of keeping it in proportion to all the other problems,
the problems of all the other people.
Now all the very varied types of people who sooner or later draw
near to the Catholic Faith have moved towards it from the most
widely different standpoints, across most varying distances,
and rejecting or renewing or reshaping the most queerly contrasted
types of non-Catholic thought. My own thought, when it was
not yet Catholic, was often blasted with the name of Optimist;
but it was not quite so bad as that sounds today. It was an attempt
to hold on to religion by the thread of thanks for our creation;
by the praise of existence and of created things. And the curious
part of it is that I found that this piece of private judgment,
or private nonsense, was really much more true than I ever thought
it was; and yet, if that truth were left to stand alone, it would
be a complete falsehood.
For the sake of illustration, or in a rather special sense
of illumination, I will take the metaphor of a window; a thing
which always had, and still has, an almost weirdly vivid effect
on my own imagination. My own original view, which would originally
have been an entirely non-Catholic if not anti-Catholic view,
might be roughly stated thus. "After all, what could be more mystical
or magical than ordinary daylight coming in through an ordinary window?
Why should anybody want a new heaven shining on a new earth;
why need they dream of strange stars or miraculous flames, or the sun
and moon turned to blood and darkness, in order to imagine a portent?
The mere fact of existence and experience is a perpetual portent.
Why should we ever ask for more?"
There is an old literary joke or game, familiar I think among
the transcendental tricks of the Cavalier poets; a game that is called
echo verses. It is a sort of punning upon the last syllable of a word;
by which Echo is made to answer mockingly the question asked
in the line of verse. Thus, to transfer it to a modern topic,
the poet might ask, "Say, what high hope is founded on eugenics?"
And the obliging echo would answer, "Nix"; or a paean in praise
of some Socialist or ex-Socialist statesman would begin with
the line, "Labour's great leader; mighty Democrat", and end with
the repetition, "Rat".
I am haunted by this parallel in the curious logical answer to my
own question; which was at once a repetition and a contradiction
and a completion. For it seemed to me that when I asked that question,
"Why is not the daylight enough?" the ancient voice of some mystery
such as an old religion answered my words merely by repeating them,
"Why is not the daylight enough?" And when I said, "Why should
not that wonderful white fire, breaking through the window,
inspire us every day like an ever-returning miracle?" the echo
out of that old crypt or cavern only answered, "Why not indeed?"
And, the more I thought of it, the more I thought that there was the hint
of some strange answer in the very fact that I had to ask the question.
I had not lost, and I have never lost, the conviction that such
primal things are mysterious and amazing; but if they were amazing,
why did anybody have to remind us that they were amazing?
Why was there, as I had already realised that there certainly was,
a sort of daily fight to appreciate the daylight; to which we had to
summon all imagination and poetry and the labour of the arts to aid us?
If the first imaginative instinct was right, it seemed clearer
and clearer that something else was wrong. And as I indignantly
denied that there was anything wrong with the window, I eventually
concluded that there was something wrong with me.
In this case, the divine dictionary had answered my own personal question
as directly and even personally as if the answer had been written for me.
It justified the instinct that inspired me to accept the daylight as a
divine reality; but it also solved the problem that puzzled me about
the difficulty of thus accepting the daylight all day and every day.
Creation was of the Creator and declared as good; the power in it could
be praised by angels forever and by the sons of God shouting for joy.
If we were ourselves only occasionally overheard in the act of shouting
for joy, it was because we were only partially or imperfectly the sons
of God; not indeed wholly disinherited, but not wholly domesticated.
In short, we suffered by the Fall or Original Sin; but it is important
to note that this is not an answer to the particular question,
except in the form of the more moderate Catholic doctrine,
and not the old pessimist Protestant doctrine of the Fall.
This particular problem arose entirely out of the fact that man
is imperfect; but not, in the pessimist sense, perfectly imperfect.
The whole paradox is in the fact that a part of his mind remains
almost perfect; and he can perpetually perceive what he cannot
perpetually enjoy. I was as certain that existence is ecstatically
more excellent than non-existence as I was that plus two is
different from minus two. Only there is a practical psychological
difficulty about always going into ecstasies over this fact.
Man is not symmetrically unsymmetrical; he is a sort of one-eyed
creature ever since he fought a duel with the devil; and the one eye
sees the eternal light eternally, while the other has grown tired
and blinks or is almost blind. Thus the authority solved this
private problem, not by denying the truth of my private judgment,
but by adding to it the larger and more general judgment of the Fall.
And then, in the very act of understanding my own little
private problem, I understood the public authority which I have
compared to an encyclopaedia. Here there were thousands of other
private problems solved for thousands of other private persons;
masses of them had nothing to do with my own case at all;
but one of them turned and confronted my own case in a curious way.
I began to realize that it would not do to act as so many of the most
brilliant men of my time had acted. It was not enough for a man
to value a truth merely because he had picked it up by himself;
to take it away with him and turn it into a private system;
at the best into a philosophy and at the worst into a sect.
He was very proud of answering his own question without the help
of an encyclopaedia; but he did not even pretend to answer all
the other questions in the encyclopaedia.
Now I felt very strongly that there ought to be answers, not only
to all the other questions which all the other people were asking,
but also answers to other questions which I should ask myself.
And the moment I began to think about these other problems I saw at
once that I could not even satisfy myself with the solution of one of
those problems. The practical example which occurred to me was this.
I said to myself; it is all very well to say that the miracle
of daylight coming through a window ought to be enough to make
a man dance with joy. But suppose another man uses your argument
as a justification for putting innocent men in prison for life,
in a cell with one window, and then leaving them to dance.
What will become of all your own denunciations of slavery and
the oppression of the poor, when that highly practical statesman
has founded a new commonwealth on your new creed?
And then I think there spread out before me, like a vast dazzling
plan with innumerable details, some vision of the thousand things
that have to be interrelated and balanced in Catholic thought;
justice as well as joy; liberty as well as light; and I felt certain
that the mere proportion of all these things, not the negation
of any of them, needed, to harmonize it and hold it steady,
a power and a presence mightier than the mind of any mortal man.
IF I HAD ONLY ONE SERMON TO PREACH
If I had only one sermon to preach, it would be a sermon against Pride.
The more I see of existence, and especially of modern practical
and experimental existence, the more I am convinced of the reality
of the old religious thesis; that all evil began with some attempt
at superiority; some moment when, as we might say, the very skies were
cracked across like a mirror, because there was a sneer in Heaven.
Now the first fact to note about this notion is a rather curious one.
Of all such notions, it is the one most generally dismissed
in theory and most universally accepted in practice. Modern men
imagine that such a theological idea is quite remote from them;
and, stated as a theological idea, it probably is remote from them.
But, as a matter of fact, it is too close to them to be recognised.
It is so completely a part of their minds and morals and instincts,
I might almost say of their bodies, that they take it for granted
and act on it even before they think of it. It is actually
the most popular of all moral ideas; and yet it is almost entirely
unknown as a moral idea. No truth is now so unfamiliar as a truth,
or so familiar as a fact.
Let us put the fact to a trifling but not unpleasing test.
Let us suppose that the reader, or (preferably) the writer, is going
into a public-house or some public place of social intercourse;
a public tube or tram might do as well, except that it seldom allows
of such long and philosophical intercourse as did the old public house.
Anyhow, let us suppose any place where men of motley but ordinary
types assemble; mostly poor because the majority is poor some
moderately comfortable but rather what is snobbishly called common;
an average handful of human beings. Let us suppose that the enquirer,
politely approaching this group, opens the conversation in a chatty way
by saying, "Theologians are of opinion that it was one of the superior
angelic intelligences seeking to become the supreme object of worship,
instead of finding his natural joy in worshipping, which dislocated
the providential design and frustrated the full joy and completion
of the cosmos". After making these remarks the enquirer will gaze
round brightly and expectantly at the company for corroboration,
at the same time ordering such refreshments as may be ritually
fitted to the place or time, or perhaps merely offering cigarettes
or cigars to the whole company, to fortify them against the strain.
In any case, we may well admit that such a company will find it
something of a strain to accept the formula in the above form.
Their comments will probably be disjointed and detached; whether they
take the form of "Lorlumme" (a beautiful thought slurred somewhat
in pronunciation), or even "Gorblimme" (an image more sombre but
fortunately more obscure), or merely the unaffected form of "Garn";
a statement quite free from doctrinal and denominational teaching,
like our State compulsory education. In short, he who shall attempt
to state this theory as a theory to the average crowd of the populace
will doubtless find that he is talking in an unfamiliar language.
Even if he states the matter in the simplified form, that Pride
is the worst of the Seven Deadly Sins, he will only produce
a vague and rather unfavourable impression that he is preaching.
But he is only preaching what everybody else is practising;
or at least is wanting everybody else to practise.
Let the scientific enquirer continue to cultivate the patience
of science. Let him linger--at any rate let me linger--
in the place of popular entertainment whatever it may be,
and take very careful note (if necessary in a note-book) of the way
in which ordinary human beings do really talk about each other.
As he is a scientific enquirer with a note-book, it is very
likely that he never saw any ordinary human beings before.
But if he will listen carefully, he will observe a certain tone taken
towards friends, foes and acquaintances; a tone which is, on the whole,
creditably genial and considerate, though not without strong likes
and dislikes. He will hear abundant if sometimes bewildering allusion
to the well-known weaknesses of Old George; but many excuses also,
and a certain generous pride in conceding that Old George is quite
the gentleman when drunk, or that he told the policeman off proper.
Some celebrated idiot, who is always spotting winners that never win,
will be treated with almost tender derision; and, especially among
the poorest, there will be a true Christian pathos in the reference
to those who have been "in trouble" for habits like burglary
and petty larceny. And as all these queer types are called up
like ghosts by the incantation of gossip, the enquirer will gradually
form the impression that there is one kind of man, probably only
one kind of man, perhaps, only one man, who is really disliked.
The voices take on quite a different tone in speaking of him;
there is a hardening and solidification of disapproval and a new
coldness in the air. And this will be all the more curious because,
by the current modern theories of social or anti-social action,
it will not be at all easy to say why he should be such a monster;
or what exactly is the matter with him. It will be hinted at only
in singular figures of speech, about a gentleman who is mistakenly
convinced that he owns the street; or sometimes that be owns the earth.
Then one of the social critics will say, "'E comes in 'ere and 'e
thinks 'e's Gawd Almighty." Then the scientific enquirer will shut his
note-book with a snap and retire from the scene, possibly after paying
for any drinks he may have consumed in the cause of social science.
He has got what he wanted. He has been intellectually justified.
The man in the pub has precisely repeated, word for word,
the theological formula about Satan.
Pride is a poison so very poisonous that it not only poisons
the virtues; it even poisons the other vices. This is what is felt
by the poor men in the public tavern, when they tolerate the tippler
or the tipster or even the thief, but feel something fiendishly wrong
with the man who bears so close a resemblance to God Almighty.
And we all do in fact know that the primary sin of pride has this,
curiously freezing and hardening effect upon the other sins.
A man may be very susceptible and in sex matters rather loose;
he may waste himself on passing and unworthy passions, to the hurt
of his soul; and yet always retain something which makes friendship
with his own sex at least possible, and even faithful and satisfying.
But once let that sort of man regard his own weakness as a strength,
and you have somebody entirely different. You have the Lady-Killer;
the most beastly of all possible bounders; the man whom his own
sex almost always has the healthy instinct to hate and despise.
A man may be naturally slothful and rather irresponsible; he may
neglect many duties through carelessness, and his friends may still
understand him, so long as it is really a careless carelessness.
But it is the devil and all when it becomes a careful carelessness.
It is the devil and all when he becomes a deliberate and self-conscious
Bohemian, sponging on principle, preying on society in the name
of his own genius (or rather of his own belief in his own genius)
taxing the world like a king on the plea that he is a poet,
and despising better men than himself who work that he may waste.
It is no metaphor to say that it is the devil and all.
By the same fine old original religious formula, it is all of the devil.
We could go through any number of social types illustrating the same
spiritual truth. It would be easy to point out that even the miser,
who is half-ashamed of his madness, is a more human and sympathetic
type than the millionaire who brags and boasts of his avarice and calls
it sanity and simplicity and the strenuous life. It would be easy
to point out that even cowardice, as a mere collapse of the nerves,
is better than cowardice as an ideal and theory of the intellect;
and that a really imaginative person will have more sympathy with men who,
like cattle, yield to what they know is panic, than with a certain
particular type of prig who preaches something that he calls peace.
Men hate priggishness because it is the driest form of pride.
Thus there is a paradox in the whole position. The spiritual idea
of the evil of pride, especially spiritual pride, was dismissed
as a piece of mysticism not needed by modern morality, which is
to be purely social and practical. And, as a fact, it is very
specially needed because the morality is social and practical.
On the assumption that we need care for nothing except making
other human beings happy, this is quite certainly the thing
that will make them unhappy. The practical case against pride,
as a mere source of social discomfort and discord, is if possible
even more self-evident than the more mystical case against it,
as a setting up of the self against the soul of the world.
And yet though we see this thing on every side in modern life,
we really hear very little about it in modern literature and
ethical theory. Indeed, a great deal of modern literature and ethics
might be meant specially for the encouragement of spiritual pride.
Scores of scribes and sages are busy writing about the importance
of self-culture and self-realisation; about how every child is
to be taught to develop his personality (whatever that may be);
about how every man must devote himself to success, and every
successful man must devote himself to developing a magnetic and
compelling personality; about how every man may become a superman
(by taking Our Correspondence Course) or, in the more sophisticated
and artistic type of fiction, how one specially superior superman can
learn to look down on the mere mob of ordinary supermen, who form
the population of that peculiar world. Modern theory, as a whole,
is rather encouraging egoism. But we need not be alarmed about that.
Modern practice, being exactly like ancient practice, is still heartily
discouraging it. The man with the strong magnetic personality is
still the man whom those who know him best desire most warmly to kick
out of the club. The man in a really acute stage of self-realisation
is a no more pleasing object in the club than in the pub.
Even the most enlightened and scientific sort of club can see
through the superman; and see that he has become a bore.
It is in practice that the philosophy of pride breaks down;
by the test of the moral instincts of man wherever two or three are
gathered together; and it is the mere experience of modern humanity
that answers the modern heresy.
There is indeed another practical experience, known to us all,
even more pungent and vivid than the actual unpopularity of the bully
or the bumptious fool. We all know that there is a thing called
egoism that is much deeper than egotism. Of all spiritual
diseases it is the most intangible and the most intolerable.
It is said to be allied to hysteria; it sometimes looks as if it
were allied to diabolic possession. It is that condition in which
the victim does a thousand varying things from one unvarying motive
of a devouring vanity; and sulks or smiles, slanders or praises,
conspires and intrigues or sits still and does nothing, all in one
unsleeping vigilance over the social effect of one single person.
It is amazing to me that in the modern world, that chatters
perpetually about psychology and sociology, about the tyranny
with which we are threatened by a few feeble-minded infants,
about alcoholic poisoning and the treatment of neurotics, about half
a hundred things that are near the subject and never on the spot--
it is amazing that these moderns really have so very little to say
about the cause and cure of a moral condition that poisons nearly
every family and every circle of friends. There is hardly a practical
psychologist who has anything to say about it that is half so
illuminating as the literal exactitude of the old maxim of the priest;
that pride is from hell. For there is something awfully vivid
and appallingly fixed, about this madness at its worst, that makes
that short and antiquated word seem much more apt than any other.
And then, as I say, the learned go wandering away into discourses
about drink or tobacco, about the wickedness of wine glasses or
the incredible character of public-houses. The wickedest work in this
world is symbolised not by a wine glass but by a looking-glass;
and it is not done in public-houses;, but in the most private
of all private houses which is a house of mirrors.
The phrase would probably be misunderstood; but I should
begin my sermon by telling people not to enjoy themselves.
I should tell them to enjoy dances and theatres and joy-rides and
champagne and oysters; to enjoy jazz and cocktails and night-clubs
if they can enjoy nothing better; to enjoy bigamy and burglary and
any crime in the calendar, in preference to this other alternative;
but never to learn to enjoy themselves. Human beings are happy
so long as they retain the receptive power and the power of reaction
in surprise and gratitude to something outside. So long as they
have this they have as the greatest minds have always declared,
a something that is present in childhood and which can still preserve
and invigorate manhood. The moment the self within is consciously felt
as something superior to any of the gifts that can be brought to it,
or any of the adventures that it may enjoy, there has appeared a sort
of self-devouring fastidiousness and a disenchantment in advance,
which fulfils all the Tartarean emblems of thirst and of despair.
Difficulties can easily be raised, of course, in any such debate
by the accident of words being used in different senses; and sometimes
in quite contrary senses. For instance, when we speak of somebody
being "proud of" something, as of a man being proud of his wife
or a people proud of its heroes, we really mean something that is
the very opposite of pride. For it implies that the man thinks
that something outside himself is needed to give him great glory;
and such a glory is really acknowledged as a gift. In the same way,
the word will certainly be found misleading, if I say that the worst
and most depressing element in the mixed elements of the present
and the immediate future, seems to me to be an element of impudence.
For there is a kind of impudence that we all find either
amusing or bracing; as in the impudence of the guttersnipe.
But there again the circumstances disarm the thing of its real evil.
The quality commonly called "cheek" is not an assertion of superiority;
but rather a bold attempt to balance inferiority. When you walk up
to a very wealthy and powerful nobleman and playfully tip his hat over
his eyes (as is your custom) you are not suggesting that you yourself
are above all human follies, but rather that you are capable of them,
and that he also ought to have a wider and richer experience of them.
When you dig a Royal Duke in the waistcoat, in your playful manner,
you are not taking yourself too seriously, but only, perhaps, not taking
him so seriously as is usually thought correct. This sort of impudence
may be open to criticism, as it is certainly subject to dangers.
But there is a sort of hard intellectual impudence, which really
treats itself as intangible to retort or judgment; and there are
a certain number among the new generations and social movements,
who fall into this fundamental weakness. It is a weakness;
for it is simply settling down permanently to believe what even
the vain and foolish can only believe by fits and starts, but what
all men wish to believe and are often found weak enough to believe;
that they themselves constitute the supreme standard of things.
Pride consists in a man making his personality the only test,
instead of making the truth the test. It is not pride to wish
to do well, or even to look well, according to a real test.
It is pride to think that a thing looks ill, because it does not look
like something characteristic of oneself. Now in the general clouding
of clear and abstract standards, there is a real tendency today
for a young man (and even possibly a young woman) to fall back on that
personal test, simply for lack of any trustworthy impersonal test.
No standard being sufficiently secure for the self to be moulded
to suit it, all standards may be moulded to suit the self.
But the self as a self is a very small thing and something
very like an accident. Hence arises a new kind of narrowness;
which exists especially in those who boast of breadth. The sceptic
feels himself too large to measure life by the largest things;
and ends by measuring it by the smallest thing of all.
There is produced also a sort of subconscious ossification;
which hardens the mind not only against the traditions
of the past, but even against the surprises of the future.
Nil admirari becomes the motto of all nihilists; and it ends,
in the most complete and exact sense, in nothing.
If I had only one sermon to preach, I certainly could not end it
in honour, without testifying to what is in my knowledge the salt
and preservative of all these things. This is but one of a thousand
things in which I have found the Catholic Church to be right,
when the whole world is perpetually tending to be wrong;
and without its witness, I believe that this secret, at once a sanity
and a subtlety, would be almost entirely forgotten among men.
I know that I for one had hardly heard of positive humility until
I came within the range of Catholic influence; and even the things
that I love most, such as liberty and the island poetry of England,
had in this matter lost the way, and were in a fog of self-deception.
Indeed there is no better example of the definition of pride than the
definition of patriotism. It is the noblest of all natural affections,
exactly so long as it consists of saying, "May I be worthy of England."
It is the beginning of one of the blindest forms of Pharisaism
when the patriot is content to say, "I am an Englishman."
And I cannot count it an accident that the patriot has generally
seen the flag as a flame of vision, beyond and better than himself,
in countries of the Catholic tradition, like France and Poland
and Ireland; and has hardened into this heresy of admiring merely
his own breed and bone and inherited type, and himself as a part
of it, in the places most remote from that religion, whether in
Berlin or Belfast. In short, if I had only one sermon to preach,
it would be one that would profoundly annoy the congregation,
by bringing to their attention the permanent challenge of the Church.
If I had only one sermon to preach, I should feel specially confident
that I should not be asked to preach another.
IF DON JOHN OF AUSTRIA HAD MARRIED MARY QUEEN OF SCOTS
Why is it that the world's most famous love story, after the archetypal
story of Adam and Eve, is the story of Antony and Cleopatra? I for
one should answer, to begin with, because of the solid truth
of the story of Adam and Eve. I have often wondered whether,
when the moderns have done playing with that story, burlesquing it,
and turning it upside down and tacking on a modern moral like a new tail,
or expanding it into an evolutionary fantasia that nobody can make head
or tail of, it will ever occur to anybody to see bow sensible it is,
exactly as it stands. Even if it is an old fable, the old fable
is much truer with the old moral. Christians are not constrained,
and least of all Christians of my own confession, to treat Genesis with
the heavy verbalism of the Puritan--the Hebraiser who knows no Hebrew.
But the curious thing is that the more literally we take it the truer
it is; and even if it were materialised and modernised into a story
of Mr. and Mrs. Jones, the old moral would still be the sound one.
A man naked and with nothing of his own is given by a friend the free
run of all the fruits and flowers of a very beautiful estate;
and only asked to promise that he will not interfere with one
particular fruit-tree. If we all talk till we are as old
as Methuselah, the moral remains the same for any honourable man.
If he breaks his word he is a cad; if he says, "I broke my word
because I believe in breaking all limitations and expanding into
infinite progress and evolution, he is ten times more of a cad;
and has, moreover, become a bore as well as a bounder.
But it is this modern suggestion, that Man was right to be bored
with Eden and to demand evolution (otherwise mere change), that is
very relevant to the question I have asked about Antony and Cleopatra.
It is also very relevant to the question I am going to ask about
two other famous figures in history: a woman and a man.
For upon this modern theory the Fall really was the Fall;
for it was the first action that had only tedium as a motive.
Progress began in boredom; and, heaven knows, it sometimes seems
likely to end in it. And no wonder; for of all utter falsehoods
the most false, I think, is this notion that men can be happy
in movement, when nothing but dullness drives them on from behind.
Children, and such happy people, can go on from something they
really like to something they will like more. But if ever there was
a whisper that might truly come from the devil, it is the suggestion
that men can despise the beautiful things they have got, and only
delight in getting new things because they have not got them.
It is obvious that, on that principle, Adam will tire of the tree
just as he has tired of the garden. "It is enough that there
is always a beyond"; that is, there is always something else
to get tired of. All progress based on that mood is truly a Fall;
man did fall, does fall, and we can today see him falling.
It is the great progressive proposition; that he must seek only
for enjoyment because he has lost the power to enjoy.
Now this shadow of failure on all fame and civilisation which the agnostic
poet preferred to call "the something that infects the world,"
and I shall cause general pain by calling Original Sin, does manifest
itself markedly in the sort of historical legends that exist.
But I would urge here that it appears in the historical legends
that do not exist. I refer especially to that grand historical
episode of the heroic honeymoon, otherwise called the marriage
of pure minds, which I study here as closely as is possible in a case
that does not exist. It is a remarkable fact, when we consider
how much happiness love has doubtless given to mankind as a whole,
that mankind has never pointed to any great historical example of a hero
and a heroine wedded in a way entirely worthy of them; of a great man
and a great woman united by a great love that was entirely supreme
and satisfying, as in the tradition of the gigantic loves of Eden.
Anybody who imagines that I am talking pessimism, about ordinary
people in love, will impute to me the very reverse of what I mean.
Millions of people have been happy in love and marriage,
in the ordinary way of human happiness; but then that precisely
consists in a certain commonsense admission of original sin;
in humility and pardon and taking things as they come. But there has
not been any example on the grand scale, of a perfect marriage--that has
remained in human memory like a great monument. All those monuments,
though often of the purest marble, hewn from the loftiest mountain,
have very clearly across them the crack from the earthquake in
the beginning. The noblest knight of the Middle Ages, St. Louis,
was less happy in his marriage than in all other relations.
Dante did not marry Beatrice; he lost his love in infancy and found
her again in Paradise or in a dream. Nelson was a great lover,
but we cannot say that his love made him more great, since it
made him do in Naples the only mean action of his life.
These historic examples have become legends or traditions; but they
have become tragic traditions. And the central literary tradition
of all is that typically tragic one I have named, in which even
perfect love was whimsically imperfect, and certainly suffered by very
imperfect people; in which the hero learned no lesson except delay;
in which the heroine inspired nothing except defeat; in which romance
made him less than a Caesar and has unkindly compared her to a snake;
in which the man was weakened by love and the woman by lovers.
Men have taken Antony and Cleopatra as the perfect love story,
precisely because it is the imperfect love story. It mirrors
the thwarting, the unworthiness, the disproportion which they
have felt as spoiling so many splendid passions and divine desires;
and mirrors them all the more truly because the mirror is cracked.
I imagine that poets will never leave off writing about Antony
and Cleopatra; and all they write will be in the mood of that great
French poet of our own time, who describes the Roman warrior gazing
into the unfathomable eyes of the Egyptian queen, and seeing
beneath a spinning and sparkling light the eddies of a vast sea,
filled with the rout of all his ships.
I have here dared to call up out of the dust another warrior,
whose destiny turned also with the topsails and high poops
of the galleys; and another woman, whose legend also has been
sometimes twisted into the legend of a snake. There was never any
doubt about the beautiful colours or graceful curves of the snake;
but, in fact, the woman was not a snake, but very much of a woman;
even by the account of those who call her a wicked woman.
And the man was not only a warrior, but a conqueror;
and his great ships sweep through history not merely to defeat,
but to a high deliverance, in which he did not lose the empire,
but saved the world. Whatever else we may think of the woman,
none can doubt where her heart would have been in that battle,
or what sort of song of praise she would have sent up after that victory.
There was much about her that was militant, though her life might
well have sickened her of militancy; there was much about him
that was sensitive and sympathetic with that wider world of culture
for which her soul sickened till she died. They were made
for each other; they were in fact the heroic lovers, or perfect
human pair, for whom we have looked elsewhere in history in vain.
There was only one small defect in their purple and impassioned
love story; and that is that they never met.
In truth, this dream began to drift through my mind when I first
read a parenthetical remark by Andrew Lang, in a historical study
about Philip of Spain. Referring to the King's half-brother,
the famous Don John of Austria, Lang remarked casually:
"He intended to carry off Mary Queen of Scots," and added caustically:
"He was incapable of fear." Of course nobody is incapable of fear.
He was certainly, in the common sense, incapable of obeying fear:
but, if I understand the type, he was not incapable of
enjoying fear as an element in a mystery like that of love.
It is exactly because love has lost that slight touch of fear,
that it has become in our time so flat and flippant and vulgar;
when it has not become laboriously biological, not to say bestial.
And Mary was dangerous as well as in danger; that heart-shaped face
looking out of the ruff in so many pictures was like a magnet,
a talisman, a terrible jewel. There was, even then, in the idea
of eloping with the tragic yet attractive Franco-Scottish princess,
all the ancient savour of the romances about delivering a lady
from dragons, or even disenchanting her out of the shape of a dragon.
But though the idea was romantic, it was also in a sense what is
now called psychological; for it exactly answered the personal
needs of two very extraordinary personalities.
If ever there was a man who ought to have rounded off his
victorious career by capturing something more human and spiritual
and satisfying than wreaths of laurel or flags of defeated foes,
it was Don John of Austria. Because his actual historical
life rises on a wave of conquest in relation to these things,
and then sinks again into something less epical and simple,
his life has something of the appearance of an anti-climax;
and reads like a mere stale maxim that all victories are vanities.
He tried to crown his chief exploit by founding a kingdom of his own,
and was prevented by the jealousy of his brother; he then went,
somewhat wearily, I imagine, as the representative of the same
brother to the Flemish fields laid waste by the wars of the Dutch
and the Duke of Alva. He set out to be more merciful and magnanimous
than the Duke of Alva; but he died in a net or tangle of policies;
of which the only touch of poetry was a suggestion of poison.
But in that broad and golden dawn of the Renaissance, full of
classical legends, carrying off Mary Stuart would have been like carrying
off Helen of Troy. In that red sunset of the old chivalric romance
(for the sunrise and the sunset were both in that bewildering sky)
it would have seemed a magnificent materialisation of one of those
strange and stately public love affairs, or knightly services,
which preserved something of the Courts of Love and the pageant
of the Troubadours; as when Rudel publicly pledged himself to an
unknown lady in a castle in the east, almost as distant as a castle
east of the sun; or the sword of Bayard sent across the mountains
its remote salute to Lucretia. That one of these great loves
of the great should actually be achieved in the grand style, that,
I fancy, would have been a wildly popular episode in that epoch.
And to the career of Don John it would have given a climax and a clue
of meaning which its merely military successes could not give;
and handed his name down in history and (what is much more important)
in legend and literature, as a happier Antony married to a
nobler Cleopatra. And when he looked into her eyes he would
not have seen only bright chaos and the catastrophe of Actium,
the ruin of his ships and his hopes of an imperial throne;
but rather the flying curve and crescent of the Christian ships,
sweeping to the rescue of the Christian captives, and blazed upon
their golden sails the sunburst of Lepanto.
The converse is also true. If ever there was a woman who was
manifestly meant, destined, created, and as it were crying aloud
to be carried off by Don John of Austria, or some such person,
it was Mary Queen of Scots. If ever there was a woman who went
to seed for want of meeting any sort of man who was anything like
her equal, it was she. The tragedy of her life was not that she
was abnormal, but that she was normal. It was the crowd all round
her that was abnormal. There is almost a sort of antic allegory,
in that sense, in such accidents as the fact that Rizzio had
a hump and Bothwell some sort of a squint. If her story seems
now to be steeped in morbidity, it was because the mob was morbid.
Unfortunately for this ill-fated queen, she was not morbid.
It is the other characters, each in his own way, which pass before us
in misshapen outlines like the dwarfs and lunatics in some tropic
tragedy of Ford or Webster, dancing round a deserted queen.
And, by a final touch, all these ungainly figures seem more tolerable
than the one that is externally elegant, the hollow doll, Darnley;
just as a handsome waxwork can seem more uncanny than an ugly man.
In that sense she had seen handsome men and ugly men and strong
men and clever men; but they were all half-men; like the hideous
cripples imagined by Flaubert, living in their half-houses with
their half-wives and half-children. She never met a complete man;
and Don John was very complete. In that sense she had been given
many things; the crown of Scotland, the prospect of the crown of France;
the prospect of the crown of England. She had been given everything
except fresh air and the sunlight treatment; and all that is typified
by the great ships with their golden castles and their leaping flags,
that go forth to meet the winds of the world.
We know why Mary Stuart was killed. She was not killed for having
killed her husband, even if she had killed her husband; and recent
study of the Casket Letters suggests that her enemies are more
clearly convicted of forgery than she was ever convicted of murder.
She was not killed for trying to kill Elizabeth, even if the whole
story of trying to kill Elizabeth was not a fiction employed by those
who were trying to kill Mary. She was not killed for being beautiful;
that is one of the many popular slanders on poor Elizabeth.
She was killed for being in good health. Perhaps she was the only person
who was ever condemned and executed merely for being in good health.
The legend which represented Elizabeth as a lioness and Mary as a
sort of sickly snake is largely abandoned; anyhow, it is the very
reverse of the fact. Mary was very vigorous; a strong rider,
and as a dancer almost ready to outrun the Modern Girl.
Curiously enough, her contemporary portraits do not convey
much of her charm, but do convey a great deal of her vigour.
But, as anyone may have noticed in the animal spirits of some of the
finest actresses, vigour has sometimes a great deal to do with charm.
Now it was essential to the policy of Cecil, and the oligarchs
rich with the loot of the old religion, that Mary should die
for Elizabeth, and Mary, despite her misfortunes, did not show
the smallest disposition to die. Elizabeth, on the other hand,
was still dying rather than still living. And when the Catholic
heir inherited, it might go ill with the Protestant lords.
They therefore applied to Mary, at Fotheringay, one of the sharpest
possible remedies for good health, which has seldom been known to fail.
Her energy, which had thus brought her to her death, had also brought
her through her life; and may be the key to many of the riddles
of her life. It may be that her repeated ill-luck in marriage
embittered her more than it might a woman less normal and elemental;
and that the very levities, which led to her being painted as a harlot
or a vampire, sprang from her primary fitness to be a mother and a wife.
It may be (for all I know) that a fairly healthy person, in such a
horrible experience, might have wasted her natural instincts on some
violent adventurer like Bothwell; those things are always possible;
but I confess I could never see that in this case they were necessary.
I have often fancied that the alliance may have been more politic,
and even cynical, than appeared to that fine romantic novelist,
the forger of the Casket Letters. Or it might have been surrender
to a sort of blackmail; it might have been many things.
Anyhow, being surrounded by brutes, she chose the best brute;
though he is always represented as the worst. He was the only one of them
who was a man as well as a brute; and a Scotsman as well as a man.
He at least never betrayed her to Elizabeth; and all the others
did nothing else. He kept the borders of her kingdom against
the English like a good subject and a normal soldier; and she might
very well have thrown herself under his protection for that alone.
But whether or no she sought satisfaction in such a marriage,
I am sure that she never found satisfaction in it; I am sure
she found only a new phase of the long degradation of living
with her inferiors.
There was always in her heart a hunger for civilisation.
It is an appetite not easily appreciated now, when people are
so over-civilised that they can only have a hunger for barbarism.
But she loved culture as the Italian artists of the previous
century had loved it; as something not only beautiful but
bright and shining and new; like Leonardo's first sketches of
flying-machines or the full revelations of perspective and light.
She was the Renaissance chained up like a prisoner; just as
Don John was the Renaissance roaming the world like a pirate.
This was, of course, the perfectly simple explanation of her
frequent and friendly toleration of a hunchback like Rizzio
and a young lunatic like Chastelard. They were Italy and France;
they were music and letters; they were singing-birds from the South
who had happened to perch on her window-sill. If there are still any
historians who suppose that they were anything more to her than that,
especially in the case of the Italian secretary, I can only say
that such learned old gentlemen must be pretty much on the moral
and mental level of Darnley and his company of cut-throats.
Even if she was a wicked woman, there is no sense in supposing
that she was not an intelligent woman, or that she never wished
to turn from her laborious and life-long wickedness for a little
intelligent conversation. The apology for my own (somewhat belated)
experiment in matchmaking is that she might have been very different,
when married to a man who was quite as brave as Bothwell and quite
as intelligent as Rizzio, and, in a more practical and useful fashion,
at least as romantic as Chastelard.
But we must not be romantic; that is, we must not concern ourselves
with the real feelings of real and recognisable human beings.
It is not allowed. We must now sternly turn our attention
to scientific history; that is, to certain abstractions
which have been labelled The Elizabethan Settlement, the Union,
the Reformation, and the Modern World. I will leave the Romantics,
those unpresentable Bohemians (with whom, of course, I would not
be seen for worlds), to decide at what date and crisis they would
like Don John finally to fulfil his design; whether his shining
ship is to appear in the wide waters of the Forth as the mad mob
in Edinburgh is waving scurrilous scrolls and banners before the window
of the Queen; or, on the contrary, a dark boat with a solitary figure
is to slide across the glassy stillness of Loch Leven; or a courier
hot with haste in advance of a new army hurl a new challenge into
the bickering parleys of Carberry, or a herald emblazoned with God
knows what eagles and castles and lions (and presumably a bar sinister)
blow a trumpet before the barred portals of Fotheringay.
I leave that to them; they know all about it. I am an earnest
and plodding student of the dry scientific details of history;
and we really must consider the possible effect on such details
as England, Scotland, Spain, Europe, and the world. We must suppose,
for the sake of argument, that Don John was at least sufficiently
strong to assert Mary's claim to sovereignty in Scotland to begin with;
and, despite the unpleasant moralising of the mob in Edinburgh, I think
such a restoration would have been generally successful in Scotland.
Professor Phillimore used to say that the tragedy of Scotland
was that she had the Reformation without the Renaissance.
And I certainly think that, while Mary and the southern prince were
discussing Plato and Pico della Mirandola, John Knox would have found
himself a little out of his depth. But on the assumption of popular
rulers and a strong Spanish backing, which is the essence of this fantasy,
I should say that a people like the Scots would have gobbled up
the strong meat of the Revival of Learning quicker than anybody else.
But in any case, there is another point to be considered.
If the Scots did not figure prominently in the Renaissance, they had,
in their own way, figured most brilliantly in the Middle Ages.
Glasgow was one of the oldest universities; Bruce was counted the fourth
knight in Christendom; and Scotland, not England, continued the tradition
of Chaucer. The chivalrous side of the regime would surely have
awakened noble memories, even in that ignoble squabble. I must here
unfortunately omit a very fine chapter from the unpublished Romance,
in which the lovers ride down to Melrose (if necessary by moonlight)
to the reputed resting-place of the Heart of Bruce; and recall
(in ringing phrases) how Spanish and Scottish spears had once
charged side by side upon the Saracen, and hurled far ahead,
like a bolt above the battle, the heart of a Scottish King.
This fine piece of prose must not delay us, however, from facing
the next fact; which is that Mary, once safe, would survive
as the Queen of England as well as Scotland. It is enough
to say that medieval memories might have awakened in the North;
and the Scots might even have remembered the meaning of Holyrood.
Don John died trying to keep his temper with Dutch Calvinists,
about ten years before the affair of the Armada; and, much as I
admire him, I am glad he did. I do not want my individual dream
or romance, about the rescue and elopement of Mary Stuart,
mixed up with that famous international collision, in which as
an Englishman I am bound to sympathise with England and as an
Anti-Imperialist with the smaller nation. But, it may be said,
how can an Englishman in any case reconcile himself to a romance
that would involve the Elizabethan policy being overthrown
by a Spanish prince, the throne occupied by a Scottish queen;
or some part at least of the Armada's purposes achieved? To which I
answer that such a question recoils ruinously on those who ask it.
Let them merely compare what might have happened with what did happen.
Was Mary a Scot? We endured one in her son. Was Don John a foreigner?
We submitted to one when we expelled the grandson of her son.
Mary was as English as James the First. Don John was as English
as George the First. The fact is that, whatever else our policy
of insular religion (or whatever we call it) may have done,
it certainly did not save us from alien immigration, or even from
alien invasion. Some may say we could not accept a Spaniard,
when we had been recently fighting the Spaniards. But, when we did
accept a Dutch prince, we had been recently fighting the Dutch.
Blake as well as Drake might complain that his victories had
been reversed; and that we had, after all, allowed the broom of
Van Tromp to sweep not only the English seas, but the English land.
A whole generation before the first George came from Hanover, William of
Orange had marched across England with an invading army from Holland.
If Don John had really brought an Armada with him (and Armadas are often
awkward during elopements) he could hardly have inflicted a heavier
humiliation on us than that. But, of course, the truth is that I am
sensitive on the point of patriotism; much more sensitive than anybody
was in those days. Extreme nationalism is a relatively new religion;
and what these people were thinking of was the old sort of religion.
It really made a great difference to them that Dutch William was
a Calvinist while Don John was a Catholic; and that whatever George
the First was (and he was nearly nothing) he was not a Papist.
That brings me to a much more vital phase of my vision of what
never happened. But those who expect me to break forth into thunders
of theological anathema, will here be rather abruptly disappointed.
I have no intention, I have no need, to argue here about Luther and Leo
and the rights and wrongs of the revolt of new sects in the North.
I need not do so, for the simple reason that I do not believe,
in the case here imagined, that we should have been primarily concerned
about the North. I believe we should have realised instead the enormously
important position in the South; and even more so in the East.
All eyes would have been turned to a far more central battle
of civilisation; and the hero of that battle was Don John of Austria.
It has been remarked, and not untruly, that the Papacy seemed
curiously negligent of the northern danger from Protestantism.
It was; but chiefly because it was not at all negligent of the eastern
danger from Islam. Throughout all that period Pope after Pope
issued appeal after appeal to the princes of Europe to combine
in defence of all Christendom against the Asiatic attack.
They had hardly any response; and only a scratch fleet of their
own galleys with some Venetian, Genoese, and others, could be
sent to stop the Turk from sweeping the whole Mediterranean.
This is the huge historic fact which the northern doctrinal quarrels
have concealed; and that is why I am not concerned here with the northern
doctrinal quarrels. That age was not the age of the Reformation.
It was the age of the last great Asiatic invasion, which very nearly
destroyed Europe. About the time the Reformation was beginning,
the Turks, in the very middle of Europe, destroyed at a blow
the ancient kingdom of Bohemia. About the time the Reformation had
finished its work, the hordes out of Asia were besieging Vienna.
They were foiled by the stroke of Sobieski the Pole,
as a hundred years before by the stroke of Don John of Austria.
But they came as near as that to submerging the cities of Europe.
It must also be remembered that this last Moslem thrust was really
a savage and incalculable thing, compared with the first thrust
of Saladin and the Saracens. The high Arab culture of the Crusades
had long perished; and the invaders were Tartars and Turks and a rabble
from really barbarous lands. It was not the Moors but the Huns.
It was not Saladin against Richard or Averroes against Aquinas;
it was something much more like the worst and wildest shocker
about the Yellow Peril.
I have a great respect for the real virtues and the sane if sleeping
virility of Islam. I like that element in it that is at once
democratic and dignified; I sympathise with many elements in it which
most Europeans (and all Americans) would call lazy and unprogressive.
But when all allowance has been made for these moral merits,
of the simpler sort, I defy anybody with a sense of cultural
comparison to tolerate the image of Europe of the Renaissance given
up to Bashi-Bazouks and the wild Mongol mobs of the decline.
But it is almost as bad if we consider only the vetoes of primitive Islam;
and most of its virtues were vetoes. When all is said,
to the eyes of Mediterranean men especially, there passed across
their shining sea merely the shadow of a great Destroyer.
What they heard was the voice of Azrael rather than Allah.
Theirs was the vision that would have been the background of my dream;
and lifted all its nobler figures, English, Spanish, or Scottish,
into the altitudes of defiance and martyrdom. The dry wind that
drove before it a dust of broken idols was threatening the poised
statues of Angelo and Donatello, where they shine on the high places
around the central sea; and the sand of the high deserts descended,
like moving mountains of dust and thirst and death, on the deep
culture of the sacred vines; and the songs and the deep laughter
of the vineyards. And above all, those clouds that were closing
round them were like the curtains of the harem, from whose corners
look out the stony faces of the eunuchs; there spread like a vast
shadow over shining courts and closing spaces the silence of
the East, and all its dumb compromise with the coarseness of man.
These things, above all, were closing in upon that high and thwarted
romance of the perfect Knight and Lady, which men of the Christian
blood can never attain and never abandon; but which these two alone,
perhaps, might have attained and made one flesh.
Historians quarrel about whether the English under Elizabeth
preferred the Prayer-Book or the Mass-Book. But surely nobody will
quarrel about whether they preferred the Crescent or the Cross.
The learned dispute about how England was divided into Catholics
and Protestants. But nobody will dispute what England would have felt,
when told that the whole world was now desperately divided into
Christians and Mohammedans. In short, I think that under this
influence England would have simply broadened her mind; even if it
were only broadened to take in a big battle instead of a small battle.
Of that broader battle, and our best chances in it, Don John of Austria
was universally regarded as the incarnation and the uplifted sign.
Not only the praise due to heroes, but the flattery inevitably paid
to princes, would have carried that triumph before him wherever
he went like a noise of trumpets. Everybody would have felt in him
both the Renaissance and the Crusade; as those two things are warp
and woof in the golden tapestries of Ariosto. Everybody would
have felt both the rebirth of Europe and its all-but death.
Nor need the praise have come merely from any common flatterers.
All good Englishmen could have become good Europeans; I should
express my meaning better if I said great Europeans. In all
that crowd, perhaps, only Shakespeare could not have been greater.
And yet I am not so sure; for he might certainly have been gayer.
Whatever his politics were (and I suspect they were much like
those of his friend the Catholic Southampton) there is no doubt
that his tragedies are eternally twisted and tortured with something
like an obsession about usurpation and slain kings and stolen crowns;
and all the insecurity of royal and every other right.
Nobody knows how his heart, if not his mind, might have expanded
in that truly "glorious summer" of a sovereignty which satisfied his
sixteenth-century hunger for a heroic and high-hearted sovereign.
He at least would not have been indifferent to the significance of the
great triumph in the Mediterranean. Supporters of the extreme spiritual
insularity have often quoted the great lines in which Shakespeare
praised England, as something separate and cut-off by the sea.
They rather tend to forget what he really praised her for.
This nurse, this teeming womb of royal kings,
Feared by their breed and famous by their birth,
Renowned for their deeds as far from home,
For Christian service and true chivalry,
As is the sepulchre in stubborn Jewry
Of the world's ransom, blessed Mary's Son.
I really think that the man who wrote those lines would have welcomed
the victor of Lepanto almost as warmly as he must have welcomed
a Scotch Calvinist who was frightened of a drawn dirk.
About Mary I imagine there would have been no difficulty at all.
Mary was the perfectly legitimate heir to the throne of England, which is
more than can be said for Elizabeth. The general sense of loyalty
to the legitimate sovereign, which was enormously strong in England,
would have flowed towards her more freely than towards Elizabeth;
because she was a more popular and approachable sort of person.
She who had so often, and perhaps too often, kindled love even in
the very house of hatred, might surely have been loved sufficiently
in a happier household of love enthroned; as in the glowing palace
of René of Provence. I see no difficulty about her popularity;
but even her husband, whether he were called Consort or King,
might surely, to say the least of it, have been as popular
as any other king-consort. I will not say he would be more
popular than William of Orange; for he could not be less.
But the English can be polite to foreigners, even foreign consorts.
Tennyson, as Poet Laureate, was struck by the resemblance
between Prince Albert and an ideal knight of the Round Table.
Ben Jonson, as Poet Laureate, would not have to stretch politeness
quite so far, in order to compare Don John to an Arthurian knight.
At least nobody could say he was a carpet-knight. But, what is much
more important, Britain would have been in another and more real sense
back in Arthurian times. It would be defending the whole tradition
of Roman culture and Christian morals against heathens and barbarians
from the ends of the earth. If that had been fully realised,
do you think anyone would have gone about asking whether a good
Calvinist ought to be a Supralapsarian or a Sublapsarian? It would
no longer be a provincial question of whether some Puritan trooper
had knocked the nose off a stone saint in Salisbury Cathedral;
it would be a question of whether some dervish out of the desert should
dance among the shattered fragments of the Moses of Michelangelo.
All normal Christians, if they had understood the peril, would have
closed up in defence of Christendom. And England would have got
glory in the battle, as she did when that ship with crimson sails
carried the English leopards to the storming of Acre.
It might, I fear, have meant a certain amount of hostility to France:
the rival of the Spanish-Austrian combination; though even here
there are reconciling influences and Mary's sympathies would always
have been with the country of her youth and her most famous poem.
But, anyhow, it would not have been like the hostility to France,
or rather blind hatred of France, which we did inherit from the victory
of the Whigs. It would have been more like the medieval wars
with the French, waged by men who were half French themselves.
The English conquests in France were a sort of eddy and backwash
of the original French conquest in England; the whole business
was almost a civil war. For there was more internationalism
in medieval war than there is in modern peace. The same was true
of the actual wars which did break out between France and Spain;
they did not break the inner unity of the Latin culture.
Louis the Fourteenth was guilty of a slight exaggeration in saying
that the mountains called the Pyrenees have entirely disappeared from
the landscape. Many careful tourists have verified their existence
and reported the royal error. But there was this truth in it;
that the Pyrenees were in every sense a natural division.
The Straits of Dover soon became a very unnatural division.
They became a spiritual abyss, not between different patron saints
but between different gods; perhaps between different universes.
The men who fought at Crecy and Agincourt had the same religion--
to disregard. But the men who fought at Blenheim and at Waterloo
had this entirely novel feature--that the English had an equal hatred
for French religion and for French irreligion. They could not understand
the ideals of either side in the great civil war of all civilisation.
The limitation was really rather like the Straits of Dover,
being both narrow and bleak and dangerous enough to be decisive;
bitter as the sea and aptly symbolised by sea-sickness. Perhaps,
after all, there was a point in the tale told in our nursery histories--
that it was the last Catholic queen who felt the loss of the last
French possession, and had "Calais" written on her heart.
With her died, perhaps, the last of that spirit which had somewhere
in its depths a spiritual Channel Tunnel.
But this linking up of Europe in the Renaissance would
have made easier and not harder the linking up of Europe
in the Revolution; in the sense of the general Reform that was
really rational and necessary in the eighteenth century.
It would have been larger and clearer in its tests and ideals,
if it had not been anticipated by a mere triumph of the richest
aristocrats over the English crown. If England had not become
entirely a country of squires, it might have become, like Spain,
a country of peasants; or at any rate remained a country of yeomen.
It might have stood the siege of commercial exploitation and
commercial decline, of mere employment followed by mere unemployment.
It might have learned the meaning of equality as well as liberty.
I know at least one Englishman who wishes to-day that he were as
hopeful about the immediate future of England as about the immediate
future of Spain. But in my vision they might have learned from each
other and produced, among other things, one prodigious consequence;
America would be a very different place.
There was a moment when all Christendom might have clustered together
and crystallised anew, under the chemistry of the new culture;
and yet have remained a Christendom that was entirely Christian.
There was a moment when Humanism had the road straight before it;
but, what is even more important, the road also straight behind it.
It might have been a real progress, not losing anything of what was
good in the past. The significance of two people like Mary Stuart
and Don John of Austria is that in them Religion and the Renaissance
had not quarrelled; and they kept the faith of their fathers while full
of the idea of handing on new conquests and discoveries to their sons.
They drew their deep instincts from medieval chivalry without
refusing to feed their intellects on the sixteenth-century learning;
and there was a moment when this spirit might have pervaded the whole
world and the whole Church. There was a moment when religion could
have digested Plato as it had once digested Aristotle. For that matter,
it might have digested all that is soundest in Rabelais and Montaigne
and many others; it might have condemned some things in these thinkers;
as it did in Aristotle. Only the shock of the new discoveries
could have been absorbed (to a great extent indeed it was absorbed)
by the central Christian tradition. What darkened that dawn
was the dust and smoke from the struggles of the dogmatising
sectaries in Scotland, in Holland, and eventually in England.
But for that, on the Continent, the heresy of Jansenism had never so much
over-shadowed the splendour of the Counter-Reformation. And England
would have gone the way of Shakespeare rather than the way of Milton;
which latter degenerated rapidly into the way of Muggleton.
There is perhaps, therefore, something more than a fancy,
certainly something more than an accident, in this connection between
the two romantic figures and the great turning-point of history.
They might really have turned it to the right rather than the left;
or at least prevented it from turning too far to the left.
The point about Don John of Austria is that, like Bayard and a few
others in that transition, he was unmistakably the original
medieval knight, with the wider accomplishments and ambitions
of the Renaissance added to him. But if we look at some of
his contemporaries, as for instance, at Cecil, we see an entirely
new type, in which there is no such combination or tradition.
A man like Cecil is not chivalrous, does not want to be chivalrous, and
(what is most important of all) does not pretend to be chivalrous.
Of course there was sham chivalry, as there is a sham of everything;
and mean and treacherous medieval men made a false parade of it
with pageants and heraldry. But a mean man like Cecil did not make
any parade of it, or any pretence of it. So far as he knew or cared,
it had gone clean out of the world. Yet in fact it had not gone;
and a great rally of it among his foes would still have commanded
the natural loyalty of Europeans. That is what makes this story
so strange; that the forces were there for the deliverance.
The Romance of the North could really have replied to the Romance
of the South, the rose crying to the laurel; and she who had changed
songs with Ronsard, and he who had fought side by side with Cervantes,
might truly have met by the very tide and current of their time.
It was as if a great wind had turned northward, bearing a gallant ship;
and far away in the North a lady opened her lattice upon the sea.
It never happened. It was too natural to happen. I had almost
said it was too inevitable to happen. Anyhow, there was
nothing natural, let alone inevitable, about what did happen.
Now and again Shakespeare, with a horror almost bordering
on hysteria, will thrust into the limelight some clown or idiot,
to suggest, against the black curtain of tragedy, this incongruity
and inconsequence in the things that really do happen.
The dark curtains open and there comes forth something; certainly not
the Lion of Lepanto clad in gold, nor the Heart of Holyrood, the queen
of the poets, who called up the songs of Ronsard and Chastelard;
but something quite different and doubtless a sort of comic relief:
Jacobus Rex, the grotesque king; clumsy, querulous, padded like
an armchair; pedantic; perverted. He had been brought up
carefully by the elders of the True Kirk, and he did them credit;
piously explaining that he could not bring himself to save his
mother's life because of the superstition to which she was attached.
He was a good Puritan; a typical Prohibitionist; intolerant of tobacco;
more tolerant of torture and murder and things yet more unnatural.
For though he shook with terror at the very shape of the shining sword,
he had no difficulty about consigning Fawkes to the rack,
and when death had merely been attained by the art of poisoning,
he was ready with a pardon, as he cowered under the threats of Carr.
What things lay behind those threats and that pardon there is here,
I am glad to say, no need to inquire; but the stink of that court,
as it reaches us through the purlieus of the Overbury Murder,
is such as to make us turn for fresh air. I will not say to the ideal
loves of Mary and Don John of Austria, which I have merely imagined,
but to the very worst version of the bloody loves of Mary
and Bothwell which their most furious enemies have denounced.
Compared with all that, loving Bothwell would be as innocent
as plucking a rose, and killing Darnley as natural as pulling
up a weed.
And so, after that one wild glimpse of the possibility of the impossible,
we sink back at the best into a series of third-rate things.
Charles the First was better, a man sad and proud, but good
so far as a man can be good without being good-humoured. Charles
the Second was good-humoured without being good; but the worst
of him was that his life was a long surrender; James the Second had
his grandfather's virtues, so far as they went, and was therefore
betrayed and broken. Then came William the Dutchman, with whom
there again enters the savour of something sinister and alien.
I would not suggest that such Calvinists were Antinomian Calvinists;
but there is something strange in the thought that twice,
in that time, there entered with that unnatural logic the rumour
and savour of unnatural desire. But by the time we come to Anne and
the first featureless George, it is no longer the King that counts.
Merchant princes have superseded all other princes; England is
committed to mere commerce and the capitalist development;
and we see successively established the National Debt,
the Bank of England, Wood's Halfpence, the South Sea Bubble,
and all the typical institutions of Business Government.
I will not discuss here whether the modern sequel, with its
cosmopolitan trusts, its complicated and practically secret
financial control, its march of machinery and its effacement of
private property and personal liberty, be on the whole good or bad.
I will only express an intuition that, even if it is very good,
something else might have been better. I need not deny that in certain
respects the world has progressed in order and philanthropy; I need only
state my suspicion that the world might have progressed much quicker.
And I think that the northern countries, especially, would have
progressed much quicker, if the philanthropy had been from the first
guided by a larger philosophy, like that of Bellarmine and More;
if it had drawn directly from the Renaissance and not been deflected
and delayed by the sulky sectarianism of the seventeenth century.
But in any case the great moral institutions of modern times,
the Straddle, the Wheat Corner, the Merger, and the rest will
not be affected by my little literary fancy; and I need feel no
responsibility if I waste some hours of my inefficient existence
in dreaming of the things that might have been (which the determinists
will tell me could never have been) and in weaving this faded
chaplet for the prince of heroes and the queen of hearts.
Perhaps there are things that are too great to happen, and too
big to pass through the narrow doors of birth. For this world
is too small for the soul of man; and, since the end of Eden,
the very sky is not large enough for lovers.
The following is a Gaslight etext...
from Recent essays
edited by W.A.J. Archbold
Longmans, Green and Co. Ltd. (1926)
IF NAPOLEON HAD WON THE BATTLE OF
WATERLOO
BY G. MACAULAY TREVELYAN
In July 1907 the Westminster Gazette
offered a prize for an essay on this subject.
This was the successful essay.
THE day of the signature of the Convention of Brussels, June 26, 1815, is the
point of time that divides into two strangely contrasted halves the greatest car
eer of modern times, and ushers in the reign of the Napoleon of Peace. When, in
that little room in the Hôtel de Ville, now filled every morning by crowds of tour
ists, the red-coated patrician, who had once been regarded by his partial countr
ymen as the rival of the lord of armies, sat listening in proud and stoical humi
liation to the torrent of words poured forth in dispraise of war by his perambul
atory host, who, with clenched fists, invoked the Goddess of Peace, the laconic
Englishman probably thought that he was present at a Napoleonic farce of the usu
al character. He did not guess that his conqueror had in all truth drained the c
up of Peace, a draught as bitter to Napoleon as Defeat was bitter to his conquer
ed foe. Wellington, indeed, during the terrible week between the battle and the
Convention, had not uttered one complaint against Blucher for breaking tryst, no
r shown to his staff-officers one sign of his agony -- beyond the disuse of his
customary oaths.
A new Napoleon had been evolved, the Napoleon of Peace, a mere shadow, in spir
itual and intellectual force, of his former self. The Buonaparte of 1796 would h
ave urged the advance of Ney's columns until they had destroyed the last of Well
ington's regiments, and would himself, with the bulk of his army, have fallen on
the traces of Blucher, instead of suffering him to effect a junction with the A
ustrians and Russians, and so present a barrier to the French reconquest of Germ
any. Nor would the Napoleon of 1813, who refused, in defeat, the most favourable
offers of a settlement, have hesitated after such a victory as that of Mont St.
Jean to undertake with a light heart the subjugation of Central and Eastern Eur
ope. But the Napoleon of 1815, one week after his triumphal entry into Brussels,
was offering to Wellington the same facilities to evacuate the scat of war whic
h the English general had offered at Cintra, seven years before, to the defeated
lieutenant of the Emperor. And this unexpected clemency was extended to England
, in order as easily and as quickly as possible to remove from the scene of affa
irs and from the counsels of the Continental monarchs the paymaster and invetera
te instigator of war, and so to clear the stage for Napoleon and the time-servin
g Metternich to arrange by collusion a permanent and lasting peace for all Europ
e, not exclusive of England herself.
Whence came this extraordinary change in the intentions, one might say in the
character, of the French Emperor? The history of what passed in the headquarters
at Brussels between June 16 and 26 can never be fully known, though whole libra
ries have been written upon the subject. Secret agents of Metternich had been in
Brussels as early as June 14, with orders, in case Wellington were defeated, in
stantly to offer Napoleon the Rhine frontier and the bulk of the Italian Peninsu
la, and to represent to him how utterly impossible it was that he should hold do
wn Germany after the national movement of 1813. The latter argument, though base
d upon a just insight into the condition of the Fatherland, would have had littl
e effect upon the man to whom it was addressed had he been sure of support from
France herself. But, so far from being dazzled by the news of Mont St. Jean, Par
is, on June 20, formed a determined alliance of all classes and all parties -- L
iberals, Jacobins, Royalists, and old servants of the Empire, -- to insist upon
peace. The representatives commissioned by the Chambers and by other bodies, off
icial and unofficial alike, were welcomed in the Belgian capital, and supported
in their petition by all the marshals and by almost every superior officer. But
Napoleon's will, it appears, was not finally overcome until the great review of
June 24, held outside the town for the purpose of testing the attitude of the co
mmon soldiers. Though most of them were veterans, they had too lately rejoined t
he camp to be altogether insensible to the national feeling; many of them had co
me out to liberate France, not to subjugate Europe -- a task which no longer see
med as easy as before the days of Borodino and Leipzig. The long shout for "Peac
e" that ran down the lines seems to have dazed the Emperor. He spoke no word to
the assembled troops to thank them for the late victory, rode slowly back like o
ne in a trance, dismounted in the square, passed through the ante-chamber starin
g vacantly at his marshals and Ministers as if on men whom he had never seen bef
ore. As he reached the threshold of his cabinet his eye lit upon the Mameluke by
the door, who alone in all the crowd was gazing with intense devotion on his ma
ster. The Corsican stopped, and still in a reverie, interpellated the Oriental:
"The Franks are tired of war, and we two cannot ride out alone. Besides, we are
growing old. One grows old and dies. The Pyramids they grow old, but they do not
die." Then, with intense energy, he added: "Do you think one will be remembered
after forty centuries?" He stood for a moment, as if waiting for an answer from
the mute, then dashed through the door, flung himself at the table, and began d
ictating messages of peace to Wellington and the allied Sovereigns.
Napoleon's physical condition probably contributed no less than the attitude o
f the French army and people to the formation of his great resolution; during th
e critical week, the decision between peace and war seems to have been as much a
s he could attend to in his waking hours, which were greatly curtailed by his pe
culiar malady. Hence it was that he made no serious effort to follow Blucher's r
etreat through Namur, beyond leaving a free hand to Grouchy. Though he was not y
et sufficiently cognisant of his growing feebleness to delegate to anyone either
his military or political duties, he seems to have been subconsciously aware th
at the two together were beyond his strength. It is, therefore, not strange that
he decided to accept the Rhine frontier and the hegemony in the Italian Peninsu
la as the basis of a permanent peace, and that his ever-increasing lassitude of
body kept him faithful to the decision during the last twenty years of his life.
Those years were a period of but slight change for Europe. Monarchs and people
s were too much exhausted to engage in war for the alteration of frontiers; inte
rnal reform or revolution was rendered impossible by the great standing armies,
which the very existence of Napoleon on the French throne, valetudinarian though
he was known to be, rendered necessary, or at least excusable, in England, Aust
ria, and the German States. Hatred of the crowned Jacobin, and fear of renewed F
rench invasions, gave to the Governments of the ancien régime a measure of popular
ity with the middle classes which they would not otherwise have enjoyed; it has
even been suggested that reform might have made some notable step forward in Eng
land within twenty years of Mont St. Jean, had the great Tory champion succeeded
in overthrowing the revolutionary Emperor on the field of battle.
As it was, the condition of England was most unhappy. In spite of the restorat
ion of trade with the Continent impeded indeed by the extravagantly high tariffs
due to Napoleon's military ideas of economic science, in spite of our continued
supremacy at sea, the distress grew yearly more intolerable, both among the rur
al and industrial populations. The taxation necessary for the maintenance of bot
h fleet and army on a war footing allowed no hope of amelioration; yet while Nap
oleon lived and paraded his own army and fleet as the expensive toys of his old
age, the Tory Ministers could see no possibility of reduction on their part. Pro
bably they were glad of the excuse, for the great army enabled them to defy the
Reformers, who became ever more violent as year after year passed by without pro
spect of change. If Mont St. Jean had been a victory for England, and if it had
been followed by that general disarmament to which Wellington himself had looked
forward as the natural consequence of Napoleon's downfall, Catholic Emancipatio
n must have been granted to Ireland, and this concession would at least have ave
rted the constant revolts and massacres in that unhappy country which so sorely
tempted Napoleon to resume hostilitie's during the last ten years of his life. I
n Great Britain, where starvation and repression were the order of the day, ther
e occurred in 1825 the ill-advised but romantic rebellion of Lord Byron, in whos
e army the rank and file consisted almost entirely of working men, and the leade
rs (except Napier) had no more knowledge of war than was possessed by such ruffi
ans as Thistlewood and the ex-pirate Trelawny. The savage reprisals of Governmen
t established the blood-feud between one half of England and the other. The exec
ution of Lord Byron made a greater noise in the world than any event since the f
all of the Bastille, though it was not immediately followed by political changes
. After two years of terror, Canning, who was always suspected by his colleagues
of semi-populax sympathies, restored partial freedom of the Press in 1827, and
it became apparent in the literature of the next decade that all young men of sp
irit were no longer anti-Jacobins -- no longer even Whigs, but Radicals. The wor
ship of the dead poet went side by side with the worship of the living. The writ
ings of Shelley, especially after his long imprisonment, obtained a popularity w
hich was one of the most curious symptoms of the time. His "Men of England, wher
efore plough?" was sung at all Radical gatherings, and his ode on the death of N
apoleon (The Dead Anarch, 1836) passed through twenty-five editions in a year. T
he younger literary stars, like Tennyson and Arthur Hallam, blazed with revoluti
onary ardour. Excluded from Oxford and Cambridge, the Dissenters and Radicals fo
rmed a University at Manchester, which soon almost monopolised the talent of the
country. Meanwhile serious politicians like Lord John Russell and the irrepress
ible Mr. Brougham abandoned the older Whig creed and declared for Universal Suff
rage. No wise man, in the year after Napoleon's death, would have foretold with
confidence whether England was destined to tread the path of revolution or to co
ntinue in the beaten track of tyranny and obscurantism. At least, it was clear t
hat there was no longer any third way open to her, and that the coming era would
be stained with blood and violence. Whiggery died with Grey -- that pathetic an
d futile figure, who had waited forty years in vain. The English character was n
o longer one of compromise; it was being forced by foreign circumstances into an
other and more violent mould.
Similarly in the Continental States outside the limits of the Napoleonic Empir
e, the ancien régime was not only triumphant but to some extent popular and nation
al, because the late persecutor of the German and Spanish peoples still remained
as their dangerous neighbour, and was still by far the most powerful prince in
Europe. In Spain the Liberals and Freethinkers were extirpated with an efficienc
y which Torquemada might have approved; the Inquisition was indeed abolished in
consequence of Napoleon's threat of war in 1833, a year in which the Tories were
unable to give Spain diplomatic support, because the execution of the eccentric
"gypsy-Englishman" for smuggling Bibles into Andalusia had raised a momentary s
torm among their Evangelical supporters in the House and country. But the disapp
earance of the Inquisition made no real difference to the methods of Church and
State in Spain, and the diplomatic incident only served, as it was intended, to
restore the old Emperor's popularity with the French Liberals.
Meanwhile the revolted Spanish colonies in South America continued their effor
ts for freedom with ever-increasing success until the interference of the Englis
h army, sent out by Government on pure anti-Jacobin principles, against the wish
and the interest of the British merchants trading in those parts. "We must pres
erve," said Castlereagh, "the balance between monarchy and Republicanism in the
New World as in the Old." But not enough troops could be spared from policing th
e British Islands to do more than prolong the agony of the Transatlantic struggl
e. The vast expanses of the Pampas became a permanent Field of Mars, where liber
al exiles and adventurers of all countries, principally English and Italian, sid
e by side with the well-mounted Gauchos, waged a ceaseless guerilla war on the E
nglish and Spanish regulars. Here Napier's brothers avenged his death on the arm
y of which they had once been the ornaments; and Murat, riding-whip in hand, was
seen at the head of many a gallant charge, leading on the Italians whose idol h
e had now become in either hemisphere. "The free life of the Pampas" became to t
he young men of Europe the symbol of that spiritual and political emancipation w
hich could be realised only in exile and secured in rebellion and in war. Hence
it is that the note of the Pampas is as prevalent as the note of Byron in the li
terature and art of that epoch.
In Germany the national hopes of union and liberty were cheated by the monarch
s, who continued, however, to enjoy safety, prestige, and the bodyguard of those
great standing armies which were necessary to secure French respect for the Rhi
ne frontier. The reforms previously effected in those German States which had be
en either subject to Napoleon's rule or moved by his example, were permitted to
remain, wherever they made for the strength of the monarchic principle. The Prus
sian peasants were not thrust back into serfdom; the reformed Civil Service was
kept in some of the "Westphalian" States; the Act of Mediation and the Abolition
of the Prince-Bishoprics were maintained for the benefit of the larger princes.
But all traces of the Code Napoléon were abolished in Hesse-Cassel and Hanover; w
hile the University and National movements were effectively suppressed throughou
t the Fatherland under Austrian influence, paramount since the failure of Blücher
in Flanders and the deal between Metternich and Napoleon at the Conference of Vi
enna in 1815. If Prussia obtained nothing else, she recovered her share of Polan
d whose cries were smothered by the Christian Powers of the East as easily as Gr
eece was put down by the Turk.
The only Germans who were at once contented and well governed were those on th
e left bank of the Rhine, who continued to be, in peace as in war, the quietest
and most loyal of all Napoleon's subjects. The French were less easy to satisfy;
they had, indeed, forced their lord to make peace, but could they also compel h
im to grant that measure of liberty which they now claimed? The solution of that
question would scarcely have been possible except by violent means had the Empe
ror retained half of his old health and vigour. But it was solved provisionally
from year to year, because the energies of the autocrat decreased in almost exac
t proportion to the increase of his subjects' demand for freedom. He cared not w
ho wielded powers which he was no longer in a condition to exercise himself, and
was ready, out of sheer indifference, to hand them scornfully over to Ministers
more or less in sympathy with the Chambers. So long as he could keep his own ey
e on the censorship, it was rigid; but when he became too ill to read anything e
xcept the most important despatches, the censorship was again as feebly administ
ered as in the days of the last two Bourbons. Under these conditions of irritati
ng but ineffectual repression, French literature and thought were stimulated int
o a life almost as flourishing as in the days of the Encyclopædists. The Romantic
movement undermined the Imperial idea with the intellectuals; the "breath of the
Pampas" was felt in the Quartier Latin. It was in vain that the police broke th
e busts of Byron and forbade plays in which the unities were violated.
Yet as long as Napoleon lived and let live the Liberals, the quarrel of the ru
led against their ruler was but half serious. The movement towards a fresh revol
ution was rather a preparation for his death than a very deliberate disloyalty t
o the man who had saved France from the ancien régime. And whatever the workmen an
d students might think, the peasants and soldiers regarded the political and soc
ial condition of France after Mont St. Jean as almost perfect. The soldiers were
still the favourites of Government; the peasants at length tilled in peace and
security the lands which their fathers had seized from the nobles and the clergy
. The religion of the vast majority of Frenchmen was respected, but the priest w
as confined to the church; the home and the women belonged to the father of the
family, and the school to the state.
Indeed, the chief cause of complaint against Napoleon's government, in the eye
s of the majority of his subjects, was not political, social, or religious, but
administrative. The executive machine at Paris, to which the life of the remotes
t hamlets was "mortised and adjoined," worked with an inefficiency resultant on
the bad health of the autocrat. His personal attention to business became more a
nd more irregular, and since the ineradicable tradition of the imperial service
was to wait upon his initiative, France was scarcely better governed from the Tu
ileries in 1820 than she had been in 1807 from the camp-fires of Poland.
In the treaties of Autumn 1815 the wily Metternich had succeeded by a masterpi
ece of cunning, in retaining the Venetian territories for Austria, as the price
of abandoning at the conference the claims of Prussia to expansion in Germany. A
s in Northern Europe the Rhine, so in Italy the Mincio, became the geographic bo
undary between the Napoleonic system and the ancien régime -- both as yet rather f
eebly threatened by the rising spirit of Italian nationality. Murat, who had by
his recent conduct fairly sacrificed the goodwill of both parties, lost his king
dom and fled to South America. No one dared to propose to Napoleon the restorati
on of the temporal power of the Pope; it had, indeed, no more claim to recogniti
on than that of the Prince-Bishops, whose recently secularised territories none
of the German Princes proposed to restore. Sicily, protected by the British ship
s, remained to the House of Bourbon. From the moment that the signature of peace
the fear of the French invasion, British influence waned at Palermo, and the ol
d methods of Sicilian despotism returned. But the fact that the King of Sicily w
as obliged by the Powers to renounce all his claims to the throne of Naples stoo
d him in good stead with his insular subjects, whose jealousy was appeased by th
is act of separation.
All the Italian peninsula, except the territory of Venice, was subject to the
unifying influence of the French Imperial system. The Code Napoléon, the encourage
ment of the middle class, the abeyance of clerical influence in government and e
ducation in favour of military and official ideals, continued as before the peac
e. The Clerical and Liberal forces, still divided by the deadliest enmity, which
would certainly break out in bloodshed if the foreigner were ever to be expelle
d from Italy, were alike hostile to the French. But, whereas the Clericals hoped
to restore the ancien regime, either by extending the Austrian dominions or cal
ling back the native Princes, and especially the Pope, the Liberals, on the othe
r hand, dreamed of an Italian Republic. These two movements were represented to
Italy and to the world, the one by the Prince of the House of Savoy, the hope of
the reactionaries; and the other by the son of the Genoese doctor, the founder
of the formidable "Società Savonarola," in which many of the rising generation has
tened to enlist themselves. In 1832 both these romantic young men fell victim Na
poleon's police; Charles Albert was detected in disguise in Turin, and suffered
the fate of the Duc d'Enghien. Mazzini, who had the year before escaped with dif
ficulty from the Venetian Alps, where he had raised the national flag against Au
stria, attempted a rising against Napoleon in the streets of Genoa, but being op
posed by the Italian soldiery, who found all that they wanted in the existing régi
me, was captured and shot, with twelve of his followers.
The executions of the Savoyard Prince and the Genoese prophet served to remind
Europe that Napoleon, in his old age, still remained, as in his youth, the enem
y alike of the ancien régime and of democratic liberty. Which of the two would be
the chief gainer by his death it was impossible to predict.
On the evening of June 4, 1836, Napoleon was presiding, with even more than hi
s habitual invalid's lethargy, at one of his Councils of State. The latest repor
ts from Italy were presented, and a closer entente with the Austrian police was
under discussion. The Emperor had been sitting, silent and distracted, his head
sunk on his breast. Suddenly the word "Italy" penetrated to his consciousness. H
e looked up with fire in his eyes. "Italy!" he said; "we march to-morrow. The ar
my of the Alps will deserve well of the Republic." Then, more distractedly, he m
urmured: "I must leave Josephine behind. She will not care." He had often of lat
e been talking thus of his first Empress, whom he seemed to imagine to be somewh
ere in the palace, but unwilling to see him. It was the custom of the Council, d
ictated by the physicians, to adjourn as soon as he mentioned her name. The Mini
sters therefore retired.
The rest of the story can best be told by M. Villebois, physician of the Imper
ial Household:
"While the Council sat I was walking in the Tuileries Gardens below. It was a
hot and silent night of June. The city was at rest and the trees slept with her.
Suddenly from the open window of the Council Chamber, a noise, inconceivably un
melodious, makes itself heard. I look up, and behold the Emperor standing alone
at the balcony, with the lights behind him framing him like a picture. With the
gestures of a wild animal just set free, he is intoning, in a voice of the most
penetrating discord, the Revolutionary hymn of France, which he has forbidden un
der penalty of the law to the use of his subjects. But to him, I know it, it is
not a hymn of revolution but a chant du depart. I rush upstairs, and find a grou
p of Ministers and lackeys trembling outside the door. No one dares enter. 'Doct
or,' said old Marshal ----, 'he sang that cursed song like that the night before
we crossed into Russia. On that occasion we stood in the room below and tremble
d, and one told me that he had sung it thus, in solitude, on the night before he
first crossed into Italy.'
"Pushing past the brave old man, I opened the door and entered alone. The soun
d had now ceased, but the song had penetrated through the summer night, and in t
he Rue de Rivoli a drunken ouvrier had caught it up and was thundering it out. I
looked round for my master, and did not at first see him. Suddenly I perceived
that Napoleon was lying dead at my feet. I heard the oaths of the ouvrier as the
police seized him under the arcade."
(End.) 1

You might also like