2003 - Michael Pakaluk - Degrees of Separation in The Phaedo
2003 - Michael Pakaluk - Degrees of Separation in The Phaedo
2003 - Michael Pakaluk - Degrees of Separation in The Phaedo
MICHAEL PAKALUK
ABSTRACT
It can be shown that, if we assume Ôsubstance dualismÕ, or the real distinctness
of the soul from the body, then the standard objections to the Cyclical Argument
in the Phaedo fail. So charity would presumably require that we take substance
dualism to be presupposed by that argument.
To do so would not beg any question, since substance dualism is a signi cantly
weaker thesis than the immortality of the soul. Moreover, there is good textual
evidence in favor of this presumption. A closer look at the immediately preced-
ing passage, viz. ÒSocratesÕ DefenseÓ, reveals an argument for a real distinction
between soul and body, not unlike DescartesÕ famous argument, based on the
identi cation of an activity in which the soul can in principle engage on its own,
without assistance from the body.
The argumentative project of the Phaedo, on this reading, becomes: given that
the soul is really distinct, show that it is immortal. And Plato aims to do this in
two stages. The three initial arguments are meant to establish merely the mini-
mal claim that the continued existence of the soul across cycles of reincarnation
is the most plausible view to take, given substance dualism; and it is left to the
Final Argument to argue for something that we might regard as immortality, that
is, the imperishability of the soul, come what may.
The three initial arguments for immortality in the Phaedo – the Cyclical
Argument (CA), the Recollection Argument (RA), and the Af nity
Argument (AA) – are preceded by a passage in which Socrates, as if on
trial, defends himself against the charge that he is being reckless in not
resisting death (63a3-69e5). What is the function of this passage, typically
called ÔSocratesÕ DefenseÕ (SD)? A common view is that the passage is
simply SocratesÕ profession of ÔfaithÕ in life after death; 1 and, in the
remainder of the dialogue, Socrates tries to give plausible reasons for this
ÔfaithÕ – just perhaps succeeding in his nal attempt. Another common
view is that SD is of merely rhetorical or literary signi cance, and that
the argumentation of the dialogue begins properly with CA.2 I shall take
a different approach. On my reading, the philosophical substance of the
Phaedo begins properly with SD, which should be understood as offering
an argument for a real distinction between soul and body, roughly analo-
gous to the famous argument of Descartes. The arguments that follow
upon SD, then, naturally enough take this distinction for granted. Yet
when we read the dialogue in this way, we see that its successive argu-
ments are cumulative and constructive: in PlatoÕs intention, the Phaedo is
not a dialogue of Ôfaith seeking reasonsÕ so much as of reason strength-
ening and con rming itself. And SocratesÕ arguments in the end are prob-
lematic, not because they are in some crude way fallacious, but rather
because they articulate and defend, with some power and success, a philo-
sophical dualism which is deeply problematic.
I develop my interpretation by defending four claims: (I) on the
assumption of substance dualism, CA is not evidently unsound; (II) sub-
stance dualism is asserted in SD; (III) SD argues for substance dualism;
(IV) SD was intended by Plato to provide the context of the three initial
arguments and therefore counts as the Ôprimary argumentÕ of the Phaedo.
2
David Gallop says that CA is the rst in Ò. . . the series of arguments that form
the core of the dialogueÓ (Plato: Phaedo, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), 103. C.J.F.
Williams refers to CA as Ò[t]he rst solid bit of argumentation you get in PlatoÕs
PhaedoÓ, in ÒOn DyingÓ, Philosophy 1969 (44) 217-30.
DEGREES OF SEPARATION IN THE PHAEDO 91
10. Thus, living things do not perish when they come to be dead, and in
this sense they are immortal.
PlatoÕs strategy is to connect this present life of a living thing with a pre-
vious life; that done, he draws the general conclusion that living things
were previously alive; yet, he reasons, they could not have come alive
again, if they did not endure in the interval between their previous life
and their current one; and thus, as regards any living thing, we can have
some con dence that it will continue to endure, in the interval after this
current life and before its next life.
Thus stated, the argument is clearly unsound, because the rst premise
is in need of two familiar quali cations. That Ôopposites come from oppo-
sitesÕ is true only if: (i) we presume that we are not dealing with a case
of simple generation, where something comes to be F only in coming to
be simpliciter; and (ii) the opposites are ÔcontradictoryÕ, rather than mere
ÔcontraryÕ opposites. But if premise 1. is quali ed accordingly, premise 2.
needs to be revised: being dead and being alive are not contradictory
opposites, since there are things that are neither dead nor alive. Yet if we
rewrite premise 2., so that it involves opposites that are properly contra-
dictory, e.g. ÔBeing not alive and being alive are opposite attributesÕ, then
premise 5. needs to be changed accordingly, becoming: ÔEverything that
is not alive was previously aliveÕ – which is evidently false.
It would be good to have a diagnosis of why the argument goes wrong,
and for this purpose GallopÕs commentary is particularly useful. Gallop
correctly notes, for instance, that Plato in CA tends to speak as though it
is the soul which comes to be alive, rather than the animal, but – Gallop
objects – this Òinsinuates a view of ÔbirthÕ in which the soulÕs discarnate
existence is already covertly assumed. And since that is precisely what
the argument purports to prove, the very conception of incarnation can be
seen to beg the essential questionÓ (105). Again, Gallop wonders why we
shouldnÕt understand Ôbeing deadÕ (in our premise 2. above) to mean, sim-
ply, Ôceasing to existÕ, in which case, clearly, Ôbeing aliveÕ and Ôbeing
deadÕ could not be treated as opposing predicates, as CA requires, since
one would, in that case, be treating existence as though it were a predi-
cate. Speculating on why Plato might have resisted this identi cation, Gallop
remarks that Òa wedge might be driven between Ôbeing deadÕ and Ôceas-
ing to existÕ by treating SocratesÕ soul as a separate subject, distinct from
Socrates himself, and alternating between incarnate and discarnate states.
But this would be, once again, to assume what has to be provedÓ (106).
Again, objecting to (our) premise 3. above, Gallop remarks that ÒThe
sense of Ôcoming to be aliveÕ required for the argument is not that in
92 MICHAEL PAKALUK
which a living thing comes into being, but that in which a soul Ôbecomes
incarnateÕ in a living body. Yet it cannot do this unless it already exists
before birth or conception. And whether it does so or not is just what is
at issueÓ (110).3
So Gallop maintains that CA goes awry because Plato begs the ques-
tion, surreptitiously supposing that the soul is a distinct subject, indepen-
dent of the body. (Call this view Ôsubstance dualismÕ, for short.4)
Yet because one manÕs begging the question is simply another manÕs
tacit assumption, we might wonder how CA would fare, if we were to add
new premises that made this assumption explicit.
Let us assume:
I. Every living thing has a soul, which is a distinct substance from the
body.
II. Death is the complete separation of a soul from any body. 5 That is,
death and life are states of a soul, which we de ne as follow:
1. To be dead = to be completely separated from any body.
2. To be alive = to be joined to some body.
By these de nitions, being alive and being dead are indeed contradictory
opposites. Furthermore, the generation of a living thing becomes simply
the combination, or coming together, of two elements, body and soul; and
the destruction of a living thing would be their separation.
We may then restate the argument. First we introduce the necessary
quali cation in the rst premise, making it explicit that the principle involves
contradictory opposites:
1. Anything that comes to take on an attribute which has a contradictory
opposite, previously had that opposite attribute.
We also rewrite the next two premises in accordance with our new
assumptions:
3
He adds: ÒA thing cannot be said to Ôcome to life againÕ in the sense required by
the argument, unless the persistence of an independent subject, Ôthe soulÕ, is already
assumed. Yet this is just what has to be provedÓ (110).
4
We should not take this phrase as implying that, according to Plato, the body of
a living thing, and perhaps even a corpse, is a substance as well as the soul (this Plato
would deny, I believe); or that Plato thought that all existing things could be sorted
into two exclusive and exhaustive kinds, souls and bodies (this too Plato would deny).
5
Compare 64c4-8.
DEGREES OF SEPARATION IN THE PHAEDO 93
This is unsupported as it stands, but it is not dif cult to provide some sup-
port. Suppose we assume something like ÒThe soul is continually subject
to changeÓ or even ÒNo soul remains unchanged foreverÓ – perhaps
because we have a notion of nature as necessarily involving change, and
we regard the soul as within nature. Then it would follow that any soul
that, as it happens, is completely separated from a body, in fact came to
be so: it was not always so. But any soul that came to be separated from
6
We might imagine, say, a single thing coming into existence out of nothing, and
its becoming steadily differentiated into two components as it springs into existence,
as an instance of two things coming to be joined while coming into existence. But this
speculation, besides involving creation ex nihilo, the coherence of which Plato would
deny, seems rather to be a case of two things coming to be separated, rather than
joined.
94 MICHAEL PAKALUK
any body, by premise 1., was previously joined to some body. So we need
to supplement the argument in some such way as follows:
5.1. Nothing that changes in some respect is ever eternally unchanged in
that respect.
5.2. No soul that comes to be joined to a body is ever eternally in a state
of separation from a body.
5.3. Therefore, every soul that is completely separated from a body but
will be joined to a body was previously joined to a body.
Of course it remains possible that souls do not exist eternally through the
past but come into existence themselves, from being compounded out of
simpler parts. Plato aims to rule out this alternative, of course, initially in
the Af nity Argument and then more de nitively in the Final Argument
of the Phaedo. Yet in the context of the Cyclical Argument he might rea-
sonably maintain, simply, that a conception of nature according to which
souls are successively compounded and decomposed out of simpler parts
introduces unnecessary complications – what agent compounds them, once
their parts are scattered? – and therefore should not be entertained with-
out evidence or supporting reasons.
The rest of the argument proceeds as before, now without any hitches:
6. Therefore, any soul that comes to be alive, i.e. joined to some body,
was previously alive.
7. Therefore, living souls come from previously living souls.
8. Therefore, living souls will once again become living souls.
9. Nothing comes to take on again, at a later time, an attribute that it
now has, if it perishes in the process.
10. Thus, souls that are now alive, i.e. joined to some body, do not per-
ish after they come to be dead, i.e. after they come to be completely
separated from any body.
The argument is not meant of course to be a deduction based on neces-
sary principles and on the meanings of words: obviously, premise 8. involves
something like an inductive inference: from the conclusion that the soul
of a living thing has in the past undergone cycles of reincarnation, we can
be con dent that it will continue to do so in the future. Rather, the argu-
ment aims to sketch the most reasonable picture of the world (diamuy-
ologÇmen 70b6, cp. muyologeÝn, 61e2), given the assumption that the soul
is a distinct substance from the body. 7 Given that assumption – and if we
7
We might expect it to rely on principles that are true typically and Ôfor the most
DEGREES OF SEPARATION IN THE PHAEDO 95
partÕ, which should be presumed to have force unless we are given reason to think
otherwise.
8
Or consider a series of temporal, rather than modal, assertions about the soul:
(i)Õ The soul continues to exist only momentarily upon the destruction of the body.
(ii)Õ The soul exists for a signi cant interval upon the destruction of the body.
(iii)Õ The soul exists for an inde nite time upon the destruction of the body.
(i)Õ is perhaps roughly the same as substance dualism, under some understandings, but
(ii)Õ and (iii)Õ are stronger, and immortalism would require at least these.
96 MICHAEL PAKALUK
it is not bound by nature to die with itÓ.9 The dif culty also gets stressed
near the end of the second set of Objections, usually attributed to Mer-
senne: Ò. . . you say not one word about the immortality of the human
mind. . . . We now make the additional point that it does not seem to fol-
low from the fact that the mind is distinct from the body that it is incor-
ruptible or immortal. What if its nature were limited by the duration of
the life of the body, and God had endowed it with just so much strength
and existence as to ensure that it came to an end with the death of the
body?Ó 10 In reply, Descartes agrees and refers to his Synopsis, where he
acknowledges that, in fact, a proper demonstration of the immortality of
the soul must go far beyond the mere argument for a real distinction and
depend up on Òan account of the whole of physicsÓ.11 We might appro-
priately understand CA, then, not to be begging any questions, but rather
to be lling in some of the gap Mersenne had noticed.
Note, furthermore, that the precise worry at which CA is directed takes
it for granted that the soul is one thing and the body another, but that the
soul is relatively frail and needs, as it were, to be shielded or protected
by the body. As Cebes says at 70a2-6: Òmen fear that when itÕs been sep-
arated (¤peidŒn pallag») from the body, it may no longer exist any-
where, but that on the very day a man dies, it may be destroyed and per-
ish, as soon as itÕs separated (eéyçw pallattom¡nh) from the body; and
that as it goes out (¤kbaÛnousa), it may be dispersed like breath or smoke,
go ying off, and exist no longer (oéd¢n ¦ti) anywhere at all.Ó WhatÕs
imagined here, in fanciful, popular imagery, is momentary separation, then
dispersion. Similar language is used when Socrates paraphrases the con-
9
Letter to Mersenne of 24 December 1640, in J. Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff,
Dugald Murdoch, and Anthony Kenny, eds. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes,
vol. III: Correspondence, (ÔCMSKÕ) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991),
163. This is a good statement of the limited character of substance dualism. Descartes
here mentions needing to prove that ÒGod could not annihilate the soulÓ because this
would be required in order to establish the absolute necessity of the soulÕs continued
existence. Of course he also means to insinuate that, since GodÕs interfering to anni-
hilate the soul seems unlikely, then to show a real distinction is to go a long way
towards establishing immortalism.
10
John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, Dugald Murdoch, eds., The Philosophical
Writings of Descartes: Vol. II, (ÔCSMÕ) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1984), 91. Note the similarity between MersenneÕs supposition and CebesÕ objection
that, for all we know, the soul may wear out and die, even if not on account of the
bodyÕs dissolution.
11
CSM 10, 108-109.
DEGREES OF SEPARATION IN THE PHAEDO 97
cern later, at 80d9-11: Òcan it be that this, which weÕve found to be a thing
of such a kind and nature, should on separation (pallattom¡nh) from
the body at once (eéyæw) be blown apart and perish, as most men say?Ó
Someone might object that we should not place too much emphasis on
the precise way in which the worry that motivates CA is presented. That
worry is, after all, said to be one that concerns Ôcommon peopleÕ or Ômost
menÕ: it is feared Ôby people generallyÕ (toÝw nyrÅpoiw, 70a1-2) that the
soul will be dispersed when it leaves the body; it is Ôthe popular fearÕ (tò
tÇn pollÇn, 77b3-4); this is Ôas most people sayÕ (Ëw fasin oß polloÜ
nyrvpoi, 80d10-e1). And it was of course an ancient and common belief
in popular Greek religion that the soul was some shadowy thing distinct
from the body. IsnÕt Plato simply motivating an argument for immortal-
ity by bringing in this popular belief, which he and his interlocutors obvi-
ously do not endorse?
But Greek popular views on the survival of the soul were indistinct and
mixed; Plato might just as easily in the context have made reference to
the Ôbelief of most menÕ that the soul does survive death, in some atten-
uated condition, in Hades. Clearly, what Plato does is to select some
aspect or strand of popular opinion to suit his purposes. But what are those
purposes? We see them at the beginning of SD. After it is mentioned that
Ômost peopleÕ regard philosophers as walking dead men, living impover-
ished lives, Socrates tells his interlocutors to dismiss what most people
think, so that they can speak among themselves (eàpvmen g‹r . . . pròw
²mw aétoæw, xaÛrein eÞpñntew ¤keÛnoiw, 64c1-2). Socrates then introduces
the de nition of death as the separation of the soul from the body (64c4-
8) and gives his Defense. The whole argument of SD is meant to be devel-
oped among friends who share philosophical views that set them apart
from Ômost peopleÕ. Thus, when the views of Ômost peopleÕ are brought
in again, just before CA, this is to introduce a doubt not shared by Socrates
and his circle. (To be precise: it is not shared by them insofar as they rely
on their philosophical conception of the soul. Of course, it is shared by
them insofar as they are open to in uence from common views, on
account of Ôthe child inside us, who has fears of that sortÕ, 77e5.) But
since the purpose of the appeal to what Ômost peopleÕ think at this point
is precisely to raise a doubt Ôfrom the outsideÕ, as it were, then what Ômost
peopleÕ are said to concede – that the soul is separable from the body –
may reasonably be taken to represent the state of the argument at that
point, among Socrates and his friends.12
12
That the Greek mind at the time of Plato might admit some kind of dualism while
98 MICHAEL PAKALUK
not admitting immortalism is strikingly although indirectly con rmed in a (much later)
argument attributed to Chrysippus, who grants that death is the separation of the soul
from the body, but who takes this to imply that the soul is not immortal: since only
those things that were in contact can become separated, and since only a corporeal
can be in contact with a corporeal, then the soul as well as the body must be corpo-
real (SVF 2.270). (I owe this point to Sean Kelsey.)
13
That CA begins from conclusions of SD, shared by SocratesÕ interlocutors, is per-
haps suggested as well by CebesÕ remark at 69e6: ÒThe other things you say, Socrates,
I nd excellent; but what you say about the soul is the subject of much disbeliefÓ.
Notice Cebes does not say that he himself doubts anything that Socrates has said about
the soul. Moreover, we need not take d¡ at 70a to be adversative: the sentence could
have the sense, ÒAlthough I personally agree with everything youÕve said, people are
liable to take issue with what youÕve said about the soul.Ó
14
Burnet: ÒThe philosopher will not fear death; for his whole life has been a
rehearsal of deathÓ (63e8 ad loc.), in PlatoÕs Phaedo, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1911).
Hackforth: Socrates Òis not so foolish as to complain at the approach of that for which
his whole life has been a preparationÓ (42). Gallop: ÒThe philosopherÕs whole life is
a preparation for death. He should therefore welcome death when it comesÓ (86).
Rowe: Òthe true philosopher will look forward to his death, which is a reward rather
than a punishment for his way of lifeÓ, in Plato: Phaedo, (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1993), 135. Yet later Rowe writes, somewhat more accurately: ÒIf
[dying and being dead] is the philosopherÕs sole preoccupation, he can reasonably be
expected to be Ôeager for itÕÓ (ibid., 64a8 ad loc.).
DEGREES OF SEPARATION IN THE PHAEDO 99
15
Of course someone who visited Paris in one of the stronger senses might also do
so in a weaker sense: a man who once traveled there might spend his years pining
and yearning to return.
16
I do not deny that at some points in SD Socrates appeals to consistency, in the
sense that he points out how absurd and foolish it would be, to vacillate: Òif theyÕve
set themselves at odds with the body at every point, and desire to possess their soul
alone by itself, wouldnÕt it be quite illogical if they were afraid and resentful when
this came aboutÓ (67e6-68a1). But a change in course is a foolish vacillation, rather
than reasonable repentance, only if the course is a good one from the start; yet this is
what SD aims to defend.
DEGREES OF SEPARATION IN THE PHAEDO 101
17
Observe that this is exactly where the de nition of death from 64c4-8 gets
recalled.
102 MICHAEL PAKALUK
a philosopherÕs present life with his condition after death would appear to
clinch the case.18
We can conclude, then, that SD af rms that a true philosopher, through
his asceticism and dedication to a life of study, achieves death in the strict
sense and to some degree. But since separation in the strict sense could
not take place at all unless, in principle, it could take place completely,
what Socrates asserts in his Defense is substance dualism. We should take
this af rmation, then, to be in force as Socrates next turns to the CA.
18
Yet it should be said that there are passages of SD that indicate that separation
is intended in sense (4). For instance, at 66b6 Socrates says that Òas long as we pos-
sess the body, and our soul is contaminated by such an evil, weÕll surely never ade-
quately gain (kthsÅmeya ßkanÇw) what we desireÓ, which seems to imply that we do
gain it fairly well already in this life.
19
CSM 95.
20
Both sorts of argument may be found in the Meditations. It is not uncommon for
DEGREES OF SEPARATION IN THE PHAEDO 103
students, encountering that work for the rst time, to take Descartes to have estab-
lished the distinction between the soul and body in the Second Meditation alone. That
is because the Second Meditation contains an intuitive or ÔprovisionalÕ argument. Yet
the whole apparatus of the ÔCartesian circleÕ, which is meant to justify the inference
from conception to the world, by giving a criterion of the trustworthy operation of our
powers of conception, is of course developed in the successive Meditations and not
concluded until the Sixth.
21
On the other hand, precisely because substance dualism is a weaker position than
immortalism, GallopÕs claim that Socrates has indeed ÔprejudgedÕ the issue is mis-
taken.
104 MICHAEL PAKALUK
22
The argument is meant to be roughly analogous to the paraphrase of DescartesÕ
in Margaret D. Wilson, Descartes, (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978), 189.
23
It is not important for our purposes why he claims this, only that he does so.
Commentators object that, in the RA which follows, Socrates will argue that sense
experience plays an invaluable role in provoking recollection of the Forms; conse-
DEGREES OF SEPARATION IN THE PHAEDO 105
so on. Of course, all of these activities, too, require essentially the assis-
tance of the body, so in avoiding these, too, the philosopher aims not to
be not dead.
Finally Socrates turns to a particular activity of the soul, thinking or
reasoning: ÒSo isnÕt it in reasoning (logÛzesyai), if anywhere at all, that
any of the things that are become manifest to it?Ó (65c2-3). He considers
this activity both from the point of view of the activity itself (65c5-d1),
and from the point of view of the object of that activity (65d7-e9), and
in each case he argues both that there can be differences in degree of
ÔpurityÕ and that the philosopher strives for the purest degree:
And it reasons best, presumably, when- LogÛzetai d¡ g¡ pou tñte k‹llista,
ever none of these things bothers it, ÷tan aét¯n toætvn mhd¢n paralup»,
neither hearing nor sight nor pain, nor m®te ko¯ m®te öciw m®te lghdÆn
any pleasure either, but whenever it mhd¡ tiw ²don®, ll ÷ti m‹lista aét¯
comes to be alone by itself as far as kayƒ aêt¯n gÛgnhtai ¤Çsa xaÛrein tò
possible, disregarding the body, and sÇma, kaÜ kay ÷son dænatai m¯ koin-
whenever, having the least possible com- vnoèsa aétÒ mhd ptom¡nh ôr¡ghtai
munion and contact with it, it strives toè öntow.
for that which is. (65c5-9)
. . . whoever of us is prepared to think ùw ’n m‹lista ²mÇn kaÜ krib¡stata
most fully and minutely of each object parskeu‹shtai aétò §kaston dianohy°-
of his inquiry, in itself, will come clos- nai perÜ oð skopeÝ, oðtow ’n ¤ggætata
est to the knowledge of each? (65e2-4) àoi toè gnÇnai §kaston;
quently it would seem a true philosopher could not afford to dismiss it entirely, even
if this were possible. Yet such an admission makes the senses only instrumentally valu-
able for arriving at the truth, and the use of the senses would play no role in that
activity which, strictly, constitutes our grasping of truth. (We might think that Plato
has Socrates so strongly discountenance sense perception in SD, precisely because
what is at issue there is not truth so much as whether sense perception can be taken
as an end in knowing.)
106 MICHAEL PAKALUK
24
It is because of this connection between knowledge of the Forms and self-knowl-
DEGREES OF SEPARATION IN THE PHAEDO 107
edge that I take Socrates later to assert, in the course of RA, what appears to be over-
stated at rst, viz. that the hypothesis of the Forms, and that of immortality, stand or
fall together: ÒIt is equally necessary that those objects exist, and that our souls existed
before birthÓ, 76e5-6.
108 MICHAEL PAKALUK
bodies, then one might reasonably anticipate that a fully separated soul
will have more virtue than any that is still embodied – thus corroborating
SocratesÕ claim. However, another reason for the deduction is surely that
it suggests that the soul is not naturally joined to the body: that the soul
fares poorly to the extent that it is joined, and that it ourishes to the
extent that it becomes separated, would seem to indicate that the soul is
independent and distinct, since one might expect that nothing naturally
dependent on another thing would get better by being cut off from it.
IV. SD was intended by Plato to provide the context of the three initial
arguments and therefore counts as the Ôprimary argumentÕ of the Phaedo.
On the interpretation defended here, an interesting structure emerges for
the Phaedo. The three main parts of the dialogue may be taken to corre-
spond to distinctions we drew earlier: SD maintains that the soul is capa-
ble of existing when the body is destroyed; the three initial arguments
maintain that it does in fact do so, through repeated cycles of incarnation
(unless liberated from those cycles through devotion to philosophy); and
the nal argument (FA) maintains that the soul necessarily exists when
the body is destroyed, because by no process of change in nature can the
soul go out of existence.25
The result of SD is provisional in the sense that it takes our ability to
conceive of the soul as independent of the body to be a prima facie rea-
son for regarding it as distinct. This result is, however, powerful, as far
as it goes, since it shifts the burden of proof. But since SD concludes
merely that the soul can exist when the body is destroyed, it provides only
a basis for hope that the soul continues to exist after the demise of the
body, as Socrates stresses in many passages: ÒI expect (¤lpÛzv) to join
the company of good menÓ (63c1); ÒthatÕs why I am not resentful, but
rather am hopeful (eëelpiw) that there is something more in store for those
whoÕve diedÓ (63c4-5); Òa man who has truly spent his life in philoso-
phy . . . is hopeful (eëelpiw ) that, when he has died, he will win very great
bene ts in the other worldÓ (63e9-64a2); Òif thatÕs true . . . thereÕs plenty
of hope (poll¯ ¤lpÛw) for one who arrives where IÕm goingÓ (67b7-8);
Òthey may hope (¤lpÛw ¤stin) to attain what they longed for throughout
lifeÓ (68a1-2).
25
That is, we might say that the dialogue defends, successively, Òsubstance dual-
ismÓ, Òweak immortalismÓ, and Òstrong immortalismÓ. (See the chart at this articleÕs
end.)
DEGREES OF SEPARATION IN THE PHAEDO 109
26
Surprisingly, none of the major commentaries sets off the passage following AA
and identi es it as ÒReprise of SocratesÕ DefenseÓ, or some such thing.
110 MICHAEL PAKALUK
worse for the dead Ó (my italics, 72e1). Editors tend to strike the ital-
icized phrase, not on the basis of evidence in the manuscripts, but on
the grounds that, as Rowe puts it, the phrase Òmakes no sense in this
context and is clearly an interpolation from 63c6-7Ó, sc. from SD. But
if CA is meant to rely upon and develop SD, the phrase does make
sense: relying on the ÔhopeÕ articulated in SD, and which is implied
by the doctrine of Ôpuri cationÕ (see 69c2-d1), Socrates anticipates a
fuller conclusion, to which he cannot quite help himself here, but
which he will more adequately support by the time he reaches AA
(cf. 80d5-81c).
(ii) AA refers back explicitly to SD at 79c2-8: ÒNow werenÕt we saying
a while ago that whenever the soul uses the body as a means to study
anything, either by seeing or hearing or any other sense – because to
use the body as a means is to study a thing through sense percep-
tion – then it is dragged by the body towards objects that are never
constant, and is confused and dizzy, as if drunk, in virtue of contact
with things of a similar kind?Ó The reference is to 65b1-7. But what
is especially striking is the formula, toèto g‹r ¤stin tò diŒ toè sÅmatow,
tò diƒ aÞsy®sevw skopeÝn ti, which makes it clear Plato wants to
stress the principle that, if it is necessary to mention or refer to the
body in specifying that activity, then that activity is not one that the
soul can engage in Ôalone by itselfÕ.
(iii) Again, AA refers back to SD at 79d9-e1: ÒOnce again, then, in the
light of our earlier and present arguments (¤k tÇn prñsyen kaÜ ¤k tÇn
nèn legom¡nvn), to which kind do you think the soul is more similar
and more akin?Ó Since Socrates is looking for his interlocutor to draw
a conclusion based on what he had just said, at 79c2-8, it is clear
that Socrates means to include SD among the earlier arguments,
viewed as of a piece with the present ones. (It is not to the point that
Socrates speaks of legñmena rather than lñgoi; clearly AA is an argu-
ment, and he uses the same term for SD as AA.)
(iv) The passage at 79e9-80a5 has little cogency if not read with SD as
its backdrop. That passage begins: Ò. . . when soul and body are pre-
sent in the same thingÓ (¤peidŒn ¤n tÒ aétÒ Îsi cux¯ kaÜ sÇma). But
this is an odd gure of speech, apart from the viewpoint of substance
dualism; yet this way of speaking has not been licensed by any par-
ticular text after SD. Furthermore, the passage presumes that Ônature
ordains that [body] shall serve and be ruled, whereas the other shall
rule and be masterÕ, and commentators complain that this premise is
entirely new, unsupported, and at odds with the notion that the soul
DEGREES OF SEPARATION IN THE PHAEDO 111
27
In this way we see how a common objection to RA may be answered. Bostock
objects that Plato gives no reason why the capacity to grasp the Forms might not sim-
ply be present in the soul from birth, in the manner of Ôinnate ideasÕ: Ò. . . it is open
to an objector to maintain that we were just born with this knowledge of equality, but
did not have to learn it at any previous time. When Plato himself belatedly notices
this objection, at 76c14-15, he gives a reply which can only be regarded as missing
the pointÓ (102). But it looks rather as if Bostock has missed the point: to hold that
the soul comes into existence with such knowledge would be to postulate an effect
without a cause. How does it come to have those innate ideas? Nothing comes from
nothing. (The doctrine of innate ideas that survives into the modern era presupposes
for its cogency the view that the soul is immediately created by God.)
112 MICHAEL PAKALUK
28
The quotation is from DescartesÕ Synopsis, CSM 9.
29
CSM 9-10.
30
Yet the FA is still needed, because AA says merely that the soul is best likened
to indestructible things, and therefore has the character of an induction or analogical
inference; also, because the whole drift of SD and its reprise is that the soul may have
more or less of the character of corporeality, and so it needs to be made clear that its
having this character is secondary, derivative, and accidental to it.
DEGREES OF SEPARATION IN THE PHAEDO 113
31
I regard the objections of Simmias and Cebes as representing PlatoÕs concern that
the new natural philosophy denies the priority of the soul – a concern which nds full
expression in Laws X. There Plato insists that the soul is older than corporeal beings
and their cause, whereas the new natural philosophy would make the soul derivative
and dependent upon corporeal things. See 889b1-890b1, 891c1-8, 892a4-b8.
32
Note that, at the end of the Final Argument, both Cebes and Simmias af rm that
they now nd all the arguments beyond doubt: Ò. . . for my part IÕve no further objec-
tions, nor can I doubt the arguments at any pointÓ (Cebes, 107a3); Ò. . . nor have I
any further ground for doubt myself, as far as the arguments goÓ (Simmias, a8-9).
33
Etienne Gilson, The Unity of Philosophical Experience, (New York: Charles
ScribnerÕs Sons, 1937), 302.
114 MICHAEL PAKALUK
diagnoses of fallacious argument are much too super cial, as are those
remedies that would have us look instead at incidental dramatic details.
There is no merit in simply overlooking the powerful philosophical view
which the dialogue expresses. 34
Department of Philosophy
Clark University
34
I wish to thank Sean Kelsey, Anthony Price, and Paul Woodruff as well as the
participants in the 25th Texas Workshop in Ancient Philosophy for comments on
earlier drafts of this paper.
The Argumentative Structure of the Phaedo
Motivating Worry Source of Worry Thesis Defended Kind of Argument Kind of Conviction
I. SocratesÕ Perhaps Socrates SocratesÕ friends Substance dualism Prima facie, Hope
Defense has recklessly and disciples provisional
neglected his
own good in not
resisting death
II. The Three Perhaps the soul The Ôcommon manÕ Weak Inductive, Sound inference
Initial disperses upon immortalism plausible story
Arguments separation from (reincarnation)
the body
III. The Final Perhaps the soul Presocratic Strong Deductive, Certainty, proof
Argument wears out natural philosophy immortalism necessary
eventually (divinity of
the soul)
DEGREES OF SEPARATION IN THE PHAEDO
115