This Content Downloaded From 117.212.145.123 On Fri, 07 Aug 2020 06:04:48 UTC
This Content Downloaded From 117.212.145.123 On Fri, 07 Aug 2020 06:04:48 UTC
This Content Downloaded From 117.212.145.123 On Fri, 07 Aug 2020 06:04:48 UTC
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Columbia Law Review Association, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to Columbia Law Review
6 Thus Lawrence, Int. Law (5th ed.) 10-12, says that international
law may be regarded as an a priori investigation into what the rules of
international intercourse ought to be or historical investigation of what
they are: "Two principal views may be held as to the nature and origin
of these rules (of international law). They may be considered to be an
imperfect attempt to give effect to an absolute right which is assumed to
exist and to be capable of being discovered; or they may be looked upon
simply as a reflection of the moral development and the external life of
the particular nations which are governed by them." Hall, Int. Law (6th
ed.) 1.
7 For example, Germany's attempt to justify her violation of the neu-
trality of Belgium in 1914.
12Hall, Int. Law (6th ed.) 13-16, says international law constitutes a
branch of true law because cast in a legal mould and treated in practice
as being legal in character, although lacking the sanction of
determinate political authority, and lying, as he admits, on
the extreme frontier of law. Hall, op. cit. 18, says absolute
independence of state is unnecessary to the conception of a legal relatio
between communities independent of each other; that international law
could exist just as well in a world of equal states dependent on a com-
mon superior, which is true, because then there would be a common
political superior exercising to a greater or less extent the power of
state. It is not, however, a question of conception, but a question of fact
We are studying bodies which have no external superior in fact, and tha
is all there is to it. The facts might have been otherwise, they may be
otherwise in the future, in either of which events we will be studying
different facts. Hershey, Int. L. 5-9, describes international law as a
branch of true law and discusses the external factors determining state
conduct. 'Ihe proposition he states demonstrates the obscurity in the use
of the word law. If true law is municipal law, then law must have
political power to enforce it and international law is not true law. He
points out that some branches of municipal law are not enforced by
political power of the state and that, in some cases, where the political
power assumes to act, it fails because the people are not in accord. That
is to say, the factors determining conduct in municipal life may not agree
with the political power and its exercise will be futile. Lawrence, Int.
Law (5th ed.) 2, says that the principles of international law are rules
whether they are or are not laws, but the question whether it (interna-
tional law) confers rights, depends on whether the term law is properly
applied. The question as to the application of the term law depends
on the definition of the term law. It is reasoning in a circle to argue that
the distinction between international and municipal law is based on any
meaning given the word law. 1 Oppenheim, Int. L. (2nd ed.) 8-15, after
15 What has been called reciprocating will, 1 Lorimer, Int, 109 et seq.,
reciprocating power, 1 Lorimer, op. cit., 133 et seq.
16 In .their intercourse with distant and weak states there has been
too much disposition among the states of Europe to avail themselves
of that law (law of nations) when it has been "in their favor and to
repudiate its obligations when it would have been against them;" Man-
ning, Int. L (2nd ed.) Amos. 88n; See Woolsey, Int. L. (6th ed.) 4.
International law is not confined to Christian States or members of the
family of nations; I Philjimore, Int. L. (3rd ed.) 20-23; see Lawrence,
Int Law (5th ed.) 57, 58.
17Thus, Hershey, Int. L. 171, says that the objects of the law of
nations are (1) Material goods and things; (2) Individuals or persons
(including corporations), and that the main things to which the rules of
international law apply are land territory, the open sea, vessels and other
public property of various sorts. A tempest may sweep a vessel from
her moorings, but if the port regulations require that she be moved,
that can only be accomplished by the act of individuals whose conduct,
with respect thereto, is determined by the external factor of the political
power of the state.
27 1 Halleck, Int. L. (4th ed.) 59; Hershey, Int. L. 161 n2; 1 Lorimer,
Inst., 160 et seq.; 1 Oppenheim, Int. L. (2nd ed.) 209, 210; 1 Phillimore,
Int. L. (3rd ed.) 5; 3 Phillimore, Int. L. (3rd ed.) 58.
28 This is one of the many instances which make the writings on inter-
national law such strange reading to practical lawyers. A slight differ-
ence like this in the meaning of the word gives the whole discussion a
different color. Responsibility in the municipal law is the normal state
of affairs, and the case to which our attention is particularly called is the
case where there is a departure from that normal state of affairs, that is,
the case of irresponsibility. The same conception appears in popular
usage when we speak of the irresponsibility of youth. Now the question
is, is there any distinction between states with respect to capacity?
51 This fact should be kept in mind because many persons speak of the
beginning of international law in the seventeenth century, and say that
international law is scarcely three hundred years old. Such philosophers
are, of course, inaccurate. It is the conscious study of international law
which is only about three hundred years old. For reference to views of
the principal writers see Hall, Int. Law (6th ed.) 2, nl.
62 For discussions of the history of the science of the Law of Nations,
see Hershey, Int. L. 56, 91; Manning, Int L. (2nd ed.) Amos. 8, et seq.;
1 Oppenheim, Int. L. (2nd ed.) 83-104; Wilson & Tucker, Int L 6, et
seq "Historical Development," Wilson & Tucker, op. cit. 12, et seq.
"The History of International Relations During Antiquity and the Middle
Ages," Amos. S. Hershey, 5 Amer. J. Int. L. 901 et seq. See Hershey,
op. cit. 26-55. "History of International Law since the Peace of West-
phalia," Amos S. Hershey, 6 Amer. J. Int. L. 30 et seq.; Hershey,
cp. cit. 56-91. For accounts of the history of international law and dis-
cussions of the various theories, see 1 Halleck, Int. L. (4th ed.) 1-49;
1 Oppenheim, op. cit. 45-104. "Ward Foundation and History of the
ILaw of Nations in Europe to the Age of Grotius," Robert Ward. "His-
tory of International Relations before Grotius," Walker, Science, Int. L
57-90; Twiss, L. of Nations, Peace (2nd ed.) 155 et seq.; Woolsey, Int.
L. (6th ed.) 6-10. 1 Oppenheim, op. cit. 4, says that international law,
in the meaning of the term as used in modem times, did not exist during
antiquity and in the first part of the middle ages. What is the difference,
however, between the modern meaning and the ancient? If he means
that the science of international law did not exist, he is correct; if he
does not mean this, it is difficult to tell what he does mean. He also
says (Vol. 1, p. 4) that it is a product of modern civilization and is four
hundred years old and the roots go far back into antiquity. "The In-
ternational Law and Custom of Ancient Greece and Rome," Coleman
Phillipson. See 11 Columbia Law Rev. 489.
53 "The distinction, however, between the two branches of Interna-
tional Jurisprudence is extremely important. It is this: The obligationes
jltris privati inter gentes are not-as the obligationes juris publici inter
gentes are-the result of legal necessity, but of social convenience, and
they are called by the name of Comity-comitas gentium. 1 Phillimore,
Int. L. (3rd ed.) 12, 13.
54Hall, Int. L. (6th ed.) 51, et seq.; Hershey, Int. L. 4, Lawrence,
Int. L. (5th ed.) 5; 1 Oppenheim, Int. L. (2nd ed.) 4; 1 Westlake,
Int. L. (2nd ed.) 246, et seq.; Woolsey, Int. L. (6th ed.) 102-109.
"Grundzuge des Englisch-Amerikanischen Privat-und Prozessrechts,
Besonders in Vergleiche mit den Systemen des Europaischen Kontinents,"
Arthur K. Kuhn. See 10 Amer. J. Int. Law, 674. "A Treatise on the
Conflict of Laws," Vol. 1, Part 1, Joseph Henry Beale. See 10 Amer.
J. Int. Law, 665.
SUMMARY
63 Zouche, in 1650, first called the subject, "Jus Inter Gentes," but the
phrase "law among nations" is due to the Chancellor d'Aguesseau;
Thomas W. Balch, 64 Univ. of Pa. Law Rev. 113. See, however, Whea-
ton, Elements (Dana's ed.) 20; Woolsey, Int. L., (6th ed.) 10. "Jus
Gentium and International Law," Gordon E. Sherman; 12 Amer. J. Int.
Law 56.
64 The term "international law" was invented by Jeremy Bentham in
1780; Wheaton, Elements (Dana's ed.) 20. "As, however, there cannot
be a sovereign authority above the several sovereign states, the Law of
Nations is a law between, not above, the several states, and is, therefore,
since Bentham, also called 'International Law';" 1 Oppenheim, Int. L
(2nd ed.) 4. International Law has been objected to, Wheaton, op. cit.
16. Hershey, Int. L., 2, et seq., uses the term "International Public Law,"
after using "International Law," thereby suggesting the title "International
Private Law," or, as more commonly used, "Private International Law."
65 Interstate law has been suggested, see Hershey, Int. L. 2, n2.
66 As to title, see Hershey, Int. L. 2; Wheaton, Elements (Dana's ed.)
20, et seq.
67 This obscurity referred to by Lawrence, Int. Law (5th ed.) 8.