Introduction The Analytic Philosophy of Politics

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 3

© Giovanni Mascaretti

DOI: https://doi.org/10.22439/fs.v0i24.5531
ISSN: 1832-5203
Foucault Studies, No. 24, pp. 185-187, June 2018



Below is the first complete English translation of the conference Foucault delivered under the
title “La philosophie analytique de la politique” on his visit to Japan in 1978. The interest of
this conference resides in the fact that it provides one of Foucault’s clearest accounts of his
own approach to the analysis of power and practices of resistance. Foucault’s discourse is
organized around the following initial question: how can philosophy still play its ancient role
of “counter-power” in the face of the forms of domination marking 20th century Western
societies? Foucault’s response to this question is premised upon his stark critique of the
traditional juridico-political theories of power. As he argues at greater length in the first
volume of The History of Sexuality, in fact, all these theories rely on a prior and universal
representation of power as a homogeneous and unitarian essence, which not only remains
inadequate to grasp the way “power is and was exercised”,1 but also serves as a source of
legitimation for modern institutions through the concealment of the concrete mechanisms of
power. To the contrary, Foucault adopts a very different methodological attitude: rather than
elaborating an overarching theory of power centred upon the study of the macro-level
dimensions of the state and social hegemonies, Foucault engages in a series of historical
investigations of “focal points of experience”2 (like madness, criminality, and sexuality) in
order to reveal the regional, unstable, and marginal cluster of force relations shaping our
ordinary experience of power.
In this sense, Foucault delineates an unexpected convergence between his own
approach and Anglo-American analytic philosophy, especially ordinary language philosophy
as formulated by Ludwig Wittgenstein. The aim of ordinary language philosophy is to
propose a “critical analysis of thought on the basis of the way one says things”, while rejecting
any massive disqualification or qualification of language. Correspondingly, the task Foucault
attributes to his “analytic philosophy of politics” or “analytico-political philosophy” is to
examine “what ordinarily happens in power relations”, namely to describe the reality of
power without falling prey to sweeping condemnations or appreciations.3 To state it
otherwise, excluding any return to the ancient models of philosophy as prophecy, pedagogy
or lawgiver, Foucault holds that today philosophy can maintain its critical role of counter-
power only insofar as it abandons the moral and juridical vocabulary of “good” and “bad”,
“right” and “wrong”, “legitimate” and “illegitimate” in favour of an analysis of power


1 M. Foucault (1978), History of Sexuality, Volume 1: An Introduction (The Will to Knowledge), trans. R.
Hurley, New York: Pantheon Books, pp. 87–8.
2 M. Foucault (2010), The Government of Self and Others. Lectures at the Collège de France (1982–83), eds.
A. Davidson, F. Gros, F. Ewald, and A. Fontana, trans. G. Burchell, London and New York: Palgrave
MacMillan, p. 3.
3 M. Foucault, Michel (2001), “La philosophie analytique de la politique”, in Dits et Écrits II, 1976–88,
eds. D. Defert, F. Ewald, and J. Lagrange, Paris: Gallimard, p. 541.
1 185
© Giovanni Mascaretti
DOI: https://doi.org/10.22439/fs.v0i24.5531
ISSN: 1832-5203
Foucault Studies, No. 24, pp. 185-187, June 2018

relations “in terms of existence”,4 namely as games marked by specific tactics and strategies,
rules and accidents, stakes and objectives.
Far from being concerned with the justification of our principles of justice like analytic
political philosophy, therefore, Foucault’s analytic philosophy of politics clearly has a “realist
spirit”:5 its ultimate function is to make visible the differentiated and concrete mechanisms of
power constituting those apparently natural and familiar limits of the present we take for
granted. However, the role of an analytico-political philosophy is not a purely descriptive and
intellectual one. Rather, rendering visible how power actually works enables at the same time
to “intensify the struggles that develop around power, the strategies of the antagonists within
relations of power, the tactics employed, the foyers of resistance”.6
As it promotes a new picture of power, Foucault’s analytic philosophy of politics also
entails a redefinition of the very notion of resistance. Indeed, if power can no longer be
conceived as a top-down, uniform, and general form of domination stemming from a central
point, then one should call into question the traditional, exclusive portrait of resistance as a
revolutionary uprising aimed at a total liberation from power. For Foucault, this does not
mean that one should turn towards reformism. Conversely, alongside revolutionary acts of
liberation from states of domination, Foucault emphasises the existence of particular and
diffused practices of resistance characterized by both a local point of emergence and a
“transversal” dissemination across countries as well as political and economic regimes. Being
irreducible to the structure of revolution, such practices are “anarchistic” struggles, whose
immediate aim is to destabilize the “intolerable” games of power that develop around the
different issues constituting the very “texture of our everyday life”, like madness,
delinquency, illness, prison, sexuality, etc.7 Despite their diversity, however, all these practices
of freedom have a common target, i.e. the individualising mechanisms of subjection resulting
from the secular transposition of the Christian techniques of pastoral power into the modern
state. As Foucault claims in 1982, in fact, “the political, ethical, social, philosophical problem of
our days is not to try to liberate the individual from the state, [...] but to liberate us both from
the state and from the type of individualization linked to the state”,8 a problem that still
haunts us in these critical times.


4 Ibid., p. 540.
5 D. Lorenzini (2015), Éthique e politique de soi. Foucault, Hadot, Cavell et les techniques de l’ordinaire,
Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin, pp. 23–6.
6 Foucault, “La philosophie analytique de la politique”, p. 540.
7 Ibid., pp. 542–45.
8 Foucault, Michel (2000), “The Subject and Power”, in Essential Works of Foucault, Volume 3: Power, ed.
J. D. Faubion, trans. R. Hurley et al., New York: New Press, p. 336.

1 186
© Giovanni Mascaretti
DOI: https://doi.org/10.22439/fs.v0i24.5531
ISSN: 1832-5203
Foucault Studies, No. 24, pp. 185-187, June 2018

Author bio
Giovanni Mascaretti
Lecturer in Political Theory, Research Methodology and International Relations
University of Kurdistan
Erbil, Kurdistan Region of Iraq
[email protected]/[email protected]

References
• Daniele Lorenzini (2015), Éthique e politique de soi. Foucault, Hadot, Cavell et les
techniques de l’ordinaire, Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin
• Michel Foucault (2010), The Government of Self and Others. Lectures at the Collège de
France (1982–83), eds. A. Davidson, F. Gros, F. Ewald, and A. Fontana, trans. G.
Burchell, London and New York: Palgrave MacMillan:
https://doi.org/10.1057/9780230274730
• Michel Foucault (1978), History of Sexuality, Volume 1: An Introduction (The Will to
Knowledge), trans. R. Hurley, New York: Pantheon Books
• Michel Foucault, Michel (2001), “La philosophie analytique de la politique”, in Dits et
Écrits II, 1976–88, eds. D. Defert, F. Ewald, and J. Lagrange, Paris: Gallimard
• Michel Foucault (2000), “The Subject and Power”, in Essential Works of Foucault,
Volume 3: Power, ed. J. D. Faubion, trans. R. Hurley et al., New York: New Press
1 187

You might also like