F 2000k Governance Failure

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 23

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/311992245

Governance Failure

Chapter · January 2000

CITATIONS READS

90 1,157

1 author:

Bob Jessop
Lancaster University
322 PUBLICATIONS   15,566 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

Critical and Cultural Political Economy View project

Populism View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Bob Jessop on 31 December 2016.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


The Dynamics of Partnership and Governance Failure
Bob Jessop

In G. Stoker, ed., The New Politics of British Local Governance, Basingstoke:


Macmillan (2000), pp. 11-32.

The 1970s saw growing assertions that state intervention was failing and that the state
itself was in crisis. In the 1980s the dominant neo-liberal response in Britain to this alleged
crisis largely involved turning to the market and, to a lesser extent, community or family
self-help. Successive Thatcher and Major governments promoted privatization,
liberalization, de-regulation, the use of market proxies in the residual state sector, cuts in
direct taxes to enhance consumer choice, and internationalization to promote capital
mobility and the transfer of technology and 'know-how'. They also advocated an enterprise
culture and popular capitalism to make civil society more market-friendly. This project was
intended to re-equip Britain with a liberal, night-watchman state with progressively smaller
and more balanced budgets and thereby boost this slimmed-down state's capacity to
perform its remaining core functions. However, while this neo-liberal programme was still
being pursued and, indeed, intensified, it also became apparent that the turn to the market
had not delivered all that had been promised. Market failures and inadequacies had not
been eliminated yet an explicit return to the state was ideologically and politically
unacceptable. Thus, as early as the 1980s, one could discern increasing government
interest at all levels in how public-private partnerships and similar forms of governance
might contribute to public policy and purposes. This alternative to marketization was
steadily reinforced during the Conservative years and is likely to become yet stronger
under 'New Labour' with its declared commitment to a 'stakeholding society'. The
expansion of governance is not meant to return Britain to a discredited corporatism (let
alone a tripartite corporatism with the active involvement of organized labour) but, rather,
to address real limitations of the market, state, and mixed economy as means of dealing
with various complex economic, political, and social issues. One area where a turn to
governance has been popular is local economic and social development and it is this that
provides the empirical focus of the following theoretical reflections on the various ways in
which coordination mechanisms can fail and how tendencies to failure may themselves be
governed.

1
1. Market Failure

Many economists tend to assume that the 'procedural rationality' of perfect markets
guarantees market success. Failure occurs when economic exchanges do not produce
what a perfect (hence 'imaginary') market would deliver. Since market rationality depends
on free and equal exchange rather than on the purposes of economic transactions,
success or failure cannot, on most accounts, be judged through substantive criteria such
as market forces' uneven impact on wealth, income, lifechances, or regional imbalance.
For, provided that inequalities derive from (or are consistent with) the operation of perfect
markets, they must be judged as rational and fair. At best one could see such problems as
market 'inadequacies' rather than genuine market failures. There is no shortage of claims
about such inadequacies, however, nor about the need to remedy them as well as market
failures through social and political action of various kinds.

In a market-rational framework, state and market are strictly demarcated. The state should
stay at arms-length from market forces, merely establishing and defending the framework
for market institutions. The latter can then allocate goods and services in the most efficient
way. The market also functions as a learning mechanism. Thus Hayek argues that market
failure is an essentially 'trial-and-error' discovery mechanism whereby markets prompt
economic agents to learn and innovate. In the long run, on this view, the market provides
the most flexible and least disastrous coordinating and adaptive mechanism in the face of
complex interdependence and turbulent environments. Moreover, for neo-classical and
Austrian theorists alike, the initial response to market failure is 'more market, not less' --
even if this often requires, in the short-term, yet further state intervention. But it is
debateable, to say the least, whether even perfect markets could eliminate all forms of
market failure. Even neo-classical economists recognize the extent to which markets may
not 'suitably capture the full social benefits or levy the full social costs of market activity'
(Wolf 1978: 138).

The critique of markets has been taken furthest by Marxists and political ecologists.
Marxists argue that capitalism is distinctive not for markets as such but their extension to
labour-power. It is market-mediated exploitation of wage-labour that drives 'economic
growth' -- not the inherent efficiency of markets. Markets may mediate the search for

2
added value but cannot produce it. The commodification of labour-power also generates
basic contradictions that cannot be resolved through the market mechanism. Among other
examples, the commodity is both an exchange-value and use-value; the wage is both a
cost of production and source of demand; money is both national money and international
currency; and productive capital is both abstract value in motion and a concrete stock of
time- and place-specific assets in the process of valorization. Thus, for Marxists,
phenomena attributed to market failures or inadequacies often express underlying
contradictions of capitalism. It follows that state intervention may at best only modify the
forms or sites of these contradictions -- introducing class struggles into the state and/or
generating tendencies towards fiscal crisis, legitimacy crisis, rationality crisis, etc.. Political
ecologists add to such criticisms the market-mediated despoliation of the environment and
commitment to unsustainable development.

2. State Failure

Whereas neo-classical economists' solution for market failure or inadequacy is to extend


the market, welfare economists call for more state intervention. This is intended both to
avoid or correct market failures and to subordinate market forces to specific public
purposes. More generally, the rationale for state activity is not procedural (as with the
market) but substantive. It is found in the definition and enforcement of collectively binding
decisions in the name of the public interest or general will. This rationale is expressed
through imperative coordination (or hierarchy) rather than the anarchy of market forces.
State failure is judged in turn according to this substantive rationality: it refers to the failure
to realize the state's own political project(s) within the terms of its own operating rules and
procedures. In democratic regimes these rules and procedures include respect for legality
and the regular renewal of popular mandates for action. In this context, the primary
criterion for identifying state failures is not allocative efficiency (as this is defined in terms
of the procedural rationality of the market). Instead, it is the effectiveness (as often
symbolic as material) with which specific state projects are realized. It is certainly possible,
however, for efficiency to count among criteria for the success of specific projects. Thus
'value-for-money' was one objective of the recent neo-liberal state project.

3
Moreover, just as market failure can be related to substantive factors that block the
realization of its procedural rationality, so state failure can be linked to specific procedural
factors that block effective policy-making and implementation. Thus various commentators
suggest that planning, bureaucracy, participation, reliance on professional expertise, etc.,
may each fail in different ways to generate adequate policies and/or to secure their
effective realization. Resulting tendencies towards implementation and fiscal crises can
lead in turn to problems of political legitimacy where the state's public purposes are not
seen to be achieved. One response to this within the state is a constant cycling through
these different modes of policy-making and implementation in the attempt to compensate
for their respective tendencies to failure.

Just as neo-classical economists make unrealistic assumptions about markets, welfare


economists make implausible claims about states. They assume that states not only have
all the information necessary to maximise social welfare but also have both the internal
organizational capacities and the powers of external intervention needed to achieve their
public objectives. Yet it is widely recognized that state managers (especially elected
politicians) have short-term time horizons and are vulnerable to lobbying; that states are
subject to bounded rationality (limited information, uncertainty, and time pressures) when
acting; that they often pursue multiple, contrary, and even contradictory goals -- many of
which are also inherently infeasible; that state capacities are limited both by 'internalities'
(calculations of private costs and benefits that differ from public goals) and external
resistance; that nonmarket outputs are usually hard to define in principle, ill-defined in
practice, and difficult to measure; and that state intervention may prompt rent-seeking
behaviour among policy-takers that merely redistributes rather than creates resources
(Offe 1975; Wolf 1978).

There are different responses to state failure. Liberal critics see market forces as a self-
correcting learning mechanism and the state as inherently incorrigible and ineducable.
They do not ask whether state failure could be corrected in similar ways to market failure
but seek to replace it with the market. But other critics allow both for self-correcting policy
cycles and/or institutional re-design in the state. Relevant measures in the latter regard to
improve policy coordination and implementation can include redefining the division of
labour in the state and wider political system, increasing state autonomy so that it is less

4
vulnerable to particularistic lobbying, boosting reflexivity (including through auditing and
the contract culture), and reorienting time horizons in favour of longer-term policy-making
and policy-taking.

3. Governance as a Response to Market and State Failure

Discussions of market and state failure often appear to rest on diametrically opposed
theoretical and politico-ideological positions. Yet they share some core assumptions. Both
presume a dichotomistic 'public-private' distinction and a zero-sum conception of the
respective spheres of the market and state. Thus, on the one hand, critics of state failure
see the economy as the site of mutually advantageous, voluntary exchange among
formally free, equal, and autonomous economic agents; and, on the other hand, they
regard the state as premised on organized coercion that intrudes on the private liberties of
citizens (especially in their capacity as economic agents). Conversely, critics of market
failure see the state as a sovereign authority empowered to pursue the public interest
against the particularistic, egoistic short-term interests of citizens (especially those of
property owners). In both cases, the more there is of the state, the less there is of the
market; what varies is the positive or negative evaluation of this ratio.

Literature on governance rejects this rigid polarization between the anarchy of the market
and the hierarchy of imperative coordination in favour of the concept of 'heterarchy', i.e.,
horizontal self-organization among mutually interdependent actors. It recognizes the
equivalence of the twin tendencies to market and state failure and proposes to reconcile
and transcend them by relying on procedures that cut across the market and state divides.
These include interpersonal networking, interorganizational negotiation, and 'de-centred
intersystemic context steering' (dezentrierte Kontextsteuerung). The first two of these
forms of governance should be familiar; the last requires some initial comment. It
comprises efforts to steer (guide) the development of different systems by taking account
both of their own operating codes and rationalities and of their various substantive, social,
and spatio-temporal interdependencies. This is facilitated by communication oriented to
intersystemic 'noise reduction' (mutual understanding), negotiation, negative coordination,
and cooperation in shared projects. And is reflected in the use of symbolic media of
communication such as money, law, or knowledge to modify the structural and strategic

5
contexts in which different systems function so that compliance with shared projects
follows from their own operating codes rather than from imperative coordination (see
Glagow and Willke 1987).

The rationality of governance is neither procedural nor substantive: it is best described as


'reflexive'. The procedural rationality of the capitalist market is essentially formal in nature,
prioritizing an endless 'economizing' pursuit of profit maximization; the substantive
rationality of government is goal-oriented, prioritizing 'effective' pursuit of successive policy
goals. Both approaches are particularly prone to problems of bounded rationality,
opportunism, and asset specificity (Coulson 1997). Advocates of governance suggest that
these problems can be avoided by instituting negotiation around a long-term consensual
project as the basis for both negative and positive coordination among interdependent
actors. The key to success is continued commitment to dialogue to generate and
exchange more information (thereby reducing, without ever eliminating, the problem of
bounded rationality); to weaken opportunism by locking partners into a range of
interdependent decisions over short-, medium-, and long-term time horizons; and to build
on the interdependencies and risks associated with 'asset specificity' by encouraging
solidarity among those involved. The rationality of governance is dialogic rather than
monologic, pluralistic rather than monolithic, heterarchic rather than either hierarchic or
anarchic. In turn this suggests that there is no one best governance mechanism.

The conditions for such reflexive rationality are as complex as those for well-functioning
markets or state planning. Interpersonal networking, interorganizational negotiation, and
intersystemic steering are different modes of coordination and pose different problems in
this regard. Specific objects of governance also affect the likelihood of success. For
example, governing the global economy, human rights regimes, and transnational social
movements clearly involve very different problems. Turbulent environments pose different
governance problems from those that are relatively stable -- especially as time is required
for self-organization to operate consensually. Governance mechanisms must provide a
framework in which relevant actors can reach agreement over (albeit possibly differential)
spatial and temporal horizons of action vis-à-vis their environment. They must also
stabilize the cognitive and normative expectations of these actors by shaping and
promoting a common 'worldview' as well as developing adequate solutions to sequencing

6
problems, i.e., predictably ordering various actions, policies, or processes over time,
especially where they have different temporal logics. At stake here is establishing secure
bases of coordination with their own structurally-inscribed strategic selectivity.

4. Governance Failure?

The growing interest in governance mechanisms as a solution to market failure or state


failure should not lead to neglect of governance failure. Governance need not prove more
efficient procedurally than markets and states as means of economic or political
coordination mechanism nor are they guaranteed to produce more adequate outcomes. A
commitment to continuing deliberation and negotiation does not exclude eventual
governance failure. The criterion for such failure is not, however, immediately obvious.
There is no pre-given formal maximand or reference point to judge governance success,
as there is with monetized profits in the economy and/or the (imaginary) perfect market
outcome. Nor is there a contingent substantive criterion -- the realization of specific
political objectives connected to the (imagined) public interest -- as there is with imperative
coordination by the state. The primary point of governance is that goals will be modified in
and through ongoing negotiation and reflection. This suggests that governance failure may
comprise failure to redefine objectives in the face of continuing disagreement about
whether they are still valid for the various partners.

But one can also apply procedural and substantive criteria to heterarchy and assess
whether it produces more efficient long-term outcomes than the market and more effective
long-term outcomes than imperative coordination by states. This involves adopting an
evolutionary perspective and requires comparative evaluation of all three modes of
coordination in terms of all three of their respective rationalities. This can be seen in the
increasing interest in heterarchy as a mechanism to reduce transaction costs in the
economy in cases of bounded rationality, complex interdependence, and asset specificity.
It is also reflected in the state's increasing interest in heterarchy's potential for enhancing
the former's capacity to secure political objectives by sharing power with forces beyond it
and/or delegating responsibilities for specific objectives to partnerships (or other
heterarchic arrangements). Likewise, of course, partnerships (or other heterarchic

7
arrangements) may simplify the pursuit of their own goals by relying on the market and/or
state to fulfil certain aspects of their jointly-agreed projects.

5. Potential Sources of Governance Failure

Rather than pursue these relatively abstract arguments about markets, states, and
governance and their forms of failure, I will now try to relate them to local economic and
social development. This analysis moves in three steps: an initial review of possible
sources of governance failure, identification of some basic dilemmas of governance at the
level of public-private partnerships (as derived from case studies in the North West and
Thames Gateway regions), and some brief references to specific examples of governance
arrangements and their tendencies to failure.

There are three main sets of factors that limit the success of governance in local economic
and social development. The first set affects all forms of economic and social coordination
and is inscribed in capitalism itself. The latter has always depended on a contradictory
balance between marketized and non-marketized organizational forms. Although this was
previously understood mainly in terms of the balance between market and state,
governance does not introduce a neutral third term but adds another site upon which the
balance can be contested. For new forms of governance provide a new meeting ground
for the conflicting logics of accumulation and political mobilization.

The second set concerns the contingent insertion of partnerships into the more general
state system -- especially in terms of the relative primacy of different modes of
coordination and access to institutional support and material resources to pursue
reflexively-arrived at governance objectives. Among crucial issues here are the flanking
and supporting measures that are taken by the state; the provision of material and
symbolic support; and the extent of any duplication or counteraction by other coordination
mechanisms.

We can distinguish three aspects of this second set of constraints. First, as both
governance and government mechanisms exist on different scales (indeed one of their
functions is to bridge scales), success at one scale may well depend on what occurs on

8
other scales. Second, coordination mechanisms may also have different temporal
horizons. One function of governance (as of quangos and corporatist arrangements
beforehand) is to enable decisions with long-term implications to be divorced from short-
term political (especially electoral) calculations. But disjunctions may still arise between
the temporalities of different governance and government mechanisms. Third, although
various governance mechanisms may acquire specific techno-economic, political, and/or
ideological functions, the state typically monitors their effects on its own capacity to secure
social cohesion in divided societies. It reserves to itself the right to open, close, juggle,
and re-articulate governance arrangements not only in terms of particular functions but
also from the viewpoint of partisan and overall political advantage.

The third set of constraints is rooted in the nature of governance as self-organization.


First, governance attempts may fail because of over-simplification of the conditions of
action and/or deficient knowledge about causal connections affecting the object of
governance. This is especially problematic when this object is an inherently unstructured
but complex system, such as the insertion of the local into the global economy. Indeed,
this leads to the more general 'governability' problem, i.e., the question of whether the
object of governance could ever be manageable, even with adequate knowledge (Mayntz
1993; Malpas and Wickham 1996). Second, there may be co-ordination problems on one
or more of the interpersonal, interorganizational, and intersystemic levels. These three
levels are often related in complex ways. Thus interorganizational negotiation often
depends on interpersonal trust; and de-centred intersystemic steering involves the
representation of system logics through interorganizational and/or interpersonal
communication. Third, linked to this is the problematic relationship between those
engaged in communication (networking, negotiation, etc.) and those whose interests and
identities are being represented. Gaps can open between these groups leading to
representational and legitimacy crises and/or to problems in securing compliance. And,
fourth, where there are various partnerships and other governance arrangements
concerned with interdependent issues, there is a problem of coordination among them. I
address this problem below in terms of metagovernance (section 7).

9
6. Partnership Dilemmas

These potential sources of governance failure assume different forms in different contexts.
Based on interviews with those involved in partnerships in the North West and the
Thames Gateway regions, we can specify four sets of strategic dilemmas that affect
economic development partnerships as they seek to develop a consensual approach to
the joint pursuit of a medium- to long-term strategy that advances both the individual and
collective interests of their various members. These dilemmas comprise:

Cooperation vs Competition: capitalist economies operate through an unstable mix of


cooperation and competition. One horn of the resulting dilemma is how to maintain
interpersonal trust, secure generalized compliance with negotiated understandings,
reduce noise through open communication, and engage in negative coordination in the
face of the many and varied opportunities that exist for short-term self-interested
competitive behaviour -- behaviour that could soon destroy the basis for continuing
partnership. The other horn is that an excessive commitment to cooperation and
consensus could block the emergence of creative tensions, conflicts, or efforts at crisis-
resolution that could promote learning and/or learning capacities and thereby enhance
adaptability. This horn is especially acute when the environment is turbulent, speedy
action is required, incrementalism is inappropriate, and it would take time to build
consensus. Such dilemmas have been widely discussed in recent analyses of flexible
industrial districts, learning regions, innovative milieux, etc.. They also occur politically in
the trade-off between partnership and partisanship. For partnerships are typically linked to
differential advantages for political parties, tiers of government, and departmental interests
as well as to differential economic interests of various kinds. This poses dilemmas both in
relation to any given partnership and, even more acutely, in relation to the opportunities
that may exist for juggling multiple partnerships to secure partisan advantage.

Openness vs Closure: heterarchic governance arrangements operate in complex, often


turbulent, environments. They face problems in remaining open to the environment at the
same time as securing the closure needed for effective coordination among a limited
number of partners. One horn of the resulting dilemma is that closure may lock in
members whose exit would be beneficial (e.g., inefficient firms, underemployed workers,

10
sunset sectors) or block recruitment of new social partners (e.g., new firms, marginalized
workers, sunrise sectors). The other horn is that openness may discourage partners from
entering into long-term commitments and sharing long-term time horizons. This may
prompt opportunism in (the potentially self-fulfilling) case that partnerships dissolve or
involve high turnover. It is reflected in the choice of maximizing the range of possible
actions by expanding relevant bases of membership or favouring the 'small is beautiful'
principle for the purpose of focused and timely action; and the choice of variable
geometries of action versus fixed spatial boundaries for membership of a governance
arrangement. An interesting variant of this latter version of the dilemma (especially given
the increasing importance of interregional cooperation in Europe) is whether to permit
transnational partnerships or to insist on the defense of national sovereignty.

Governability vs Flexibility: heterarchic arrangements are said to permit longer term


strategic guidance (lacking in markets) whilst still retaining flexibility (lacking in hierarchies
with their rule-governed procedures). But this is also the site of a dilemma: that between
governability (the capacity for effective guidance) and flexibility (the capacity to adapt to
changed circumstances). This assumes several forms. Reducing complexity through
operational rules as a precondition for governing a complex world needs to be balanced
against the recognition of complexity to mobilize the 'requisite variety' of actors and
resources. Avoiding duplication to limit resource costs needs to be balanced against
maintaining an adequate repertoire of actions and strategic capacities. A third variant is
posed in the choice between exploiting past organizational and interorganizational
learning to standardize around 'best practice' and maintaining adaptability in the face of a
turbulent environment by avoiding 'lock-in' to outmoded routines. This last problem is
particularly associated with efforts to impose 'best practice' from above rather than
encourage diversity and allow for horizontal communication and learning among
partnerships.

Accountability vs Efficiency: most public-private partnerships are expected to serve the


public interest as well as to deliver private benefits. But this blurs the public-private
distinction and poses a familiar dilemma in terms of accountability versus efficiency. On
the one hand, there are problems about attributing responsibility for decisions and non-
decisions (i.e., acts of commission or omission) in interdependent networks. These

11
problems are more acute when partnerships are interorganizational rather than
interpersonal. On the other hand, attempts to establish clear lines of accountability can
interfere with the efficient, cooperative pursuit of joint goals. A related dilemma is that
public-private arrangements run the risk of allowing the exploitative capture of public
resources for private purposes and/or extending the state's reach into the market
economy and civil society to serve the interests of the state or governing party. A third
version of this dilemma concerns the relative primacy of economic performance and social
inclusion -- how far the maximand in public-private partnerships is marketized economic
performance as opposed to addressing problems of social cohesion.

7. Metagovernance

If markets, states, and governance are each prone to failure, how is economic and political
coordination for economic and social development ever possible and why is it often judged
to have succeeded? In part this can be explained through the multiplicity of satisficing
criteria and the range of potential vested interests so that at least some aims are realized
to a socially acceptable degree for at least some of those affected. A further explanation
can be derived from the observation that 'governing and governance itself should be
dynamic, complex and varied' (Kooiman 1993: 36). This highlights the role of the 'meta-
structures' of interorganizational coordination (Alexander 1995: 52) or, more generally, of
'metagovernance', i.e., the governance of government and governance.

Metagovernance should not be confused with some superordinate level of government in


control of all governance arrangements nor with the imposition of a single, all-purpose
mode of governance. Rather, it involves managing the complexity, plurality, and tangled
hierarchies characteristic of prevailing modes of coordination. It involves defining new
boundary-spanning roles and functions, creating linkage devices, sponsoring new
organizations, identifying appropriate lead organizations to coordinate other partners,
designing institutions, and generating visions to facilitate self-organization in different
fields. It also involves providing mechanisms for collective feedback and learning about
the functional linkages and the material interdependencies among different sites and
spheres of action, and encouraging a relative coherence among diverse objectives, spatial
and temporal horizons, actions, and outcomes of governance arrangements. It involves

12
the shaping of the context within which these arrangements can be forged rather than
developing specific strategies and initiatives for them.

Governments play a major and increasing role in metagovernance. They provide the
ground rules for governance and the regulatory order in and through which governance
partners can pursue their aims; ensure the compatibility or coherence of different
governance mechanisms and regimes; act as the primary organizer of the dialogue
among policy communities; deploy a relative monopoly of organizational intelligence and
information with which to shape cognitive expectations; serve as a 'court of appeal' for
disputes arising within and over governance; seek to re-balance power differentials by
strengthening weaker forces or systems in the interests of system integration and/or social
cohesion; try to modify the self-understanding of identities, strategic capacities, and
interests of individual and collective actors in different strategic contexts and hence alter
their implications for preferred strategies and tactics; and also assume political
responsibility in the event of governance failure. This emerging role means that
networking, negotiation, noise reduction, and negative as well as positive coordination
occur 'in the shadow of hierarchy' (Scharpf 1994: 40). It also suggests the need for almost
permanent institutional and organisational innovation to maintain the very possibility
(however remote) of sustained economic growth.

Thus metagovernance does not eliminate other modes of coordination. Markets,


hierarchies, and heterarchies still exist; but they operate in a context of 'negotiated
decision-making'. Thus, on the one hand, market competition will be balanced by
cooperation, the invisible hand will be combined with a visible handshake. On the other
hand, the state is no longer the sovereign authority. It becomes but one participant among
others in the pluralistic guidance system and contributes its own distinctive resources to
the negotiation process. As the range of networks, partnerships, and other models of
economic and political governance expand, official apparatuses remain at best primus
inter pares. For, although public money and law would still be important in underpinning
their operation, other resources (such as private money, knowledge, or expertise) would
also be critical to their success. The state's involvement would become less hierarchical,
less centralized, and less dirigiste in character. The exchange of information and moral
suasion become key sources of legitimation and the state's influence depends as much on

13
its role as a prime source and mediator of collective intelligence as on its command over
economic resources or legitimate coercion (Willke 1992).

8. Metagovernance Failure

Recognizing possible contributions of reflexive metagovernance to economic and social


coordination is no guarantee of success. It is certainly not a purely technical matter that
can be resolved by experts in organizational design or public administration. For all the
technical activities of the state in whatever domain are conducted under the primacy of the
political, i.e., the state's concern with managing the tension between economic and
political advantages and its ultimate responsibility for social cohesion. This fact plagues
the liberal prescription of an arms-length relationship between the market and the
nightwatchman state -- since states are rarely strong enough to resist pressures to
intervene when anticipated political advantage is at stake or it needs to respond to social
unrest. This can be seen in the telling title of Michael Heseltine's report to Cabinet on the
change of direction on policies for the inner city: It took a riot (1985).

To minimize the risks of metagovernance failure, a repertoire of responses is needed to


retain the ability flexibly to alter strategies and select those that are more successful. This
may well seem inefficient from an economizing viewpoint because it introduces slack or
waste. But it also provides major sources of flexibility in the face of failure (cf. Grabher
1994). For, if every mode of economic and political coordination is failure-laden, relative
success in coordination over time depends on the capacity to switch modes of
coordination as the limits of any one mode become evident. This provides the basis for
displacing or postponing failures and crises. It also suggests that the ideologically-
motivated destruction of alternative modes of coordination could prove counter-productive:
for they may well need to be re-invented in one or another form. There are further
dilemmas here from an evolutionary viewpoint: (a) learning versus forgetting; and (b)
removing particulars versus retaining the general. If one affirms the maxim that 'it is
necessary to change society to preserve it', then there should be mechanisms for social
forgetting as well as social learning. One should also recognize that, even if specific
institutions and organizations are abolished, it may be necessary to safeguard the
underlying modes of coordination that they embody.

14
These dilemmas are evident from the experience of the Thatcher and Major governments.
The neo-liberal hostility to the interventionist state, trade unionism and corporatism,
municipal socialism, and other features of the postwar settlement was reflected in
continuing efforts to destroy, weaken, or marginalize them. But, whilst this was perhaps
necessary to change attitudes in the attempted modernization of the British economy,
state, and society, it also dissipated experience and knowledge that could still prove
useful. And, whilst it removed specific institutional and organizational obstacles to the neo-
liberal project, it also deprived the central state in the short-term of an adequate range of
modes of coordination to deal with complex issues in an environment made more
turbulent by the intended and unintended effects of its own radical policies. So the
Thatcher and Major governments eventually found it necessary to re-learn lessons about
the limits of the market mechanism and to re-invent alternative modes of coordination to
supplement, complement, or compensate for the operation of market forces. This re-
discovery was usually disguised behind changed names, innovative discourses, and
institutional turnover. Nonetheless the usual policy cycle of market, governance, and state
was repeated in central government policies for urban regeneration.

9. Two Case Studies

This section briefly illustrates some of the above themes by considering two cases from
our two regional research sites (the Thames Gateway and the North West). The first
concerns an interorganizational partnership centred in Dartford in North West Kent and
concerned with a particular property-led development project; the second concerns
networks mobilized around the Manchester Olympic bids as a larger place-marketing
exercise for Manchester and the North West. Both cases can be interpreted as instances
of governance failure as well as governance success.

a) Kent Thames-side Agency and London Science Park at Dartford

When we conducted interviews in Dartford at the beginning of our research on the


Thames Gateway region some four years ago, we were confidently informed by various
politicans, local government officers, and spokesmen for Dartford Chamber of Commerce

15
that one of the town's big successes was to have secured the London Science Park at
Dartford (hereafter LSP). At the conclusion of our research, the science park project had
been scaled down and was still far from being fully established. Exploring the reasons for
this illustrates many of the constraints on local governance identified above (sections 5
and 6).

The first set of constraints has to do with the dynamic of capitalism that were far beyond
the control of the local authority and its partners. Three major obstacles (among many) to
the LSP's timely establishment can be noted: the uneven development of the South East
economy, the problems of property-led development under a neo-liberal regime, and the
conflicting temporal and spatial horizons of action of different public and private sector
partners. The Thames Gateway initiative (initially flagged as the East Thames Corridor)
was intended to redress the overheating of the South East economy (especially to the
west of London) and to exploit the opening towards Europe by promoting growth in the
east; this would have the additional advantage of exploiting brownfield and derelict land
along the Thames and thus relieve pressure on the green belt. But the problems of
industrial and urban decay affecting the east Thames region were not removed simply
through declaration of the Thames Gateway initiative (especially given the emphasis on
private enterprise more than public funding) and continued to disfavour investment in the
region for high tech projects. Moreover, as the property-led development approach needs
continued economic expansion to justify investment, the collapse of Lawson's boom in the
late 1980s and the resulting overhang of property investments in the City and South East
proved a further disincentive. This in turn produced conflicting expectations about the
various time horizons and priorities for profitable development of the proposed LSP site
between private and public sector partners -- compounded by the greater spatial scope of
action for the two partners whose activities extended well beyond the local to the regional,
national, and international scales. This was reflected in conflicts around three issues: the
most appropriate uses, the ideal sequencing, and the proper distribution of profits from
bringing different parcels of land in different ownership into development. A merger
between Glaxo and Wellcome also altered the interests of a key partner.

The second set of constraints has to do with the insertion of the London Science Park
project into the wider set of local government and governance arrangements. Of particular

16
significance here was the turbulent political environment for the partners in the Kent
Thames-side agency concerned with the LSP. The rationale for the partnership was the
pooled interdependence of Dartford Borough Council (a major local landholder and
planning authority wishing to upgrade the town's image and economic prospects), the
Wellcome Foundation (a leading international pharmaceutical company and major local
employer), the local health authority (with a redundant hospital site and plans for
expansion), Blue Circle Industries (a major landowner and property developer by virtue of
its disused chalk pits in North West Kent), and the University of Greenwich (interested in
developing a new campus, including student accommodation, and boosting research links
with industry by locating at the LSP site). Three sources of uncertainty and turbulence
(among others) that affected the project were: (a) central government-induced changes in
the status, powers, and ownership rights of the health authority (in turn a regional health
authority, a district authority, and NHS trust) and hence in its interests in the project; (b)
politically-motivated delays in government commitments to infrastructural projects and
spending essential to the overall growth dynamic of the sub-region -- notably around the
Channel Tunnel Rail Link, the international rail terminal, and road links; and (c) changes in
central government policy on higher education and training that affected the interests of
the University of Greenwich regarding campus accommodation and research strategy.

Paradoxically, the partnership itself appears to have worked well. A clear recognition of
pooled interdependence provided a continuing framework for negotiation around the need
to balance conflicting property interests and the overall economic, political, and social
benefits of cooperation; a flexible framework that avoided a once-and-for-all decision on
the appropriate legal form and membership of the partnership encouraged a balance
between openness and closure and between governability and flexibility; and the insertion
of the LSP into a broader and largely consensual local and regional accumulation strategy
developed by the borough council permitted balance between economic efficiency and
political accountability. As delays in complementary economic projects (a major regional
shopping centre, an international rail terminal, the high speed channel tunnel rail link) are
overcome and the Thames Gateway role as the bridge between London and Europe
becomes a reality, the prospects for a scaled-down version of the LSP feeding into a more
general pattern of synergetic growth look better than they did at the end of our research.

17
b) The Manchester Olympic Bids

The Manchester Olympic bids illustrate the paradox of a successful failure, a project that
could be successfully marketed despite failing in key respects (Bovaird 1994). If one
regards them as place-marketing exercises linked to property-led development, they
helped market Manchester, mobilized important grants for urban regeneration, and
secured widespread recognition and support at home and abroad. Indeed, if one accepts
that the actual staging of the Games could prove costly, the eventual failure to secure
them could even be considered a success (contrast the Olympic experiences of Montr‚al
and Barcelona or Sheffield and the World Student Games). The presentational politics of
the bidding process required a united front among local partners and this, combined with
the broadly positive-sum nature of the Olympics-legitimated but state-aided and property-
led development project, provided the context in which the various dilemmas of
partnership were managed in the short-term.

From a governance viewpoint, three points need making. First, Manchester's Olympic
strategy illustrates the complementarity and interdependence among different scales of
economic and political action. Local governance is not confined to the local level. The bid
strategy and outcome involved a complex interplay between (a) local economic and
political capacities and priorities, (b) national and international systems of rule-setting
(especially those of the Department of the Environment and the International Olympic
Committee), and (c) European and central government political and economic strategies.
Second, the broad-based grant-coalition that fronted the Olympic bids was firmly rooted
not only in material interdependences but also in established informal interpersonal
networking among business leaders, political figures, and other local elites. This was the
basis of trust for interorganizational negotiations and the formation of a broad-based
hegemonic project for the region. Although Sir Bob Scott (whose role was famously
described as 'a man and his secretary sitting in an office and masquerading as an
institution') achieved a high profile in the bid process as the public (and acceptable) face
of private capital, a key meta-governance role was also performed by the local authorities
under the leadership of Manchester City Council. This is clear not only in promotional
activities but also in various project management activities. And, third, the Olympic bids
provided a positive-sum game for developing a broadly consensual local accumulation

18
strategy and hegemonic project. They provided the basis for levering European and
central government funding, secured property-led regeneration, enhanced the image of
Manchester (with some skilfully contrived confusion between Manchester City Council and
Greater Manchester), promised benefits to the North West more generally, and attracted
considerable local popular support. With the second failure to win the Olympics
nomination, much of this unity and support has been dissipated. A pattern of
fragmentation and duplication of partnerships has re-asserted itself. This illustrates the
role of strategy and vision as well as structures in maintaining local governance (for further
details on this case study, see Cochrane et al., 1996; and Jessop et al., 1999).

10. Concluding Remarks

In short, markets, states, and governance all fail. This is not surprising. For failure is a
central feature of all social relations: 'governance is necessarily incomplete and as a
necessary consequence must always fail' (Malpas and Wickham 1995: 40). Given the
growing structural complexity and opacity of the social world, indeed, failure is the most
likely outcome of most attempts to govern it in terms of multiple objectives over extended
spatial and temporal horizons -- whatever coordination mechanism is adopted. This
emphasis on the improbability of success serves to counter the rhetoric of partnership that
leads commentators to highlight achievements rather than failures and, where they
recognize failure, to see it as exceptional and corrigible in regard to their preferred mode
of coordination even as they see coordination failure elsewhere as inevitable. This
polarization is reflected both in the succession of governments and in policy cycles within
governments in which different modes of policy-making succeed each other as the
difficulties of each become more evident. Postwar British politics offers plenty of evidence
of this through the increasingly hectic oscillation among liberal, dirigiste, and corporatist
modes of economic intervention (witness, in particular, the successive U-turns in the
Heath government of 1970-74 and the Wilson-Callaghan governments of 1974-79).

Once the incompleteness of attempts at coordination (whether through the market, the
state, or heterarchy) is accepted as inevitable, it is necessary to adopt a satisficing
approach that has at least three key dimensions:

19
• a reflexive orientation to what will prove satisfactory in the case of failure, to compare
the effects of failure/inadequacies in the market, government, and governance, and
regular re-assessment of the extent to which current actions are producing desired
outcomes.

• deliberate cultivation of a flexible repertoire (requisite variety) of responses so that


strategies and tactics can be combined to reduce the likelihood of failure and to alter
their balance in the face of failure and turbulence in the policy environment. Moreover,
as different periods and conjunctures require different kinds of policy mix, the balance
in the repertoire will need to be varied. And

• a self-reflexive 'irony' in the sense that participants must recognize the likelihood of
failure but proceed as if success were possible. The supreme irony in this context is
that the need for irony holds not only for individual governance mechanisms but also
for metagovernance itself.

For reasons I have explored in more detail elsewhere (Jessop 1997b, 1998), I suggest
that public-private partnership in its various forms is especially appropriate for securing
economic, social, and community development in the current period despite its inevitable
tendencies towards governance failure. This suggests the need to put such governance
arrangements at the core of the coordination repertoire with diverse flanking and
supportive measures from other modes of coordination. But there must also be greater
commitment to a participatory politics based on stakeholding and to sustainable economic
and community development.7308

References

Alexander, E.R. (1995) How Organizations Act Together: Interorganizational Coordination


in Theory and Practice, Amsterdam: Overseas Publishers Association.
Bovaird, T. (1994) 'Managing Urban Economic Development: learning to change or the
marketing of failure?', Urban Studies, 31 (4/5), 573-604.

20
Cochrane, A., Peck, J., and Tickell, A. (1996) 'Manchester plays games: exploring the
local politics of globalisation', Urban Studies, 33 (10), 1319-1336.
Coulson, A. (1997) 'Transaction Cost Economics' and its Implications for Local
Governance', Local Government Studies, 23 (1), 107-113.
Grabher, G. (1994) Lob der Verschwendung, Berlin: Edition Sigma.
Jessop, B. (1995) 'The Regulation Approach and Governance Theory: Alternative
Perspectives on economic and political change?', Economy and Society, 24 (3), 307-
333.
Jessop, B. (1997a) 'A neo-Gramscian approach to the regulation of urban regimes', in M.
Lauria, ed., Reconstructing Urban Regime Theory, London: Sage, 51-73.
Jessop, B. (1997b) 'The Governance of Complexity and the Complexity of Governance:
Preliminary Remarks on some Problems and Limits of Economic Guidance', in A.
Amin and J. Hausner, eds., Beyond Markets and Hierarchy: Third Way Approaches to
Transformation, Aldershot: Edward Elgar, 111-147.
Jessop, B. (1998) 'The Rise of Governance and the Risks of Failure: the Case of
Economic Development', International Social Science Journal, issue 155, 29-46.
Jessop, B. (1997d) 'The Entrepreneurial City: Re-Imaging Localities, Redesigning
Economic Governance, or Restructuring Capital?', in N. Jewson and S. MacGregor,
eds, Realising Cities: New Spatial Divisions and Social Transformation, London:
Routledge, 28-41.
Jessop, B., Peck, J., and Tickell, A. (1999) 'Retooling the machine: economic crisis, state
restructuring and urban politics', in A.E.G. Jonas and D.Wilson, eds., The Urban
Growth Machine: Critical Perspectives Twenty Years Later, New York: State
University of New York Press.
Kooiman, W. (1993) 'Governance and governability: using complexity, dynamics and
diversity', in idem, ed., Modern Governance: New Government-Society Interactions,
London: Sage, 35-48.
Malpas, J. and Wickham, G. (1995) 'Governance and Failure: on the Limits of Sociology',
Australian and New Zealand Journal of Sociology, 31 (3), 37-50.
Mayntz, R. (1993) 'Governing Failures and the Problem of Governability: some Comments
on a Theoretical Paradigm.' in J. Kooiman, ed., Modern Governance: new
Government-Society Interactions, London: Sage, 9-20.

21
Offe, C. (1975) 'The Theory of the Capitalist State and the Problem of Policy Formation.' in
L.N. Lindberg et al., eds., Stress and Contradiction in Modern Capitalism, Lexington:
D.C. Heath, 125-144.
Scharpf, F.W. (1994) 'Games Real Actors could Play: Positive and Negative Coordination
in Embedded Negotiations', Journal of Theoretical Politics, 6 (1), 27-53.
Willke, H. (1992) Ironie des Staates: Grundlinien einer Staatstheorie polyzentrischer
Gesellschaft, Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
Wolf, C. (1978) 'A Theory of nonmarket failure: framework for implementation analysis',
Journal of Law and Economics, 21 (1), 107-139.

Note: The principal publications from this research project to date are listed above. Further
information on other publications and work in progress is available from the author.

22

View publication stats

You might also like