White - 1990 - Environmental History, Ecology, and Meaning
White - 1990 - Environmental History, Ecology, and Meaning
White - 1990 - Environmental History, Ecology, and Meaning
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 150.165.254.27 on Tue, 12 May 2020 18:34:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Environmental History, Ecology,
and Meaning
Richard White
Over the last fifteen years, Donald Worster has been the most thoughtful and
stimulating of American environmental historians. His concern with big problems,
the clarity of his thought and prose, and his grasp of the field make him the ideal
choice for explaining the fallacy of writing history as if human beings "have not been
and are not truly part of the planet." His emphasis on the material grounding of
human history is particularly timely given the current prominence of post-
structuralist analysis with its potential for moving historical analysis ever further
away from concern with the physical world in which human beings live.1
And yet in reading Professor Worster's article, at least some environmental
historians besides myself will get an odd feeling of displacement among familiar
surroundings. Reading the article is like viewing a television interview with a family
that presents itself as altogether too harmonious. If conflicts or problems are ad-
mitted, they are minor; basic disagreements are quashed. Wayward spouses, delin-
quent children, threatening illnesses, and mortgages in arrears are not for public
view.
Such public presentations are hardly simple falsehoods, for the family member
doing the speaking gets, in effect, to define the family as it ideally should be and
as he or she hopes it will be. Similarly, Worster's account of environmental history
is as much a prescription as a description. And while I share most of his ambitions
for the field, things are not as harmonious or simple as they seem. Rather than
quarrel with his prescriptions or present an alternate version, I'd like to examine
some of the underlying issues that prompt Worster's program.
Donald Worster is, first of all, attempting to define a new historical field in a way
that makes it central to the discipline as a whole. He places environmental history
at the point where the natural and the cultural intersect and interact with each
other. With the field defined this way, it is difficult (I hope) for most historians to
force it to the periphery of historical concerns.
I Post-structuralism refers to the work of those recent thinkers who have, in Hans Kellner's words, "challenged
the primacy and security of meaning of history, of narrative, and the idea of 'man' which is constructed by these
practices." At their most extreme, post-structuralists reduce history to a pure textuality in which it differs little from
any other form of narrative. Hans Kellner, "Narrativity in History: Post Structuralism and Since," History and
Theory, 26 (Dec. 1987), 2-29.
This content downloaded from 150.165.254.27 on Tue, 12 May 2020 18:34:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1112 The Journal of American History
Having defined the field, Worster outlines what might be called its methods.
Here, however, under the guise of stating conventional wisdom, he is trying to create
it, or rather to impose a much older construct on the field. Environmental history
has a base (natural history), a structure (productive relations or modes of produc-
tion), and a superstructure (culture and ideology). In his hierarchical model, he
seeks to avoid reductionism and any simple material determinism. The "great chal-
lenge," as he states it, is identifying the reciprocal relationships between the levels.
Worster's final task, which takes up more than two-thirds of the article, is osten-
sibly to review "the broader themes" of environmental history, but it is really more
an attempt to set its agenda. He examines only one theme -agroecology- which
he deems primary, for in obtaining food humans "have been connected in the most
vital, constant, and concrete way to the natural world." Agroecology becomes a case
study showing how his methodology illuminates the most "basic and revealing" of
the concerns of environmental history the production of food. The discussion, as
would surprise no one familiar with Worster's work, ends with an examination of
the causes and consequences of the rise of capitalist agriculture.
Worster's procedures are analogous to those of our family host who shows the tele-
vision audience around the house and then describes a new addition the family is
constructing out back. He seems to hide nothing. He displays the blueprint (his
base/structure/superstructure), his scale model (agroecology); he even admits that
the building site (the science of ecology) has certain problems. What the camera
misses are the family arguments over the blueprint, the omission of certain critical
details in the model, and the slow sinking of the foundation of the house itself.
The uninitiated will misconstrue the argument if they think Worster's blueprint
has old-fashioned, even vulgar, Marxist lines. The inspiration is really Braudelian.
Worster is building for the longue duree, and his plan - and agroecological model -
are full of the long-term conjunctures, disequilibriums, and equilibriums that mark
Fernand Braudel's work. With the always notable exception of Alfred W. Crosby,
American environmental historians have usually operated on a much smaller tem-
poral and geographical scale than Worster sketches out here. While his colleagues
have thought of intellectual progress in terms of adding another bath, Don Worster
is ready to build Trump Towers in the backyard.2
His model for the field differs from much current work in scale, and also because
to construct it, Don Worster is urging scholars who have often written inductively
(or at least pretended to) to think deductively. His model for agroecology makes
sense only when we realize that we already know the critical structures, conjunctures,
and disequilibriums that demand study; the most important of them is the rise of
capitalism with its "radical simplification of the natural ecological order." The.crea-
tion of the capitalist mode of production becomes the key environmental process;
the most influential determinant of environmental change since the last Ice Age.
2 For an overview of Fernand Braudel's concerns that enables a reader to compare them with Donald Worster's,
see Fernand Braudel, Afterthoughts on Material Civilization and Capitalism (Baltimore, 1977), 3-35. See Alfred
W. Crosby, Ecological Imperialism: The Biological Expansion of Europe, 900-1900 (New York, 1986).
This content downloaded from 150.165.254.27 on Tue, 12 May 2020 18:34:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Environmental History, Ecology, and Meaning 1113
3 Maurice Godelier, The Mental and the Material: Thought, Economy, and Society (Bristol, 1986), 35.
4 See Marshall Sahlins, Culture and Practical Reason (Chicago, 1976), esp. 126-65.
5 Stephen Gudeman, Economics as Culture: Models and Metaphors ofLivelihood (London, 1986), 26. See also
Stephen Gudeman, The Demise of a Rural Economy: From Subsistence to Capitalism in a Latin American Village
(London, 1978).
This content downloaded from 150.165.254.27 on Tue, 12 May 2020 18:34:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1114 The Journal of American History
6 Richard White, The Middle Ground: Europeans, Indians, and Empires in the Pays den Haut, 1650-1815 (New
York, forthcoming).
7 Sahlins, Culture and Practical Reason, 205. See also Pierre Clastres, Society against the State (New York, 1987),
189-218.
This content downloaded from 150.165.254.27 on Tue, 12 May 2020 18:34:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Environmental History, Ecology, and Meaning 1115
ance in nature that, once achieved, will maintain itself. Those verities gave historians
standards against which to measure and evaluate the repercussions of human action.
As Professor Worster points out, the science of ecology no longer bestows such
verities. Historians thought ecology was the rock upon which they could build en-
vironmental history; it turned out to be a swamp. Ecology provides the land upon
which Worster's agroecology, and the other wings and additions attached to environ-
mental history, must sit. For although in popular speech (as in my own metaphor)
ecology has been reified into nature, ecology is, in fact, only an academic discipline.
The questioning of ecological verities within the science has consequences graver
than Worster admits. In modern ecology the idea of a natural climax- a community
of plants and animals ideally adjusted to a given environment - has largely van-
ished. Along with climax, the idea of successional communities has come into
doubt. A picture of constant flux replaced succession with "only different kinds
degrees of vegetational stability and instability, different kinds and rates of pop
tion change." Nature, in the words of one ecologist, is only a "veritable shimmer
of populations in space and time."8
One of the ironies of environmental history is that historians have themselves
helped erode ecological verities even as they used them to evaluate history.
Historians revealed to ecologists how far back human manipulations of the envi
ment went and how extensive they were. It became harder for scientists to thin
that the communities they were describing and studying were the results of na
processes alone. Ecologists themselves turned to historians to help reconstitute t
science to study human social and economic processes as well as biological proces
Historians, who had relied on the scientists to provide their basic guidelines, a
scientists, who saw historians helping transform their object of study, met in
of mutual bewilderment. Things will certainly progress beyond this - and a new
exciting scholarly hybrid may result -but so far there has been little progress
The erosion of ecology has certainly not eliminated historians' conviction that en-
vironmental and social change are interlinked, but it has tended to focus attention
largely on the grossest examples of that linkage. Those gross examples are uniformly
disasters: dust bowls, the pandemics that devastated the Western Hemisphere, the
devastation of the Sahel by human use and by drought. Unable to trace the everyday
consequences of environmental change induced by humans with the precision they
would like, historians gravitate to disasters where the human impact is clear.10
Such efforts are useful and revealing, but they can attain the larger goals that Don
Worster outlines only in part. To read much environmental history is to become con-
vinced that only a miracle has preserved life on this planet, and that all environ-
8 R. H. Whittaker cited in Edward Goldsmith, "Ecological Succession Rehabilitated," Ecologist, 15 (1985), 106,
which contains a defense of old-fashioned ecology, reproducing the attacks on it.
9 This meeting quite literally took place at a National Science Foundation conference on Landscape History
and Ecological Succession, at Duke University, Jan. 28-31, 1988.
10 Donald Worster, The Dust Bowl: The Southern Plains in the 1930s (New York, 1979); Alfred W. Crosby,
The Columbian Exchange: Biological and Cultural Consequences of 1492 (Westport, 1972); Richard W. Franke
and Barbara H. Chasin, Seeds of Famine: Ecological Destruction and the Development Dilemma in the West
African Sahel (Montclair, 1980).
This content downloaded from 150.165.254.27 on Tue, 12 May 2020 18:34:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1116 The Journal of American History
11 Anthony Giddens, Central Problems in Social Theory: Action, Structure, and Contradiction in Social Anal-
ysis (Berkeley, 1979); Anthony Giddens, A Contemporary Critique of Historical Materialism (Berkeley, 1981).
This content downloaded from 150.165.254.27 on Tue, 12 May 2020 18:34:59 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms