Utilitarianism
Utilitarianism
Utilitarianism
Utilitarianism
- Is an ethical theory that argues for the goodness of pleasure and the determination of
right behavior based on the usefulness of the action’s consequences.
- This means that pleasure is good and that the goodness of an action is determined by its
usefulness.
- It claims that one’s actions and behavior are good inasmuch as they are directed toward
the experience of the greatest pleasure over pain for the greatest number of persons.
Utilitarian Thinkers:
Jeremy Bentham (1748 - 1832)
- He was born on Feb 15, 1748 in London, England.
- He was the teacher of James Mill, father of John Stuart Mill.
- He first wrote about the greatest happiness principle of ethics and was known for a
system of penal management called PANOPTICON.
- He was an advocate of economic freedom, women’s rights and the separation of church
and state, among others.
- He was also an advocate of animal rights and the abolition of slavery, death penalty and
corporal punishment for children.
- He denied individual legal rights nor agreed with the natural law.
- On his death on June 6, 1832, he donated his corpse to the University College London,
where his auto - icon is in public display up to this day to serve as his memorial.
- The principle also refers to pleasure as good if, and only if, they produce more happiness
than unhappiness.
*This means that it is not enough to experience pleasure, but to also inquire whether the things
we do make us happier.
*Having identified the tendency for pleasure and the avoidance of pain as the principle of utility,
BENTHAM then equates happiness with pleasure.
We need to understand the nature of pleasure and pain to identify a criterion for distinguishing
pleasures and to calculate the resultant pleasure or pain.
What Bentham identified as the natural moral preferability of pleasure, Mill refers to as a theory
of life.
E.g.
If we consider what moral agents do and how they assess their actions, then it is hard to deny
the pursuit for happiness and the avoidance of pain.
*While utilitarian supporters do not condone excessive pleasures while others are suffering, it
cannot be justified on utilitarian grounds why some persons indulge in extravagant pleasures at
the expense of others.
Suppose nobody is suffering, is it morally permissible on utilitarian principles to maximize
pleasure by wanton intemperance?
Bentham and Mill do not have the same view on these questions.
- He also argues that quality is more preferable than quantity (in contrary to Bentham).
- An excessive quantity of what is otherwise pleasurable might result in pain.
- We can consider our experience of excessive eating or exercising.
- E.g.
- Eating the right amount of food can be pleasurable, excessive eating may not be.
- In deciding over two comparable pleasures, it is important to experience both and to
discover which one is actually more preferred than the other.
- There is no other way of determining which of the two pleasures is preferable except by
appealing to the actual preferences and experiences.
- Actual choices of knowledgeable persons point that higher intellectual pleasures are
preferable than purely sensual appetites.
*Another comparison between intellectual and bestial pleasures, Mill offers an imaginative
thought experiment. He asks whether a human person would prefer to accept the highly
pleasurable life of an animal while at the same time being denied of everything that makes him a
person.
As human beings, we prefer the pleasures that are actually within our grasp. It is easy to
compare extreme types of pleasures as in the case of pigs and humans, but it is difficult to
compare pleasures deeply integrated in our way of life.
E.g.
Some people prefer puto to bibingka OR
Liking of Moira than of KZ Tandigan
Principle of the Greatest Number
Equating happiness with pleasure does not aim to describe the utilitarian moral agent alone and
independently from others.
This is not only about individual pleasures, regardless of how high, intellectual, or in other ways
noble it is, but it is also about the pleasure of the greatest number affected by the consequences
of our actions.
- Utilitarianism cannot lead to selfish acts.
- It is neither about our pleasure nor happiness alone, it cannot be all about us.
- If we are the only ones satisfied by our actions, it does not constitute a moral good.
- If we are the only ones who are made happy by our actions, then we cannot be morally
good.
- In this sense, it is not dismissive of sacrifices that procure more happiness for others.
- It is interested with everyone’s happiness.
- E.g.
- Eradication of a disease using technology
- It is interested with the best consequence for the highest number of people.
- It is not interested with the intention of the agent.
- It is based solely and exclusively on the difference it makes on the world’s total amount
of pleasure and pain.
*If actions are based only on the greatest happiness of the greatest number, is it justifiable to let
go of some rights for the sake of the benefit of the majority?
Rights
- A valid claim on society and are justified by utility.
- It is referred to the interests that serve general happiness.
- E.g.
- The right to due process
- The right to free speech or religion
- These rights are justified because they contribute to the general good.
- (which means that society is made happier if its citizens are able to live their lives
knowing that their interests are protected and that society (as a whole) defends it.)
- It is justifiable on utilitarian principles inasmuch as they produce an overall happiness
that is greater than the unhappiness resulting from their implementation.
- Utilitarian argues that issues of justice carry a very strong emotional import because the
category of rights is directly associated with the individual’s most vital interests. All of
these rights are predicated on the person’s right to life.
- Mill associates utilitarianism with the possession of legal and moral rights.
- We are treated justly when our legal and moral rights are respected.
- Mill creates a distinction between legal rights and their justification.
- He points out that when legal rights are not morally justified in accordance to the
greatest happiness principle, then these rights need neither be observed, nor be
respected.
- Mill seems to be suggesting that it is morally permissible to not follow, even violate an
unjust law.
- The implication is that those who protest over political policies of a morally
objectionable government act in a morally obligatory way. While this is not always
preferred, he thinks that it is commendable to endure legal punishments for acts of civil
disobedience for the sake of promoting a higher moral good. At an instance of conflict
between moral and legal rights, he points out that moral rights take precedence over
legal rights.
- While it can be justified why others violate legal rights, it is an act of injustice to violate
an individual’s moral rights. BUT he provides some extenuating circumstances in which
some moral rights can be overridden for the sake of the greater general happiness.
- E.g.
- Wiretapping case —- it seems that one’s right to privacy can be sacrificed for the sake of
the common good. This means that moral rights are only justifiable by considerations of
greater overall happiness.
- In this sense, the principle of utility can theoretically obligate us to steal, kill, and the
like.
- While there is no such thing as a laudible and praiseworthy injustice, Mill appeals to the
utilitarian understanding of justice as an act justified by the greatest happiness
principle.
- There is no right to violate where utility is not served by the social protection of
individual interests.
- While he recognizes how utilitarian principles can sometimes obligate us to perform
acts that would regularly be understood as disregarding individual rights, he argues that
this is only possible if it is judged to produce more happiness than unhappiness.
*Mill’s moral rights and considerations of justice are not absolute, but are only justified by their
consequences to promote the greatest good of the greatest number.
Justice can be interpreted in terms of moral rights because justice promotes the greater social
good.