Spiritual Intelligence or Spiritual Consciousness?: Commentary
Spiritual Intelligence or Spiritual Consciousness?: Commentary
COMMENTARY
Requests for reprints should be sent to John D. Mayer, Department of Psychology, University of New
Hampshire, Durham, NH 03824.
48 MAYER
To me, the term intelligence refers to a capacity or ability that primarily concerns
performing valid abstract reasoning with coherent symbol systems. This abstract
reasoning criterion overlaps only partly with the eight criteria of an intelligence,
originally developed by Gardner (1993, pp. 62–68), and used by Emmons to assess
spiritual intelligence. The “abstract reasoning” criterion represents a more classical
approach to intelligence: Symposia on intelligence over the years repeatedly con-
clude that the first hallmark of intelligence is the capacity to carry out abstract rea-
soning (Sternberg, 1997). Such thinking involves the ability to carry out many
types of mental transformations, such as identifying similarities and differences,
making generalizations, mentally rotating figures, and other tasks, all according to
specifiable rules (e.g., Carroll, 1993).
By contrast, only one or two of Gardner’s (1993, pp. 62–68) eight criteria, his
“core mental operations,” and perhaps his “symbol system” requirement, approxi-
mate abstract reasoning. The remaining six criteria are a combination of cultural,
empirical, and other characteristics. Because the criteria are each equally
INTELLIGENCE OR CONSCIOUSNESS? 49
tuality. Consider children who feel spiritual with every part of themselves; who talk to
imagined or (some would say) real divine presences far more easily than adults. They
have taken a leap of imaginative purity that would confound most adults. Whether
such children are intelligent, however, seems irrelevant to their conscious experience
of spirituality.
To be sure, some cognition (and therefore, intelligence) is present in all men-
tal life. Praying for the health and welfare of one’s family requires knowledge of
what “health,” “family,” and “welfare” are. Cognition is not, however, primary
in such instances, and we would expect the person praying to attend to spiritual
matters but not necessarily to possess high intelligence in order to pray. My
point is that intelligence does not exist simply because some cognition is pres-
ent, but rather, abstract reasoning must be primary. Consider the realm of artifi-
cial intelligence. We usually attribute intelligence to those machines that reach a
critical mass of cognitive processing, such as a general-purpose computer that
can solve a variety of problems or a computer dedicated to a mentally demand-
ing activity such as playing chess. By comparison, a television is not primarily
distinguished by its intelligence, even though it certainly processes information
and might even contain a “smart chip” that permits it to solve certain limited
problems.
Elsewhere, I have argued that there exists an extremely heterogeneous class of per-
sonality parts that include basic, brain-related mechanisms or modes of processing.
These are variously called enablers or enabling mechanisms because they enable
human personality to operate (e.g., Averill, 1992; Mayer, 1995; Mayer, Chabot, &
Carlsmith, 1997). Each class reflects distinct mental operations, as measured by
psychometric and experimental methods; moreover, each class roughly corre-
INTELLIGENCE OR CONSCIOUSNESS? 51
sponds to the excitation of distinct brain regions (see Hilgard, 1980; MacLean,
1973; Mayer, Chabot, & Carlsmith, 1997, for reviews).
These enablers can be divided into four broad categories, which include cogni-
tion, motives, emotions, and consciousness. At this near-brain level, it is possible
to separate out something like a pure motive (e.g., thirst), a pure feeling (e.g., sad-
ness), a pure mental capacity (e.g., the capacity to remember digits), and pure con-
sciousness (e.g., awareness of being alive). Each one of these areas of function can
itself be broken down into a still-heterogeneous area of activity. For example, mo-
tives such as hunger and thirst pertain to metabolic function whereas motives such
as the need for affiliation or aggression pertain to social function. Similarly, cogni-
tion involves both verbal and spatial reasoning, which may involve different areas
of the brain (e.g., Kosslyn et al., 1999). As a first approximation, however, it
makes sense to talk about the broad, biologically related classes of motives, emo-
tions, cognitions, and consciousness.
Motives, emotions, or cognitions rarely operate on their own, however, but
rather blend together to some degree. They join in two ways: first, at the near-bi-
ological level itself and then as they are synthesized when a person learns and
thinks about the world. At the near-biological level, the four classes of enablers
are interconnected and act on one another. Table 1 shows some ways that a given
motive, emotion, cognition, or conscious activity (listed down the left-hand side)
acts upon another (as listed across the top). For example, we can think of con-
sciousness acting on emotion—to make it felt, attended to, examined. Similarly,
we can think of an emotion, such as fear, acting on consciousness to narrow it
down to self-preservation.
Enablers stay relatively unchanged in terms of function and purpose through-
out the life span. At the same time, by virtue of operating in a changing, growing
mind, they can become enhanced, or guided, in some ways. Thus, short-term
memory can be enhanced by learning mnemonics (i.e., memory tricks). Con-
sciousness appears able to guide or steer itself through the use of self-sugges-
tion, the influence of current concerns, meditative practices, and other
procedures (e.g., Csikszentmihalyi, 1990; Ornstein, 1972). Such directed con-
sciousness seems to describe Emmons’s first aspect of spiritual intelligence,
transcendence. Transcendence includes such qualities as leaving behind physi-
cality, and sensing bonds with humanity. This seems, to me, close to what psy-
chologists call “structuring,” or “developing” consciousness, as opposed to
cognition; such structuring guides a person’s attention to certain mental phe-
nomena (e.g., breathing, oneness) until the conscious state is altered. Similarly,
Emmons’s second manifestation of spiritual intelligence, mysticism, seems ex-
plicable this way. Mysticism involves entering spiritual states of consciousness
in which, through the use of special rituals and prayer, one may become espe-
cially contemplative, have flashes of insight, or even see visions. Thus, both
transcendence and mysticism appear primarily to involve highly structured con-
52 MAYER
TABLE 1
Potential Actions On One Another of Motives, Emotions, Cognitions, and Consciousness
System That
Acts Motivation Emotion Cognition Consciousness
Emmons’s spiritual intelligence and its five aspects seem to cover a variety of
parts of mental life: from structured aspects of consciousness to nonintellective
personality traits. To me, Emmons’s proposed spiritual intelligence does not yet
meet the criterion of primarily involving abstract reasoning. This does not pre-
clude some future version of the concept from meeting such a conceptual crite-
rion. Then, one could determine whether the intelligence also satisfies necessary
empirical criteria. There is no doubt that some spiritual individuals reason, and
often with great sophistication. There exist important philosophies of guilt, lov-
ing kindness, mercy, humility, and other feelings and their relation to ultimate
issues (e.g., Otto, 1950; Peli, 1984). We would need to know more, however,
about the unique features of such reasoning before spiritual intelligence can be
better understood.
To illustrate what I mean about understanding the reasoning involved in spiritu-
ality, consider the recent case of emotional intelligence (e.g., Mayer & Salovey,
1997; Salovey & Mayer, 1990) as a candidate intelligence. Emotions had been
studied for centuries before the concept of an emotional intelligence could be fully
developed. The idea of emotional intelligence developed from a centuries-old,
philosophical literature on the meaning of emotions (e.g., Calhoun & Solomon,
1984; Frank, 1988). It developed, as well, from several decades of more concerted
scientific work on the nature of emotion, its language, and its meanings (e.g.,
Bower, 1981; Buck, 1984; Ortony, Clore, & Collins, 1988; see Clark & Fiske,
1982; Forgas, in press, for reviews). This work culminated, perhaps, with empiri-
cal work in artificial intelligence and computer understanding of emotions (Dyer,
1983; Picard, 1997).
INTELLIGENCE OR CONSCIOUSNESS? 55
Some flavor of the rules discovered in such work can be obtained from consider-
ing the fictional character, Jane, who was angry one afternoon at 2 p.m., and ashamed
at 3 p.m. Given such information, one could surmise that, in-between her anger and
her shame, she may have expressed anger and then thought the better of it, or discov-
ered new information which rendered the anger unjustified and petty-seeming, or
simply felt ashamed she was angry—as she often does. One can see it is less likely
that in-between she had a wonderful interview with the Queen of England (Mayer,
Caruso, & Salovey, 1999). Reasoning like this, I would argue, concerns how one
emotion can change into certain emotions but not others, given a specific circum-
stance. Understanding such rules is as complex and sophisticated, in its own way, as
is syllogistic reasoning.
A similar working out of the rules of spiritual intelligence would provide a
firmer basis for such a proposed entity. It seems to me, however, that esoteric prac-
tices of spirituality, along with the lengthy training necessary to learn certain spiri-
tual practices, has impeded the study of the reasoning that is a part of spirituality.
The rules of spirituality, whatever they may be, remain to be elaborated, codified,
and understood. As I review works by more intellectually oriented spiritual writ-
ers, I see the possibility of codifying such thought, but, to the best of my knowl-
edge, it has not yet taken place.
A great service could be done in this area by first elucidating the intellectual
underpinnings—the abstract reasoning—involved in spirituality. We must un-
derstand the symbol system of spiritual and religious writing better to understand
the sort of reasoning that takes place within it. What are the mental transforma-
tions necessary to think spiritually? Can the rules of such reasoning be made ac-
cessible to the scientist, to computer representations? Are there special instances
when spiritual thought achieves a critical mass of abstract reasoning, and there-
fore qualifies as an intelligence? At present, spiritual intelligence, like spiritual-
ity itself, remains mysterious in many respects. As Emmons pursues his journey
of describing a spiritual intelligence, I look forward to what he will teach us
about the quality of thought that accompanies spirituality.
REFERENCES
Averill, J. R. (1992). The structural bases of emotional behavior: A metatheoretical analysis. Review of
Personality and Social Psychology, 13, 1–24.
Bower, A. T. (1981). Mood and memory. American Psychologist, 36, 129–148.
Buck, R. (1984). The communication of emotion. New York: Guilford.
Calhoun, C., & Solomon, R. C. (Eds.). (1984). What is an emotion?: Classic readings in philosophical
psychology. New York: Oxford University Press.
Carroll, J. B. (1993). Human cognitive abilities: A survey of factor-analytic studies. New York: Cam-
bridge University Press.
Clark, M. S., & Fiske, S. T. (1982). Affect and cognition: The 17th Annual Carnegie Symposium on Cog-
nition. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.
56 MAYER
Csikszentmihalyi, M. (1990). Flow: The psychology of optimal experience. New York: HarperCollins.
Dyer, M.G. (1983). The role of affect in narratives. Cognitive Science, 7, 211–242.
Elkins, D. N., Hedstrom, L. J., Hughes, L. L., Leaf, J. A., & Saunders, C. L. (1988). Toward a humanis-
tic–phenomenological spirituality: Definition, description, and measurement. Journal of Humanis-
tic Psychology, 28, 5–18.
Forgas, J. P. (in press). Handbook of affect and social cognition. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum
Associates, Inc.
Frank, R. H. (1988). Passions with reason: The strategic role of the emotions. New York: Norton.
Gardner, H. (1993). Frames of mind: The theory of multiple intelligences. New York: Basic Books.
Hilgard, E. R. (1980). The trilogy of mind: Cognition, affection, and conation. Journal of the History of
the Behavioral Sciences, 16, 107–117.
Kelly, G.A. (1955). The psychology of personal constructs (Vol. 1). New York: Norton.
Kosslyn, S. M., Pascual-Leone, A., Felician, O., Camposano, S., Keenan, J. P., Thompson, W. L.,
Ganis, G., Sukel, K. E., & Alpert, N. M. (1999). The role of Area 17 in visual imagery: Convergent
evidence from PET and rTMS. Science, 284, 167–170.
MacLean, P. D. (1973). A triune concept of the brain and behavior. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Markus, H. (1977). Self-schemata and processing information about the self. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 35, 63–78.
Mayer, J. D. (1995). A framework for the classification of personality components. Journal of Personal-
ity, 63, 819–877.
Mayer, J. D. (1998). A systems framework for the field of personality psychology. Psychological In-
quiry, 9, 118–144.
Mayer, J. D. (in press). Emotion, intelligence, emotional intelligence: Individual differences in hot pro-
cessing. In J. P. Forgas (Ed.), The handbook of affect and social cognition. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum Associates, Inc.
Mayer, J. D., Caruso, D., & Salovey, P. (1999). Emotional intelligence meets traditional standards for an
intelligence. Intelligence.
Mayer, J. D., Chabot, H. F., & Carlsmith, K. (1997). Conation, affect, and cognition in personality. In G. Matthews
(Ed.), Cognitive science perspectives on personality and emotion (pp. 31–63). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Mayer, J. D., & Salovey, P. (1997). What is emotional intelligence? In P. Salovey & D. Sluyter (Eds.),
Emotional development and emotional intelligence: Implications for educators (pp. 3–31). New
York: Basic Books.
Mayer, J. D., Salovey, P., & Caruso, D. R. (in press). Competing models of emotional intelligence. In R.
J. Sternberg (Ed.), Handbook of human intelligence (2nd ed.; pp. 3–44).
Murray, H. A., & Kluckhorn, C. (1956). Outline of a conception of personality. In C. Kluckhorn & H. A.
Murray (Eds.), Personality in nature, society, and culture (2nd ed.). New York: Knopf.
Ornstein, R. (1972). The psychology of consciousness. New York: Viking Penguin.
Ortony, A., Clore, G. L., & Collins, A. (1988). Cognitive structure of emotions. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Otto, R. (1950). The idea of the holy (2nd ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.
Peli, P. (1984). Soloveitchik on repentance. New York: Paulist Press.
Picard, R. W. (1997). Affective computing. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Salovey, P., & Mayer, J. D. (1990). Emotional intelligence. Imagination, Cognition, and Personality, 9,
185–211.
Scarr, S. (1989). Protecting general intelligence: Constructs and consequences for intervention. In R. L.
Linn (Ed.), Intelligence: Measurement, theory, and public policy. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.
Schank, R. C., & Abelson, R. P. (1977). Scripts, plans, goals, and understanding. Hillsdale, NJ: Law-
rence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.
Sternberg, R. J. (1997). The concept of intelligence and its role in lifelong learning and success. Ameri-
can Psychologist, 52, 1030–1045.