Worksheet: Logical Statements Solutions
Worksheet: Logical Statements Solutions
Hildebrand
Remarks: Here are some tips in correctly interpreting implications stated in English:
• Rephrasing the given sentence (without changing is meaning) can make it
easier to determine its logical structure. For example, “P is true whenever Q
is true” clearly has the same meaning in English as “Whenever Q is true, then P is
true”, which in turn is the same as “If Q is true, then P is true.”. In the latter form,
the logical interpretation is obvious: Q =⇒ P , or equivalently P ⇐= Q.
• Be familiar with the pairs of words that have opposite meanings: “necessary”
and “sufficient” are reverses of each other, as are “only if ” and “if ”. If you are not
sure about the correct interpretation of one of these words in a given phrase, try re-
placing it by its reverse. For example, consider the statement “P is true only if Q is
true”. Replacing “only if” by “if” gives “P is true if Q is true”, which is the same as
“If Q is true, then P is true”, hence means Q =⇒ P , i.e., P ⇐= Q. Thus, the given
statement, “P is true only if Q is true”, must be the reverse of P ⇐= Q, i.e., P =⇒ Q.
2. Negations of English sentences. Negate the following statements. Express the negations
in English, avoiding the use of words of negation when possible.
1
Math 347 Worksheet: Logical statements Solutions A.J. Hildebrand
2
Math 347 Worksheet: Logical statements Solutions A.J. Hildebrand
4. Negations of mathematical statements, II. This problem requires the formal definitions
of a bounded set or function, and increasing, decreasing, nonincreasing, nondecreasing func-
tions. These definitions can be found in Chapter 1 of the text and are collected below. (Here
S is any set of real numbers, and f denotes a function from R to R.)
(a) Express the statement “f is not bounded ” without using words of negation.
“(∀M ∈ R)[∃x ∈ R)(|f (x)| > M ].”
“For all M ∈ R there exists x ∈ R such that |f (x)| > M .”
(b) Express the statement “f is not increasing” (i.e., the negation of the “increasing” prop-
erty) without using words of negation.
“(∃x, y ∈ R)[(x < y) ∧ (f (x) ≥ f (y))]”
“There exist real numbers x, y such that x < y and f (x) ≥ f (y).”
(c) Compare the definitions of “nonincreasing” and “not increasing” (the latter being the
negation of “increasing”). Does one imply the other? Are there functions that satisfy
one property, but not the other?
“Not increasing” means that there exist real numbers x, y such that x < y and
f (x) ≥ f (y). “Nonincreasing” means that for all real numbers x, y we have x < y and
3
Math 347 Worksheet: Logical statements Solutions A.J. Hildebrand
f (x) ≥ f (y). Thus, “nonincreasing” is a stronger property than “not increasing” (“for
all” is stronger than “there exists”), so “nonincreasing” implies “not increasing”.
The converse (i.e., the implication “not increasing” =⇒ “increasing”) is in general
not true. For example, the function f (x) = sin x is “not increasing”, but it is not
“nonincreasing”.
(*) “For every > 0 there exists δ > 0 such that |f (x)| < whenever |x| < δ.”
The following statements are small perturbations of this definitions, some of which are equiv-
alent to the original definition, while others are “botched” versions of this definition that have
a drastically different meaning.
Which versions are equivalent to the above limit definition, and which are not?
Harder, but very instructive: For those definitions that are not equivalent to limx→0 f (x) = 0,
try to determine, in as simple a language as possible, what they really define. Find examples
(if they exist) of functions that satisfy the definition, and of functions that don’t satisfy it.
(Cf. Exercises 2.25–2.27 in the text for similar problems. In some cases this can be quite
some quite tricky!)
(a) For every > 0 there exists δ > 0 such that for all x ∈ R, |x| < δ implies |f (x)| < .
Analysis: This is the same as (*), except that “|f (x)| < whenever |x| < δ” is replaced
by “|x| < δ implies |f (x)| < .” Since the latter statements are equivalent, the given
statement is equivalent to that in (*).
(b) For every δ > 0 there exists > 0 such that for all x ∈ R, |x| < δ implies |f (x)| < .
Analysis: This differs from (*) in that the types of quantifiers (∀ or ∃) for δ and have
been switched. This, however, changes the meaning completely, and the statement is
no longer equivalent to that in (*). (In fact, the statement given here is satisfied, for
example, for any function f that is bounded, since one can choose to be the bound
M .)
(c) There exists δ > 0 such that for every > 0 and for all x ∈ R, |x| < δ implies |f (x)| < .
Analysis: This differs from (*) in that the order of the quantifiers ∀ > 0 and ∃δ > 0
has been switched. This changes the meaning completely, and the statement is not
equivalent to (*). (For example, the function f (x) = x satisfies (*), but does not
satisfy the given statement.)
(d) For every > 0 and for all x ∈ R there exists δ > 0 such that |x| < δ implies |f (x)| < .
Analysis: Here the order of the quantifiers ∀x ∈ R and ∃δ > 0 has been switched,
allowing the δ to be chosen after x has been choosen. This alters the situation com-
pletely. For example, any function f with f (0) = 0 satisfies this statement: Simply
choose δ = |x|/2 when x 6= 0.
6. Additional resources.
This material is covered at the beginning of Chapter 2, on pp. 27–34 of the text; be sure to
read this section, study the examples and the general remarks and comments given there. Ad-
ditional practice problems can be found in Homework 2; particularly instructive are Problems
2.10, 2.23, and 2.24 from HW 2.