Modal VP-Ellipsis: Syntax: Detecting Its Parameters
Modal VP-Ellipsis: Syntax: Detecting Its Parameters
Abstract
*
For discussions at various stages, I am grateful to C.Baatz, B. Drubig, J. Hartmann' A.
Kroch, L. López,W. Stemefeld, S. Winkler, the audiences in Tübingen and Tromsø,
where parts of this material were presented, and to two reviewers. I wish I could have
more ñrlly explored all their suggestions. special thanks go to the organizers and the
audience of Approaches to Historical syntax 2002 (Linguistic Association ofFinland),
particularly to J. Rostila and A. Warner. The research for this study has been supported
by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft through SFB 4411813, which is hereby
acknowledged. The usual disclaimers apply.
I The field of English studies often uses the strong/weak terminology (cf., e.g.,
Huddleston & Pullum 2002), whereas the formal semantics school in the Lewis-K¡atzer
tradition the universaVexistential one. Nothing relevant should hinge on notation for the
purposes ofthis paper.
MODAL SYNTAX: DETECTING ITS PARAMETERS WITH VP-ELLIPSIS 29
2. Epistemics go farther
This cannot be interpreted with the negation scoping over the epistemic
modal.
Further elements that lend themselves to scope comparisons with
epistemics are tense and deontic modals, prima facie both not too practical
choices due to the morphosyntax of standard English registers, which
precludes the modals from directly combining with tenses (though not with
ãspect, cf. Jack might be driving to his ffice) and with each other-the
laiter restriction being not cross-dialectal. Drubig (2001), however,
observes an instance where tense-modal interaction can be directly
wiûressed in English. The diagrostic originates in Hoffinann's (1976) rule
of past tense replacement. This states that, in a set of certain delimited
contexts, a past tense morpheme (-ed) is tealized as have. Through this
replacement, the past tense morpheme can override the dilemma of getting
30 REMUS GERGEL
On closer semantic and pragmatic inspection, it turns out that they are not.
Assuming a somewhat similarly restrictive, i.e. mostly an evidentiality-
based concept of epistemicity, as the one explicitly argued for by Drubig,
Condoravdi (2001) and Stowell (forth.) show that counterexamples which
allow have to scope over the modal are not bona fide epistemics (though
traditionally classified as such), but rather metaphysicals or alethics.3
2 Huddleston & Pullum (2002) classify should as medium modality given its
peculiarities. In this paper I will not deal with the specifics of this particular type of
modality. Cf. also de Harm (1997).
i An interesting question sometimes explored in the literature is to what extent scope
reversal relates to the morphology ofthe modal itself. For discussion on the particular
case ofEnglish see Condoravdi (2001) and Stowell (forth.), who suggest semantic and
syntactic explanations, respectively, why scope reversal, i.e., counterfactual alethics,
should be only possible for non-present modals such as might, could, should.
MoDAL SYNTAX: DETECTING ITS PAR.AMETERS WITH VP-ELLIPSIS 3l
This section starts the discussion of the interaction between modals and
ellipsis in English. we will particularly see that the diachronic treatment of
the English modals makes (a minimum of) two distinct positions necessary,
specifically one preceding and one following their reanalysis. The
discussion is less refined than in the other sections, mainly due to the fact
that one seems to be better advised to discuss various readings and their
syntactic correlations in synchronic terms with an accessible language.
Nonetheless, the diachronic data prove the point of looking at modals and
ellipsis in conjunction. We will see that the modals were picked up by the
process ofdiachronic reanalysis from a projection different from V (cf. the
"standard" reanalysis theory developed in the wake oflightfoot 1979)'
We tum our attention to the most relevant period for the reanalysis,
i.e. the time span ranging over the later periods of Middle English (ME) to
early Modem English (ModE). It will be argued that an appropriate
approximation equates the post-reanalysis position of the modals indeed
with T, but the pre-reanalysis one with a lower projection, quasi-functional
in nature, but crucially still able to license VP-ellipsis.
The fact that the reanalysis stranded the emerging ModE modals
roughly in T is generally accepted and convincingly demonstrated by
Roberts (1985, 1993). However, based on the quantitative and theoretical
analysis in Gergel (2002), drawing on the second version of the Pmn
Helsinki Parsed Corpus of Middle Englßh (PPCME2), I argue that the
existence of ellipsis makes the standard account untenable with respect to
where the reanaþsis picked the modals up.o While the standard view of the
reanalysis assumes that the premodals were fully lexical verbs up into the
sixteenth century, when they allegedly have cataclysmically reanalyzed, it
(6) But for he couþe not selle and undo his clooþ as a womman
but since he could not sell and undo his clothes as â woman
schulde _, he was...
should he was ...
(POLYCH,VIII,l 05.367 7s)
s
The notation follows the PPCME2 standa¡ds.
Moo¡l Svnrax: DETECTING lrs PARAMETERS wlrH VP-ELLIPSIS 33
(ll) þei sent hir fro þe lryngß coferes what þei wold-
they sent her from the king's coffers what they would./ wanted to
(CAPCHR,150.35l6)
(12) * Mary wondered which conference talk Tommy refused to attend and Susan
wonders which colloquium talk Mary refused
-.
Furthermore, from the corpus-theoretic perspective, it is noteworthy that
virtually all elliptical examples are parsed as M in the PPCME2-and not
as V, which is an altemative annotational variant used in the corpus, e.g,
especially for earlier instances of modals. In terms of numerical
developments, after a collapse in the early Middle English period, the
relativè frequency of verbal elliptical structures in relation to the total
number of tokens increases with approximately 50o/o per cor?us-segment, a
6 cf. Gergel (2002) for further empirical evidence, discussion of some pitfalls, and
additional corpus-theoretic and numerical argumentation.
34 REMUS GERGEL
trend that may be taken as significant for an internal gmmmar change in the
sense of Kroch (1989, 2002).
Before investigating how the reanalysis might have worked on the
syntactic component diachronically, wê need to sketch some facts
underlying VP ellipsis in slmchronic terms. With Harley (1995), Emonds
(2000), among others (and contra, e.g., the classical analysis of Emonds,
1970),1assume that ModE verbs like have and be are merged directly in a
projection structurally higher than V, which predicts the properties setting
them apart from main verbs today. For the purposes of ellipsis licensing
this has an interesting consequence. Consider (l3F(16), (cf. Emonds
2000).
(13) * Since in the past you have represented us well, I'm sure you must _ yesterday.
(14) Since in the past you have represented us well, I'm sure you must have _
yesterday.
(15) * I makeMary be examined often even though her brother refuses to _.
(16) I make Mary be examined often even though her brother refuses to be_.
The ungrammaticality of examples like (13) and (15) suggests that the
verbs have and be cannot be generally deleted under a T-element such as
musÍ oÍ to-by contrast, it is well-known that under the appropriate
parallelism requirements in terms of feature subsets (e.g. Oku 2001) VPs
headed by genuine main verbs can. An explanation of these facts is that
deletion of the VP depends on a set of two licensers in order for it to safely
occur. Consider (17).
Licensers VPE
111
(17) site
o
lrp Subjr To [¡p l¡ F
t Giu"n that at the latest on minimalist assumptions categories are but feature bundles,
the issue of what F is does not affect the positional argument of this section. We have a
distinct projecting head accommodating auxiliaries. Regarding the set of solutions for F
one has various candidates following recent options ofinvestigation in this domain. Fox
& Lasnik (2003: 151) operate with aspect. Thus if we replace F in (17) with Asp we
essentially get the Fox & Lasnik proposal for licensing ofVP-ellipsis. Though I haven't
been able to fully evaluate this recent approach, as Fox and Lasnik þ. 151) seem to
concede, in their framework not much hinges on the label of the projection below T -
Mooel Svur¡x: DETECTING ITS PARAMETERS wlrH VP-ELLIPSIS 35
perhaps due to the different focus oftheirpaper. Gergel (2002) argues for a syntactic Pr
head in the position occupied by F, partly following Bowers (2001) and additional
diachronic argumentation.
8
The relative positions ofthe modals on the one hand, and belhave on the other in pre-
and post-reanalysis grammars are surprising at first sight. There is, however, rather
strong evidence for this rough modals/"aspectuals" dichotomy for the data at hand.
First, note that there is indication that roughly 99%o of the verbal elliptical structures in
ME are licensed by modals solely - notby havelbe, not by verbs (cf. Gergel 2002' vtith
the estimate based on studies on the PPCME2). Second, the peculiarities of have, and
especially of åe with respect to vP-ellipsis are late changes, as is well-known. This fact
was noted and seriously discussed by Anthony TVamer, and explored in various
diachronic and synchronic studies; cf. Warner (1995) among others. For time and space
reasons, the changes axe not discussed here, but the relevant approximating
generalization is clear: Preceding these late changes, the "aspectuals" could establish
antecedent-ellipsis dependencies following the same or similar retrieval rules as used in
the parallelism-requirements for main verbs, whereas today they no longer can under
the same conditions.
Note also that I am not ruling out that aspectuals and main verbs be further
distinguished following various criteria, e.g., semantic, typology-oriented ones (e.g., in
the spirit ofHeine 1993), or even further syntactic ones. All that I am saying is that for
the course run by English the ellipsis-facts strongly suggest taking havelbe all in all
below the critical double-line of co-licensers before the reanalysis, and that they are
merged higher up later on. A third piece ofevidence can be adduced from linearization
36 Rptrtus Gnncel
(18) And whan thß creatur was fþud [gracyowslyJ comen a-geyn ..
and when this creature AUX thus graciously come.PRT again...
(KEMPE,9, 139)
For modals, the comparable configurations are not available in the entire
PPCME2 independently of adverb classes. Given that ME is the flourishing
period of non-finite modals when compared to the other stages of English,
the failure of the test can indeed not be blamed on a lack of in-situ modals.
The phenomenon can straightforwardly be explained by means of the
intermediate projection. With modals, the intermediate position cannot be
facts. Modals productively co-occur with havelbe in Modem English. However the use
of such sequences is late (cf., e.g., van Gelderen 2003: 35). One way to go would be that
having found a licit position to be first-merged (namely in F in (17), after F has been
evacuated by the modals thorough the reanalysis), have/be have now found a more
natural position to be licensed in cases where modals are present in the initial
numeration of a given sentence, i.e. in the quasi-functional F in post-reanalysis
-
grammars they are not blocked by the presence ofthe modals from that position.
MoDAL SYNTAX: DETECTING ITS PARAMETERS WITH VP.ELLIPSIS 37
made visible due to the fact that it most probably does not exist, as shown
by the unattested pattems in (22), and (23)-the premodals occupying F
themselves.
e While the contrast (20) vs. (22) may speak for itselt the reviewer furthermore
perspicuously points out that firther complications arise from the attested type I gave in
(21) (and cross-comparisons between this type and the three others). For instance, what
is the projection where the final adverb in (21) is merged to. While a definite take on the
issue indeed has to await furthe¡ research on adverbial syntax, I think the data are less
confusing than they appear. First, adjunction is out ofthe question for the data we are
concemed with as mentioned above. Then we are essentially left with two options:
. either move the non-finite verb in configurations such as (21) over the
adverb,
, or merge the adverb to a relatively low position (perhaps in a vP-shell
architecture).
Given that there is no modal in the numeration in data reflecting (21), this being the
crucial point in the pair (20)-(21), I am not sure whether the first option should be
discarded in order to keep the "base-generating" modal position free. It is, however,
38 R¡rr¿us Genc¡l
intermediate position may be detectable with verbs, but not with modals. If
the modals are structurally higher then verbs, as we have seen based on the
discriminating ellipsis evidence above, then this fact is explained.
4. Cartography
more than anything an independent matter of empirical finding whether non-finites have
the ability to undergo at least some shorter movements in ME, and what principles this
movement should exactly obey. Cross-linguistically this option is certainly available
(see, e.g., Bok-Bennema 2002 for interesting facts regarding short V-movement in
Romance, partly foreshadowed by Pollock's 1989 system), and it is not unlikely to find
it, e.g., for reasons of participle-morphology licensing in English varieties either, as
recently assumed by Roberts & Roussou (2003:2.1). Otherwise the second option or a
variant thereof, needed for what appear to be cases of apparent low adverbs in any
event, may be involved.
'0 Butler capitalizes on the necessity-possibility distinction drawn in Cormack & Smith
(2002). Cinque also has distinctions befween necessity and possibility, although he
argues against this split in the epistemic domain. I focus on Butler's structure, rat¡er
than Cormack & Smith's for the purposes of this paper, first, because it allows a more
straightforward comparison with Cinque's well-known cartography; second because it
is worked out in a close relationship with the interface interpretation; and third, because
it has roughly the usual assumptions on the grammatical model, whereas, e.g., Cormack
and Smith's introduces additional assumptions, (for instance, on Merge) and the split-
sign hypothesis, which would need an additional layer oftheorizing.
MoDAL SYNTAX: DETECTING ITS PARAMETERS WITH VP.ELLIPSIS 39
(24)
FocP
[neg] FinP
Iposs] TP
T'
T P
FocP
lnegl
VP
Let's start with the theoretical implications. First, rather complex at first
glance, this phrase marker is on the one hand overall much less articulate
and hence perhaps more learning adequate than Cinque (1999)'s influential
cartogaphy of the functional domain. This comparison holds even if the
latter were truncated to the modality-relevant projections, for more
appropriate conÍast. At the same time, the structure is symmetrical in
interesting ways. Note that necessity c-commands possibility twice, once in
the higher domain of epistemicity, and once again in the lower one in
charge of root modality. We mainly concentrate on modality, though Butler
assumes connections between the heads hosting the modals and functional
projection in the sense of Rizzi's (1997) Split-CP hypothesis, as the
labelling in (24) shows.
Second, the reduplicative character of many of Cinque's projections
has been recently critiqued as a way-out solution designed to fit scope facts
otherwise not accommodated. Recursion might, however, be simply a
descriptive necessity, in view of the wide fypological view argued by
Cinque-style approaches. How is then the tension to be solved? In fact,
40 Rrvus Gpncel
once one assumes a structure along the lines of (24) and, crucially,
substantiates the evidence for it, the alleged weakness ofrecursion can tum
into a virtue. For instance, this structure has recursion in a// nodes
responsible for modal interpretation. Cinque's original formulation, where,
for instance, evidentiality only appears once, does not. What I consider the
main effect of this line of thought is the ability to descriptively generate the
wide gamut that Cinque aims at in the domain of modality; but at a lower
cost. Incidentally, it is also very well known that similar phenomena exist
in other functional domains as well; e.g., in the domain of focalization.rr It
is no little achievement to make rich structures fit explanatory and
acquisition-based principles. In this line of reasoning, leaming one segment
of the structure and re-applying the same part at a later age in a higher
domain of the clause would facilitate the task of the language learner
considerably. The reapplication might be motivated by meta-
representational interpretative impact as approaches such as Papafragou
(1998) would suggest. Furthermore, if the recent phase-theoretical concems
(Chomsky 2001) are on the right track, then a structure rounding off the vP
and then ending symmetrically in a reduplicated CP would also be in line
with it.
Consider now the main empirical support Butler adduces to underpin
the structure proposed, e.g., through examples like the ones rendered as
(zsYQÐ below.
The set ofsentences above can be used for two purposes. On the one hand,
the relative order epistemic vs. root comes to the fore when considering
subject scope relative to the modal in (25) vs. (26) and (27). While an
" From this kind of research, Butler adopts the labelling ForceP, FocP, FinP, as
aforementioned; see Rizzi (1997), and Drubig (2003) for ampler discussion of layered
effects in the domain of focalization. I leave information-structural concems aside in
this paper.
Mooel Swr¡.x: DETECTING ITs PAR{METERS viITH VP-ELLIPSIS 4l
epistemic doesn't allow the subject to scope over it, as in (25), the two
dèontics clearly do. The scope position for subjects assumed in this context
is the (generatively) traditional Spec, TP. On the other hand, the possibility
vs. necessity divide is deducible from the comparison between (26) and
(27) and the indicated scope relations. These sentences suggest that while
possibility scopes below, necessity scopes above negation.
(28) ECP: At LF, a quantifier cannot bind its trace across an epistemic modal.
* Q¡... [Epistemic Modat (...t¡...) (cf. F&I 2003: (31))
Suppose the modal in (29) is epistemic. Then it also must get scope over
the quantifier. As a counterfoil to the observation on epistemics it is useful
to observe that, by contrast, deontics and tenses do not obey it. For
instance, on a deontic reading (30) allows both scope atrangements modal
> quantifier ('it is necessary that most students get outside funding') on the
reading facilitated by continuation in a., and quantifier > modal (very
roughly 'for most students it is the case that they necessitate outside
funding') on the reading induced by b.
42 RIMUS GERGEL
In the same vein, the tense in (31) displays both options with respect to
relative scope with the quantifier.
As the contrast between (29) on the one hand, and (30F(31) on the other
illustrates, quantification constitutes a vivid domain to observe
discriminating effects of epistemic modals. While it might be too early to
fully assess F&I's approach, there is initial evidence presented in section 6
that to the extent that it is corect, its main syntactic effect can be derived
from the syntax and semantics of epistemic modals in general.
First, note that for some of the examples above, e.g., (1) or (29), it could be
counterargued that not only do they not parallel semantic paraphrases
which would allow the modals to scope lower but, put simply, they also
override overt syntax, so that the entire matter becomes a somewhat
impalpable "scope matter," in many syntacticians' view not a satisfactory
situation. This alone would make additional evidence necessary.
Second, though appealing, Butler's s¡rmmetric approach has some
loops in the argumentation. It distinguishes strong from weak modality in
both phases. But the evidence is not as well-balanced and symmetrical as
the tree-structure proposed. Consider again the negation-based evidence,
used as a crucial argument. The bottom line is the assumption that negation
resides in a distinct head sandwiched between modals in both phases, thus
serving as the scope element relative to each necessity and possibility can
be tested, both in the epistemic and the root domain. However, the main
support adduced with respect to negation is of the type rendered above in
MoDAL SYNTAX: DETECTING ITS PARAMETERS WITH VP-ELLIPSIS 43
(25YQ7), i.e., in which only root necessity and possibility can be told
apart. But for epistemic modalify, negation only indicates the ordering
modal > negation, not the relative scope of strong and weak modality; cf.
(32), and (33).12
12
Butler (2003: 984) presents evidence with respect to negation in the higher domain
þhase); however, with suppletive forms. That is, instead of capturing the syntax of
epistemic may and must, we leam interesting things about suppletive forms like can't
and needn't, which in logical terms should do. For the purposes of natural language
analysis, however, this rests on the assumption that they are the exact linguistic
equivalents of the modals nay and must in negated contexts. This would need
investigation first. If, based on empirical inquiry, it tums out that they are, then this
paper may provide strong empirical support to the suggestions based on negation..
13
The ECP as rendered above is a more accurate statement than a preliminary version
F&I offe¡ and which for lack of space I omit.
to Cf., e.g., Fox (1995), and Fox (2000) with updates-which F&I also cite and wo¡k
with for other purposes.
44 R¡røus GBncsL
However, in (35), only the overt scope relation is possible, viz. no scope
reversal and thus no ambiguity is possible given that in logical terms
movement of the quantifier in the elliptical conjunct would be vacuous.
The laws of Quantifier Independence predict this lack of movement (Partee
et. al. 1993: 148). In other words, the universal quantifier from the elided
site in (35) has a right to stay in situ, because moving over another
universal would not make an interpretative difference. This indeed predicts
the ungrammaticality of the superfluous derivation in (36). The
generalization beyond this kind ofbehavior is, according to Fox, along the
lines of (37).
(37) Ellipsis Scope Generalization (ESG): The relative scope of two quantifiers, one
of which is an antecedent VP of an ellipsis construction, may differ from the
surface c-command relation, only if the parallel difference will have semantic
effects in the elided VP. (cf. Fox, 1995:149)
The sentences above all lack the epistemic inte¡pretation according to the
aforesaid studies. Leaving wl¡-movement per se aside, we return to our
more central concems in this study. It is thus possible that the cartogaphic
approach gains consolidating support from further syntax-oriented studies.
Without getting into the issue of how quantificational elements move and
get into scope positions, note that albeit being able to cross nonfinites, by
and large they do not cross finite clause-boundaries, as opposed for
instance to topicalization (cf. Johnson, 2000 for discussion). By way of
simplified midway conclusion, given the following conditions:
. when merged into a derivation epistemics close off the finite
clause,
r (epistemic) modals only appear in hnite clauses in (standard)
English,
. quantification generally stays within the finite clause,
then the ECP follows. If correct in some form, then this line of thought
makes the interesting quantificational facts derivable and aligns them in the
more general context of research on modal syntax, ideally towards
explanation.r5
15
F&I 1e.g., section 3.2) also mention the quest for explanation. They contend that one
should explain why epistemics should be so high. Though not too often asked,
requirements asking not only for proofthat a node X c-commands a node Y, but, after
having presented syntactic evidence that it does so, also asking why this is the case may
have an interesting appeal fiom a more general perspective on language. From what we
know on the specific case of epistemics, language acquisition, and the way mental
representations work are things that come to mind, but essentially such requirements fall
outside the scope of syntax proper. As a matter of fact, if seriously asked, the issue may
46 R¡rr¿us GrncBr-
need an investigation of the standard theory about C¡1¡ as being operative in some
version of the syntactocentric T-model, in which phrase-structure is rather an axiom
than a theorem - an exploration that would take us too far afield here.
16
This is a somewhat puzzlingly declared argument when fending off cartography. Is
the set {ror+ have to, need+not, can't} of (41) representing the low modals, and the
others are still "the high ones"? Then one could simply restrict the domain of the
topological account to the complement set, e.g., due to morphosyntactic reasons, and
then still derive the ECP. It seems a dubious move to discard topology while taking
topological relations for granted. I take it that the proper logic of the ECP argument
should involve an additional step of a reductio ad absurdum, and continue the argument
from there.
MoDAL SYNTAX: DETECTING ITS PARAMETERS WITH VP-ELLIPSIS 47
tt While negation often plays a central role in cartography oriented approaches, it is less
than accurate to assume that it is the only argument ofthe topological account; see for
other arguments Jackendoff (1972), Cinque (1999), Drubig (2001), Butler (2003), and
the discussion ofthis paper, among others.
r8
One may slightly disagree with the terms of Cormack & Smith here, who claim that
need is a negative polarity item, although they give the right contexts of its occurrence
elsewhere. Particularly need as a modal is also licensed by, e.g., interrogatives. By
contrast, there are languages that have indeed developed modal uses more restrictedly
licensed by negation. Thus German brauchen'need' is a case in point. This verb is not
standardly licensed in intenogatives in its modal use, but it is by negative polarity
contexts.
48 Rnrøus Genc¡r
(42) John can't seem to run very fast. (Quirk 1965: 217 , cited from Langedoen 1970:
2s)
(43) John must wash his car every day and Peter must
-
too (*epi)
(44) John will often sit there and do nothing and Bill will
-
too (*epi)
(45) John may not obey his mother, but he must his
-
father (??epi)
(46) Jane may wash her car and Mary may/mighlcould - too.
(47) Mary will talk to her boss and John might to his.
-
(48) John will fly to London and Mary may too. (Boðkovic, 1994: 280)
(49) You have to be a real masochist to
-
want to direct," he says with a smile. But
Fearheiley does, and Smith might- , too. (Gazette.Nel, Maryland, Ãttg.29,2002)
50 REMUS GERGEL
(50) Mary may know about the meeting and Melissa may too.
-
V/ith know it is even clearer that temporal forward-shift for
a predicate 71ke
may isnot compulsory and we have an epistemic reading on the modal.
What the examples (43F(50) may indicate instead is that the
necessity/possibility (or universal/ existential) divide also plays a part in
the licensing of elliptical phenomena. They thus offer additional evidence
for an essential subset of the relations proposed. The epistemic/root divide
is, however, also crucial. Note that it is only for epistemics that necessity
and possibility part ways with respect to ellipsis. Ellipsis then first takes
epistemic and root modals apart in that only the former show the variation
in licensing, and furthermore takes apart the epistemic class in that, within
it, a higher head of strong existential quantification (e.g., must) is not an
appropriate licenser. It is worth noting that this neatly complements the
evidence from negation presented by Butler. While ellipsis operates as just
mentioned, negation hrst distinguishes must and may with respect to
epistemic vs. root status (in that only the latter shows scope variation) and
then fine-grainedly takes apart the deontics into necessity and possibility,
though not epistemics, as we have seen.
(iÐ You must have acquired all the credits to get your diploma.
52 RBtr¡us Gencsl
While the arguments have been put forward for English, there is to my
mind no immediate reason to overgeneralize to other languages. Rich
functional hierarchies are perhaps best thought of as telescopic in that
particular languages may pull out certain subsets of them and
grammaticalize them accordingly, or may not. Moreover, elliptical
processes quite in the same vein may function in a number of various ways
and may be more or less developed in certain areas in different varieties. In
general, English has a well-developed fype of VP-ellipsis, as numerous
attempts to compare other systems to its criteria have shown (cf. Holmberg
2001, Ngonyani 1996, among others). Without getting into the exploration
of further elliptical systems, let's just note that there may be parallels in
subdomains. For instance, German allows VP-like elision only under very
restricted lexical and information-structural conditions (Klein 1993,
Winkler 2003). It has, however, an overt anaphoric form es with some of
the hallmarks of VP-ellipsis if not all (López & Winkler 2000).
Interestingly this form of VP-replacement follows the epistemic-root
dichotomy, in that it is only licensed with non-epistemic modals (Ross
1969). This would then again confirm the intuition expressed in Drubig
(2001) that epistemic modality is not an appropriate licenser. Romanian, to
take a typologically different example, behaves----once more with the
proviso on elliptical structures and modal grammaticalization-primarily
sensitive to the other parameter, viz. necessity vs. possibility.
References
Denison, David. (1992) Counterfactual 'May Have.' In Marinel Gerristen & Dieter Stein
(eds.), Internal and External Factors ín Syntactic Change, pp' 229-56. Berlin:
Mouton de Gruyter.
Depiante, Marcela A. (2000) The Syntax of Deep and Surface Anaphora: A Study of
Null Complement Anaphora and StrippinglBare Argument Ellipsis. Ph.D.
dissertation, University of Connecticut.
Drubig, H. Bernhard (2001) The s¡mtactic form of epistemic modality. Ms., University
ofTübingen.
(2003)Towardatypologyof focusandfocusconstructions. Linguístics 41: 1-50.
Emonds, Joseph E. (1970) Root and Structure Preserving Transformatìons.
- Bloomington: Indiana University Linguistics Club.
(2000) Lexicon and Grammar: The English Syntacticon. Berlin: Mouton de
Gruyter.
-von Fintel, Sabine (2003) Epistemic containment. Linguístic Inquiry 34'.
Kai & Iatridou,
173-98.
Fox, Danny (1995) Economy, scope and semantic interpretation - evidence fiom VP
ellipsis. NEZS 25: 143-57.
(2000) Economy and Semantic Interpretation. Carrrbndge, MA.: MIT Press.
Fox, Danny & Lasnik, Howard (2003) Successive-cyclic movement and island repair:
- the difference between sluicing and VP-ellipsis. Linguistic Inquiry 34:. 143-54.
van Gelderen, Elly (2003) ASP(ect) in English Modal Complements. Studia Linguistica
57:2743.
Gergel, Remus (2002) Short-distance reanalysis of Middle English modals: evidence
from ellipsis. Ms., University of Tübingen.
de Haan, Ferdinand. 1997. The Interaction of Modality and Negation. A Typological
.Slrzdy. New York: Garland.
Harley, Heidi B. (1995) Subjects, Events and Licensing.Ph. D. dissertation, MIT.
Harris, Alice C. & Campbell, Lyle. 7995. Historical Syntax in Cross-Linguistic
Perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University P¡ess.
Heine, Bemd (1993) Auxiliaries: Cognitive Forces and Grammaticalization. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Hofinann, T. Ronald (1976) Past Tense Replacement and the Modal System. ln James
McCawley (ed.), Syntax and Semantics. Notes from the Linguistic Underground,
pp. 85-100. New York: Academic Press.
Holmberg, Anders (2001) The syntax ofyes and no in Finnish. StudÌa Linguistica 55:
14t-7 5.
Huddleston, Rodney & Pullum, Geoffrey K. (2002) The Cambridge Grammar of the
Englßh Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Jackendoff, Fiay (1972) Semantic Interpreturion in Generative Grammar. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Johnson, Kyle. (2000) How Fa¡ Will Quantifiers Go? In Roger Martin & Juan
Uriagereka (eds.), ,lrep by Step Essays On Minimalist Syntax in Honor of Howard
Lasnik, pp. 187-210. Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press.
MoDAL SYNTAX: DETECTING ITS PARAMETERS WITH VP-ELLIPSIS 55
Klein, Wolfgang (1993) Ellipse. In Joachim Jacobs, Amim von Stechow & Theo
Vennemann (eds.), Syntax: Ein internationales Handbuch zeitgenössischer
F or s chung, pp. 97 8-87 . Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Kratzer, Angelika (1981) The Notional Category of Modality. In Hans-Jürgen
Eikmeyer & Hannes Rieser (eds'), Words, l\lorlds, and Contexts, pp. 38--74'
Berlin: Mouton de GruYter.
Kroch, Anthony ( I 989) Reflexes of grammar in pattems of language change. Language
variation and change 7:199-244.
(2002) Modelling language change. Paper presented at DIGS VII, University of
Girona, June 2002.
-Langendoen, Terence D. (1970) The'can't seem to'construction. Lingußtic Inquiry I:
25-35.
Lasnik, Howard (1999) Pseudogapping Puzzles. In Elabbas Benmamoun & Shalom
Lappin (eds.), Fragments: Studies in Ellipsis and Gapping, pp' l4l-74. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Lewis, David (1973) Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.
Lobeck Anne C. (1995) Ellipsis: Functional Heads, Lícensing and Identification.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
López, Luis. (2002) On Agreement: Locality and Feature Valuation. In A¡temis
Alexiadou (ed.), Theoretical Approaches to Llniversals, pp. 165-209. Amsterdam:
John Benjamin.
López, Luis & Winkler, Susanne (2000) Focus and Topic in VP-anaphora constructions'
Linguis t i cs 3 8 : 623 464.
Ngonyani, Deo (1996) VP ellipsis in Ndendeule and Swahili applicatives. UCLA
lVorking Papers in Syntax and Semantics 1: 109-128.
Oku, Satoshi (2001) A minimalist Theory of LF-Copy. In Galina M. Alexandrova &
Olga Amaudova (eds.), The Minimalist Parameter, pp. 281-294. Amsterdam:
John Benjamins.
Papafragou, Anna (1998) Inference and word meaning: the case of modal auxiliaries.
Lingua 105: 147.
Partee, Barbara H., ter Meulen, Alice & Wall, Robert E. (1993) Mathematical Methods
in Linguistics. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Pollock, Jean-Yves (1989) Verb movement, UG, and the structure of lP. Linguistíc
Inquiry 20:365424.
Quirk, Randolph (1965) Descriptive statements and serial relationship. Language 41:
20s-17.
Reis, Marga (2001) Bilden Modalverben im Deutschen eine syntaktische Klasse? ln
Reima¡ Müller & Marga Reis (eds.), Modalität und Modalverben im Deutschen,
pp. 287-318. Hamburg: Buske.
Rizzi, Luigi (1997) The Fine Structure of the Left Periphery. In Liliane Haegeman (ed.),
E leme nts of Gramm ar, pp. 28 1-337 . Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Roberts, Ian G. (1985) Agreement parameters and the development of English modal
auxiliaries. Natural Langtage and Linguistic Theory 3: 2l-58.
56 REMUS GERGEL
Contact information:
Remus Gergel
SFB 44Il 813
Nauklerstrasse 35/ 3.05
7 207 4 T äbingen, Germany
Tel.: ++49 (0)70711 29-771.63
Fax: ++49 (0\70711 29-5830
Email: [email protected]