Philippa Foot - Natural Goodness-Oxford University Press, USA (2001) PDF
Philippa Foot - Natural Goodness-Oxford University Press, USA (2001) PDF
Philippa Foot - Natural Goodness-Oxford University Press, USA (2001) PDF
Foot, Philippa , Griffin Professor of Philosophy Emeritus , University of California, Los Angeles, and Honorary Fellow of
Somerville College, Oxford
Print ISBN 0198235089, 2001
Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other
countries
Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system,
or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford
University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate
reprographcs rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the
above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above
You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover and you must impose this same
condition on any acquirer
Contents
Preface......................................................................................................................................................... 2
Introduction ............................................................................................................................................... 3
1 A Fresh Start?.......................................................................................................................................... 5
2 Natural Norms ..................................................................................................................................... 18
3 Transition to Human Beings .............................................................................................................. 26
4 Practical Rationality ............................................................................................................................. 35
5 Human Goodness ................................................................................................................................ 44
6 Happiness and Human Good ............................................................................................................ 54
7 Immoralism ........................................................................................................................................... 65
Postscript .................................................................................................................................................. 76
Bibliography ............................................................................................................................................ 77
Preface
I have been writing this book for many years, and have benefited greatly from discussions with
colleagues, especially at Oxford and UCLA, but also at many other universities. If I have here
repeated other people's arguments without acknowledgement I only hope they will blame a
defective memory rather than professional thievishness.
It will be obvious that I owe most to the work of Elizabeth Anscombe, and to early discussions
with her. But I must also give special thanks to Christopher Coope, Peter Conradi, and Michael
Thompson who read the whole of a first draft of the book and sent me wonderful comments.
Anselm Müller has also read some chapters for me and helped me a great deal, and I have had
many good discussions with John Campbell, Rosalind Hursthouse, and Gavin Lawrence.
Finally, I am extraordinarily grateful to Peter Momtchiloff at the Oxford University Press for
his unfailing encouragement and patience, and to Angela Blackburn, whose editing has saved
me from many blunders.
PRF
Oxford, May 2000
Introduction
Introduction
Philippa Foot
What is this book about? It is a book of moral philosophy, which means that we must discuss
right and wrong and virtue and vice, the traditional subjects of moral judgement. But being a
book of philosophy, it has to do only with a peculiar type of question about these subjects that is
perhaps best identified either by example or by the special kind of malaise that we feel when
examples of it appear. 1
Wittgenstein wrote of thinking that one cannot see one's way around, saying 'We feel as if we
had to repair a torn spider's web with our fingers.' 2 And while on the topic of philosophy in
general and Wittgenstein's philosophy in particular, I should like to take this chance to pass on
a piece of advice that I have kept in mind throughout the writing of this book, remembering it
as his on one of the two occasions when he took part in a public discussion in Oxford.
Wittgenstein interrupted a speaker who had realized that he was about to say something that,
although it seemed compelling, was clearly ridiculous, and was trying (as we all do in such
circumstances) to say something sensible instead. 'No,' said Wittgenstein. 'Say what you want to
say. Be crude and then we shall get on.' The suggestion that in doing philosophy one should not
try to banish or tidy up a ludicrously crude but troubling thought, but rather give it its day, its
week, its month, in court, seems to me very helpful. It chimes of course with Wittgenstein's
idea that in philosophy it is very difficult to work as slowly as one should.
No one doubts, I think, that there are peculiarly philosophical difficulties in understanding
ordinary moral judgements, because questions such as 'Why should I do what is right and
good?' arise naturally and yet are so hard to understand. One feels that there must be
something wrong with this question, but cannot say what it is that is wrong. Later I shall
discuss this very problem, but the argument must start a long way back, and the starting point
is crucial. We might be inclined to start, as for instance G. E. Moore did one hundred years ago
in his vastly influential Principia Ethica, by fixing our eyes on the peculiarity of goodness when
predicated as a property in a sentence such as 'Pleasure is good'; 3
but I believe that to take such a starting point is to skew the enquiry from the outset. If in
everyday life someone said to us 'Pleasure is good', we should ask, 'How do you mean?'—
indicating that as it stands the proposition seems void for uncertainty, as a lawyer might say.
Moore regularly speaks of the judgement that a certain thing—pleasure, for instance, or
friendship—'is good', as if 'X is good' could be taken as the standard form of predication for it,
as for 'X is red'. It seems to me, however, extremely important that this should be challenged
1 The first such problem—later identified as philosophical—that I remember worrying about was when a grown-
up used the words 'If I were you', and I wondered how we should notice the difference if she were me!
2 Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, section 106.
before we start on the usual discussions of the way in which Moore himself thought that
goodness was a special kind of property (a 'non-naturalistic' property) and the theories that
developed out of this thought. For the acceptance of this rarely appropriate form of words
makes it hard to see the real logical grammar of evaluations, in which, in most contexts, 'good'
requires to be complemented by a noun that plays an essential role in determining whether we
are able to speak of goodness rather than badness, or indeed of goodness or badness at all.
Peter Geach made this point in a sadly neglected article entitled 'Good and Evil', where he puts
'good' in the class of attributive adjectives, to which, for example, 'large' and 'small' belong,
contrasting such adjectives with 'predicative' adjectives such as 'red’. 4
Such a colour word operates in in dependence of any noun to which it is attached, but whether
a particular F is a good F depends radically on what we substitute for 'F'. As 'large' must
change to 'small' when we find that what we thought was a mouse was a rat, so 'bad' may
change to 'good' when we consider a certain book of philosophy first as a book of philosophy
and then as a soporific. Seen in the light of Geach's distinction, thoughts about good actions,
which are fundamental to moral philosophy, appear with thoughts about good sight, good
food, good soil, or good houses.
Geach's insistence that 'good' and 'red' are logically different is very important and takes us
some of the way in the task of bringing back words 'from their metaphysical to their everyday
use', as Wittgenstein said was characteristic of his own late philosophy. 5
But as Geach would, I am sure, agree, there are further distinctions of logical grammar to be
made before we shall have identified the category to which moral evaluation belongs. What I
mean here by a logical category of evaluation can be illustrated by the contrast between
evaluating, say, a house from a utilitarian point of view, when questions such as 'for whom?'
will have to be answered before an evaluation can be made or, by contrast, evaluating a house
aesthetically, when this question would be out of place. These are two different logical
categories in which evaluations can be made, and the aim of this book is to find that other one
to which the moral evaluation of human actions belongs.
My constructive task is therefore to describe a particular type of evaluation and to argue that
moral evaluation of human action is of this logical type. I am going to write about what may
conveniently be called 'natural goodness and defect in living things', and this explains the title
of my book; but the conjunction merely marks a term of art invented for the sake of
convenience, and the sense of the expression will have to be given later on. In this brief
introduction I shall go no further than to remark that by natural goodness I emphatically do
not mean the goodness thought by many to belong, for instance, to some but not other sexual
practices because some but not others are 'natural'. What I do mean is goodness of an
individual living thing (or of some characteristic or operation of it) as evaluated in a way that is
not, I believe, sufficiently distinguished in moral philosophy, although it is easily recognized
4 I have sometimes secured instant recognition of this point by holding up a small bit of torn paper in front of an
audience and asking them to say whether or not it is good. An offer to pass it round so that they can see it better
gets a laugh that recognizes a logical—grammatical—absurdity.
5 Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, section 116.
1 A Fresh Start?
that a living thing can be evaluated in other logically different ways, as by its usefulness or
dangerousness to us, or by its beauty or ugliness. My general thesis is that moral judgement of
human actions and dispositions is one example of a genre of evaluation itself actually
characterized by the fact that its objects are living things; though much more must be said later
about that.
1 A Fresh Start?
Philippa Foot
For better or worse—and many will say worse—I have in this book the overt aim of setting out
a view of moral judgement very different from that of most moral philosophers writing today.
For I believe that evaluations of human will and action share a conceptual structure with
evaluations of characteristics and operations of other living things, and can only be understood
in these terms. I want to show moral evil as 'a kind of natural defect'. Life will be at the centre of
my discussion, and the fact that a human action or disposition is good of its kind will be taken
to be simply a fact about a given feature of a certain kind of living thing.
To make such a suggestion, as I interpret it, is to contemplate a naturalistic theory of ethics: to
break really radically both with G. E. Moore's anti-naturalism and with the subjectivist theories
such as emotivism and prescriptivism that have been seen as clarifications and developments
of Moore's original thought. To get so much as a hearing for such a position, I must first
describe, and give reasons for rejecting, the subjectivism that for the past sixty years or so has
dominated moral philosophy in Britain, America, and other countries in which analytic
philosophy is taught. This is the subjectivism—often called 'non-cognitivism'—that came to the
fore with A. J. Ayer, C. L. Stevenson, and Richard Hare, informed the work of John Mackie and
many others, and has lately appeared, refreshed, in Allan Gibbard's 'expressivist' account of
normative language. Simon Blackburn, reviewing Gibbard's Wise Choices, Apt Feelings, has said
that he hopes this book will now set the agenda for moral philosophy. 1
I myself, for all my admiration for Gibbard, hope that it will not do that. So I should say why I
believe that these non-cognitivist theories—one and all—are based on a mistake.
To identify the common characteristic of the apparently somewhat diverse moral philosophies
that I have just grouped together, and also to do justice to them, it will be good to start by
asking how the whole non-cognitivist business began. One finds its deepest roots in David
Hume. But more immediately, Ayer and Stevenson's emotivism, like Hare's prescriptivism,
came into being as a result of the 'linguistic turn', popularized by logical positivism but
developing far beyond it. For with 'linguistic philosophy' came the idea of explaining the
singularity of moral judgement in terms of a special use of language, called 'evaluation' but
more akin to exclamation and command than to anything one would normally mean by that
term. With this idea it seemed possible, at last, to say clearly what G. E. Moore had meant, or
should have meant, when he insisted that goodness was a special kind of 'non-natural'
property. 2
meaning, and otherwise not—'description' would still not, according to these theories, reach all
the way to moral judgement. 5
Someone convinced of the utility—or whatever—of certain kinds of action would not—indeed
could not—straightforwardly and with sincerity make the judgement about their moral
goodness unless he found in himself the right feelings and attitudes, or was ready to take the
step of committing himself to act in a particular way. For moral evaluation, something
'conative' had to be present as well as belief in matters of fact.
What all these theories tried to do, then, was to give the conditions of use of sentences such as 'It
is morally objectionable to break promises' in terms of something that must be true about the
speaker. He must have certain feelings or attitudes; he must commit himself to acting in a
certain way; he must at least feel remorse if he does not so act. Meaning was thus to be explained
in terms of a speaker's attitude, intentions, or state of mind. And this opened up a gap between
moral judgements and assertions, with the idea that truth conditions give, and may exhaust,
the meaning of the latter but not the former. Thus it seemed that fact, complementary to
assertion, had been distinguished from value, complementary to the expression of feeling,
attitude, or commitment to action. Propositions about matters of fact were assertable if their
truth conditions were fulfilled, but moral judgements, through conditions of utterance, were
essentially linked to an individual speaker's subjective state.
It is this kind of thing that seems to me all wrong, and to which I referred in the lecture 'Does
Moral Subjectivism Rest on a Mistake?' on which this chapter is based. So what, then, is the
mistake? It is the mistake of so construing what is 'special' about moral judgement that the
grounds of a moral judgement do not reach all the way to it. Whatever 'grounds' may have
been given, someone may be unready, indeed unable, to make the moral judgement, because
he has not got the attitude or feeling, is not in the 'conative' state of mind, is not ready to take the
decision to act: whatever it is that the theory says is required. It is this gap between ground and
moral judgement that I am denying. In my view there are no such conditions on moral
judgement and therefore no such gap.
It was not, however, a fit of collective madness that seized moral philosophers in the mid-
twentieth century, and still grips them today. Their theories were devised to take account of
something that really is a feature of moral judgement: the 'action-guiding' character of
morality, which Hume had insisted on and taken as the foundation of his moral philosophy.
Morality, Hume had said, is necessarily practical, serving to produce and prevent action, and I
shall call this 'Hume's practicality requirement'. 6
Nor am I denying that his demand must be met. My contention is rather that the theories I am
attacking tried to meet it in the wrong way. This, substantially, is what this chapter is about.
If I am to prove my thesis I must, of course, produce an alternative to the non-cognitivist way
of showing that moral judgement is essentially 'action-guiding'. So what is my own account of
the matter? It is, to state it briefly, that Hume's demand is met by the (most un-Humean)
thought that acting morally is part of practical rationality.
Now I am quite aware that to make this suggestion will seem most foolhardy: a case of putting
one's head, philosophically speaking, into the lion's mouth. For is it not difficult to establish
5See Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, chapter 1, paragraph 10.
6See Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, Book III, part I, section 1, and An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of
Morals, section 1.
Philippa Foot
even the coincidence of moral and rational action? What, after all, about those problem cases
where justice or charity forbids the only way out of a tight corner, and the life of the agent may
even be at stake? Isn't the demonstration of the rationality of just action a problem with which
David Gauthier, for instance, has been wrestling for years, with great energy and skill? 7
And isn't this the fence at which I myself have repeatedly fallen, trying now this way, now that,
of getting over—from 'Moral Beliefs' in 1958 to 'Morality as a System of Hypothetical
Imperatives' in 1972? All of this is true, and if I am hopeful of greater success this time round it
is because I think I now see why I couldn't have managed it before. Roughly speaking, it was
because I still held a more or less Humean theory of reasons for action, taking it for granted
that reasons had to be based on an agent's desires. To be sure, in another article written in 1972
I had (rather inconsistently with my doubts about the rational status of morals) allowed
considerations of self-interest an independent 'reason-giving' force. 8
But this didn't help with the rationality of disinterested justice, which rationality I was, rather
scandalously, inclined to restrict to those whose desires were such as to allow them to be
described as lovers of justice. I have therefore, rightly, been accused by my critics of
reintroducing subjectivity at the level of rationality while insisting on objectivity in the criteria
of moral right and wrong.
In common with others, I took it for granted at that time that a discussion of the rationality of
moral action would start from some theory or other about what a reason for action must be:
rather favouring a desire-fulfilment theory, with some special allowance for the force of
considerations of self-interest. I now believe that both the self-interest theory of rationality and
the theory of rationality as desire fulfilment are mistaken. Moreover, there seems to be a
mistake of strategy involved in trying to fit the rationality of moral action into either theory:
such an enterprise implying that we first come to a theory of rational action, and then try as
best we can to slot in the rationality of acts of justice and charity.
That this was a mistake of strategy was suggested to me by my friend Warren Quinn, and
while I do not think that he really developed the idea himself, the same thought is implicit in
his attack on end-neutral, Humean, theories of rationality, in an important article, 'Putting
Rationality in its Place', reprinted following his very sadly early death in the collection of his
papers called Morality and Action. What, asked Quinn, would be so important about practical
rationality if it were rational to seek to fulfil any, even a despicable, desire? In asking this he
was questioning whether it is right to think that moral action has to be brought under a pre-
established concept of practical rationality, and this seems to me to be very important indeed.
My own view is, and perhaps his was, that there is no question here of 'fitting in' in this
direction. I do not, therefore, want to canvas the rival claims of self-interest or maximum
satisfaction of desires as accounts of practical rationality, and then try, as Gauthier and many
others do, to explain the rationality of moral action in terms of the one that wins out. But nor
do I think, on the other side, that the whole of practical rationality can be brought under the
umbrella of 'morality', as we usually understand that term.
As I see it, the rationality of, say, telling the truth, keeping promises, or helping a neighbour is
on a par with the rationality of self-preserving action, and of the careful and cognizant pursuit
of other innocent ends; each being a part or aspect of practical rationality. The different
considerations are on a par, moreover, in that a judgement about what is required by practical
rationality must take account of their interaction: of the weight of the ones we call non-moral as
well as those we call moral. For it is not always rational to give help where it is needed, to keep
a promise, or even, I believe, always to speak the truth. If it is to be said that 'moral
considerations' are always 'overriding', it cannot be these particular considerations that we
refer to, but must rather be the overall judgement about what, all things considered, should be
done. Sorting out this particular point of precedence is, I think, a matter of keeping one's head
and remembering that some expressions do and some do not imply overall judgement:
imprudence, for instance, being by definition contrary to rationality, but self-sacrifice not.
Leaving aside this complication, we may think of the different requirements of rationality in
action as on a par. I shall argue later that there is a unity to these different grounds of practical
rationality that may not be obvious right away. What I want to stress at this point is that in my
account of the relation between goodness of choice and practical rationality it is the former that
is primary. I want to say, baldly, that there is no criterion for practical rationality that is not
derived from that of goodness of the will.
How, I shall be asked, can that be so, given that promises must often be kept, truth told, or
succour given, even when that is contrary to self-interest or to heart's desire?
The demonstration may start, I believe, with some observations on the nature of a virtue. It is in
the concept of a virtue that in so far as someone possesses it, his actions are good; which is to
say that he acts well. Virtues bring it about that one who has them acts well, and we must
enquire as to what this does and does not mean.
What, for instance, distinguishes a just person from one who is unjust? The fact that he keeps
his contracts? That cannot be right, because circumstances may make it impossible for him to
do so. Nor is it that he saves life rather than kills innocent people, for by blameless mishap he
may kill rather than save. 'Of course,' someone will say at this point, 'it is the just person's
intention, not what he actually brings about, that counts.' But why not say, then, that it is the
distinguishing characteristic of the just that for them certain considerations count as reasons for
action, and as reasons of a given weight? Will it not be the same with other virtues, as for instance
for the virtues of charity, courage, and temperance? Those who possess these virtues possess
them in so far as they recognize certain considerations (such as the fact of a promise, or of a
neighbour's need) as powerful, and in many circumstances compelling, reasons for acting.
They recognize the reasons, and act on them.
Thus the description 'just', as applied to a man or a woman, speaks of how it is with him or her
in respect of the acceptance of a certain group of considerations as reasons for action. If justice
is a virtue, this is what the virtue of justice rectifies, that is, makes good. It is no part of the
goodness that is goodness of the will that someone should be physically strong, should move
well, talk well, or see well. But he must act well, in a sense that is given primarily at least by his
recognition of the force of particular considerations as reasons for acting: that and the influence
that this has on what he does. The just person aims at keeping promises, paying what is owed,
and defending those whose rights are being violated, so far as such actions are required by the
virtue of justice. Likewise, he recognizes certain limitations on what he may do even for some
virtue-given end; as he may not kill an innocent person even for the sake of stopping someone
else from killing a greater number, though he may (to use one of Elizabeth Anscombe's many
memorable examples) destroy someone's property to stop the spread of a fire. And again he
Philippa Foot
acts accordingly. Similarly, if charity is a virtue, this is because it makes its possessor's action
good in the area of aims such as the relief of poverty. Here again, recognizing particular
considerations as reasons for action, he acts on these reasons as he should. 9
Now in describing virtues in terms of (a) the recognition of particular considerations as reasons
for acting, and (b) the relevant action, I have only been expressing familiar and time-honoured
ideas of moral goodness. But how can it be denied that I have at the same time been talking
about practical rationality? The discussion has been about human goodness in respect of
reason-recognition and reason-following, and if this is not practical rationality I should like to
know what is. The reply from those who hold a preconceived theory of practical rationality
will be, no doubt, that rationality is the following of perceived self-interest; alternatively, that it
is the pursuit, careful and cognizant, of the maximum satisfaction of present desires; each
respondent suggesting that one of these rival theories gives the concept of practical rationality.
At the very least, they may argue, such theories give a valid alternative idea of practical
rationality, to set beside the one that emerged from our discussion of justice and charity as
virtues having to do with the following of reasons. But I suggested earlier that this was a
mistake: that we should not think in terms of rival theories, but of the different parts of
practical rationality, no one of which should be mistaken for the whole. An action can be
contrary to practical rationality in that it is dishonest or disrespectful of others' rights, or that it
is foolishly imprudent; or, again, that the agent is, for example, careless, timid, or half-hearted
in going for what he wants.
Given that there are at least so many different cases, which it may or may not be useful to
categorize, it is not surprising that the blanket term 'practical irrationality', and cognates such
as 'contrary to practical reason', may go along with different subsidiary descriptions. I do not
want to argue about bits of linguistic usage: about where, for instance, the particular term
'irrational', or again 'unreasonable', is or isn't at home. It is obvious that some terms such as
'silly' or 'foolish', and even 'irrational' in its common use, do not correctly describe the actions
of, for instance, the Great Train Robbers; even though in being dishonest, and criminally
careless of the life of the train driver, what they did was contrary to justice and so, in the view I
am expounding, to practical rationality. It makes for nothing but confusion to centre an
argument about practical reason around one particular expression cut off from its genuine
application, as Allan Gibbard did in supposing moral judgement to be expressible in terms of
what does or does not 'make sense': 10
as if that were the way to say what was wrong with the train robbers' actions, or with the
notoriously extortionist English landlord Rachmann's dealings with his tenants!
There is no doubt but that there are different kinds of cases of contrary-to-reason-ness, and not
surprisingly it is possible to contravene rationality in more than one way at the same time. I
once read of a burglar who was caught because he sat down to watch television in the house he
was burgling, thus adding the contrary-to-reasonness of imprudence to that of dishonesty.
Because his actions were faulty in that he did not hurry away with the swag, we can say, if we
like, that he should have done so. It does not follow, however, that he would have acted well if
9 The fact that possession of a virtue carries implications that go beyond actions or even intentions is given explicit
recognition later in this book. See Chapter 4.
10 See Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings, for instance, pp. 7, 37, 38.
1 A Fresh Start?
he had avoided imprudence, because no one can act with full practical rationality in the pursuit
of a bad end. 11
It is, I think, possible to see, even if not as yet very clearly, the common thread linking these
different parts of practical rationality. The root notion is that of the goodness of human beings
in respect of their actions; which means, to repeat, goodness of the will rather than of such
things as sight, dexterity, or memory. Kant was perfectly right in saying that moral goodness
was goodness of the will; the idea of practical rationality is throughout a concept of this kind.
He seems to have gone wrong, however, in thinking that an abstract idea of practical reason
applicable to rational beings as such could take us all the way to anything like our own moral
code. For the evaluation of human action depends also on essential features of specifically
human life.
Elizabeth Anscombe brings out this dependence of morality on the life of our species in a
passage in her article 'On Promising and its Justice'. There she points out facts about human life
that make it necessary for human beings to be able to bind each other to action through
institutions like promising, such as that there are so few other ways in which one person can
reliably get another to do what he wants. And what hangs on this may, we might add, be
something very important, such as that one's children should be cared for after one's death. I
shall consider Anscombe's discussion of promising at more length in Chapter 3.
Anscombe writes, '[G]etting one another to do things without the application of physical force
is a necessity for human life, and that far beyond what could be secured by . . . other means.' 12
Anscombe is pointing here to what she has elsewhere called an 'Aristotelian necessity': that
which is necessary because and in so far as good hangs on it. 13
We invoke the same idea when we say that it is necessary for plants to have water, for birds to
build nests, for wolves to hunt in packs, and for lionesses to teach their cubs to kill. These
'Aristotelian necessities' depend on what the particular species of plants and animals need, on
their natural habitat, and the ways of making out that are in their repertoire. These things
together determine what it is for members of a particular species to be as they should be, and to
do that which they should do. 14
And for all the enormous differences between the life of humans and that of plants or animals,
we can see that human defects and excellences are similarly related to what human beings are
and what they do. We do not need to be able to dive like gannets, nor to see in the dark like
owls; but our memory and concentration must be such as to allow us to learn language, and
our sight such that we can recognize faces at a glance; while, like lionesses, human parents are
defective if they do not teach their young the skills that they need to survive.
Moreover, in that we are social animals, we depend on each other as do wolves that hunt in
packs, with cooperation such as our own depending on special factors such as conventional
arrangements. Like the animals, we do things that will benefit others rather than ourselves:
there is no good case for assessing the goodness of human action by reference only to good that
each person brings to himself. Is it, one wonders, some lingering shadow of the thoroughly
discredited doctrine of psychological egoism—of the belief that all human action is directed to
the good of the agent himself—that inclines us to an egoistic concept of practical rationality? I
do not know what else should make us think that the evaluation of reason-following behaviour
must be altogether different in its conceptual structure from the evaluation of the behaviour of
an animal. And it will surely not be denied that there is something wrong with a free-riding
wolf that feeds but does not take part in the hunt, as with a member of the species of dancing
bees who finds a source of nectar but whose behaviour does not let other bees know of its
location. These free-riding individuals of a species whose members work together are just as
defective as those who have defective hearing, sight, or powers of locomotion.
I am therefore, quite seriously, likening the basis of moral evaluation to that of the evaluation
of behaviour in animals. I should stress, however, that it is important not to underestimate the
degree to which human communication and reasoning change the scene. The goods that hang
on human cooperation, and hang too on such things as respect for truth, art, and scholarship,
are much more diverse and much harder to delineate than are animal goods. Animals are
different also from us in that to do what they should do—what is needed and is within their
capacity—they do not have to understand what is going on; whereas a human being can and
should understand that, and why, there is reason for, say, keeping a promise or behaving
fairly. This last may seem a tall order, but this human understanding is not anything hard to
come by. We all know enough to say. 'How could we get on without justice?', 'Where would
we be if no one helped anyone else?', or 'How could we manage if there were no way of
making decisions for us all?'
Anyone who thinks about it can see that for human beings the teaching and following of
morality is something necessary. We can't get on without it. And this is the nub of the proper
answer to the challenge that I made in 'Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives',
where I asked why it should be thought rational to follow morality, but not to obey duelling
rules or silly rules of etiquette. In that article I myself made a rotten job of answering my own
question because, still under the influence of Humean ideas of practical rationality, I thought
irrelevant what is now turning out to be most relevant. 15
Later on, Warren Quinn helped me by pointing out that after this change I could at least claim
to have found the basis for a unified theory of rationality. For if the virtues nowadays thought
of especially worthy to be called moral virtues, and often contrasted with prudence, are
'Aristotelian necessities' for human beings, so too is a reasonable modicum of self-interest, if
It was, I remember, a remark of Rosalind Hursthouse's in a discussion that put me right about this. See also
15
only because, once grown, we can look out for ourselves much better than anyone else can do it
for us. 16
Good hangs, too, on the careful and cognizant pursuit of many more particular ends, and in
general in satisfying appetites and following desires.
It is time now for me to return to the main line of my argument against non-cognitivism. It is
because I see practical rationality as determined in this way that I claim to be able to interpret
the 'action-guidingness' of moral judgement in terms of the practical rationality of moral action.
And please notice that I have not reintroduced, via the concept of practical rationality itself, a
subjective (agent-centred) condition on moral judgement. For I have not subscribed to a desire-
based, Humean, theory of practical rationality: nor have I any reason to go along with
Gibbard's 'expressivist' account of what it is we are doing when we say that a certain action is
rational. Nothing of that kind has had any part in what I have said.
If I am right, therefore, about judgements of practical rationality and their ground, and right in
seeing the kind of thing that Elizabeth Anscombe said about promising as simply one
particular application of general (species-based) criteria of evaluation, I can claim to see how, in
principle, a non-subjectivist—indeed cognitivist—reply might be given to Hume's demand that
morality be shown to be 'necessarily practical'. Considerations about such things as promising,
neighbourliness, and help for those in trouble have, I maintain, the same kind of connection
with reasons for action as do considerations of self-interest or of means to our ends: the
connection going in each case through the concept of practical rationality and the facts of
human life. So I think that we can see as hopeful the project of producing a cognitivist
alternative to theories such as emotivism, prescriptivism, and expressivism: an alternative that
takes care of just what they were trying to take care of, in the way of a necessary connection
between moral judgement and action.
I am sure that it will be objected at this point that even if, along these lines, a certain conceptual
link has been shown to hold between moral language and action, via the fact that a moral
judgement speaks of what there is reason to do, this will not have put the connection in the
right place. For, it will be said, a relation has not been shown that holds between moral
judgement and the action of each and every individual. This, however, I would dispute. On a
'practical rationality' account, a moral judgement says something about the action of any
individual to whom it applies: namely, something about the reason that there is for him to do it
or not do it, whether or not he recognizes that, and whether or not, if he does recognize it, he
also acts on it as he should. Moreover, it can explain moral action in an individual who knows
that he has reason to act morally; because acting on reasons is a basic mode of operation in
human beings. This, too, is part of my account of the way in which morality is necessarily
practical: it serves to produce and prevent action, because the understanding of reasons can do that.
16In theory, this could, of course, be different for some other kinds of rational beings. Perhaps they would find it
impossible to think calmly about their own future, and would have invented a kind of 'buddy system' by which
each person had someone else to look out for him. We should find this extremely inconvenient except in bringing
up children when they are small.
Philippa Foot
We must be careful, however, not to tie moral judgement too closely to action. One who is the
subject of a true moral judgement does not always do what it says he should do, since he may
not recognize its truth, and may not act on it even if he does. In spite of recognizing the force of
Hume's 'practicality requirement', we must allow for ignorance, for weakness of will, and also
for the phenomenon of shamelessness. It should be seen as an advantage, not a disadvantage, if
my 'rationality' account leaves room for this last. No doubt quite open shamelessness is fairly
rare (even today), at least in the circles in which most philosophers live. But it is important to
recognize that shamelessness can coexist with the use of moral language, and to see that this
shamelessness is not the same as insincerity. I have read, for instance, of a member of a group
of city louts out for a day in the country to hunt down some small inoffensive animal, who,
though described as 'the conscience of the group', said 'I know I'm on earth 70 years and that
I'm not going anywhere else. If I choose to spend my day out in the countryside doing
whatever I feel like, then that's what I'll do.' And again of a certain Brooklyn machine politician
who had the gall to say that while people think it hard to stand up for what is right, what is
really hard is what he was doing, 'standing up day after day, week after week, for what is
wrong'. Like Alec D'Urberville in Hardy's novel, this politician might have said 'I have lived
bad, and I shall die bad', meaning what he said, but without the slightest intention to reform.
There are, it is true, some who try to hide their shamelessness by making an attack on morality.
But more people than we like to admit are simply shameless. Are they then not 'endorsing the
norm' of justice and charity, to use Gibbard's words for what he sees as expressing a state of
mind in moral judgement? Well, I do not know what is meant by this somewhat contrived
expression. I suppose that most criminals do not think much about the topic of morality, being
in this rather like the British politician who, when confronted with a nasty fact about the arms
trade, is reported to have said 'I do not much fill my mind with what one set of foreigners does
to another.' I suppose one can evade either 'endorsing' or not 'endorsing' morality, or part of
morality, by simply refusing to think about it; and I suppose that most of us do that at times.
But D'Urberville seems not, on the night he seduced Tess, to have pushed morality out of sight,
when he said 'I have lived bad, and I shall die bad', and it is important to contrast his mentality
with the point of view of those whom we may call '(ideological) immoralists', such as
Thrasymachus, Callicles, Nietzsche, or André Gide. For they queried whether human goodness
and badness are what they are supposed to be, whereas D'Urberville implicitly endorsed
ordinary moral opinion, as did the Brooklyn machine politician, and perhaps also the 'city
hunter' who seems to have thought that there was reason for him to let harmless animals live.
By contrast with these shameless individuals, the immoralists are bringing arguments in favour
of some different standard of human goodness.
I am not, of course, denying that there are many ambiguous cases; but the two poles of
shamelessness and immoralism nevertheless exist. And it is not the shameless, but those who
in their heart of hearts agree with, say, Thrasymachus or Nietzsche, who are insincere if they
speak as we do about what is right and wrong.
It follows, therefore, from the line of argument of this chapter that Hare, who said that moral
language was 'prescriptive'—and who so defined the prescriptive use of language that anyone
1 A Fresh Start?
To answer this question it will be useful to consider an article by Michael Smith in which what
he calls 'the Humean theory of motivation' is defended. He writes:
We are likely to be seduced by this because it is natural to think in the following way. Take as
an example that of someone who throws away his supply of cigarettes. He does so because he
wants to give up smoking. And he wants to give up smoking because he wants a healthy old
age. The series goes on—A for the sake of B—but it can't go on forever. 21
Must it not end with something that the agent 'just wants'; in other words, with some 'conative'
element in his individual psychological state?
The question is meant to be rhetorical; but the answer to it is 'No'. For what, we must ask, gives
the agent this goal? Does he find himself trembling at the thought of cancer at 50? Is he in a
state of anxiety at the thought of how much he smokes? Perhaps. But nothing of this kind has
to be part of the story, as Smith himself admits. So why do we say that what gets the whole
thing going must be a desire or other 'conative' element in the subject's 'psychological state'?
Suppose instead that it is the recognition that there is reason for him, as for anyone else, to look
after his future so far as circumstances allow? Why should not this be where the series of
questions 'Why?' comes to an end? Those already in thrall to the mechanical picture of the
workings of the mind will deny it. Others may, however, consider the question why should we
not take the recognition of a reason for acting as bringing the series to a close? Recognition of a reason
gives the rational person a goal; and this recognition is, according to the argument of the
present chapter, based on facts and concepts, not on some prior attitude, feeling, or goal. The
only fact about the individual's state of mind that is required for the explanatory force of the
proposition about the requirement of rationality is that he does not (for some bizarre reason)
deny its truth. He only needs to know, like most adults, that it is silly to disregard one's own
future without special reason to do so. No special explanation is needed of why men take
reasonable care of their own future; an explanation is needed when they do not. Nor does
human cooperation need a special explanation. Most people know that it is, for instance,
unreasonable to take benefits and give nothing in return.
In denying the neo-Humean account of reasons for action in general it is, however, important
to stress that there are some that do depend on what a particular person wants. If I want to see
the Taj Mahal, I have reason to buy a ticket to India as someone who detests all things Eastern
does not. The imperative is, as Kant would say, hypothetical: if I no longer want to see India,
the reason may well disappear. Another obvious example is that of someone who, feeling
hungry and having no food in the house, goes down the road to buy something to eat. If he
were not hungry, he would not have this reason to go, and unless there were some other
reason in the offing, the facts about the food shop and the empty larder could not explain why
he went to the shop.
My conclusion is, therefore, that neither directly (through conditions on sincere moral
utterances) nor indirectly (through the thought that moral judgement can explain action) does
the acceptance of 'Hume's practicality requirement' give any support to non-cognitivism in
ethics. Nor has any reason been given for the existence of a logical gap between a moral
judgement and its grounds. The premises of a moral argument give grounds for an assertion
about what it is morally good—and therefore about what it is practically rational—to do. And
for anything that has been shown to the contrary, these premises could even entail the conclusion,
though I have certainly not argued that this is so. I have very little idea of how much 'play'
there will in the end turn out to be in disagreements between moralities, and how many grey
areas and irreconcilable opinions we shall want to recognize. One can keep an open mind
about that.
What, then, is to be said about the relation between 'fact' and 'value'? The thesis of this chapter
is that the grounding of a moral argument is ultimately in facts about human life—facts of the
kind that Anscombe mentioned in talking about the good that hangs on the institution of
promising, and of the kind that I spoke of in saying why it was a part of rationality for human
beings to take special care each for his or her own future. In my view, therefore, a moral
evaluation does not stand over against the statement of a matter of fact, but rather has to do
with facts about a particular subject matter, as do evaluations of such things as sight and
hearing in animals, and other aspects of their behaviour. Nobody would, I think, take it as
other than a plain matter of fact that there is something wrong with the hearing of a gull that
cannot distinguish the cry of its own chick, as with the sight of an owl that cannot see in the
dark. Similarly, it is obvious that there are objective, factual evaluations of such things as
human sight, hearing, memory, and concentration, based on the life form of our own species.
Why, then, does it seem so monstrous a suggestion that the evaluation of the human will
should be determined by facts about the nature of human beings and the life of our own
species? Undoubtedly the resistance has something to do with the thought that the goodness of
good action has a special relation to choice. But as I have tried to show, this special relation is
not what non-cognitivists think it is, but rather lies in the fact that moral action is rational
action, and in the fact that human beings are creatures with the power to recognize reasons for
action and to act on them. This in no way precludes recognition of the part played by
'sentiments' such as (negatively) shame and revulsion or (positively) sympathy, self-respect,
and pride in motivating human virtue. I think that David Wiggins is right often to have
stressed this side of Hume's moral philosophy. 22
2 Natural Norms
Philippa Foot
I hope I have said enough in the previous chapter to raise doubts about the necessity and even
the possibility of interpreting 'moral language' in expressivist terms. I suggested that it is
'Hume's practicality requirement' that gives such theories their undoubted attraction, and
promised an account of thoughts about goodness and badness in action that would meet this
requirement differently. In the following chapters of this book I shall try to make this promise
good.
The central feature of my own account is that it will set the evaluation of human action in the
wider contexts not only of the evaluation of other features of human life but also of evaluative
judgements of the characteristics and operations of other living things. Expressivist theories
have the remarkable though seldom-mentioned consequence of separating off the evaluation of
human action not only from the evaluation of human sight, hearing, and bodily health but also
from all evaluation of the characteristics and operations of plants and animals. 23
For it is obvious that no expressivist account will do in those other domains: we cannot think
that the use of the word 'good' is to express a 'pro-attitude' in what we say about the roots of
nettles or the fangs of ferocious beasts. Nowadays such evaluations are apt to be marginalized
as if they were fanciful extensions of the 'proper' evaluations that express our attitudes,
practical decisions, or desires. But when I was told by a certain philosopher who wanted to
explain 'good' in terms of choices, that the good roots of trees were roots of the kind we 'should
choose if we were trees', this finally confirmed my suspicion of the kind of moral philosophy
that was his. Thinking of goodness as emotivists and prescriptivists think of it we may see as
quite remarkable that the word 'good' and its cognates can be used as it is in the description of
sub-rational living things. To be sure, almost anything in the world can be said to be good or
bad in a context that sufficiently relates it to some human concern or to the needs of a plant or
animal. But features of plants and animals have what one might call an 'autonomous',
'intrinsic', or as I shall say 'natural' goodness and defect that may have nothing to do with the
needs or wants of the members of any other species of living thing, and in this they are notably
different from what is found elsewhere in other things in the world outside, as for instance
rivers or storms.
Judgements of goodness and badness can have, it seems, a special 'grammar' when the subject
belongs to a living thing, whether plant, animal, or human being. This, at least, is what I argue
in this book. I think that this special category of goodness is easily overlooked; perhaps because
we make so many evaluations of other kinds, as when we assess non-living things in the
natural world, such as soil or weather, or again assess artefacts either made by humans as are
houses and bridges, or made by animals as are the nests of birds or beavers' dams. 24
But the goodness predicated in these latter cases, like goodness predicated to living things
when they are evaluated in a relationship to members of species other than their own, is what I
should like to call secondary goodness. It is in this derivative way that we can speak of the
goodness of, for example, soil or weather, as such things are related to plants, to animals, or to
us. And we also ascribe this secondary goodness to living things, as, for instance, to specimens
of plants that grow as we want them to grow, or to horses that carry us as we want to be
carried, while artefacts are often named and evaluated by the need or interest that they chiefly
serve. By contrast, 'natural' goodness, as I define it, which is attributable only to living things
themselves and to their parts, characteristics, and operations, is intrinsic or 'autonomous'
goodness in that it depends directly on the relation of an individual to the 'life form' of its
species. On barren Mars there is no natural goodness, and even secondary goodness can be
attributed to things on that planet only by relating them to our own lives, or to living things
existing elsewhere.
We shall of course need to consider why it is that natural goodness and defect belong only to
living things and not to other objects in the world around us such as rocks and storms. What is
it about living things that allows us to attribute goodness to them in this special way? Why can
we not attribute natural goodness, for example, to the tributaries of rivers, when they are such
as to allow a river to maintain its natural progressive pattern from upland to lake or sea?
It may be thought that the topics raised in the preceding paragraphs are of no relevance to
moral philosophy, even if interesting in themselves. But this is just what I want to question. My
belief is that for all the differences that there are, as we shall see, between the evaluation of
plants and animals and their parts and characteristics on the one hand, and the moral
evaluation of humans on the other, we shall find that these evaluations share a basic logical
structure and status. I want to suggest that moral defect is a form of natural defect not as
different as is generally supposed from defect in sub-rational living things. So this is what I
shall go on to argue, after a discussion of 'natural goodness' as it is found in sub-rational living
things.
Firstly, therefore, I shall explore natural goodness in plants and in animals other than human
beings. For help I shall turn to a paper published by Michael Thompson: a paper I admire very
much.
Michael Thompson's subject in this paper, which is called 'The Representation of Life', is the
description of living things. His thesis is that to understand certain distinctive ways in which
we describe individual organisms, we must recognize the logical dependence of these
descriptions on the nature of the species to which the individual belongs. Species-dependence
is his leitmotif. For this reason he concerns himself with propositions of the form 'S's are F' or
'The S is F', where 'S' holds a place for the name of a species (or 'life form' as he is ready to say
for the sake of those who want to give 'species' a technical definition) and 'F' a place for a
predicate; so that a representative sentence would be 'Rabbits are herbivores' or 'The rabbit is a
herbivore'. He contrasts the logical form of the sentences
S's are F (Rabbits are herbivores)
S's do V (Rabbits eat grass)
with
N.N. is F (Mrs Muff is a rabbit)
N.N. is doing V (Mrs Muff is eating grass).
He points out, referring back to an early article by Elizabeth Anscombe, a peculiarity of the
logical form of the first pair of sentences: that they are logically unquantifiable. 25
They do not speak of an individual rabbit, though the same verbal form can of course be used
with that reference, as when the conjurer says to his wife 'The rabbit does not look well.' Nor,
of course, do the propositions that interest Michael Thompson predicate something of every
member of the species: 'Cats are four-legged but Tibbles may have only three.' Elizabeth
Anscombe's original example concerned the number of teeth that human beings have—which
is 32, though most human beings have lost quite a few and some never had the full
complement. It is arguable that if 'The S is F' (understood in this way) is true then at least some
S's must be F. But even if this is so, 'Some S's are F' is clearly not the whole of what such a
proposition asserts. Thompson speaks in this context of a 'natural-history account' of the life
form or species: of how creatures of this kind live. And he points out, as part of his insistence
on the way in which descriptions of individuals depend on the species to which they belong,
that without this reference, 'life activities' such as eating or reproducing cannot even be
identified in an individual. Eating, for instance, is essentially, conceptually, related to
nourishment, and could not be conclusively identified by a story about the taking in, crushing,
transforming, and spewing out of substances since, for all that, its purpose might be not the
maintenance of tissue but, say, skunk-like defence. Mitosis occurs in amoebae and human
beings, and is given a uniform description in textbooks: in the first, however, it is reproduction
of an individual organism, but in the second not. 26
Thompson also points out peculiarities of the time references found within such propositions.
It is said for instance that certain animals mate at a certain time of the year, and give birth, or
lay eggs, so many weeks or months later; but this is 'typically a matter of before and after—"in
the spring", "in the fall" . . . and not of now and then . . . and when I was young and so forth'. 27
Natural-history sentences, which Thompson also calls 'Aristotelian categoricals', speak of the
life cycle of individuals of a given species. 28
In one way, therefore, this is the time-span with which they have to do. In another way,
however, a longer time reference is needed, since we must speak of reproduction, and the
characteristics of a single individual cannot determine what will count as another of the same.
It will no doubt be objected here that reproduction is in fact not fixed, since species themselves
are subject to change. This is of course important, and it means that Aristotelian categoricals
must take account of sub-species adapted to local conditions. The history of a species is not,
however, the subject with which Aristotelian categoricals deal. Their truth is truth about a
species at a given historical time, and it is only the relative stability of at least the most general
features of the different species of living things that makes these propositions possible at all.
They tell how a kind of plant or animal, considered at a particular time and in its natural
habitat, develops, sustains itself, defends itself, and reproduces. It is only in so far as 'stills' can
be made from the moving picture of the evolution of species that we can have a natural history
account of the life of a particular kind of living thing. And it is only in so far as we have a
'natural history account' that we can have a 'vital description' of individuals here and now.
Let us now ask how all this is relevant to the normative judgements that we make about plants
and animals when we say, for instance, that a plant in our garden is diseased, or not growing
properly, or that a certain lioness is a neglectful parent, or a particular rabbit not as
reproductive as a rabbit should be. Thompson suggests that the relation between the
Aristotelian categorical and the evaluative assessment is very close indeed. In fact, he says that
if we have a true natural-history proposition to the effect that S's are F, then if a certain
individual S—the individual here and now or then and there—is not F it is therefore not as it
should be, but rather weak, diseased, or in some other way defective. 29
The evaluative assessment is the product of propositions of the two logically different kinds.
Essentially, I think that Thompson is right about this, although I seem to see a gap in his
account of Aristotelian categoricals that has to be filled in here. For I think he has not said
enough to isolate the kind of proposition that will yield evaluations of individual organisms.
His talk of 'natural-history propositions' was perhaps misleading in that it did not explicitly
separate out what I would like to call the teleological from the non-teleological attachment of
predicates to a subject term that is the name of a species. Consider, for instance, a sentence such
as 'The blue tit has a round blue patch on its head.' This is superficially like 'The male peacock
has a brightly coloured tail', but in a way of course it is not. For, on the assumption that colour
of head plays no part in the life of the blue tit, it is in this respect quite unlike the colour of the
male peacock's tail: there would be nothing wrong with the blue tit in my garden in that it had
a drab-coloured head; and the peculiarity might or might not accompany a defect. So how are
we to distinguish these two types of propositions? Or how, again, are we to distinguish the
case of leaves rustling when it is windy from that of flowers opening when the sun comes out?
It is natural to say that the rustling of its leaves plays no part in the life of a tree, whereas
pollination is gained by a display of scent and colours in sunshine. But then we must ask what
we mean by 'playing a part in the life' of a living thing. What counts as 'its life' in this context?
And what is 'playing a part'?
There emerges here the special link, mentioned but not explored by Thompson, between his
'Aristotelian categoricals' and teleology in living things. Aristotelian categoricals are
propositions having to do with the way that certain features appear or that certain things are
done in organisms of a given species either by the whole organism or by their characteristics or
parts. But, speaking now for myself rather than for Thompson, I should say that to obtain the
connection between Aristotelian categoricals and evaluation another move must be made. I
should say that in plants and non-human animals these things all have to do, directly or
indirectly, with self-maintenance, as by defence and the obtaining of nourishment, or with the
reproduction of the individual, as by the building of nests. This is 'the life' characteristic of the
kind of animal with which the categoricals here have to do. What 'plays a part' in this life is
that which is causally and teleologically related to it, as putting out roots is related to obtaining
nourishment, and attracting insects is related to reproduction in plants. 30
We start from the fact that there is a basis for the Aristotelian categorical that does not come
from the counting of heads. What is this basis? In what was said about the blue tits and the
peacocks it was suggested that some but not all general propositions about a species have to do
29Ibid. 295.
30It is obvious that the causality here is that of necessary rather than sufficient conditions: the hazards of nature
and the existence of the food chain mean that most, even healthy, members of most species of animals are unlikely
to live long.
Philippa Foot
with the teleology of living things of this kind. There is an Aristotelian categorical about the
species peacock to the effect that the male peacock displays his brilliant tail in order to attract a
female during the mating season. The display serves this purpose. Let us call such language,
purposive language. But be careful here! Where something that S's do is, in this sense,
purposive we should beware of slipping over into saying of an individual S that it has this
purpose when it does this thing. Plants grow upwards in order to get to the light, but it is
fanciful to say that that is what my honeysuckle is trying to do or that that is 'its end'.
Migrating birds flying off in order to reach the southern insects do not have this as their end or
purpose even though it could be said to be the end or purpose of the operation. 31
What is crucial to all teleological propositions is the expectation of an answer to the question
'What part does it play in the life cycle of things of the species S?' In other words, 'What is its
function?' or 'What good does it do?' 32
Philosophers are sometimes afraid of recognizing teleological language, thinking it must be
something left over from a world-view in which all nature was seen as reflecting the will of the
deity. 33
But Thompson is surely right to say
Natural-teleological judgements may . . . be said to organize the elements of a natural
history; they articulate the relations of dependence among the various elements and
aspects and phases of a given kind of life.
And so . . . even if the Divine Mind were to bring a certain life-form into being 'with a view to'
securing an abundance of pink fur along the shores of the Monongahela, this would have no
effect on the natural-teleological description of that form of life. 34
What, then, determines the truth of the teleological propositions of the non-quantifiable form
that meet Thompson's conditions? We start from the fact that it is the particular life form of a
species of plant or animal that determines how an individual plant or animal should be: the
Aristotelian categoricals give the 'how' of what happens in the life cycle of that species. And all
the truths about what this or that characteristic does, what its purpose or point is, and in
suitable cases its function, must be related to this life cycle. The way an individual should be is
31 It is only rarely that we can say of an individual animal that it is trying to do something or other, and perhaps
only where it has a repertoire of ways of achieving an 'end' closely connected with these bits of behaviour, as
when a dog tries to get out of a shed in which it has been confined.
32 It is imperative that the word 'function' as used here is not confused with its use in evolutionary biology, where,
as Simon Blackburn has put it in the Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy, 'the function of a feature of an organism is
frequently defined as that role it plays which has been responsible for its genetic success and evolution' (149-50).
Features that are functional in this sense are what Dawkins, for instance, calls 'adaptations', when he defines an
adaptation both historically and as 'approximately an attribute of an organism that is "good for something" ' (The
Extended Phenotype, 290). In such contexts it is supposed to make sense to speak of the good of a species, as if a
species were itself a gradually developing, one-off organism, whose life might stretch for millions of years.
Perhaps the extinction of a species is imagined as a kind of death, and therefore as if it were an evil, with that
which makes for its continuance thought of as 'for its good'! It is easy to confuse these technical uses of words such
as 'function' and 'good' with their everyday uses, but the meanings are distinct. To say that some feature of a
living thing is an adaptation is to place it in the history of a species. To say that it has a function is to say that it has
a certain place in the life of the individuals that belong to that species at a certain time.
33 Thompson, 'The Representation of Life', 293-4. See also Lawrence, 'Reflection, Practice and Ethical Scepticism',
section VI, 2.
34 Thompson, 'The Representation of Life', 294.
2 Natural Norms
Thus, evaluation of an individual living thing in its own right, with no reference to our
interests or desires, is possible where there is intersection of two types of propositions: on the
one hand, Aristotelian categoricals (life-form descriptions relating to the species), and on the
other, propositions about particular individuals that are the subject of evaluation.
It will be useful to remind ourselves at this point of the elements that came to light in the
earlier discussion of 'good' and 'bad' as applied to characteristics and operations of plants and
animals.
(a) There was the life cycle, which in those cases consisted roughly of self-maintenance and
reproduction.
(b) There was the set of propositions saying how for a certain species this was achieved: how
nourishment was obtained, how development took place, what defences were available,
and how reproduction was secured.
(c) From all this, norms were derived, requiring, for instance, a certain degree of swiftness in
the deer, night vision in the owl, and cooperative hunting in the wolf.
(d) By the application of these norms to an individual member of the relevant species it (this
individual) was judged to be as it should be or, by contrast, to a lesser or greater degree
defective in a certain respect.
There are here many details that are not germane to the aim of this book. But something more
must be said about the way in which Aristotelian categoricals about the 'how and what' of the
life cycle determine normative assessments of individual living things in the here and now or
there and then of historical place and time.
As illustration let us consider the Aristotelian categorical stating that the deer is an animal
whose form of defence is flight. From this we know that it is a defect, a weakness, in an
individual deer if it is slow of foot. Swiftness, as opposed to fierceness or camouflage, is what
In most cases we speak of what each member of the species needs to be and to do in order that it should flourish.
35
But of course what is needed may be needed in a group, like cooperation in a pack, or obedience to a leader, and
what a member of the species is or does may advantage others rather than himself.
Philippa Foot
fits it to escape from its predators. But two remarks must be added about this. In the first place,
swiftness does no more than fit it to survive: in some circumstances even the greatest speed
possible for this type of animal would not be enough. Moreover, by chance it may sometimes
be that the fastest deer fleeing from one predator is the very one that gets caught in a trap. 36
Secondly, what is excellence, and what defect, is relative to the natural habitat of the species.
Even in a zoo a fleeing animal like a deer that cannot run well is so far forth defective and not
as it should be, in spite of the fact that, as this particular individual is by chance placed, this
may be no disadvantage for defence or feeding or mating or rearing the young.
A further consideration, when we are describing the life form of certain animals, is that they
live cooperatively. The swiftness of a deer fits it to preserve its own life by evading a predator.
And the night vision of the owl is something it needs if it is to survive and rear its young. The
fact is, however, that while there are many examples that are like this in the life of animals,
there are also what we could call 'other-regarding' goodnesses and defects in their case. Take,
for instance, the dance of the honey bee which tells other bees of a source of food. No doubt an
individual bee that does not dance does not itself suffer from its delinquency, but ipso facto
because it does not dance, there is something wrong with it, because of the part that dancing
plays in the life of this species of bee. Similarly, cooperation is something on which good hangs
in the life of the wolf, and the free-riding wolf is not behaving as it should. Such facts will be
relevant when we come to consider analogies and disanalogies between the 'life forms' of
animals and human beings. Peter Geach said in his book on The Virtues that 'Men need virtues
as bees need stings', deliberately allowing for the other-regarding aspect of virtues such as
justice and charity. 37
The way Geach made his point is perhaps confusing, and I should prefer to say that virtues
play a necessary part in the life of human beings as do stings in the life of bees. For of course
we cannot say that individual bees 'need to sting', as if they themselves would suffer if they did
not. Similarly, if we imagine a species of monkeys which groom each other but not themselves,
and which are not rewarded for their grooming, it would be confusing to say of them 'These
monkeys need to groom'. That way of putting it might give a picture of anxious little monkeys
restless until they could find some grooming to do!
Let us now turn from these remarks about the different forms that Aristotelian categoricals can
take in plants and animals and sum up what has emerged about the natural norms existing,
independently of human desires or interests, in this domain. We have seen that natural
goodness and defect in the domain of plants and animals depends essentially on the form of
life of the species to which an individual belongs. Pliability is good in a reed though a defect in
an oak. (When the wind blew hard, La Fontaine's boastful oak tree was put to shame by a
reed.) And an explorer would have been wrong if, meeting his first tortoise, he had marked it
down for lack of speed. A strength or a weakness in a living thing cannot be identified in the
same way as, say, hardness or softness in a rock. Goodness in plants and animals nests in an
interlocking set of general concepts such as species, life, death, reproduction, and nourishment,
36 As it may be the skilful archer who fails to hit a target in the presence of a freak gust of wind.
37 Geach, The Virtues, 17.
2 Natural Norms
together with less general—we might say local—ideas such as that of fruiting, eating, or fleeing.
Moreover, we notice that the use of such words in such contexts is literal here, but most often
fanciful or poetical when used outside the domain of living things. Nor did we need to draw
on descriptions of specifically human life as if the language had to be transferred from there to
be understood. Some intelligent Martians who themselves did not think in terms of goodness
and badness might (even if landing in the rain forest and knowing nothing of humans) realize
that the plants and animals on earth could be described in propositions with a special logical
form, and come themselves to talk about the newly met living things as we do. They would
rightly see the existence of this different order of things in the world as an extremely
interesting ontological fact, allowing them to invent and deploy a range of concepts that they
did not have before.
So far nothing has been said about primary goodness in human beings, and it is crucial to my
project that there should be no cheating—no smuggling in—but rather a fresh start, when we
try to see how goodness is determined for sight, locomotion, and so on in human beings, never
mind for such things as character, action, and will that belong exclusively to human life. But we
should notice that in the description of natural goodness in plant and animal life we have been
talking about normative judgements of goodness and defect that, even here, would naturally
be called 'evaluative'. If a philosopher says that 'normative' language is something different
from this kind of talk, he or she may be thinking that real norms are something 'endorsed',
though I hope that the arguments of the previous chapter may have done something to raise
doubts about whether we really know what this means. 38
In any case, the norms that we have been talking about so far have been explained in terms of
facts about things belonging to the natural world. We have not had to think that in evaluations
of non-human living things our use of 'good' has to be explained in terms of 'commendation' or
any other 'speech act', nor as the expression of any psychological state. The main thesis of this
book is that propositions about goodness and defect in a human being—even those that have to
do with goodness of character and action—are not to be understood in such psychological
terms. In describing my view, Thompson rightly said that I saw vice as a form of natural defect,
and I have therefore used a corresponding wording in the title of this book. 39
I should be the first, however, to admit that appearances are against my thesis. For how could
there be a human life form that played the same logical role in the determination of goodness
here as the equivalent in the case of plants and animals? There will surely be objection to the
idea that a natural form of life characteristic of humankind could determine what you or I ought
to do. What does it matter to me what species I belong to? Should we not protest on behalf of
individuality and creativity against bringing in the human species when asking what I
myself—this particular person—should do?
My final task will be to examine such protests on behalf of human freedom and individuality.
But next we must see how Thompson's schema might look if applied to human life.
38 Did the Brooklyn politician of Chapter 1 'endorse' the norm that he recognized when he said that what was really
difficult was to stand up day after day for what was wrong?
39 'The Representation of Life', 296.
Philippa Foot
In the previous chapter I described the evaluation of properties and operations of plants and of
animals considered in their own right, without reference to what we might desire of them or
the use they might be to members of other species of living things; so it was about what I call
'natural' excellence and defect. I wrote about goodness and badness, and therefore about
evaluation in its most general form; but we might equally have been thinking in terms of, say,
strength and weakness or health and disease, or again about an individual plant or animal
being or not being as it should be, or ought to be, in this respect or that.
Let us call the conceptual patterns found there, patterns of natural normativity. The next
question is whether the same structure of judgement is to be found as we move first from
plants and animals to human beings, and then from the evaluation of human characteristics
and operations in general to the special subject of goodness of the will.
The idea that any features and operations of humans could be evaluated in the same way as
those of plants and animals may provoke instant opposition. For to say that this is possible is to
imply that some at least of our judgements of goodness and badness in human beings are given
truth or falsity by the conditions of human life. And even if it is allowed that certain
evaluations of this kind are possible—those vaguely thought of perhaps as 'merely
biological'—there is bound to be scepticism about the possibility that 'moral evaluation' could
be like this. Surely, it will be urged, we must start afresh when thinking about the subject of
moral philosophy. I believe, however, that this is only partly true. Those who insist on the fresh
start probably think that it is true because the core meaning of a word such as 'good' when
used 'in moral judgement' must have to do with the expression of pro-attitudes or feelings, or
again, with the performance of 'speech acts' such as commendation or commitment. But that
way of trying to give an account of the meaning of 'good' in so-called 'moral contexts' was just
what was criticized in the opening chapter of this book. I wrote it because I knew that I needed
to attack that preconception in order to get so much as a hearing for the thought that there is no
change in the meaning of 'good' between the word as it appears in 'good roots' and as it appears in 'good
dispositions of the human will'.
For my own part I do not of course deny that between the evaluation of the roots of plants and
of the actions and desires of human beings there is a change of characteristic context and
purpose. We interest ourselves in the roots of plants at the garden centre, whereas interest in
the goodness of actions has rather to do with the choice of lives, the education of children, or
with decisions of social policy. But the belief that the word 'good' must mean something
different in the former and the latter is, I think, simply a prejudice coming from the type of
ethical theory that has dominated analytic philosophy in the past half-century.
Let us therefore keep an open mind about the way in which we may or may not need a fresh
start when broaching the subject of goodness and defect in the human will. Human beings can
be judged better or worse in many other ways as well, and we should now see whether natural
3 Transition to Human Beings
normativity is in general the order of the day, or whether we have to abandon the schema as
soon as we make the transition to the evaluation of rational beings such as ourselves.
After this transition, what differences and similarities do we find? With the change of subject
there will of course be a great increase in the number of respects in which evaluation is
possible, if only because human lives contain so many and such diverse activities: because
human beings do so many different kinds of things. This variety is not, however, in itself what
is most interesting from the philosopher's point of view, given that as philosophers we want to
understand the conceptual structure of evaluation rather than details of the buzz and bloom of
the animate world. So we shall want to discover not what goodness is in the case of, say, the
activity of house-building over against the building of nests, but rather what goodness in
performance of these and other activities may have to do with the manner of living and the
good of our own species.
The question is, therefore, whether characteristics of humans can be evaluated in relation to the
part they play in human life, according to the schema of natural normativity that we found in
the case of plants and animals. In favour of this there is the fact that a certain network of
interrelated concepts such as function and purpose is found where there is evaluation of all kinds
of living things, including human beings. It is possible, of course, that the meaning of words
such as 'function' or 'purpose' should diverge when used in speaking on the one hand of
characteristics and operations of plants and animals and on the other of those of human beings.
But it seems significant that there is a special form of explanation—teleological explanation—to
which the idea of function and purpose is related in each case.
If we ask either with regard to a plant or to an animal why it does a certain thing or has a
certain characteristic, we are satisfied with an answer that places this operation in the life of
that species. 40
Moreover, if we consider the concepts involved we should be surprised to be told that there is
no common meaning or shared logical structure between evaluations of botanical and
zoological subjects. The common structure of evaluation seems unaffected by the radical
difference between the two. Animals operate very differently from plants, because perception
plays a large part in the way that they gain nourishment, defend themselves, and reproduce.
Yet there is no reason offhand to suppose that the word 'function' has a different meaning in a
sentence about the function of the spreading of a peacock's tail and in one that speaks of the
opening of a flower in sunlight. There seems to be identity in the general structure of such
explanations throughout the sub-rational world, in spite of the differences appearing in a range
of subsidiary concepts. It is true, for example, that an answer to a 'Why?' question about an
animal may be in terms of appetite and therefore not just about what it needs but also about
what it wants: even about what it 'tries to do'. Since plants do not have desires or appetites, no
feature or operation in a plant can be explained by what it wants, and although we sometimes
say that a plant is 'trying to get to the light', this must be recognized as a fanciful use of the
40We are not then interpreting it as a historical question, as 'proper function' is interpreted, for instance, by Ruth
Millikan in Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories, chapter 1, and as 'function' would generally be
interpreted in evolutionary biology. As David Wiggins says in Postscript 4 in Needs, Values, Truth, 353, 'we really
need to describe what morality has become, a question on which evolutionary theory casts no particular light'.
Philippa Foot
words. Yet we find, as already suggested, the same structural terminology as of goodness or
defect relating to parts, characteristics, and operations, and also terms such as 'function' and
'purpose' and expressions such as 'in order to' or 'in order that' in things as different from each
other as plants and animals.
The question remains, however, as to whether once we have made the transition from sub-
rational to rational beings we may not need a new theory of evaluation. Surely, my critics will
say, it must be so, given the part that the life cycle of a plant or animal rightly played in
Michael Thompson's account of the conceptual structure within which the evaluation of
properties and operations of individual organisms had a place. For such an evaluation is based
on the general relation of this kind of feature to the pattern of life that is the good of creatures of
this species. But how could we possibly see human good in the same terms? The life cycle of a
plant or animal ultimately has to do with what is involved in development, self-sustenance,
and reproduction. Are we really going to suggest that human strengths and weaknesses, and
even virtues and vices, are to be identified by reference to such 'biological' cycles?
This challenge, ill-conceived as it is in suggesting that the natural-history account of human
beings could be explained in terms of a merely animal life, raises a most important and difficult
topic. For it is true that in the course of describing 'natural goodness' in plants and animals we
have implicitly adverted to the idea of the good of a living thing as well as its goodness in
various respects, and the two ideas, though related, are distinct. That this is so can be seen if we
think about what it means to benefit a plant or an animal. Very often, to be sure, a living thing
is benefited by itself being made better, and there must be a systematic connection between
natural goodness and benefit—whether reflexive or other-related as in the case of the stinging
bees. But it does not follow that benefit of either kind follows goodness whatever circumstance
an individual happens to be in. In our earlier example it was the swiftest deer, ahead of the
others, that fell into the hunter's trap; and the properly acting bee that stings a gardener may
well bring about the destruction of the nest.
Whether an individual plant or animal actually succeeds in living the life that it is its good to
live depends on chance as well as on its own qualities. But its own goodness or defect is
conceptually determined by the interaction of natural habitat and natural (species-general)
'strategies' for survival and reproduction. What conceptually determines goodness in a feature
or operation is the relation, for the species, of that feature or operation to survival and
reproduction, because it is in that that good lies in the botanical and zoological worlds. At that
point questions of 'How?' and 'Why?' and 'What for?' come to an end. But clearly this is not
true when we come to human beings.
Take reproduction, for instance. Lack of capacity to reproduce is a defect in a human being. But
choice of childlessness and even celibacy is not thereby shown to be defective choice, because
human good is not the same as plant or animal good. The bearing and rearing of children is not
an ultimate good in human life, because other elements of good such as the demands of work
to be done may give a man or woman reason to renounce family life. And the great (if often
troubling) good of having children has to do with the love and ambition of parents for
3 Transition to Human Beings
children, the special role of grandparents, and many other things that simply do not belong to
animal life.
Moreover, the good of survival itself is something more complex for human beings than for
animals; even for the animals closest to us. The human desire to live is, of course, instinctual,
but it often also has to do with a desperate hope that something may yet turn out well in the
future. And it seems that the preciousness of the unique memories that each person has is part
of what he or she may cling to even in the most terrible of circumstances. In other words, the
teleological story goes beyond a reference to survival itself.
The idea of human good is deeply problematic. One may be inclined to think of it as happiness,
but much would have to be said before that could be so understood as to be true, and I shall
discuss this in a later chapter. Here I want only to recall that Wittgenstein famously said on his
deathbed, 'Tell them I have had a wonderful life.' The example should teach us not to be too
ready to speak of every good life as 'a happy life': Wittgenstein surely did not have a happy
life, being too tormented and self-critical for that.
Thus the idea of a good life for a human being, and the question of its relation to happiness, is
each deeply problematic. And, moreover, there is so much diversity in human beings and
human cultures that the schema of natural normativity may seem to be inapplicable from the
start. Nevertheless, for all the diversities of human life, it is possible to give some quite general
account of human necessities, that is, of what is quite generally needed for human good, if only
by starting from the negative idea of human deprivation. For then we see at once that human
good depends on many characteristics and capacities that are not needed even by animals,
never mind by plants. There are, for instance, physical properties such as the kind of larynx
that allows of the myriad sounds that make up human language, as well as the kind of hearing
that can distinguish them. Moreover, human beings need the mental capacity for learning
language; they also need powers of imagination that allow them to understand stories, to join
in songs and dances—and to laugh at jokes. Without such things human beings may survive
and reproduce themselves, but they are deprived. And what could be more natural than to say
on this account that we have introduced the subject of possible human defects; calling them
'natural defects' as we used these terms in the discussion of plant and animal life?
We can see, moreover, that, as with animals, some defects have as we might say 'a reflexive
role', in that the deprivation comes primarily to the defective individual; but that there are
some that chiefly or at least most directly affect other people. We might think here, for instance,
of the failure of maternal affection, or of (non-iterated) 'prisoner's dilemma' cases where each
person gains from the action of others but loses through his own. 41
The way of solving the dilemma, however we should understand its details, depends on our
human way of thinking. We act within a language that allows us to say 'I owe it to him' or 'I
suppose I should play my part' (as we nowadays think, for instance, of taking a bus rather than
a car, to reduce traffic on the road, knowing that we ourselves may need to get somewhere
urgently by car some other time). There are also human enjoyments such as songs and
For discussions of the 'prisoner's dilemma' see Parfit, Reasons and Persons, chapter IV, and Gauthier, Morals by
41
Agreement, passim.
Philippa Foot
ceremonials that need cooperative participation. And, further, human societies depend on
especially talented individuals playing special roles in a society's life. As some species of
animals need a lookout, or as herds of elephants need an old she-elephant to lead them to a
watering hole, so human societies need leaders, explorers, and artists. Failure to perform a
special role can here be a defect in a man or woman who is not ready to contribute what he or
she alone—or best—can give. There is also something wrong with the rest of us if we do not
support those of genius, or even special talent, in their work.
In spite of the diversity of human goods—the elements that can make up good human lives—it
is therefore possible that the concept of a good human life plays the same part in determining
goodness of human characteristics and operations that the concept of flourishing plays in the
determination of goodness in plants and animals. So far the conceptual structure seems to be
intact. Nor is there any reason to think that it could not be in place even in the evaluations that
are nowadays spoken of as the special domain of morality. This special domain—and more
generally that of goodness of the will—will be discussed in detail in the next two chapters. But
if we ask whether Geach was right to say that human beings need virtues as bees need stings
(see Chapter 2), the answer is surely that he was. Men and women need to be industrious and
tenacious of purpose not only so as to be able to house, clothe, and feed themselves, but also to
pursue human ends having to do with love and friendship. They need the ability to form
family ties, friendships, and special relations with neighbours. They also need codes of
conduct. And how could they have all these things without virtues such as loyalty, fairness,
kindness, and in certain circumstances obedience?
Why then should there be surprise at the suggestion that the status of certain dispositions as
virtues should be determined by quite general facts about human beings? But let us see how in
a particular case this would work out. Let us take a longer look at Elizabeth Anscombe's paper
in which she describes how it might be shown that someone acted badly in breaking a promise
or other kind of contract. 42
In the essay 'On Promising and its Justice' to which I referred in Chapter 1 she remarks that
much human good hangs on the possibility of one person being able to bind another's will by
something in the nature of a promise or other contract. One can see that this is true. Any
exchange of goods or services above the most primitive level of direct simultaneous exchange
depends on the carrying out of tacit or explicit understandings of which keeping a promise is
one specific form. And it is easy to see how much good hangs on the trustworthiness involved
if one thinks, for instance, of the long dependency of the human young and what it means to
parents to be able to rely on a promise securing the future of their children in case of their
death. It would be different if human beings were different, and could bind the wills of others
through some kind of future-related mind-control device. But we have not got such powers,
any more than animals who depend on cooperative hunting have the power of catching their
prey as tigers do, by solitary stalk and pounce.
42 She was not, of course, suggesting that it is always wrong to break a promise, but saying why, when it is so, it is.
3 Transition to Human Beings
Anscombe believes that such considerations show that to break a promise is, in the absence of
special circumstances, to act badly. The demonstration depends on an identification of
elements of human good together with the story of what creatures of the human species can
and cannot do. We see here the interaction of what Anscombe calls 'Aristotelian necessities'
with Thompson's 'Aristotelian categoricals'. Aristotelian necessity is the necessity of that on
which good hangs, and Anscombe points out that it was in just this sense that wartime posters
challenged would-be travellers with the question 'Is your journey really necessary?' 44
In this same sense, she says, it is 'necessary' in many circumstances that human beings should
be able to bind each other's wills. But the demonstration also relies on considerations about
what human beings do, and do not, have in their repertoire that plays so large a part in
determining their natural-history story.
This was the method of derivation that Michael Thompson was using in discussing goodness
and defect in plants and animals, and he of course emphasizes his debt to Anscombe. Intending
to follow Thompson, I offer the following botanical example for comparison. We are, let us
suppose, evaluating the roots of a particular oak tree, saying perhaps that it has good roots
because they are as sturdy and deep as an oak's roots should be. Had its roots been spindly and
all near the surface they would have been bad roots; but as it is they are good. Oak trees need
to stay upright because, unlike creeping plants, they have no possibility of life on the ground,
and they are tall heavy trees. Therefore oaks need to have deep sturdy roots: there is something
wrong with them if they do not, and this is how the normative proposition can be derived. The
good of the oak is its individual and reproductive life cycle, and what is necessary for this is an
Aristotelian necessity in its case. Since it cannot bend like a reed in the wind, an oak that is as
an oak should be is one that has deep and sturdy roots.
Thus the structure of the derivation is the same whether we derive an evaluation of the roots of
a particular tree or the action of a particular human being. The meaning of the words 'good'
and 'bad' is not different when used of features of plants on the one hand and humans on the
other, but is rather the same as applied, in judgements of natural goodness and defect, in the
case of all living things.
43 Anscombe, 'On Promising and its Justice', in Collected Philosophical Papers, iii. 18.
44 Ibid. 15.
Philippa Foot
Something more needs, however, to be said about promise-keeping. For the derivation might
(plausibly though wrongly) be thought to be of a utilitarian tenor, and thus open to the
objection that in rare cases where it could be broken with the slightest risk of harm or
annoyance to anyone, a promise would be without moral force. It might of course be said that
as a recognized institution this would not be as useful as our own, and that one should
therefore be careful not to weaken confidence in what we have. Yet this seems not to be the
whole point, as the following real-life example shows.
[H]e had with him a native who had entered into his service on the express condition of
never being photographed. The natives, as everyone knows, consider that something is
taken out of them when their likeness is taken by photography. One day when the
native was fast asleep, Maklay, who was collecting anthropological materials, confessed
that he was awfully tempted to photograph his native, the more so as he was a typical
representative of his tribe and would never have known that he had been
photographed. But he remembered his agreement and refrained. 45
This example allows us to confront the problem of the wrongness of breaking a particular
promise, cut off from thoughts about the harm that might on a particular occasion result from
breaking it. Maklay would have been justified in thinking that it wouldn't do any harm if he took
the photograph. The promisee deeply wounded? The institution of promising weakened? Both
wildly unlikely here.
The servant was fast asleep and the picture would not even have been developed until Maklay
got back to Russia. No one need ever have known of the broken promise. Nevertheless Maklay
would surely have acted badly had he taken the photograph. We can of course think of
circumstances in which so much good hung on it that he would have been right to have done
so; but there is nothing of that in Kropotkin's report. So why should he have kept his promise?
How do good and bad come in here?
As a first attempt to answer this question one may remark that promises belong to the area of
trust and of respect for others. It would have been deeply disrespectful of Maklay to take
advantage of his servant, particularly as the latter saw it as so important not to be
photographed. 46
And disrespect and untrustworthiness are bad human dispositions. It matters in a human
community that people can trust each other, and matters even more that at some basic level
humans should have mutual respect. It matters, not just what people do, but what they are. 47
This should be said, but may seem merely to introduce a different form of utilitarian defence,
resting on the utility of dispositions. 48
And there is, in favour of such a theory, the difficulty in the idea that trustworthiness, never
mind respect, could be turned off and on, as it were.
What is more germane to the argument of the present book is to notice that utilitarianism never
gets off the ground in a schema such as we find in the work of Elizabeth Anscombe and Michael
Thompson. For utilitarianism, like any other form of consequentialism, has as its foundation a
proposition linking goodness of action in one way or another to the goodness of states of affairs. 49
And there is no room for such a foundational proposition in the theory of natural normativity. Where,
after all, could 'good states of affairs' be appealed to in judging the natural goodness or defect
in characteristics and operations of plants and animals? In evaluating the hunting skills of a
tiger do I start from the proposition that it is a better state of affairs if the tiger survives than if
it does not? What about pestilential creatures such as mosquitoes, to which the pattern of
natural normativity also applies?
It could be argued that this only shows that I am wrong in thinking that the evaluation of
human action has the same conceptual structure as the evaluation of operations in the sub-
rational living world. For surely human beings, who are capable of judging which states of
affairs are better and which worse, could never be right to choose to produce a worse state of
affairs when they could produce a better? Mustn't they always choose the better over the
worse? To this one should reply roundly that it is no doubt a truism that they should act as well
as they can. And there is also no doubt often a place for an enquiry, somewhere within
morality, for a question about which action will have the best consequences on the whole,
given, for example, that the end is to relieve suffering or to see that justice is done. Such uses of
propositions about good and worse states of affairs create no problems such as may have
seemed to arise about Maklay's promise, or again about the idea that certain actions, such as
torture, must always and everywhere be beyond the pale. It is only when we think of a
judgement about good states of affairs as consequentialists do—that is, see it as foundational—
that we go wrong. 50
47 It is one of the great advantages of the recently reawakened interest in the virtues that this subject comes to the
fore. A virtue is more than a settled disposition to act in a certain way. See 1 Corinthians 13 on charity. And for an
idea of the subtlety of this subject, see Macaulay's observation that Charles II was wrongly praised for his lack of
vanity: for, said Macaulay, the king was not 'above' vanity but rather 'below' it, indifferent to the opinion of his
fellow men because he saw each one as up for sale. Macaulay, History of England, i. 135.
48 Compare Robert Adams, 'Motive Utilitarianism'.
49 For this structure, see Amartya Sen, 'Utilitarianism and Welfarism', 464-5.
50 Thus, I am not wanting to run an everyday expression out of town: only to give it its proper place in the whole
of a conceptual scheme. As an architect must distinguish a pillar that merely holds up an internal arch from one
that is weight-bearing in relation to the building itself, so a philosopher must be careful not to exaggerate the
structural importance of some common form of words.
Philippa Foot
The idea of good and better states of affairs does not belong to the basic structure of the
evaluation of human action any more than to the evaluation of operations or other features of
other living things. If there are any who dispute this they might return to Chapter 2 or to the
example just given about goodness and defect in an oak. It would be ludicrous to suppose that
in that description, which drew on the idea of botanical flourishing, I committed myself to the
proposition that it was 'a good thing' if plants lived and 'a bad thing' if they died!
Nevertheless, we have not got to the bottom of the question of why Maklay was right to think
that he should indeed have kept his promise even in circumstances such as those in which he
found himself. It is not enough to say that natural goodness in humans requires dispositions
and attitudes as well as particular actions. Nor is it enough to deny that the idea of a global best
state of affairs plays any role in determining natural goodness as I understand it. For there are
human virtues especially needed in scholarly work, as for instance love of truth, and it is up to
a scholar to pursue the truth resourcefully and persistently. Isn't it therefore the case that
Maklay positively should have obtained this photographic record, which might have
contributed to anthropological knowledge and would by hypothesis have done no one any
harm? For a solution to this problem I suspect that we have to look to a part of Anscombe's
work on promising that I have not yet discussed: her work on what she has called 'stopping
modals'. 51
I myself can go no further than to point out that when Maklay said to himself that he should
not photograph his servant, his thought was dependent on a special kind of linguistic device
that humans have developed for themselves. Something of its special nature appears if one
contrasts keeping a promise with, say, doing what others expect one to do. It is often extremely
useful for people to be able to anticipate each other's behaviour, so one might say that 'good
hangs on it' and suppose that people should behave predictably. But of course this is true only
where harm of a certain seriousness is actually likely to ensue, as when, by dashing across the
road, a pedestrian makes an oncoming driver swerve. There is no basis for an objection to
behaving in an unpredictable way except in its possible consequences. This is not true,
however, of breaking a promise. In giving a promise one makes use of a special kind of tool
invented by humans for the better conduct of their lives, creating an obligation that (although
not absolute) contains in its nature an obligation that harmlessness does not annul.
In the preceding pages I have been applying an idea developed in previous chapters about the
evaluation of operations and characteristics of plants and animals to human beings, showing
something of how this would work out in terms of Elizabeth Anscombe's discussion of the
wrongness of promise-breaking, and then, supposing that her view might be mistaken for a
form of utilitarianism, explaining how radically a moral theory of natural normativity differs
from any form of consequentialism.
In the chapter as a whole I have been following up the thought that when we think about the
idea of an individual's good as opposed to its goodness, as we started to do in introducing the
concept of benefit, human good must indeed be recognized as different from good in the world
of plants or animals, where good consisted in success in the cycle of development, self-
maintenance, and reproduction. Human good is sui generis. Nevertheless, I maintain that a
common conceptual structure remains. For there is a 'natural-history story' about how human
Anscombe, 'Rules, Rights and Promises', in Collected Philosophical Papers, i. 100-2. See also 'On the Source of the
51
Authority of the State', Collected Philosophical Papers, iii. 138-9 and 142-5.
4 Practical Rationality
beings achieve this good as there is about how plants and animals achieve theirs. There are
truths such as 'Humans make clothes and build houses' that are to be compared with 'Birds
grow feathers and build nests'; but also propositions such as 'Humans establish rules of
conduct and recognize rights'. To determine what is goodness and what defect of character,
disposition, and choice, we must consider what human good is and how human beings live: in
other words, what kind of a living thing a human being is.
4 Practical Rationality
Philippa Foot
In the previous chapter I described what I believe to be the conceptual underpinnings of the
ascription of 'natural goodness', moving from plants and animals to human beings and
suggesting that the same normative pattern is found in our evaluations of all three kinds of
living things.
Now I come face to face with an apparently unanswerable objection, which is that human
beings as rational creatures can ask why what has so far been said should have any effect on
their conduct. For let us suppose that the normative pattern that I called 'natural normativity'
does govern our evaluations of human beings as human beings. Suppose that human beings
are defective as human beings unless they do what is needed for human good, including such
things as refraining from murder and keeping promises. The sceptic will surely ask 'But what if
I do not care about being a good human being?'
This is an objection to take seriously. For, after all, human beings are rational beings. It is part
of the sea change that came at the point of transition from plants and animals on one side to
human beings on the other that we can look critically at our own conduct and at the rules of
behaviour that we are taught. The strange possibility seems even to arise that human beings
could be as such defective in that they must sometimes either act badly, for example, in
breaking a promise, or else act irrationally in keeping it where there is no reason so to do. If
this were believed to be the case, our moral sceptic would probably point triumphantly to the
irrelevance of a demonstration that there was human defect in promise-breaking, murder, and
so on.
This is the difficulty with which the present chapter is concerned. I must, however, object to the
precise way in which it was formulated. For the question is not whether we have reason to aim
at being good human beings, but rather whether we have reason to aim at those things at
which a good human being must aim, as for instance good rather than harm to others, or
keeping faith. The problem is about the rationality of doing what virtue demands. And it has
seemed to some to be an especially difficult problem for anyone who has an objective theory of
moral evaluation as I do myself.
Gary Watson, a philosopher who is himself sympathetic to moral objectivism, posed this as a
difficulty for someone like myself in the form of two questions:
Philippa Foot
1. Can an objective theory really establish that being a gangster is incompatible with being a good
human being?
2. If it can, can it establish an intelligible connection between [this] appraisal and what we have
reason to do as individuals? 52
I accept the challenge of answering question 1 in the affirmative, having already suggested the
kind of ground on which a human being could be appraised as a bad—a defective—human
being if, being a gangster, he goes in for robbery and murder. I therefore answer 'Yes' to
question 1 and now move on to question 2.
First, however, I want to say more about the idea that human beings are rational creatures, in
being able to act on reasons, whereas even the higher animals, in many ways so like us, are
different in that they cannot act rationally or irrationally because they do not act on reasons as
we do.
It is easy to say this, but less easy to explain what we mean. The best way to understand it is, in
my view, to consider what Aquinas said on the subject. That rational choice is possible for
human beings is, of course, an ancient doctrine. Aristotle spends much time in expounding the
idea of choice 'on a rational principle' or logos. 53
And Aquinas, following Aristotle as he so often does, explains this by contrasting animals and
men. He says that animals, like small children, do not exercise choice (electio). What does he
mean by this? Do sheep not choose one patch of grass rather than another when they move to
graze in a particular part of a field? Aquinas considers this example, and allows that such
animal movements 'partake of choice' in so far as they show 'appetitive inclination' for one
thing rather than another. 54 He even stresses the fact that animals, having perception as plants
do not, may do what they do for an apprehended end (propter finem). Nevertheless he insists
that in doing something for an end animals cannot apprehend it as an end (non cognoscunt
rationem finis). A kind of knowledge is needed even for the 'participation in the voluntary' that
is possible for animals. However, Aquinas says, 'Perfect knowledge of the end consists in not
only apprehending the thing which is the end but also in knowing it under the aspect of end
and the relation of the means to that end' ('sed etiam cognoscitur ratio finis, et proportio ejus
quod ordinatur ad finem ipsum'). And similarly he denies that animals have knowledge of the
relation of means and ends as humans do. In a way they can be said to have this knowledge,
since they go for one thing to get another. But here, too, Aquinas says that they do not have the
kind of knowledge of the relation that human beings have. 55
There is surely something interesting and important here. But what exactly does Aquinas
mean? What does it mean to speak of not knowing an end as an end or a means as a means to that
52 Watson, ‘On the Primacy of Character’, 67. He says in his footnote 25 that by ‘an objective theory’ he means one
such as my own.
53 See Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, Book III, chapters 2-3, 1111b4-1113a14, and Book VI passim.
54 Aquinas, Summa Theologica, First Part of the Second Part, Question XIII, article 2.
end? It is not, after all, that human beings see something that is their quarry as glowing in a
special way, or with 'E' for End over it like the Hollywood sign; as if animals just saw some
food and moved to eat it whereas an extra property was visible to the human eye. We may be
inclined to think that what is 'extra' over and above the apprehending that we share with
animals must be something 'mental', something 'in the mind' that accompanies every act or
pursuit. But of course the idea of such an accompaniment is simply an invention of just the
kind that Wittgenstein so often exposes in his writings on the mind. 56
If 'seeing an end as an end' belongs to the mind, it is not in that way that it does. We must not
hope to find something extra—our awareness of the ratio, of an end, or of the relationship of
means and end—by Lockean introspection. 57
We must rather ask, as Wittgenstein teaches us, for the wider context in which the puzzling
idea belongs. Here, as elsewhere, 'the inner' stands in need of public criteria, and we should ask
about the surroundings in which human awareness of ends as ends could be found, looking of
course at speech as well as action.
Activities are important and will play their part in allowing us to say, of a growing child, for
instance, that he or she now has the idea of having a purpose and of finding something else by
which it may be fulfilled. But speech is crucial here in marking the difference between animals
and humans. We know what an animal is going after only by what it does, whereas a growing
child will be able to tell us. Moreover, the child learns a language that includes linguistic forms
that have no counterpart even in the most intricate 'language of the beasts'. A child gradually
comes to use words not only to get what it wants but also to speak about what it is going to do;
and comes to understand and use the locutions by which choices are debated and actions
explained, justified, and recommended. It is the use of such parts of our language, appearing
for the most part in regular ways in the web of actions, that allows us to say, without appealing
to a hidden mental 'realm', that ends and means may be 'in our minds'. It makes sense to ask
what someone thought about the pros and cons of a particular choice because we can ask him
and be given an answer. And he himself can go through arguments that have as a conclusion
'so that is what I shall do'. When we say that human beings are able to choose on a rational
ground as no animal can, it is because human action belongs in such surroundings, and so,
ultimately, because humans use language not matched by anything in animal life. 58
Thus what Aquinas says about animals and small children being able to have ends but not to
see them as ends seems comprehensible and acceptable. And the same point could be made in
terms of what is seen as good. For it can be said that while animals go for the good (thing) that
they see, human beings go for what they see as good: food, for example, being the good thing that
animals see and go for and that human beings are able to see as good. It is for this reason that
56 See Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, e.g. sections 157-9, 165, 171, 305-8, 444.
57 See Locke, An Essay concerning Human Understanding, Book II, chapter ix.
58 Human beings can be described as trying to achieve objectives that are remote from what they are presently
doing because they can be said to 'have such and such in mind'. All that is necessary for this is an ability to tell of
such an objective. The objective is what they have in mind, though it is not something that need be occupying space
in the mind like obsessive thoughts or the thinking out of a plan. Since telling is not something that animals can
do, only what is immediately related to what they are doing can be their objective in the sense of what they are
trying to get or to do.
Philippa Foot
while no animal can be said to 'know the better and choose the worse', it makes sense to
describe a human being as doing this. We can, to be sure, mark hesitation in an animal that is,
for instance, torn between hunger and fear; but nothing in an animal's behaviour could lead us
to say that it saw that one alternative was better than another but that its action did not match
its thought! The problem of akrasia (incontinence, or so-called weakness of will) concerns a
description applying only to rational beings such as us.
Let us start, therefore, with the fact that there is this great difference between human beings
and even the most intelligent of animals. Human beings not only have the power to reason
about all sorts of things in a speculative way, but also the power to see grounds for acting in one
way rather than another; and if told that they should do one thing rather than another, they can
ask why they should. Quite early on, a child learns that a 'should' needs a ground, unlike an
order, which may simply be reiterated or backed up by a threat. 59
It is, I think, the fact that a man or a woman can question what reason he or she has for doing
something that makes the comparison between the 'natural' or 'autonomous' evaluation of
plants or animals and the same evaluation of human beings qua human beings seem at first
sight so unsuitable. A human being as a rational animal will ask 'Why should I do that?',
particularly if told that he should do something distasteful that seems to be for the advantage
of others rather than himself. And a philosopher, even if in propria persona a respectable person
inclined to keep his promises and pay his debts, is honour bound to carry such questioning to
the limit. Must he or she not either deny that natural goodness in a human being is like that
same goodness in a bee or a wolf in the way I have suggested that it is, or else dismiss the fact
as of no practical importance, asking to be given reason to do what a good human being does?
It is for the sake of meeting this challenge that I shall embark, in the present chapter, on a
discussion of practical rationality; asking about the nature and provenance of reasons for
acting.
We shall need first of all to sort out some of the rather complex conceptual connections
between statements about what an agent should do and what there is reason for him to do. So
we need to separate different types of proposition in which practical 'shoulds' and reason-
statements appear, and can draw here on a distinction that Donald Davidson has made familiar
to us: between
1. What N should do relative to a certain consideration
and
2. What N should do ‘all things considered’ (‘a.t.c.’). 60
Here, given that he cannot both nurse his cold and rescue his finances, we have him saying to
himself 'I should go out' and also 'I should not go out'. 61
But there is, as Davidson points out, no contradiction, given that the two 'shoulds' are relative
to different considerations. He has reason to go out and reason not to go out. Neither (1) nor (2)
gives a final or verdictive 'should'-statement about what it is rational to do. It may be that there
are stronger reasons for, for example, staying in than going out. Or one may have simply to
plump for one or the other.
Where there is something that a.t.c. one should do we may say that one of the original 'should'
statements—the one that recommended the less good alternative—is, relative to the a.t.c.
judgement, 'a prima facie "should" '. But I do not like this terminology for the following reason.
Every 'should'-statement that gives even a reason for φ-ing must itself be based on a certain
consideration (or considerations) that can be quoted in answer to the question 'Why do you
think that that is a reason for φ-ing?' (After all, we do not just conjure even relative 'shoulds'
out of the air, and shouldn't be allowed to get away with a claim to 'just see' that a reason
exists.) My immediate point is that these considerations (call them reason-giving
considerations) may themselves only defeasibly give any reason for acting. Take, for instance,
the consideration that a certain man is my father, as it might stand as evidence for the
proposition that there is reason for me to look after him in old age. No doubt the fact of being
someone's offspring is usually reason-giving, and in families there are often anguished
deliberations about what, in view of this relative 'should', ought a.t.c. to be done. But now
suppose that this man is my father only by virtue of having raped my mother and that he later
offered her no support. It would seem a bit thick that he should say that I had any reason to
help him. The fact that he was my father was a prima-facie ground for saying that I had such a
reason, but in view of all the circumstances there was actually no 'should' at all; nothing that
had even to be taken into account in deliberating what to do.
I prefer, therefore, to keep the description 'prima facie "should" ' for this case, and shall refer to
the 'shoulds' in my original example concerning the nursing of a cold and the avoiding of an
overdraft as relative 'shoulds'. There is also, however, to be considered the judgement that 'All
things considered, N should φ'. For suppose we add to the previous example the fact that N
finds he has a temperature of 103 degrees. Undoubtedly he has flu and if he struggles out he
risks serious illness. In such a situation the only rational thing for him to do is to stay in. It is
just too bad that inconveniences will follow from the fact that his account at the bank will be
overdrawn. He should stay in. It is the rational thing to do. He may of course say that it is bad
that he is going to be overdrawn, but this only means that it is unfortunate: something to be
deplored. If he stays in, he acts as he should (final 'should') have acted, which implies that he
did not act badly in so doing. He would rather have acted badly—imprudently—had he gone
out in the circumstances as now described, though we can add other elements that would have
61 He will also have to take into account any other reasons for doing one action rather than another, since other
considerations will usually have come in if only to the ruling out of other alternatives, as for instance that he
should telephone a neighbour (whom he hardly knows) and ask him to collect the cheque and take it to the bank.
It is seldom that there would not be a way of nursing the cold and avoiding being overdrawn whatever was against
using that method, and when I said that he could not both nurse the cold and avoid being overdrawn, I meant that
there were no eligible means.
Philippa Foot
made it the right thing to do, for instance by supposing that the prevention of an accident hung
on his rising from his bed. In the absence of a new condition such as this, we had in our
example an overriding or final 'should'.
Let us now see what this implies. It implies that there was reason for the agent to do the action
named in the 'should'-proposition; but that was implied by relative 'shoulds' as well. (He had
reason to go to the bank as well as reason to stay in bed.) The special characteristic of an a.t.c.
or final 'should' is its conceptual connection with practical rationality, as was suggested above
when we said that with a temperature of 103 degrees, the only rational thing to do was to stay
in. This has important consequences. For the actions of anyone who does not φ when φ-ing is
the only rational thing to do are ipso facto defective. It does not matter whether we say that he
acts irrationally, or rather say 'acts in a way that is contrary to practical rationality'. In either
case it is implied that he does not act well.
It is this 'should' that we must be concerned with when we set out to answer Gary Watson's
challenge, because his question—put in terms of showing a reason for acting—was, of course,
about practical rationality. At this point I want, therefore, to go back to consider an old article
of mine that has (rightly) come in for plenty of adverse criticism. In that article, 'Morality as a
System of Hypothetical Imperatives', I pointed out that the question of the rationality of moral
action was not settled by showing that a moral judgement was like a Kantian categorical
imperative in that its truth did not depend on an agent's desires or interests. For this same
independence belongs to a whole range of propositions that are never thought to have that
status, such as, for instance, those detailing the rules of a club. If someone is a member of a club
he can be told that he should not do this, that, or the other, and he cannot deny it on the
ground that this is nothing to him. The unchangeable truth of what is said does not, however,
show that there is any reason for the agent to act as the rules prescribe. In The Brothers
Karamazov, Dostoevesky has Father Zosima telling how as a young man he had abandoned a
duel with an apology. When his second cried out that it was against the rules to apologize in
the middle of a duel, he replied:
'Gentleman, is it really so extraordinary in these days to meet a man who will
acknowledge his own stupidity and apologise in public for the wrong he has done?'
'But not in a duel,' shouted my second again. 62
My point in bringing forward such examples was, of course, to insist that the rationality of
moral action was not in any way to be bolstered up by the fact that the 'shoulds' they contained
were independent of an agent's interests or desires. And (intransigently) I suggested that until
the matter was otherwise demonstrated, we should say that only interests or desires could give
practical rationality to moral action.
I now wonder why, given the obvious indigestibility of the idea that morality is indeed a
system of hypothetical imperatives, I should have accepted it even for a short while. What
seemed to force it on me was the sheer difficulty of showing a practical rationality that was
62 John Jones gave me this example. I particularly like, and have used, his translation, from his Dostoevsky, 330.
4 Practical Rationality
independent of desire or interest. But why, we may ask, did these particular demonstrations, or
some clever adaptation of them, seem the only possible ones to be considered by those of us
who were not to be satisfied by any Kantian alternative? Why did desire and interest continue
to hover as candidates? I think that their seductiveness depends for most people on a
combination of two factors.
Firstly, each can be a genuine reason-giving factor. A desire to see the Taj Mahal can in the right
circumstances make it rational to plan a trip to India and visit a travel agent; and similarly the
knowledge that cigarettes are carcinogenic can rationalize giving up smoking by showing that
it is in one's interest to do so. 63
Secondly, to many philosophers each is apt to seem to have a special, perhaps unique, power to
explain human action. That this is the case seems, and always seemed, to me to be merely an
illusion rife among philosophers. For after all an action can be explained by all sorts of causes,
as for instance (a) habit, (b) a tendency to mimic the actions of others, (c) something significant
about the occasion on which one first did what one is now going to do, (d) the fact that it is
substitutionally representing some other action, or (e) even something as far out as post-
hypnotic suggestion. What tells us that conscience cannot explain action? Someone may give as
the explanation of his action a thought about right and wrong, and it may be a true
explanation, as Kropotkin clearly supposed in his story of Maklay's decision not to photograph
his sleeping servant (see Chapter 3 above). So offhand we have no reason to suppose that
acting as conscience demands has to be brought into a special mould, as of a belief and a
'conative state', before we can see it as a genuine explanation of what someone does. If we like,
we can say that someone whose action is explained in this way is 'wanting to do what is right';
but now we are simply expressing the agent's intention in terms of wanting, not showing the
explanation as fitting a favoured mould.
The problem is not, then, to show that a belief about right and wrong can explain an action, but
that a belief of such a kind can give the agent reason to do or not to do it. 64
Can it be the case that someone who does what is wrong thereby acts in a way that is contrary to
reason? May we add considerations that are about right and wrong to the list of rationalizing
considerations given above? I suggested in Chapter 1 that we can indeed do so, because one
who acts badly ipso facto acts in a way that is contrary to practical reason. This was the view
that Warren Quinn suggested, and I now want to argue for it and consider its consequences.
In his article 'Rationality and the Human Good', Quinn attacked a view of practical rationality
that he called 'neo-Humean' and defined as 'one that makes the goal of practical reason the
maximal satisfaction of an agent's desires and preferences, suitably corrected for the effects of
misinformation, wishful thinking, and the like.' 65
63 That prudence on its own can motivate seems to me to have been demonstrated by Thomas Nagel many years
ago, in The Possibility of Altruism, chapters V and VI. If philosophers still insist that only the presence of what they
call a 'conative state' can explain an action, they are, to my mind, ignoring his lesson.
64 Christine Korsgaard brilliantly demonstrated this in her classic article 'Scepticism about Practical Reason'. She
and I agree in our opposition to internalist theories of motivation, but differ radically in our accounts of the
foundations of morality.
65 'Rationality and the Human Good', in Morality and Action, 210.
Philippa Foot
He pointed out that by this account, practical reason, which would concern only the relation of
means to ends, would therefore be indifferent to nastiness or even disgracefulness in an agent's
purposes. And Quinn asked, in the crucial sentence of the article, what then would be so important
about practical rationality? In effect he is pointing to our taken-for-granted, barely noticed
assumption that practical rationality has the status of a kind of master virtue, in order to show
that we cannot in consistency with ourselves think that the Humean account of it is true. Seeing
this as a move of great originality and extreme importance, I asked myself why, if there were
indeed this conceptual restraint on practical rationality, it should be supposed that there is an
independent concept of it with which the requirements of moral goodness must somehow be
shown to be consonant. 66 I see Quinn as watching us all struggling to tie a horse to the back of a
cart, and suggesting ‘Try it the other way round’.
This now seems to me to be the correct way of meeting the challenge that I myself issued in
'Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives' and at that time despaired of meeting:
namely, to show the rationality of acting, even against desire and self-interest, on a demand of
morality. The argument depends on the change of direction that Quinn suggested: seeing
goodness as setting a necessary condition of practical rationality and therefore as at least a part-
determinant of the thing itself. 67
Nor is this a quite unfamiliar way of arguing. Many of us are willing to reject a 'present desire'
theory of reasons for action because we think that someone who knowingly puts his future
health at risk for a trivial pleasure is behaving foolishly, and therefore not well. Seeing his will
as defective, we therefore say that he is doing what he has reason not to do. Being unable to fit
the supposed 'reason' into some preconceived present-desire-based theory of reasons for
action, we do not query whether it really is a foolish way to behave, but rather hang on to the
evaluation and shape our theory of reasons accordingly. And it is exactly a generalization of
this presumption about the direction of the argument on which I am now insisting. For what,
we may ask, is so special about prudence that it alone among the virtues should be reasonably
thought to relate to practical rationality in such a way?
With all this in mind I shall now return to Gary Watson's challenge to those who hold objective
theories of moral judgement such as my own. It will be useful to begin by speaking about
reason in general under the following headings:
(A) Reasons for acting, which we may call practical reasons.
(B) Reasons for believing, which we may call evidential or demonstrative reasons.
As philosophers, and therefore theoreticians, our job is of course to give the second type of
reason, arguing for or against the truth of a variety of propositions that seem to involve special
66
Later in this article Quinn gives an explicitly Aristotelian account of human good.
I see Quinn as watching us all struggling to tie a horse to the back of a cart, and suggesting 'Try it the other way
round'.
67 The mathematical coherence of choices, and that they be as informed as they should, could also be requirements
of practical rationality.
4 Practical Rationality
problems—like those, for instance, about personal identity or the existence of an external
world. But among these many 'philosophical' subjects we find that of the nature of practical
reasons, and in this special case we shall have to give reasons of type B for theses about reasons
of type A. (This is what has been going on in the present chapter, as it was in Quinn's article.)
When Gary Watson issued the challenge described on p. 53 above, he was asking a question
that belongs here, since he was wanting to know whether on an objective theory of moral
goodness an 'intrinsic link' could be established between moral goodness and reasons for action.
My argument in the last few pages has been designed to show that there is such a link.
Earlier in the book, in Chapters 1-3, I gave reasons for believing propositions about natural
goodness and badness in various plants, animals, and human beings; for instance, for believing
that an individual oak tree with superficial, spindly roots was to be evaluated as defective, and,
passing to human beings, gave reasons of the same form for the assertion that Maklay would
have acted badly had he photographed his sleeping servant. In the latter case the immediate
reason was that he had promised not to do so, and I drew on Anscombe's arguments for the
assertion that, absent extenuating circumstances, to break a promise was as such to act badly.
Finally, supposing that doubts might be raised about the relevance of such considerations to
moral philosophy, I argued for the extension of the concept of natural normativity to human
beings, even to the moral evaluation of human action and will, and so argued for what Watson
regarded as an objective theory of moral judgement. In the previous pages I have turned to the
problem of practical reasons, and have gone on to answer 'Yes' to his question 2.
Returning now to the beginning of the present chapter, to the sceptic who was supposed to
have asked why he should do that which the good person must do, I would point out that
there are two ways of understanding this question. If we understand the words 'that which a
good person must do' 'transparently' (extensionally) as referring to, for example, keeping
promises or refraining from murder, then our answer must consist in showing him why in
doing these things he would act badly, and we are still in Chapters 1-3. But if his words are
understood opaquely (intensionally) as referring to bad actions under that description, we must
try to show him the conceptual connection between acting well and acting rationally; so that if
he is to challenge us further, this is where the challenge must come. If the sceptic does not
succeed in refuting us here, but still goes on saying that he has not been shown that there is
reason for acting as a good person would act, it is no longer clear what he is asking for. To ask
for a reason for acting rationally is to ask for a reason where reasons must a priori have come to
an end. And if he goes on saying 'But why should I?', we may query the meaning of this
'should'.
No doubt what our sceptic (especially if he be a gangster) really means to insist is that we have
not been able, in anything we have said, to touch his desires; and if he is a dangerous person
that may be what we shall most care about. But the fact that we might hunt around for
something that has a chance of affecting his actions should not be taken as giving any support
to a philosophy that takes practical reasons to encompass only reasons of that kind.
5 Human Goodness
Philippa Foot
In earlier chapters I described a logical structure that belongs to the evaluation of all living
things 'in their own right', or 'autonomously'; that is, where 'natural' goodness or defect is in
view. I said something about differences as well as similarities in the evaluation of plants,
animals, and human beings. But now, as we move in towards the subject of 'moral goodness',
new specialities appear, and we see that we have a way of speaking of goodness in human
beings not corresponding to anything in the other cases. I am thinking now of the thoughts
expressed by sentences in which the word 'good' is joined to the name of the species itself, as
when we speak of 'a good human being' or, more colloquially, 'a good person'. There is no
equivalent to this in the language in which we evaluate plants and animals. Firstly, in so far as
we do speak of 'a good S' in these other cases (where, incidentally, we tend rather to say 'a
healthy S' or 'a good specimen of an S'), we are thinking about the plant or the animal as a
whole; whereas to call someone a good human being is to evaluate him or her only in a certain
respect. And as suggested in the previous chapter, this particular evaluation can only be of
human beings. For to speak of a good person is to speak of an individual not in respect of his
body, or of faculties such as sight and memory, but as concerns his rational will. 1
In the present chapter I want to consider this particular case of evaluation in more detail, and it
may seem that I have now reached the subject of 'moral evaluation'. But I want to show that the
judgements usually considered to be the special subject of moral philosophy should really be
seen as belonging to a wider class of evaluations of conduct with which they share a common
conceptual structure. It is worth remarking that in considering reasons for action in the earlier
chapters we seemed to move quite naturally between the example of someone kept in bed by
flu and that of the explorer Maklay bound by his promise to his servant. Various observations
were made about the relation between the concepts of goodness and reasons with no distinction
of 'non-moral' and 'moral' examples. Was this a mistake? I shall try to show that it was not.
My own view is that it is right to see moral judgements as belonging with other evaluations
that may perhaps appear not weighty enough to merit such proximity. Thinking about reasons
for action, we saw that there is a use of the word 'should' (a practical 'should') that implies a
reason, and even an 'a.t.c.' reason for action. 2
The use of 'should' in such practical contexts tells us of a possible defect in action, but does not
itself tell us whether or not anything of importance is involved. Anscombe shows in other
places that she regards lying as often a very serious transgression, but this could not be said of
other items in her list. A 'should not' or 'should' may mark something very important, but often
an action that it would be merely silly to do or not to do.
How is it then that moral evaluation seems to most philosophers nowadays to be a very special
subject, that may have to be understood in terms of the expression of special mental states such
as approval, or mental acts such as endorsing? This must have something to do with the fact
that these philosophers are focusing on evaluations which are often used in a special context, as
when members of society are expressing disapproval of something others have done, and
especially where the public good or the rights of a third party are involved. Use in such
contexts should not, however, be taken to imply a special logical grammar. Whether or not
there is one is the subject next to be explored.
Many if not most moral philosophers in modern times see their subject as having to do
exclusively with relations between individuals or between an individual and society, and so
with such things as obligations, duties, and charitable acts. It is for this reason that, of the four
ancient cardinal virtues of justice, courage, temperance, and wisdom, only the first now seems
to belong wholly to 'morality'. The other three virtues are recognized as necessary for the
practice of 'morality' but are now thought of as having part of their exercise 'outside morality'
in 'self-regarding' pursuits, 'moral' and 'prudential' considerations being contrasted in a way
that was alien to Plato or Aristotle. 4 J. S. Mill, for instance, expresses this modern point of view
quite explicitly, saying in his essay On Liberty that 'A person who shows rashness, obstinacy,
self-conceit . . . who cannot restrain himself from harmful indulgences' shows faults (Mill calls
them 'self-regarding faults') which 'are not properly immoralities' and while they 'may be
proofs of any amount of folly . . . are only a subject of moral reprobation when they involve a
breach of duty to others, for whose sake the individual is bound to have care for himself'. 5
There is of course nothing wrong with using the word 'moral' as Mill does. It fits in with much
of our everyday usage, and I do not want to involve myself in a discussion of the variations in
usage found even today. 6
What concerns me is not the exact meaning of 'moral' when used as Mill used it but rather the
substance, if there is any substance, of a distinction between 'moral' evaluation and the other
evaluations of which he wrote in the passage just quoted.
Perhaps it will seem strange even to raise the question of substance, because there is after all a
special lexicon for Mill's 'sphere of morality'. Words such as 'wicked' and 'evil' are applied to a
deed such as murder but not to even the greatest act of self-destructive folly as such. Even to
4 Gavin Lawrence is a notable exception to the generalization I have just made. See Lawrence, 'The Rationality of
Morality', 106.
5 Mill, On Liberty, chapter IV, 134-5.
6 I would remark, however, that Isaiah Berlin spoke in a lecture of the 'moral impact' of the Busch Quartet's
call an action 'wrong' outside some technical context is to imply that it is unjust, or perhaps
uncharitable; that it has to do with conduct whose defect lies in what is done against other
individuals or against the public good. Indeed, parts of this special 'moral' vocabulary serve the
purpose of picking out special relationships in which individuals stand to other individuals or
to society, as, for example, that of having rights, obligations, or duties. And some of these
words such as 'wicked' and 'evil' also mark the seriousness of the subject, and the extreme
reactions evoked by horrifying and revolting actions of murderers, child abusers, or torturers.
The social and emotional surroundings of our use of the vocabulary of moral censure are very
different from those settings in which we speak of rashness, obstinacy, imprudence, and folly.
But I shall argue that there are features common to all these evaluations that may be labelled
'evaluations of the rational human will'.
What, then, are the features that such evaluations share? In the first place, they all have as their
subject not physical or mental abilities, but voluntary action and purpose. This is something
that is generally recognized where 'moral' evaluation is concerned. For it is obvious that not
everything that humans do counts for or against moral goodness. No one is called a murderer
because in slipping and falling on a mountainside he has killed someone. What is done
involuntarily does not feature, and force, too, can take away voluntariness of movement, as in
one who is blown along by the wind or carried away by strong men. 7
Moreover, we must surely count not perhaps as involuntary but as less than voluntary what is
done under torture that no one could be expected to withstand.
A more difficult part of this subject opens up, however, when acting with knowledge is added
to the conditions of an action's voluntariness. 8
Some examples of excuse in this area are evident enough.
For a doctor might kill a patient she was treating in emergency conditions (as, for instance,
when the victim was trapped halfway up a cliff), but do this only through ignorance of the
patient's allergy to a standard drug. This doctor might say that sadly she had done the wrong
thing; but she had perhaps acted heroically in climbing up to give help. Here we must agree
with Kant that the unfortunate outcome is irrelevant to goodness of the will, and blame 'step-
motherly Nature' instead. 9
The action of the doctor in this example, though it was intentional under the description 'giving
treatment', was of course not intentional under the description 'killing'—under which it could
otherwise have been an immediate subject of adverse moral judgement. The example was,
however, carefully chosen. For not every case of acting in ignorance is excusable in this way.
Our doctor acted in an emergency, so that discovery of the allergy was ruled out. And it was
implied that she gave the standard treatment, as any conscientious medic would have done.
This last remark points to the fact that lack of knowledge of what one is doing, though it 'takes
away something of voluntariness', does not always excuse. For ignorance itself may be
voluntary, as when, in present-day Britain, an arms dealer takes care not to enquire whether
the weapons that he is shipping to one country will not be shipped on to a repressive regime.
Or if he 'enquires', his conclusion may be guided by self-interest rather than by the evidence at
hand: he holds a convenient opinion that does not absolve him, because it is not held, as we
say, in good faith. 10
Furthermore, an agent's ignorance may be imputed to his will if, through negligence, he has
not taken the trouble to find out facts that he could, and should, have known. This is a
particularly interesting case, as well as one that is of everyday practical importance. There may
be no moment at which this person decided not to discover the facts, or made it impossible to
do so. The fault may be one of pure omission; but omission in action is a common fault, and
omitting to find out what one could and should have found out is only a special case of this.
The omission may be culpable on account of some special position of responsibility held by the
agent, but the practical importance of the subject of culpable ignorance does not come only
from special positions of responsibility. For are there not things that most adults in countries
such as Britain not only could but should know? I am thinking, for instance, of the basic
principles of first aid, and procedures such as cardiac pulmonary resuscitation. To say this may
seem to be going too far, given that no one can be expected to know everything that he or she
might need to know in order to save a life. But such examples give a clue to the criteria by
which it can be judged that most of us here not only can but also should learn about first aid.
That there must be a 'should' as well as a 'could' for culpable ignorance is seen by contrasting
this example with one that I remember Elizabeth Anscombe giving to illustrate the point.
Suppose, she said, that an infant had been left on the doorstep of her house and had perished
during the night because she had not known that it was there. It is not that she could not have
known, because had it been her practice to check her doorstep every hour upon the hour
through every night this child would have been saved. But of course it cannot be said that she
should have done this. Nor is it difficult to see the factors that distinguish this example from
that of failure to learn elementary first aid. In both cases, as it happens, the evil that could come
about through ignorance is very great, and this is relevant. On the other hand, the likelihood of
such knowledge being needed is very different, and so too is the cost to the agent of getting it. 11
With these observations we have been tracing logical limits to evaluations whose subject is
goodness and defect of human action considered as such. The discussion may have seemed to
have to do in particular with what is nowadays called 'moral judgement' and was explicitly
distinguished as such by Mill. Yet 'self-regarding' failings come under the heading of lack of
wisdom, and the corresponding descriptions are conceptually constrained by conditions of
voluntariness, as are 'moral' descriptions such as 'wicked'. No one is said to do something
foolish when what he does is involuntary, as, for instance, if he falls into the sea when hit by a
10 Many of the beliefs of slave owners, and of white people under South Africa's apartheid regime, must have been
of this kind.
11 The case of acting in ignorance through failure to find out what one could and should have found out is
particularly interesting from the point of view of philosophy of mind. For this voluntariness is attributed to the
action on account of what should have been known, and so to the agent's will in a way that depends on evaluation
itself. The idea that voluntariness is discovered by a causal investigation of the operation of a faculty is hereby
shown as a mistake.
Philippa Foot
giant wave. And here, too, ignorance may absolve, as it absolves of imprudence those who took
up smoking in the years before the link between smoking and cancer was known. But, as
before, ignorance has this logical force only when it was itself not ignorance of what the agent
could and should have known. An illiterate in our society who could learn to read, but does
not take the trouble to do so, shows lack of wisdom. And wisdom is a telling concept from just
this point of view because it itself implies no more knowledge and understanding than anyone
of normal capacity can and should acquire in the course of an ordinary life.
A special connection with the voluntary is, then, the first of the conceptual marks of the special
evaluations, picked out from others (such as speech defects) which have to do with goodnesses
and defects in human beings but are not of the kind that I have indicated by saying that they
are about goodness and defect of the rational will. And my present point is that their subject
matter is more extensive than that picked out by Mill when he spoke of 'morality'. So there is
this first reason for treating the subject of the virtues as a whole, as the ancients did.
There is, moreover, a second important feature of Mill's 'moral' evaluations that can be shown
to belong to this wider class. It can be summarily described by saying that goodness or badness
can come from different formal features of a single action, which may be distinguished as
follows.
Firstly, goodness can come from the nature of the action itself—from what it is that is done. So,
in general, an act of saving life is good in this respect, while an act of killing is bad. 12
Secondly, the end for which an action is done is an independent source of goodness or badness
in it. A good (even obligatory) action may be bad in that it is done for a bad end, as a
blackmailer may save the life of his victim in order to continue his extortion. Or, again, a bad
action may be done for a good end but one that does not justify it; as when an executor
destroys a will in order to see that money goes to a poor person rather than a rich legatee.
Contrast an end that does justify, like the need to destroy someone's property to stop the
spread of a fire.
A third source of goodness or badness in an action lies in its relation to the agent's judgement
of whether he or she is acting badly or well. Here, too, goodness or badness may be combined
with either goodness or badness in either act or end. It is often supposed that the fact that
someone is doing what he thinks right is a circumstance that annuls actual badness of act or
purpose; but Aquinas (whose discussion of this topic is a wonderful piece of moral philosophy)
insists that erring conscience does not excuse. 13 What Aquinas says is illustrated by a sad story
of the fate of a Jewish child sent to a family in Norway in hope of safety when Prague was
overrun by the Nazis. She died in Auschwitz because, after the invasion of Norway, the
12 I am in general following Aquinas in making these distinctions; but what he says about species and
circumstances of an action is complex, and I am not trying exactly to represent his view about this. It is natural to
say that circumstances often affect the goodness or badness of an action, as the circumstance that the subject has
been convicted of a crime by due process of law changes what is done in depriving him or her of liberty. And an
end can also operate in this way as a circumstance, though this is not, of course, to say that even a good end will
always do so. See the discussion of 'absolutism' on pp. 77-80, 114-115.
13 See Aquinas, Summa Theologica, First Part of the Second Part, Question XIX, articles 5 and 6.
5 Human Goodness
Norwegian family who loved the child thought that it was their duty to hand her over to the
Gestapo when ordered to do so. They believed, no doubt through some sympathy with the
Nazis, that this was 'the right thing to do'. The erring conscience, or as Aquinas always says,
'reason or conscience' (ratio vel conscientia), does not excuse.
What, then, should the Norwegian couple have done? On Aquinas's reckoning they would
have acted badly whether they had or had not given up the Jewish child. The point is that in
such a situation there is no way for people of such views to act well, and in this example it is not
unreasonable to say that they were at fault in this. They already knew that the child needed
shelter from the Nazis, and that the Nazi policies were wicked was something that they could
and should have recognized. It is hard, however, to believe as Aristotle and Aquinas both
suggest, that errors of principle are never excusable. There are, after all, famously disputable
matters of right and wrong. 14
I have gone into the question of different sources of badness in action because it seems to me
that the subject is seldom well treated in modern moral philosophy. So far, my examples in this
section have been from the area that Mill assigned to morality. But these faults have their
parallels in those that he excluded, in which self-destructiveness takes the place of cruelty to
others, and indifference to one's own good that of indifference to theirs. Thus, firstly, there are
generally bad acts, such as self-mutilation or suicide, whose badness need not depend on harm
likely to come to anyone else. 15 Secondly, no one can act well in seeking, or carelessly incurring,
even a lesser harm to himself through self-hatred or the kind of spitefulness to oneself that
Dostoevsky unforgettably described in Notes from the Underground. Finally, here again one
cannot act well in doing what, rightly or even wrongly, one seriously thinks that one should not
do.
So far, therefore, we have seen no reason to think that Mill's 'moral' evaluations should be
treated differently from other evaluations concerning the human will. Nor does one appear if
we continue the investigation by asking about the overall judgement in cases where there is a
mixture of good and bad in cases such as those described in the previous paragraph, and
where there may of course also be goodness and badness from 'inside' and 'outside' of Mill's
specially distinguished area of morality. In our much earlier example of the foolish burglar
whose action was defective in one way in that he was plying his dishonest trade and in another
in that he was tarrying in front of the television set (Chapter 1), we have a double dose of
badness. So we may mix and match ad lib and then ask about the result. What if different
elements point evaluation in different directions? When can an action be called good in such a
case? Will it, for instance, be enough for goodness that what is done is (intentionally) to save a
life or bring some other kind of help to a person who needs it? This seems plausible until we
think of a blackmailer saving someone from drowning only so as to be able to go on with his
extortion. And what again of an action with a good end but carried out by immoral or by
foolish means; or of an action that in itself perhaps should be done but is thought to be foolish or
'wrong' by the doer? Can any of these actions, containing both good and bad elements, be
called good? Aquinas, whose distinctions we followed earlier, says firmly that in every one of
them the actions are bad, invoking the principle that a single defect is enough for badness,
while goodness must be goodness in all respects. 16
Aquinas here sees asymmetry in the concepts of badness and goodness, which may strike one
at first sight as simply wrong. Yet on reflection we observe that this is indeed part of our way
of thinking. It is enough to make a house a bad house that it is either badly designed or damp,
whereas neither the fact that a house is well designed nor the fact that it is dry is sufficient to
make it good. Small faults are not always counted in, but a consideration of major faults and
excellences works in this asymmetrical way.
It seems, then, that an action is bad if it has badness from its kind, its end, or its contrariety to
the agent's beliefs about what it is good or bad to do. So much for the negative side: we now
know what is, formally speaking, sufficient for volitional defect. But what of goodness? What is
sufficient for that? Again Aquinas says something that may surprise us. For he says of any
individual action (that is, one individuated by the fact that it is done by a particular person at a
particular date and time) that if it is no way bad then it is good.17
This has also seemed evident to Anscombe. 18
16 Aquinas, Summa Theologica, First Part of the Second Part, Question XVIII, article 4.
17 Ibid. article 9.
18 Anscombe, 'Practical Inference', 34.
5 Human Goodness
It may be said that we think differently about human action, and it is true that we sometimes
do when it comes to picking out certain actions for special praise. But then it is important to
remember that no special praise is due when a rich person contributes to charity a sum of
money that he or she would not even miss; while a simple action like telling the truth in a law
court, or giving honest opinion on a candidate for an academic position, may merit special
praise when performed in especially difficult circumstances. 19
Under Hitler's regime, as under Stalin's, the temptation to prevaricate must have been very
great indeed. And extra special goodness does not belong only to what is generally thought of
as belonging to the sphere of morality. For clearly it can be an exercise of the virtues of hope
and of courage simply to struggle on rather than commit suicide in the face of great adversity.
To behave with wisdom in fortunate circumstances may be nothing special, but for a single
mother with small children in cramped bed and breakfast accommodation it must be very hard
indeed. As a certain doctor put it,
it is easy to eat healthily . . . and to address your addiction to cigarettes if you are not
having to deal with conditions that challenge your capacity to get, intact, from one end of the day
to the other. 20
If acting wisely rather than self-destructively in such circumstances were said to be the kind of
action that should be picked out as especially good, one could go along with that.
So far, then, our conceptual analysis has seemed to favour a comparison rather than a contrast
between the two classes of evaluations that I see as belonging together. One who objects to this
has, however, another card to play. For he or she may insist that there is nevertheless a logical
difference between 'moral' and 'non-moral' evaluations because, in a clash of reasons for action
based on requirements of justice or charity and reasons having to do with one's own needs or
desires, the former always trump the latter and take the trick. We saw in discussing Maklay's
promise (Chapter 3) the kind of example that may be in mind.
This belief in the general overridingness of Millian 'moral' considerations does not, however,
seem to me defensible, and one may wonder why it is held. That it is may have something to
do with the special position of certain prohibitions that as a matter of fact all have to do with
what Mill counted as morality. For a good case can be made out for a limited moral absolutism
by which certain such actions are held to be such as to rule out circumstances in which it could
ever be right to perform them. Adultery and lying have been suggested as having this
character, though I myself would not agree with Aristotle, Aquinas, or Anscombe about either.
I think it especially ludicrous to suggest, for instance, that those fighting with the Resistance
against the Nazis should not if necessary have lied through their teeth to protect themselves or
their comrades. An absolute moral ban on torture seems, however, to be another matter. If the
19 It is important, of course, to distinguish difficult circumstances from the kind of difficulty that comes from lack of
virtue itself. For this distinction see Foot, 'Virtues and Vices', section II.
20 P. F. Naish, Chairman, Prevention of Heart Attacks and Strokes Enterprise, North Staffordshire Royal Infirmary:
To see this we have only to go back to our example of the person in bed with flu. Suppose this
patient had promised to go to help a friend on the day on which he is ill. Unless the promise
were a very solemn promise, or the breaking of it very serious for the promisee, he will be able
to say in exoneration, 'I am sorry, but I was not able to get out that day.' It is not that his legs
would have failed him, but rather that there was something else that he should, all things
considered, have done, that is, to keep to his bed. In fact it is often reasonable for agents to give
themselves (never mind their families) preference over others. As John Taurek pointed out
some time ago in an excellent article, it is not at all generally believed that, for example, one
should incur the certainty of losing a limb even to save another from injury more serious than
that. 23
The slogan 'Moral considerations are overriding considerations' expresses not a truth of moral
philosophy but an implausible doctrine about what should be done.
21 I was glad to see an article by Ronald Dworkin that supports this opinion ('Report from Hell', New York Review of
Books, 17 July 1986). He sees the ban on torture as a barrier to the power of a tyrannical ruler. One might also see
torture as the ultimate negation of the impulse humans have to come to each other's aid.
22 Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, 180.
My opponent in the main line of our controversy may protest that my attention to a wide class
of evaluations has, in taking us outside the realm of obligation and duty, also taken us outside
moral philosophy. One might say, 'So much the worse for moral philosophy!' I do not, as I have
said, much care how the word 'moral' is used. But it seems important to recognize as virtues of
the will (as volitional excellences) a readiness to accept good things for oneself, and to see the
great importance for life of the self-regarding aspect of virtues such as hope and a readiness to
accept good things. 24
And on the negative side, we might want to use the description 'moral fault' in thinking of the
kind of timidity, conventionality, and wilful self-abnegation that may spoil no one's life but
one's own. That we tend to speak in moral philosophy only of volitional faults that impinge
particularly on others gives the whole subject an objectionably rigoristic, prissy, moralistic tone
that we would hardly care to take up in everyday life. It also tends to cloud understanding by
suggesting that there is a special meaning for words such as 'ought' in such contexts. In fact
'ought' is very close to 'should', and if we speak of 'a moral context' this usually simply
indicates the presence of a reason for acting that has to do with others rather than oneself.
24A graduate student once said that my lectures had first made him see 'that to be anti-sex could be immoral'. I
liked that.
Philippa Foot
I have argued earlier that it is wrong to look for an independent criterion of practical rationality
to which goodness in action must somehow be shown to conform. Instead, rational choice
should be seen as an aspect of human goodness, standing at the heart of the virtues rather than
out there on its own.
I want to tackle this problem head-on. But first it should be separated from the once influential,
now largely discredited, idea that no one ever does (can) pursue anything except his or her own
happiness. This was a theory based on a heady mixture of conceptual intuition and
psychological scepticism: the first probably coming from a confused acknowledgement of real
conceptual relations between the concepts of desire, achievement, and satisfaction; the second
from the everyday observation that people often seek their own happiness while denying that
they do. Neither psychological hedonism nor psychological egoism can be established in either
way. Happiness is not the universal aim of action. Brave people choose great and immediate
evils, such as certain death, in order to rescue or defend others. And even in their choice of
lives some reject happiness for the sake of some other goal. 25
What is problematic for morality about the relation between virtue and happiness does not
come from the direction of such theories as psychological hedonism or psychological egoism,
but rather from the idea that happiness is Man's good, together with the thought that happiness
may be successfully pursued through evil action. For then it would seem that there is an
independent criterion of rational action—the pursuit of happiness—with rationality on
occasion demanding what virtue forbids.
Indeed, the thought that happiness is humanity's good may seem to disrupt the argument of
the preceding chapters on natural normativity through the idea that the instantiation of the
human life form lies in happiness, which should therefore be the determinant of virtue. For
When told that marriage to Nijinsky would ruin her life, the future Madame Nijinska replied, 'I am going to
25
marry him in spite of everything . . . I'd rather be unhappy serving Nijinsky's genius than be happy without him.'
Romola Nijinsky, Nijinsky, 204.
6 Happiness and Human Good
how then could it be that virtue sometimes requires the sacrifice of happiness? And how is it
that happiness can, it seems, be obtained by wickedness? Can these things be denied?
In the following pages I shall do my best to sort out this tangled skein of ideas, though
recognizing that my best efforts are going to be pretty pathetic in this deep and difficult part of
moral philosophy. Later in this chapter I shall question the assumption that happiness can be
taken tout court to be Man's good, arguing that on some interpretations of the word 'happiness'
this is unacceptable. Firstly, however, full justice must be done to the thought that happiness
can successfully be pursued through doing evil. I shall therefore give a sketch of happiness as
there construed, with the plea that we should not too quickly reject each and every picture of
wickedness and happiness conjoined.
It may be useful, however, to begin even further back than this, by saying something about the
different ways in which happiness is predicated of human beings—as we speak, for example,
of their being happy doing something, being in a happy frame of mind, or having a happy life.
Some of these different predications will make their separate appearances in this discussion of
the relation of happiness to virtue; so one needs to have a variety of uses in mind.
Let us begin with the proposition that someone is happy doing something or other. What is
intended here may be quite minimal: when we say 'happy φ-ing' we may signify nothing more
than an absence of restlessness, or efforts to change a situation, so that we can say even of an
animal that, for instance, it is 'quite happy where it is'. And when said of human beings, who,
unlike animals, can be contented or discontented, 'happy doing such and such' may simply
connote an absence of discontent. 'Happy φ-ing' is, however, more likely to tell of enjoyment,
or pleasure, or liking-to-do: here enjoyment comes on the scene, as something that must, one
would think, be part of a happy life.
Enjoyment is a difficult concept. Activities are most often what people are said to enjoy, and
when they enjoy such things as holidays or jobs, enjoying activities will be a large part of what
is meant. It does, however, make sense, though it is rare, to speak of enjoying the fact that such
and such; and it turns out, interestingly enough, that enjoyment of activities often involves
thoughts. For although one can enjoy sex, or eating and drinking, or movement, simply on
account of what it is pleasurable to feel, it would be hard to explain enjoyment of philosophy,
or even of gardening, in these terms. In a whole range of such cases, what seems to be
important to the enjoyment is the perception of something seen as good. Often achievement
itself will be the good, and that may be all there is to it, as when someone is doing a crossword
puzzle or some other thing that in itself is pointless. But it may also be what is being achieved
that is seen as good in itself. So if there were a people who accompanied their activities with
variable movements of a hand, and a steady hum, we might find ourselves translating the first
as, roughly, 'Good, I'm getting on', and the second as, 'Good, something desirable is being
achieved', when each could, in the absence of negative factors, be seen as an expression of
enjoyment. What is remarkable is that both of these bits of language would be propositional. I
have been struck by how much the enjoyment of gardening is like this. It owes, I find, little to
pleasant sensation or movement and much to awareness both of immediate achievement
('That's got it well dug in!') and the prospect of good things to come; so that goodness is here
prior to enjoyment, as well as (in some sense) implied by it; and the same is no doubt true of
Philippa Foot
enjoying doing philosophy. What we have here is propositional, though not, of course, such as
to require episodes of thought, because it is a sense of how things are, and therefore not
essentially episodic. It may seem puzzlingly like a coloured film over the surface of the mind
until it is noticed that it has the distinctive relation to the time sequence that belongs to a belief.
Beliefs, which even if long-standing may never have been formulated by the one who has
them, can be attributed to him or her in the present tense, irrespective of whether, at the time of
attribution, they occupy the mind. 26
This is one way in which thoughts, and particularly the thought of good, plays a part in
happiness, but it is not the only way. For so far we have been dealing only with enjoyment, and
enjoyment does not have to be seen as the chief element in happiness. If someone has much to
enjoy in his life this is at least a factor counting in favour of his happiness. But happiness is also
a matter of that to which one might give the general title of gladness. Sometimes the gladness
will attach to particular moments, as when good news is heard, or good things especially
salient in one's mind, but gladness, unlike enjoyment, does not as such occupy clockable time,
and this part of happiness too may take the form of a sense of things being well, rather than of
thoughts that occupy the mind. Being contented, by and large, with the way things are in one's
life, or at least being conscious of the good things in it, is obviously a large part of happiness,
and the question 'Are you happy?' may ask someone how it is with him or her precisely in this
respect.
Finally, in this brief sketch of some of the different contexts in which the term 'happy' and its
cognates are found, we should note the expression 'a happy frame of mind', which describes a
mood in which someone is cheerful, confident, ready for enjoyment, and apt to have a sense of
things being well. That things are well with him may be what he really believes, but a happy
mood is something so much on the surface that it can cover up actual knowledge that things
are not well at all.
It is evident, however, that what has been said so far is quite inadequate as an account of that
sense of the word in which it can be said that happiness is humanity's good. For one recalls
Wittgenstein's famous death-bed insistence that he had had a wonderful life, which I have
never seen questioned as the truth. Interpreted in terms of happy states of mind it would,
however, have been very puzzling indeed if a life as troubled as his had been described as a
good life. What Wittgenstein said rang true because of the things he had done, with rare
passion and genius, and especially on account of his philosophy. Did he not say elsewhere 'The
joy of my thoughts is the joy of my own strange life'? 27
Joy is of the essence of a good life, but is of course compatible with prolonged suffering. In this
connection I think also of an old Quaker woman of whom I have read, who after much
persecution and suffering spoke of her 'joyous life' preaching the Word. She did not speak of
her life as a happy life; it would have been puzzling if she had. So this example, too, helps us to
question the identity of meaning between the expressions 'a good life' and 'a happy life' if the
latter is thought of simply in terms of contentment, enjoyment, or pleasure.
26 Wittgenstein stressed the importance of differences in the way that different 'psychological concepts' were
'clockable'. See Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology, vol. ii, sections 43-63.
27 'Die Freude an meinem Gedanken ist die Freude an meinem eigenen seltsamen Leben.' MS of 1931, quoted by
Contentment is not only not necessary but also not sufficient for a happiness that could
convincingly be called humanity's good. I recall a talk by a doctor who described a patient of
his (who had perhaps had a prefrontal lobotomy) as 'perfectly happy all day long picking up
leaves'. This impressed me because I thought, 'Well, most of us are not happy all day long
doing the things we do', and realized how strange it would be to think that the very kindest of
fathers would arrange such an operation for his (perfectly normal) child.
Such a procedure would of course be dangerous, because who knows in an uncertain world
whether the servants paid to provide leaves or simple toys for the whole of the child's life
would really do that? Setting this aside, we can suppose ourselves looking back in the life of a
man or woman who has in fact spent a lifetime in childish pursuits. That he or she was
perfectly happy doing this is a description that could really apply. But the example shows that
when we talk about a happiness that is supposed to be humanity's good we cannot intend
pleasure or contentment alone. As Aristotle remarked, we should not wish to continue in the
pleasures of childhood at the cost of remaining a child. 28
What, then, is the elusive concept of happiness that could rightly be given a central role in moral
philosophy? Most people would say that it is a state of mind, and there is no doubt something
correct about that. Nevertheless the mistake may lie right here. For the description inclines us
to think of the concept of happiness as if it had the same logical grammar as that of, for example,
excitement or elation, and that is not right. To see this we may return to the idea of a child's
pleasure, asking why Aristotle was right to dismiss the thought that we would exchange this
for the things that can be good in an adult life. What is it that is in its nature impossible for a
child? It is not intense pleasure—a child can have that. Nor is it a state of mind such as
excitement or elation that can be predicated wherever there are certain signs: squealing and
giggling, for instance, and begging for more of whatever it is that pleases the child so much.
And we can of course say of a child that he or she 'is happy' paddling or building sandcastles.
What seems to be missing—and necessarily missing—is the dimension of depth: a dimension
that we cannot count as irrelevant to the happiness-as-good of a grown-up. We are mistaken if
we think of happiness as something 'in the mind' in principle detachable from a person's
resources of experience and belief, as if a mental state were like the surface of a pond that could
be described in terms of the coming and going of water beetles there, without any reference to
what was lower down.
The important point is that such an idea of deep happiness is completely wrong, and I think
further enquiry will be useful in spite of the fact that the idea of depth in human feeling and
thought is itself not easy to explain. 29
We should remind ourselves that the use of the word 'deep' as applied, for example, to love, to
friendship, or to happiness is something that we have been able to learn like any other part of
language, and therefore has public criteria. Yet the difficulties are real. For the thoughts that
may afflict one here are exceedingly odd. I have caught myself in the ridiculous thought that
what is deep must have something to do with taking a deep breath, or with what is deep
within one's carapace like one's viscera or one's heart. A slightly more sensible but still quite
mistaken suggestion is that the deep is what causes a lot of disturbance in our lives. That
cannot be right, because we understand someone very well if he says on his death-bed that he
wasted his life on trivial things; and things that do not really matter—like a bad faux pas, or the
non-arrival of an invitation to a party of the duchesse de Guermantes—can create any amount
of disturbance, right up to obsession. It is no good saying that they do not bring deep feelings,
since the concept of depth is just what we are trying to understand. Nor will it do to think that
whatever someone minds about on his death-bed is what he feels deeply about, since all sorts
of strange things may be said there. 30
What is characteristic of each of these suggestions is that it is reductive: one is trying to find
some less puzzling substitute for the troublesome proposition about what is deep. But perhaps
this is itself a mistake. Perhaps 'deep', as used in the way in which we are interested, yields
what we might call a 'ground-floor' expression and so, though it has some traceable
connections with what is not physically on the surface of things, has surroundings of its own
that partly determine its meaning in a psychological context. 31
One can say that bona fide attributions of deep happiness take place in a characteristic
syndrome of spontaneous utterance, action, gesture, and response. But what is at least as
important to the discussion of the connection between virtue and happiness is that there is also
a restriction of cause and object. This is shown by the fact that it does not make sense, without a
very special background, to suggest that someone found deep happiness, in, say, a running
victory in a dispute with a neighbour over a morning newspaper or a milk bottle, however
much we think of 'fizzy' behaviour and elation. Whereas deep happiness and joy over the birth
of a child? That is a different matter! 32
It is not just what someone says but what he says it about that matters, and why should it not be
so? We are tempted to think of deep happiness as explicable psychologically in a way that makes
it possible to separate it from its objects. But why should this be possible? Why shouldn't the
communality of meaning not depend here on a shared reaction among human beings to certain
things that are very general in human life? Are not these reactions shared even by people of
very different cultures; not, of course, exactly, but nevertheless with sufficient similarity for
people of one age or culture to understand depth of happiness over a birth and depth of grief
about the death of parent, child, or friend?
Thus possible objects of deep happiness seem to be things that are basic in human life, such as
home, and family, and work, and friendship. They are, in a way, ordinary things, even though,
in a person such as Wittgenstein, the chief joy of his life was in the quest for truth, and in other
exceptional men and women it is in artistic creation or the exploration of strange lands. Most
people, of course, find their greatest happiness in more mundane surroundings. I think, as
illustration, of a story of Gertrude Stein's in which she writes of a rather simple woman, Anna,
30 William Pitt the Younger's last words may have been 'Oh my country, how I leave my country!', but in a
different report, 'I think I could eat one of Bellamy's veal pies.' See Lord Rosebery, Pitt, 269 and Appendix D.
31 It is relevant here to remember Wittgenstein's insistence that what is in the language has 'need of public criteria'.
friend after the birth of a longed-for child, 'Today I took my first steps in the real world.'
6 Happiness and Human Good
who was in service with a doctor and cooked for him and his bachelor friends. Stein says that
this was a very happy time in Anna's life. 33
The description 'deep happiness' seems in order here. Why? Well, they ate so much, and Anna
had a good job to do and a proud place in the world.
Similarly, there is the case of Caleb Garth in George Eliot's Middlemarch, a character who is a bit
solemn for our taste, but definitely the salt of the earth. In the passage that interests me he is
reporting to his wife the news that he has been asked to manage part of Sir James Cheetam's
country estate:
It's a fine bit of work, Susan! A man without a family would be glad to do it for nothing .
. . [I]t's a fine thing to come to a man when he's seen into the nature of business: to have
the chance of getting a bit of the country into good fettle as they say. . . . I'd sooner have
it than a fortune. I hold it the most honourable work that is. 34
Once again, it seems to me, we have an indication of deep happiness, understandable
particularly if we remember the predominance of agriculture in the economy of England at the
time of which George Eliot wrote. To get a bit of land into good shape was to do something
important, having to do with getting food; also with improving the tenants' houses, which was
a particular concern of Garth's. Land was home and livelihood to oneself and others, and it
would have been with a sense of such things in the background that he expressed a special
kind of pleasure at being given the job.
I want to draw from these examples, and in general from the discussion of deep happiness, the
thought that we should be suspicious of the idea that whenever we speak of happiness we are
speaking of a state of mind which seems as detachable from beliefs about special objects as is,
for example, having a headache, or a tune running though one's head. 35
It seems to me that this picture should be shaken by a realization of the impossibility of
attributing a grown-up's deep happiness to a young child. If we say that 'that' might happen to
be found 'there', we must surely ask 'But what, now, is that?'
It seems certain, therefore, that we must go beyond the description of a life of pleasure and
contentment in looking into the concept of human happiness. It is not enough, however, to say
that a life of trivial pleasures and contentment cannot plausibly be identified with a life that is
good in the sense that Wittgenstein must have intended when he spoke of having had a
wonderful life. Something important is still missing, because, though it seems that this must be
problematic, we have not yet said anything decisive against the conjunction of even the
greatest, deepest, happiness with wickedness.
This new problem is one that has for me centred round an example that I constructed on
reading long ago of a Nazi who had had a leading role in the running of one of Hitler's death
camps and was reported as saying in later years that 'whatever happened next' he would not
be 'the real loser'. He had, he said, thoroughly enjoyed living in Brazil and had not thought
much about the past. As I discovered only recently, this particular man—Gustav Wagner—was
deceiving himself: he became suicidal later on. Perhaps there is always a price to pay for
wickedness, in real self-esteem or in the possibilities of loving relations with others. 36
I am, however, dissatisfied with such a solution to this new problem. It puts too much weight
on a rather uncertain hypothesis. What do I really know about the possibility of combining
wickedness and happiness? Drawing on the literature about men of his ilk, can we not
realistically suppose that a certain Nazi commandant—call him 'Z'—enjoyed his 'work' in the
camp as he made the day-to-day arrangements for the death of great numbers of men, women,
and children in the gas chambers? Going about his tasks in good spirits, in a happy frame of
mind, he could have had a sense of achievement in solving administrative problems; on
occasions he might himself have selected prisoners for death or for 'punishment', taking
pleasure in his power to terrify them and to have them destroyed or spared at the wave of a
hand.
Nor can we avoid our dilemma by reminding ourselves that happiness is not just a matter of
enjoyment, cheerful mood, and happy occupation, but must extend all the way into the
underlying thoughts that a person has about himself and his life. For here, too, 'Z' may seem to
score. He was not ashamed of the pleasure he took in tormenting and destroying the inmates of
the camp; on the contrary, he thought that he was helping to purify the Aryan race, inspired by
Hitler's leadership and serving a great cause. If we say that he could not really have been
contented we are trying to get the facts to conform to a picture of the way we think they must
be. This in itself should suggest that something philosophically interesting is in the offing. For
Wittgenstein has told us to focus attention on just such inclinations to say 'must', and has
taught us to expect to find in them not truth but rather the crooked reflection of a real
'grammatical' (meaning conceptual) truth. 37
In the following pages I shall try not to forget what the facts do really allow us to believe about
the ordinary human goods of affection and friendship that are necessarily forfeited by one
who, like our 'Z', has a profound lack of humanity. But I want to explore the thought that a
tendency to go beyond what we really observe reflects a conceptual truth that is still to be
exposed. To be sure, we have already dismissed mere contentment as identical with human
good, arguing that the dimension of depth in happiness must be taken into account, and
querying the claim of the wicked to have had lives that are as happy as can be. Yet there is
surely something fundamental about the relation between human virtue and human good that
is missing still.
To get even an inkling of what this might be it is necessary, I think, to go right back to the
conceptual connection that is at the core of the idea of natural goodness as understood in this
book.
Let us think once more about plants and animals and ask about the relationship between
goodness and defect in an individual and what counts as flourishing for a member of the
36 How could Hitler and others around him have had anything more than a sentimental love of children when
they were ready to have even one single child driven into a gas chamber?
37 See Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, section 66.
6 Happiness and Human Good
species to which it belongs. To flourish is here to instantiate the life form of that species, and to
know whether an individual is or is not as it should be, one must know the life form of the
species. A quite general conceptual connection between life form and goodness is given
specification in the myriad life forms of different kinds of living things; no doubt historically by
an evolutionary story that leaves the members of each species dependent not only on their own
internal resources but also on the environment to which the species came to be adapted.
Given that goodness in respect of bodily health, of faculties such as intelligence and memory,
and so on is precisely that which fits a living thing for the instantiation of the life form of its
species, and that this counts as the good of a living thing, then in so far as this instantiation in
humans can be identified with having a good life, the question that concerns us in this chapter
is the relation between virtue and a good life and the connection of that with the happiness of
the one whose life it is. So far, as for instance in considering the case of 'Z', we have supposed
that conceptually speaking we must allow that a wicked character could have an extremely
happy life. But I now want to argue that we find in our own thought a way of understanding
human good and even human happiness that does not allow of such a combination. It may be
suggested that such usages are merely pious, depending on a religious faith that defines true
happiness in religious terms, as perhaps the contemplation of the Deity, or a happiness to be
thought in terms of a Muslim afterlife. I think, however, that this would be a mistake, and that
there is something here to be recognized by people of all faiths or none. This is, however, an
extremely difficult subject. It is too quick to say that because human goodness belongs to those
who have the virtues, human good is what they will attain in acting well. 38
What, we may ask, are we even talking about if we speak of human good? And given the
fantastic diversity of human lives can we really think of a species-wide notion of human good at
all? Is it even clear what terms we should use at this point? We can speak of a human being as
flourishing, but as applied to members of the human race this has too special a connotation, in
that it suggests untroubled success. We accepted Wittgenstein's description of his life as a good
life, but to give so troubled a man as an example of one who had flourished would suggest a
special philosophical use of the terms.
Indeed, there may be an unwelcome whiff of philosophy even in speaking of human good. One
is tempted to use capitals, as if we were quite at home with the idea, for instance in the
question 'Is happiness Man's Good?', and in speaking like this we may already lose ourselves.
There is nothing wrong with giving a word or an expression a special meaning in philosophy,
but then its meaning must really be made clear. Otherwise an obtruding picture may lead us to
invent a logical grammar in a way that will likely foul up the debate. 39
38 Neither Elizabeth Anscombe nor Gavin Lawrence is a philosopher to be accused of hastiness in thought. But I
wish they would not move from accounts of the merely clever practical inferences of the one whose ends are bad
straight to the assertion that he 'gets a great evil for himself'. To be sure, Aristotle seems to say just this when
discussing practical inference in the Nicomachean Ethics, Book VI, chapter 9, 1142b17-20. But the question is, what
should lead us to accept what he says?
39 I think, for instance of the way philosophers tend to speak of 'the mind' while pointing at their heads. No one
points at his head when saying 'I haven't made up my mind' or 'My mind is all confused', and a teacher has no
special reason to think of a student's head while describing the qualities of his mind.
Philippa Foot
How then shall we avoid such rarefactions in thinking about human good, while yet avoiding
the too special implications of a word such as 'flourishing'? I think that we may get a first
glimpse of our quarry by considering the concept of benefit as this is applicable in the domain of
life. Let us ask what it is to benefit a living thing, as this seems, after all, to be the same as doing
something that is for its good. The concept of benefit seems to have the right kind of generality,
and will of course cover both a beneficial change in an organism and that which protects it
from external harm. To benefit an individual it may be necessary to act on it—to make it
better—or on the other hand to act on its environment. St Jerome healed the lion's paw but
Noah sheltered his animals from the flood. 40
We may notice in passing, however, that neither making a plant, animal, or person better by
providing what makes him or it better, like medicine, nor improving environmental
circumstances, is necessarily beneficial as things work out. St Jerome would not have benefited
the lion had it leaped forward in relief from pain, but fallen straight into a trap. And going back
to humans, we notice that there have been times when it was precisely the healthy men who
were sent to the mines, and that humane doctors working in the hospitals (the 'sick barracks')
of Hitler's or Stalin's death-dealing labour camps were sometimes careful that their patients
should not get back to work too fast.
Let us now consider the concept of benefit specifically in relation to human beings, using the
discussion as a first step to an understanding of the idea of happiness that would disallow the
combination of wickedness and felicity in the case of our fictional but only too lifelike 'Z'. To
begin the discussion, I would here call on a common understanding of the idea of benefit. For
suppose that we think of some really wicked persons such as the serial killers Frederick and
Rosemary West, who did not even spare their own children in their career of abuse and
murder. For many years they were able to act out their sexual fantasies free from detection, and
might well have continued to do so to the end of their natural lives. What then would it have
been right to say about the contribution of those whose behaviour made this kind of thing
possible? Would they have benefited the horrible Wests? It seems to me that in our natural
refusal to say so we glimpse a conceptual truth that does not usually lie so clearly on the
surface. And that if the usual conceptual connections hold here, as they surely do, between
benefit and what is for someone's good, what has come to the surface is also about that.
That happiness can be seen in this way—as conceptually inseparable from virtue—is shown, I
believe, more closely in another example that has puzzled me for many years. I am thinking of
the case of some very brave men who opposed the Nazis. 41
I know about most of these particular people, many of whom were very young, from letters
published in a book called Dying We Live, which should be better known than it is. 42
These are letters from prisoners about to be executed after trial in Nazi Germany: letters
written to their wives, or parents, or sweethearts, which, because of that, give a very poignant
40 I would add at this point that animals cannot be said to be flourishing if they are not living anything like a
natural life. An animal is not benefited by being kept alive by artificial feeding and induced to breed by artificial
means, because such a life would be too far from its life form. What fitted such an unnaturally fixed-up animal for
survival, such as extreme docility, might not be goodness but perhaps defect in a thing of its kind.
41 Many discussions with Gavin Lawrence have kept this case continually in my mind and helped me very much.
42 H. Gollwitzer, K. Kuhn, and R. Schneider (eds.), Dying We Live: The Final Messages and Records of Some
sense of what it was that they were losing in laying down their lives. At the time when the
letters were written, the die was already cast: probably no one of them could have escaped
death whatever he might have said or done. But earlier, as when, for instance, a pastor among
them had refused to stop preaching against the ill-treatment of Jewish people, they must have
had a choice between the life they could have had with their families, and the death that
awaited them in prison. In any case no one of them would, I am sure, have been willing to try
to buy better treatment at the end by renouncing his anti-Nazi allegiance. So let us adapt the
example and suppose that when they wrote the letters they still had such a choice.
I think that, as so developed, this is a particularly interesting case because, as already
suggested, but for the dreadful times they lived in most of these men—let us call them the
Letter-Writers—might have had especially happy lives. The letters give the impression that
those who wrote them were especially well fitted for the enjoyment of the best things in life: for
great happiness. So one may very naturally say that they knowingly sacrificed their happiness
in making their choice. And yet this does not seem to be the only thing we could say. One may
think that there was a sense in which the Letter-Writers did, but also a sense in which they did not,
sacrifice their happiness in refusing to go along with the Nazis. In the abstract what they so
longed for—to get back to their families—was of course wholly good. But as they were placed
it was impossible to pursue this end by just and honourable means. And this, I suggest,
explains the sense in which they did not see as their happiness what they could have got by
giving in. Happiness in life, they might have said, was not something possible for them. 43
It may seem that one can get to the bottom of this matter simply by thinking about the shame
that men of the Letter-Writers' calibre would no doubt have felt, in later life, had they gone
along with the Nazis. This is of course important, for they might have felt that everything that
came later was corroded by the fact that it had been gained by acting in this way. Yet this is not
the heart of the matter. For supposing that they had been offered a 'Lethe-drug' that would
have taken from them all future knowledge of the action? They would not have accepted. And
there would have been a way in which they would not have felt that happiness lay in acceptance. 44
It is the latter difficult thought that I want to hold on to, and to understand. At the very least its
presence gives us a clear indication that happiness isolated from virtue is not the only way in
which the concept is to be found in our thoughts.
The suggestion is, then, that humanity's good can be thought of as happiness, and yet in such a
way that combining it with wickedness is a priori ruled out. Wittgenstein in speaking of his life
as a wonderful life certainly did not mean that it had been a life of virtue; but I am sure that he
43 Readers of these letters have been struck by the extraordinary sense of happiness that they radiate, which has
perhaps to do with the fact that practically all the writers were devout Christians who thought of themselves as
carrying out a task laid on them by God. One recognizes that such beliefs must often fail to sustain someone in
terrible circumstances. Yet even there a brave man or woman might under a certain description be glad of what had
happened; as someone thrown back unconscious into his cell after torture might say 'Good!' on realizing that he
had not given information; in spite of a consuming dread of what would happen next day.
44 To see it as happiness they would have to have changed, and would not have accepted the prospect of such a
change. The case is not like that of, say, a retiring person who cannot imagine himself happy in a public role, but
might nevertheless be glad if he could change himself. Related to this is the fact that one would not wish for the
sake of someone one loved that 'in the tight corner' they would be able to forsake their virtue in time; which shows
the inadequacy of a 'virtue ethic' theory that makes much of the fact that they would not be able all at once to change
a deep-seated disposition to act in a certain way.
Philippa Foot
would not have counted as a source of happiness anything he saw as evil in it. Of course, if
perfection were in question no human life could be a good life and the concept would have no
application. Nevertheless, when Aristotle gave an introductory account of eudaimonia in terms
of activity in accordance with virtue, in Book I of the Nicomachean Ethics, he described
something of which we too have, it seems, an idea. He insisted that the life of one who could be
counted as eudaimon required favourable external circumstances. No one, he said, could so
describe Priam given the great misfortunes he suffered in the sacking of his city and the loss of
his sons. Yet operation according to virtue, whatever the virtues might later be shown to be,
was the essence of the concept of eudaimonia itself as introduced in Book I of the Nicomachean
Ethics.
The conclusion of the present chapter is that happiness is a protean concept, appearing now in
one way and now in another. There was nothing wrong with what the doctor said of his
patient who was 'perfectly happy all day picking up leaves'. And there is also a sad truth to be
recognized in the saying about the wicked who flourish like the bay tree. But there is a third
interpretation of the word happiness: the one in which we must understand someone who in
sacrificing his life for the sake of justice would not have said that he was sacrificing his
happiness, but rather that a happy life had turned out not to be possible for him. We cannot
ignore this interpretation of the concept if we identify happiness with human good.
In terms of contemporary discussions of happiness and its relation to virtue, I should describe
my own view in the following terms. I agree with John McDowell that we have an
understanding of the word 'happiness' that is close to Aristotle's eudaimonia in that operation in
conformity with the virtues belongs to its meaning. 45
In my own terminology 'happiness' is here understood as the enjoyment of good things, meaning
enjoyment in attaining, and in pursuing, right ends. I do not, however, accept McDowell's
apparent identification of happiness with a life of virtue, or his idea that a loss incurred through
an action necessary for virtue is 'no loss at all'. He seems to me to allow too little for the
genuine tragedy that there may be in a moral choice. I myself would rather say that there is
indeed a kind of happiness that only goodness can achieve, but that by one of the evil chances
of life it may be out of the reach of even the best of men.
I believe that in thus disagreeing with McDowell I am agreeing with what David Wiggins has
said against what he calls McDowell's 'rigorism'. I should also like to draw attention to
Wiggins's excellent desire to bring Hume's theory of the human sentiments into the debate at
this point. For there is a way in which a good person must not only see his or her good as
bound up with goodness of desire and action, but also feel that it is, with sentiments such as
pleasure, pride, and honour. 46
45 See especially McDowell, 'The Role of Eudaimonia in Aristotle's Ethics' and 'Eudaimonism and Realism in
Aristotle's Ethics'.
46 See Wiggins, 'Eudaimonism and Realism in Aristotle's Ethics: A Reply to John McDowell'.
7 Immoralism
7 Immoralism
Philippa Foot
Immoralism is nowadays a somewhat neglected subject: one can search the indexes of dozens
of contemporary works without finding a single entry under this heading. Many contemporary
moral philosophers seem to agree with Prichard who, notoriously, scolded Plato for accepting
the challenge of immoralists such as Thrasymachus and Callicles (in the Republic and the
Gorgias) to show that the just man was happier than the unjust. 47
And while Nietzsche's work now interests many analytic philosophers, one finds few who
actually try to confront him. This seems to me a mistake, if only because the whole idea of
immoralism is hard to understand. Nietzsche said that he was attacking the premises of
morality. Does it then have premises? What could these be? I want to consider the subject of
immoralism in the light of the account of moral evaluation given in previous chapters of the
present book.
In the Republic the immoralist case is put forward by the Sophist Thrasymachus and (as Devil's
advocates) by the brothers Glaucon and Adeimantus who are not satisfied with Socrates' way
of refuting Thrasymachus in Book I. 48
Thrasymachus had said that justice (that is, the just actions of just men) served the interests of
the stronger, identifying the stronger first as the rulers who lay down laws to their own
advantage, but later as strong, ruthless individuals who swindle honest men in such matters as
contracts, 'plundering by fraud and force alike the goods of others, sacred and holy things,
private and public possessions, and never pettily but always on a grand scale'. 49
These strong men, powerful enough to escape retribution, profited from the self-inflicted injury
of the just, whose obedience was not virtue but silly good nature. Therefore the life of the
unjust was superior to that of the just. The strong who practised injustice followed good policy
(euboulia) and were wise and good (phronimoi and agathoi). So it was wrong to prize justice over
injustice.
Socrates tied Thrasymachus up in knots, but left Glaucon and Adeimantus dissatisfied: they
thought that Socrates had failed to refute the strongest arguments in favour of injustice, and
were ready to put them forward on the Sophist's behalf. They wanted to be confirmed in their
view that the life of the just is better than that of the unjust. Glaucon therefore argues, in the
role of an immoralist, that most people think injustice in itself better than justice, praising the
latter only for the rewards that society attaches to it. It is true that justice is better for those who
cannot get away with injustice, but the life of the strong unjust man is best of all. Those who
praise and practise justice do so only because they fear injustice: unable to live the best of lives,
they settle for the second best, which is neither to suffer nor to do injustice. They practise
justice unwillingly and from inability to inflict injustice, as is proved by the fact that no one of
them would act justly if, through a magic ring of invisibility, they could become invulnerable.
If someone with such a power refrained from plunder he would not be admired but rather seen
as the most foolish of men.
Glaucon asks Socrates to show that justice is better than injustice in itself as existing in the soul,
quite apart from penalties and rewards, and suggests that in the argument they should strip
these away, contrasting the life of a just man reputed unjust with one unjust but reputed just.
Glaucon himself believes that justice is one of those good things desired for what they are in
themselves as well as for their consequences. He wants Socrates to show that this is so, thus
comparing justice to thought, sight, and health, rather than to gymnastic exercises or medical
treatment which, though advantageous in their outcome, are troublesome in themselves.
Adeimantus too presses this request, asking Socrates to show that injustice is the greatest of
evils in the soul of him who has it, and justice the greatest good. Otherwise, he says, the best
policy will be to be unjust and not be found out. It will not be justice but the appearance of
justice that men should seek.
These then are the elements in the immoralist position as represented in Books I and II of the
Republic. Socrates assailed it by accepting the request of Glaucon and Adeimantus to show
what justice is in the soul: that it is health rather than disorder there. He denied that happiness
lies in the possession of wealth and power or any other of the advantages listed by
Thrasymachus, insisting that it rather lay in harmony in the soul.
It is not relevant to the thesis of the present book that I should consider the arguments
developed in the remainder of the Republic. It will be more to my present purpose to ask what
reply we ourselves might want to make to immoralism as Plato saw it. We need, however, to
think a little about what can even be understood as looking at justice in itself as it is in the soul.
What is the inside and what the outside here?
It is very easy to put this last question in a way that produces nothing but puzzlement. But I
suggest that a couple of analogies can help us. Suppose, for instance, that we think first about
friendship among humans as this might appear to some not very intelligent visiting Martians
who, without being able to talk to us or read our literature or philosophy, have been studying
the phenomenon of friendship here on earth. They report that certain humans are linked with
certain others in performing what seem to be services, unpaid except by reciprocity. The tacit
arrangement seems to be that if humans A and B are friends each is able to call on the other
when in difficulties, and there may be exchanges of gifts. Both the services and the gift-giving
can be a considerable nuisance to the giver. He or she apparently performs them because
everyone needs friends, except perhaps for a very few who are especially rich and powerful.
The ordinary needy human would prefer to be like these few, but in fear of friendlessness
settles for the next best thing, which is to be a friend and so to be able to call on friends. The
institution serves him, and so he praises it.
These Martians would see friendship very much as Plato's immoralists see justice. In itself
acting as a friend is, the Martians suppose, disagreeable, like gymnastic exercise or medical
treatment.
For the run of humans it is, however, worthwhile for its rewards. Were it possible to get these
rewards by gaining the reputation of being a friend without really accepting its duties, that is
what any human would seek. The point of my analogy lies, of course, in the fact that these
Martians would be failing to understand what friendship actually is in human life. And if, rather
7 Immoralism
labouring the point, we described the way in which they have got things wrong, we should
find that without any philosophical intention we had described what friendship is in the
human mind and heart. What friendship requires a friend to do for a friend may indeed be
onerous, involving even life itself. But what is done in friendship is done gladly, con amore:
perhaps with regret but without resentment about the way the chips have fallen. We ourselves
know perfectly well that it is not true that the best life would consist in successfully pretending
to friendship: having friends to serve one but without being a real friend oneself. A
Thrasymachean view of friendship would instantly be recognized as wrong.
Nor is this an isolated case. A similar analogy could be suggested if the subject were not
friendship but rather the relation between parents and children. Here too, unintelligent
Martians might think that parents saw looking after children as worthwhile only because
children help with the harvest and support parents in old age. And with this example one can
see, again, the existence of the concept of one's own good that was on the scene in the discussion
of our Letter-Writers in the previous chapter. 50
A loving parent would often be puzzled if told 'You should just consider your own good' if the
good of the children were at stake. Naturally, there can be consideration of advantages on one
side or the other, having to do, for instance, with an interesting job for a parent in one country
and better schooling for the children elsewhere. But there is a way in which a loving parent
does not really separate his or her good from the good of the children. And I think it is wrong to
suppose that this is only because one will affect the other. Joseph Conrad's story of the sea
captain, who happily if ruefully sold his boat (which was day-to-day his whole life) for the sake
of sending money to his far-away grown-up daughter, may be thought rather sentimental by
the critics, but nevertheless rings true. 51
If he cared more deeply about his daughter than about his own future there is a sense in which
he could not in his mind oppose his good to hers.
It may of course be questioned whether such analogies can really help us to understand what
justice is 'in the soul'. After all, we can hardly think that people pay debts, keep promises, or
refrain from taking the goods of others out of love! Of course not. Hume, who so much stressed
the part played by sympathy in the moral life, had to admit the difficulty of cases like that of
paying a debt to a profligate creditor. Nevertheless, it is one of the advantages of the recent
interest in virtue theories of ethics that moral philosophers are thinking about virtues rather
than bare acts. For Aristotle was surely right to distinguish doing what the just man does from
doing it as the just man does it. 52
Aristotle's stress was mainly on the stability of the principle of true justice; but we might also
think of it in terms of the underlying thoughts, feelings, and attitudes of one who recognizes
the claim of any human being to a certain kind of respect. Here it is perhaps enough to point
out that it makes sense to speak of those who are lovers of justice—as of those who love truth.
The plot thickens, however, if we leap across the centuries to confront the greatest of those who
have been called immoralists; that is, to confront Nietzsche. Few contemporary moral
philosophers, at least in the analytic tradition, have really joined battle with Nietzsche about
morality. By and large we have just gone on taking moral judgements for granted as if nothing
had happened. We, the philosopher watchdogs, have mostly failed to bark; which, given
Nietzsche's genius and his great and continuing influence, is surely rather odd. For while J. P.
Stern surely exaggerates the extent to which Hitler embodied Nietzsche's values, 53 and
Nietzsche sometimes spoke out against anti-Semitism, nevertheless the Nazis were able to call
on him in defence of their genocidal policies. That alone should wake us up.
I want to challenge Nietzsche. But that is easier said than done, if only because it is hard even
to locate the field of battle. Nietzsche called himself an immoralist and said that he was
attacking morality itself, but he is not consistent in this and many interpreters have denied that
he was really an immoralist. The word does not matter, but it is impossible, I believe, to
confront him without separating out at least three distinct theses that might come under this
description.
There is, first of all, Nietzsche's insistence that free will is simply an illusion. It has recently
been strongly argued that these views on moral responsibility are central to Nietzsche's
immoralism because they explain the reach of his attack on morality, beyond 'the morality of
pity' to 'morality itself'. 54
I think that this is right, but nevertheless want to put his attack on free will aside. For here
Nietzsche's attack was on the idea of a pure substance standing outside nature but nevertheless
intervening to cause actions in the world. Perhaps he had in mind something like Kant's
Noumenal Self; he was certainly wholly hostile to Kant and Schopenhauer even in their idea of
a more real world behind the world of appearances. The denial of free will was indeed a pillar
of Nietzsche's attack at least on a certain kind of morality, because he saw such a metaphysic of
the self as necessary to the idea of moral responsibility and the morality of desert. To sweep
them away would be to destroy the kind of judging, particularly the blaming, that seemed to
him to be of the essence of morality and to show a detestable love of retribution. Nietzsche
loathed the idea of punishment, saying (surely rightly) that we should mistrust anyone in
whom an instinct to punish was strong. 55
Why, then, do I want to leave his denial of free will aside? Because really to threaten morality
itself Nietzsche would have had to show not only that free will as he understood it was an
illusion, but also that no other distinction between voluntary and involuntary action (Aristotle's,
for instance) would do instead. He seems to be wrong about this. And perhaps he is also wrong
in thinking that moral evaluation of voluntary action and character requires the kind of
attribution of responsibility that he thinks of as the moral way of judging, and speaks of as
essentially unfair. Bernard Williams, discussing Nietzsche, says:
Reminded both that different pictures of action have been held in other cultures, and that the
notion of action itself is less than transparent, we can be helped to see that the integrity of
action, the agent's genuine presence in it, can be preserved without this picture of the will. 56
53 Writing of Nietzsche's belief in the unconditioned value of self-realization and self-becoming, he says, 'No man
came closer to the full realization of self-created values than A. Hitler': Stern, Friedrich Nietzsche, 86.
54 See Clark, 'Nietzsche's Immoralism and the Concept of Morality', in R. Schacht (ed.), Nietzsche, Genealogy,
Morality, 15-34.
55 He also thought that many criminals were simply strong men destroyed by society's hatred: 'Skirmishes of an
If this is right, it is not Nietzsche's metaphysic of the soul that is most important to one who
believes, as I do, that we should take the threat of his immoralism seriously, and wants to ask
how it might be met.
For this reason I shall now turn to a different strand in Nietzsche's immoralism, to the attack on
specifically Christian morality, which was especially prominent in his earlier writings—for
instance, in Human, All Too Human. Here, when Nietzsche called himself an immoralist or
attacked morality, his target was primarily what he called 'pity morality'. That is to say, it was
the Christian teaching that he identified especially with 'herd morality', the morality of 'the
weak and inferior' who, while secretly cruel and above all resentful, performed acts of
'kindness' with which they would demean the recipient and bolster up their own self-esteem. 57
All this has to be taken seriously because Nietzsche can claim, almost equally with Freud, who
admired him greatly, to be the founder of the theory of depth psychology. In this vein he
makes observations impossible to dismiss. He recognized only Dostoevsky as his superior,
claiming himself to be an innovating genius in the field. And indeed Nietzsche's psychological
insights have rightly won him many admirers. He saw the frequent insincerity of professions
of altruism, and the vanity and malice that lurks behind many of our kindly everyday actions.
But of course he goes much further than this. He says that we do kindnesses to others so as to
make them think well of us, then buy back this good opinion to soothe our self-hatred. We
relieve our dullness with tales of others' misfortune. We torment others by displaying our
virtues. Meanwhile, above all, we ourselves are resentful of our need to accept morality's
control.
At this point Nietzsche's immoralism is like that of Thrasymachus, and that of Plato's other
immoralist Callicles in the Gorgias, because supposedly good and admirable characters are
depicted as weak and therefore as objects of scorn. And Nietzsche's attack, if sustainable,
would be more deadly than the others, just because he is speaking in sophisticated ways of
what acts of justice and charity are in the soul. He is thus trespassing on the very ground of
Plato's own defence against Thrasymachus; he is representing a moral man as a wretched,
fearful creature, tormented by a biting conscience and unable to seek his own good. The
morality of pity, which is not even helpful to others, is above all harmful to the moral man
himself. Like Callicles, Nietzsche sees human beings as tamed by morality and, like tamed
animals, as thereby reduced. 58
He represents human good in terms of individuality, spontaneity, daring, and a kind of
creativity that rejects the idea of a rule of life that would be valid for others as well. Members of
'the herd' are, by contrast, conforming, fawning, propitiating, 'dog-like' creatures. They settle
for a banal kind of happiness; they 'have little pleasures for the day and little pleasures for the
night; and they take good care of their health'. 59
What are we to make of these charges against Christian morality? Anyone who is sympathetic
to the representation of human goodness as 'natural goodness', as that has been described in
57 For a fuller description of Nietzsche's doctrines see Foot, 'Nietzsche: The Revaluation of Values', in R. Solomon
(ed.), Nietzsche, 156-68, and 'Nietzsche's Immoralism', in R. Schacht (ed.), Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality, 3-14.
58 Apparently Nietzsche was influenced by Plato's portrait of Callicles. But he would not at all have agreed with
Callicles that the man who is to act rightly 'should let his appetites grow as large as possible . . . and to fill them
with whatever he has appetite for at any time'. Plato, Gorgias, 491E5-492A3.
59 Nietzsche, Thus Spake Zarathustra, Zarathustra's Prologue, section 5.
Philippa Foot
the present book, must take them very seriously indeed. For what Nietzsche is denying of the
supposed virtue of charity is exactly the connection with human good that was earlier said to give a
character trait that status. Taking pity (Mitleid) to be at the core of Christianity, he insisted that it
was a kind of sickness, harmful to pitied and pitier alike. He claimed that this morality was
'slave morality' and said that it grew out of the resentment felt by the weak on account of their
inferiority. Nietzsche described resentment (Ressentiment) as 'aggrieved conceit, repressed
envy'.60
As Robert Solomon has put it, 'frustration lies at the heart of Ressentiment, its description often
embodies such metaphors . . . as "simmering," "seething," and "fuming".' 61
This is strong stuff. For it goes without saying that one consumed by Ressentiment lives a
wretched life—that Christian morality seen like this has a systematic connection not with
happiness but rather with frustration, and of course with deprivation of the kind of creativity,
freedom, and lightness of spirit that Nietzsche rightly sees as a great part of human good. But
does one really have to see a morality that stresses the humanness of sympathy—Hume's, for
instance—as mistaken? Are those whose compassion for the unfortunate may even go so far as
to rule their lives really to be seen as thereby expressing a twisted sense of inferiority? Is
charity really mostly a sham? Sometimes, of course, it may be a sham, and Nietzsche, with his
devilish eye for hidden malice and self-aggrandizement and for acts of kindness motivated by
the wish to still self-doubt, arouses a wry sense of familiarity in most of us. But this is not to say
that there is not a great deal of genuine charity—of the genuine virtue—in people who do not
at all fit the picture Nietzsche draws of those master types who hold themselves at a distance
from the Christian 'herd'. Thinking of the ordinary unpretentious men and women who seem
to find special happiness in working for the relief of suffering, one must surely find Nietzsche's
dismissive views on compassion rather silly.
To say this is not, however, to reject the depth psychology that is more or less taken for granted
nowadays. Perhaps most of us can now come to terms with the thought that our motives are
seldom without any trace of vanity or self-regard. Perhaps today we can recognize how much
of malice, vanity, and even aggression is often present in what we do, without drawing an
immoralist conclusion. A story is told of an old priest, who, asked if he had learned anything
about human beings in his many years of hearing confessions, first said 'No', but then, 'Yes.
There are no grown-ups.' Is it not possible to think that he spoke truly, acknowledging the
greedy, jealous, small child that is ever with us, and yet insist that genuine kindness exists? If
so, by the criteria of natural normativity charity is a prime candidate as a virtue, because love
and other forms of kindness are needed by every one of us when misfortune strikes, and may
be a sign of strength rather than weakness in those who are sorry for us. We may reasonably
think, moreover, that charity makes for happiness in the one who has it, as hardness does not.
We are now, of course, in an area in which philosophy can claim no special voice: facts about
human life are in question and so no philosopher has a special right to speak. But we can use
Nietzsche's attack on 'the morality of pity' to unravel a tangle that may otherwise ensnare us
when we try to confront him. For we often find in his writings a claim that he is engaged on
'the revaluation of values', and this is a confusing idea. What could it mean to revalue values?
By what values are the values to be revalued? And can these values be revalued in their turn?
We shall not, I think, get anywhere by asking questions in which such abstractions appear out
of context. 62
But if we look at what was going on in Nietzsche's attack on Christian morality as he conceived
it, the puzzle disappears. He was saying that something thought good was not really good:
'Pity is thought good but is not really good.' Here we have the 'X is good' form that does not in
general give a determinate thought.63
But clearly what is in question is whether pity is a disposition that should be cultivated or rather
avoided in human life; that is, whether someone is to be seen as a good person in so far as he or
she feels compassion for others, or rather the reverse as Nietzsche suggests. He is focusing on
an evaluative assessment of attitudes and feelings that he finds in Christian morality. He is
denying the proposition 'To pity others is to have a good disposition towards them', and so is
challenging a judgement about what I have called natural goodness and defect in the human
species.
How are we to understand such a challenge? To set it in the right conceptual framework one
might usefully compare his challenge with an evaluation that has to do with a characteristic
found in a species of animal, for instance, the dancing operation in honey bees. The dancing of
a homecoming bee leads other bees to a source of nectar and so plays a beneficial role in the life
of the hive. But at one time this supposition was queried. So suppose it were not true after all
that other bees found nectar by reacting to the movements of an individual returning to the
hive; in that case, unless the dance played a part in the life of the dancer itself, unless it was
something that a homecomer needed to do for its own good, there would be no merit in a bee's
dancing and no 'natural defect' in an individual bee just because it did not dance.
This outlines a procedure in which an evaluation might be revalued, and the procedure is in
principle no different when an evaluation of a characteristic or an operation of human beings is
in question. It might have been thought, for example, that it was good for human beings to be
as fat as possible, before it was realized that corpulence went with ill-health. And in our own
lifetime extant moral beliefs about various sexual practices have come to many of us to seem
mistaken; we have re-evaluated old beliefs about the baneful influence of, for instance,
masturbation or homosexuality, and so revised former evaluations. If we take this as an
example of revaluing values, we can look at Nietzsche's attack on Christian values more or less
on his own terms. He asked whether pity was good for the one pitying or the one pitied, and
this was the right question to ask. To be sure, his treatment of the topic was all mixed up with
gratuitous contempt for the kind of human beings he saw as inferiors and some pretty strange
ideas about the resentment and hidden malice of those who accept conventional moral
restraints. I have suggested that he got his facts wrong; but if his facts had been right, his
62 Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, section 116: 'What we do is to bring words back from their metaphysical
to their everyday use.'
63 Compare my objections to G. E. Moore in the Introduction to this book.
Philippa Foot
revaluation of pity would have been right as well. To some extent I suppose that Nietzsche was
indeed right if we are thinking, strictly speaking, of what we call 'pity'. For we may think that
no one really likes being pitied. It is rather what we call compassion that is respectful and
good.64
So much, then, for Nietzsche's attack on what he had labelled 'pity morality'. The theme
continued throughout his writings; but increasingly, as time went on, he moved to a different
and more sinister point of view, in that he went so far as to deny 'intrinsic badness' in the doing
of any kind of act. In The Genealogy of Morals, published in 1887, he wrote:
To talk of intrinsic right and wrong is absolutely nonsensical: intrinsically, an injury, an
oppression, an exploitation, an annihilation can be nothing wrong, in as much as life is
essentially . . . something which functions by injuring, oppressing, exploiting, and
annihilating, and is absolutely incomprehensible without such a character. 65
The reason given here as to why no action can be intrinsically wrong is not one that we can
take very seriously, because it depends on an illicit identification of features of the plant and
animal worlds with human acts of injury or oppression. We must look for a more interesting and
original argument than this, and indeed that is to be found in a part of Nietzsche's theory of
psychology that is more radical and more threatening than anything I have touched on so far.
His most deeply rooted thought about the goodness and badness of human actions was based
on something we might label 'psychological individualism', or perhaps 'personalism'. He
thought profoundly mistaken a taxonomy that classified actions as the doing of this or that,
insisting that the true nature of an action depended rather on the nature of the individual who did it.
(I think he must have seen a classification under descriptions such as 'murder' or 'oppression'
rather as Linnaeus must have seen previous taxonomies of plants, or as a scientist conversant
with the classification of metals by their molecular structure might see the taxonomies of
alchemy.)
A denial of the intrinsic badness of kinds of actions may, of course, look like nothing more than
the common (though I myself believe mistaken) belief that there are no kinds of actions,
however horrific, that could not in extreme circumstances be justified by a pressing end. 66
But it is more than this. Nietzsche was speaking about injury and oppression; using
descriptions tending to imply that such arguably extenuating circumstances were not on the
scene. In any case his own thought was different. It was that right and wrong in action could
not be determined by what was done except in so far as that stood in a certain relation to the particular
nature of the person who performed it. Thus, while he was ready to castigate certain types of
individuals as cruel monsters or licentious beasts (having no time for either), he spoke
indulgently of the nobles of earlier times, whom he saw as 'pranksome' (spöttisch) in performing
acts of plunder, murder, and rape. 67
64 For a discussion of the meaning of Mitleid in Nietzsche, see Kaufmann, Nietzsche, 363-71. Also Salaquarda,
'Nietzsche and the Judaeo-Christian Tradition', in The Cambridge Companion to Nietzsche, 90-118.
65 Nietzsche, The Genealogy of Morals, Second Essay, section 11
The fact that he said such things might incline us to say that Nietzsche was undoubtedly an
immoralist. But perhaps the sense of that word as applied to Nietzsche is not as clear as it once
seemed to be. For he was, after all, ready to endorse what we may be inclined to see as moral
judgements on types of human beings, as he notably did in speaking scornfully of the merely
licentious, as contrasted with those who undertook the noble task of forming in themselves a
body of strong but controlled and disciplined passions. Indeed we might give a list of
Nietzschean virtues, putting courage and integrity at the head of that list and, on the other
side, Nietzschean vices such as the malice and inauthenticity that he attributed to 'members of
the herd'. But even in this part of his work he attacked deeply rooted moral views, because he
gave the 'affects' of cruelty and lust (the dark passions) an essential place in human life. He
seemed to think them especially necessary for the transformation to a higher form of human
being that he believed possible—if only people would listen to him. The image of the tree that
had to grow with its roots in the mud worked powerfully in Nietzsche's mind, and it must
surely have been this part of his philosophy that he was thinking of when he recognized the
hatred that his writings would arouse, and the dangerousness of the seas of thought on which
he had embarked. 68
How, one may wonder, did Nietzsche come to this strange position, embraced with such
passionate intellectual integrity and a surpassing courage that prevented him from shrinking
from even the most dangerous of thoughts? His crucial idea was, I think, about what
constituted a good life for a human being, that is, his idea of human good. The terms in which
he was ready to describe such a thing were 'creativity', 'self-confidence', 'lightness of spirit',
'daring', and so forth. But beyond these very general descriptions he thought that nothing
could be said. He spoke with special scorn of the belief that there could be a good that was not
just my good or your good but 'good and evil the same for all'. 69
He would, perhaps, have agreed with the basic schema described in earlier chapters of the
present book in so far as he would have thought that a genuine virtue would have to be such as
to fit an individual for his own good. But where this good lay was, in any specific terms,
something that an individual had to determine for himself, creating his own values rather than
paying heed to anyone else.
Delving further into the origins of this moral taxonomy, we find that it depended on
psychological theories that go far beyond the observations involved in Nietzsche's attack on
'pity morality' as described earlier in this chapter. In his theoretical psychology, of which he
was very proud, he asserted the existence of a constellation of drives (Triebe) that he thought
must underlie the relatively superficial elements that psychologists so far had had in their
sights. But the truth is that as far as these drives were concerned he had nothing more to offer
than the concept of a depth psychology and a promissory note filled out only with the highly
dubious suggestion that they could all be reduced to a will to power. Freud was by comparison
an empirical scientist, ready after all to give up his overarching 'pleasure principle' when it
conflicted with observed facts. Nietzsche, however, fell into the philosophers' trap of inventing
But given the horrors of the past century I think that today it would be especially strange not to
see the 'what' of actions as even more important. We have seen such terrible things done in
Soviet Russia and Nazi Germany, in Chile, Cambodia, Rwanda, that we cannot but have a
sense of the awfulness of this very fact. It is no doubt of practical import to us to know what kind
of a man can give the orders issued by Hitler, Stalin, Pol Pot, or Pinochet, and the personal evil
of the legion of torturers now at their loathsome business in so many countries of the world—if
only to know how we ourselves might come to act like that. But we do not need to know
anything of that kind before branding the things that were and are still being done as utterly
wicked. At this point Nietzsche's insistence on individualistic evaluation seems simply absurd,
as if we should need to probe deep into the psychology of a Mengele or an Eichmann before we
could evaluate their actions. Thomas Mann was surely right when he said, already in 1947,
How bound in time, how theoretical too, how inexperienced does Nietzsche's
romanticizing about wickedness appear . . . today! We have learned to know it in all its
miserableness. 71
It follows that we have to take actual human life into account, and so to think about what men
and women would be tempted to do in the absence of moral teachings. Human life, unlike the
life of animals, is lived according to norms that are known and taken as patterns by those
whose norms they are. So we have to teach children what they may and may not do. Nor could
70 See p. 48.
71 Mann, Nietzsche's Philosophy in the Light of Recent Events, 35.
7 Immoralism
these norms be taught simply by telling children that they are to be courageous and 'authentic',
however important it is to encourage them to be daring and also to allow them to discover their
true desires. The norms to be followed must largely be formulated in terms of the prohibition
of actions such as murder or theft. In human life it is an Aristotelian necessity (something on
which our way of life depends) that if, for instance, a stranger should come on us when we are
sleeping he will not think it all right to kill us or appropriate the tools that we need for the next
day's work. In human life as it is, this kind of action is not made good by authenticity or self-
fulfilment in the one who does it. Some generally wrong actions are, it is true, justified by
special circumstances, as promise-breaking sometimes is; or justified by a special role, such as
that of a magistrate or parent. But in admitting this we are getting nowhere near to Nietzsche's
denial of the intrinsic rightness or wrongness of kinds of actions, a denial that seems to me to
be a totally false doctrine, tempting those who see themselves as exceptional to think that when
they murder and torture they are doing nothing wrong. 72
For a description of how this came about in the case of the Nazis, see Jonathan Glover's very interesting book,
72
Humanity, 316-64.
Philippa Foot
Postscript
I have been asked the very pertinent question as to where all this leaves disputes about
substantial moral questions. Do I really believe that I have described a method for settling them
all? The proper reply is that in a way nothing is settled, but everything is left as it was. The
account of vice as a natural defect merely gives a framework within which disputes are said to
take place, and tries to get rid of some intruding philosophical theories and abstractions that
tend to trip us up. There is nothing in the idea of natural normativity that should disturb the
good work that many philosophers have recently done, for instance, on problems in medical
ethics having to do, for instance, with distinctions between doing and allowing, or again on the
doctrine of double effect.
It may be thought that in one area at least there must be a greater knock-on effect. It may seem
that the suggestion of a form of goodness common to all living things must carry implications
about the way we should treat animals and even plants. But this is a complete
misapprehension. Moral philosophy has to do with the conceptual form of certain judgements
about human beings, which cover a large area of human activities. Thoughts about cruelty to
animals, or about the wanton destruction of useful or beautifully ingenious living things,
belong within the usual distinctions of virtues and vices. Goethe told his secretary Eckermann
of a certain Englishman who, owning an aviary, was so struck one day by the beautiful
appearance of a dead bird that he straight away had the rest killed and stuffed. Hardly a crime!
And yet there was something wrong with that man.
Bibliography
Bibliography