Science Education: Typical NOS Concepts
Science Education: Typical NOS Concepts
Science Education: Typical NOS Concepts
Science education
What are the benefits for scientists and others from learning the general prin-
ciples of scientific method? And which scholars have best clarified and docu-
mented those benefits?
The first chapter mentioned various positive or negative assessments of
these benefits by scientists and philosophers. But it noted that the most careful
assessments have been by science educators, while leaving documentation of
their findings to this chapter. Six benefits were listed: better comprehension,
greater adaptability, greater interest, more realism, better researchers, and
better teachers.
Science educators typically place various aspects of scientific method within
several broader contexts, including inquiry, practice, and the nature of science
(NOS). “For science educators the phrase ‘nature of science,’ is used to describe
the intersection of issues addressed by the philosophy, history, sociology, and
psychology of science as they apply to and potentially impact science teaching
and learning. As such, the nature of science is a fundamental domain for guiding
science educators in accurately portraying science to students” (McComas,
Clough, and Almazroa, in McComas 1998:5). Educators and scientists alike
perceive the importance of the NOS in the science curriculum (McComas 1998;
Khine 2011).
This chapter first reviews the typical NOS concepts that have been developed
primarily for K–12 (kindergarten through high school) science education. It
then reviews numerous and extensive empirical investigations by science edu-
cators that document the previous six benefits. Finally, it lists 10 academic NOS
concepts better suited to undergraduate and graduate students and science
professionals.
234
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
Typical NOS concepts 235
Figure 13.1 Fourteen typical concepts for the nature of science (NOS) for K–12 education.
This list represents a consensus among science education guidelines from eight nations.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
236 Science education
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
Typical NOS concepts 237
Out of Africa, and Evolution. The students’ general NOS conceptions were
assessed with a 40-item questionnaire and their context-specific NOS concep-
tions by a 10-item questionnaire for each of the 10 specific contexts. Table 7
in Urhahne et al. (2011) presented the 70 correlation coefficients between gen-
eral and context-specific NOS conceptions for the 7 concepts in the 10 specific
contexts.
For this concepts-by-contexts dataset, the relative importance of general and
context-specific aspects of the NOS can be quantified by a standard statistical
tool, the analysis of variance. It identifies three sources of variance: concept
main or general effects, context main effects, and concept-by-context inter-
action effects. These account for 1%, 26%, and 73% of the total variance,
respectively. Hence, interaction effects (73%) seem to be about three times as
important as main effects (27%). However, to be more precise, only half of this
interaction contains systematic patterns of interest, and the remainder is mostly
noise. Hence, general and context-specific aspects of NOS were about equally
important in this particular study.
Such results make sense. Although researchers in the physical, biological, and
social sciences make use of all of the general principles of scientific method, the
emphasis on various principles does vary somewhat among disciplines.
As evidence that a treatment of scientific method can serve diverse scientists
and nonscientists alike, despite some variations in emphases, I would men-
tion the tremendous breadth of disciplines that have publications citing this
book’s predecessor, Scientific Method in Practice (Gauch 2002). Those publica-
tions are in many sciences: anthropology, astronomy, bioinformatics, chemistry,
climatology, ecology, geophysics, hydrology, morphology, natural resources,
oceanography, physics, proteomics, psychology, seismology, sociology, taxon-
omy, toxicology, and zoology. They are also in technology: agriculture, com-
puter science, engineering, medicine, pharmacology, public health, and space
exploration. And they are in business, economics, education, law, management,
music, and philosophy.
In review, there is considerable consensus on basic NOS concepts, and there
are widely adopted assessment instruments. Furthermore, this NOS consen-
sus suits multicultural settings, while respecting indigenous knowledge for its
own merits, but without confusing or diluting mainstream science. There is
evidence that the NOS has context-specific as well as general aspects, so differ-
ent scientific disciplines such as geology and physics have somewhat different
NOS emphases.
However, there are legitimate concerns about characterizations of scientific
method in the typical NOS concepts developed for K–12 education. “The issue
of methodology seems to be dismissed altogether by saying that there is no
single method for doing science. . . . While it is certainly true that there is no
single scientific method in the sense of a mechanical procedure that determines
knowledge production step by step, there are general methodologies . . . that
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
238 Science education
guide scientific practice in general ways. Moreover, without the idea of a sci-
entific method or methodological rule, it is difficult to see how science can be
self-corrective and provide reliable knowledge” (Irzik and Nola 2010). Indeed,
the third item in Figure 13.1 is “There is no one way to do science (there-
fore, there is no universal step-by-step scientific method),” without any further
elaboration on scientific method. Accordingly, a later section in this chapter
proposes more advanced concepts for the NOS in general and scientific method
in particular that are suitable for undergraduate and graduate students and sci-
ence professionals. But, first, the following six sections document benefits that
result from studying and mastering the general principles of scientific method.
Better comprehension
The NRC has expressed the essential goal of science education in a mere four
words: “scientific knowledge with understanding” (NRC 1996:21). Hence, sci-
entific literacy requires comprehension of both scientific content and scientific
method. This literacy also relates to technological competence.
An explicit goal of the National Science Education Standards is to establish high levels
of scientific literacy in the United States. An essential aspect of scientific literacy is
greater knowledge and understanding of science subject matter, that is, the knowledge
specifically associated with the physical, life, and earth sciences. Scientific literacy also
includes understanding the nature of science, the scientific enterprise, and the role of
science in society and personal life. . . .
The goal of science is to understand the natural world, and the goal of technology
is to make modifications in the world to meet human needs. . . . Technology and sci-
ence are closely related. A single problem often has both scientific and technological
aspects. (NRC 1996:21–24)
Students must master scientific method and the NOS in order to make
scientific knowledge their own: “As Plato insisted so long ago, education is
not just the having of correct beliefs, it is the having of adequate reasons for
these beliefs” (Matthews 1998). To describe the opposite situation for a student
learning only science’s facts, he quoted memorable words from John Locke:
“Such borrowed wealth, like fairy money, though it be gold in the hand from
which he received it, will be but leaves and dust when it comes to use.”
One item among the “modest goals” for NOS instruction advocated by
Matthews (1998) is logic: “Given that being able to reason clearly is an obvious
component of being scientific, then one of the low-level nature of science
objectives might be to teach some elementary formal and informal logic.” Basic
instruction in deductive and inductive logic can reduce common fallacies and
misconceptions and can enhance reasoning, particularly the kind of reasoning
needed to evaluate competing hypotheses.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
Better comprehension 239
A similar win-win situation for scientific content and scientific method was
encountered in the context of college physics. Numerous students were tested
on acceleration, velocity, vectors, and forces.
It is well known that students come to the study of science with many naive prior notions
about the physical world and that these notions are very difficult to change. . . . It is less
well appreciated that students also come with many naive conceptions about the goals
of science and about the kinds of thinking needed for science. These conceptions,
imported from everyday life or from prior schooling, are even more difficult to change
than students’ naive notions about the physical world. Furthermore, their effects are
all-pervasive, affecting greatly what students try to learn and how they go about learning
it. . . .
An introductory physics course needs thus also to discuss explicitly the goals of science
and the ways of thinking useful in science. These issues cannot merely be addressed by
a few occasional remarks. They need to be constantly kept in students’ focus, and be
used as a framework within which more specific scientific knowledge and methods are
embedded. (Reif 1995)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
240 Science education
Yet another win-win combination for content and method was found by
Cartier and Stewart (2000) in the context of high school genetics. “In contrast to
what is popularly believed, focusing on epistemological issues in the classroom
does not have to mean teaching less subject matter in exchange. In fact, helping
students to appreciate the epistemological structure of knowledge in a discipline
can provide them with the means to more fully understand particular knowledge
claims and their interrelationships” (Cartier and Stewart 2000).
These empirical findings prompt some commentary on the National Science
Education Standards (NRC 1996). The Standards include prominent curricu-
lum requirements for the NOS or, in their terminology, for “science as inquiry.”
That is commendable, given the findings of science educators. However, a table
on changing emphases is organized under two headings: “Less emphasis on”
and “More emphasis on” (NRC 1996:113). The very first item is less emphasis
on “Knowing scientific facts and information” and more emphasis on “Under-
standing scientific concepts and developing abilities of inquiry.” This might be
called the trade-off model, or the win-lose model, in which inquiry wins and
information loses. Admittedly, given a fixed schedule, an hour more for the
NOS does mean an hour less for science content. But that does not necessarily
imply less content because NOS instruction can pave the way for more rapid
coverage of more deeply comprehended material. By analogy, first sharpening
a dull ax means less time spent chopping wood, but that does not necessarily
mean less firewood and, indeed, the more likely outcome is more firewood.
Hence, a better model, and a realistic expectation as well, would be to put both
“Knowing scientific facts and information” and “Understanding scientific con-
cepts and developing abilities of inquiry” under the column “More emphasis
on.”
Similarly, the more recent NRC (2012:41) position paper on science education
reiterates this perception of tension or trade-off between content and method:
“From its inception, one of the principal goals of science education has been to
cultivate students’ scientific habits of mind, develop their capability to engage in
scientific inquiry, and teach them how to reason in a scientific context. There has
always been a tension, however, between the emphasis that should be placed
on developing knowledge of the content of science and the emphasis placed
on scientific practices” or methods. But, again, extensive empirical evidence
supports a positive interaction or synergy between content and method, not a
negative interaction or tension.
Greater adaptability
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
Greater adaptability 241
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
242 Science education
Research clearly shows . . . that transfer of NOS knowledge does not happen automat-
ically. Students do not learn relevant NOS aspects through historical examples alone
or by instruction that refers only casually to elements of the nature of science. Several
researchers have pointed out that complex NOS ideas should be accompanied by explicit
and reflective discussion of the underlying concepts and principles. (Urhahne et al. 2011)
Greater interest
The understanding of, and interest in, science and engineering that its citizens bring
to bear in their personal and civic decision making is critical to good decisions about
the nation’s future. The percentage of students who are motivated by their school and
out-of-school experiences to pursue careers in these fields is currently too low for the
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
Greater interest 243
nation’s needs. Moreover, an ever-larger number of jobs require skills in these areas,
along with those in language arts and mathematics. . . .
A rich science education has the potential to capture students’ sense of wonder about
the world and to spark their desire to continue learning about science throughout their
lives. Research suggests that personal interest, experience, and enthusiasm—critical to
children’s learning of science at school or other settings—may also be linked to later
educational and career choices. Thus, in order for students to develop a sustained
attraction to science and for them to appreciate the many ways in which it is pertinent
to their daily lives, classroom learning experiences in science need to connect with their
own interests and experiences. (NRC 2012:x, 28)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
244 Science education
More realism
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
More realism 245
involves scientific method because methods precede and enable results. The
level of certainty accorded to any given scientific result ranges from highly
tentative to confident fact, and the scope ranges from particular situations to
great generality.
Science is replete with ideas that once seemed promising but have not withstood the test
of time, such as the concept of the “ether” or the vis vitalis (the “vital force” of life). Thus
any new idea is initially tentative, but over time, as it survives repeated testing, it can
acquire the status of a fact—a piece of knowledge that is unquestioned and uncontested,
such as the existence of atoms. . . .
Scientific knowledge is a particular kind of knowledge with its own sources, justifications,
ways of dealing with uncertainties, and agreed-on levels of certainty. When students
understand how scientific knowledge is developed over systematic observations across
multiple investigations, how it is justified and critiqued on the basis of evidence, and
how it is validated by the larger scientific community, the students then recognize that
science entails the search for core explanatory constructs and the connections between
them. They come to appreciate that alternative interpretations of scientific evidence can
occur, that such interpretations must be carefully scrutinized, and that the plausibility
of the supporting evidence must be considered. . . .
Decisions must also be made about what measurements should be taken, the level
of accuracy required, and the kinds of instrumentation best suited to making such
measurements. As in other forms of inquiry, the key issue is one of precision—the goal
is to measure the variable as accurately as possible and reduce sources of error. The
investigator must therefore decide what constitutes a sufficient level of precision and
what techniques can be used to reduce both random and systematic error. . . .
Under everyday circumstances, . . . Newton’s second law accurately predicts changes in
the motion of a single macroscopic object of a given mass due to the total force on it.
But the second law is not applicable without modification at speeds close to the speed of
light. Nor does it apply to objects at the molecular, atomic, and subatomic scale or to an
object whose mass is changing at the same time as its speed. (NRC 2012: 79, 251, 59–60,
114)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
246 Science education
risk and probability, and what roles do they play when one is trying to provide
scientific answers to questions? What is the difference between correlation and
causation?”
What science educators have found is that an understanding of science’s
method powerfully promotes the educational goal of developing realistic ideas
about science. This makes sense given that powers and limits are largely con-
sequences of methods: “Understanding how science operates is imperative for
evaluating the strengths and limitations of science” (William F. McComas, in
McComas 1998:12). Also, “The ability to distinguish good science from paro-
dies and pseudoscience depends on a grasp of the nature of science” (Matthews
2000:326).
Empirical studies by science educators have shown that good understanding
of scientific method promotes realistic beliefs not only for ordinary scientific
inquiries but also for scientific matters having substantial worldview import.
For example, Lawson and Weser (1990) conducted a large empirical study of 954
college students in a nonmajors biology course. Scientific reasoning was assessed
by students’ answers to 16 questions involving conservation of mass; volume
displacement; control of variables; and reasoning about proportions, proba-
bilities, combinations, and correlations. Students who performed poorly were
referred to as “intuitive” thinkers, moderately well as “transitional” thinkers,
and quite well as “reflective” thinkers. Scientific beliefs were examined with
seven questions regarding special creation, orthogenesis, the soul, constitu-
tive nonreductionism, vitalism, teleology, and nonemergentism. Students were
pretested for both scientific reasoning and scientific beliefs, and then post-tested
after the biology course by readministering the same questionnaires. These data
were subjected to PCA to characterize the main patterns, as well as statistical
tests to detect specific differences between intuitive and reflective students.
Their main finding was: “As predicted, the results showed that the less skilled
reasoners were more likely to initially hold the nonscientific beliefs and were
less likely to change those beliefs during instruction. It was also discovered
that less skilled reasoners were less likely to be strongly committed to the
scientific beliefs.” Their suggested explanation was that reflective students hold
beliefs more strongly than intuitive students “because they have acquired the
reasoning skills that enable them to consider the alternative beliefs and the
evidence in a hypothetico-deductive manner to arrive at firm conclusions.”
There were numerous positive interactions between reasoning level and strength
of confidence in scientific beliefs. Their two main conclusions were: “(1) teachers
should be aware that students may hold beliefs that are inconsistent, even
contradictory to scientific beliefs and that these beliefs may be difficult to
alter; (2) some students lack the reasoning skills that appear to be necessary
to comprehend the arguments and evidence in favor of scientific beliefs; thus
instruction should focus on ways of improving student reasoning skills as well
as teaching scientific conceptions.”
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
Better researchers 247
Better researchers
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
248 Science education
nor guaranteed.” This result echoes Ryder and Leach’s conclusion that it is
easier to produce competent technicians than creative scientists. It also rein-
forces the unanimous finding in countless studies that progress in understand-
ing the NOS, even in the context of authentic research experience, will not occur
unless this topic receives intentional, explicit, reflective attention.
Sadler et al. (2010) provided an ambitious review of 53 empirical studies
of research apprenticeships for secondary and college students as well as K–12
teachers. Research apprenticeships promoted positive outcomes for interest and
career aspirations in science, knowledge of specific science content, technical
and statistical skills, confidence in one’s ability to do scientific research, and
dispositions for effective communication and collaboration. By contrast, on the
matter of principal concern here, again extensive empirical evidence showed
that research experience prompted rather little growth in NOS understanding.
Apprenticeship programs are often touted as effective vehicles for learning about the
NOS. The basic argument is that opportunities to work with scientists offer new per-
spectives on how science is done and the nature of scientific knowledge. This argument
is based on an implicit model of NOS learning. That is, learners will gain sophisti-
cated understandings of NOS by virtue of participating in authentic science activities
without instruction dedicated to the realization of this goal. Many science education
researchers have challenged the notion that implicit approaches for teaching about NOS
results in meaningful learning. These critics have argued that explicit approaches that
support learner development of sophisticated NOS ideas through targeted instruction
and learner reflection are more likely to result in NOS learning. It is possible to partner
apprenticeship experiences with explicit NOS instruction. (Sadler et al. 2010)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
Better teachers 249
of scientific research. Science educators should bear in mind these two findings
as they seek to give scientists their winning combination of strength in both the
research technicalities of a given specialty and the general principles of scientific
method.
Better teachers
Regarding science and technology faculty, the NSF (1996:ii) advises that “It
is important to assist them to learn [and teach] not only science facts, but,
just as important, the methods and processes of research.” Likewise, the NRC
(1996:21) requires that science teachers understand the NOS, including the
“modes of scientific inquiry, rules of evidence, ways of formulating questions,
and ways of proposing explanations,” and the NRC (1999:41, 2012:253–260,
319–323) reaffirms those requirements. In addition to items such as “physical
science” and “life science,” one of the eight categories of content standards for
science is the “history and nature of science” (NRC 2001:148).
Matthews (1994:199–213, 2000:321–351) documented that knowledge of
the history, philosophy, and method of science can strengthen teachers. Such
knowledge “can improve teacher education by assisting teachers to develop a
richer and more authentic understanding of science, . . . can assist teachers [to]
appreciate the learning difficulties of students, because it alerts them to the his-
toric difficulties of scientific development and conceptual change, . . . [and] can
contribute to the clearer appraisal of many contemporary educational debates
that engage science teachers and curriculum planners” (Matthews 1994:7). The
NRC concurs.
Teaching science . . . requires that teachers have a strong understanding of the scientific
ideas and practices they are expected to teach, including an appreciation of how scientists
collaborate to develop new theories, models, and explanations of natural phenomena.
Rarely are college-level science courses designed to offer would-be science teachers, even
those who major in science, the opportunity to develop these understandings. Courses
designed with this goal are needed. (NRC 2012:256)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
250 Science education
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
Academic NOS concepts 251
Sigma Xi, asked the incisive question, “But what kind of scientific literacy is
important?” His reply was that “The basic concepts measured by survey ques-
tions may have little to do with the kinds of knowledge that are needed for
competitiveness in the technological world.” Accordingly, it would be regret-
table if “Basic literacy and numeracy take precedence over more sophisticated
scientific understanding in the priorities of education.” The very real value of
basic scientific literacy for “simple good citizenship in a technological world”
for all K–12 students should not be allowed to supersede or dwarf the equally
real value of advanced scientific literacy for college students and science profes-
sionals. Neither elementary nor advanced education should be neglected.
Accordingly, in contrast to the typical NOS concepts for K–12 education that
Figure 13.1 showed, Figure 13.2 shows academic NOS concepts suitable for
college students and science professionals. There is almost no overlap between
these two lists of concepts.
These ten academic NOS concepts have two main sources. One is the litera-
ture in science, statistics, and philosophy, which informs topics such as the PEL
model, deductive and inductive reasoning, and parsimony and accuracy. The
other is position papers on science education, which motivate topics such as
the relationship between the sciences and the humanities, science’s presuppo-
sitions, and science’s worldview import. These 10 items are representative, not
exhaustive. Additional topics in this book on scientific method include expli-
cation and defense of science’s rationality, science’s ethics and responsibilities,
and effective pedagogy for science education.
Between Figures 13.1 and 13.2, there is one intentional and direct conflict:
The first item in the typical NOS concepts is “Scientific knowledge while durable
has a tentative character,” whereas the corresponding last item in the academic
NOS concepts is “Much scientific knowledge is certain, some is probable, and
some is speculative; and scientists ordinarily make careful, justified, and real-
istic claims for their findings.” In support for this shift toward more confident
language, there has been a change from the excessive emphasis on tentative-
ness in the AAAS (1989, 1990) and NRC (1996) position papers to explicit
recognition of “fact” and “knowledge that is unquestioned and uncontested”
in the more recent NRC (2012:79) position paper, as already quoted at greater
length in this chapter’s section on more realism. Indeed, “a focus on practices
(in the plural) avoids the mistaken impression that . . . uncertainty is a universal
attribute of science. In reality, practicing scientists employ a broad spectrum of
methods, and although science involves many areas of uncertainty as knowl-
edge is developed, there are now many aspects of scientific knowledge that are
so well established as to be unquestioned foundations of the culture and its
technologies. It is only through engagement in the practices that students can
recognize how such knowledge comes about and why some parts of scientific
theory are more firmly established than others” (NRC 2012:44).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
252 Science education
Science is one of the liberal arts. There is a rich traffic of ideas between the sciences
and the humanities. Philosophy of science is especially relevant for scientists.
Scientific inquiry involves the general principles of scientific method pervading all
sciences and the research techniques of a given specialty. General principles need be
mastered only once, whereas specialized techniques change from project to project.
The winning combination for scientists is mastering both.
The PEL model asserts that when fully disclosed, any argument supporting a scientific
conclusion necessarily has premises of three kinds: presuppositions, evidence, and
logic.
Science’s presuppositions are installed by philosophical reflection on any exemplar of
rudimentary common sense, such as “Moving cars are hazardous to pedestrians.”
Science’s presuppositions and logic are rooted in common sense, not worldview dis-
tinctives, so they are worldview independent. But empirical and public evidence from
the sciences and the humanities can have worldview import, and personal experience
is also potentially relevant although not public evidence. Worldview conclusions based
on worldview-independent presuppositions and logic and on worldview-informative
empirical and public evidence are the prerogative of individual scientists; but they are
not the prerogative of scientific institutions because the scientific community lacks
consensus.
Deduction reasons from a given model to expected observations. Predicate logic
requires only several axioms, and arithmetic, probability, and other deductive systems
such as geometry and calculus can be added with several more axioms.
Induction reasons from actual observations to inferred model. The probability of evi-
dence given hypothesis, P(E | H ), is related to its reverse conditional probability,
P(H | E ), by Bayes’s theorem, which also involves the prior probability P(H ). Con-
fusing these reverse conditional probabilities is a fallacy, as is ignoring the influence
of prior probabilities.
Evidence is evaluated by multiple criteria, including accurate fit with the data, par-
simony, robustness to noise, predictive accuracy, generality, unification of diverse
phenomena, explanatory power, testability, and coherence with other knowledge.
For noisy data being fitted by a model family, which represents an extremely common
situation in science and technology, the optimal tradeoff is at the peak of Ockham’s
hill, with less complex models underfitting signal and more complex models overfitting
noise. A parsimonious model can be more accurate than its data, thereby increasing
repeatability and accelerating progress.
Much scientific knowledge is certain, some is probable, and some is speculative; and
scientists ordinarily make careful, justified, and realistic claims for their findings.
Figure 13.2 Ten basic concepts for the nature of science (NOS) at an academic level.
University undergraduate and graduate students and science professionals need to
understand the NOS at a higher level than the typical NOS concepts developed for K–12
education.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
Academic NOS concepts 253
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
254 Science education
Summary
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
Summary 255
TOUS and VNOS instruments for assessing student understanding of the NOS
use that consensus, and their wide adoption has facilitated comparisons among
studies.
From hundreds of empirical studies, science educators have found six ben-
efits from explicit and reflective study of the NOS. (1) Understanding of sci-
entific method promotes learning of scientific content, so rather than being
competitive goals, there is a win-win situation for content and method. (2)
Understanding the general principles of scientific method promotes greater
adaptability, transferring knowledge to solve new problems. (3) A humanities-
rich version of science that includes historical and philosophical elements from
the NOS stimulates greater student interest in science. (4) Understanding scien-
tific method and the NOS promotes more realism about the accuracy and scope
of specific findings as well as the powers and limits of science more generally. (5)
Mastering scientific method is necessary for developing better researchers who
are not merely competent technicians but rather are actually creative scientists.
(6) Grasping the NOS results in better teachers of both the NOS and science
content.
College students and science professionals need to master academic NOS
concepts rather than the typical NOS concepts intended for K–12 students.
Ten basic items merit inclusion at the academic level. (1) Science is among
the liberal arts and there is a rich traffic of ideas between the sciences and the
humanities. (2) The winning combination for scientists is mastering both the
general principles of scientific method pervading all sciences and the research
techniques of a given specialty. (3) The PEL model asserts that when fully
disclosed, any argument supporting a scientific conclusion necessarily has
premises of three kinds: presuppositions, evidence, and logic. (4) Science’s
presuppositions are installed by philosophical reflection on any exemplar of
rudimentary common sense, such as “Moving cars are hazardous to pedestri-
ans.” (5) Although science’s presuppositions and logic are rooted in common
sense and thereby are worldview independent, empirical and public evidence
from the sciences and the humanities can have worldview import, and per-
sonal experience is also potentially relevant although not public evidence. (6)
Deduction reasons from a given model to expected observations. (7) Induction
reasons from actual observations to inferred model. (8) Evidence is evaluated
by multiple criteria, including accurate fit with the data, parsimony, robust-
ness to noise, predictive accuracy, generality, unification of diverse phenom-
ena, explanatory power, testability, and coherence with other knowledge. (9)
A parsimonious model, at the peak of Ockham’s hill, can be more accurate
than its data, thereby increasing repeatability and accelerating progress. (10)
Much scientific knowledge is certain, some is probable, and some is speculative;
and scientists ordinarily make careful, justified, and realistic claims for their
findings.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015
256 Science education
Study questions
(1) Regarding the first benefit of NOS instruction, better comprehension, what
do you think of the win-win situation depicted for NOS and science? Is
the empirical evidence convincing? Do you find this win-win situation
surprising or expected?
(2) What are some empirical findings by science educators showing that NOS
understanding promotes adaptability, interest, and realism?
(3) What are some empirical findings by science educators showing that NOS
understanding makes for better researchers and better teachers?
(4) What are three or four academic NOS concepts relevant for enhancing
perspective on science? Explain each briefly.
(5) What are three or four academic NOS concepts relevant for increasing
scientific productivity? Explain each briefly.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 29 Dec 2017 at 16:19:35, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139095082.015