Introducing Criminology

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 217
At a glance
Powered by AI
The text discusses the history and evolution of criminology as a field of study, from early biological approaches to more modern multi-disciplinary perspectives. It also introduces some of the key concepts and theories around defining crime, offenders, and the study of criminology.

Approaches discussed include biological, psychological, and sociological perspectives. Biological approaches examined physical traits and genetics, while psychological approaches considered factors like family background, learning theories, and cognitive processes. Sociological approaches discussed include strain theory, social learning theories, subcultural theories, and control theory.

Psychological approaches consider factors like family background, experiences, mental processes, learning theories, personality, socialization, and cognitive processes like rational choice theory and self-concept.

Contents

Introducing criminology

i
Introducing Criminology

ii
Contents

Introducing criminology

Clive Coleman
Clive Norris
First published by Willan Publishing 2000
This edition published by Routledge 2011
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
270 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016

Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group

© Clive Coleman and Clive Norris 2000

The right of Clive Coleman and Clive Norris to be identified as the authors of this Work has
been asserted by them in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988

All rights reserved; no part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval;
system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying,
recording or otherwise without the prior written permission of the Publishers or a licence
permitting copying in the UK issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency Ltd, 90 Tottenham
Court Road, London W1P 9HE.

First published 2000

ISBN 10: 1-903240-10-7 (cased)


ISBN 10: 1-903240-09-3 (paper)
ISBN 13: 978-1-903240-10-6 (cased)
ISBN 13: 978-1-903240-09-0 (paper)

British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data

A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.

Set in Palatino and Gill Sans

iv
Contents

Contents

Preface viii

Introduction 1

1 Crime, the criminal and criminology 6


What is crime? Who is the criminal? 6
The legalistic position 6
Conduct norms and their violation 7
Extending the concept of crime 8
The legalistic position restated 9
Crime as the violation of human rights 10
Crime as a social construction 11
What is criminology? 12
A multi-disciplinary discipline? 15
Criminology through the ages? Lombroso and all that 16
The classical school 17
The moral statisticians 20
The Italian positive school 21
The British context 23
Conclusion 24

2 Offenders and non-offenders: spot the difference? 26


Biological approaches 27
Physical characteristics and crime 27
Twin studies 28
Studies of adoptees 28
The new biology of crime 29

v
Introducing Criminology

Psychological approaches 31
Psychoanalytic approaches 33
Learning theories 35
Cognitive approaches 41
The revival of approaches locating the sources of crime in the
individual 50
Conclusion 54

3 A broader vision of crime 56


Environmental criminology 56
Sutherland, differential association and white-collar crime 60
Merton, anomie and strain 61
Subcultures, gangs and delinquency 64
Control theory 67
Interactionism, labelling and moral panics 69
Radical criminologies 73
Feminist perspectives 76
Left realism 79
Postmodernity, postmodernism and the modernist project 83
Conclusion 85

4 Thinking seriously about serial killers 87


Murder most horrid: defining serial murder 88
How many serial murders, murderers and victims? 91
A growing menace? 93
Types of serial murderer 94
Understanding serial murder 99
Biology: natural born killers? 100
Psychology: inside the mind of the serial killer? 102
Sociology: outside the mind of the serial killer? 107
Post-mortem 114

5 Policing and the police: key issues in criminal justice 116


Introduction 116
Definitions and delivery 119
Enforcement, prevention and detection: the police role
examined 121
Discretion and discrimination 130
Discretion 130
Discrimination 134
Due process and deviancy 139
Due process 140
Crime control 141
Conclusions 145

vi
Contents

6 CCTV and crime prevention: questions for criminology 146


Crime prevention 146
The rise of CCTV 149
Does CCTV reduce crime? Methodological concerns 151
What is meant by CCTV? 152
What is meant by crime and how can it be measured? 153
The concept of reduction and its measurement 156
Experimental design 161
Does CCTV reduce crime in town centres?
The evaluation evidence 165
Realistic evaluation 169
Context 170
Mechanisms 170
Outcomes 171
CCTV, discrimination and social exclusion 172

7 Criminology: some concluding thoughts 176

Bibliography 180

Index 198

vii
Introducing Criminology

viii
Crime, the criminal and criminology

Preface

When we asked friends and colleagues for advice on writing an intro-


ductory book on criminology, some of them said ‘don’t do it’. While they
may simply have been taking a dim view of our abilities, we prefer to think
they had in mind the difficulties involved in doing the task well. Perhaps
they were right. Overviews of the discipline, especially in a short volume,
often seem superficial, failing to give a full appreciation of the issues. In
attempting to provide depth, however, comprehensiveness is usually
sacrificed. We have attempted a mix of overview and in-depth examina-
tion of particular areas. Inevitably, some areas have not been covered at all,
such as victims, and prisons and punishment. We hope, however, we have
given a clear indication of the subject matter of criminology, the diversity
of approaches within it and the way in which criminologists go about their
work.
In the chapters that follow, Clive Norris was mainly responsible for the
content of chapters 5 and 6, and Clive Coleman for the remainder. We have
benefited from the advice of others, who kindly read and made comments
on draft sections when they had better things to do. We are very grateful to
Gerry Johnstone, Dave Metcalf, Jason Ditton, Keith Bottomley and Mike
McCahill. They must not, of course, be held responsible for the outcome.
Finally, we must thank our publisher, Brian Willan, who has been helpful,
constructive and supportive throughout.

Clive Coleman and Clive Norris


September 2000

ix
Introducing Criminology

x
Introduction

Introduction

Crime and criminology were two of the growth industries of the second
half of the twentieth century. Crime and how to respond to it are major
issues of today. Many universities now offer degree courses in crimin-
ology, and it is often taken as an element in other degree programmes. In
addition, there is significant interest on the part of the general public.
There seemed to be a need for a relatively short book that would welcome
people to the subject, being suitable for those who were just interested in
it, those thinking of taking it up, or those who have already embarked on a
course of study. There are plenty of big American-style textbooks that
attempt a comprehensive coverage. This book does not try to do this. The
first three chapters are broadly based, taking an overview of some major
themes and approaches. The second half of the book provides a more
detailed insight into the way in which criminologists go about their
business by looking in depth at three topics, selected to illustrate work that
has been done in different areas of criminology. We like to think that what
we are doing is rather like inviting readers to a party, at which they will
meet some key figures in the subject, eavesdrop on some of their conversa-
tions and arguments, and learn how they go about their work in terms of
actual research.
This book, then, invites the reader to a party, given to celebrate the
birthday of criminology, although there is some dispute about the date of
this. Many of the guests will have claims to be called criminologists. They
may surprise you by the diversity in their backgrounds and interests.
Among the guests you will meet: an Italian Professor with a fascination
with your bodily measurements, for whom size is important, and who
claims to be the father of criminology; a rather challenging person who
tells you that it is necessary to change the nature of our greedy capitalist
society before we can make real progress in dealing with crime; someone

1
Introducing Criminology

who wants to improve the conditions in our prisons and limit their use to
the smallest number of cases; a civil servant who works for a big
government department, which is concerned with the running of the
criminal justice system. Finally, a rather troublesome gatecrasher, who
regrets that criminology was born at all. Still want to come? Then read on...
Parties can be fun; they can also be tense but revealing occasions. The
world of criminology is not so very different from this. As we shall see,
criminologists seem to form themselves into identifiable groupings, which
do not always communicate easily with each other, almost as if they speak
different languages. Indeed, they often do speak different languages, and
criminology can develop in different ways in different countries (see Nye
1984 on the conflict between the ‘French’ and ‘Italian’ schools). The
occasional skirmish is to be observed, the reasons for which are not always
clear to outsiders. When criminologists are gathered together, it is not all
sweetness and light, for big questions are asked by them, to which there
are no easy answers. Since criminology raises issues about human nature
and social order, and connects with the world of human suffering, it deals
with questions that matter to people’s lives. It is therefore not surprising
that heat is often generated.
Birthday parties are often occasions for reminiscence. Guests tell stories
that illustrate the character of the person whose big day is being
celebrated. Some of the older guests are able to recall the very early history
of the person, and even how they were first contemplated (or not) and
conceived. This book will begin by asking such basic questions about the
character of criminology: what is it about? It will attempt to trace its
history and origins from the earliest times, when it may have been a mere
twinkle in someone’s eye. Who were the parents, and what were they like?
What impact did they have on the development of their offspring? Did
others have an influence on the development of criminology in ways that
the parents did not contemplate? Has there been dispute over the
parentage of the subject, and over the way in which its life and career
should develop?
Indeed, we may even find those at the party who, far from celebrating
the birth and continued existence of criminology, are essentially critical of
its fundamental character and concerns: has it spent much of its time on
the ‘wrong’ subject matter and asking the ‘wrong’ questions? Does it need
to change in a radical way or even be abolished altogether? The basic
nature of criminology, its origins and its subject matter are the focus of the
first chapter of this book.
Parties are also occasions where games are often played. What kinds of
games are played by criminologists? In chapter 2 we begin to look at a
game which has consistently been played by criminologists over the years:
‘spot the difference’ between offenders and non-offenders. The intention
has been to discover how offenders and non-offenders differ from each

2
Introduction

other. If differences could be found, it was thought that these would


provide vital clues to the causes of offending. Some have suggested that
the place to look for such differences is in the biological make-up of
individuals – that their genetic or physical characteristics, for example,
hold at least some of the clues to understanding crime and the criminal.
Others took the view that, while not necessarily discounting some role for
biological differences, the important differences between individuals with
regard to the causes of crime are psychological. Chapter 2 therefore looks
at the various perspectives within psychology which have attempted to
understand crime, with special reference to the game of ‘spot the dif-
ference’.
Chapter 3, entitled ‘A broader vision of crime’, is mainly concerned
with the sociological approach to understanding crime. For much of its
history, sociologists who have attempted to study crime have played their
own version of ‘spot the difference’. For them, the biological and
psychological approaches were either looking in the wrong place, or at
least their work needed to be supplemented by an understanding of the
social background and circumstances of offenders in order to explain
crime. Chapter 3 also documents a growing disenchantment with the
game of ‘spot the difference’. The game had not only proved to be more
difficult than initially expected, but some came to regard the whole
exercise as a fruitless quest. While some argued that the game should be
abandoned altogether, others took the view that it should at least be
supplemented by other activities and questions. It is clear that criminolo-
gists have become less preoccupied with playing ‘spot the difference’ than
they used to be.
For readers who have got this far and are still not convinced that this is
a party worth attending, we try a different tack in the three chapters that
follow. Having provided broad overviews of some key issues and
perspectives in criminology in the first three chapters, we move on to
examine three topics from different key areas of criminology. The first of
these topics is serial murder.
At parties and other social gatherings with ‘normal’ people, we find
that our trade as criminologists (if exposed) is often the source of great
curiosity. Some of the most frequently asked questions are about serial
killers, for there seems to be great interest in this topic and a demand for
material on it, as a visit to the crime section of any book shop will show. It
is sometimes assumed that criminologists are people like the character Fitz
in the TV series Cracker, who spend their time getting inside the minds of
serial killers and constructing profiles that will enable the forces of law and
order to track them down.
While criminologists might, quite rightly, try to distance themselves
from this narrow and rather misleading (but apparently glamorous) view
of their role, the serial killer does present a legitimate challenge to the

3
Introducing Criminology

criminologist. Surely this type of offender is a good candidate for ‘spot the
difference’? If theories of crime in general are difficult to construct when
crime is such a varied category, ranging from the theft of milk from
doorsteps to serial rape, surely such a specific crime as this should be a
good candidate for constructing a criminological theory? We therefore
give the experts pencils and paper, and ask them to come up with their
theoretical ‘profiles’ of the serial killer. Which, if any, is the most
convincing in terms of contributing to our understanding – that produced
by biology, psychology or sociology? The chapter serves as an illustration
of some of the procedures and problems involved in constructing a theory
of a particular type of crime.
While for many years the quest to understand and explain crime has
been a major preoccupation of criminology, a rather more recent focus has
been the workings of the criminal justice system. Rather than attempting
to give an overview of this area, we take an example of one important
agency within it – the police. Often seen as playing a key role as gate-
keepers in the criminal justice process, placed as they are at the entry point
of the formal process, the police are also the agency with which most
readers are likely to be familiar. Even if readers have not had their collars
felt, they are likely to have had some contact with the police, and to have
consumed a rich diet of representations of the police and policing through
the mass media.
We focus on some key issues that have preoccupied criminologists in
their study of the police. Firstly, what is their role? Are they solely respon-
sible for policing, or are other agencies involved? What do the police
actually do? Is their main role best seen as the control of crime, as is often
suggested? Secondly, we introduce two concepts that are important in the
study of criminal justice: discretion and discrimination, which we discuss
in the context of the police and policing. What is discretion and why does
it exist? Does police discretion result in discrimination against certain
groups in the population? Here we introduce the concept of police culture,
which has often been used to explain the way in which police discretion is
exercised. Finally, we outline a framework which has been commonly
used in the study of criminal justice: the distinction between due process
and crime control models of criminal justice. We discuss these models in
relation to policing, and ask how police practice in violation of ‘due
process’ might come about.
Another area that has received increasing attention in recent years is
crime prevention. Our final main chapter provides a brief introduction to
this area, before examining in depth a highly topical example of crime
prevention activity – closed circuit television (CCTV) systems. After
examining the reasons behind the popularity and growth of CCTV, we
look at a key question that criminologists are often expected to answer
about such initiatives: does it reduce crime? As an illustration of the

4
Introduction

attempt to evaluate policy measures to see if they actually ‘work’, it


demonstrates some of the difficulties involved in answering by research
such an apparently straightforward question. Finally, we raise some
broader issues raised by CCTV. Criminological research which merely
concentrates on the technical evaluation of such measures has often been
criticised for its narrow focus. Our position throughout this book is that
criminology should locate its studies in a broader political and social
context. We therefore raise some of the broader issues about CCTV. Is it a
technology that benefits all (apart from the potential criminal) or can it
lead to discrimination and social exclusion for certain groups in the
population?

5
Introducing Criminology

Chapter 1

Crime, the criminal and


criminology

Having invited you to the party, it is now time to find out more about the
guests and their activities. The starting point is to introduce you to two key
terms: crime and the criminal. Although the meaning of these terms may
initially seem obvious, there have long been arguments about the defini-
tion of them. These arguments are important, for they raise key issues
about criminology and its scope, and the way in which societies identify
and respond to actions as criminal. This leads into a consideration of the
nature and focus of criminology itself. There are different ideas about its
nature and aims, which will be explained. The final part of the chapter
attempts to contribute to our understanding of criminology by taking a
brief overview of its history, particularly in its early days. When was it
born, and do those early years help to explain its nature and development
in the years to come?

What is crime? Who is the criminal?

The legalistic position


For most of us, these do not appear to be particularly difficult questions.
Crime is that action which is prohibited by the criminal law, and the
criminal is the agent who carries out that action. Michael and Adler (1933:
2) are often cited as an example of the legal definition of crime: ‘the most
precise and least ambiguous definition of crime is that which defines it as
behaviour which is prohibited by the criminal code’. They recognised that
the definition of the criminal was rather more difficult, for although any
person who breaks the criminal law is a criminal, how are such persons to
be identified by criminologists? They conclude that ‘the most certain way
... to distinguish criminals from non-criminals is in terms of those who
6
Crime, the criminal and criminology

have been convicted of crime and those who have not. ... The criminologist
is therefore quite justified in making the convict population the subject of
his studies as he does’ (Michael and Adler 1933: 3). In practice, for many
years criminologists conducted studies of prisoners; the prison provided a
convenient captive sample for researchers and a context within which
their specialism could develop with a particular focus – the individual
criminal. However, prisoners are only a sample of those convicted of
crime, who in their turn are only a sample of those who have broken the
criminal law; it cannot be assumed that such samples are representative of
all law-breakers.

Conduct norms and their violation


Not everyone was happy with such a focus on crime and the criminal. One
of the dissenters was Thorsten Sellin, a famous sociologist of his day, who
put forward an argument which has been heard in a number of different
versions over the years. Sellin (1938) pointed out that the criminal law
often reflected the values of powerful interest groups, even in democra-
cies, rather than the moral standards within the general population. What
is defined as criminal could vary over time and between different societies,
making crime and the criminal a very slippery subject matter for the
scientist, who should be using concepts that had a ‘universal’ nature,
rather than ones which had a different meaning depending upon the
particular society and historical time.
Rather than using ‘ready made’ terms and subjects of study defined by
non-scientists, Sellin argued, scientists should be free to define their
own terms, to reflect the nature of the subject matter and its ‘universal’
properties. Since all social groups in any society had rules or norms, a
better basis for scientific investigation would be the study of these conduct
norms. The more complex the society, the more likely that norms would
come into conflict, such as where individuals are members of groups with
different norms, or where one group has power over another with dif-
ferent conduct norms. These conduct norms, how they develop and relate
to each other, and violations of them would be the focus of study, rather
than crime and criminal as defined by the criminal law and the criminal
justice system.
Many of these points were to be reiterated in years to come. The point
about the relationship between criminal law and power rang a few bells in
the USA, a country which had experienced Prohibition. This involved
legislation that prohibited the manufacture, sale and transportation of
‘intoxicating liquor’ and represented a political victory for the moral code
of one segment of American society at the expense of others. Sellin’s view
that we should study the origins and violations of conduct norms was
increasingly taken up by those who began to speak of ‘deviant behaviour‘
as the focus of study, rather than crime. Most difficult to grasp is his idea
7
Introducing Criminology

that conduct norms could somehow be identified and classified into


‘universal categories, transcending political and other boundaries, a
necessity imposed by the logic of science’ (Sellin 1938:31). This is an
example of the attempt to imitate the way in which the natural sciences
operated: to develop concepts and terms which would be equally
applicable whether you found yourself in Tipperary or Timbuctoo (in the
way that those such as velocity, density, gravity are in natural science).
Most important for current concerns is that Sellin did not argue that the
concept of crime should be extended to all violations of conduct norms,
perhaps aware of the confusion this would create: ‘extension of the
meaning of the term crime is not desirable. It is wiser to retain that term for
the offenses made punishable by the crimincl law ...’ (Sellin 1938: 32).
Others came to a different conclusion.

Extending the concept of crime


Like Sellin, Edwin Sutherland was concerned about the narrow focus of
much criminology. He, however, was interested in the offences committed
by business and professional people in the course of their occupations
(what he called white-collar crime), and the way in which these were
virtually ignored by criminologists and their theories of criminal
behaviour. Sutherland (1940) therefore conducted a study of the decisions
made by courts and commissions of the USA against the seventy largest
business corporations in such matters as false advertising, anti-trust
activity, labour relations, and infringement of patents, copyrights and
trademarks (types of white-collar crime now frequently referred to as
corporate crime). He found that 547 such adverse decisions had been
made, an average of 7.8 per corporation, with each having at least one
made against it. However, only 49, or 9 per cent of these decisions were
made by criminal courts. Undaunted, Sutherland attempted to show that
the remaining decisions were that the behaviour was ‘actually’ criminal.
He did this by extending somewhat the definition of crime, which he
claimed involves two things: ‘legal description of an act as socially
injurious and legal provision of a penalty for the act’ (Sutherland 1945:
132). Note that this definition still takes the law as its yardstick, but not just
the criminal law. In a sense, therefore, he was still clinging to a legalistic
definition. According to this definition the remaining actions of the
corporations were therefore ‘crimes’, although they were in practice
treated as if they were not crimes. They thus avoided the usual stigma
(and some of the harshest punishments) which were attached to offences
treated by the criminal law, an example of what he termed the differential
implementation of the law. He saw three main reasons for this relative
leniency: the higher status of the offenders; the trend away from punitive
responses; and the relatively undeveloped public hostility towards such
offenders.
8
Crime, the criminal and criminology

Sutherland was pointing to what he saw as class bias in the usual


definition of crime and bias towards the respectable in the operation of the
legal system. Not only were ‘white collar’ persons treated more leniently
when they were caught, but also many such offenders were never prose-
cuted in the first place. Futhermore, if criminologists confined their
attention to crime as usually defined, a kind of class bias would be intro-
duced into their study, with a concentration on those from the poorer and
less powerful sections of society. If so, the theories of crime likely to
develop from such a blinkered vision would be correspondingly partial.
Finally, since these sorts of offenders and offences rarely found their way
into the official crime statistics (produced by the agencies of the criminal
justice system), they were even more likely to be ignored by criminologists
and not seen by the public as being part of the ‘crime problem’. If taken
seriously, the implications were momentous, requiring us to revise our
ideas about crime and the criminal, the way to get information on them,
and the kinds of theories we need to explain them.

The legalistic position restated


The sorts of arguments put by people like Sellin and Sutherland clearly got
up the noses of some other criminologists, particularly those with a legal
background, for whom ‘crime’ had a very precise meaning, and for whom
the term ‘criminal’ should only be applied after the operation of the due
process of criminal law. To take any other approach would lead to
confusion and unethical branding of those who should be regarded as
innocent until proven guilty. Paul Tappan is a good example of someone
whose nostrils were particularly affected. Tappan (1947) accepted that it
was quite legitimate for sociologists to study all sorts of ‘conduct norms’
and their violation. But for him criminal law provides us with an
important, and fortunately very precise, type of these conduct norms:
‘crime is an intentional act in violation of the criminal law (statutory or
case law), committed without defense or excuse, and penalized by the
state as a felony or misdemeanor’ (Tappan 1947: 100). In addition, Tappan
accepted that convicted criminals were not necessarily representative of all
offenders, because of the selective processes of the discovery, detection,
prosecution and adjudication of offenders. Nevertheless, ‘ajudicated
offenders represent the closest possible approximation to those who have
in fact violated the law, carefully selected by the sieving of the due process
of law’ (Tappan 1947: 102), and should be the focus of study. It would be
wrong to identify someone (or a business corporation) as a criminal unless
they had been convicted of a crime.
In some ways, Tappan’s background as both lawyer and sociologist
appears to be pulling him in different directions. It is, however, easy to see
the force of his concerns. But if his definition of crime is accepted and
criminology is simply the study of violations of criminal law, there remain
9
Introducing Criminology

objections to a discipline which limits itself to a subject matter defined by


the state (and, by implication, powerful interests which may influence the
law-making process). Disciplines such as sociology could take a broader
view of a wide range of different rules and violations of them. Questions
had also been raised about the nature of criminal law and the interests it
represented. Why not study the law in this way, rather than simply be-
haviour that violates it? As we shall see, sociologists gradually took up
these questions. Unfortunately, those who attempted to extend the con-
cept of crime to cover various kinds of misbehaviour not presently
covered by the criminal law found themselves getting bogged down in
acrimonious debates about definitions and terms, as happened with
Sutherland (1945) and his work on ‘white-collar crime’. As for the
‘criminal’, Tappan’s views raise a key issue: if it is possible that adjudica-
ted offenders are not representative of those who have broken even the
criminal law, this represents a serious problem for those trying to make
generalisations about criminals. This was enough to make some research-
ers attempt to find out about those who had broken the law but had not
been caught (such as by the use of self-report studies, which ask people
directly about their involvement in offending: see Coleman and Moynihan
1996: chapter 3). It was also a powerful impetus to look at those processes
of law enforcement and criminal justice to see in what ways they were
selective.

Crime as the violation of human rights


If Tappan was disturbed by the ideas of Sellin and Sutherland, he would
have been dismayed by those of Herman and Julia Schwendinger (1970)
some years afterwards. These writers were concerned with the attempt to
identify basic human rights (such as personal security) rather than legal
rules as the way to define crime. As such, forms of social organisation, as
well as individuals, which violate such rights are criminal:

individuals who deny these rights to others are criminal. Likewise,


social relationships and social systems which regularly cause the
abrogation of these rights are also criminal. If the terms imperialism,
sexism and poverty are abbreviated signs for theories of social
relationships or social systems which cause the systematic abroga-
tion of basic rights, then imperialism, racism, sexism and poverty can
be called crimes according to the logic of our argument.
(Schwendinger and Schwendinger 1970: 148)

Although it is difficult to do justice to the ‘logic of their argument’ here,


their position is that the definition of crime is inescapably political. Those
accepting the legalistic approach of state-defined crime run the risk of

10
Crime, the criminal and criminology

becoming subservient to that particular state, the status quo, and the
interests it serves. For example, consider the position of a criminologist in
Nazi Germany of the 1930s, where certain groups in the population had
their human rights attacked, with the support of the state and its legal
apparatus. From the human rights perspective, the state can be seen as a
perpetrator of crime, rather than simply the authority that defines crime.
For the Schwendingers the role of the criminologist should be to engage in
the stuggle for those basic human rights so that criminologists become
guardians of those rights rather than defenders of the current order of
things (consider again the predicament of our criminologist in Nazi
Germany). What the human rights approach shares in common with that
of some earlier writers is the attempt to identify certain basic standards,
any deviation from which is ‘crime‘.

Crime as a social construction


What was clear from previous debates was that the contents of the
category of crime, as defined by the criminal law, varies over time and
place. Sutherland and Cressey (quoted in Rock 1973: 20) produced a list to
illustrate the variety of acts which had been defined as crimes at some
point, which included ‘printing a book, professing the medical doctrine of
circulation of the blood, driving with reins, selling coins to foreigners,
having gold in the house, buying goods on the way to market or in the
market for the purpose of selling them at a higher price, writing a cheque
for less than a dollar’. So various are the things that have been defined as
crimes that some took the view that the only thing they have in common is
the fact that they have been defined as crimes by the criminal law. One
reason why some scholars had spent so much time trying to identify the
‘essential’ nature of crime was that they were concerned with developing a
theory (a systematic explanation) of criminal behaviour. If crime was in
fact a rag-bag of assorted acts with very little in common between them,
the chances of developing a general theory of crime seemed pretty slim
indeed. Some researchers tried to reformulate their subject matter as
deviant behaviour, anti-social conduct or the violation of conduct norms.
At least these, defined by the researcher rather than the state, might have
enough in common to make generalisations possible.
As we shall see, the years of effort in attempting to develop such
theories took their toll. Eventually, some gave up the quest altogether and
explored other avenues. If crime was simply that which has been
designated as such by the criminal law, why not study how this comes
about? Why not look at the criminal law itself as socially created, in
particular social, economic and political circumstances? The variability
and the political nature of criminal law were no longer problems hamper-
ing progress, but something to be investigated. From this perspective,

11
Introducing Criminology

crime was defined in particular historical circumstances, as a result of the


activities of agents with varying degrees of power. Here were new
processes and topics for investigation. In this view, criminal law was a
social construction (rather than a set of given rules, violation from which
was the principal topic for study). According to one version of this per-
spective it can be viewed as a collection of ‘negative ideological categories
with specific historical applications ... categories of denunciation or abuse
lodged within very complex, historically loaded practical conflicts and
moral debates ... these negative categories of moral ideology are social
censures’ (Sumner 1990: 26, 28).
If criminal law was a social construction ripe for investigation, so were
crime and the criminal. How do some acts and persons come to be
designated as criminal by the criminal justice system, out of a pool of
possible candidates? Here we are speaking of social processes that
produce recorded crimes, suspects, charged persons, prosecutions and
various outcomes, such as discharges or prison sentences. These processes
can be studied to see precisely how crimes and criminals are ‘produced’.
Seen in this way, crime and the criminal are the focus for investigation, but
in a very different way from the traditional approach with its search for the
causes of crime. For example, it asks such questions as what impact do
race, class and gender have on whether an individual becomes a suspect
for crime? The approach described briefly here is concerned with the
processes of criminalisation. Such an approach focused attention on who
made the rules, and who enforced them, rather than merely on who broke
them; as we shall see in Chapter 3, it began to take on increasing
importance in the study of crime, largely as a result of that body of work
which came to be known as the labelling perspective, particularly through
the writings of its best known proponent, Howard Becker (1963).
Taken to extremes, such an approach can result in an equally blinkered
approach to that found in traditional criminology. With its primary focus
upon the process of criminalisation, it can lead to a neglect of the original
action of the offender, its meaning and the reasons behind it. It is also
important that the study of criminalisation should be supplemented by
study of those areas that frequently escaped the attention of the conven-
tional criminal justice system and often criminology too, such as child
abuse, domestic violence, corporate/white-collar ‘crime’, and crimes of
the state such as torture, ‘disappearances’, ethnic cleansing and genocide.
Perhaps it is helpful to distinguish three questions which have frequently
been confused in debates:
• what is crime?
• what should be criminal?
• what should criminologists study?

12
Crime, the criminal and criminology

These questions are still important in contemporary criminology, and


are frequently revisited, especially by those working from a politically
radical position and those working on areas such as corporate crime
(see, for example, Slapper and Tombs 1999: chapter 1). Such debates about
the definition of crime and the subject matter of criminology do not
preoccupy all criminologists in their everyday work; many criminologists
have taken the definition of crime and the criminal as given, whereas
others see them as problematic, that is something to be questioned and
investigated.

What is criminology?

One basic definition of criminology is that it is the study of crime and


the criminal. As we have seen above, however, criminologists are not
necessarily agreed on the definition of these two basic terms; rather than
being taken for granted, some criminologists insist that these very terms
should be seen as problematic. What this means is that we should ask the
sorts of questions that were raised in the last section. Whenever the terms
crime and criminal are used, we must be aware that there are alternative
uses of these key terms. This is not to be pedantic (although it may seem
like it), but is rather a recognition that different uses of the terms carry all
sorts of implications and baggage with them. So, if we take the position
that crime is violation of criminal law, criminals are those who have been
convicted of a criminal offence, and that these are what criminologists
should study, all sorts of implications and consequences follow from this.
On the other hand, if we say that the subject matter of criminology should
be the violation of human rights, a rather different conception of the disci-
pline comes into view. The terms ‘crime’ and ‘criminal’ should not be ac-
cepted at face value, and consideration of the definition of them is for us a
key part of the subject matter of the discipline.
Having made this basic point, it is possible to specify other aspects of
the subject matter of something that could be called ‘criminology‘ in its
widest sense.

• the attempt to describe and analyse the extent, nature, and distribution
of the various forms of ‘crime’ and ‘offenders’.
• the analysis of the ‘causes’ of crime, including the attempt to develop
theories which will help us to explain and understand it.
• the study of the formulation of criminal laws. Although this area is
often said to be part of the sociology of law rather than criminology
itself, our discussion above indicates the value of such study to
criminology.

13
Introducing Criminology

• the study of the various processes of law enforcement and criminal


justice, such as policing, sentencing, etc. The term ‘criminal justice’ is
often used to refer to the rather narrower field of the study of policy and
practice in relation to crime by various agencies, but such work is
frequently regarded as part of criminology.
• following on from the last point, the analysis of the various forms of
policy and practice in punishment. This might range from looking at
the effectiveness of different penal measures to the relationship of
different regimes of punishment to the wider society in which they are
located. This area of study is often referred to as penology.
• the study of attempts to control, reduce or prevent crime, by, for
example, altering aspects of the situations in which it occurs, ‘treating’
individual offenders, or implementing broad social policies. There is
clearly some overlap here with the study of criminal justice processes
and punishment listed above.
• investigation of the victims of crime – the extent, distribution and
nature of victimisation; their role in crime and criminal justice and
policy issues concerning them. This area is frequently referred to as
victimology.
• attitudes and reactions to, and representations of, crime on the part of
groups not already mentioned, such as the general public, politicians
and the mass media.
This list is not exhaustive, but does give an indication of the range of
possible areas of study. In addition, there has been increasing recognition
that the study of crime and the criminal often cannot be easily separated
off from the other elements. This was one implication of our discussion of
definitions. Those who use official statistics of crime, for example, have to
take on board that those statistics are the product of the actions of suspects,
victims, members of the public, and the police as agents of criminal justice.
In order to do this, the actions of those agents have to be understood,
together with any interaction between them (Coleman and Moynihan
1996). To focus on only one of these produces a partial criminology (Young
1997: 485).
However, it is important to note that people engaged in some of the
activities listed above will not necessarily see them as ‘criminology’, or
describe themselves as criminologists. They might prefer to see them-
selves, for example, as sociologists or psychologists with an interest in
crime and associated areas; they identify themselves with that discipline
rather than with criminology. In addition, perhaps because of the history
of criminology and its traditionally rather narrow focus (see below), many
are anxious to avoid being identified too closely with it. We now look
briefly at relationships between criminology and a range of academic
disciplines and at that history.
14
Crime, the criminal and criminology

A multi-disciplinary discipline?
Criminology is often described as a multi-disciplinary enterprise (Garland
1997: 19; Lanier and Henry 1998: 5). What this means is that ‘criminolo-
gists draw upon a variety of other disciplines, most notably sociology,
psychology, psychiatry, law, history, and anthropology – indeed, one of the
major dynamics of modern criminology is the incessant raiding of other
disciplines or ideologies for new ideas ...’ (Garland 1997: 19). To these
disciplines could be added those of biology, geography, economics, and
political science, all of which have made forays into the subject or have
been raided in the way that Garland suggests. Two points follow from this.
One is that this promiscuity – the frequent intercourse with a variety of
partners – can make life both interesting and difficult. Variety may be the
spice of life, but each of these disciplines tends to have its own assump-
tions, basic ideas and concepts, a bank of shared knowledge, a particular
focus of inquiry, favoured methods of investigation, and a view of the
world which leads to particular kinds of policy implications. Disciplines
are also internally diverse, harbouring different perspectives within them
(see, for example, the various approaches in psychology and sociology
discussed in Chapters 2 and 3). All of this makes for a very diverse but
intellectually challenging subject. Few criminologists are equally at ease
with all of these disciplines.
The second point concerns criminology’s claim to be a discipline at all.
Is the enterprise so parasitic upon those other disciplines that it has no
right to be called one itself? Is it merely the application of a number of
other disciplines to a particular subject matter – one largely defined by the
state as a problem? Is it better seen as a field of study, rather than a
discipline as such? (Lea 1998)
While it has often been argued that criminology is not, or should not be
seen as, a discipline at all, others have taken the view that the existence of
a discipline is not merely about such matters as having a distinctive and
defensible subject matter or methods of enquiry, but also about institu-
tional foundations and structures:

its claim to be an empirically grounded, scientific undertaking sets it


apart from moral and legal discourses, while its focus upon crime
differentiates it from other social scientific genres, such as the
sociology of deviance and control, whose objects of study are
broader and not defined by the criminal law. Since the middle of this
century, criminology [in Britain] has increasingly been marked off
from other discourses by the trappings of a distinctive disciplinary
identity, with its own journals, professional associations, professor-
ships and institutes. ...such a discipline came to exist as an accredited
specialism, supported by universities and governments alike.
(Garland 1997: 11)
15
Introducing Criminology

Garland’s argument is that the reasons for the existence of criminology are
to be found in particular historical circumstances, and that its coming into
being was by no means inevitable. It is also a history that tells us a great
deal about the nature of criminology today. For one thing, this may help us
to understand why many working on studies of crime and justice do not
adopt this disciplinary identity, do not necessarily belong to the
professional associations or publish in the specialist journals.

Criminology through the ages? Lombroso and all that

Garland (1997) has suggested that criminology grew out of a convergence


between two projects – the governmental and the Lombrosian. The first
refers to ‘the long series of empirical enquries, which, since the eighteenth
century, have sought to enhance the efficient and equitable administration
of justice by charting the patterns of crime and monitoring the practice of
police and prisons’ (Garland 1997: 12). The other, the Lombrosian project,
had a differerent objective – to build a science of causes, ‘based on the
premise that criminals can somehow be scientifically differentiated from
non-criminals’ (Garland 1997: 12). This distinction captures well two
major emphases in terms of aims and objectives of the subject. The first is
primarily concerned with applied, practical matters, with policy and
governance (not necessarily by government agencies) of the population in
the widest sense, with its management and control. The other is a more
‘academic’ theoretical enterprise, the search for the ‘causes of crime’,
which in Garland’s account is tied to a particular assumption that is said to
have emerged in the work of Lombroso, and is correspondingly ‘deeply
flawed’ (Garland 1997: 12).
We begin looking at the attempt to identify differences between
criminals and non-criminals in the next chapter. The two projects, govern-
mental and Lombrosian, create a particular tension in the discipline, with
different criminologists according differing weights to them in their work.
But ‘the combination of the two seems essential to criminology’s claim to
be sufficiently useful and sufficiently scientific to merit the status of an
accredited, state-sponsored, academic discipline’ (Garland 1997: 12).
Although both projects have experienced significant changes since, the
discipline continues to be structured by them.
Garland’s detailed and stimulating account cannot be reproduced here.
It does, however, provide a useful corrective to textbook histories, which
can be so brief and sweeping that they often seem to do for criminology
what 1066 And All That (Sellar and Yeatman 1930) did, but tongue in cheek,
for history (e.g. the industrial revolution was described as a wave of
gadgets sweeping across the country). His account, which stresses
particular, historically specific features, has a number of consequences.

16
Crime, the criminal and criminology

First, although some have attempted to write a history of the discipline by


going back through history and searching for assorted writings about law-
breakers and punishment (see Drapkin 1983), these writings are not
necessarily criminology. Second, although most textbooks begin their
discussion of the subject rather later (in the eighteenth century), with what
is usually called the ‘classical school‘ of criminology, this for him makes
little sense

given that they made no general distinction between the


characteristics of criminals and non-criminals, and had no concep-
tion of research on crime and criminals as a distinctive form of
enquiry. To use such a term to characterise eighteenth century
thought seriously misrepresents the character of these writings and
forcibly assimilates them to a project that was not invented until a
century later.
(Garland 1997: 15–16)

By this analysis, although we seem to be closer to locating a birthday for


criminology, the classical school becomes the criminology that never was;
according to Garland’s definition of criminology, the classical school does
not qualify. For others, however, the classical school can be seen as ‘the
first clearly identifiable school of criminology in retrospect’ (Hughes 1998:
26). For Hughes, Garland’s defintion of criminology is too restrictive in its
emphasis on the attempt to identify the characteristics of the criminal by
scientific means. It is certainly true that criminology has made constant
reference to the classical school thoughout its short history and that its
ideas continue to appear in thinking and practice. In that sense at least, it is
certainly a perspective that we need to consider here.

The classical school


The classical school (not that they knew themselves as such) grew out of
the work of a group of ‘Enlightenment’ philosophers of the eighteenth
century, who argued that human problems should be tackled by the
application of reason, rather than tradition, religion or superstition. Their
appearance was no coincidence, but related to the social context: a Europe
in which a rising middle class was seeking to free itself from the shackles
of regimes in which the monarchy, the aristocracy and the church were
very much dominant. Some of these Enlightenment thinkers turned their
attention to the nature of the criminal law and punishment, putting
forward radical ideas for its reform. They opposed the unpredictable,
discriminatory, inhumane and ineffective criminal justice systems that
were to be found in their day, systems that often left much to the discretion
of the judges (including the frequent use of ‘mercy’ and pardons), employ-

17
Introducing Criminology

ed barbaric, cruel methods of punishment (and torture for extracting


confessions), and seemed to any intelligent observer to be very ineffective
in preventing crime.
The programme for changing this state of affairs was to produce a
system in which law and punishment were predictable, non-
discriminatory (treating all who had broken a particular law alike),
humane and effective. Thus punishment should avoid unnecessary
suffering, should be proportionate to the crime committed, follow as
certainly and quickly as possible after the offence, and be just sufficient to
act as a deterrent to the crime. As one of the most famous members of what
came to be known as the classical school put it: ‘in order for punishment
not to be, in every instance, an act of violence of one or of many against a
private citizen, it must be essentially public, prompt, necessary, the least
possible in the given circumstances, proportionate to the crimes, dictated
by the laws’ (Beccaria 1963: 99; first published 1764).
A number of writers have attempted to distil the various ideas and
assumptions thought to underlie the approach of those considered to be
members of the classical school and to arrange them under certain
headings that allow comparisons to be made with other approaches (see,
for example Young 1981; White and Haines 1996; Lanier and Henry 1998).
The story goes something like this:

Human nature
People are seen as self-interested, rational creatures (able to weigh up
competing courses of action), able to make and act in accordance with
personal choices (often described as ‘free will‘).

Conception of society or social order


Left to their own devices, people will follow their own selfish interests,
which will often conflict, resulting in a war of all against all. Because
people are rational creatures, they can see the advantages in giving up part
of their freedom to do as they please, accepting a set of laws in exchange
for protection of life and property from a sovereign or state. Thus comes
into being what was called the social contract, a basis for social order. A
violation of law is a violation of this contract and justifies the right to
punish.

Causes of crime
Since people are normally rational creatures, it seems to follow that either
the pleasure or gain from the crime outweighs the pain of punishment
associated with it, or that people are making irrational decisions for some
reason (e.g. the institutions of law or education may be sending out
‘wrong’ or confusing messages, so that people do not have the appropriate
information to make rational decisions).

18
Crime, the criminal and criminology

Implications for policy


Criminal justice should be subject to strict rule of law (due process) and
punishments should be known, fixed and just severe enough to deter.
Discretion of judges should be minimised as far as possible in sentencing.

Other headings for comparison are often included. Such frameworks are
invaluable in getting a grasp of the various perspectives and their basic
concepts. There are, however, one or two limitations. First, such outlines
are the product of a great deal of simplification; complexity and variety is
often lost. We must not expect all of the thinkers who are grouped together
under such labels to subscribe to identical ideas. Furthermore, the attempt
to provide satisfying contrasts between classicism and its opponent in the
nineteenth century (positivism) sometimes goes too far. For example,
Beirne (1993) has argued that, contrary to popular belief, Beccaria (the
most frequently given example of a ‘classical’ thinker), did not subscribe to
a view of humans as endowed with ‘free will’ and ‘rational choice’, but
was concerned with ‘the application to crime and penal strategies of the
“science of man,” a deterministic discourse implicitly at odds with the
conventional assumption about ... “classical criminology“ ‘ (Beirne 1993:
5). Beirne suggests that Beccaria was involved in a very rudimentary
attempt to forge some key concepts of an embryonic criminology. These
concepts include “crime,” “criminal,” and “causes of crime” ‘ (Beirne 1993:
44). Perhaps unborn as yet, but the embryo was in place?
There is little doubt that the ideas of the classical school were very
influential in the field of law, criminal justice and penal strategies.
Criminal justice systems, especially those of western societies, often
incorporated elements of the classical programme. Putting such principles
into practice raised some problems, however. One concerned the assump-
tion that all people were equal before the law and able to make equally
rational decisions. What about, for example, children and those suffering
from mental illness? Pure classicism, with its focus upon the crime rather
than the offender, seemed to be oblivious to the differences between
individuals which might influence notions of their culpability for a crime.
Revisions to the classical scheme were therefore made in various legal
systems, such as provision for the consideration of ‘mitigating circum-
stances’ (elements from the history and current situation of the person),
that could be seen as affecting the operation of free will and rationality on
the part of the individual. The resulting amalgam of classical and other
principles is often referred to as neo-classicism.
A second main problem concerns the nature of society. Classical theory
urges that all are equal before the law, but how is this to work when society
itself is characterised by major inequalities? First, we might ask whether
inequalities in the wider society are themselves involved in the origins of
crime – a possibility that is not fully considered by the framework.

19
Introducing Criminology

Secondly, it is often remarked that people with resources of various kinds


(such as education, or access to the best legal representation) are more able
to benefit from a criminal justice system which in principle treats all as
equal before the law. Finally, if a poor person is to be punished with equal
punishment as a rich person for the same offence (e.g. by a fine), this
attempt to treat individuals equally may have more serious consequences
for the former, who may thus be punished disproportionately. In an un-
equal society, the promise of equality before the law is very difficult to
deliver in practice.

The moral statisticians


The main focus of the classical school was upon the reform of the criminal
law according to certain principles. A rather different focus was taken up
by the group of scholars who emerged early in the nineteenth century, and
attempted to apply the methods and techniques which had mostly been
developed in the natural sciences to ‘moral’ (social) phenomena. Their
work was facilitated by the publication of national crime statistics in
France, which first appeared in 1827. The appearance of such statistics was
an aspect of the development of the ‘governmental project’ referred to
earlier, a project which concerned itself with the governance (managing
and regulating) of the people, especially what were often described as the
‘dangerous classes’ (Hacking 1990). Such statistics can be seen as a way of
assessing the nature and extent of the ‘problem’ and monitoring the
reponse to it. Adolphe Quetelet was one of the best known of the moral
statisticians, and conducted extensive analyses of those statistics, includ-
ing the influence of the seasons, climate and sex, on the ‘propensity to
crime’. His work revealed a remarkable consistency in patterns of re-
corded crime, suggesting that crime was subject to the same kinds of laws
that were being established in the natural sciences:

every thing which pertains to the human species considered as a


whole, belongs to the order of physical facts: the greater the number
of individuals, the more does the influence of individual will dis-
appear, leaving predominance to a series of general facts, dependent
on causes by which society exists and is preserved ... we shall
determine their influence on society, just in the same way as we
determine effects by their causes in physical science
(Quetelet 1842, in Muncie et al 1996: 27–28)

Quetelet came to the conclusion that the causes of crime were to be found
in aspects of social organisation, and that it was up to ‘legislators’ to
identify and remove them as far as possible. In their attempt to use
methods modelled on the natural sciences, and to identify causes of crime

20
Crime, the criminal and criminology

that could be stated in the same manner as the laws of those sciences, the
moral statisticians have some claim to have been founders of a ‘scientific’
study of crime. However, they had no conception of a scientific specialism
that could be separated off from other areas of study. The accolade of
founder of ‘scientific’ criminology has usually been awarded to Cesare
Lombroso. Very different from the moral statisticians, Lombroso’s focus
was upon the individual criminal, whom he thought could be the object of
study for a new discipline.

The Italian positive school


While equally determined to place his studies on a scientific basis,
Lombroso’s (1876) early work owed most to biology, especially the work
of Charles Darwin on the evolution of species. Through extensive
measurements of convicted criminals, he claimed to have discovered
physical differences in their anatomical make-up. These he likened to
features to be found in ‘savages’ and apes. Lombroso concluded that
criminals were ‘throw-backs’ to an earlier stage of human evolution; they
were atavistic. These sorts of ideas gave the criminal a new social
significance. If criminals were lower in the evolutionary scale, they – along
with others – raised the spectre of degeneration, and could be seen as a
threat to the evolutionary process and candidates for such measures as
isolation, prevention from breeding and so on (Nye 1984; Pick 1989).
Lombroso’s ideas were in many ways consistent with those of others of his
time, who drew attention to the study of the ancestry of offenders and the
notion that physical features were an indication of a person’s character or
‘type’ (see also Jayewardene 1963, for the view that certain English prison
doctors anticipated some of Lombroso’s ideas).
Lombroso’s intial ideas and research studies were heavily criticised in
his own lifetime, and he had modified his views considerably by the end of
his career. His colleagues, Ferri and Garofalo, stressed the idea that crime
has many causes, and that it is important to look at psychological and
social causes as well as biological ones. The work of the Italian Positive
School should be seen in a broader context. It sought to distinguish itself
from the classical school in particular, stressing the superiority of its
‘scientific‘ approach to what it claimed was the pre-scientific approach of
the classical school, which was to some extent caricatured. Here is a
debate between not only two sets of ideas, but two interest groups –
judges, legislators, lawyers in the classical camp, and a new breed of
scientific experts in the positivist camp – vying for dominance. For the
positivists:

• The idea that people were endowed with free will was mocked as being
untenable. Human behaviour was determined by a range of factors.

21
Introducing Criminology

• The ideas of the classical school were derided as being rooted in


metaphysical speculation, while positivism was rooted in the search for
evidence, using the methods of scientific investigation, such as observa-
tion and measurement.
• Punishments for crime, based on the principles of the classical school,
were outdated and barbaric (since people could no longer be seen as
responsible for their actions in the way envisaged by that school). The
new experts could be far more humane and effective in crime control.
Policy and practice would therefore involve the application of science,
aimed at the prevention and treatment of criminality.

If Lombroso’s work on attempting to identify human ‘types’ was part of


an already established tradition of research, the idea of a distinctive
science of the criminal was new:

His conception of the criminal as a naturally occuring entity – a fact


of nature rather than a social or legal product – led Lombroso to the
thought of a natural science which would focus on this entity, trace
its characteristics, its stigmata, its abnormalities, and eventually
identify the causes which make one person a criminal and another a
normal citizen.
(Garland 1997: 30)

What was remarkable was how, from such initial ideas, there grew an
international movement, calling itself criminology, in order to distinguish
its broader vision from the criminal anthropology of Lombroso himself,
the specific notions of which were soon discredited. Garland (1985, 1997)
suggests that among the reasons behind its popularity and growth
towards the end of the nineteenth century are the following:

• the development of various forms of statistical data, such as the kind


that had already been exploited by the moral statisticians;
• the advances in, and increasing prestige of, the discipline of psychiatry;
• it connected with, and gave scientific respectability to, prejudices and
fears about the ‘dangerous classes‘ in the expanding cities;
• it offered new possibilities for the scientific, expert and seemingly
humane regulation of the population for governments and administra-
tors, when existing strategies were perceived as failing;
• the development of the prison in the nineteenth century provided a
context within which it could develop as a practical form of knowledge,
with the individual criminal a readily available and ‘obvious‘ object of
study.
22
Crime, the criminal and criminology

The British context


According to Garland (1997), the new movement initially had relatively
little impact in Britain. More significant in the context of Britain was the
work of the developing discipline of psychiatry and that of certain prison
doctors, whose work was also focused on criminals as objects of study, but
set in a very practical context (the everyday demands of the criminal
justice system and the prisons) compared to the more ambitious en-
deavours of Lombroso and his colleagues. Although they were concerned
with the range of psychological conditions that criminals (and others)
could exhibit, there was by this time generally resistance to the idea of the
criminal as a distinctive type of person (Garland 1997: 35) and to the
criminology that had emerged on the continent that initially had this
notion as its justification. Rather than consciously trying to give birth to a
new science or discipline, they were more concerned with some pressing
practical problems, such as how to classify offenders and how to make
sense of those who would not respond to prison discipline. Only after the
extravagant claims of Lombroso had been undermined, in the period
leading up to the First World War, did such researchers begin to describe
their work as criminological – in the wider sense of scientific research on
crime and criminals – work that was nevertheless still largely moulded by
medical and legal concerns.
One major exception to the early British tradition is the study by
Goring, The English Convict (1913), which illustrates well the application of
methods that would be approved by the new positivism, such as large
samples, use of control groups, meticulous measurement, and advanced
statistical techniques well beyond those used by Lombroso. Whilst
refuting the precise notions of Lombroso’s physical criminal type, Goring
concludes that there is a ‘physical, mental, and moral type of normal
person who tends to be convicted of crime’ (quoted in Pick 1989: 187) – a
person of poor physique and mental capacity. Not departing so dramatic-
ally from Lombroso as often thought, Goring’s book also contains a case
against the idea that crime is largely due to environmental factors, as
argued by Quetelet and others. Goring’s affinity with the ideas of the
eugenics movement, and its concern with improving the ‘stock’ of
humankind, was consistent with his view that key factors could be
inherited and that policies should take this into account (see Beirne 1993:
chapter 6).
Much criminological research that was to follow can be seen as an
attempt to find to what extent crime was due to nature (inherent proper-
ties of the individual) or nurture (environmental factors). In particular,
there were sustained attempts to find biological, psychological and social
causes for crime, an enterprise that we examine in the next two chapters.
What seemed to be agreed was that scientific methods were the route to

23
Introducing Criminology

take in discovering these causes. Although contested, especially in the


second half of the twentieth century, the claim (or the quest) to be a science
has frequently been a key element in criminology’s attempt to distinguish
itself from other discourses on crime.

Conclusion

It seems agreed that the infant discipline was with us at least by the fourth
quarter of the nineteenth century, but there has been some confusion over
both its birthday and parentage. Many commentators have suggested that
Lombroso was the father of the infant, a sickly child who was nursed into
relative health by others. But the child needed a name. Lombroso’s own
preference was eventually brushed aside – he was increasingly seen as a
suspect guardian for the infant discipline – and the name criminology
emerged, probably, it now seems, the idea of one of its godfathers,
Garafalo in 1885 (Beirne 1993: 235). The kind of academic enterprise
favoured by the Italian positive school was certainly the first to bear the
name of criminology. While the classical school, the moral statisticians and
the practical efforts of psychiatrists and prison doctors had already
produced offspring with rather different perspectives, which still have
some resonance in contemporary criminology, Lombroso was certainly
influential in moulding the character of a criminology at the end of the
nineteenth century as a separate scientific discipline with a particular
focus on the criminal.
There is one history of criminology which portrays it as a succession of
perspectives, usually beginning with the classical school, through the
work of the moral statisticians, to the work of Lombroso and his col-
leagues and beyond. This view suggests that there has been a long
connected sequence of reflections on a given topic. In a loose definition of
the subject, these are all forms of ‘criminology’. Alternatively, criminology
proper is seen as emerging as these reflections shift from the speculative to
the scientific. For others, such as Garland (1997), these histories will not do
at all. For him, the development of criminology as a specialised form of
enquiry, engaged in the scientific study of ‘the criminal’, an object of study
that was not given but constructed in a particular way, was the product of
particular historical circumstances. The study of crime and justice could
have been continued by a wide range of parties, from different disciplines
and agencies, without the formation of a criminology as such (the
argument that a separate discipline of criminology is neither necessary nor
desirable is still to be heard). Instead, the idea of a specialist discipline,
focused on the study of the criminal, emerged in Europe at the end of the
nineteenth century. Although based on a notion of the criminal that was to
be discredited, this did not stop its rapid development.

24
Crime, the criminal and criminology

In Britain, however, although research on criminals had been estab-


lished in the nineteenth century, a university-based discipline did not exist
before the mid-1930s, and it was not until the late 1950s and early 1960s
that the conditions existed for its consolidation and development –
primarily in the form of government decisions (driven by their own
particular concerns) to fund criminological research both in the Home
Office and in the university. For Garland (1997), it is when we see a coming
together of the governmental, administrative project and the academic,
scientific project (allied with the view that the latter can contribute to the
former) that we begin to see the emergence of criminology as a viable
independent discipline here.
There was an extraordinary growth in the discipline in the last three
decades of the twentieth century – both in the teaching of the subject in the
universities, where there are now many degree programmes, depart-
ments, professorships and specialist journals, and in research, within and
outside the universities. This growth has taken place within a context of an
expanding higher education sector, but also within a social and political
context where there are pressing concerns about crime, victims, the
criminal justice system, prisons, and so on. Criminology is shaped by such
concerns and by its relationship with government, its policies and
institutions.
This close relationship with the governmental project has clearly been
not only a major source of growth for the discipline, but has also
fundamentally affected its nature over the years. This is a major reason
why some scholars are fundamentally critical of much criminology. For
them, that close relationship with the governmental project is too narrow
and restrictive, and leads to what is often rather dismissively called
‘administrative criminology’ – in which the main concern is with policy-
relevant research aimed at controlling and reducing crime and improving
the effectiveness of the criminal justice system. According to such critics,
there is also a need for a broader, critical perspective on crime and justice
that is not limited in this way (see Muncie 2000, for a recent example,
arguing that criminology should focus on ‘social harms’ rather than crime,
and social justice rather than criminal justice).
This chapter began with some apparently straightforward questions:
what is crime? who is the criminal? what is criminology? what is its
history? We have seen that there is more than one possible answer to each
of these questions. Furthermore, the answers are interlinked, for the
answer to one question has implications for the others. Considering such
questions is not a waste of time, but raises key issues about criminology
today and its future.

25
Introducing Criminology

Chapter 2

Offenders and non-offenders:


spot the difference?

Since the early days of their discipline, many criminologists have played
the game of ‘spot the difference’ between offenders and non-offenders. If
differences could be found, it was thought that these would hold the key
to developing a theory (a systematic account of the causes) of crime, as
well as opening up the possibility of an intervention before a crime is com-
mitted. We have seen how Lombroso became famous, and then infamous,
for his attempts to find biological differences between the two groups.
Although Lomboro’s specific ideas were largely discredited, this did not
stop the attempt to continue the broad tradition of searching for biological
differences in the twentieth century. Others have looked for differences in
terms of psychology; here the differences sought may be, for example, in
terms of types of personality, one or more of which may be suggested as
having a propensity to crime in general, or to a certain kind of crime.
In their extreme form, approaches which concentrate on characteristics
of the person (whether they are biological or psychological in their focus)
are what Albert Cohen (1966: 43) called ‘kinds of people theories’ of crime
or deviance. They lead to the question ‘How did they get that way?’ The
answer to this may be, for example, in terms of heredity, or some accident
resulting in brain damage, or a distinctive form of personality develop-
ment or learning. At the other extreme, there are those approaches that
seem to suggest that people who commit crime are not special kinds of
people at all, but that we should look to the situation or circumstances in
which people are located in order to explain crime. The key differences to
spot, such as various kinds of stresses or frustrations, the presence of
significant opportunities to commit crime, pressure to conform to group
expectations, or the absence of effective sanctions to deter crime, lie in the
context, rather than in the person. Sociological approaches to crime, which
are considered in the next chapter, frequently take this view.

26
Offenders and non-offenders: spot the difference?

Such a neat division between approaches which focus on the person


and those that focus on the situation merely gives us two extreme types. In
practice, there is frequent overlap. First, some theories suggest that the
causes of crime lie in a conjunction of a particular kind of person with
particular sets of circumstances; for example, some people might respond
to extreme frustration by violence against others, but some will not.
Second, a moment’s reflection should reveal that the division between
person and circumstances cannot be a rigid one; circumstances and
experiences in the past are frequently seen as having a way of getting
‘inside’ the person, leaving an imprint that affects their future conduct.
Finally, many researchers now take the view that the search for a simple
theory of crime (as in some earlier attempts to ‘spot the difference’) is a
misguided quest; what we call crime is a varied phenomenon and the
result of a highly complex process of interaction between a multiplicity of
elements. The objective should therefore be to understand the complex
processes that seem to result in an increased probability of crime. The
identification of ‘risk factors’ that seem to be more common among
groups of offenders is an important, but modified, version of ‘spot the
difference’. Bearing this in mind, we begin by looking at attempts to
identify biological factors in crime, before moving on to efforts at the level
of psychology.

Biological approaches
Physical characteristics and crime
There has been an enduring search for the causes of crime from the
discipline of biology in the twentieth century. First, there has been a
continuing interest in the possibility of a link between physical charac-
teristics and crime. Researchers have therefore continued to measure the
bodily characteristics of ‘criminals’ (usually convicted persons) and
compared them with control groups of the ‘normal’ population (on the
assumption, of course, that these would be largely people who had not
committed crime). Hooton’s (1939) study along these lines was very much
like Lombroso’s early work in its notion that criminals were an ‘inferior’
type of person who could be identified by certain measurable bodily
characteristics. Others introduced the idea of body types (somatotypes),
which were thought to be linked to temperament (Kretschmer 1936), and
then to the propensity to commit crime (Sheldon 1949). A number of
studies which explored these ideas came up with the finding that the
‘criminal’ group tended to cluster within a certain body type – in the
mesomorphic grouping, the lean and muscular type said to have an
assertive temperament. Such a correlation (a statistical association
between body type and crime) is open to rather different interpretations,

27
Introducing Criminology

such as that muscular individuals would be more likely to be attracted to


and better equipped to participate in activities that reward strength and
toughness.

Twin studies
There was also an attempt to explore the genetic contribution to crime.
This was done in two main ways: twin studies and adoption studies. Twin
studies are a classic way of attempting to assess the relative contribution of
heredity and environment to a trait or behaviour. There are two sorts of
twins: monozygotic and dizygotic. Monozygotic twins (commonly
referred to as identical twins) come from the same egg and share the same
genetic makeup. Dizygotic twins, on the other hand, are from different
eggs, fertilised in the womb at about the same time. They share less of their
genetic makeup with each other. It is known that certain traits (such as hair
or eye colour) tend to be shared by monozygotic twins, but not so
frequently by dizygotic twins. The reason for this is that such traits are
under the control of the genetic make-up, which monozygotic twins have
in common, thus creating a high degree of correspondence (called
concordance) for such traits.
If it could be shown that there are higher concordance rates for criminal-
ity in monozygotic twins than in dizygotic twins, wouldn’t this suggest
that there was a strong genetic component to crime? A number of studies
conducted over the years, some of them much more sophisticated than
others, have come up with the finding that the concordance rates for crime
(usually measured by official convictions) are higher for identical twins
than those for other twin pairs (see, for example, the overview in Raine
1993). Contemporary researchers do not claim that there is a ‘crime gene’,
but this evidence does lead some to suggest that a genetic factor is
influencing the propensity to crime. Again, this is a correlation, and an
interesting one at that. Alternative interpretations have been suggested,
such as that identical twins may be more alike in this way and in other
forms of behaviour because, on the whole, they may be treated more alike
in their upbringing. That is, the explanation for the higher concordance
could be environmental rather than genetic. Researchers in this tradition
have sometimes conducted a slightly different type of study in order to
provide more evidence.

Studies of adoptees
Studies of adoptees track the development of siblings who have been
separated at an early age. Identical twins would be ideal for such research,
but separations of these are unusual and such studies are therefore rare.
Siblings share a genetic make-up to a significant degree, but are thus
exposed to different environments. The researchers then examine the

28
Offenders and non-offenders: spot the difference?

relationship between the criminal convictions of the adoptees and the


convictions of the biological and adoptive parents. For example, one
Danish study (Mednick et al 1987) found a stronger relationship between
the criminal convictions of biological parents and their adopted-away
children than that between the adopting parents and the children. The
relationship was particularly strong for chronic offending and was found
to hold in the face of a variety of methodological criticisms and alternative
interpretations, which had bedevilled many earlier studies of this type.
They conclude that some factor is being transmitted from the biological
parents to their children, and that this factor must be biological, although
accepting the important interaction with social factors.
Similar findings were reported by a Swedish study (Bohman et al 1982).
If the conclusions made are well founded, there needs to be detailed
investigation of what exactly is being genetically transmitted and the
processes through which it influences behaviour such as crime, difficult
issues that are not tackled by such studies. Perhaps for this reason, another
tradition of research in this area has attempted to explore the physiological
processes and mechanisms, especially those involved in the functioning of
the nervous system, that might help us to understand criminal and ‘anti-
social behaviour’.

The new biology of crime


Researchers have investigated the EEG (electroencephalogram) readings
of offenders; examined their emotional responsiveness by measuring their
heart rate, blood-pressure, breathing patterns and sweat secretion; charted
their hormone, neurotransmitter and blood sugar levels. Others have
attempted to forge a link between defects in the functioning of the brain
and offending, focusing, for example, on:

• epilepsy and its possible link with offending;


• the role of head injuries in possibly producing such syndromes as
‘hyperactivity’ (attention deficit disorder) and delinquency;
• the possibility that offenders are deficient in certain skills, especially
those related to language, which happen to be controlled by a certain
part of the brain.

Although this list may seem rather a rag-bag of topics, recent research has
been more clearly directed to explore the role of such processes in creating
differences in personality, learning, motivation and the processing of
information and thus in impulsivity, aggression, emotional responsive-
ness and stimulus-seeking behaviour, with a particular focus upon the
‘psychopathic personality’ (see chapter 4) and the notion that this may
have a biological basis.
29
Introducing Criminology

A recent book on this area of study ends with what Rutter et al (1998:
127) describe as ‘over-the-top’ claims:

the evidence is overwhelming that crime is in large part due to


problems in the brain, that these problems are what distinguish the
criminal few from the mischievous many and that they can be
identified early on and, to an as yet unknown degree, treated. Many
will protest that our new understanding of the brain’s biology takes a
drably determinist view of human nature. It doesn’t ... . Biology
dictates destiny only if it is ignored.
(Moir and Jessel 1995: 332)

By contrast, another text, which looks carefully at the research studies


conducted in this area with a much greater awareness of methodological
and other limitations, suggests that ‘the role played by biological
processes in crime is likely to be relatively modest and indirect ... [but] the
evidence to date is sufficient to indicate that criminology cannot ignore the
relevance of a biological level of analysis’ (Blackburn 1993: 137).
What is most striking is the way in which some sociological texts give
very little attention and credibility to the biological perspective. One
possible reason is the technical nature of many of the studies: the literature
can be difficult to fathom. There is a natural preference for one’s own
discipline. Psychology, on the other hand, has an important interface with
this material (often referred to as psychobiology) and most texts include a
discussion of biological factors in crime (see, for example, Feldman 1993;
Hollin 1989). But the stance taken by some sociologists is grounded in
philosophical, methodological and other objections. One argument is that
such work has been positivist in nature:

• that it is determinist in its assumptions, giving no role to human


purpose and meaning;
• that it claims to use the methods akin to those of the natural sciences,
methods that are inappropriate to the study of social life;
• that conflicts of value and interest in society are ignored and a
consensus model of society is assumed, in which, for example, the
definition of crime or anti-social behaviour is not seen as problematic
(on these points see, for example, Taylor, Walton and Young 1973: 31–
40).

Furthermore, it is often suggested that a biological perspective takes


attention away from the wider social, economic and political context and
its importance in understanding crime. Despite the claims of biologists to
accept interaction between the biological and the social, there is still

30
Offenders and non-offenders: spot the difference?

sometimes resistance from sociologists to their individually-based, clinical


approach, which seems to turn social problems into medical issues and
leaves such matters as the structure of inequalities in the wider society
unexamined. This may suit established interests in that society very nicely
indeed, but runs counter to the perspectives of many sociologists, who
also frequently adhere to egalitarian principles. Finally, concerns are often
expressed about the way that such ideas might be used, especially given
past history, in which, for example, ways of preventing ‘criminals’ (and
others) from reproducing themselves have frequently been advocated.
The use of drugs, surgery and, perhaps in the future, genetic screening to
identify ‘risky’ individuals in this and other areas, raises many complex
and controversial issues. As such, the new biology of crime is a body of
work that criminologists need to engage with on an informed basis.

Psychological approaches

There is sometimes confusion about the nature and scope of psychology


and its relationship to psychiatry and psychoanalysis. While psychology is
a discipline which seeks an understanding of all human behaviour and
mental processes, psychiatry has been concerned with the more special-
ised understanding and treatment of those with mental illnesses or
disorders. Psychiatry in Britain has its roots in the ‘psychological medi-
cine’ or ‘alienism’ of the middle of the nineteenth century. It maintained its
links with medicine, and psychiatrists in Britain still receive a foundation
in medicine before proceeding to train in the discipline. As Garland (1985)
makes clear, the emerging discipline of psychiatry had a close relationship
with criminology. Although it was accepted from an early date that most
prisoners were not mad or insane in the popular sense, much early
research on crime and offenders was carried out in Britain by psychiatrists
and prison physicians, who commonly held the view that many offenders
suffered from mental illness or abnormality when those terms are given a
broader meaning to include ‘moral disorders’ (Johnstone 1996), and who
tailored their work to the administrative needs of the system in which they
worked. The result was an ‘institutionally based, medico-legal crimin-
ology, which predominated in Britain for much of the nineteenth and the
first half of the twentieth century’ (Garland 1997: 38), concerned with
practical tasks, such as ‘the giving of evidence before courts of law, or the
decisions as to classification, diagnosis, and regimen which prison medical
officers made daily’ (Garland 1997: 36). This focus contrasted with the
broader, theory building ambitions of criminology on the continent of
Europe and in the USA.
According to Blackburn (1993: 32), early academic psychology took
little interest in crime. Most psychological research was done by those

31
Introducing Criminology

prison doctors we have just encountered, until the very influential work
by Cyril Burt (1925), published as The Young Delinquent. This work, based
on extensive statistical analysis of the characteristics and background of
400 schoolchildren, took the view that delinquency was the outcome of
various combinations of factors, from a long list of possibilities, operating
in each case (a multi-factor approach). He concluded that poor discipline,
poor relationships in the family, and particular types of temperament were
especially important.
Reflecting a rather different tradition was the establishment of the
Institute for the Study and Treatment of Delinquency (ISTD) in 1931, and
its associated Psychopathic Clinic in 1933 (later renamed the Portman
Clinic). What was significant about these developments was the influence
within them of psychoanalytic ideas. Psychoanalysis represents one par-
ticular perspective within psychology which by no means has been
subscribed to by all psychologists. It is therefore time to briefly survey the
major perspectives in the discipline which have attempted to aid the
understanding of crime. As ever, the divisions between them are never
entirely clear cut, and there is considerable diversity within each. What is
presented here is a little like a set of quick sketches of some old friends.
Atkinson et al (1993: 7) suggest that there are five major perspectives in
modern psychology. Any topic in the discipline, such as learning or crime,
can be approached by one or more of these.
• The biological perspective attempts to understand behaviour by
reference to electrical and chemical processes taking place within the
body, especially in the brain and nervous system. We have already
encountered this approach in our consideration of the biological level of
analysis above.
• The psychoanalytic approach takes the view that people have a
complex inner mental life, much of which takes place at an unconscious
level, and which holds the key to understanding behaviour. Pheno-
mena as diverse as dreams and emotional problems can have deeper
meanings which can be uncovered by the analyst.
• The behavioural perspective, most associated with the work of
Skinner. The focus is primarily upon overt behaviour, its observable
antecedents and consequences, rather than upon internal processes, as
is the case with the first two approaches. Few psychologists today
would describe themselves as behaviourists, but the influence of the
approach has been considerable.
• The cognitive approach has developed strongly in recent years, and
was partly a response to the narrowness of the behaviourist approach.
It is explicitly concerned with mental processes, such as perception,
memory, decision-making and problem-solving.

32
Offenders and non-offenders: spot the difference?

• The phenomenological perspective focuses upon describing the sub-


jective experiences of people, rather than upon theories and prediction.
Some of these approaches are called humanistic, in that they focus upon
those features which are distinctive to people rather than animals (note
that much research in psychology has been conducted on animals), and
some of which are said to reject the use of ‘scientific methods’ to under-
stand human nature. In stating that ‘to assume that problems of mind
and behaviour can be solved by discarding all that we have learned
about scientific methods of investigation seems fallacious’ (Atkinson et
al 1993: 12), these writers are reflecting a very common view within
psychology.

Unfortunately, it is not possible to find theories of crime that cor-


respond exactly with these five perspectives. In fact, psychologists have
taken relatively little interest in crime as such, preferring to concentrate
upon such topics as aggression or sexual deviation. The most self-
contained group of theories is the psychoanalytic, and we start with these.
We then look at a number of attempts to see crime as a result of learning
processes. It is here that we begin to see the different approaches adopted
by behaviourist and cognitive perspectives.

Psychoanalytic approaches
Although these approaches trace their ancestry to Freud, we should not
expect those under this heading always to agree with him, or with each
other. Certain common ideas can be identified which seem relevant in the
context of crime.

• Children are born with certain antisocial and pleasure-seeking


impulses and successful socialisation depends upon the development
of an internal agency (such as the ‘superego’) which will regulate
conduct in line with group standards.
• For this socialisation to occur successfully depends on satisfactory
parent–child relationships.
• Disturbed or unsatisfactory relationships with the parents at different
stages of development will result in unconscious conflicts within the
child, which will result in problems of various kinds in later life.
• The nature of the problem, one of which may be crime, depends on the
nature of those problematic relationships and the stage of development
in which they occurred.

Such ideas enjoyed considerable popularity in the first half of the


twentieth century, before falling out of favour within criminology.

33
Introducing Criminology

Aichhorn (1955, originally published 1925), Alexander and Staub (1931)


and Alexander and Healy (1935) subscribed to the notion that criminals
were those who had been unsuccessful in the movement from the infantile
‘pleasure principle’ to the ‘reality principle’ that normally governed the
conduct of adults. Healy and Bronner (1936) saw crime as the result of
inner dissatisfactions, with their roots in a failure to experience a strong
emotional bond with another person, usually a parent. Delinquency was
the acting out or the sublimation (channelling into another form) of these
inner processes. Glover (1960) suggested that psychopaths are persons
whose superego development has been prematurely arrested, with hostile
identifications with parent(s), who have failed to satisfy the child’s
‘dependency needs’.
But probably the best known of those who were indebted to such ideas
was John Bowlby (although there were other major influences on his
work) and his theory of maternal deprivation. This was originally based
on his study of 44 juvenile thieves who had been referred to a child
guidance clinic; these were compared with a matched group of other
children attending the clinic for whom there had been no reports of
stealing (Bowlby 1944). The ‘thieving’ group were found to have much
higher rates of separation from their mothers for six months or more in the
first five years of life. This led Bowlby to conclude that a warm and
unbroken relationship with a mother or permanent mother substitute was
necessary for mental health, and that such separation was responsible for
many of the more serious cases of delinquency.
Unfortunately, a larger and more ambitious study (Bowlby et al 1956)
failed to come up with clinching evidence for the theory, and the earlier
study in particular came in for some heavy criticism, especially over the
methodology employed: the samples were not representative, the com-
parison group was poorly matched, and the assessment of the children
may well have been unreliable (for example, it was conducted by people
who were aware which children were ‘delinquent’ and which were not,
knowledge which might well have affected those assessments).
However, these ideas helped to stimulate a body of research on the role
of family background, focusing at first and rather narrowly on broken
homes, but eventually broadening out into studies of a whole range of
factors, such as those affecting the quality of upbringing and its impact on
delinquency (see Feldman 1993: 184–205 and Blackburn 1993: 160–173)
One expert in the field (Rutter 1972; 1981) concluded that the concept of
maternal deprivation had outlived its usefulness, and that separation per
se was not important for later delinquency, although a failure to form any
attachment to the carer was.
Assessments of the contribution of psychoanalytic perspectives to the
understanding of crime have ranged from the general to the specific. It has
been remarked that these ideas do not help us much in understanding the

34
Offenders and non-offenders: spot the difference?

age distribution of crime, particularly the way in which crime reduces


after a peak in the mid or late teens. Similarly with the finding that women
have much lower crime rates then men. Blackburn (1993: 115) notes that
since Freud maintained that men resolve the oedipal complex more
completely than women, they should have more developed superegos
than women and thus lower rates of crime. Blackburn (1993: 116) also
suggests that theories that rely on unconscious conflicts may be more
useful in accounting for ‘irrational’ crimes, and that most offenders do not
seem to be neurotic or ‘psychopathic’. Thus such theories may be only
useful for some crimes and offenders. Feldman (1964) has pointed out that
neurosis may be the result of crime and the associated experiences that
might accompany it, as much as its cause. Because such studies of
offenders are usually retrospective, it is difficult to be sure which came
first.
These are mainly points of detail. Much of the resistance to psycho-
analytic ideas has been based on broader objections: ‘the lack of scientific
method in formulating the theories, the vague and untestable nature of
many of the central concepts, and the reliance on the interpretive skills of
the analyst in the understanding of any given behaviour’ (Hollin 1989: 37).
Many psychologists were resistant to such ideas as ‘unconscious conflicts’
and other mysterious and difficult to research concepts, such as the
superego, and to a method that seemed to formulate and validate its
theories through the retrospective interpretation of case materials by the
analyst. How could he/she ever be wrong? It seems, however, that there is
more interest in such perspectives in recent years:

contrary to the somewhat overdone positivist critiques, the theory


has proved to be falsifiable, and has withstood the test in certain
respects ... . The resistance of psychologists to the notion of un-
conscious processes has also begun to dissipate ..., and with the
cognitive ‘revolution’ psychology has begun to move closer to
psychoanalysis.
(Blackburn 1993: 116)

We shall clarify the last point made a little later. The view expressed seems
a little different from that when Rutter and Giller (1983: 257) concluded
some years ago that psychoanalytic theories ‘have not proved to be
particularly useful either in furthering our understanding of crime or in
devising effective methods of intervention’.

Learning theories
Differential association
One of the earliest attempts to view crime as a product of learning was
developed by the famous criminologist, Edwin Sutherland, whom we
35
Introducing Criminology

have already met in the context of his ‘discovery’ of white-collar crime.


Sutherland was keen to develop a general theory of criminal behaviour,
especially one that could accommodate white-collar crime as well as the
crimes of the less powerful and prosperous (Sutherland and Cressey
1960). One part of his theory was concerned with explaining how
individuals came to be involved in crime. This contrasted with the more
sociological component which was more concerned with explaining
variations in the incidence of crime in different parts of the social structure.
The individual-level explanation was called the theory of differential
association. It claims that criminal behaviour is learned in a process of
communication with other people, mostly in small intimate groups. The
learning includes techniques for committing crime, but, more important,
particular kinds of attitudes, motives and rationalisations. A person
becomes criminal because the definitions favourable to violation of law
they hold outnumber definitions unfavourable to violation of the law. The
impact of differential associations varies according to their frequency,
duration, priority (how early in life they occur) and intensity (how
significant the source of definitions is to the individual concerned). In
terms of ‘spot the difference’, note that Sutherland is suggesting that the
learning process involved is no different from any other learning: it is the
content of the learning that is important. In addition, no assumptions are
made in the general theory about individual differences, such as in
biological make-up or personality. Individuals differ in terms of the
number and nature of the definitions they have learned.
The theory has enjoyed a great deal of attention, especially among
sociologists, and is still being discussed in the literature of criminology.
Over the years, however, it received considerable criticism, including the
view that the theory was vague and untestable in its original form, and
therefore not a ‘scientific’ theory. The ‘obvious’ solution was to try to
reformulate the theory in a more testable form. Others suggested that
there were exceptions to the theory, perhaps undermining its claim to be a
theory of all criminal behaviour. Box (1971: 121) complained about the
silence of the theory on the contribution of the person to the process of
learning: a passive and empty vessel into which various cultural norms
and values are poured. Are we simply the imprint of a kind of balance
sheet of our learning experiences? Others commented that the theory
needed to take account of research and theory on learning in psychology
(see below).

Classical conditioning
The name of Ivan Pavlov will always be remembered in connection with
his dogs. Pavlov conducted one of the most famous experiments into the
way in which organisms learn. The salivation of dogs was measured, and,
as you might expect, the dogs would begin to salivate on the appearance

36
Offenders and non-offenders: spot the difference?

of food. The food is referred to as an unconditioned stimulus, which


produces an unconditioned response, for no learning is involved in this
sequence. If, however, some other stimulus were to occur consistently
before the appearance of the food, such as a buzzer being sounded, the
dogs would come to salivate when experiencing this stimulus on its own.
The dogs had learned that one stimulus follows another. In technical
terms, in this instance a conditioned stimulus (such as the buzzer) is
producing a conditioned response (the salivation).
Although there is more to this body of experimentation than we can
present here, the basic idea of Pavlovian or classical conditioning should
be clear. Although there is no theory of crime today based entirely on such
principles, for human learning is clearly more complex than this alone,
they do feature as one element in a number of theories (e.g. Eysenck 1977;
Wilson and Herrnstein 1985). One example is the idea that children must
be conditioned not to offend, and that this can be achieved by consistently
creating unpleasant sensations in the child whenever it misbehaves, or is
about to do so. In time, the child will come to associate misbehaviour with
the unpleasant feelings, such as fear and anxiety, that have accompanied it
in the past. These feelings have thus become a conditioned response,
which, it is argued, serves to control the behaviour of the individual.
Hans Eysenck (1977) has formulated a theory of crime (or rather, of
antisocial behaviour) that employs this idea among a number of themes.
The first is the approach to personality, a concept which suggests that
people tend to behave consistently in different situations and at different
times. It proposes that this can be described according to three dimensions
or scales, with most individuals falling somewhere in the middle of the
two extremes of each: extroversion–introversion; neuroticism–stability;
and a third scale which attempts to measure something called psycho-
ticism. Extroverts are said to be sociable, active, optimistic, but impulsive
and sometimes unreliable, whereas introverts are seen as quiet and
reserved, tending to plan ahead and be pessimistic. Neurotics are moody,
anxious, restless and rigid in their attitudes; at the other extreme are those
who are emotionally stable. Various descriptions of psychoticism have
been offered; it seems that the person high on this scale has such
characteristics as being cruel and inhumane, hostile to others and
aggressive, lacking in feeling and insensitive, and troublesome.
The second theme is that personality has a biological basis, which has a
large inherited component. In particular, because of biological differences,
extroverts are said to condition less quickly and less strongly than
introverts, need more intense stimulation to achieve pleasurable states of
consciousness, and be less responsive to pain. Neuroticism too is said to
have a biological basis, with high levels of resulting anxiety also
interfering with the conditioning process. Eysenck maintains that psycho-
ticism also has a biological basis.

37
Introducing Criminology

The third element is an account of the socialisation process. In this, the


view is taken ‘that antisocial behaviour, being obviously egocentric and
orientated towards immediate gratification, needs no explanation’
(Eysenck 1987: 30); instead, the theory seeks to explain how egocentric and
aggressive impulses are controlled in a way that results in conforming
conduct. The answer lies in Pavlovian (or classical) conditioning. Anti-
social behaviour is punished by parents, teachers and others; if done
consistently, the behaviour and even the contemplation of it is accom-
panied by a conditioned anxiety response, so that the behaviour is
avoided. Thus a ‘conscience’ is formed which is a ‘conditioned reflex’. The
degree of socialisation in any individual is therefore dependent on a
combination of the biological make-up of the child (which affects its
conditionability) and the nature of conditioning experiences of the
individual. According to the theory, we should expect to see offenders
scoring high on the three personality factors (extroversion, neuroticism
and psychoticism). The theory is therefore sometimes called ‘the three
factor theory’.
There have been many attempts to test Eysenck’s theory (for sum-
maries see, for example, Eysenck 1987, Hollin 1989, Blackburn 1993).
These mostly involve comparing the scores on the three personality
factors, singly or in combination, of groups characterised by official
convictions or self-reported offences, with the scores of groups of non-
offenders. While Eysenck’s (1987) review of the evidence is optimistic,
Feldman (1993: 435) concludes that the theory’s predictions ‘while poorly
supported in incarcerated populations of offenders, are consistently well
supported by self-report studies in the general population’.
The reasons for this difference in the findings according to how
criminality is measured are not entirely clear. Hollin (1989) concludes that
overall ‘[t]he weight of empirical evidence lends support to Eysenck’s
thesis that there is a relationship between personality (as he defines it) and
crime’. However, as Feldman (1993: 169) points out, these results are only
correlations. These do not necessarily show that the causal processes
specified in the theory are at work, and he suggests some alternative
explanations for the correlations between the personality scores and
measures of offending. In addition, the factor of psychoticism is open to
dispute: although it produces some of the strongest correlations with
offending, this is hardly surprising since the scale measures such items as
aggressiveness and antisociality, which are hard to distinguish from the
characteristics of what needs to be explained. Blackburn (1993: 127) makes
the point that there is no explanation which might link this factor to
socialisation, thus weakening the power of the theory.
Other ideas upon which the theory is based have also been disputed.
The theory focuses only upon the role of punishment in the training of
children. The role of parental affection and the use of positive

38
Offenders and non-offenders: spot the difference?

reinforcement for approved conduct are important but are ignored in the
framework (Feldman 1993: 169). Hollin (1989: 58) makes the point that
Eysenck’s approach to the study of personality is only one of several
approaches, and has been criticised (Mischel 1968), and that other
personality dimensions may prove to be linked to criminality. Although
Feldman (1993: 169) concludes that the approach is likely to play a role in
the explanation of criminal conduct, it is not comprehensive in its
approach, ignoring such items as the role of instigating events and many
social factors in explaining crime. The theory of Trasler (1962) was an
attempt to incorporate a range of social factors, such as child-rearing
practices, in a similar approach. Overall, there is clearly some diversity of
opinion on the theory. While some appear to see some merit in the
approach, others are more critical, such as Blackburn (1993: 127) who
concludes that it ‘is not well supported’.

Operant learning
This perspective upon learning originates from the work of B.F. Skinner,
the famous psychologist associated with that approach in psychology
called behaviourism. In this view, behaviour can be seen to operate on the
surrounding environment to produce consequences which may be
rewarding or aversive for the individual concerned. In the first case the
behaviour is said to be reinforced and will tend to be repeated, whereas in
the second the behaviour is said to be punished and will become less
frequent. Cues in the environment signal to the individual when particular
behaviours are likely to be reinforced or punished in these terms. The
individual thus has a learning history which explains the ‘acquisition’ of
particular patterns of behaviour.
Crime has been analysed in these terms as an operant behaviour,
with the criminal to be understood in terms of a particular background
of reinforcement and punishment experiences. Jeffery (1965) attempted
to reformulate differential association into a theory of differential
reinforcement, as did Burgess and Akers (1966: 137), for whom criminal
behaviour is said to be ‘learned according to the principles of operant
conditioning’. For some critics, these attempts to improve on differential
association were hardly an improvement. For Taylor, Walton and Young
(1973: 133) such an approach may be well founded on studies of rats (the
original Skinner studies were also conducted with pigeons), but human
purpose, choice, and the development of what people find rewarding is
actually much more complex than this framework allows. For many
psychologists, the focus on events external to the individual produced an
unduly restricted analysis, neglecting the role of processes within the
individual, processes that were the focus of a developing cognitive
psychology.

39
Introducing Criminology

Social learning theory


Some psychologists sought to follow in the footsteps of operant theory,
but to improve upon it by incorporating additional dimensions. Bandura
(1977) included ‘external’ reinforcement in his approach, but noted that
behaviour could equally be learned by observing the behaviour of others
(especially those with status, success and/or the ability to control
rewards) and its consequences in terms of reinforcement or punishment,
and can also be reinforced or punished by the self (such as in reflecting on
achievements and failures), thus making its repetition more or less likely.
If behaviour has been reinforced in the past, this generates an expectancy
that it will be in the future. These additions reflect a cognitive element in
the theory, in the sense that they involve mental processes on the part of
the individual, and not just ‘external’ reinforcement or punishment.
Bandura has increasingly come to incorporate cognitive elements into his
approach, stressing the way in which the individual processes and
structures experience. His more recent work is now called social cognitive
theory (Bandura 1986).
Akers (1977) has developed his own version of social learning theory.
To the main ideas of Sutherland’s original theory, and his own earlier
notion of differential reinforcement, is added the notion of imitation, a
process that is affected by the characteristics of persons who are models,
the observed behaviour, and the observed consequences of it (as in
Bandura’s approach outlined above). As a sociologist, Akers stresses that
the social structure has an impact on the process of learning, and thus on
behaviour. Differences in learning contexts may be created by the
individual’s family, peer group and school; by their age, sex, race and
class; and finally by the wider community and society in which they are
located. Akers claims that most research relevant to this theory has
provided evidence which is supportive of the approach, and has been
involved in some of this research himself (Akers et al 1979). Social learning
theories of various kinds have enjoyed a certain popularity over recent
decades and are often included in attempts at integrating various separate
theories in order to achieve a more comprehensive approach that is
intended to combine the strengths but counter the weaknesses of any
single theory on its own (see, for example, Elliott et al 1985 on delinquency
and drug use).

Overview
Learning theories have received a considerable amount of attention over
the years from psychologists and sociologists in the quest to understand
crime. In terms of ‘spot the difference’, they suggest that criminal be-
haviour is to be understood by reference to differences in the learning
experiences of individuals. However, while some suggest that pre-existing
differences between individuals (e.g. in their biology or personality) are

40
Offenders and non-offenders: spot the difference?

important in understanding the impact of those experiences (e.g.


Eysenck), others ignore or give far less attention to this possibility in their
framework.
Learning theories have come in for some criticism, particularly differen-
tial association, and those which are based on the more behaviouristic
accounts of learning which rely most heavily on classical and operant
conditioning. These are criticised as putting forward an over-simplistic
view of human nature and the learning process, conceiving it in an over-
mechanical way, making the individual a passive receptor of that process.
As such, they do not allow for human purpose and meaning, or recognise
that some individuals may not be receptive to the learning process, or that
the same event can be experienced very differently by different people.
An approach which gives more attention to the actor’s creative and
interpretive contribution to learning and action as a whole has therefore
been advocated by some psychologists. It has long been a criticism within
psychology that behaviouristic accounts are deficient in that they do not
give sufficient attention to ‘internal’ mental processes, focusing as they do
on ‘external’ events. This is why there has been an increasing focus upon
cognitive processes within psychology and the study of learning, in the
hope that these will help us to understand the complexity of human
behaviour. Learning theories of crime have therefore often moved in this
direction, increasingly incorporating cognitive elements. The boundary
between learning theories and our next topic, cognitive theories, is
therefore not clear cut.

Cognitive approaches
The criminal personality?
In 1976, Yochelson and Samenow made a remarkable claim – to have
discovered the distinctive thinking patterns of the criminal, with styles
and ‘errors’ of their very own. Over 40 such errors of thinking are
described, including pervasive fearfulness, especially of a state in which
the individual feels worthless, the ‘power thrust’ – a need for power and
control, ‘fragmentation’ – inconsistencies in thinking, a failure to empa-
thise with others, perceiving themselves as victims, poor decision-making,
and extensive fantasies of antisocial acts.
Although this study is clearly cognitive in its focus upon thinking
processes, it is open to considerable criticism. The study is based on a
sample of 240 male offenders, many of whom had been committed to a
psychiatric hospital for assessment, or because they had been found ‘not
guilty by reason of insanity’. This is hardly a representative sample of
offenders to make generalisations about the ‘criminal mind’. Second, no
attempt was made to compare this sample with a comparison group of
non-offenders, to see how distinctive the findings were. Third, the

41
Introducing Criminology

interviews conducted for the study have been criticised as unsystematic,


with insufficient attention to validity and reliability (Hollin 1989: 47).
Fourth, the study produces an arbitrary list of patterns and errors, which
does not relate to any broader theory of cognitive functioning (Blackburn
1993: 203). We do not fully understand how the patterns originated,
neither can we be sure that they ‘cause’ criminal behaviour. According to
Blackburn (1993: 203), it seems likely that the patterns described approxi-
mate to those of a particular personality disorder, rather than to some
‘criminal mind’.

Kohlberg’s theory of moral development


Kohlberg (1964, 1978) has suggested that the cognitive process of moral
reasoning in people develops through a number of levels over time. The
pre-conventional or pre-moral stage (level 1) is characteristic of pre-
adolescent children and some adolescents and adults. The conventional
level (level 2) is attained by most adults and adolescents, while the post-
conventional or principled level 3 is only reached by a minority of adults.
Each level has two stages within it, making six stages altogether. For
example, whereas the reasoning for doing the ‘right’ thing at stage 1 is
simply to avoid punishment, at stage 6 it is commitment and belief in
moral principles. Movement to a higher stage depends on intellectual
capacity and experiences, particularly role-taking opportunities. Kohlberg
attempted to develop an approach in which people actively construct
moral judgements rather than passively learn them from the external
environment.
We clearly cannot do full justice to the theory here. However, it is
important to note that it is a theory of moral reasoning rather than of
criminal behaviour as such. We should not expect a perfect correspond-
ence between the nature of people’s reasoning and their actual behaviour.
It is, however, reasonable to suggest from it that offenders may tend to be
characterised by ‘underdeveloped’ moral reasoning. Researchers have
therefore attempted to compare the moral judgements of delinquents and
non-delinquents. Blackburn (1993: 132) concludes that the evidence from
research indicates ‘a correlation between moral development and delin-
quency, but pre-conventional reasoning seems most evident in younger
and in more psychopathic delinquents’, but there are certain important
qualifications.

• These findings relate only to ‘official’ delinquents; no clear relation has


been established with self-reported delinquency.
• There appear to be differences according to type of offence or offender.
Thornton and Reid (1982), for example, found that those convicted of
offences involving personal material gain were less ‘mature’ in their
moral judgements than those convicted of assault for no material gain.
42
Offenders and non-offenders: spot the difference?

• The studies conducted in this area, which involve presenting


respondents with hypothetical situations about which they are asked to
make moral judgements have been criticised as having doubtful
relevance to thinking about crime in real concrete situations.
• Hollin (1989: 52) suggests that the concept of moral development needs
clarifying. While research studies have concentrated on the content of
moral codes in terms of beliefs and attitudes, this is different from the
process of moral reasoning. Furthermore, we should not expect
behaviour necessarily to correspond with either of them, knowing as
we do the capacity of people to behave in ways they believe to be
wrong.

Hollin (1989: 53) concludes that a ‘direct causal link between moral
functioning and criminal behaviour remains to be established’. Research
continues, and if elements of the theory survive the test, they will certainly
need to be complemented by other factors and approaches, such as aspects
of situations which are known to influence behaviour in the ‘real’ world.

Attempting to identify some key variables


The two examples of the cognitive approach we have considered both took
a broad approach in attempting to identify overall differences between
offenders and non-offenders. Others have taken a more specific approach
in that they try to take more specific variables which frequently appear in
theories and endeavour to assess their relationship with crime, antisocial
behaviour, etc. Perhaps more progress can be made by taking a more
focused approach, picking off targets one by one? We take a number of
variables and consider them in turn.

Intelligence It has long been pointed out that samples of offenders score
lower on average than non-offenders on measures of intelligence. This
finding was often treated with scepticism or even dismissed. Critics
pointed out that the studies producing this finding were conducted with
officially convicted offenders, who might be a biased sample, and even
surmised that less intelligent offenders would be more likely to get caught.
More recent studies, which take class and race into account, and use self-
reported rather than simply official measures of offending, still find a
small but significant correlation, especially for verbal ability (Blackburn
1993: 187). This finding is open to a number of interpretations, such as that
low intelligence affects the ability to think in an abstract way, foresee the
consequences of actions and appreciate the feelings of victims – all
cognitive processes (Farrington 1997: 386). Another is that its effect is via
low school attainment (which is also a predictor of offending), which may
set in train a process of disengagement from school, truancy, and

43
Introducing Criminology

association with other ‘problem’ children. This interpretation is consistent


with a number of sociological theories.
Impulsivity and low self-control A number of theories of crime suggest that
offenders are characterised by impulsivity (Eysenck 1977, Wilson and
Herrnstein 1985) or by low self-control (Gottfredson and Hirschi 1990).
Other similar or related concepts which are used are low impulse control,
inability to delay gratification and low tolerance for frustration. Such
variables are measured in a variety of ways, including: by self-report
questionnaire items such as ‘I generally do and say things quickly without
stopping to think’; by using the assessments of teachers or others of
individuals’ degree of daring, concentration or restlessness; by psycho-
motor tests, such as the Porteus Mazes, which attempt to assess speed and
inaccuracy in completing tasks.
Both Hollin (1989) and Blackburn (1993) take overviews of the research
conducted and suggest that the results are mixed and inconsistent. They
suggest two possible reasons for this. One is that there appear to be a range
of different measures and definitions being employed in this area, an
indication that we are not dealing with a single phenomenon, but
something more complex. Secondly, offenders are a pretty mixed bunch
(what is often referred to as ‘the heterogeneity of the offender popula-
tion’), so it should not surprise us if some groups of offenders score more
highly on this while others do not. Farrington’s (1997: 384–5) more recent
brief overview, on the other hand, presents only evidence which supports
the link between impulsivity and offending, and draws attention to
research on ‘hyperactivity-impulsivity-attention-deficit’ (HIA), a cluster
of personality factors, its link with offending, and the suggestion that this
may have a biological basis. This is a reminder that more attention needs to
be paid to ‘impulsivity’ itself, including its theoretical significance, for it
can be employed in different ways by different theoretical perspectives –
biological, psychoanalytic, behavioural, and cognitive – for it to constitute
an explanation.

Self-concept Some attention has been given by psychologists to the idea


that offenders may differ in terms of their self-concept from non-offenders.
Research studies indicate that offenders, on average, have lower levels of
self-esteem than non-offenders (Blackburn 1993: 198). A number of
theories have employed the idea of self-concept. In Reckless’s (1961)
containment theory, a favourable self-concept is one insulator against
deviant behaviour. One strand of the labelling perspective (of which more
later) is that stigmatising and in other ways negative social reactions to a
rule-breaker may result in shifts in self-concept, or a ‘symbolic
reorganisation of self’ (Lemert 1967), which makes further deviance more
likely. For Kaplan (1980) delinquency is a way of enhancing self-esteem, a

44
Offenders and non-offenders: spot the difference?

way of restoring a sense of self-worth which has been lacking in conven-


tional spheres of the person’s life. Blackburn’s (1993: 199) review of the
evidence concludes that the research evidence for any of these specific
views is weak and inconsistent and ‘has not established any consistent
causal relationship between self-concept and delinquency’ and that the
correlation between them may be the result of the operation of other
variables. He also suggests that temporary changes in self-esteem rather
than the relatively stable self-concept may be more relevant to particular
deviant acts.

Values, beliefs and attitudes Perhaps offenders differ from others in their
values, beliefs and attitudes to an extent which would make their
offending easier to understand? This would be consistent with various
learning theories, and also with sociological subcultural theories, which
suggest that delinquents hold alternative sets of norms and values, which
result in law-breaking conduct (see, for example, Cohen 1955, for whom
the delinquent subculture was the opposite of middle-class values). This is
a huge topic, and what research has been conducted has mainly been with
reference to juveniles. With gang delinquents, there seems to be some
evidence of differences in values, beliefs and attitudes, but the similarities
to conventional norms and values are more striking (see, for example,
Short and Strodtbeck 1965).
Matza (1964) came to the rescue, pointing out that delinquency was
mostly episodic in nature, so that various theories which saw delinquents
as having been programmed into an alternative set of norms and values
would predict too much delinquency. For him, delinquents largely
subscribe to conventional values, and his account stresses the situational,
interactional context of delinquency, suggesting that individuals drift into
delinquency, partly through the episodic release from the moral bind of
law through techniques of neutralisation. These are invocations of extenuat-
ing circumstances for breaking rules that are claimed to neutralise the guilt
that would otherwise be felt in breaking the law, such as a denial of
responsibility (‘I couldn’t help it’), or appeal to higher loyalties (‘I know
it’s wrong, but I can’t let down my mates’). Since these are essentially
situational processes, it has proved difficult to test them out, as some have
tried to do, by the use of questionnaires and interviews away from those
situations, and it remains unclear to what extent these techniques precede
acts or are rationalisations/excuses after the event.
This material is primarily sociological, but similar concerns can be
found in psychology. For example, in Bandura’s (1983) theory of
aggression, personal and social standards of behaviour can be neutralised
by ‘cognitive distortions’ such as dehumanising or blaming the victim.
Abel et al (1984) found seven types of such distortion among child
molesters (such as ‘children don’t tell because they enjoy the sex’).

45
Introducing Criminology

Attribution theory examines how individuals explain unwelcome or


unexpected events, and it seems accepted that such cognitive attributions
are important in anger and aggression (Blackburn 1993: 223). However, the
suggestion that offenders differ from non-offenders in terms of their ‘locus
of control’ (Rotter 1975) – a general belief that events are controlled by
factors external to the individual rather than by one’s own actions – has
not received consistent support in research studies (Blackburn 1993: 202;
Hollin 1989: 48), although Werner (1989) found that ‘internality’ was a
significant protective factor among those at risk for criminality.

Skills that relate to relationships with other people There has also been some
interest in those skills that relate to relationships with other people. Role-
taking – seeing things from the point of view of others – is a key element in
Kohlberg’s theory outlined above, and research studies indicate that
offenders have a tendency to see things from their own viewpoint
(egocentrism) rather than that of other people (Hollin 1989: 49; Blackburn
1993: 205), but also that skills in role-taking might be employed in certain
sorts of manipulative offending behaviour – a further reminder of the
varied nature of crime and offenders. Findings are rather inconsistent on
empathy – the capacity to appreciate the feelings of others and, perhaps, to
respond to them – partly, perhaps, because there are a number of different
concepts and measures of this (Blackburn 1993: 205).
Interpersonal problem-solving skills have also been investigated, with
some evidence emerging that offenders are less thorough and capable in
such problem situations, suggesting that they may act in real situations on
the basis of limited or misleading information (Blackburn 1993: 207).
Rutter, Giller and Hagell (1998: 151–2) draw attention to recent research
studies which suggest that aggressive individuals have a distorted way of
processing information in social encounters, including wrongly perceiv-
ing negative intentions in others, misinterpreting social interactions and
concentrating on the aggressive behaviour of others: this may be the result
of their own past experiences. Finally, there is the linked area of social
skills. It is often assumed that offenders are deficient in such skills, and
indeed, training in such skills is often used in the treatment of offenders.
Unfortunately, Blackburn (1993: 207) suggests that the evidence on this
score is limited, partly because of the lack of agreement on the definition,
measurement and identification of such skills, and concluding that delin-
quents are probably varied in this respect.

Rational choice perspectives


Rational choice perspectives are cognitive in the sense that they focus
upon the decisions people make in different situations of opportunity and
in relation to particular types of crime. Rational choice theories grew out of
the concern with situational crime prevention – attempting to reduce

46
Offenders and non-offenders: spot the difference?

crime by altering aspects of the situations in which crime occurs, such as


by changes in the layout of housing estates or the provision of locks and
bolts. Although such studies helped to show which measures had an
impact and which did not, they did not look at offenders and the decisions
they made when confronted with such preventive measures. For example,
did they give up altogether, choose another target, a different location, or
even a different kind of crime (the last three are forms of what is called
displacement, in which crime is not prevented in an absolute sense)?
While situational crime prevention had an immediate policy relevance,
rational choice perspectives held the promise of filling these gaps in its
framework for preventing crime.
There is a variety of approaches that come under this heading. Some
have adopted the approach of classical economic theory, with its assump-
tions of the rational actor seeking to maximise returns and minimise costs
in crime as in economic behaviour. This approach has had limited
usefulness in looking at the complexity of crime. More realistic is the
framework developed by Cornish and Clarke (1986). There are three basic
elements in their approach.

• The image of a reasoning offender. Offenders seek to benefit themselves by


crime, and make decisions and choices, which are characterised by a
degree of rationality. This is not full rationality as in some other
approaches, but one limited by such factors as the time and information
available for making a decision, and the cognitive abilities of the
individual.
• A crime-specific focus. It focuses upon crime rather than the offender, and
on specific kinds of crime, rather than attempting to tackle crime in
general, as many theories did in the past.
• They make a key distinction between criminal involvement and criminal
events. The first refers to ‘processes through which individuals choose
to become initially involved in particular forms of crime, to continue
and desist’ (Cornish and Clarke 1986: 2). These can clearly take place
over long periods of time, and involve a variety of different sorts of
information. Criminal event decisions, on the other hand, are usually
processes that take place over much shorter periods of time, employing
a more limited range of information, for example about the area and the
particular house in the case of a decision to burgle.
From these three principles, four models are developed for the example
chosen – burglary in a middle-class suburb.

• An initial involvement model, which includes the sorts of factors that


other theories have focused upon, such as psychological characteristics,

47
Introducing Criminology

upbringing, social factors, and previous experience and learning, as


well as those processes and information which lead the individual to a
decision to commit burglary (needs, solutions evaluated and perceived,
reactions to chance events).
• An event model involves those processes and information involved in the
selection of a particular target in a particular location.
• A continuing involvement model, focusing upon increased professional-
ism, changes in life style and values, and changes in peer group, ‘that
influence the constantly re-evaluated decision to continue with this
form of burglary’ (Cornish and Clarke 1986: 6).
• A desistance model, which focuses upon external events and re-evalua-
tion of readiness which may result in the decision to desist from the
particular crime.
Similar models can be developed for other types of crime (see, for
example, the studies of different types of crime in Cornish and Clarke
1986). Such an approach feels very different from some of the others we
have considered. It touches the parts that other theories rarely reach, such
as the immediate, situational aspects, and the processes of continuance
and desistance in crime, viewed within a framework stressing choice and
decision-making.
Whereas the traditional approaches we have looked at were almost
exclusively concerned with the background factors and differences which
may predispose individuals to become involved in offending, the image of
the reasoning offender seems to stress the ‘foreground’ and features that
offenders have in common with other people, implying ‘the essentially
non-pathological and commonplace nature of much criminal activity’
(Cornish and Clarke 1986: 6). There have been other attempts in
contemporary criminology, but in a very different way, to focus on the
‘foregound’ rather than on the traditional background factors in crime; in a
controversial book, Jack Katz (1988) attempted to explore what he sees as
the neglected ‘lived realities’ of crime, including the ‘sensual’ and other
attractions of ‘doing evil’.
Rational choice theory has attracted some criticisms. First, it is often
said that rational choice theories are limited because offenders rarely act in
a rational way. For example, Wright and Decker (1994: 197), in their
fascinating study of active burglars in St Louis, Missouri, suggest that
rational choice theories pay too little attention to ‘the subjective influence
of emotions on offender decision-making’. Their burglars typically made
decisions in a hurried, emotional way, in contrast to the picture created
through interviews of offenders in prison (on whom most of the research
has been done), who may ‘rationally reconstruct’ their crimes well after
the event. Although this may be a valid criticism of some versions of the

48
Offenders and non-offenders: spot the difference?

approach, Cornish and Clarke do not assume full rationality, and accept
that offences differ according to the extent of cognitive processing
involved. The approach does, however, generally focus our attention on
certain aspects of decision-making rather than others.
A related point is that although this approach may be helpful in looking
at many property crimes, such as burglary, it is of little value with offences
like murder, rape, and assault (Trasler 1986). Cornish and Clarke (1986)
reply that violence is still chosen by the individual, and decisions,
however rudimentary, are made about the victim, the location and timing,
although they accept that ‘special motivational theories’ may be included
in accounts of some crimes.
These first two points indicate that the approach is more a perspective
into which a variety of ideas and findings can be incorporated, rather than
a specific theory in the traditional sense. It tells us where to look, rather
than what to expect when we get there.
The third point, also made by Trasler (1986) concerns the crime-specific
focus. Since much crime is committed by a smallish group of offenders
who do not specialise much, is this focus the best strategy? Cornish and
Clarke deny that their framework assumes offenders tend to specialise,
but concede that it may not be sensible to construct separate involvement
models for those crimes which are largely perpetrated by the same sorts of
offenders.
The fourth and final point concerns the narrow focus engendered by the
approach. Wright and Decker (1994) conclude from their study that the
approach fails to take account of the wider social and cultural context
within which decisions are made; for example, street life culture, which
stressed such features as self-reliance and spontaneity, had a considerable
impact on their burglars’ decisions, such as ill-gotten gains being spent on
drugs, alcohol and status-enhancing goods. Although a wider perspective
is allowable in the involvement models, this seems to fade from view in
practice, where the concern is very much with situational elements that,
hopefully, can be manipulated by immediate policy measures.
The dominance of policy relevance and situational factors leads to a
neglect of wider social, economic and political contexts, which may be
crucial in understanding crime and crime rates but which are deemed to
be of little practical use. This is hardly surprising, given that these studies
grew out of research sponsored by the Home Office in the wake of its
concern with crime prevention; they have been designated by Jock Young
(1994), rather unsympathetically, as examples of the ‘new administrative
criminology’, tied to state interests in controlling and reducing crime, if
possible by methods that are cheap, practicable and do not disturb the
status quo. Few civil servants or politicians in office welcome research that
calls for fundamental social change to prevent crime. Management of the
crime problem takes priority over the understanding of underlying

49
Introducing Criminology

causes. For Young, the new administrative criminology is a major force in


British criminology, and can be seen as the new establishment criminology,
sponsored by the state, and a well resourced tradition compared to that
which is practised elsewhere.

The revival of approaches locating the sources of crime in the


individual

Rutter, Giller and Hagell (1998) note that research focusing on individual
characteristics had become unfashionable by the 1970s. Self-report studies
had revealed that delinquent acts were so widespread, it seemed unlikely
that theories stressing individual differences would be useful in
accounting for them. Sociological approaches, which we consider in the
next chapter, were also much in vogue. It seems fair to say that the 1980s
and 1990s have seen a resurgence of interest in theories and research on
crime which locate the causes within the individual. This point has been
made by a number of commentators, including Lilly, Cullen and Ball
(1995: 196) and Rutter, Giller and Hagell (1998: 127). The reasons given for
this revival by the two sets of authors are, however, very different. The
revival of interest in individualistic theories, according to Rutter, Giller
and Hagell, is due to five factors:

• The increasing influence of biological psychiatry in the study of


behaviour, even though overstated claims are often made in this
context, and it must not be forgotten that people are also social animals.
• More recognition of the heterogeneity of antisocial behaviour, with
more focus on different types. For example, they suggest that antisocial
behaviour that persists throughout the lifecourse in certain individuals
is more likely to be explained in terms of individual differences than
that which is more common, but limited to the adolescent phase.
• A clearer acceptance that individual factors operate in a probabilistic,
not deterministic fashion and that there is a complex and dynamic
interaction between the person and the environment.
• A recognition of the steps needed to distinguish causal relationships
from mere correlations – something that was too rarely done in the past,
a point we have frequently made in the course of this chapter.
• A strengthening of the research base on the characteristics of indi-
viduals in relation to antisocial behaviour.

However, such an account stresses the factors internal to criminology


and its associated disciplines, what Jock Young (1994: 71) refers to as their

50
Offenders and non-offenders: spot the difference?

‘interior’ history. He adds that academic debate also has an exterior


history – that it is also driven by events in the world outside, the world of
politics and practice. This context is stressed by Lilly, Cullen and Ball
(1995), who relate the revival of individualistic theories to the conserva-
tism of the 1980s and early 1990s. Both the USA and Britain experienced
long periods of conservative rule at this time, with Ronald Reagan and
Margaret Thatcher and their governments springing to mind. Such a
context, they suggest, was conducive to theories locating the roots of crime
in the individual’s will, mind or body, in the form of rational choices,
psychological or biological differences, approaches which appeal to those
who prefer not to consider fundamental social change, for they focus on
the individual as the problem, leaving the wider social context un-
examined. They also tend to lead to ‘get tough’ policies on crime, such as
incapacitation of the wicked and deterrence for the calculating, rational
offender, policies Lilly, Cullen and Ball view as expensive and of limited
effectiveness. Altogether, these approaches are branded – crudely and
misleadingly – as examples of ‘conservative criminology’.
Elsewhere in the same discussion Lilly, Cullen and Ball say that not all
individualistic theories are inherently conservative, nor are their authors
necessarily to the right of the political spectrum, and neither are the
policies that seem to arise from them necessarily right-wing (Lilly, Cullen
and Ball 1995: 219). Although we can see that individualistic approaches
might appeal to those reluctant to consider fundamental social change,
there seems a good deal more diversity in this collection of ideas that any
apparently persuasive labelling as ‘conservative’ seems to allow. Although
it is true that individualistic accounts are (almost by definition) weak on
the wider social context, this is at least partly due to the conventional
academic division of labour, in which sociological approaches are often
separated off from psychological and biological ones, and may in turn be
weak in their consideration of the individual level.
Even the idea that ‘conservatives’ will prefer individualistic accounts is
not a universal truth. Lilly, Cullen and Ball (1995: 201) state that a further
conservative view suggests that the sources of crime lie in the breakdown
or erosion of traditional social institutions, such as the family, schools,
churches and stable employment. This kind of argument is clearly
sociological in content, rather than individualistic. There are, then, a
number of themes to be found in ‘conservative’ thinking about crime and
policy, which are not fully clarified by this discussion. There are, for
example, important differences between what might be called ‘tradition-
alist’ conservatism and the (now not so) New Right (Tame 1991).
Having said this, we must not forget Young’s (1994) important point
about the exterior history of academic debate. It is certainly true that there
was an ascendancy of the right in Britain and the USA in the 1980s and
early 1990s, and that crime was high on the agenda of the governments in

51
Introducing Criminology

both countries. While Britain saw the emergence of what Young calls the
new administrative criminology with its focus on situational crime
prevention and rational choice, he sees something rather different as the
‘establishment’ criminology in the USA, a creature he calls ‘right realism’.
This is based largely on the work of James Q Wilson, author of the best-
selling Thinking About Crime (1975), and an advisor to the Reagan
administration, and co-author of another highly influential book (Wilson
and Herrnstein 1985). The latter work embodies some of the ideas we have
discussed in this chapter, and its popularity is consistent with the
increasing attention paid to individual differences in recent years.
Wilson and Herrnstein are said to be ‘realist’ by Young in the sense that
they accept that crime is a real problem in American society, that it had
grown rapidly over the years and needed to be taken seriously in terms of
explanation and policy. This contrasted with those who seemed to suggest
that concern about crime had been inflated by misleading statistics and the
mass media. Unlike the exponents of the new administrative criminology
in Britain, who had turned away from traditional theories of crime, Wilson
and Herrnstein put forward a general theory of criminal behaviour – or at
least of serious ‘street’ and ‘predatory’ crime. It is a theory based on the
principles of behavioural psychology, including the work of Eysenck. It
recognises that crime can be understood in terms of the immediate
circumstances in which it occurs or in terms of enduring dispositions of
the individual. The main elements can be summarised as follows:

• Choice: people choose actions in terms of the gains and losses that are
associated with various alternatives. We therefore need to understand
the way in which people evaluate those gains and losses.
• Conditioning: both classical conditioning, involving the autonomic
nervous system as in Eysenck’s theory, and operant conditioning have a
key role to play. The susceptibility of the individual, and the effective-
ness of the conditioning are therefore important factors. Some people
are so resistant to classical conditioning that they are deficient in
‘conscience’.
• Impulsiveness: some people have difficulty in seeing the likely future
consequences of their behaviour, or discount those they can foresee to
such an extent that they are resistant to the operant conditioning that
might result in them choosing ‘non-crime’. The rewards of crime are
generally in the present, whereas the costs often occur in the future,
whereas the opposite is the case for ‘non-crime’.
• Equity and inequity: people evaluate situations in terms of the gains
being received by people (e.g. income or material goods) relative to the
contributions made (e.g. amount of work, degree of skill). Individuals
differ in their evaluations of what is seen as fair or unfair because of a
52
Offenders and non-offenders: spot the difference?

range of factors, including their level of understanding and social


learning. People also differ in their responses to situations of perceived
inequity, partly according to individual differences.

The theory can be summarised by the following quotation:

The larger the ratio of the rewards (material and non-material) of


non-crime to the rewards (material and non-material) of crime, the
weaker the tendency to commit crimes. The bite of conscience, the
approval of peers, and any sense of inequity will increase or decrease
the total value of crime; the opinions of family, friends, and
employers are important benefits of non-crime, as is the desire to
avoid the penalties that can be imposed by the criminal justice
system. The strength of any reward declines with time, but people
differ in the rate at which they discount the future. The strength of
any reward is also affected by the total supply of reinforcers.
(Wilson and Herrnstein 1985: 61)

The book is an attempt to integrate a number of elements that we have


come across into one framework: choice, conditioning or learning, indi-
vidual (including biological) differences, and people’s subjective evalua-
tions of situations. But for many commentators, what is most striking
about their approach is the role given to constitutional factors, including
the endorsement of the study of body types mentioned earlier. Wilson and
Herrnstein (1985: 103) are not unusual in their view that ‘crime cannot be
understood without taking into account individual predispositions and
their biological roots’. For them, ‘spot the difference’ of this kind has an
important part to play. They are, however, aware of the complex
relationships between such variables and the social realm, suggesting that
long-term trends in crime rates can be understood by reference to three
main factors.

• the proportion of young males in the population – likely to be


temperamentally aggressive and with short time horizons.
• changes in the benefits (e.g. more opportunities) and costs (e.g. risk of
punishment, costs of being out of work) of crime.
• changes in society’s degree of investment in inculcating self-control in
individuals (e.g. through families and schools).

The theory has been subjected to criticism. Lilly, Cullen and Ball (1995), for
example, mention the lack of clarity in the basic concepts, the selective use
of evidence, concentrating on that which supports the theory, and the
neglect of offending such as white-collar crime, which arguably can often

53
Introducing Criminology

be seen as predatory. It is, however, the wider implications of the work that
they find most disturbing – the idea that biological differences between
individuals (mainly among the poor, who seem to specialise in the type of
crime upon which the theory concentrates), are the root of much crime, has
particular implications about human nature and what policies should be
implemented to reduce crime. This is a further example of resistance by
sociologists to the biological approach to explaining crime (which is only
one element in this theory) that we mentioned earlier in the chapter.

Conclusion

Playing the game of ‘spot the difference’ between offenders and non-
offenders has proved more difficult than we might have first thought.
Along the way, however, we have learned some lessons. First, there is the
‘heterogeneity of the offender population’ – that offenders and crime are
varied in nature, so that we should not expect all offenders to be alike in
certain respects, such as in their biological or cognitive functioning. We
should therefore be sensitive to different types of crime and offender –
from the serial sex offender through to the juvenile shoplifter, from the
drugs dealer to the violent offender. Some might suggest that this
diversity makes the task a fruitless one – that the only thing such persons
and acts share is the fact that they are defined as criminal. Others have
dedicated themselves to the game with renewed enthusiasm in recent
years, determined to make a go of it by using more specific targets in their
studies. Rutter, Giller and Hagell (1998: 166) suggest that individual
characteristics are more likely to affect antisocial behaviour which begins
early in childhood and carries on during the life of the individual, rather
than the more common variety which seems to be limited to the adolescent
phase.
Second, there is the plethora of possibly overlapping ‘variables’ which
have been investigated in relation to offending, which have often been
conceptualised and measured in a variety of ways. For example, are
impulsivity and hyperactivity part of a single syndrome or separate
factors? Rutter, Giller and Hagell (1998: 149), in their recent review, rate
hyperactivity (or inattention) as having the most robust association with
antisocial behaviour which begins early in childhood and tends to persist
into adulthood, but say it is unclear whether this is separate risk factor or
part of a broader one with impulsivity and ‘cognitive impairment’. They
conclude the best-supported risk factors are ‘hyperactivity, cognitive
impairment (especially with respect to verbal and executive planning
skills), temperamental features (especially impulsivity, sensation seeking,
lack of control, and aggressivity), and a bias in social cognitive information
processing’ (Rutter, Giller and Hagell 1998: 166).

54
Offenders and non-offenders: spot the difference?

Third, there is the variety of research methods used, ranging from


artificial experimental settings to which subjects are asked to respond,
through to long-term studies of the development of a group over time. Is
offending measured by official convictions (as was traditionally the case)
or by self-reports? Do different methods make a difference to the findings?
If so, why? How applicable are some of these findings (for example, from
experimental and survey research) to ‘real’ situations?
Fourth, we see that a correlation between two variables does not
necessarily mean the relationship is a causal one: more sophisticated
research is needed to take that further step. And to constitute an
explanation, which helps us to understand how a variable produces the
effects it does, we need a theoretical understanding of the processes at
work. Given the various difficulties of the enterprise, it is not surprising
that some have turned to a more modest approach, which promised to
bring more immediate results, especially in relation to doing something
about controlling crime, such as rational choice perspectives.
Fifth, it should be noted that some of the criticisms of the approaches
we have considered here are concerned with some of the broader
implications of this work: what do these studies imply about human
nature, about policy, and about politics? Are some aspects ignored or
neglected? For example, it has been a common complaint that the broader
social context has been neglected, and that a conventional definition of
crime is usually employed, with white-collar offenders, for example,
rarely making an appearance. The next chapter looks at approaches that
have attempted to deal with some of these sorts of issues.
Finally, in terms of ‘spot the difference’, this chapter has shown how we
can identify two rather different emphases in this area of criminology. On
the one hand, there is what Garland (1996) has called ‘the criminology of
everyday life’, such as rational choice and situational perspectives, in
which crime is seen as commonplace and offenders as not very different, if
at all, from the rest of ‘us’. It stresses the ‘foreground’ of offending and the
possibilities for preventive action in that context. On the other hand, there
is a criminology which still stresses, but in a softened, less ambitious form,
the notion of difference, in that attempts are made to identify the risk
factors which might distinguish offenders (or particular sorts of them)
from non-offenders. This focuses on the ‘background’ and individual
characteristics of offenders. The first has echoes of the ‘classical school’
that we considered in the first chapter; the second, buttressed by such
developments as the new biology of crime, can trace its ancestry to the
work of nineteenth-century positivism.

55
Introducing Criminology

Chapter 3

A broader vision of crime

A major focus of the last chapter was the attempt to identify the causes of
crime, primarily through the approaches of biology and psychology. At
first, the discipline of sociology continued to play this traditional game but
looked for causes elsewhere, in the social contexts in which individuals
and groups were located – the sociological version of ‘spot the difference’.
Either the approaches considered in the last chapter were looking for those
causes in the wrong place, or at least those approaches needed to be
supplemented with a broader vision. We shall see how, eventually, some
sociologists turned away from the search for causes, and began exploring
other avenues. We look first at the approach which looked for the origins
of crime in the urban environment, before reviewing some other major
perspectives that have influenced criminology over the course of the
twentieth century. Although many of these perspectives are sociological,
others, such as feminism and postmodernism, cannot be neatly identified
with any traditional discipline of this kind; their ideas, however, have
implications for both sociology and criminology.

Environmental criminology

As we saw in chapter 1, the nineteenth century saw efforts to identify


patterns in the new statistics of crime and to explain the distributions
revealed. A. M. Guerry, for example, one of the ‘moral statisticians’,
pioneered the use of maps in the study of crime. In the first half of the
twentieth century, a group of sociologists at the University of Chicago
undertook studies of the structure of the city and the social and cultural
forms that developed within it. Two of these researchers, Shaw and
McKay (1942), plotted data on where juvenile delinquents lived on a map

56
A broader vision of crime

of Chicago divided into concentric zones, radiating from the city centre to
the outer commuter zone. They found that rates of delinquency declined
as you moved out from the centre, a pattern that was also found in other
American cities of the time and which came to be known as the zonal
hypothesis. There was a particular focus upon one zone, the zone in
transition, an area of the city characterised by low rents and physical
deterioration adjacent to the city centre, where there was a concentration
of delinquents. This concentration was found to persist over long periods
of time, despite the fact that the composition of the population living in the
area had changed frequently over time, since it was the area where the
various new immigrant groups tended to live until they could afford to
move elsewhere. This diverse and rapidly changing population, they
argued, led to social disorganization – an absence of stable or common
standards and a breakdown in community institutions – and a resulting
failure to socialise or control children effectively. Social disorganization
was seen as a key explanation for high rates of delinquency in such areas.
To the zonal hypothesis and social disorganization can be added a third
key idea – cultural transmission. Shaw and McKay suggested that in such
areas of the city, delinquent traditions could become established and
passed on in play groups and gangs. Such ideas were taken up and
developed by subcultural theory and by Sutherland in his theory of
differential association. Overall, the Chicagoan perspective can be seen as
being very different from many of those considered in the last chapter. The
focus in understanding crime was not on the characteristics of individuals,
but on the social circumstances brought about by rapid change in certain
parts of the city. The policy implications involved the physical renewal of
such areas and the attempt to redress social disorganization by com-
munity development.
More recent studies of the distribution of offender residence in the
Chicago tradition have failed to confirm the universality of the original
zonal distribution. In England, for example, planned development and the
location of council housing on the periphery of cities, thus relocating
higher risk populations away from the inner city, have led to more
complex patterns (Morris 1957; Baldwin and Bottoms 1976). Even recent
study of Chicago itself (Bursik 1986) has found the original model no
longer applies.
The work of the Chicago School established a tradition of research into
the spatial distribution of offenders, but more recent studies have also been
concerned with the spatial distribution of offences (the two need to be
carefully distinguished – see below). Although the Chicago School
advocated the use of other sources of data, including participant observa-
tion, in the study of patterns of social life in the city, much of the early work
conducted on spatial distributions has been criticised for its failure to treat
official statistics of crime and offenders with caution, for these may be

57
Introducing Criminology

affected by such factors as different police practices between areas, and


therefore give a misleading picture. Some researchers have therefore
attempted to supplement official data with self-report data on offenders,
and victim survey data on offences, intending to provide measures that are
independent of the criminal justice process and possible biases.
The concept of social disorganization has also been subjected to con-
siderable criticism. Some critics pointed out that some of the areas labelled
in this way did have their own, if unconventional, forms of social
organization. The more qualitative, first-hand research studies of the
Chicago School, and even Shaw and McKay’s concept of delinquent
traditions, seemed to endorse this view. Sutherland (1947) suggested that
the term ‘differential social organization’ was more open to such pos-
sibilities and thus preferable. Others criticised social disorganization for
the way in which it seemed to concentrate solely on processes taking place
within the zone in transition. This led to a neglect of processes in the wider
society, especially the distribution and operation of power, such as in the
form of decisions by politicians, officials and business corporations which
have important consequences for such areas. Bursik and Grasmick (1993)
claim that the concept of social disorganization is still useful, provided
that we take this criticism on board: stability is needed for the processes of
social control to operate, from those in the family through to those which
are organised in the public sphere.
Studies in England, on the other hand, have found that social dis-
organization, at least when measured by high population turnover, does
not seem to hold the key (see, for example, Baldwin and Bottoms 1976).
Social class, an obvious alternative explanation, is inadequate on its own,
for there are many differences in offender rates between areas with a
similar social composition. Studies have pointed to the following factors in
creating areas with especially high rates of offender residence:

• the importance of the local housing market in distributing crime-prone


individuals to certain parts of the city, including the way in which
council housing is allocated (e.g. some areas build up concentrations of
those in most severe housing need, and likely to have other problems,
in the difficult-to-let areas);
• the patterns of culture and social life in an area which influence such
matters as the socialization of children and friendship patterns (for
example, is there a criminal subculture on an estate?) (on these first two
points, see Bottoms and Wiles 1997);
• the way in which a reputation as a ‘problem area’ can be generated (by,
for example, media coverage focussing on an area’s problems), and
have real consequences, such as in terms of decisions made by existing
and potential tenants, small businesses and so on – not to move in, or to

58
A broader vision of crime

move out (see, for example, Damer 1974), thus contributing to the
neighbourhood’s decline.

Explaining the distribution of offences is a rather different exercise from


explaining the distribution of offenders. For example, offenders do not
necessarily commit their offences in the areas where they live. The
traditional pattern is that offences tend to be concentrated in city centres.
This is not necessarily the case for all offences (for example, domestic
violence), and this pattern may alter as opportunities arise elsewhere
owing to major changes in the location of opportunities (such as out of
town shopping centres). The concept of opportunity, which includes the
density, attractiveness and accessibility of targets, is therefore a good
starting- point when searching for an explanation.
Criminologists have also employed what is known as routine activities
theory, which builds on the concept of opportunity in suggesting that crime
is more likely to occur the more there is a ‘convergence of likely offenders
and suitable targets in the absence of capable guardians’ (Cohen and
Felson 1979: 590). For example, this approach suggests that rates of
household burglary in the suburbs rose as more homes became
unoccupied during the day, owing to changing ‘routine activities’ on the
part of occupants. Illuminating attention has been given to such topics as
decision-making by ‘likely offenders’ (which is by no means as rational as
the opportunity model alone seems to suggest) and to the question of
where such offenders commit offences (evidence suggests a preference for
areas that present opportunities and with which they are familiar)
(Bottoms and Wiles 1997). Wikstrom (1990) has attempted to bring a range
of such factors together into a tentative model to explain variations in
crime rates in the urban environment. As with the explanation of offender
rates, it is important not to focus exclusively upon what is going on within
the areas, and to look at the broader context of power and decision-making
in the wider society that may influence such things as opportunities for
crime and routine activities, and how areas can change fairly rapidly over
time (Bottoms and Wiles 1997).
We have only scratched the surface of the field known as environmental
criminology. There are other questions that have attracted attention
because of the apparent policy relevance of any approach which promised
to explore the relationship between the physical environment and crime. Is
it possible to ‘design out crime’ by changes to the physical layout of the
environment? Can we stop the process of neighbourhood decline into a
‘problem area’ by attention to the physical environment? Criminologists
still ask some of the same sorts of questions as Shaw and McKay; in the
next section we revisit the work of Edwin Sutherland, whose theory of
differential association has much in common with their concept of cultural
transmission.

59
Introducing Criminology

Sutherland, differential association and white-collar crime

We have already met Edwin Sutherland in previous chapters. In chapter 1,


we saw how he entered the debate about the definition of crime, when he
argued that the definition should include what he called ‘white-collar
crime’. We then saw in chapter 2 how he therefore formulated a theory of
criminal behaviour that would encompass these offences as well as those
that made up the more traditional subject matter of criminology.
Sutherland’s theory stressed the origins of learning experiences in the
company we keep, especially in small intimate groups. He is a good
example of someone who was determined to formulate, as best he could, a
general theory of criminal behaviour, that is a systematic explanation
covering all criminal behaviour.
The quest for such a general theory has been the objective of some
criminologists throughout the history of the discipline, and remains
important for some today. Some have argued that this quest is pointless
and doomed to failure, because, for example, of the sheer variety of
crimes, which perhaps only share in common the fact that they have been
labelled as such. Others suggest that any such theory will not tell us very
much: it will need to be so flexible, broad and all-encompassing that it will
end up as a collection of bland generalizations. Sutherland’s own theory,
according to Nelken (1997: 902) is ‘now regarded as flawed and super-
ficial, and the search for a universal theory of crime has lost its attractions’.
Maybe so, but Sutherland’s theory aroused enough interest to be the
subject of research and debate for many years afterwards.
What of Sutherland’s attempt to change the face of criminology by the
‘discovery’ of white-collar crime? Sutherland’s (1949: 9) original defini-
tion, ‘crime committed by persons of high social status in the course of
their occupations’, has been criticised for failing to distinguish offences
committed against the organisation from those committed on its behalf.
Some have therefore suggested a distinction between occupational and
corporate (or organizational) crime. Although attempting to render the
original concept redundant, such reformulations lose something of the
original force of Sutherland’s concept, which was part of a wider critique
of the narrow focus of criminology, and remains in use by some writers.
We have seen in chapter 1 how a good deal of energy has been expended
on whether white-collar crime is ‘really’ crime.
Research on white-collar crime has been made difficult by the paucity of
good information on which to base generalizations (Nelken 1997: 891).
Many such offences are not included in the official statistics of crime, often
being dealt with, if at all, by specialist agencies, and self-report and victim
surveys (victimization is often thinly spread among victims who often
unaware of their own victimization) are of little use. Researchers have
therefore often had to use such sources as newspaper reports, journalistic

60
A broader vision of crime

accounts and very patchy agency records, which are hardly a good basis
on which to come to conclusions about the extent, nature, impact and
trends in white-collar crime. Researching the relatively powerful is often
difficult enough in any case: Sutherland’s (1949) key text was originally
published in a ‘cut’ version, because of the inflammatory nature of some of
its findings. Little wonder, perhaps, that much work has involved
attempting to demonstrate the seriousness of, and harm created by, such
actions (Nelken 1997: 893), rather than the kind of work which has
characterised ‘ordinary’ crime.
Those who have looked for explanations of white-collar crime have
revisited the old questions: is it so different from other types of crime to
merit its own theoretical approach, or should our theories of crime be able
to accommodate it? Are explanations based on individual characteristics
or structural considerations more appropriate, or some combination of the
two? Finally, in terms of the response to white-collar crime, should it be
treated (in terms of, for example, policing, prosecution and punishment)
in the same way as ordinary crime, or is it so different that different
treatment can be justified? The persistence of such basic questions
underlines Nelken’s (1997: 895) point that ‘ambiguity about the nature of
white-collar crime and the best way to respond to it, form an essential key
to the topic’.
Slapper and Tombs (1999: 1) suggest that Sutherland’s ‘efforts to
redirect the energies of academic criminology were, in the immediate term
at least, a failure’. There has, however, been a clear growth in interest in the
topic in more recent times, spurred on, perhaps, by the increasing concerns
about the insidious activities of professionals and organizations, which
have the capacity to affect so many lives, in local, national and,
increasingly, global contexts. The environmental movement is but one
example of this, and we now hear calls for a ‘green’ criminology, focusing
on environmental violations and their control (South 1998). There can,
however, be a tendency for the topic to become a ‘specialism’ within
criminology, rather than being placed at the heart of research and teaching.
As such, it can be somewhat marginalized, the more so because of its
‘ambiguous’ character and its capacity, even today, to raise awkward
questions.

Merton, anomie and strain

One of the most enduring and influential attempts to provide a broad


sociological framework for the understanding of deviant behaviour
(including crime) is Robert Merton’s theory of anomie. First outlined in
1938 and subsequently developed by Merton in a number of places, it has
been a source of research and theory ever since, whether being praised,

61
Introducing Criminology

criticised, added to or modified by subsequent generations of crimin-


ologists. Borrowing and modifying the concept of anomie from the
famous French sociologist Emile Durkheim, it was an attempt to explain
why rates of deviant behaviour vary between societies, and between
different groups in the same society, thereby tackling what was seen as the
traditional sociological task. It was an explicit attempt to explore the
sources of deviance within the wider society, rather than locating them in
‘biological drives’ or ‘individual malfunction’. For Merton, deviant
behaviour could even be seen as a normal (i.e. typical) response to an
abnormal situation. Merton makes an important distinction between the
cultural goals of a society and the institutionalized means (or legitimate
avenues) for achieving those goals. The sources of high rates of deviant
behaviour lie in a disjunction between these two elements. Merton
suggested that the United States in particular (and other societies
which were structured in similar ways) was characterised by such a
disjunction.
American society places great stress on the cultural goal of success,
usually in terms of money. The culture also includes an ideology of
equality of opportunity – that success goals are open to all-comers,
regardless of origins. In reality, access to the success goals through the
institutionalized means is not an equal opportunity game: there is
inequality of opportunity. Certain groups in particular find themselves
often losing out the in race for success. They therefore experience the
disjunction more acutely than others: ‘it appears from our analysis that the
greatest pressures towards deviation are exerted upon the lower social
strata’ (Merton 1957: 144). This, of course, concurred with the knowledge
that, according to official statistics, offenders tended to come from the
lower social classes. According to Merton, a number of different
adaptations are open to those experiencing this disjunction between goals
and means.

• Conformity: in spite of the disjunction, people still maintain allegiance


to both cultural goals and means.
• Innovation: the cultural goals continue to be embraced, while the
institutionalized means are replaced by technically more efficient
means for achieving the goals, some of which may well be illegitimate.
• Ritualism: in response to the frustrations inherent in the quest for
success, the cultural goals are no longer stressed, but the institution-
alized means continue to be followed. There is a feeling of resignation,
of ‘playing safe’.
• Retreatism: the goals and the institutionalized means are abandoned,
such as with heavy drinkers and drug addicts.

62
A broader vision of crime

• Rebellion: allegiance is withdrawn from both cultural goals and


institutionalized means and new ones substituted in their place.

Merton (1957: 157) thus speaks of a ‘strain toward anomie’ where the
culture and the social structure do not mesh together, with anomie itself
seen as normlessness, a breakdown of the norms, ‘a breakdown of the
regulatory structure’ in which, at the extreme, ‘calculations of personal
advantage and fear of punishment are the only regulating agencies’. This
idea of strain has resulted in commentators calling this an example of a
sociological strain theory.
Despite its success, Merton’s theory has received much criticism over
the years. Much of it has suggested that the theory is incomplete and
undeveloped as a theory of deviant behaviour – a limitation that Merton
has readily accepted since the earliest statements of the approach (Merton
1938: 682). For example, it has often been said that it fails fully to account
for different outcomes: why do some still conform when experiencing
acutely the disjunction? how do we account for different kinds of deviant
behaviour adopted? Albert Cohen (1965) pointed out that the framework
was individualistic, neglecting group processes and their role in deviance,
and ignored the role of the social reaction to deviance in shaping it.
Cloward and Ohlin (1960) maintained that not only were legitimate
opportunities unequally distributed in society, so too were illegitimate
opportunities, making a difference in what kind of deviance, if any, the
individual might turn to when subjected to strain. A further comment was
that Merton perhaps gave undue weight to social class in his explanation.
After all, any theory of rates of deviant behaviour might be expected to be
able to account for the more dramatic variations in rates according to
gender and age, but Merton is silent on these issues.
These and other criticisms failed to silence the theory, which, although
subject to the changing fads and foibles in criminology and sociology,
continued to appear in various forms over the years. Steven Box (1983)
adapted Merton’s concept of anomie for the study of corporate crime,
arguing that such organizations are profit-seeking institutions in an
uncertain environment, leading to the exploration of alternative, and
perhaps illegal, means that will reduce that uncertainty. A similar
argument is used by Passas (1990), also in relation to corporate deviance.
Market capitalism, which promotes the pursuit of profit by the most
technically efficient means, while encouraging appetites and consumption
irrespective of the capacity for their fulfilment, does appear to be a recipe
for the strain toward anomie in the way that Merton suggested.
Messner and Rosenfeld (1994) in their ‘institutional anomie theory’
broadly follow Merton’s framework in accounting for high rates of crime
in the USA, adding that economic institutions are so dominant in that
society that people are less socialized or constrained by values, commit-

63
Introducing Criminology

ments and beliefs other than those of the market place. Agnew (1985), on
the other hand, has pressed the claims for a strain theory which is more
social psychological in approach, arguing that ‘negative relationships’ of
various kinds create negative emotions in the person. Whether crime and
delinquency or some other adaptation results from this strain depends on
a variety of constraints. Some evidence seems to suggest that delinquent
behaviours are associated with various negative relationships and life
events (Agnew and White 1992).
Lea and Young (1984), in what they call their ‘left realist’ approach,
stressed the role of relative deprivation in creating crime – a level of
perceived unfairness in one’s allocation of resources. More recently, Jock
Young (1999) has argued that the rise in crime in the second half of the
twentieth century is due to the combination of relative deprivation and
rising individualism, in a society that has become more socially exclusion-
ary, while culturally inclusionary (through the mass media) – thus
fostering expectations that the society cannot satisfy in significant groups
in the population, precisely what Merton had in mind.
In the global context, Rock (1997: 239) suggests that the concept of
anomie, in the sense of chronic deregulation, is appropriate to a number of
places around the world which are tottering on the brink of chaos and
lawlessness, where the state is struggling or has withdrawn from the battle
to maintain order. Merton’s account of anomie, which was developed
within the context of the USA at a particular time, will not necessarily
apply there. Finally, Merton’s theory became a major element in some
subcultural theories of delinquency, to which we now turn.

Subcultures, gangs and delinquency

Albert Cohen (1955: 59) suggested that subcultures arise as collective


responses to ‘problems of adjustment’ shared by people who are ‘in
effective interaction with one another’. In other words, they provide a set
of shared solutions to the problems that a group faces. Cohen (1955)
himself produced an account of the ‘delinquent subculture’, which he
saw as originating in the status frustration experienced by the working-
class boy in the middle-class institution of the school, an arena where he
found himself at a disadvantage. One response to this was a rejection of
middle-class norms and values and the development of a set that
were their very opposite. This process explained the ‘malicious, non-
utilitarian and negativistic’ nature of much delinquency, such as
vandalism. Thus, for the working-class boy who is unsuccessful at school
and therefore deprived of status in that context, the gang and the
delinquent subculture become an alternative source of status, measured
by criteria that the boy can meet. Such a subculture does not have to be

64
A broader vision of crime

reinvented by each cohort of youth in such a position, but is a ‘ready-


made’ solution available for those experiencing such problems of
adjustment.
Cloward and Ohlin (1960) developed a similar approach to the same
subject matter – gang delinquency. While Cohen (1955) had reservations
about Merton’s anomie, Cloward and Ohlin imported it in more or less
pure form as the problem of adjustment faced by many city boys of
working-class origin in the USA, especially the more able and ambitious.
They then attempted to account for the possible diversity in outcomes –
addressing a weakness in anomie theory on its own. First, in areas of the
city where there were established illegitimate opportunity structures, such
as organized crime and rackets, criminal subcultures or gangs would tend
to arise. Second, where no such illegitimate opportunities existed, conflict
gangs would focus on fighting. Third, retreatist subcultures, focusing on
drug use, were made up from those who failed to find a place in criminal
or conflict subcultures.
We can see clearly that the object of attention at this time was the gang
delinquency of lower-class boys in large cites, which was seen at that time
as the problem in need of explanation and policy response. Gangs were
seen as groups with a stable membership, a clear structure and leadership.
Members were seen as committed to a distinctive set of norms and values,
with delinquency a central activity in the gang. The gang was the carrier of
the subculture; the one implied the other.
Finally, the subculture was seen as very different from the norms and
values of the wider society; for Cohen (1955) it was the very antithesis of
middle-class culture. These theoretical assumptions were rarely support-
ed by research studies, even in the USA (see, for example, Short and
Strodtbeck 1965). Delinquency did indeed tend to occur in groups, but
these were typically loose-knit peer groups, or ‘near-groups’ (Yablonsky
1962) rather than structured gangs. Delinquents were not found to be
committed to a delinquent set of norms and values and delinquency was
not a central or required activity. As Matza (1964) pointed out, such
assumptions would predict too much delinquency; a more appropriate
image was that of the drifter between convention and crime, episodically
released from the moral bind of law by techniques of neutralization (see
previous chapter) and the desire to experience oneself as an active agent,
able to make things happen.
Attempts to apply such theories in the British context were equally, if
not more, disappointing. Downes (1966) found little evidence for status
frustration or frustrated ambition among London delinquents. Instead,
the typical response to lack of success in school and work was dissociation
– opting out, or at least playing down their importance, turning instead to
leisure, where a lack of satisfying opportunities might lead to attempts to
generate a little excitement and sometimes illegal behaviour. In Parker’s

65
Introducing Criminology

(1974) study in Liverpool, stealing car radios was a way of buying yourself
a ‘good time’, again a response to limited leisure opportunities. Although
the original theories were found wanting, a great deal was learned about
delinquency in the process of testing them out.
These theories, which attempted to tie together delinquency, sub-
culture, gangs and the social predicament of the working-class boy, were
eventually judged a failure, even though they had a major impact on social
policy in the USA in the 1960s. Gangs continue to be studied, especially in
the USA (see, for example, Huff 1996), although the lesson seems to be not
to make too many assumptions about their nature and development
without research evidence. Muncie (1999: 164) suggests that:

American gang research has warned of imputing any uniformity to


the processes of gang formation and development. Noting a rapid
spread of street gangs in almost all cities of the United States, this
research has come to argue that most gangs are neither stable in
membership nor cohesive. Yet the age spread of gang members
appears to have extended into the forties and their common
characteristics remain criminality, drug use, drug trafficking and
violence.

Subcultural theory did not wither and die, but reappeared in new guises.
As we shall see, that group of criminologists called the ‘left realists’ draw
extensively on subcultural theory. Another major development was the
work produced on the range of youth leisure styles (or subcultures) which
appeared in Britain from the 1950s onwards: teds, mods, rockers,
skinheads, punks, rude boys, and so on (for a brief overview, see Muncie
1999). One of the best known books on the subject suggested that such
subcultures could be seen as forms of ‘resistance through rituals’ (Hall and
Jefferson 1976): that such youth styles were coded responses to the
contradictions and conflicts faced by (especially working-class male)
youth within the social, economic and historical context of post-war
Britain. Such forms of ‘resistance’ were commonly seen as ‘imaginary’,
symbolic or ‘magical’ rather than as real solutions to the problems faced by
such groups.
Such approaches came under attack for their neglect of girls, especially
in the earlier work, the overplaying of the political significance of such
subcultures and the underplaying of their commercial aspects, and the
concentration on the radical and spectacular aspects as opposed to their
conservative and unremarkable features (Muncie 1999: 185–192).
Nevertheless, the structure of subcultural theory can still be clearly
seen: subcultures as collective responses to problems arising from the
wider social context for particular groups of people. There were, however,
clear differences from the earlier American theories; for example, these

66
A broader vision of crime

theories did not see these particular subcultures as having crime or


delinquency as their major activity. Even though law-breaking might
occur (for example, illegal drugs) and such subcultures were often seen as
‘deviant’ in the wider society, their focus was said to be on leisure and
style. The customary linking of subcultures, gangs and delinquency had
been superseded: each should be examined in its own right. Even if the
kind of scenario described by subcultural theories of gang delinquency
existed at all, it was clear that these approaches provided no explanation
for the great deal of ‘mundane’ delinquency that was being revealed by
self-report studies. It seemed that a new kind of approach was needed.

Control theory

Most of the sociological approaches we have considered up to now seem


to be suggesting that we need to explain why people deviate from
conformity, in asking ‘why do people break the law?’ It is as if conformity
itself needs no explanation; only deviation from it needs to be accounted
for. Control theory suggests otherwise: it starts off by assuming that crime
and delinquency need no special explanation, for they bring with them
their own attractions and rewards, such as money, possessions, excitement
and power over others. Instead, it is conformity that needs explanation,
rather than being assumed. So control theory asks ‘why don’t we all break
the law?’ The answer lies in the idea of control or constraint: that people
who conform do so because they are controlled or constrained. These
controls can be inside or outside the person (internal or external controls).
Those stressing the former tend to be classified as biological or
psychological (such as Eysenck 1977, discussed in the last chapter), and
the latter as sociological, although the division is not a hard and fast one.
Here, we shall mainly be discussing the second approach, sometimes
called social control or social bond theory. Control theories have a long
pedigree and are often to be found lurking within other theories; the
concept of social disorganization suggested conditions under which social
control breaks down, and anomie is often seen as a lack of moral restraint
or regulation, which allows individual ambitions, self-interest and
appetites a free rein.
Although there are a number of examples, the sociological control
theory that provided an influential outline was set out and tested by Travis
Hirschi (1969) at the end of the 1960s. Hirschi sought to demonstrate the
superiority of his version of control theory over competing explanations of
delinquency, which were already beginning to look rather jaded, some
reasons for which we outlined in the last section. Hirschi outlines four
types of social controls (or elements of the social bond) that make up the
theory.

67
Introducing Criminology

• Attachment. This refers to the sensitivity of the individual to the


opinions, concerns and feelings of others, such as parents, friends,
teachers. Whether the person takes those into account will depend on
the quality of the relationships with those people; if the relationships
are strong, conformity is more likely; if they are weak, the individual
becomes freer to deviate.
• Commitment. This suggests that a major reason for conformity is fear
of the consequences of deviation. We spend time, energy and bits of our
selves in certain activities with an eye to the future, such as an
education, career, or just building a reputation as a certain kind of
person. These can be put at risk by episodes of delinquency, as any
young person who acquires a criminal record will testify. Aspiration,
ambition and commitments of these kinds therefore play a part in
producing conformity.
• Involvement. People who are kept busy doing ‘conventional things’
have less time or opportunity to get up to mischief. Adolescents with
large amounts of unstructured time at their disposal, on the other hand,
are a problem waiting to happen. This is a contemporary version of the
old saying that ‘the devil makes work for idle hands’.
• Belief. Whereas traditional subcultural theory suggested that delin-
quents held a different set of norms and values and asked how this
situation arose, control theory asks how some individuals can break
rules in which they basically believe. Hirschi suggested that there is
variation in the degree to which individuals think they should abide by
the rules of society, variation which may be due, for example, to
differences in socialization. In some, there is therefore an absence of
moral restraint that makes delinquency possible.

Control theory has had a relatively successful career. Research studies


have fairly consistently supported certain elements, especially those of
attachment and commitment. The evidence for the element called involve-
ment was not convincing, even in Hischi’s (1969) own study of over four
thousand school students in California, which found that only some
activities were particularly likely to induce conformity: these were
studying and doing homework, which could be seen as indicators of
another element, commitment. Elements from the theory have popped up
in many places since Hirschi’s original study, usually modified or com-
bined with some other elements in order to overcome perceived weak-
nesses and gaps. For example, it has been said that the theory neglects
group processes and the role of delinquent friends in delinquency. While
Hirschi suggested that delinquents would lack social bonds to anyone,
some researchers claim that bonding to delinquent peers is a key factor, if
not the key factor, in delinquency (see, for example, Elliott et al 1985).
68
A broader vision of crime

Hirschi (1979) is against the attempt to integrate elements of control


theory with elements from other theories, such as strain and social
learning (see, for example, Elliott et al 1985), when this involves taking
elements from theories that are based on very different assumptions about
human nature. He does, however, see that the approach is compatible with
some others, such as rational choice theory (Hirschi 1986), with its
calculative model of the actor. Steven Box (1971, 1981), although making
substantial use of the approach in his work, nevertheless suggested that it
had a rather narrow focus on the delinquent, rarely going beyond the
family, the peer group and the school in its analysis. In the end we need to
know why it is that some young people fail to become bonded to the
‘conventional’ social order. To answer that question surely needs a wider
perspective that takes into account the wider structures and processes of
society (such as those implied by the term ‘racism’), that influence the lives
and prospects of young people.
A further point often made is that the theory has been most used to
account for ‘ordinary’ juvenile delinquency, rather then other forms of
crime. Nelken (1997: 903), for example, suggests that it (at least in its
original format) is a ‘weak candidate for explaining white-collar crime’
because such individuals often appear to have substantial commitments.
However, the theory has been used extensively in attempting to account
for the low rates of crime of women compared to men (Heidensohn 1985,
1996; Hagan et al, 1979, 1985; Hagan 1988), and frequently appears as a
component in more broad-ranging theories of crime (see, for example,
Braithwaite 1989). Meanwhile, Hirschi himself appears to have drifted
away from his more sociologically inclined control theory, now pressing
the claims of a general theory of crime that stresses the role of low self-
control. This emphasises the importance of a relatively stable individual
characteristic, for which the major cause is seen as ineffective child rearing
(Gottfredson and Hirschi 1990) – a further example, perhaps, of the revival
of approaches focusing on the individual discussed in the last chapter.

Interactionism, labelling and moral panics

For much of its history, as we have seen, criminology has concentrated on


the question of aetiology: what are the original causes of crime and
delinquency? The attempts to answers this question have varied; bio-
logical, psychological and sociological approaches in particular have been
employed. Although control theory tried to ask the key question in a
rather different way, it was still concerned with the causes of conforming
and delinquent conduct. A rather different focus emerged from a group of
sociologists (e.g. Becker 1963: Lemert 1951, 1967) who were working
within the tradition of what is called symbolic interactionism, an approach

69
Introducing Criminology

which focuses upon the symbolic meanings and understandings which


are developed in the course of social interaction. Complex social inter-
action was seen as a rich field for investigation, and deviance, rather than
crime, became one of the objects of attention. Such an approach urged the
study of social processes such as the definition of deviance, social
reactions to it, and the emergence of deviant identity, which it felt had been
much neglected in the study of crime and deviance. Perhaps because of
some well known passages in the work of Howard Becker (1963),
commentators began to speak of the emergence of something called
labelling theory, even though the approach was not only concerned with
labelling, and, on its own admission, was hardly systematic or grand
enough to be called a theory in the strict sense. In addition, labelling could
be, and was, analysed with the help of a range of perspectives in sociology,
not just interactionism (Plummer 1979). The ‘labelling’ and interactionist
perspectives on deviance were not, therefore, identical.
It was the concept of labelling that caught the imagination, perhaps
because of a social context in countries like the USA and Britain of the late
1960s, which experienced such things as increasingly visible social
diversity, social change, new radical social movements, protest and civil
disobedience, with the power of the state and definitions of crime and
deviance becoming more open to question. Becker’s (1963: 9) statement
has now become something of a cliché:

social groups create deviance by making the rules whose infraction


constitutes deviance, and by applying those rules to particular
people and labelling them as outsiders. From this point of view,
deviance is not a quality of the act the person commits, but rather a
consequence of the application by others of rules and sanctions to an
‘offender’. The deviant is one to whom the label has successfully
been applied; deviant behaviour is behaviour that people so label.

As Schur (1971) suggested, labelling could take place at a number of levels.


First, that of collective rule making. The study of law making and the
origins of rules of various kinds had been much neglected in the past, but
became a key area of study. Becker (1963) led the way with his study of the
laws relating to drugs in the USA. Such studies raised questions about
power and politics, for laws were the result of a political process, and
helped to bring the study of power and the state to a more central position
in the study of criminology.
Second, labelling was a routine activity by those agents and organiza-
tions which were responsible for the identification and processing of
deviance. The perspective urged and undertook studies of the interaction
between alleged rule-breakers and those agencies. They explored the
possibility that such characteristics as social class, race, gender and

70
A broader vision of crime

demeanour could have a bearing on one’s chances of acquiring a deviant


label. Such studies cast the routine statistics produced by those agencies in
a new light. For example, crime statistics were reconceived by some as
indices of organizational processes, rather than as measures of criminal
behaviour (Kitsuse and Cicourel 1963). If such statistics were ‘socially
constructed’, what did this mean for all those criminological studies that
had used officially registered crime and offenders to develop theories of
crime?
Third, labelling could take place in interpersonal relations in everyday
interaction. What cues do people use to recognise a person as deviant? Are
stereotypes important in this? Once labelled, is there a tendency to
reinterpret the past as evidence that the person was ‘like that all along’
(retrospective reinterpretation)? And what of the consequences of being
labelled for individuals and groups concerned? Does the individual find
conventional opportunities, such as employment, more restricted? Is the
individual’s sense of self, or personal identity affected – do they begin to
think of themselves in a different way? And, finally, what are the con-
sequences of these processes for the future conduct of the individual? Is
further deviance more likely? Lemert (1967) introduced the concept of
secondary deviation, which referred to that deviation which is a response
to the problems created for the individual by the labelling process (or
social reaction, as he called it). Overall, Lemert was raising the possibility
that processes normally considered to operate as ‘social control’ could
have the opposite effect.
Such ironic possibilities were taken seriously on this side of the Atlantic,
but with a distinctive twist. Studies began to speak of a process of deviancy
amplification resulting from the labelling of certain individuals or groups,
such as drug-takers (Young 1971), or youth groups such as mods and
rockers (Cohen 1973a). Often implicated in this process were the mass
media, inflating concern about a particular problem and carrying
powerful messages about it, including the production and transmission of
stereotypes. Such processes might have a powerful impact on the group
concerned, including the amplification of their deviance (Young 1971). In a
distinctively British development of the labelling perspective, there
arrived the concepts of the folk devil and moral panic, concepts that have
been extensively used in criminology and sociology, with the latter
entering journalistic and everyday use. They were used in an important
study of the concern about ‘mugging’ in 1970s Britain, which suggested
that this was a moral panic, based on a label imported from the USA with-
out any firm basis in statistical trends, but which carried messages about
law and order, race, crime and the condition of Britain, and served as a
kind of scapegoat which drew attention away from the ‘real’ problems
facing British society at that time. (Hall et al 1978; for a critique of their use
of statistical data and the concept of moral panic, see Waddington 1986).

71
Introducing Criminology

Plummer (1979) has summarised the labelling approach as being con-


cerned with the nature, origins, application and consequences of deviancy
labels. There is little doubt that it has had an enormous impact on the
study of crime and deviance ever since, directing attention to new and
neglected questions. From the 1960s onwards, a significant body of work
began to focus upon the process of criminalization, rather than the
traditional study of the causes of crime, about which serious reservations
were being raised after many years of effort with fairly unimpressive
returns. The approach did, however, harbour certain confusions and
weaknesses.
First, there was confusion over whether it was a theory, providing us
with a systematic explanation of something (such as ‘career’ or secondary
deviance), or merely a perspective which raises distinctive questions and
issues. Plummer’s (1979) view is that only by regarding it as a perspective
will we appreciate its value. As a theory it seems one-sided and simplistic;
the idea that labelling may lead to further deviance may be useful as a
hypothesis, but one that has not proved to be very fruitful. It is now
thought better to ask under what circumstances labelling may have that
consequence. Braithwaite (1989), for example, has argued that ‘re-
integrative shaming’ of offenders may avoid the counterproductive con-
sequences that seem to follow from stigmatizing, exclusionary forms of
justice.
Second, the approach was criticised from the very start for its neglect of
the original causes or motivations for deviance. To some extent, this seems
unfair, for the approach never intended to cover this, but to be a corrective
to the overemphasis on this in the past. However, on its own, the per-
spective did have the consequence of ignoring such matters or seeing
them as trivial. At the very least, a truly interactionist approach should be
concerned with the meanings of action for the people concerned, even if
the search for original causes is regarded as a fruitless quest.
Third, the approach is often said to be deficient in its analysis of power
and structure. Gouldner (1975), for example, noted the concentration in
practice on the ‘local caretakers’ of social control and their dealings with
the deviant, rather than the sites of real power, such as in the state. Others,
such as Taylor et al (1973), suggested the approach lacked a developed
analysis of social structure and power, making it difficult to tackle such
questions as law-making. Some of the reasons for this might lie in the
interactionist foundations of key exponents, a framework better suited to
the analysis of deviance in social interaction. As we shall see, others who
felt they were better equipped for a broader structural analysis were
happy to take up such questions (see the next section on radical
criminologies).
Fourth, the overall image of the deviant created has been criticised: the
image, for example, as a passive victim of the labelling process, who

72
A broader vision of crime

appears ‘more sinned against than sinning’ (Gouldner 1975: 38). This may
romanticise the deviant, diverting attention from the original action and
the suffering created for any ‘real’ victims, who seem to have been
forgotten.

Radical criminologies

There is no single ‘radical’ criminology. It is not a unified and unchanging


body of ideas. Better to speak of radical criminologies, which perhaps
share in common a critique of ‘orthodox’, ‘establishment’ or ‘mainstream’
criminology, and a commitment to radical change, not only in the
discipline and the way in which we respond to crime, but in the wider
society, which is seen as intimately connected with crime and the response
to it. Beyond this, there is some diversity: for example, radical
criminologies can come from a variety of political positions (such as
Marxism, anarchism, feminism – in all of which there can be divergent
positions). Two developments justify separate sections: left realism (which
some do not feel qualifies as truly radical, in any case) and feminist
criminologies. In order to understand the origins and nature of radical
criminology, we need to go back to the late 1960s and early 1970s. In this
brief account, we shall concentrate on Britain.
The late 1960s saw the emergence of a group called the National
Deviancy Conference, a loosely organized group of sociologists and
activists who held a series of very well attended conferences, some of the
papers from which were subsequently published (see, for example, Cohen
1971). The group had perhaps two basic things in common: a dissatisfac-
tion with ‘traditional’ or mainstream criminology, and the fact that they
were much influenced by the labelling perspective. According to its critics,
British criminology had a distinctive character, with two features singled
out for particular criticism (see Cohen 1973b).
First, it was felt to have a clinical or psychological bias, with a
dominance of certain disciplines, such as psychiatry and psychology,
which tended to look for the sources of crime within the individual, rather
in the way described in the last chapter. Sociological questions were felt to
be neglected.
Second, it was considered to be dominated by correctional interests,
that is a concern with the causes of crime and ways of controlling
and managing it, rather than in attempting to understand it. Part of the
reason for this lay in the alliance between the Home Office and the
Cambridge Institute of Criminology, with the former having control of
much research funding and access to research sites. Understandably, the
Home Office would prefer to sponsor research that would serve the needs
of policy makers and practitioners, leading to a conservative, state-aligned

73
Introducing Criminology

discipline that failed to ask fundamental questions. Such questions were,


to some extent, being raised by the labelling perspective: questions about
the definition of deviance; questions about the way in which labels were
applied and the possibly counterproductive effects of this. Here was a
perspective that urged a shift in focus from crime to criminalization and
harboured a critique of the state, rather than serving its interests.
Some of those sharing these ideas nevertheless became dissatisfied by
some of the limitations of the labelling perspective which were outlined in
the last section. In particular, some felt that a more developed political
analysis of crime, law and social structure could be achieved. Taylor
Walton and Young’s The New Criminology (1973) is a key text in radical
criminology, and attempts to provide a comprehensive framework for a
‘fully social theory of deviance’. As such it shows the influence of both
Marxism and the labelling perspective in including the study of the wider
(in terms of ‘political economy’) and immediate (social psychological)
origins of social reaction to deviance and its consequences, but also the
study of the wider and immediate origins of the deviant action itself
(neglected by a focus on labelling alone). As for what to do about crime,
the punishment/treatment of individuals or piecemeal social reform
would not deal with the problem: fundamental social change was
necessary for that. The remarkable claim is made that the crime can be
abolished under certain circumstances – a socialist society in which there
would be:

• more toleration of diversity (and less inclination to criminalize);


• the abolition of inequalities of wealth and power, which would remove
the motivation for much crime;
• the eventual withering away of the state, without which crime, which is
defined by the state, would by definition disappear. New ways of
dealing with any rule-breaking behaviour would have to be developed.

Despite some omissions and controversial claims, the book has remained
an influence ever since, both as a rallying call for radical criminology and
an agenda for criminological study (see Walton and Young 1998). Few can
claim the capacity to cover all the required elements, but Hall et al’s (1978)
study of the social reaction to law and order issues in the 1970s, which
argues that moral panics do not occur randomly, but are related to
fundamental economic, political and social crises in society, is often given
as an example of an attempt to cover certain aspects of the agenda in the
way suggested, in particular to provide a political economy of social
reaction. In Taylor et al’s (1975) next book the emphasis was more firmly
upon the need for a materialist (Marxist) analysis of crime and law in
relation to capitalist society. Some of the comprehensiveness of the earlier

74
A broader vision of crime

framework seemed to have been lost, and the move towards Marxism was
typical of radical writings during the 1970s. At the end of the decade, the
National Deviancy Conference (1979) published a collection of papers
with the symptomatic subtitle, From Deviancy Theory to Marxism.
Gradually, criticisms began to accumulate, especially of radical crimi-
nology in its more exclusively Marxist guise. One of the first came from
within Marxism itself, when Hirst (1975) suggested that the quest for a
Marxist criminology was a misguided one. Marx himself had very little to
say about crime in his writings. This was not an oversight, for crime is not
a particularly appropriate topic for Marxist analysis and peripheral to that
framework. In Hirst’s view, a Marxist criminology was just about as viable
as a Marxist analysis of sport. To be fair, Marxism was able to provide
answers (perhaps flawed or incomplete) to questions about the political
economy of social control, the state and its structures of law, but it was less
equipped to deal with the details of crime, except perhaps to suggest in a
rather simplistic way that it represented a form of rebellion against the
capitalist order, a means of survival, or an aspect of the class struggle. At
the very least, the approach needed to be supplemented by other
perspectives, but radical criminologists of this grouping were rarely
interested in empirical research on crime itself, with their sights firmly
fixed elsewhere.
A further criticism singled out what it saw as the undue utopianism of
the approach. If only a transformation of the social order is worthwhile,
with piecemeal reform seen as pointless, this may lead to a self-imposed
exclusion from important policy debates about issues that have real
consequences for people’s lives. Such an outcome also has the effect of
leaving the field open to one’s political opponents, in this case those from
the right. Indeed, during the late 1970s and early 1980s, ‘New Right’
conservatism in Britain and the USA seemed to have made the law and
order issue its own, with socialism appearing to offer few ‘realistic’
proposals about how to tackle rising crime. Jock Young (1986) has since
argued that the approach (with which he was previously associated) failed
to take crime and people’s fears of it seriously, including the real harm
inflicted by poor people on other poor people. This could hardly be
regarded as a redistribution of property, rebellion or aspect of the class
struggle. An overly romantic image of the criminal was conveyed, seen as
an embryonic class warrior, a present-day Robin Hood, redistributing
private property, with victims and the harm they experience sorely
neglected. It was in this context that Young and his colleagues argued for a
more ‘realistic’ approach from the left, that would take crime and its
victims seriously: left realism (see below p.79–82).
Further blows to the notion that a Marxist analysis would provide the
answers to crime and other problems of contemporary life occurred in the
form of the collapse of Marxist-inspired states and faith in its principles as

75
Introducing Criminology

a recipe for political and social organization, especially in Eastern Europe.


The influence of Marxism has declined greatly since the 1970s in crimi-
nology as elsewhere. A final point to mention is that made by the emerging
group of feminist scholars who began to take an interest in crime and
criminal justice; although there are many references to class in radical
criminology, issues of gender are much neglected in their studies. This is
surprising, since it appears that gender is a better predictor of crime than
class. We consider in more detail the feminist contribution below.
The impact of the radical programme has been enormous. Coupled
with the labelling perspective, the questions it has raised continue to
influence criminology in a profound way. It is now a very different dis-
cipline from that which existed in the 1960s. Not only have they influenced
others, but the radical pioneers continue to produce work that is
distinguished by its breadth of vision (see, for example, Taylor 1999, who
has carried forward the study of the political economy of crime and the
response to it). Of those who have been much influenced, it is worth
mentioning those who still call for a ‘critical criminology’ (see, for
example, Scraton and Chadwick 1991). The focus is still on the power of
the state to criminalize, but the analysis of power has also been influenced
by the French commentator Michel Foucault, with his views that power is
exercised in many sites other than the state, and that knowledge and
power are intimately connected. The vision is broader in other ways too:
responding to some of the above criticisms, the focus is still upon class, but
upon gender, race and sexuality too, and the institutionalized forms of
discrimination and criminalization based upon them. Although referred to
disparagingly by Young as remaining examples of ‘left idealism’, these
developments are important in the picture of contemporary criminology.

Feminist perspectives

Following the rapid development of the feminist movement in the 1960s,


various academic disciplines began to feel the impact of a new set of
criticisms and ideas. It was the 1970s before this impact was much felt
within criminology. At first, it took the form of a critique of mainstream
criminology (see, for example Klein 1973; Smart 1976), which began by
observing that women had been largely ignored in the discipline. The
literature was based almost entirely on studies of men and boys. When
women did occasionally make an appearance, they were treated in
unsatisfactory ways, subject to biological and psychological assumptions
of a stereotypical and sexist nature. Pollak (1961), for example, argued that
the devious and deceitful nature of women led to their contribution to
crime being much underestimated by official statistics. Although one of
the most striking things about crime rates, however they are measured, is

76
A broader vision of crime

the way in which men far outnumber women in their rates of offending,
gender was nevertheless given relatively little attention, even by the
emerging radical criminology. Following this critique, a number of studies
began to appear, as if to fill the gaps and deficiencies that had been
identified. This work focused on a number of topics and areas, such as:

• the issue of whether theories of mainstream criminology could be


adapted in order to explain the crimes of women, or, at least, their low
crime rates? If not, what kinds of theories would be useful? (Leonard
1982)
• empirical research on women and girls and their involvement in crime,
such as the study of delinquent girls in gangs (Campbell 1984);
• women as victims of crime, especially those often committed by men
and involving actual or the threat of violence, such as rape, sexual abuse
and harassment, and domestic violence (e.g. Stanko 1985). Most
famously, Brownmiller (1975) put forward a new interpretation of rape,
which saw it as power-based, the fear of which contributed to the
subordination of women, affecting their lives and choices in subtle but
pervasive ways;
• the treatment of women by the criminal justice system, as offenders and
as victims (Eaton 1986; Edwards 1984). For example, are women
offenders treated more harshly or more leniently than men?
• the role of women in social control, such as the study of women police
officers (Heidensohn 1992).

Such studies, of which only a few examples have been given, were often
conducted from a broadly feminist viewpoint, leading some to suggest
that a feminist criminology had emerged (for far more comprehensive
overviews, see Heidensohn 1985, 1996; Walklate 1995). As the title of
Gelsthorpe and Morris’ (1990) book indicated, however, it was more
accurate to speak of feminist perspectives in criminology, for there were a
number of differences in approach. It would be fair to say that, in the early
days at least, feminists had a broad concern with exposing and working to
free women from a broad range of limitations and oppressions that they
experienced. The overall quest was in this sense a gendered one, that
sought to emancipate women from those problems. In criminology and
criminal justice, this might range from correcting the way in which women
and gender had been ill-served by criminology, to attempting to rectify the
way in which rape victims are treated by the criminal justice system.
There were, however, clearly important differences within feminism
itself which manifested themselves in different emphases and approaches
towards crime and criminal justice. There are a number of ways in which

77
Introducing Criminology

these differences can be considered. For example, we can identify differen-


ces in broad political ideas, which lead to different interpretations of the
origins of the problem to be addressed, the strategy to be taken towards it,
and the kind of ideal arrangements towards which to work.
• Liberal feminism is said to be concerned with equal rights and equality of
opportunity for women (Gelsthorpe 1997: 512) and has concentrated on
sex differentials in crime and discriminatory practices in the criminal
justice system in its research (Walklate 1998: 73).
• Radical feminism, on the other hand, has focused on the oppression of
women by men in particular, and has concentrated on women as
victims (‘survivors’, a more positive term, is preferred) of ‘date’, marital
and other rape, domestic violence, murder and child abuse (Walklate
1998: 75).
• Socialist feminism sees women’s oppression as rooted in patriarchal
capitalism, seeing the need to consider the interaction of gender and
class in understanding crime (see, for example, Messerschmidt 1993)
and for fundamental economic and social change to tackle the roots of
women’s oppression.
Smart (1990), following Harding (1986) has suggested that feminist per-
spectives can also be distinguished in terms of their views on the nature
and status of knowledge (epistemology) and methodology. Much of the
early work can be seen as feminist empiricism – the attempt to provide those
studies on women, crime and criminal justice that were absent, studies
that would provide the knowledge needed to argue for policies to address
their oppression.
Standpoint feminism, on the other hand, argues that more research, more
knowledge, will not necessarily serve the feminist cause; knowledge that
conveyed the perspectives and experiences of women themselves,
achieved through the struggle against oppression, would only be ade-
quate to the task.
Finally, ‘postmodern feminism’, influenced by ideas we consider in more
detail in a later section, questions our capacity to speak of ‘women’ as
subjects with common experiences and rights; instead, diversity and
change in women’s experiences and identities are stressed. Its approach is
broadly ‘deconstructionist’: it seeks to analyse bodies of ‘knowledge’, their
construction, language, key concepts and their links with power. It is also
suspicious of ‘master narratives’ – grand theories and their associated
programmes for change. It can be seen that such a perspective is likely to
engender antagonism from those more traditional feminists who have
stressed the importance of a gendered emancipatory project in the
interests of ‘women’ – from the postmodern perspective, a subject within a
master narrative needing deconstruction? Smart (1990: 77) herself feels

78
A broader vision of crime

that it is time for feminism to abandon criminology – a discipline she sees


as trapped within the modernist project (see later sections of this chapter),
unable to deconstruct crime, for this would ‘involve abandoning the idea
of a unified problem [crime] which requires a unified response – at least, at
the theoretical level’.
With such a variety of positions, it is difficult to provide an overall
assessment. A starting-point might be to say that there has often been a
neglect of important considerations other than gender in the study of
crime, victimization and justice. Marcia Rice (1990) made the key point
that black women were missing from such studies and writings. A similar
point could be made about class, although socialist feminism is an
exception here. The uncritical use of terms such as patriarchy, capitalism,
oppression, and ‘women’ has tended to suggest that the predicament of
women is pretty much the same everywhere, although, as Carrington
(1998) suggests, we do not need to accept the whole postmodernist
package to recognise diversity and change. A further point is that much of
the early work focused, understandably, on women as offenders, victims
and in the criminal justice system. A more recent development promises to
contribute to a more fully gendered criminology (rather than a woman-
centred one) by looking at the role of masculinities, including their relation
to crime (Connell 1987, 1995; Messerschmidt 1993; Jefferson 1997), thus
counteracting the rather one-dimensional view of men, masculinity and
male power conveyed by some feminist writings.
Both Carlen (1992) and Gelsthorpe (1997) disagree with Smart’s (1990)
rejection of criminology. Carlen suggests that such a view fails to recognise
the greater theoretical diversity and flexibility of some recent criminology,
and that a deconstructionist approach can be used within it. She also feels
that although postmodern ideas about knowledge and so on are difficult
to link with political struggles, an abandonment of criminology would be
to abandon women who are affected by crime and the criminal justice
system to their fate. Better to work through such problems and to connect
with political struggles for change. For Gelsthorpe (1997: 528), although
there are useful insights to be had from postmodern approaches to
discourse and knowledge, they have little to say about concrete practices
and principles, such as visions of justice. For Naffine (1997), deconstruc-
tion on its own cannot change the institutional structures that keep
traditional practices and meanings in place.

Left realism

Left realism as a collection of ideas came to prominence within the


particular context of Britain in the early 1980s. A Conservative government
appeared to have captured the law and order issue as its own, employing

79
Introducing Criminology

it as a major plank of its electoral strategy, and successfully convincing


significant groups in the population that tough measures were needed to
deal with a rising tide of crime and disorder (including industrial conflict).
The opposition was in disarray, and seemingly unable to come up with
policies that could compete. For Young, the existing radical criminology
(what he came to call ‘left idealism’) was little help, with its reluctance to
see crime as the problem or to enter into immediate policy debates, while
the establishment criminology of the Home Office, with its focus on such
matters as crime prevention and rational choice, had little regard to the
wider structural context and its role in causing crime. The time seemed
opportune for a framework coming from the left of the political spectrum
(but nearer the centre than previous radical criminologies) that would
‘take crime seriously’ and come up with ‘realistic’ policies that would
connect with the public and help the Labour Party to recover lost ground.
It was therefore grounded in social democratic ideas, rather than those of
the far left. There are a number of key components.

• In one of the earlier statements of the approach, Young (1986: 21)


claimed that the ‘central tenet of left realism is to reflect the reality of
crime, that is in its origins, its nature and its impact’. A quest for com-
prehensiveness runs throughout, stressing the need to avoid the partial
nature of other criminologies; for example, left idealism is said to focus
upon criminalization, but rarely on crime or victims. More recent
accounts of the perspective (Young 1994, 1997) have put forward ‘the
square of crime’ as a framework, stressing the need to examine four
elements and their relationships: victims, offenders, formal agencies of
social control, and the public (informal control). Crime rates, for
example, can only be understood in terms of the interaction between
these four elements.
• The acceptance that crime is a problem, to be taken seriously, and
that there is a rational core to people’s fears of it. It is thought important
to avoid the view conveyed by left idealism that concern about crime
was a moral panic, or the kind of hysteria often to be found in the mass
media.
• A return to the aetiology (the study of causes) of crime, a topic neglected
by both left idealism and the new administrative criminology of the
Home Office. Explanations draw heavily on such frameworks as
anomie and subcultural theory: ‘Crime is one form of subcultural
adaptation which occurs where material circumstances block cultural
aspirations and where non-criminal alternatives are absent or less
attractive’ (Young 1997: 490). From the beginning, substantial use has
been made of the concept of relative deprivation (where people feel
themselves to be deprived in relation to others with whom they

80
A broader vision of crime

compare themselves), which is said to be applicable to crime through-


out the social structure, not only to economic crime, and does not make
the error of assuming that deprivation per se will lead to crime.
Explanations of victimization and the state’s reaction to crime are also
required.
• As part of its mission to convey the impact of crime, realism stresses the
need to base this on people’s experiences. Thus there is a need for
research to provide ‘an accurate victimology’ (Young 1986: 23), which
will tell us who is vulnerable to crime, and the effects on their lives. Left
realists have therefore been involved in a number of local crime
surveys, which attempt to chart these and related matters, such as the
Islington Crime Surveys (Jones et al, 1986; Crawford et al; 1990), and
those in Merseyside (Kinsey 1984) and Edinburgh (Anderson et al,
1990). Such surveys are said to need complementing with smaller-scale
qualitative studies. It has thus attempted to take seriously victims and
fear of crime, concerns said to be lacking in left idealism.
• A willingness to contribute to policy debates of the immediate, as well
as the long-term variety. As an example, a case was made for increased
democratic accountability of the police to improve relations between
communities and the police, which, it was argued, would lead to
increased flows of information and improved detection rates for crime
(Lea and Young 1984). Left realism is anxious to avoid the ‘impos-
sibilism’ of left idealism, said to be dismissive of piecemeal reform and
only interested in fundamental social and political change. Realism has
stressed the need for a multi-agency approach and intervention at all
levels, although priority is given to intervention at the level of the social
causes of crime (Young 1997: 492).
The impact of left realism has been great, including offshoots in other
countries such as Canada (e.g. MacLean 1992). Walklate (1998: 70) con-
cludes that it has ‘certainly shifted the academic agenda and contributed
to the policy one both locally and nationally’ but that it remains to be seen
if it has added to our understanding of crime. She makes the point that the
reliance on relative deprivation as a key concept does not provide a
broader picture of the political economy of crime, in the way that Currie’s
(1985) version of realism (in the USA) does. The most recent works of
Young (1997, 1999), however, attempt to cover this ground in some depth.
Left realism has been criticised for its uncritical and conventional
definition of crime, which is said merely to reflect media, political and
public concepts, and leads to a focus on street crime. Pearce and Tombs
(1992: 96) argued that the still ‘individual-centred nature of much left
realist writing’ is a handicap in the study of corporate crime, where, for
example, the individual offender–individual victim scenario does not
typically apply.
81
Introducing Criminology

The reliance on victim surveys as a method of research has also


been questioned. To what extent can these imperfect instruments, with
their focus on the attitudes and experiences of individuals, be used as
a basis to reflect ‘reality’, with its complex web of wider relationships, such
as those involving power? How can a policy agenda be compiled from
these responses, even after the required debate between the public and the
expert? Doesn’t this leave a lot of questions unanswered
about how the policy-making process can be managed (Walklate 1998:
62)?
Some have complained that the policy recommendations of the left
realists do not challenge existing power relations and are ‘politically
conservative in [their] conclusions about what can be done about the state’
(Sim et al, 1987: 59), and that they often do not differ much from the more
liberal ones of the Home Office (Downes and Rock 1998: 300). Although
left realism has stressed the importance of class, gender, race and age,
feminists in particular have argued that it has not examined their
interrelationships, with an overemphasis on the first (Edwards 1989)
and inadequacy on the second (Cain 1986: 261). To these points, it might
be added that left realism has chosen to ally itself with a political
party (Labour). It is not difficult to imagine that this may create its own
problems and constraints. For Brown and Hogg (1992: 145), for example,
this is one reason why left realism might be using an uncritical
(conventional) concept of crime – ‘as an ideological unifier: a mode for
expressing the “real” and common interests of working-class people’, as a
way of connecting with the public, gaining votes and support for party
policies.
Like almost all criminology to date, left realism is committed to what
has been called the modernist project: the quest for knowledge of a
privileged kind, a belief in progress and the solution of problems through
the application of science and reason. Left realism and criminology in
general have experienced the challenge of postmodernism, as have other
social sciences. Postmodernism challenges the nature of criminology as a
discipline. It questions our ability to grasp and represent some ‘social
reality’ out there. It challenges the use of terms like ‘crime’, ‘victim’ as if
they refer to some unified body of items with some essential nature in
common. It challenges the ability of any criminology to make claims to
‘truth’ or objective knowledge, including those about the causes of crime.
For postmodernism, left realism is hopelessly stuck in the past, unable to
respond to these challenges, with its emphasis on representing the ‘reality’
of crime, and the ‘lived realities’ of victims, its quest for causes, and its
search for knowledge that will assist in formulating those policies that will
advance human progress. In the postmodern view, left realism, and most
criminology, appears to be a hopeless case. It is time to look at the themes
of postmodernism in more detail.

82
A broader vision of crime

Postmodernity, postmodernism and the modernist project

Postmodernism, despite the label, is not a uniform and consistent body of


ideas. It is more a collection of themes, which have their origins in the
work of a number of thinkers, who would not necessarily want to be
grouped under the title, and would not agree with each other on every
detail, or even on certain major ideas. If this is not confusing enough, the
language in which the material is expressed is frequently a barrier to
communication, and there are at least two rather different sets of themes
that are often discussed under the heading.
The first concerns the nature of the society in which we live, or are
currently moving towards. Are the structural characteristics which we
associate with ‘modern’ society, such as the class structure, industrialism
and the nation state being replaced by new forms of relationships and
organisation that are sufficiently different from the ‘modern’ to be called
‘postmodern’? Are consumerism and global information and communica-
tion technologies producing very different forms of culture and social
organisation, including our sense of time and space (Lyon 1999: 3)?
These are huge questions which cannot be answered here, but it is
worth noting that the influential work of Giddens (1990, 1991) argues that
despite important social changes, modernity is still with us: the concept of
late modernity is currently more appropriate than that of postmodernity. It
is important that the implications of such changes for crime and crime
control are explored by criminologists (see, for example, Bottoms and
Wiles, 1997: 349–354; Lea 1998). Another reason why those who are happy
to investigate such changes, however, may not be so happy to accept the
label of ‘postmodernist’ is the presence of a second set of themes that are
often grouped under the heading, themes that concern the nature and
status of knowledge – epistemology: ‘ “Post-modernism” in the hands of
some writers has had methodological links with epistemological
relativism, an intellectual position we reject, and so we would prefer “late
modernity” in order to focus on the empirical transformations presently
taking place’ (Bottoms and Wiles 1997: 349). To put it crudely, ‘epistemo-
logical relativism’ is seen as getting in the way of describing what is going
on.
Perhaps the most frequently quoted statement used to identify the first
key idea in this respect is: ‘Simplifying to the extreme, I define postmodern
as incredulity towards metanarratives’ (Lyotard 1984: xxiv). Since the
European Enlightenment of the eighteenth century, reason and science in
particular (a main metanarrative), have been seen as the provider of
knowledge that will bring emancipation. Any overarching system of
thought that claims to tell us what is ‘really’ going on the world and how
to solve our problems can be regarded as a metanarrative, such as
Marxism, feminism and criminology itself. Postmodernism is thus

83
Introducing Criminology

incredulous towards such ambitious claims to knowledge, truth and


emancipation, seeing these activities as networks of ‘language games’.
A second key idea is ‘deconstruction’ – that accounts, texts, discourses
are never settled or stable and can be broken down to show how they have
been constructed and what themes have been accentuated or repressed in
the process. Such ‘knowledges’ are thus intimately connected with the
operation of power, in their origins and their effects. We have seen earlier
how some have argued for the need to deconstruct concepts such as crime,
victim, women, men, masculinity, and so on to reveal the diversity and
differences hidden by such unifying terms, as well as whole bodies of
knowledge, such as mainstream criminology, to reveal ‘repressed’ or
hidden subjects, such as women and gender. The implication that all
knowledge is relative, never objective, certain or absolute, is what is meant
by the ‘epistemological relativism’ referred to above.
According to some, something similar to deconstruction has been going
on for some time, but without the title. For example, the labelling
perspective made the concepts of crime and deviance problematic in a
similar way, as we saw in an earlier section. The main problem with pure
deconstruction, according to Lea (1998) is that of ‘infinite regress’: that any
deconstruction that takes place can itself be deconstructed. With
postmodernism, any stopping point appears to be arbitrary. In addition,
while the approach can point to the origins and effects of ‘knowledges’ in
terms of power, it has no developed account of power, so that its
contribution to our understanding is limited. Similarly, the rejection of
metanarratives appears to distance the postmodernist from any overall
concept of justice or rationality and how we might strive to achieve them.
Bearing these points in mind, it is hardly surprising that postmodernism is
often accused of producing practical and political inertia.
Some do not despair, seeing a way out of this dark forest, arguing that
although pure deconstruction may be appropriate in the realms where it
originated, such as the analysis of literary texts, it is hardly enough in
the ‘real’ world with which criminology connects, a world of human
suffering where immediate measures and a longer-term strategy are
required. For Stan Cohen(1998), a kind of double life is called for: ‘[s]urely
it is possible to be sceptical and ironical at the level of theory – yet at the
level of policy and politics to be firmly committed’ – not expecting the
kind of integration between theory and practice advocated by Marxists
and left realists. The pragmatic position offered by Cohen seems to rather
different from that of those who deconstruct (or ‘demystify’, or ‘debunk’)
one account of ‘reality’, ‘surface appearances’ or ‘common sense’ and
produce a different account produced in accordance with some master
narrative, an activity that many sociologists, Marxists and others have
been attempting for years. Lea (1998: 172) suggests that this is in a way
what Carol Smart (1990) does in giving privileged status to the accounts

84
A broader vision of crime

provided by certain subjects, such as lesbians, gays, black people, Asians


and feminists.
Most remarkable is the ‘postmodernist constitutive’ theory of crime
developed by Henry and Milovanovic (1996). They contrast those who
practise deconstruction alone (sceptical postmodernists) with those like
themselves (affirmative postmodernists), who ‘retain revised elements of
modernism, particularly the idea that deconstruction also implies
reconstruction, and who use deconstructionist epistemology as the basis
towards reconstructing a replacement text/discourse that goes beyond the
nihilistic limits of the sceptical position ...’ (Henry and Milovanovic 1996:
5). What follows is their own account of human nature, society and social
order, the role of law, definition of crime, crime causation, and justice
policy and practices. In a sense, therefore, they too are replacing one
‘metanarrative’ with another. This shows how difficult it can be to follow
the postmodern deconstructionist approach through to its conclusion, for
most criminologists are reluctant to abandon entirely the project which
gave their discipline its reason for existence – the modernist project.
Although the foregoing discussion may seem very abstract and academic,
it raises a key issue for criminology and criminologists – how to manage
the relationship between theory and practice, between intellectual
detachment and political commitment, between doubt and action. In the
case of postmodernist ideas, this dilemma is raised in a particularly stark
form, but is there for all criminologies.

Conclusion

This chapter has attempted to give an overview of a range of sociological


and other broadly based perspectives in criminology. In doing so, a
number of themes have emerged. First, that these perspectives relate
questions about crime to aspects of the wider society, in their different
ways, from the Chicago School with its focus on the city, to feminism with
its focus on gender and power relations. Second, we have seen that the
earlier approaches took as their major task to identify the (social) causes of
crime. Gradually, different perspectives began to emerge which saw the
concept of crime as problematic, an issue we also discussed in the first
chapter of this book. In these perspectives, the focus shifted from the study
of causes of crime to the study of how certain acts and persons came to be
defined as criminal; in other words, the focus was on criminalization and
the notion that crime was a social construct.
For some (e.g. Taylor et al, 1973), the study of criminalization was a
neglected but complementary (to the study of the origins of deviant
action) field of study for any comprehensive criminology For others, the
question of the ‘causes of crime’ was no longer a question worth asking:

85
Introducing Criminology

If it is the case that ‘crime’ is a status accorded to some acts and not
others at some times and not others and in some places and not
others, and that those acts are engaged in to some degree by most
people at least some of the time, then it is highly questionable
whether there is anything special that needs to be explained about
criminal acts.
(Hester and Eglin 1992: 269)

The above statement is worth careful study; it is one version of a view that
has been advanced since the 1960s. Although it is true that the quest for the
causes of crime went into some decline in the 1970s, there has been a
revival of interest in the topic in recent years, including from the left
realists, who see crime as a problem that needs to be taken seriously in
terms of explanation and the need to do something about it on a social
level. As in the past, the understanding of causes is often taken to assist
in the development of crime control policies.
Although Henry and Milovanovic (1996: 152) suggest that sceptical
postmodernist thought denies the possibility of causal statements, they
find this ‘too extreme’ and their own ‘affirmative postmodernism’
develops its own approach to causality. We find, therefore, a diverse and
rather confusing picture among these broader perspectives in crimi-
nology; for example, if the prime focus of criminology is the study of
crime, there is no clear agreement about the appropriate questions to ask
about it. This diversity and dissensus is one thing that makes criminology
such a challenging subject. This chapter has attempted to provide a guide
to some of the major differences and disagreements.

86
Thinking seriously about serial killers

Chapter 4

Thinking seriously about


serial killers

This chapter is concerned with a topic of apparently great fascination.


Serial killers seem to be all around us – judging from films, books and
magazines of the ‘true crime’ genre. And yet, thankfully, they are a
relatively thin on the ground in the ‘real world’, despite the attempts of
some to ‘talk up’ the problem. Although your chances of coming across an
active serial killer in one week’s TV viewing are quite high, you are
unlikely to meet one as you go about your everyday activities. Why the
fascination with the topic? Does it connect with deep-seated anxieties and
fears, providing an ambivalent mix of repulsion and excitement, giving us
the ability to feel a rush of adrenaline from the safety of our armchairs? Are
there vested interests at work, realising that careers and fortunes can be
made riding on the back of the topic, if packaged in a particular way?
It may be that some will scoff at our inclusion of this topic, suggesting
that it is sensationalist, attempting to pull in readers in any way that we
can. At the same time, looking at serial killers can tell us something about
criminology’s attempt to grapple with the understanding of crime. What
steps are usually taken in this quest? What problems arise? What
perspectives are commonly employed? The chapter will begin by asking
‘what is serial murder?’ Then we shall look at estimates of its extent and
trends over time, before moving on to the attempt to divide it into a
number of different types. We shall then examine what progress has been
made in trying to understand such murders and the people who carry
them out, looking in particular at the contributions of biology, psychology
and sociology. Finally, we shall attempt to place the ‘serial murder
problem’ in a broader context. What does it tell us about ourselves, our
society and our culture? The topic thus provides an illustration of a
number of different approaches to the study of crime, many of which have
been introduced in earlier chapters.

87
Introducing Criminology

Murder most horrid: defining serial murder

Criminologists often begin by defining key terms to be used in their


enquiries. This is a wise move, for failure to do so can lead to confusion.
Although Holmes and Holmes (1998:9) begin their well known book on
serial murder by saying that ‘for the purposes of this book, homicide and
murder are used interchangeably’, the term homicide can be used very
broadly to refer to any killing of a human being. This may therefore cover
a wide variety of circumstances, including where a sentence of death is
carried out after a trial, or in armed combat when countries are at war. We
might say that criminologists are concerned with unlawful homicides,
although this does not put an end to the matter to everyone’s satisfaction.
Legal codes, whether within one state territory or international ones,
saying what is lawful and unlawful, are not necessarily uncontested or
unchanging. Consider the execution of King Charles I of England, who
lost his head in 1649. By the 1660s, following the restoration of the
monarchy, the dominant definition of the event had become murder, and
those found to be primarily responsible were savagely punished. All of
this underscores the point made earlier in this book that power and
political authority are important elements in defining crimes.
In England and Wales, there are three major types of homicide which
are violations of criminal law: murder; manslaughter; and infanticide.
Murder is the unlawful killing of another with ‘malice afore-thought’,
whereas manslaughter in unlawful killing without malice expressed or
implied. Infanticide is an offence created by the Infanticide Act 1922
(amended 1938) to cover cases where a woman causes the death of her
child (under 12 months in age) while the balance of her mind is affected by
the experience of giving birth or its after-effects. A number of other related
offences are classified separately in Criminal Statistics England and Wales
(Home Office 1998), such as causing death by dangerous or careless
driving.
Many murders involve only one event and one victim. Where there are
a number of murders committed by the same individual or group, this is
referred to as multiple murder. Holmes and Holmes (1998) have suggested
three types of this: mass murder; spree murder; and serial murder. Mass
murder, according to them, involves three or more victims, in a single
episode, although there may be short interruptions (to look for further
victims, for example), and takes place in the same general geographical
area. An example is the case of Thomas Hamilton, who in 1996 went into a
school in Dunblane, Scotland and opened fire, killing sixteen children, a
teacher, and himself. Spree murder is also said to involve at least three
victims, but the killings occur within a thirty-day time period and take
place in more than one location. To these three items, Holmes and Holmes
add a fourth to their definition: that the spree is also accompanied by

88
Thinking seriously about serial killers

another felony (i.e. another criminal offence). This would be better left out
of the definition; they admit that we do not have the information on how
many spree murders are connected to other offences, which suggests that
this should not be considered a defining characteristic in the present state
of knowledge.
The suggested dividing line between mass and spree murder is by no
means clear cut. Consider the case of Michael Ryan, who shot and killed
one victim, drove to a petrol station and shot at the attendant, and then
drove to the town of Hungerford, where he killed fifteen people before
shooting himself. Is this a mass or spree murder? Some feel that the
concept of spree murder should be omitted altogether as an unnecessary
complication (Hickey, 1997). Holmes and Holmes (1998) also suggest that
both spree and mass murder, unlike serial murders, have no ‘emotional
cooling off period’ between killings. Again, it may be unwise to imply that
such a cooling off cannot happen within an arbitrarily chosen thirty-day
period, and will always happen in any longer period. We must remember
that such definitions and distinctions are produced by the commentator
and are not ‘natural’ categories; as such, they are more or less useful
depending on how helpful they in achieving what their purpose, such as
staking out a field of study in a clear and helpful way.
According to Holmes and Holmes (1998) the third type of multiple
murder, serial murder, involves three or more victims, who are killed over a
time period of more than thirty days, with a ‘significant cooling-off period’
between the killings. Examples from England that fit this definition spring
readily to mind: Peter Sutcliffe, the ‘Yorkshire Ripper’, known to have
killed thirteen women before capture in 1980; Dennis Nilsen, who is
believed to have killed up to sixteen people in the early 1980s; Fred West,
who was accused of twelve murders before committing suicide in prison
before he could be brought to trial, and his wife Rosemary, who was
convicted in 1995 of murdering ten women and girls; Harold Shipman, the
family doctor, who in January 2000 was convicted of the murder of fifteen
mostly elderly patients and, according to the Manchester coroner, may
have been responsible for many more. In the light of this brief list of some
of the best known cases, consider the extensive definition offered by Egger
(1990: 4):

A serial murder occurs when one or more individuals (males, in


most known cases) commit a second and/or subsequent murder;
is relationshipless (no prior relationship between the victim and
attacker); is at a different time and has no apparent connection to
the initial murder; and is usually committed in a different geographi-
cal location. Further, the motive is not for material gain and is
believed to be for the murderer’s desire to have power over his
victims. Victims may have symbolic value and are perceived to be

89
Introducing Criminology

prestigeless and in most instances are unable to defend themselves


or alert others to their plight, or are perceived as powerless given
their situation in time, place or status within their immediate
surroundings (such as vagrants, prostitutes, migrant workers,
homosexuals, missing children, and single and often elderly
women).

This passage is giving us a lot of useful information about what may


indeed be common or typical characteristics of serial murder, the circum-
stances under which it is committed, the motivation behind it and the
attributes of victims. This is, however, not the same thing as a definition,
which attempts to identify what all instances share in common. In
addition, certain apparently required elements in the above can be
questioned. It is unwise to stipulate that there is always no prior
relationship between the victim and attacker (in many of the cases
involving the Wests and Shipman, there were clearly such relationships),
and that material gain never enters into the situation (see Hickey 1990 on
these points).
Eagle-eyed readers might also have noticed that Egger’s definition
merely requires a minimum of two murders to be included, whereas
Holmes and Holmes require at least three. Other writers seem to be
operating with a minimum figure of four killings (Levin and Fox 1985).
Such matters may seem unimportant, but can lead to confusion, such as
when attempts are made to assess the extent of serial murder. If people are
using different figures as part of the definition, they will come up with
different estimates (see below).
It is crucial to keep in mind the purpose for which definitions are to be
employed. In the early stages of investigation, it is best to have something
as brief as possible which seems to encapsulate some basic necessary
characteristics such as in the following definition:

Serial homicide involves the murder of separate victims with time


breaks between victims, as minimal as two days to weeks or months.
These time breaks are referred to as a ‘cooling off period’.
(Ressler, Burgess, D’Agostino and Douglas 1984, in Egger 1990: 5)

Such a definition has the advantage of not building in too many assump-
tions at an early stage.
We have already made the point that Egger’s (1990) attempt at a
definition is nevertheless useful in identifying some common character-
istics which have emerged from research on serial murder. It is important
to identify these, for they can have major implications. For example, if
serial murders tend to be ones in which there is no prior relationship
between offender and victim, this contrasts with much ‘ordinary murder’.

90
Thinking seriously about serial killers

In the majority of cases of murder, there is a pre-existing relationship


between the killer and the victim. In 1997, 54 per cent of male victims and
79 per cent of female victims in England and Wales knew the main or only
suspect before the murder (Home Office 1998: 70). This feature has the
consequence that such crimes are often relatively easy to solve. This,
together with the fact that greater resources are devoted to such crimes for
obvious reasons, means that they have a very high clear-up rate (in 1997,
the clear-up rate for homicide was 90 per cent). If, by contrast, serial
murders are typically ones in which there is no prior relationship of the
usual kind, these offences will be correspondingly difficult to clear up. In
such instances, it is easy to see the attractions of investing in such
techniques as offender profiling, which attempts to make judgements
about the characteristics of the perpetrator from the way in which the
attack was carried out, and the scene of the crime.

How many serial murders, murderers and victims?

Without accurate quantitative assessments of the extent of serial


murder, we will be unable to develop informed typologies, theories,
and policy decisions. Indeed, we run the risk of creating a social
problem, the magnitude of which may be grossly exaggerated.
(Kiger 1990: 36)

Once criminologists have looked at the definition of what they are


studying, the next step is often to assess the extent of it. Assessing the
extent of crime, offenders and victims is a notoriously difficult problem
for criminology, which has been described as having been haunted by
the ‘dark figure’ of hidden (unrecorded) crime throughout much of its
history (Coleman and Moynihan 1996). The problems are particularly
difficult in the area of serial murder, as we shall see. There are no routinely
collected statistics that provide us with figures for this category of murder,
although there are such statistics for the broad categories of homicide
referred to earlier (murder, manslaughter and infanticide). Other ways of
collecting numerical information about crime commonly used by
criminologists do not help much. Victims of serial murder find it
understandably impossible to take part in victimisation surveys, and
offenders of this type may be reluctant to confess such acts in a self-report
study!
The absence of any ready-made figures on serial murder has not
stopped people making estimates. For example, Holmes and DeBurger
(1988) suggested that a ‘reliable’ estimate for the number of victims each
year in the USA ranges from 3,500 to 5,000. They calculate this on the
following basis:

91
Introducing Criminology

• there are about 5,000 murder victims where the offender is unknown in
the USA each year;
• between a quarter and two-thirds of these, they suggest, are victims of
serial killers;
• there are a number of undetected victims, especially among those
children who go missing every year.

They suggest that the typical number of victims for each killer is 10–12.
Dividing their estimated figure for total victims of serial murder by this
number for each killer (uncharacteristically using the lower estimates this
time!), 3,500 divided by 10, gives them a figure of 350 serial killers at large
in the USA at any one time – an alarming prospect indeed.
The assumptions on which these estimates are based have been subject
to considerable scepticism, especially the notion that such a large
proportion of murders where the offender is unknown and many recorded
cases of missing children are necessarily attributable to serial killings
(Kiger 1998). Fox (1990) has described these estimates as ‘preposterous’
and probably ten times too large. At least the basis for the estimates are
made clear and open to some inspection. Norris (1988: 19) says that the
FBI’s estimate of active serial killers ‘at large and unidentified’ is 500, but
the basis for this figure is not revealed. More sober estimates have been
given for the number of active offenders at any one time, such as 35 by
Levin and Fox (1985), while Ressler et al (1988) estimate the number of
multiple murderers (a broader category) to lie between the low 30s to over
100.
Gresswell and Hollin(1994: 6) attempt a similar exercise for England
and Wales:

Such figures are difficult to generalise from outside the United


States. If the more conservative figures are applied to England and
Wales and equated with the smaller population, then one might
expect there to be between six and twenty killers active. However, if
the general murder rate for England and Wales (six times less than in
the United States) is taken into account, but assuming that detection
rates are similar in both countries, an estimate of up to four active
killers may be more realistic.

As they imply, however, the actual figure will be affected by such matters
as police efficiency, the amount of time taken to detect the offenders and
the balance between the different types of multiple murderer (mass and
spree murderers are typically at large for short periods, compared with
serial murderers).
It is hard to disagree with Kiger’s (1999: 37) conclusion that ‘there is no

92
Thinking seriously about serial killers

doubt that the nature of this phenomenon makes estimation difficult and
any absolute numbers representing a reliable reflection of the scope of the
problem, impossible’. However, the range of the estimates is great enough
to be interesting in itself, and some of the reasons for this are clear, such as
the data sources used, the assumptions made, and the definition of serial
murder being used (for example, the number of victims being used as a
defining criterion can have a considerable impact upon such estimates).
Later in the chapter, we explore the possibility that it is also tempting for
some vested interests to maximize the scale and impact of a problem with
which they are concerned.

A growing menace?

Criminologists are not only interested in the extent of crime, but also in
changes in that extent over time (trends). There seems be a prevailing idea
that serial murders have been on the increase in the USA in recent decades.
Using a combination of the existing literature and press reports, Leyton
(1989) constructs a table to convey the recorded instances of multiple
murderers in the USA, between 1920 and 1984, and summarises the main
trends in the following way:

There was essentially no change in the production of multiple


murderers until the 1960s, for the decades between the 1920s and the
1950s produced only one or two apiece. In the 1960s, this jumped to
six cases during the decade, for an average of one new killer every
twenty months. By the 1970s, this had jumped to seventeen new
cases, for an average of one new killer appearing every seven
months. During the first four years of the 1980s, the total had leapt to
twenty-five, for an average rate of production of one new killer every
1.8 months.
(Leyton 1989: 365–66)

Leyton, who is aware of some of the problems of such calculations, makes


parallel estimates of trends in the number of victims, concluding that the
frequency in the first four years of the 1980s was one hundred times that of
the 1950s (Leyton 1989: 367). His reservations about the figures seem to
centre upon the likelihood that they are an underestimate, but attempting
to track trends over time is an even more difficult exercise than estimating
contemporary figures. The use of press reports is particularly risky, for
what is undeniable is the growing media interest in this type of murder,
both in fiction and non-fiction publications, which has been sensitised to
look for and interpret killings within this kind of framework. Leyton’s
view would presumably be that such pronounced trends in his figures are

93
Introducing Criminology

unlikely to be fully accounted for by such possible sources of bias. Other


commentators come to similar conclusions about trends for serial murder
in the United States, in recent times at least: see, for example, Lowenstein
(1989); the subtitle of one book on the topic published in the late 1980s was
The Growing Menace (Norris 1988).
Can we in England and Wales (to which Home Office crime statistics
relate) sleep more soundly in our beds? Jenkins (1988) attempted to track
the incidence of serial murder (defined in this instance by four or more
victims) in the period 1940–1985; he estimated that serial killers were
responsible for 1.7 per cent of murders over this period, but for as many as
3.2 per cent in the 1973–83 period. Gresswell and Hollin (1994) take
Jenkins’ data, combine them with additional data for the 1980s from the
Home Office, and present figures for each decade 1940–1989. This gives
the following numbers of serial killers, with number of victims in brackets:

1940–9: 3 (18); 1950–9: 1 (7); 1960–9: 3 (13); 1970–9: 5 (60); 1980–9: 2 (11)
(Gresswell and Hollin 1994: 7).

They conclude that,

there is little empirical support for the idea of a dramatic increase in


serial killers since the war. Although the decade 1970–9 produced a
large number of killers and victims, 39 of the victims were killed by
just two men: Peter Dinsdale (26 victims) and Peter Sutcliffe (13
victims).
(Gresswell and Hollin 1994: 6)

The authors warn us that such figures are likely to underestimate the
extent of serial murder. The Home Office figures only include those cases
where victims have been clearly identified and attributed to a particular
offender. A less restrictive definition of a serial murderer (such as one
involving three victims) would also give a less rosy picture on numbers.
However, such data, despite their limitations, do give us some indication
of broad trends over time, and hardly suggest that there has been a recent
epidemic of serial murder in England and Wales.

Types of serial murderer

Once criminologists have charted as well as they can the extent of the
phenomenon they are studying, they commonly then attempt to develop
their understanding of it. They attempt to describe the common charac-
teristics, making generalisations about it. When this is being done, it may
be found that instances cluster into certain key groupings or types. When a

94
Thinking seriously about serial killers

systematic classification of cases into a number of types is presented, this


is often referred to as a typology. Despite the relatively small numbers of
serial murderers, some writers have seen important differences between
them and have thought it worthwhile to subdivide the category into such
types. It is possible to develop typologies of murders, murderers, or
victims. Most commonly, typologies have been developed for serial killers.
Ressler et al (1988), for example, used information from the analysis
of murders, their crime scenes and interviews with offenders to construct
profiles of murderers as either ‘organised’ or ‘disorganised’. An ‘organi-
sed’ murderer would normally be profiled as, for example, someone with
good intelligence and social skills, likely to plan murders, target strangers,
demand submissiveness from victims and use a vehicle in the commission
of the crime. By contrast, the ‘disorganised’ murderer is profiled as having
only average intelligence, being socially immature, likely to live or work
nearby and may know the victim, who is likely to be killed spontaneously
and suddenly, leaving an untidy crime scene with no attempt to conceal
the body. Those characteristics listed here are only some of those in each
profile. Since the originators of the framework were working under the
aegis of the US Federal Bureau of Investigation, it should be no surprise
that the primary purpose of it is to aid the investigation of such crimes.
A rather different classification has been suggested by Hickey (1991,
1997: 26), who delineates three groups: first, travelling serial killers, who
may cover many miles in the course of a year, leaving victims dispersed in
different places; second, local serial killers, ‘who never leave the state in
which they start killing in order to find additional victims’; and third,
‘place-specific killers’, ‘who never leave their homes or places of employ-
ment, whose victims already reside in the same physical structure or are
lured each time to the same location’ and who include people such as
nurses, housewives and the self-employed. Although it is clear that serial
killers can be classified according to their degree of geographical mobility,
it is unclear what the wider purpose of the typology might be. Does it, for
example, help us in understanding the motives of such offenders, or the
meanings which their actions have for them?
Perhaps the most widely known typology is that developed by Holmes
and DeBurger (1988) and Holmes and Holmes (1998), who have de-
veloped separate typologies for male and female serial killers. For males
there are four types.

Visionary
These killers are said to be responding to inner voices or hallucinations.
The break with reality is such that these individuals are often said to be
‘psychotic’. Key features are said to typify their murders, such as the
victims being randomly selected strangers, the murder spontaneous and
disorganised, and the location concentrated in certain areas.

95
Introducing Criminology

Missionary
This type has decided to rid the locality or the world of particular groups
he deems undesirable, such as drug dealers, drug users, prostitutes or
homosexuals. Although such individuals may be seen as being
characterised by a fixation, they are not normally considered psychotic.
Their victims are randomly selected strangers from specific types of
person, the act planned and organised in concentrated locations.

Hedonistic
This is a mixed group with three sub-types. Lust murderers are those for
whom violence and sex are intimately linked, and sexual practices and
mutilations may follow after the death of the victim. Thrill killers are
similar, but the victim is kept alive as long as possible in order to relish
their suffering. Comfort killers are those who kill for financial or other
material gain.

Power/control type
This killer is motivated by the desire to have, quite literally, the power of
life and death over the victim. Although sex may occur, this is not the
primary motivation.

A separate typology has been developed for female serial killers (Holmes
and Holmes 1998), although there is a considerable overlap with the
typology for males. The visionary corresponds to the male type, and the
comfort murderess, who kills for ‘creature comfort’ reasons, corresponds to
the male hedonistic/comfort type. A frequently cited case of this type is
that of Dorothea Puente, who was charged with nine murders in
California in 1988. She kept a rooming-house and was charged with
poisoning some of her guests in order to benefit from their social security
cheques. The hedonistic type corresponds broadly with the other male
hedonistic types, but sex is less likely to figure. The fourth type is the power
seeker, for whom murder is ‘a way to attain a sense of power’ (Holmes and
Holmes 1998: 45). Although this sounds very much like the male power/
control type, in this case power and attention is sought not over the victim
as such, but in relation to other people. An example is the mother who puts
her child into life-threatening situations and eventually kills the child, thus
gaining power over, and recognition from others. The fifth and final type
also represents a departure from the male typology – the disciple mur-
derer, who acts under the influence or orders of the leader of a group.
Holmes and Holmes note that female serial killers are relatively un-
common, and that most of them will fall into the comfort type.
How do we judge such typologies? The first point to make is that they
can only be judged in relation to some purpose or objective, which should
be clearly specified before the typology is constructed. How good is the

96
Thinking seriously about serial killers

typology in achieving that objective? We have already made the point that
the typology developed by Ressler et al (1988) was primarily to assist in the
detection of offenders. As such, it should be judged in that light. Seltzer
(1998: 131) comments,
although the types of ‘organised’ and ‘disorganised’ killers are
directly at odds, it has become routine to find apprehended killers
designated as ‘mixed’ types. ...Despite the profilers’ high profile in
the media, however, there remains a basic disagreement about what
contribution this technique has made.
By contrast, the primary objective of the Holmes and DeBurger (1988) and
Holmes and Holmes (1998) typologies is to reveal the patterns of
motivation of serial killers. These typologies are based on particular
psychological ideas about the origins of this particular form of behaviour.
If these ideas are accurate, they may contribute to a theory of serial murder
that will help us to understand and explain it.
The second point is that typologies are intended to help us to make
sense of a wealth of detailed information. They attempt to impose order, to
allow us to see patterns rather than simply a wealth of individual detail.
They are thus an attempt to go beyond the seemingly endless description
of individual cases, to group instances together, to see common features
between them. All typologies must strike some balance between simplicity
and complexity. The simpler they are, the more readily understandable
they usually are, but they may not do sufficient justice to the phenomena;
they may impose over-simplistic patterns on complex reality. The more
complex they are, the more they can deal with differences and variation in
the social world, but the less clear and readily understandable they may
be. The typology of Hickey (1986, 1997) is clearly one of the most simple
typologies, whereas that of Holmes and Holmes (1998) is one of the most
complex. Typologies will always have limitations, precisely because they
must balance competing demands of simplicity/clarity on one hand and
complexity/depth on the other. Wherever the balance is struck, something
will be lost.
The third point to make is that typologies in criminology must decide
on the primary focus in terms of, for example, the crime, the offender or
perhaps the victim. Most of the typologies in the area of serial murder
focus on the offender. That of Holmes and DeBurger (1988), for example,
had this focus, and more precisely, looks for motivational patterns. Such
motivational patterns of offenders do not provide a complete explanation
of events. Other factors may be important in accounting for these. The
behaviour of the victim and situational factors, for example, may be very
important in explaining actual outcomes (for example, some victims
selected may die, others not), a general point which has received much
attention in criminology in recent years.

97
Introducing Criminology

Such a typology also seems to suggest a consistent and enduring


pattern of motivation on the part of the individual who is so labelled. A
common observation is that those who are eventually apprehended as
serial killers have often had the ability to ‘blend in’ and give no indication
of their chilling activities, leading relatively ‘normal’ lives most of the time.
This suggests that we need extra explanations to account for actual killing
sequences, such as the notion of ‘triggers’ which may precipitate them.
Criminological typologies and explanations must avoid giving the
impression that individuals have been simply programmed into serial
killing, rather like the killing machine in the film Terminator, the cyborg
with only one mission, with little need to shop or do the laundry. Serial
killers may have different motives for different victims, and these motives
may change over time. Gresswell and Hollin (1994) give an example from
the account of the case of Dennis Nilsen (Masters 1985), who in the middle
of a killing sequence is said to have murdered one victim not for the ‘usual’
reasons, but because he was annoying and in the way. The general point,
then, is that typologies that focus on offenders and their motivation, will
not necessarily give us a good account of events and may even mislead us
into thinking that motives of any particular offender are always pretty
much the same.
A final point concerns the scope and comprehensiveness of any
typology – does it leave certain things out that should be considered?
Holmes and DeBurger (1988), for example, leave out ‘contract’ or hired
killers, arguing that their motivation is ‘extrinsic’ rather than ‘intrinsic’.
This seems odd, given that they include the hedonistic comfort type and
comfort murderess type, both of whom may kill for largely ‘extrinsic’
motives, such as to benefit from others’ insurance policies or social
security cheques (this anomaly is rectified in later work: see Holmes and
Holmes 1998). What is also striking about the literature on multiple
murder and serial killings is the way in which some of the most dramatic
and large scale examples are neglected or ignored. We are thinking of such
things as war crimes, genocide and ethnic cleansing, which have disgraced
human history up to the present. Gresswell and Hollin (1994: 1) do at least
show an awareness of these and exclude them from consideration in the
following way:

There are many different forms of multiple homicide, ranging from


the large scale, apparently politically motivated, killings of Joseph
Stalin or Idi Amin, through the seemingly motiveless killings of Peter
Sutcliffe and Michael Ryan. In this paper, we will focus on the
phenomenon of non-politically motivated homicide in England and
Wales, particularly the type of perpetrator that clinicians and
criminologists are likely to encounter through the criminal justice or
secure hospital systems.

98
Thinking seriously about serial killers

It is quite legitimate to limit one’s attention to particular parts of a topic,


perhaps feeling that to include all instances would make the project too
diverse and unwieldy. In this instance, there seems to be an assumption
that there are ‘politically motivated’ murders, in which the analysis will be
very different and can therefore be separated off from the analysis of ‘non-
politically motivated’ multiple murder. This may prove to be the case,
although there may still be similarities worthy of study, such as a tendency
to see victims as unimportant or less than human.
What is more significant here is the conventional concentration of
criminology upon the problem as defined by criminal law of the nation
state and its criminal justice system. Instances that are seen as somehow
‘political’ can be seen as not being part of its central focus, perhaps to be
studied by other disciplines, such as political science. On the other hand,
there are those who recognise that the subject matter of criminology is
inherently political, and that simply to study crimes against the state is a
political decision when crime by or on behalf of some states is equally
deserving of our attention. Those taking this view urge the study of such
topics as the crimes of the state (Cohen 1993) and the criminology of war
(Jamieson 1998). In addition, a focus on those normally processed by the
conventional criminal justice system and secure hospitals tends to result in
a concentration upon individual offenders and their clinical and
psychological backgrounds, rather than those responsible for multiple
murders which occur in settings with a wider political context.

Understanding serial murder

Definitions, measuring the extent of serial murder, and typologies of it,


help the criminologist to map out a field of study. When criminologists try
to understand something like serial murder, the next step is often to look
for theories that might help us. One view of the nature of criminological
enquiry is that theories are systematic sets of statements that provide
possible explanations for phenomena that we find puzzling – and serial
murders certainly come into that category. This view suggests that
theories contain hypotheses that can be tested by research (the collection
and analysis of data relevant to the validity or invalidity of hypotheses).
Until this happens, the hypotheses remain hypothetical. If the data seems
to contradict the hypothesis, it needs to be rejected or reformulated, unless
the data can be rejected as not being an adequate test of the hypothesis.
Even if the hypothesis survives unscathed from the encounter with
research data, the statements in the theory remain provisional – subject to
further testing, reformulation, and possible rejection in favour of a more
satisfactory theory in the future. We have seen in the last chapter that
contributions to theories of crime have been made by various disciplines.

99
Introducing Criminology

The most common contributors to theories of crime in general, and to


serial murder in particular, have been biology, psychology and sociology.
Each will be considered in turn.

Biology: natural born killers?


The biological approach concentrates on characteristics and processes in
the human body and their possible role in the causation of crime. We have
examined something of the history of this in chapter 2. A number of
biological factors have been put forward as possible contributors to serial
murder. The first example to mention will be familiar – the idea that
heredity and genetics ‘have a role to play’ (Holmes and Holmes 1998:49).

Genetic factors
The suggestion has been made that the possession of an extra male (Y)
chromosome in the genetic make-up of some individuals (what is called
the XYY syndrome) may predispose them to violence, or even to serial
murder. Clear evidence for a causal link between the XYY pattern and
criminal behaviour has always been lacking (Mednick and Volavka 1980)
and the suggested link with serial murder seems to have been based on
one or two examples of serial killers who have had, or are thought to have
had, this genetic abnormality. Arthur Shawcross, who was arrested in
New York State in 1990 and confessed to the murder of eleven women,
having already served a prison sentence for one of two earlier killings, is
reported to have had this extra chromosome (Hickey 1997: 48). Just as one
swallow does not make a summer, one case does not make a generalisa-
tion.

Head trauma
The case of Shawcross brings to our attention a second possible biological
factor: head trauma. Shawcross had suffered head injuries as a child and as
an adult. ‘Considering that abuse is a common theme in the childhoods of
serial killers, we must also be concerned with those who received head
trauma. While head trauma may not directly cause violent behaviour, the
persistent correlation must not be ignored’ (Hickey 1997: 46). Again, there
are general lessons for the criminologist. It must first be demonstrated that
serial killers are more likely to have suffered head trauma than other
people who are in other ways like the killer group (a ‘matched’ compari-
son). Even then, a correlation does not necessarily amount to causation.
For instance, alternative explanations for the correlation need to be
discounted, e.g. that the association is produced by a third factor, such as
cold, uncaring parenting leading to both physical abuse of a child and a
psychological make-up conducive to victimising others. As we saw in
chapter 2, establishing causal generalisations is more difficult than we
might think.
100
Thinking seriously about serial killers

Abnormal brain activity


A third possibility is a link between abnormal brain activity and violent
behaviour. Holmes and Holmes (1998: 47) cite the work of Burgess et al
(1986), who found that EEG (electroencephalogram – a device for measur-
ing brain activity) abnormalities tended to disappear in people in their
thirties. As serial killers tend to cluster in the 25–35 age range, could it be
that these are often individuals whose brains have yet fully to develop,
leading to immature, childish behaviour, such as fits of rage? Do we detect
much speculation here, built on rather slim foundations, in a way that is
rather typical of much of this literature?

Other biological factors


Other authors mention other possible biological factors. Holmes and
Holmes (1998: 48) cite the work of Norris and Birnes (1988) who favour
biological explanations. Apart from the mention of head trauma, they
claim that almost all serial killers suffer from psychomotor epilepsy or
serious hormonal imbalance, which may result from a malfunctioning
limbic system (the so-called ‘animal’ or emotional brain). Holmes and
Holmes (1998: 48) point out that no sources or evidence are presented to
support these claims, although, in a manner reminiscent of Lombroso,
descriptions of the heads of some serial killers are provided. In a more
cautious vein, Hickey (1997) suggests a number of other biological factors
which, if subject to more research, may be useful in helping to understand
violent crime, such as:

• hypoglycaemia (a condition of low blood-sugar, which affects brain


function);

• levels of serotonin, a substance which seems to have a calming effect,


low levels of which may result in poor impulse control;

• differences in the characteristics of the nervous system, which make it


more difficult for some individuals to be socialised into conforming
conduct, as suggested by Eysenck (1977).

Having surveyed these views on the role of biology, it is hard to come to


any positive conclusions. It appears that very little systematic research has
been conducted into the role of such factors in serial murder. This is hardly
surprising, given the difficulties of conducting such research. As Holmes
and Holmes (1998: 49) say, until a proper sample of serial killers has been
put together and tested systematically for such factors, there is ‘no
scientific statement that can be made’ of the kind that seems to be the
objective of many of these writers. David Canter (1994: 209) gives this
verdict on the biological approach:

101
Introducing Criminology

There is, of course, likely to be some biological basis to psychological


differences between people. This could contribute to their general
characteristics in such a way that under certain circumstances they
might be more prone to commit a crime than a person who had less
of that particular aspect of their biological make-up. But this chain of
influences is so long and marginal that for most practical purposes it
is irrelevant.

Psychology: inside the mind of the serial killer?


Psychology is the systematic study of human behaviour and mental
processes, often with a particular focus upon particular characteristics and
processes which distinguish individuals from each other (see our
discussion of psychological approaches in Chapter 2). One common
stereotype of the psychologist is that of the expert with a mid-European
accent who spends hours and hours with one individual, attempting to
bring to the surface deep-seated conflicts which are beyond the subject’s
everyday consciousness. The stereotype is loosely derived from that
branch of psychology called psychoanalysis, which is by no means the only
variety of the discipline and has actually been rejected by many academic
psychologists because of what they see as its ‘unscientific’ nature.
Psychoanalysis traces its ancestry to the pioneering work of Sigmund
Freud, even though more recent work has often departed from his original
ideas. Key elements include a stress on the importance of the early years of
life, especially parent–child relationships, in the psychological develop-
ment of the individual, which can be seen as being divided into a number
of stages. Problems can arise when conflicts cannot be dealt with at the
time and are repressed into the unconscious mind, to have an influence on
the later behaviour and well-being of the individual.
A relevant example is the work of Abrahamsen (1973), who stresses that
traumas in childhood often have a sexual basis; if the child is unable to
deal with these at the time, they may be repressed into the unconscious
mind, but may surface later in the form of murder with strong sexual
components. The sexual components involve inflicting pain and suffering
on the victim as a way of gaining a sense of power and control which was
clearly lacking in the childhood experiences of the killer. Such murders
thus reflect such early experiences and attempt to compensate for them.
Although many psychologists distance themselves from the ideas and
approach of psychoanalysis, it is interesting how often the literature on
serial murder comes up with ideas and findings that are consistent with it.
It might seem reasonable to suggest that people who kill repetitively are
suffering from some form of mental disorder which would go a long way
to explaining such behaviour. The field of mental disorder is a complex
and still developing one, and we can only give a brief overview of
possibilities here.
102
Thinking seriously about serial killers

Psychosis
The first possibility to consider is that serial killers are suffering from a
form of psychosis, the symptoms of which are said to be one or more of the
following: ‘delusions, hallucinations, disorganized speech, or grossly
disorganized or catatonic behaviour’ (Hickey 1997: 53). It is all too easy to
point to examples that seem to fit this category. Joseph Kallinger claimed
to be haunted by a large floating, tentacled head called Charlie, telling him
to kill people and mutilate their genitals. The obedient Kallinger duly
obliged, murdering his own son and others in the local community.
Psychotic episodes or states are said to be brought on by ‘physiological
malfunctioning, environmental stressors, or substance use’ (Hickey 1997:
53). Although fitting well into the type of ‘visionary’ killers outlined
earlier, it seems that ‘serial killers are rarely found to be suffering from
psychotic states’ (Hickey 1997: 54), according to one author who has been
working in the field for a number of years.

Dissociative disorders
The second possibility to consider is the dissociative disorders. Dissocia-
tion refers to:

a normal psychological process which provides the opportunity for a


person to avoid, to one degree or another, the presence of memories
and feelings which are too painful to tolerate. Dissociation is a
continuum of experiences ranging from the process of blocking out
events going on around us (such as when watching a movie) to
Multiple Personality Disorder (MPD) where personalities are
separate compartmentalized entities.
(Carlisle 1998: 88)

Dissociation therefore ranges from something that is very common to


something that is extreme. Multiple personality disorder makes for good
stories and film scripts from Jekyll and Hyde onwards, but does not seem
to figure much in the world of serial murder. Kenneth Bianchi is thought to
have faked the disorder in order to support his plea of insanity, and
Hickey (1997: 55) concludes that ‘there do not appear to be any well
documented cases of MPD in serial killing’. The disorder is sometimes
referred to as the ‘UFO of psychiatry’ because some doubt its very
existence as a clinical entity.
Less extreme is Carlisle’s (1998) account of the role of dissociation in the
development of what some killers have referred to as ‘the shadow’, ‘the
beast’ or ‘the entity’. Traumatic memories and feelings may be buried
(by ‘splitting off’ or ‘blocking out’), while a rich fantasy life is developed to
provide a sense of relief and excitement which is increasingly turned
to when the person experiences stress, depression or emptiness. The

103
Introducing Criminology

fantasies are focused upon the things which cannot, at first, be done in real
life. At first, they may focus on being a hero, being the kind of person to be
admired; as time goes by and these fantasies are not fulfilled, they may
come to focus upon revenge, or sex coupled with violence. The person is
leading a kind of double life; one real, one fantasy: a struggle between the
parts is experienced. The individual may eventually find himself in a
situation that corresponds to the fantasy and ‘automatically carrying out
an act he has practised so many, many times in his mind’ (Carlisle 1998:
93). He may initially dissociate the crime, and vow that it will never
happen again. But the wish to feel such power and control becomes so
strong that eventually another murder is committed. The individual has
become what he has always feared; a fundamental shift of identity has
occurred. Guilt is compartmentalised so that it is not consciously
experienced. His secret, ‘dark side’ is experienced as having gained the
upper hand over his very being. In order to neutralise the strong
self-hate that may be engendered, he may even begin to idealise what he
has become. Carlisle (1998: 99) claims that while this model may not fit
every serial killer, it will fit most cases. Holmes and Holmes (1998: 72)
suggest it is a theory of ‘at least the sexually motivated and power-
motivated serialists’. Although it leaves a number of questions un-
answered, it does point to some important themes we shall encounter
elsewhere.

Psychopathy
Perhaps the concept most tempting to apply to the serial killer is that of
psychopathy. Henderson (1939: 19) described it as ‘a true illness for which
we have no specific explanation’. Cleckley (1976) listed sixteen
characteristics of psychopaths, and building on this, Hare (1991) has
developed a psychopathy checklist which includes such items as:

• glibness/superficial charm;
• conning, manipulative behaviour;
• lack of remorse or guilt;
• callousness/lack of empathy.

Hickey (1997: 65) states that although most psychopaths are not violent, a
common feature is their ‘constant need to be in control of their social and
physical environment. When this control is challenged, the psychopath
can be moved to violent behaviour’. He also notes that the attraction of the
term lies in the ‘catch-all’ nature of the label, apparently able to
accommodate even killers who had seemed to be Mr Nice Guy on first
impressions. But one drawback is that ‘researchers and clinicians alike
have yet to arrive at a consensus as to the proper definition of the term’
(Hickey 1997: 66). We might add that, even if it may be a useful descriptive

104
Thinking seriously about serial killers

term, this does not necessarily constitute an explanation: we still do not


know how these individuals came to have these characteristics, although
there have, for example, been attempts to discover a genetic or biological
basis for it (Schulsinger 1977). Perhaps not surprisingly, many psychia-
trists prefer to view particular violent offenders as suffering from anti-
social personality disorder, with its roots in childhood or adolescence
(Hickey 1997: 61).

Multiple-factor explanations
Perhaps the most illuminating avenue at present is provided by those who
try to take an overview of the main research findings, constructing a
model which is divided into a series of stages. It is clear that the explana-
tion of serial murder is very complex, and not to be achieved by a focus on
one concept or factor. Instead, any theory of such a rare phenomenon is
likely to include a wide range of elements, which on their own or even in
combination with some of the others, are likely to have been experienced
by a large number of persons without them becoming serial murderers. In
addition, the research evidence is not substantial in any case, because of
the rarity of serial murder and the various difficulties involved in conduct-
ing research on it. As such, theoretical models or frameworks must be
regarded as highly provisional. Gresswell and Hollin (1994) provide
one such model summarising the research on multiple murder, and
divided into three main stages: predisposing factors; maintaining factors;
situational factors and triggers. It provides a good illustration of how
psychological criminologists might approach the explanation of such a
crime.

• Predisposing factors include a childhood in which attachment and em-


pathic bonding between the child and carer fails to develop. As such,
the child may become cold and aloof towards others (Burgess et al 1986).
The child is not helped to deal with traumatic experiences, but aspects
of them (such as sadistic violence, sexual abuse) are incorporated into a
fantasy life. These fantasies are a source of pleasure and a feeling of
power and control which are lacking in ‘real’ life. As such they are
‘reinforced’ (rewarded) and he is more likely to become dependent
upon them. The child misses chances to acquire pro-social skills and
values and develops a distorted picture of himself and social relation-
ships.
• Maintaining factors are divided into three types. Cognitive inhibitory
processes are involved in overriding, or the prevention of the learning of,
inhibitions to aggression. For example, people who have experienced
the kind of background described in the previous paragraph may end
up feeling isolated and alienated, and are therefore relatively immune

105
Introducing Criminology

from feedback in respect of inappropriate violence. Such children may


also lack the capacity to relate with empathy towards others, who can
therefore be more easily victimised (Burgess et al 1986). Victims may be
literally depersonalised, and acts of childhood delinquency can escalate
to more serious acts in later life. Cognitive facilitating processes refer to the
role of fantasy, originally developed as a form of escape, as a precursor
to multiple murder. For example, Prentky et al (1989) found that 86 per
cent of their sample of serial sexual murderers admitted violent
fantasies, while only 23 per cent of their single sexual murderers did so.
Operant processes are those in which both positive and negative rein-
forcement affect the likelihood of repetition. Thus fantasy, rehearsal/
trial runs and murder itself are positively reinforced by feelings of
power and control, and negatively reinforced in so far as they provide
an escape from the negative experiences of ‘normal’ life. Prentky et al
(1989) suggest that serial killers are involved in a quest to match fantasy
with reality, an attempt which is only likely to be partly successful and
therefore likely to be repeated.
• Situational factors and triggers are often identified by criminologists to
take the explanation a little further: to explain why a crime happens
where and when it does. So, for example, Ressler et al (1988) found that
all of their sample of 36 convicted sexual murderers had experienced
various sorts of problems (concerning jobs, money matters, legal
matters and relationships) before the murder. A third said they had
been experiencing emotional states that made them ‘open for oppor-
tunities’. Gresswell and Hollin (1994: 11) suggest that individuals with
well rehearsed murder fantasies are more likely to act these out (rather
than engage in some other deviant act) when faced with a disintegra-
tion in their psychological equilibrium and familiar social world. Again,
the various factors need to be taken in conjunction to provide a more
complete explanation.

The trauma-control model


Another model, the trauma-control model, has been provided by Hickey
(1997). Although he accepts that there may be predispositional factors,
such as biological ones, destabilising traumatizations in the formative
years of life hold a key place in the model. Most commonly, these are said
to take the form of an unstable, abusive and rejecting home life. Some may
respond to these experiences in a destructive way. Such experiences foster
feelings of low self-esteem which encourage the development of fantasies.
A process of dissociation (the memory of painful experiences or the
feelings they created are suppressed) may occur; a facade of self-
confidence and control is presented to the outside world (as in the concept
of the psychopath). The individual may begin to use facilitators, such as

106
Thinking seriously about serial killers

alcohol and other drugs, pornography, or books on the occult; these are
not suggested as causal factors as such, but can lower inhibitions and feed
fantasies, which are said to be a ‘critical component in the psychological
development of the serial killer’ and ‘likely to be found in the minds of
most, if not all...’ (Hickey 1997: 91).
The fantasies increasingly involve violence, often sexual, and control
over the victim, and eventually the individual attempts to replicate them.
This is never fully achievable, but each attack may provide material for
new fantasies. Elements of the original childhood trauma may surface in
the ordeal to which the victim is subject. When a sense of control has been
reached, the victim may be slaughtered, and the individual feels a
temporary sense of equilibrium that has been missing in his life. If the
quest for fantasy fulfilment has become all-consuming, or the feelings of
low self-esteem and rejection are precipitated by events (trauma
reinforcement), the process may begin again.

Such models, which provide a kind of moving picture of a typical case,


appear to help us to understand to some extent the enigma of serial
murder. We must remember, however, the rather flimsy basis on which
such models are constructed: interviews with small, probably unrepre-
sentative samples of some of the most devious research subjects, and case
studies. To what extent is the model applicable to all the types of serial
killer or to only some of them? Are all the factors to be found in every case,
or are different combinations possible? Are there important factors which
have been omitted? To what extent are offenders driven by forces beyond
their own consciousness and/or control? These are the sorts of questions
that criminologists might ask about such a model, but even if defective in
certain respects, it is still useful in attempting to summarise what is
thought to be the case in the present state of knowledge, and provides
something that can be tested out by researchers in the future. Although
caution is recommended, it seems a little too pessimistic to say that ‘those
who commit fatal violence are compelled by forces beyond our under-
standing’ (Holmes and Holmes 1998: 59).

Sociology: outside the mind of the serial killer?


Sociologists are not primarily interested in individual differences in
behaviour, mental processes and personality in the way that psychology
is. They are more concerned with aspects of society and broad social
groupings within it (such as class, race and gender) and their impact on
behaviour. We have seen how psychological approaches to serial murder
tend to look for the causes of it within the characteristics and personal
experiences of the individual. We might expect this to be the best place to
look with such an unusual and apparently esoteric crime, with the empha-

107
Introducing Criminology

sis on individual pathology (i.e. what went wrong with the individual)
fully justified. Sociologists, however, may argue that such a focus upon
individual pathology neglects the social and cultural context within which
these crimes are located. The famous sociologist Emile Durkheim (1952,
originally published in 1897) conducted a study of suicide to demonstrate
the helpfulness of a sociological perspective with a similarly highly
individual phenomenon. Corresponding to their rather different focus,
sociologists tend to ask rather different sorts of questions. In the case of
serial murder, the following might be three examples.

• Why do there seem to be more serial killers in one society than in


another?
• If the incidence of serial murder seems to be changing over time, why is
this?
• Why do particular societies, at particular times, focus on particular
problems (such as serial murder), and see those problems in particular
ways?

We look initially at the first two questions. Then we move on to look at the
third.

The thoroughly modern multiple murderer


Despite the inherent difficulties of the enterprise, Elliott Leyton’s (1989)
Hunting Humans: the rise of the modern multiple murderer is an example of a
traditional sociological approach to the topic. His key question is, ‘why
does modern America produce proportionately so many more of these
‘freaks’ than any other industrial nation?’ (Leyton 1989: 11). The answer
comes in several stages. Leyton’s view is that multiple murderers are not
random ‘freaks’, but products of their historical time – thrown up by
specific stresses and changes in society. Multiple-stranger murders are
said to be rare in pre-industrial societies, but the economic and social
upheaval of the industrial revolution eventually produced new kinds of
murderer. In particular, there were ‘middle class functionaries – doctors,
teachers, professors, civil servants, who belonged to the class created to
serve the new triumphant bourgeoisie – [and who] preyed on members of
the lower orders, especially prostitutes and housemaids’ (Leyton 1989:
350). But why? Leyton seems to believe the answer lies in ‘a defensive
status hysteria – which manifests itself as a kind of extreme personal
insecurity – that is found so often among those who have risen or fallen
dramatically in the social hierarchy’. Multiple murder seems to be seen as
one way of ‘disciplining the social inferiors who threatened [a murderer’s]
position’ (Leyton 1989: 356, 358).

108
Thinking seriously about serial killers

But Leyton’s principal concern lies in more recent decades, where, as


we have previously seen, he presents some data to show that multiple
murder has dramatically increased since the 1950s. Since the late 1960s, it
is suggested that the American economy has increasingly ceased to
provide middle-class positions for ‘socially ambitious, but untalented (or
unconnected) young men’ (Leyton 1989: 363–4) from the working- and
lower middle-class. Some of these begin to fantasise about revenge, and a
‘tiny, but ever-increasing, percentage of them began to react to the
frustration of their blocked social mobility by transforming their fantasies
into a vengeful reality’ (Leyton 1989: 364).
Sociologists would recognise this as a strain theory of deviant behaviour:
society creates a frustration or problem of adjustment, to which deviance
is seen as a response (see chapter 3). But strain theory alone cannot
necessarily account for the nature of this deviant response: why turn to
violence rather than, say, alcohol or depression? To do so, Leyton points to
the cultural context of American society, a culture which glorifies violence
‘as an appropriate and manly response to frustration’ (Leyton 1989: 364),
and which stresses individualism and the freedom to explore one’s self
and its impulses.
To strain and this cultural context is added a third ingredient to
complete the explosive cocktail: personal and spiritual insecurity on the
part of certain individuals. Leyton examines the backgrounds of 23
multiple murderers from the USA, to show how frequently they come
from that part of the population (which he estimates as 12–20 per cent in a
modern nation state) with one of four characteristics: adopted, illegiti-
mate, institutionalised as a child or adolescent, or their mother married
three times or more. Such a family background, he suggests, will often
leave these individuals feeling socially excluded or marginal. This in-
security is said to be the breeding ground for the modern multiple
murderer.
This is an interesting thesis, with strengths and weaknesses. It is helpful
to draw attention to the cultural context, so often lacking in psychological
and biological approaches. As a social anthropologist, Leyton is aware of
the differences between cultures in respect of violence and the significant
consequences these have for patterns of behaviour. But the psychological
perspectives we have examined seem more adept at linking childhood
experiences with the development of violent fantasy and later serial
murder. Furthermore, the kind of background he describes for the offend-
er is actually the lot of many individuals in the USA, so why so few serial
murderers, not why so many? There are so many loose connections in this
circuit, that it is hardly surprising that the lights rarely come on. It is major
enterprise to forge links from the economy right through to such a
relatively unusual event as serial murder: a great deal more research needs
to be done in order to do so.

109
Introducing Criminology

Putting gender on the agenda


Another way in which we can place serial murder into a wider social and
cultural context is to consider issues of gender. Gender as an issue was
once very much neglected in criminology and in the social sciences more
generally. Major contributions have been made to rectify this in recent
years, especially by those working from a broadly feminist perspective
(see chapter 3). However, these developments do not seem to have had
much influence in much of the literature on serial murder. This is surpris-
ing, for one ‘fact’ upon which most researchers seem to be agreed is that
the majority of serial killers are men, and many of their victims, but by no
means all of them, are women. For example, in a list of 43 serial killers
given by Holmes and DeBurger (1988: 22–23), only three were women.
One rather cursory attempt to say why this should be seems to rely on
either biological factors, especially the influence of hormones, or ‘social
learning’ – that ‘there are many ways in which children are taught that
aggression is more appropriate for men than for women’ (Hale and Bolin
1998: 34). The relative contribution and interaction of biological and socio-
cultural factors (the ‘nature – nurture debate’) is a key but very difficult
issue, which is avoided by these authors.
David Canter (1994) takes as central that most serial killers and violent
criminals are men. His explanation for this is very much socio-cultural,
suggesting that the ‘inner narratives’ or stories that we construct and
through which we live our lives are taken from the wider society and
culture. Although much of his account is psychological, concentrating on
the characteristics and backgrounds of individuals of the sort described in
the section on psychology, his view is that ‘criminal narratives’ are on the
whole ‘drawn from those which our society provides for men’ (Canter
1994: 239). By contrast, ‘the typical representation of women as victims
rather than protagonists is reflected in the fact that it is relatively rare for
women to write themselves into actively violent scenarios (except as
victims)’ (Canter 1994 : 232). The fact that there are relatively few female
equivalents of Rambo may help us to understand not only why most serial
killers are likely to be men, but also that the victims are often women.
Canter (1994: 239) also suggests that ‘out of a self-perception of loneliness
and the distorted search for intimacy, there grow feelings of impotence
and isolation, embedded in anger towards others who are seen as crucial
in defining the criminal’s identity, typically women’.
A further ‘fact’ that is often put forward by writers in this field is that
whereas ‘lust’ or sex is often identified as a feature of serial killing by men,
‘lust is simply not a strong motive for murder among female serial killers’
(Hale and Bolin 1998: 46). If serial murder simply has its origins in childhood
trauma, especially sexual abuse, we might expect more women to be
involved, and for their murders to involve sexual sadism more frequently
than seems to be the case, for there is no evidence that girls are largely

110
Thinking seriously about serial killers

exempt from child abuse. Clearly, more than this is required to account for
gender differences in serial killing. Cameron and Frazer (1987), in their
discussion of sexual murder (by men) from a feminist perspective, see
‘transcendence’ – the wish to attain some kind of immortality by an extra-
ordinary action – as a reason for male predominance in this crime. Such men
are extreme products of an exaggerated culture of masculinity, for whom
aggression and male sexuality have become inextricably linked. Such men
cannot be understood apart from that wider culture which, in one way or
another, affects all our lives. Jane Caputi (1987) goes further, suggesting that
the twentieth century is characterised by a new form of genocide – sexual
murder as the ultimate expression of sexuality as a form of (male) power. It
is certainly undeniable that masculinity – or at least certain forms of it – may
be partly responsible for some very undesirable outcomes.

The social construction of a problem


Another perspective to which we wish to draw attention asks rather
different questions. The social constructionist approach questions the very
foundations of what is ‘known’ about a problem and what should be done
about it. How are problems identified in the first place? Why are some
issues rather than others singled out for special attention? Are they
interpreted in particular ways? If so, why? Are particular interests in-
volved in this process? Are some interests more successful than others in
making their claims/interpretations count? As a result, is the concern and
reaction to some problems out of all proportion to the threat that they
constitute? Can we speak of there being a ‘moral panic’ about some issues?
These are the sorts of questions that have been asked about serial murder
by some sociologists (Soothill 1993, Jenkins 1994).
The suggestion is that there are vested interests involved in creating
and maintaining a focus upon serial murder as a problem. Although
multiple murderers have existed for many years, the term serial murder is
a relatively recent invention, and the ‘framing’ of it as a problem has much
about it that is new. Much is to be gained by certain agencies if the problem
is seen to be a growing menace. First, there are what are often called the
social control agencies. According to Jenkins (1994: 213), a new problem of
serial murder was established ‘as a problem of law enforcement and
federal power rather than one of mental health or social dysfunction’. The
agencies largely responsible for this were the US Justice Department and
the FBI’s Behavioural Sciences Unit (BSU) at Quantico, a new unit keen to
expand its resources and activities in such areas as offender profiling and
crime scene analysis. With its direct access to such offenders and its
national jurisdiction, such an agency was able to establish itself as the
authority on serial offending. It shared with certain other groups ‘a
common vested interest in emphasising certain aspects of the murder
problem, above all its very large scale’ (Jenkins 1994 : 216):

111
Introducing Criminology

black groups who viewed it as part of systematic racial exploitation;


feminists who saw the offense as serial femicide, a component of the
larger problem of violence against women; children’s rights activists
concerned with missing and exploited children; as well as religious
and other advocates of a ritual murder threat.
(Jenkins 1994: 212)

In his view, the BSU personnel knew how to work an audience and to
cultivate the media, with the master-stroke of allowing the filming of The
Silence of the Lambs to take place at Quantico.
The mass media are the second major agency with vested interests in
the serial murder issue. It has become all too clear that the issue sells
newspapers, books and magazines, raises TV ratings and fills cinema
seats. According to Jenkins (1994: 221), ‘serial murder represents for the
media the perfect social problem’, fulfilling as it does the criteria for a
newsworthy story: it invokes an emotional response; there is drama in the
battle between good and evil; it involves a real harm and a potential threat
for readers and viewers, from the ‘quiet, apparently harmless person
down the street’ (as killers are often subsequently described by
neighbours); excitement often accompanies the hunt for the offender;
shock value will be contained in the unusual violent or sexual activity;
offenders often acquire a celebrity status so that coverage can be personal-
ised; it often comes with ready-made attention-grabbing features and
powerful visual images. Fiction and non-fiction alike (the distinction
between the two is by no means clear cut according to this analysis)
contribute to forming the prevailing images and ‘monster’ stereotypes,
with a heavy reliance on the material provided by the accredited agencies,
such as the BSU.
Killers themselves often play an important role in this process, and have
an intricate relationship with the media. Serial murderers often appear to
be avid consumers of media accounts of earlier cases, from daily
newspapers through to academic psychological discussions. It seems
highly likely that they will be influenced in some way by these sources,
‘which may go far in explaining why killers in different eras tend to
reproduce explanations of their offense that closely mimic the prevailing
ideological perspective of their day or even of the particular investigator to
whom they are confessing’ (Jenkins 1994: 224).
What killers say about their deeds may also be affected by the kind of
outcome they may be seeking, such as an insanity defence, or to appear in
the Guinness Book of Records: for example, some offenders have confessed
to murders they could not have committed. If the psychopathic
personality type is frequently to be found amongst such offenders, we
should remember their propensity to manipulate and to say whatever
might please the listener, whether investigator or researcher. For all these

112
Thinking seriously about serial killers

reasons, we should be treating what killers say with an enormous pinch of


salt; this is worrying when such accounts are often used as the main basis
for explanations and claims by interest groups. In fact, Jenkins suggests
that the various ‘confessions’ made over the years by any offender may
contain enough different threads and contradictions to allow a claims-
maker to choose the one that seems most convenient to whatever they are
trying to argue.
A similar analysis has been provided by Soothill (1993), who focuses
more on the developing panic in Britain, a panic all the more remarkable in
view of the very limited extent of the problem compared with the USA.
Soothill also stresses the benefits for social control agencies, especially the
police, and for media interests. To these he adds business interests, which
may benefit as law enforcement seeks the expensive advanced technology
seen to be necessary to grapple with the problem. He cites the introduction
of HOLMES – a computerised system to process large quantities of
information in connection with major enquiries – in the wake of the case of
the ‘Yorkshire Ripper’. Such a system, it was argued, would help to avoid
‘linkage blindness’ – a failure to see connections in large quantities of
information collected, a feature that had characterised the Ripper investi-
gation. Finally, he notes the vested interests of a new breed of experts, with
careers and reputations to advance. The best known figures in the field of
psychological profiling Britain are David Canter and Paul Britton. An
impression of the kinds of things at stake is provided by Britton (1997: 142–
158), who includes some rather uncomplimentary remarks about the work
of Canter. There can be research funds and reputations to be gained if
experts can impress government of profiling’s potential and their own
superior expertise in the field.
It can be seen how the social constructionist account urges us to take a
sceptical look at what is ‘known’ about serial killers and to ask different
sorts of questions. As we have seen, it asks about the fascination that
seems to exist with such offenders in the wider society. Seltzer (1998: 109)
suggests that this is one manifestation of the ‘wound culture’ that
characterises the USA: ‘the public fascination with torn and opened
private bodies and torn and opened psyches, a public gathering around
the wound and the trauma’. The popularity of such TV programmes as
Jerry Springer, Oprah, Ricki Lake, and ER are other elements in a culture in
which serial killing appears as a ‘career option’, a way of claiming an
identity, a role for which popular psychology has already provided scripts
(profiles).
A similar question is asked by Duclos (1998) who answers that

Anglo-American culture is attracted to uncommon killers because


they reflect its own image as an uncommon society. They are a
reminder of its legendary tales, which transmit deep-seated values

113
Introducing Criminology

and in which violence has always had a central role as something


which is at once desired and feared.
(Duclos 1998: 7–8).

His attempt to trace some of the elements of this culture to Germanic and
Norse myths is one highly individual (and sometimes strained) example
of the focus upon representations of violence and murder. Cultural
representations may not only have an influence on the nature and extent of
serial murder, but they may help to structure the data collected by
researchers (such as the way in which killers attempt to represent their
actions in interviews) in a very significant way. However, such an
approach still leaves us with the question of why particular individuals
find themselves taking on the role of serial killer. Giving an answer to this
question is rather more difficult than we might have thought.

Post-mortem

Much of the research on serial murder follows a particular pattern that is


common in criminology. Much of it has been concerned with definitions,
estimations of its extent and trends, and the development of typologies. A
great deal of work has been involved in gathering information on such
matters as the methods used, the locations for killings, and the charac-
teristics of victims. One major impetus for this has been to gather
knowledge that might help in the investigation of crime and the
formulation of policy. More important from a theoretical point of view has
been the attempt to identify biological, psychological and sociological
factors which might help us to make sense of this kind of murder. As in
criminology in general, the quest has been to develop a theory that might
help us to explain why these crimes occur. Such theories are ideally tested
by empirical research, in order to see how valid they are. Even by its own
standards of good procedure, such empirical work on serial murder has
been based on shaky foundations. Most samples are confined to
apprehended offenders who may not be typical or reliable; secondary
sources, such as newspapers, have often been used, rather than primary
sources; sample sizes have often been very small; and there has been no
agreed definition of the use of the term (Kiger 1990: 37); for various other
reasons too that we have discussed, such offenders are some of the most
difficult to research by conventional techniques.
An alternative strategy is to work from the ‘bottom up’ – to accept the
difficulty of the task and to concentrate on a particular case study at a time.
To build understanding by attempting to grasp the totality of one case,
rather than jumping to the development of a general theory, which may in
any case be a false quest. Such understanding should be theoretically

114
Thinking seriously about serial killers

informed, however, drawing on principles and findings of academic study


in a wider context. Otherwise it can be nothing more than journalism. As
an example, Jefferson (1997: 546) praises two works on Peter Sutcliffe, the
‘Yorkshire Ripper’, which he claims ‘render life comprehensible, at least
after a fashion’. Both (Smith 1989; Ward Jouve 1988) draw on the ideas of
psychoanalysis and masculinity to argue that his background and events
in his development, ‘repeatedly demonstrating his failure to live up to the
social expectations of manliness, led him first to blame the feminine in
himself, to hate part of himself, and then externalize that hatred and
destroy women’ (Jefferson 1997: 545). Those who might object that there
must be more to it than that are, of course, quite right. The devil is, almost
literally, in the detail and we cannot do justice to it here:

It was a grisly resolution. It was not inevitable. It was in some sense


chosen. But it is a resolution and a choice that displays a logic only
within the detail of a life observed through a lens of masculinity
which is simultaneously social and psychic, alert to the multiple
contradictions within and between these dimensions, the anxieties
and ambivalences these set up, and the compounding influence of
contingencies.
(Jefferson 1997: 545–6)

The two broad approaches outlined here are not necessarily contradictory
or mutually exclusive. Much of the literature on serial murder attempts
some combination of them. However, some would argue that, with serial
murder, and perhaps with certain other kinds of crime, the second broad
approach is currently more likely to add to our understanding than the
first.
Finally, we have encountered another perspective on serial murder,
which does not take its primary task as attempting to understand why a
given type of crime occurs. Instead, it looks at the way in which a
particular problem or crime has been socially constructed, and the various
sources of that particular construction. The focus here is on representa-
tions of serial murder, and the notion that such representations can be
deconstructed to reveal the processes and interests that contributed to
them. This illustrates perspectives that have been introduced earlier in this
book; the implication is that we should not simply accept the way in which
a problem has been defined and the seemingly authoritative ‘knowledge’
presented to us, but to examine them in a questioning frame of mind. This
can tell us something about our society, its culture and the way in which it
defines and reponds to crime and the offender.

115
Introducing Criminology

Chapter 5

Policing and the police:


key issues in criminal justice

Introduction

The police are by far the most visible institution of the criminal justice
system. While most people will have had little or no contact with prisons,
probation or the courts, there must be few who by the age of majority have
not come into personal contact of one kind or another with the police.
Indeed, for the most part, the police want to be seen. Their distinctive
uniforms with helmets fashioned to elevate their stature, and their clearly
marked patrol cars equipped with sirens and flashing blue lights are
clearly designed to draw attention to themselves. This is, of course, no
accident; the police are the visible presence of the state in civil society.
From the establishment in London of the New Police in 1829 by Sir
Robert Peel, visibility was the order of the day. There were originally to be
no detectives who could move freely among the citizenry in plain clothes,
for this would resemble a continental model of policing which, as one
parliamentary committee of the time declared, ‘would be odious and
repulsive’ to the British idea of liberty. Nor were the police to be attired in
the fashion of the military, for one of the prime justifications for the setting
up of the New Police was the failure of the army to maintain order without
recourse to gross and excessive force. This had occurred with some
frequency in the preceding fifty years and most tragically at Peterloo,
when in 1819 a demonstration was set upon by the army and hundreds
were injured and eleven people killed.
When, therefore, on 29 September 1829 the citizens of London beheld
the spectacle of groups men being marched to their beats dressed in ‘blue-
tail coat, blue trousers ... and a glazed black top-hat strengthened with a
thick leather crown’ (Critchley 1978: 51), they were witnessing the birth of
a new institution. It was an institution that was symbolically differentiated

116
Policing and the police: key issues in criminal justice

from both the military and continental models of policing through its
distinctive uniform (modelled on civilian business dress of the day), and
effectively differentiated by its mandate, which was first and foremost
preventative. This was to be achieved by providing a visible deterrent to
acts of crime and disorder. As the new Commissioners wrote in their first
force instruction: ‘It should be understood that at the outset the principal
object to be obtained is the prevention of crime.’
The public visibility of the police can be contrasted with the relatively
low visibility of the police in the criminological endeavour. Traditional
criminology largely ignored the police: Ferri’s book on The Positive School
of Criminology, published in 1906, hardly mentions them; sixty years later
Mannheim’s (1965) major 800-page, two-volume work Comparative
Criminology had no discussion of the police institution. Even as late as
1979, Holdaway (1979: 1) could write: ‘the relative dearth of research into
the British police has achieved the status of a cliché amongst sociologists.
The British police have remained largely hidden from sociological gaze.’
Criminological theory was essentially concerned with why people
broke the law and neither an analysis of law nor its enforcement seemed
relevant to this discussion. It was assumed that the relationship between
police and the law was straightforward: the police simply enforced the
law. Criminology paid little attention to how and why criminal sanctions
came to be invoked by the police against certain types of behaviours and
not others. Nor did it ask whether sanctions were applied equally to all
individuals engaged in similar types of infraction. In fact, even when this
problem was raised by authors such as Merton (1938) or Morris (1957), it
was asserted that police records and statistics based on them, despite their
limitations, did adequately represent the distribution of crime – in
particular, that crime was concentrated among the lower classes. Attention
was not, therefore, focused upon police organisation or the practice of
enforcement.
In the formative and middle years of the development of criminology,
the police institution was thus either ignored or seen as non-problematic.
However, all this was to change with the publication of Howard Becker’s
Outsiders: Studies in the Sociology of Deviance (1963), which was to become a
key text in the emergent interactionist and labelling approaches to the
study of crime and deviancy. Becker’s simple and even trite assertion that
deviant behaviour is that which is so labelled (see chapter 3) heralded a
decisive shift in the criminological agenda, both in scope and method.
The crucial role of the police in identifying and labelling persons and
actions as deviant was increasingly recognised by criminologists. What
had previously been taken for granted was now up for debate and
examination. In particular, Becker and others expanded the criminological
gaze to include in its focus not just law-breakers, but law-makers and law
enforcers as well. The process of law creation was important to Becker and

117
Introducing Criminology

the interactionist school because it raised questions about why only some
deviant acts were criminalized. This, in turn, raised questions about how
some social groups were able to assert their power to make criminal the
activities of others. The processes of enforcement were seen as important
because Becker and others did not assume a simple translation of the ‘law
in the books’ into the ‘law in action’. The rate of criminal behaviour in a
society was to be understood from the interactionist perspective as the
product of actions of persons within the criminal justice system who
defined, classified and recorded those behaviours as criminal – and these
activities were themselves worth of study.
For the interactionists, it was not the quality of the act that was
important to understanding deviancy, but the label applied to the act. This
means that they were not interested, as traditional criminology had been,
in the constitutional, psychological or physiological characteristics of
offenders, but in the processes leading to a person being officially defined
and labelled as deviant. The focus of criminological interest was thus shift-
ing away from offenders and deviants per se towards the criminal justice
system itself, its component parts and its processes. Given that the police
are the most important gatekeepers of the criminal justice system and
therefore highly influential in determining who is officially labelled as
criminal, criminological research on the police and policing assumed a
new importance. And for the interactionists, this required a different
methodology – not studies of crime rates and aggregate statistics but,
ideally, detailed and in-depth observational studies of the actual practice
of policing.
In the 1960s and 1970s then, there was a gradual opening up of the
police institution to criminological and sociological scrutiny, often in-
formed by the concerns of labelling theorists and interactionists. As Reiner
has noted,
The most characteristic type of work was close participant observa-
tion of police patrol work, primarily concerned with laying bare the
occupational culture of operational policing...in order to describe
and account for the rules and meanings that constitute it
(Reiner 1992b: 441)
However, once Pandora’s box was opened, these early concerns gave way
to new issues. The police became interesting in their own right, and in the
1980s in Britain the issues of public order (signalled largely by widespread
riots in inner city areas), police efficiency and effectiveness (given promi-
nence by the Conservative government’s concern with ‘value for money’
and limiting overall public expenditure) and miscarriages of justice (many
of which were shown, in part at least, to have emanated from poor or
corrupt policing methods), all gave rise to the police institution being
subject to an intense criminological gaze.

118
Policing and the police: key issues in criminal justice

In the rest of this chapter we propose to outline what we regard as some


of the key issues which have preoccupied criminologists in studying the
police over the past four decades:
• Definitions and delivery: what do we mean by ‘the police’ and
‘policing’? What do the police do? Is their primary role the control of
crime?
• Discretion and discrimination: how does police discretion operate?
Does it discriminate against certain groups in the population? In this
context, we discuss the concept of police culture, which has frequently
been used to explain the way in which police discretion is exercised.
• Due process and deviancy: to what extent does police practice conform
to a ‘due process’ model? How does police malpractice in violation of
due process come about?

Definitions and delivery

The word ‘police’ is derived from the Greek word ‘polis’, meaning city. As
Johnston (1992: 4) notes, before the eighteenth century, in English the word
‘police’ was used to refer to the general governance and administrative
regulation of the city. Thus the activity of policing embraced the whole
range of functions necessary for the maintenance of civic society, and if
this broader definition were still in currency today, it would include the
activities of tax inspectors, environmental health officers and school-cross-
ing patrols. Indeed, until the 1970s, the police in most parts of England and
Wales retained responsibility for such matters as taxi-licensing, dog-
licensing, diseases of animals and animal movement orders and abattoir
inspections. However, as Johnston (1992: 4) argues:

It was only in the mid-eighteenth century that the word ‘police’


began to be used, in its continental sense, to refer to the specific func-
tions of crime prevention and order maintenance. From then, it was
but a short step to defining ‘police’ in terms of specific personnel.

What this means is that when we use the terms ‘to police’ or ‘policing’ we
tend to equate them with what the police currently do, rather than with
their broader historical meaning. Indeed the most contemporary defini-
tion of ‘police’ in the Oxford English Dictionary reflects this shift, since
both the personnel and function are conflated in the same definition:

The civil force which is entrusted with the duty of maintaining public
order, enforcing regulations for the punishment or prevention of
breaches of the law and detecting crime. (OED)
119
Introducing Criminology

The importance of this is that as criminologists we need to be careful about


simply equating policing with the police. Other agencies (such as Customs
and Excise and the Factories Inspectorate) perform policing functions, and
Shearing and Stenning (1987) and Johnston (1992) have argued that the
neglected but important growth of the private security sector also requires
criminological attention. This is of particular significance, given that in
1994 it was estimated that the private security industry had a turnover of
nearly three billion pounds and employed in excess of 164,000 personnel;
it is therefore starting to rival the police in terms of expenditure and has
already overtaken them in terms of manpower (Morgan and Newburn,
1997).
Moreover, private companies are encroaching on duties that have been
the traditional preserve of the public police. Court security and the
associated prisoner escort is an obvious example. In Doncaster in 1996
Household Security, a private company, employed eleven staff to provide
car and foot patrols to residents at a cost of one pound a week to each
subscribing household (Sharp and Wilson, 2000). Thus the increasing
importance of the private security industry and the blurring of the
boundaries between public and private police reminds us that merely to
equate the activity of policing with the police misses a vast amount of
activity which should come under the banner of policing.
So far we have stressed the inappropriateness of conflating policing
with the police but this does little to tell us how to define what the public
police do. The most common way of dealing with this problem is to define
the police by their functions. As we have already seen the original instruc-
tions to the New Police issued by the first Commissioners stressed that:

the principal object to be obtained is the prevention of crime ... to this


great end every effort of the police is to be directed. The security of
person and property, the preservation of the public tranquillity, and
all other objects of a police establishment will thus be better effected
than by the detection and punishment of the offender after he has
succeeded in committing the crime.
(quoted in Critchley, 1978: 52;
see also Morgan and Newburn, 1997: 76)

In the early 1960s the Royal Commission on the Police reviewed these
aims for the first time in 130 years and although they extended the roles
somewhat to take into account the modern circumstances of the police, the
prime responsibilities of the police were still defined as being:
• to maintain law and order and to protect persons and property.
• to prevent crime.
• to be responsible for the detection of criminals.
120
Policing and the police: key issues in criminal justice

Some thirty years later a joint sub-committee of the Association of


Chief Police Officers (ACPO), the Superintendents’ Association and the
Police Federation also presented a definition of the police in terms of
their core functions. In their Statement of Common Purpose and Values they
state:

The purpose of the police service is to uphold the law fairly and
firmly; to prevent crime; to pursue and bring to justice those who
break the law; to keep the Queen’s Peace; to protect, help and
reassure the community; and to be seen to do all this with integrity,
common sense and sound judgement.
(quoted in Morgan and Newburn 1997: 77)

We can see that over the course of over 170 years there is a clear continuity
in these functionally based definitions of the police: the prevention or
crime, the detection of crime, the enforcement of law, and the maintenance
of order remain at their heart. For some this represents the genius of the
original formulation. However, there has been a growing dissatisfaction
amongst criminologists with defining the police by a set of idealised roles
which, some argue, are largely unattainable. To examine the source of this
dissatisfaction, we intend to examine the extent to which the police are
able to fulfil these functions

Enforcement, prevention and detection: the police role examined


Ironically, the majority of police work is not related to law enforcement.
For instance, Punch’s study of calls for police assistance in three East
Anglian towns revealed that between half and three-quarters of all re-
quests for assistance were for ‘service’, such as dispute settlement and
attending at road accidents, rather than law enforcement functions (Punch
and Naylor 1973). Ekblom and Heal’s (1982) study of incoming calls to a
subdivisional control room confirmed Punch’s earlier findings. Only 18
per cent of calls required the preparation of a fresh crime report and calls
relating to service functions made up by far the greatest proportion of
demand. In Punch’s terms, the police represent a ‘secret social service’. It is
secret because of the lack of recognition of the wide range of such tasks
routinely performed by officers. These early findings have been confirmed
by more recent studies: Morgan’s (1990) study and Waddington’s (1993)
study found that, respectively, only around 35 per cent and 25 per cent
of calls to police were crime related. Shapland and Vagg (1988: 39) argue
that the attempt to categorise calls into simple categories like ‘crime’
and ‘service’ at the outset is fraught with difficulties; their study
categorised calls for service according to whether they might involve
crime. On this basis over half of calls (53 per cent) were categorised as
‘potential crime’.
121
Introducing Criminology

If a different measurement device is used, that of task analysis of how


patrol officers spend their time, then even smaller proportions of police
activity are shown to be directly related to law enforcement. A study by
Comrie and Kings (1974) showed that, in both rural and urban settings,
only about 6 per cent of a patrol officer’s time was spent on incidents that
are finally defined as criminal. This figure is broadly supported by the
findings of the 1988 British Crime Survey which estimated that only 18 per
cent of contacts between police and public were crime related (Skogan
1990), although the Islington Crime survey, based on a Inner City London
borough, found that 51 per cent of contacts concerned crime (Jones et al
1986).
The accumulated evidence from various ethnographic studies also
confirms, and gives colour to, the broad range of non-crime related
activities that the police are called to deal with (Banton 1964; Cain 1973;
Holdaway 1983; Policy Studies Institute (PSI) 1983: Vol. 4; Norris 1989).
From our own experience of the reality of routine patrol the following
tasks would not be untypical of the tasks falling to uniformed patrol
officers:

• looking after a lost child


• dealing with sudden and unexplained deaths
• attending the scene of a road traffic accident
• securing entry for a resident to check on the safety of an elderly
neighbour whom she has not seen for two days
• moving on some youths who are playing football in a private resi-
dential street
• taking a report of a burglary that happened while the residents were at
work
• settling a dispute between two neighbours about the ownership of a
parking space
• moving on a drunk who has collapsed in a doorway
• informing a local resident that their father died earlier that morning and
asking them to make contact with their family
• attending the scene of a noisy party and asking the occupants to turn
the volume down
• warning a group of youths not to play on a building site as it was
potentially very dangerous
• helping a bus driver evict a passenger who had sworn at him and
refused to leave the bus.
122
Policing and the police: key issues in criminal justice

The list could go on. Name any source of human conflict or emergency
situation and the police have undoubtedly been called to deal with it. In
the light of this, Egon Bittner (1974) suggests that the key function of the
police is to deal with ‘something-that-ought-not-to-be-happening-and-
about-which-something-ought-to-be-done-now’. What is important is
that it is largely the public, not the police, who define which situations
require police intervention.
Although much police work is not directly related to law enforcement
and crime control, it is often argued that the presence of patrols on the
street has a deterrent and preventative function. A study conducted some
years ago found that some 55 per cent of patrol officers’ time was spent on
random and uncommitted patrol (Comrie and Kings, 1974). Studies of
both car and foot patrols tended to question the deterrent effect of
patrolling. Both British and American data indicated that, although some
patrol presence is necessary to deter potential offenders, the precise
number of foot or car patrols made very little difference; it is only when
patrols were removed completely that reported crime increases (Bright
1969; Kelling et al 1974).
This was hardly surprising, since foot patrol officers are only as
effective as far as their eyes can see and ears can hear and, for that matter,
so are car patrol officers. As Clarke and Hough (1984: 7) pointed out in
their review on the literature on police effectiveness:

given present burglary rates and an evenly distributed patrol


coverage, a patrolling policeman in London could expect to pass
within a hundred yards of a burglary in progress once every eight
years and even then not realise that the crime was taking place.

To become a real deterrent, the level of patrolling would have to be


increased to a point where the chance of discovery and detection of crime
was a high probability, which is not an economically feasible proposition.
Furthermore, burglars are well aware that the likelihood of being caught is
low; therefore, any realistic increase in the level of foot patrol would be
liable to have little effect. These findings were endorsed by the Audit
Commission’s (1993) evaluation of police patrolling strategies which
concluded that they were grossly inefficient as a means of controlling
crime. In recent years, police strategies have therefore attempted to shift
towards a more proactive and intelligence-driven approach.
In the past, it was commonly thought that a system of reactive policing,
with the primary aim of a swifter response to calls for assistance and
complaints, was the strategy to replace traditional patrolling (e.g. Home
Office 1967). Unfortunately, the theory behind rapid response generally
failed to take into account the length of time that callers take to contact the
police after they have discovered an offence. Ekblom and Heal’s (1982)

123
Introducing Criminology

study found that over 60 per cent of callers had delayed at least five
minutes before calling the police; Beick and Kessler’s (1977) study in the
USA found that over 50 per cent of people took between twenty and forty
minutes before calling the police, with victims often discussing with
relatives and friends what action they should take before calling. Quite
clearly, rapid response is severely limited in its effectiveness by the delay
between incident and reporting.
Contrary to the popular mythology surrounding police investigations
which portrays them as involving painstaking detective work, piecing
together disparate clues to put a name to an unsolved crime, the police are
highly dependent on victims and witnesses for the identification of
offenders. Burrows and Tarling’s (1982) study of records drawn from three
metropolitan police forces illustrates that the police are responsible for
detecting either directly or indirectly only about 15 per cent of recorded
crime. There now seems to be a general consensus of research findings that
the public is primarily responsible for the detection of between 83 and 85
per cent of cleared-up offences (Steer, 1980; Mawby, 1979; Bottomley and
Coleman, 1981).
In a recent review of detective effectiveness, Bayley concluded that
detectives:

know if perpetrators cannot be identified by people on the scene, the


police are not likely to find the criminals on their own. Nor is
physical evidence especially important in determining whether a
case is pursued, it is used as confirmation – to support testimony that
identifies suspects ... in short criminal investigators begin with
identification, then collect evidence: they rarely collect evidence and
then make an identification. If a crime can not be solved on the spot,
the case will probably be closed and the detectives will move on to
more promising cases.
(Bayley 1996: 35–36)

These generalisations are not necessarily true for serious crime, but with
most other offences, if the offender is apprehended, it is usually because
they are caught red-handed or because a victim or witness can give
specific information on the person who committed the offence. When the
police do not have such information, the probability of detecting offenders
is very low (Loveday 1996). Perhaps this is best illustrated by the case of
the Yorkshire Ripper manhunt which, by July 1979, months before he was
caught, had involved 500 police officers, 250,000 officer hours and had cost
over three million pounds (Nicholson 1979). More recently, there has been
a massive police effort in trying to establish the identity of the killer of Jill
Dando, the presenter of BBC’s Crimewatch programme, who was gunned
down in the street by an unknown attacker in 1999. Forensic evidence, and

124
Policing and the police: key issues in criminal justice

such techniques as criminal profiling, have an obvious appeal in such


cases, in which the investigation is pursued well beyond that in many
other crimes.
In summary, then, it can be argued that the police have little effect on
the prevention of crime, spend relatively little of their time dealing with it
and do little to detect it. This should not be read as a criticism of the police,
but merely a description of the reality of police work. It is however, for
Bayley, a criticism of those who peddle definitions which seek to equate
police work with a set of functions that they cannot fulfil. For him this is
surely a recipe for disaster in three ways. First, more and more money is
pumped into the police institution on the basis of a false understanding of
what the police can achieve. Second, it leads to an undermining of public
confidence in the police, as they are seen to fail. Third, it does nothing to
address the problem of crime. Instead of a focus on crime, what is needed
is a definition of policing which encapsulates the range of functions into
some form of thematic unity. With this in mind, we now want to focus on
the work of three criminologists, one British, Paul Rock, one American,
Egon Bittner, and one Canadian, Richard Ericson, each of whom has tried
to formulate a thematic definition of policing.

Paul Rock
Rock (1973) argues that there is indeed a functional unity to all the various
police activities in that they are related to the primary role of being
‘responsible for the boundary patrolling tasks of a system of social control.
They control those deviancies which are proscribed both by external law-
giving institutions and by their own law-interpreting behaviour’ (Rock
1973: 174).
To perform this primary role, there are subsidiary functions which
facilitate its implementation and these are what Rock (1973: 183) terms ‘the
incidental and unintended consequences of police work’. Thus, the range
of non-crime-related tasks that the police find themselves involved in are a
necessary price to pay for the police ‘to continue to function as effective
agents of control’ (Rock 1973: 184). The involvement in these subsidiary
tasks is a mechanism which enables the police to perform their primary
control function without undue recourse to coercive measures, by
cloaking the office in a shroud of legitimacy. Further, such interventions
enable informal contacts with the community, resulting in an increased
information flow about other, more serious matters. Thus, the ‘coercive
role style is tempered by a benign complexion’ (Rock 1973: 184); coercive
power is transposed into legitimate authority by the diversity of tasks that
the police are prepared to engage in.
Although he regards non-crime tasks as subsidiary, merely involved
in generating legitimacy to facilitate other primary tasks, Rock does alert
us to the danger of seeing the police solely in terms of the enforcement,

125
Introducing Criminology

detection and prevention of crime. If other activities are seen as peripheral,


they are in danger of being hived off to other institutions, such as private
security guards, city wardens, social workers, and the like, so that the
police can get on with their ‘primary role’.
These ideas gained strong currency during the 1990s, especially in the
Home Office. The Conservative Government White Paper on police
reform (Home Office 1993) was clear in its view that the ‘main job of the
police is to catch criminals’ (para 2.3). The view that there are ‘ancillary’
tasks that might be relinquished, leaving the (expensive) police free to
concentrate on their ‘core’ task of controlling crime, was the impetus
behind the Posen Inquiry (Home Office 1995), whose deliberations met
with considerable resistance from police staff associations and in the end
was hardly radical in its recommendations. The police role received yet
more attention in the form of an independent inquiry set up by the Police
Foundation and the Policy Studies Institute (1996). The report endorsed
the police service’s definition contained in the Statement of Common
Purpose and drew upon research studies to conclude that the police can
only have a limited impact on crime.
As Loveday (1996) has pointed out, the experience of Los Angeles,
which in the early 1990s prioritised crime control above service and low-
level order maintenance, does not support the idea of police concentration
on crime. In LA, general patrol police officers were replaced by specialist
units concerned with a narrow focus on crime control and, as a result,
officers were not available to respond to the more mundane calls for
service. There were, ironically, two consequences of this strategy: crime
rates remained the same and Los Angles experienced the worst rioting in
the USA for thirty years, after the police were filmed brutally beating a
black suspect, Rodney King (see Loveday 1996: 96). In a special report
commissioned by the Los Angeles police into the causes of the riots, it was
argued that the development of specialist squads and a narrow focus on
crime control had led to a situation where citizens only came into
adversarial contact with the police. The report concluded that:

The public, therefore, only saw the police pulling people over,
standing over prone suspects and in other tense confrontational
situations. It is not surprising that members of the community
viewed the LAPD with fear and a degree of hostility.
(quoted in Loveday, 1996: 97)

By making legitimacy the concept that unifies the diverse police functions
with the core mandate, Rock has identified an important element of British
and American police traditions. However, he still sees policing as being
defined primarily by its law enforcement functions and this, as we have
argued, is inappropriate. Egon Bittner in his book The Functions of the Police

126
Policing and the police: key issues in criminal justice

(1975) sought a different solution to the problem of definition, by


concentrating on the means rather than the ends of policing. He argued that
the key to identifying the distinctive element of policing was in its use of
force.

Egon Bittner
Bittner recognised that while other public and private officials had the
right to use force to achieve their ends, these were strictly limited to their
specific spheres of competence. Prison officers could only use force inside
a prison, mental health officials on those in their care, parents on their own
children, and so on. The police, on the other hand, have the right to use
force against any person across the whole domain of a domestic territory
and for a whole range of purposes. Thus he wrote: ‘the role of the police is
best understood as a mechanism for the distribution of non-negotiable
coercive force, employed in accordance with the dictates of an intuitive
grasp of situational exigencies’ (Bittner 1978: 33).
At first reading, this seems a remarkably obscure way of defining the
police: it certainly does not trip off the tongue, but that is because it is
trying to move beyond the specific to find a level of generality that would
make it universally applicable. If you read it again slowly, you will see that
there are three principal elements to the definition.
First, the police are a mechanism for the distribution of non-negotiable
coercive force; by saying this Bittner is drawing attention to the fact that
modern states have attempted to limit the use of coercive force by private
citizens, and have delegated this function to the police. The police thereby
become the mechanism for its distribution by deciding when, where and
against whom it is used.
Second, the police use non-negotiable coercive force. By non-negotiable
Bittner means that if a police officer decides to use force in a situation it is
difficult for anyone to legitimately challenge him or her; true the officer
might face a complaint or criminal prosecution later on, but at the time
they do not have to brook arguments or opposition – in that sense it is non-
negotiable.
Third, this force is employed in accordance with the dictates of an intuitive
grasp of situational exigencies. By this Bittner is noting that the justification
for the use of force, as such, cannot be entirely derived from any external
prescription. True, the law specifies the legitimate police use of force (in
England and Wales s.3 of the Criminal Justice Act 1967 prescribes the
circumstances and degree of force which can lawfully be used), but it
cannot say exactly when and where it may be used: that can only be
decided in the light of a police officer’s particular reading of a particular
situation at a particular time.
As Bittner notes, the utility of this definition is that it lends ‘homo-
geneity to such diverse procedures as catching a criminal, driving the

127
Introducing Criminology

mayor to the airport, evicting a drunken person from a bar, directing


traffic, crowd control, taking care of lost children, administering first aid
and separating fighting relatives’ (Bittner 1978: 38).
What has coercive force got to do with taking care of lost children?
Bittner has the answer: if a lost seven-year-old is taken to the police station,
the sergeant will probably try to keep him happy with sweets and fizzy
drinks; if the child tries to leave before his parents arrive the sergeant will
undoubtedly prevent him, if necessary by putting him in a room and
locking the door.
Bittner’s definition has been highly influential in providing a basis for
analysing patrol work. However, there has been one notable criticism of
Bittner. By making power and force equivalents, Bittner has made the
other resources at a police officer’s disposal subsidiary. As the PSI report
notes (1983: Vol. 4: 173), ‘the great majority of police officers habitually try
to avoid using more force than is necessary’. Even in adversarial situa-
tions, the police rarely resort to coercion to secure compliance (Southgate
and Ekblom 1986). Nor is this only true of British policing: in Reiss’s (1980)
study in the USA, over 90 per cent of arrests were managed without
recourse to gross force, i.e. physical coercion, threat or handcuffs. The
definition therefore obscures the diversity of strategies used to achieve
compliance (Muir 1977; Bittner and Bayley 1983; Fielding 1984). In our
view this is not a fatal criticism, but one that requires addressing.

Richard Ericson
Ericson attempts address this criticism by proposing a definition which
specifies the function of policing. As we have seen, most incidents that the
police involve themselves in do not end up with a crime report being filed,
nor do the police have much effect on either the prevention or detection of
crime. In the light of this, Ericson proposes that:

The mandate of police patrol officers is to employ a system of rules


and authoritative commands to transpose troublesome, fragile situa-
tions back into a normal or efficient state, whereby the ranks of
society are preserved ... . Therefore the patrol police are essentially a
vehicle in the reproduction of order.
(Ericson 1982: 7)

The importance of this is that it allows thematic unity, as does Bittner’s


definition, but without prejudging the resources that are used to recon-
stitute order. It locates the police firmly as the guardians of the status quo.
However, by focusing on reproduction, the question of order is made
problematic; it is not merely transmitted but ‘continually worked at
through the process of conflict, negotiation and subjection’ (Ericson 1982:
7).

128
Policing and the police: key issues in criminal justice

Unity is derived at the level of function rather than of technique; the


police are seen as restitutive in the variety of situations that they
encounter. But the definition is not imperialistic in specifying ‘whose’
order. As Sykes and Brent (1983: 28) note, the police are often called into
situations not as ‘enforcers’ of a public legal conception of order, but as
‘reinforcers’ of localised private normative conceptions of order. This
results because people confuse their ‘private informal order with the
formal legal order’. In this situation, legal sanction is often inappropriate.
Donald Black (1980), in his chapter on dispute settlement, makes the point
that people call the police because the resources they possess for the
resolution of conflict are insufficient. In the majority of these incidents,
police officers are called to act as conciliators to try to reconcile conflicting
parties. As Ericson notes, the resources that officers bring to bear cover a
wide range, including the:

general authority of his office; his procedural legal powers to detain,


search, and use of physical force; his substantive legal powers to
charge; and various manipulative strategies that form part of the
recipe knowledge of his craft. In short, he ‘negotiates order’ various-
ly employing strategies of coercion, manipulation and negotiation.
(Ericson 1982: 9)

Ericson was primarily concerned with the work of patrol police in


generating his definition. For completeness, Bayley also includes the work
of detectives in specifying the functions of the police. Drawing on the
work of Ericson, he conceptualises the modern police as performing two
major functions: authoritative intervention and symbolic justice. Authori-
tative intervention is what most uniformed officers are responsible for and
this is:

almost wholly reactive, rarely anticipatory. Crime is involved only


occasionally or ambiguously. The purpose of authoritative interven-
tion is to restore order. Almost no attempt is made to correct the
underlying conditions that have led to the need for police interven-
tion.
(Bayley, 1996: 34)

Symbolic justice, on the other hand:

is the realm of detectives and traffic officers: also largely reactive, it is


achieved through law enforcement. Its purpose is demonstrative, to
show offenders and the public that a regime of law exists ... . The
success of the police in rendering symbolic justice is almost entirely
dependent on information supplied by the public.
(Bayley, 1996: 34)

129
Introducing Criminology

Although we would argue that the distinction between uniformed and


detective officers is somewhat overdrawn (for instance, in the UK
uniformed officers make the majority of crime arrests – see Chatterton
1976), the overall point is correct. Public policing is largely concerned with
achieving authoritative intervention to reproduce order, and imposing
symbolic justice through the pursuit and arrest of offenders. Finally, there
is also clearly a great deal more that could be said about the changing
forms and functions of policing in late modern societies, including, as we
have already suggested, the way in which ‘public policing’ is only one
form of policing alongside others (see Johnston 2000).

Discretion and discrimination

As Waddington (1999: 31) has rightly observed: ‘Prior to the revisionism of


the 1960s, the prevailing assumption was that policing was little more than
the application of law’. As we have seen, much criminological attention
has been aimed at challenging this assertion. But what in practice does it
mean ‘to uphold’ or to apply the law? Does it mean that whenever a law is
broken the police must enforce it? If this were true, the police would
merely be puppets of the legal system, blindly enforcing the law regard-
less of context or consequence. What we know from detailed studies of
police work in Britain (Banton 1964; Cain 1973; Holdaway 1983;
Waddington 1993), America (Black 1980; Rubinstein 1973; Van Maanen
1978; Bayley 1994) and Canada (Ericson 1982) is that this could not be
further from the truth. The police use law, among a number of other
resources, in order to restore order and impose symbolic justice. They are
not slaves to law but law is their servant. This realisation is of profound
importance because it signals the centrality of discretion to understanding
police work. In this next section we want to examine the nature, con-
sequences and importance of discretion.

Discretion
What is police discretion? Drawing on Davis’s (1969) seminal, but general
definition of discretion, Klockars proposed the following:

A police officer or police agency may be said to exercise discretion


whenever effective limits on his, her or its power leave them free to
make a choice amongst possible courses of action or inaction.
(Klockars 1985: 93)

We can note three salient points about this definition. First, Klockars does
not use the word ‘law’, but the words ‘effective limits’; this is because even
where the law may insist on a course of action (in America there are ‘full
130
Policing and the police: key issues in criminal justice

enforcement’ statutes), if there is no mechanism for ensuring that officers


comply, they are ‘effectively’ able to choose. In the context of police this is
very important, since one of the most striking aspects of the police
organisation is that the degree of discretion is greatest at the lowest level of
the hierarchy, partly because much police work outside the station is of
such low visibility to managerial oversight (Goldstein 1960).
Secondly, discretion is not just a property of individual police decisions
in dealing with particular incidents, but of departmental policies, struc-
tures and organisation which frame those individual decisions. For
instance, the setting up of a local robbery squad to tackle a recent rise in
street crime is a discretionary decision, albeit one taken at a managerial or
organisational level. Discretion at this level has been reduced in England
and Wales since the Police and Magistrates Courts Act 1994. This enables
the Home Secretary to set national policing objectives, and police authori-
ties must produce annual local policing plans and set performance targets
to measure the achievement of objectives.
Thirdly, the exercise of discretion can involve doing something or not
doing something. This is important because the term ‘discretion’ has
sometimes been equated with a questionable decision not to arrest some-
one where there were legal grounds for doing so. The important thing to
note is that, in English law at least, the decision to arrest is itself
discretionary.
Let us take a simple example to illustrate this point. Imagine that a
police officer is called to the scene of two men fighting on a street corner.
They are still fighting when the police arrive. The officer could:
• break it up with an informal warning to both participants and take no
other action
• break it up, inquiring into the cause and attempting to conciliate and
mediate between the two parties
• formally caution one or both parties
• attempt to find the cause of the fight and arrest the person they believe
to be the most blameworthy
• arrest both parties on any appropriate public order or assault charges.
(Lustgarten 1986: 10)
As Lustgarten has rightly argued, ‘all the suggested options are within the
range of a constable’s legal powers. To say therefore that he must uphold
the law, or is responsible to the law, is in practical terms meaningless’
(Lustgarten 1996: 11).
If discretion is so subversive to our notion of the rule of law, why do the
police have it? In general there have been four major justifications for the
existence of police discretion:
131
Introducing Criminology

• the finite resources available to perform police work


• the need for interpretational latitude in applying law
• the need to preserve legitimacy
• the need for efficiency.
We will examine each in more detail below.

Resources
Given that the police have finite resources, they have to make choices
about how to deploy them and this inevitably means prioritising some
activities over others. Moreover, if the police were rigorously to enforce
some high volume offences like speeding, the capacity of others within the
criminal justice system to process them, such as the Crown Prosecution
Service and the courts, would soon be exceeded. As already noted, how-
ever, the scope for discretion in setting priorities has been lessened by the
Police and Magistrates Courts Act 1994.

Interpretational latitude
The law as it is written in the books purports to be clear and unambiguous,
but the messy reality of life rarely falls easily into the neat categories of the
law. All criminal statutes in England and Wales say that ‘a police constable
may arrest...’. Police officers have to interpret what they find to find a fit
between the events and the law, and they need to temper the law with
notions such as justice/fairness and appropriateness. As Klockars (1985:
98) notes, the law ‘overreaches’ itself and criminalizes more than it
intends. For instance, would the interests of justice be served by prosecut-
ing a surgeon for travelling at ten miles an hour over the speed limit, on
her way to perform life saving surgery, or the driver of a vehicle which due
to his own carelessness had swerved off the road resulting in the death of
his wife and daughter? Probably not.

Legitimacy
Full enforcement would lead to an undermining of the basis for police
legitimacy. One of the advantages of under-enforcement is that the police
can build up credit with a citizenry who, in acknowledgement that they
have been dealt with more favourably in the past, are more likely to
cooperate with police requests for help in the future. ‘Policing by consent’
is a key concept in this context. At the extreme, some have argued that full
enforcement would completely undermine the social fabric: ‘Any society
that committed the energy, resources and personnel to root out and punish
all wrongdoers would set off enough mass paranoia, violent conflict and
savage repression to become a charnel house, and pass into oblivion’
(Blumberg, 1970, cited in Rock, 1973: 179).

132
Policing and the police: key issues in criminal justice

Efficiency
A policy of full enforcement would not allow the police to differentiate
between important and trivial crimes, and between cases where some
productive outcome can be achieved and those where this is unlikely.
Where resources are finite (see above), decisions need to be made about
the most efficient or effective use of them. Full enforcement would also
make it impossible for the police to ‘trade’ the threat of sanction for
information. One of the key investigative strategies, especially in ‘victim-
less’ crimes, of letting the little fish go, in exchange for information so that
bigger fish can be caught, would be unworkable (see Dunnighan and
Norris 1999).
Criminologists have, then, recognised the inevitability of discretion,
that police work is only partially concerned with law enforcement, and
even when there are clear infractions of law, there is no guarantee that
arrest and prosecution will follow. This realisation has had two major
implications for criminology.
First, that recorded crime statistics cannot be treated as an accurate or
reliable measure of the nature, distribution and extent of criminality. As
Kituse and Cicourel noted, crime rates should be ‘viewed as indices of
organisational processes rather than as indices of the incidence of certain
forms of behaviour’ (Kitsuse and Cicourel 1963: 135). This insight led to a
number of important studies documenting how crime statistics were a
social construction (Bottomley and Coleman 1981; McCabe and Sutcliffe
1978; Young 1991), and the development of alternative measures of crime
and victimisation which are not reliant on police processing, such as self-
report studies and victimisation surveys (see Coleman and Moynihan
1996 for a review).
Second, if the law does not provide the full answer as to what police
officers should do in a situation, attention shifts to what else influences
their decisions. As Klockars points out, this issue strikes at the heart of
democratic governance, with its emphasis on ‘the rule of law’. As he
writes:

Under a government of laws police should not be allowed to make


what amounts to their own laws, amend laws that have already been
made, or decide that some people should have certain laws enforced
on them while allowing others to violate the same laws with
impunity. The whole idea of the police enjoying some broad
discretionary power seems to open the door to arbitrariness, favour-
itism and discrimination.
(Klockars 1985: 95)

For this reason, much criminological attention has been focused on what,
given such discretion, shapes police decision-making and the extent to

133
Introducing Criminology

which this leads to policing which is discriminatory, in the sense that the
law is unevenly applied in relation to different social groups in a way that
is ‘unjustified by legally relevant factors’ (Reiner 1992a: 162).

Discrimination
There is little doubt about the existence of what Reiner calls differentiation
– that the exercise of police powers falls disproportionately upon some
groups rather than others. Police enforcement activity largely falls upon
the young rather than the old, the poor rather than the affluent, men
rather than women, the urban rather than the rural, public rather than the
private domains, and so on. Whether and to what extent differentiation
involves discrimination are more difficult questions to answer. For
illustrative purposes, we will briefly concentrate on two areas: the ‘over-
policing’ of black people and the ‘under-policing’ of incidents of domestic
violence.

The ‘over-policing’ of black people


The ‘over-policing’ of black people has been consistently documented
by a range of studies at the level of stops, arrests and post-arrest deci-
sions:

Stops: studies have consistently found that black people are more likely to
be stopped than whites, with estimates ranging from between two and
four times what one would expect on the basis of their presence in the
population. Not only is the rate of stops greater, but a black person is more
likely to be repeatedly stopped during the course of a year (Willis 1983, PSI
1983, Skogan 1994, Norris et al 1992, Macpherson 1999).

Arrests: studies by Stevens and Willis (1979), PSI (1983), Walker et al


(1990) and Phillips and Brown (1998) have all found evidence of a higher
black arrest rate than one would expect from their presence in the
population. For instance, one of the most recent surveys, Phillips and
Brown (1998), found that in eight out of the ten police stations they
studied, black people were between two and eight times more likely to be
arrested than whites.

Post-arrest decisions: studies have also revealed how other areas of


police discretionary decision-making also seem to disadvantage black
people, such as in the choice of charge (Blom-Cooper and Drabble 1982),
the decision to caution rather than commence formal proceedings
(Landau and Nathan 1983, Jefferson and Walker 1992, Phillips and Brown
1998) and the decision to recommend bail (see FitzGerald 1993 for a
review).

134
Policing and the police: key issues in criminal justice

Of course, one possible explanation for these differences is that black


people actually do commit certain types of crime more than whites and are
therefore are more likely to be targets of police action. In this case, it could
be argued that the differentiation is justified on the basis of differential
offending profiles of the black and white communities. Despite this issue
being hotly debated amongst criminologists (see Reiner 1992a, Lea and
Young 1993), there is no easy resolution to it. For example, we do not in
this instance have enough satisfactory studies of relative crime rates that
are independent of police practice. There have been few self-report studies
of offending behaviour that have looked at ethnic differences, although
one of the few to have been conducted in this country (Bowling et al 1994,
Graham and Bowling 1996) found no significant differences between black
and white self-reported offending. However, this study has been criticised
on methodological grounds (Coleman and Moynihan 1996). As FitzGerald
(1993: 4) wrote in her report to the Royal Commission on Criminal Justice,
‘it is impossible to know the precise extent of ethnic differences in offend-
ing rates once all other relevant factors are taken into account [such as age,
employment status, area of residence, etc.]; and this makes for uncertainty
in interpreting ethnic differences at the point of entry’. The broad
consensus amongst many criminologists is that while differences in
offending behaviour may explain some of the over-representation of black
people in the criminal justice system, they only explain some of it (Lea and
Young, 1993; Smith, 1997).
For some commentators (see particularly Gilroy, 1982; Bridges 1983),
the over-enforcement of law against black people can be explained by the
informal norms, values, attitudes and beliefs which they see as comprising
the occupational police sub-culture. In particular they draw on the
findings of a raft of ethnographic studies, which document the use and
prevalence of racist language by the police and a range of negative
attitudes towards black people in general. From this it is argued that it is
easy to see how police discretion produces over-enforcement: it is the
result of officers’ prejudice and discriminatory behaviour.
However, following Reiner (1992a), we would argue that the pattern of
differentiation cannot be seen as simply a product of higher rates of
offending or as simply arising from attitudes found in the police sub-
culture; the process is far more complex and multi-layered than this.
Taking the evidence from various observation studies (including James
1979; Holdaway 1983 and PSI 1983: Vol. 4), Reiner (1992a: 157) argues that
categorical discrimination (i.e. action against members of a particular
group only on the basis that they are members of that group) is probably
the least important form of discrimination that may be operating. If
discrimination does occur, it is more likely to be operative because of other
practices which are outside of the purview of the individual police officer,
or not related to his or her attitudinal values. These additional forms of

135
Introducing Criminology

discrimination Reiner terms transmitted, interactional, institutionalised


and statistical discrimination (Reiner, 1992a: ch 4).

• Transmitted discrimination operates because the police are heavily


dependent on calls from the public and, thus, differential enforcement
rates may result. If the public are more likely to call the police to
incidents involving members of ethnic groups, then it is discrimination
by sections of the public rather than the police that is operative.
Furthermore, in their role as dispute settlers, the police are often
dependent on the preference of the complainant as to what action to
take and a higher arrest rate for ethnic groups may be the result of
public prejudice.
• Interactional discrimination results from the officer using discretion, not
on the basis of legally relevant criteria, but on aspects of the interaction
between the suspect and the officer, such as the level of respect
accorded by the suspect to the officer. The greater the disrespect shown,
the more likely that an arrest will follow. Given relationships between
some young black people and the police, such groups may thus be more
likely to have formal action taken against them. As Reiner (1992a: 167)
notes, while ‘contempt of cop’ is not a valid reason for arrest, it may
provide a possible basis for a valid booking of a suspect who would
otherwise have been let off.
• Institutionalised discrimination can arise, for example, from the more
intensive policing of particular areas with high rates of crime and
deprivation (which may also be areas of greater black residence). Thus,
particular sections of the community living in those areas are dis-
proportionately stopped, searched and arrested. Thus police policies
and procedures at an organisational level ‘may work out in practice as
discriminatory because of the structural bias of an unequal society’
(Reiner 1992a: 158).
• Statistical discrimination can be a predominant factor in proactive polic-
ing, especially in stop and search operations. If the lifestyle of a group is
thought to involve a legally proscribed activity, such as New Age
travellers or Rastafarians using marijuana, those identified as a member
of that group can become a target for police attention. An attempt has
been made to rule out stop and search on the basis of such things as
appearance and apparent lifestyle by the Police and Criminal Evidence
Act 1984. However, such practices may perhaps be one reason why
black people are more likely to be arrested as a result of proactive
policing strategies (see Phillips and Brown 1998: 38–9). Even so, it
should be remembered, as Reiner points out, that the basis for such
actions is a misguided concern with effectiveness – by targeting those
thought to be the most ‘likely’ suspects. The Stephen Lawrence Inquiry
136
Policing and the police: key issues in criminal justice

(Macpherson 1999) concluded that ‘institutional racism’ was apparent


in a number of areas; in its view, despite the complexities involved in
the interpretation of the evidence, there remained ‘a clear core of racist
stereotyping’ (para 6.45) in stop and search.

The ‘under-policing’ of incidents of domestic violence


If the police appear to over-enforce the law in relation to black people, then
conversely it has been shown that in relation to domestic violence, the law
is under-enforced. Detailed empirical studies, mainly carried out in the
1970s and 1980s, have shown how the police were reluctant either to arrest
or prosecute perpetrators of domestic violence, even when there was clear
evidence of an offence having been committed (Pahl 1982, Edwards 1989).
Moreover, even when the police did arrest, it was often for an offence of
less seriousness than the evidence would warrant, such as for ‘breach of
the peace’ rather than ‘assault occasioning actual bodily harm’. As Kemp,
Norris and Fielding (1992: 119) concluded:

Our research indicates that police officers as a matter of course tend


to decriminalise domestic disputes where there is evidence of a
criminal infraction. Even when there is a prima facie case for arrest
and charge ... they under-utilise their legal powers in order to
achieve an informal resolution, recommend civil proceedings or
make an arrest on resource [usually lesser] charges.

In a similar way to that in which the over-policing of black people has been
attributed to the values and beliefs of officers transmitted through the
occupational culture, so too has the under-enforcement of laws relating to
domestic violence. Again some commentators note the prevalence of
sexist language, stereotypical attitudes towards women in general, the
marginalisation and harassment of women police officers, and a general-
ised belief in the inappropriateness of police intervention in domestic
affairs, consigning it to the status of ‘rubbish’ work’. From this it is argued
that it is easy to see how police discretion produces a pattern of under-
enforcement; again it is seen as a result of prejudiced attitudes and values
contained within the occupational culture (Edwards 1989, Stanko 1985).
There have been concerted attempts to change police policy and attitudes
in this area in the last decade or so since these studies were conducted.
There are, however, problems with academic accounts and policy
initiatives which see a simple translation of attitudes into behaviour. For
instance, Hoyle’s (1998) study of the policing of domestic violence found
that a general open-ended question to police officers about domestic
disputes elicited a whole range of negative responses, but these
generalised attitudes were often belied by how they said they handled
specific disputes. As she reported:

137
Introducing Criminology

The initial comments were indicators of how domestic disputes are


still, to some extent, trivialised by officers within a canteen culture
discourse, whilst the response to questions about what officers
actually did in practice indicate the divide between certain negative
cultural attitudes and behaviour.
(Hoyle 1998: 76)

This gap between attitudes and behaviour was similar to that reported in
relation to ‘race’ some years ago by the PSI study Police and People in
London (1983):

Our first impression ... was that racialist language and racial
prejudice were prominent and pervasive and that many individual
officers and also whole groups were preoccupied with ethnic
differences. At the same time, on accompanying these officers as they
went about their work, we found that their relations with black and
brown people were often relaxed and friendly ... we are fairly
confident that there is no widespread tendency for black or Asian
people to be given greatly inferior treatment by the police.
(PSI, 1983: 109 and 128)

This possibility of a gap between what officers say and what they do
undermines the simplistic use of a concept of occupational culture
(usually based on what officers say) as guide to, and explanation for,
actual police behaviour (usually that considered undesirable)
A number of criminologists (Holdaway 1983; Norris 1989; Hoyle 1998;
Manning 1977; Waddington 1999) have adopted a more complex view of
police culture, which recognises that while police culture may have
negative and undesirable traits, in itself that culture has to be understood
as embracing far more than just negative attitudes. Police culture may still
be used to help explain the difference between law in action and the law in
the books, but that culture is seen as arising from the common problems
that officers face in the course of their work. It not only contains attitudes
and beliefs, but a stock of recipe knowledge on how to achieve the policing
task: a set of working rules for managing the vicissitudes of the job
(Manning 1982). And here it should be remembered that the job is not
primarily about the prevention of crime or the enforcement of laws but
about reproducing order by providing authoritative intervention and
symbolic justice. As Chatterton (1983: 208) has argued:

The decisions and actions taken at incidents reflect the concern to


control relationships between themselves and the various publics on
a division, to maintain their capacity to intervene authoritatively in
any incident and to preserve their own and others’ beliefs that they
were ‘on top of the area’.
138
Policing and the police: key issues in criminal justice

Moreover, officers are also concerned with satisfying organisational


demands that incidents are satisfactorily terminated: for example, that
once a police officer has dealt with an incident they are not called out
again, for this would suggest that the officer failed to negotiate or enforce
an effective closure to the incident in the first place, raising questions
about his or her competence (see Chatterton 1983: 201).
It should be stressed that such issues as over- and under-enforcement
and discrimination and differentiation cannot be understood in terms of
the police culture alone, but have to be seen in terms of the complex
inter-relationships between the individual officer, suspects, the public,
the occupational culture, the police organisation, the law, and the police
role.
Thus the ideal of law is of even and equal enforcement and therefore
that similar offences should be treated in similar ways. The patrol officer,
on the other hand, is not primarily concerned with such abstract notions
in individual encounters, but with authoritatively intervening to
reproduce order. Meanwhile, the occupational culture provides a set of
‘recipe rules’ for determining how this should be achieved, such as that
disrespectful and uncooperative suspects deserve to be arrested, and
about the extent to which victims’ preferences should be taken into
account (Waddington, 1999; Hoyle, 1998). Simultaneously, the police
organisation, as represented by the shift sergeant and inspector, is less
concerned with the specific outcome of any individual incident than with
its speedy termination on the ground and bureaucratic resolution at the
station. Dealing with incidents quickly and effectively and ‘clearing the
message pad’ so that an officer is free to deal with the next potential
emergency becomes a primary goal in reactive policing (Fielding et al
1989). In this context arrest, which will take an officer away from routine
policing, may be seen as an undesirable outcome; on the other hand,
targets in policing plans may encourage arrests to be made, so a balance
has to be struck. Finally, we should add that the officer also brings to any
incident their own individual norms and values, which make the in-
dividual officer the ‘final arbiter and mediator’ of the legal, organisational
and cultural influences (Fielding, 1988: 60). In this context, the concept of
police culture can only be one possible contributor to our understanding
of police discretion.

Due process and deviancy

Not only is there law which defines the range and nature of criminal
offences (such as murder or theft) – substantive criminal law – but there is
also law which attempts to regulate the treatment of those suspected of
crime – the law of criminal procedure. There are legal rules which govern

139
Introducing Criminology

such procedures as stop and search, search of premises, arrest, and the
detention and questioning of suspects. For example, the Police and
Criminal Evidence Act 1984 and its associated Codes of Practice were a
major attempt to provide for police and suspects a set of procedures in
these areas that would be clear, workable, fair, open and accountable.
There are also a whole host of subsidiary rules governing police practice
set down in non-statutory guidelines and force standing orders. Such
rules, it is often asserted, ensure that police powers are not exercised
arbitrarily, but constrained by the ‘due process of law’. As Sir Robert Mark,
the former commissioner of the Metropolitan Police, expressed it, ‘The fact
the British Police are answerable to law, that we act on behalf of the
community and not under the mantle of government, makes us the least
powerful, the most accountable and therefore the most acceptable police
in the world’ (Mark 1977: 56).
One of the most enduring yardsticks for evaluating the operation of
legal rules and the criminal justice system has been the model developed
by Herbert Packer (1968; see also King 1981) in the late 1960s. Packer
argued that systems of criminal justice can be usefully examined to see
what extent they correspond with two theoretical models: due process and
crime control. The models are ‘ideal’ types, each at either end of a
continuum; we would be unlikely to find a pure due process or crime
control model in reality. Let us briefly examine each in turn.

Due process
For Packer, a due process model emphasises the following.

• Rules protecting the suspect or defendant from error: for instance, as


identification evidence is notoriously unreliable, it is essential that
when the police carry out identity parades they are conducted in
accordance with strict protocol and procedures.
• The presumption of innocence: the police are not the arbiters of guilt
and innocence; this is the proper function of the courts. The role of the
police is to lay before the courts all the available evidence so the court
may judge. The police should therefore be under a duty to disclose
evidence which is helpful to the prosecution case but also to the
defendant. Nor is it the role of the accused to incriminate themselves
and thus they have a right to silence.

• Effective restraints on the use of arbitrary power: for instance, the police
may only arrest and detain on the basis of evidence, rather than on
personal whim or prejudice, and there must be effective means of
reviewing these decisions

140
Policing and the police: key issues in criminal justice

• An equality between the parties: suspects and defendants should be


able to draw on similar resources to the police in order to defend
themselves against charges brought against them. For instance, the
right of legal advice at the police station is a due process requirement
which seeks to balance the power of the police with the rights of the
suspect.

In the context of policing, the due process model sees the inviolability of
legal rules governing police powers as essential. The rules are there to
protect suspects against arbitrary power and when the rules are broken
cases should be dismissed, since otherwise this might lead to error and the
chance of a wrongful conviction.
Packer likened the due process model to an obstacle course which
guarantees that only those most likely to have committed a crime will
proceed to the next stage. Any weakness or impropriety at an earlier stage
will ensure that a case is discontinued. If it is not, there is a chance that the
innocent will be found guilty and, above all, the due process model seeks
to protect against this eventuality.

Crime control
In the crime control model, the following are examples of features that
would be emphasised:
• Disregard of legal controls: departure from legal propriety is seen as
inevitable. Formal legal rules get in the way of convicting the guilty and
therefore police malpractice is tolerated and even condoned.
• Implicit presumption of guilt: the police are seen as acting in good faith,
so that when they arrest and charge someone it is because they are
guilty. In this case there is little necessity for the courts to thoroughly
review cases before them; their job is merely to rubber stamp the
decision.
• High conviction rate: under a crime control system a high conviction
rate is necessary because if the courts were to acquit too many people
this would undermine the deterrent effect of the criminal law, and the
faith in police efficiency at bringing the right people to justice.
Whereas the primary function of the due process model is the acquittal
of the innocent, the crime control model prioritises the punishment of the
guilty.

The enduring significance of the two models has been in the realisation
that while policing is presented as being in line with due process values,
this rhetoric is undermined by the operational reality of police practice.

141
Introducing Criminology

This was particularly highlighted by the spate of miscarriages of justices


which led to the setting up of the Royal Commission on Criminal Justice in
1991. A recurring feature in many of the cases was the role of the police in
fabricating evidence, the use or threat of violence or other non-legal
sanctions to obtain confessions, and the failure to disclose information
relevant to the defence (see Rozenberg 1992 for a review of these earlier
cases).
This should come as no surprise to criminologists, who have frequently
discovered the predominance of crime control practice rather than due
process values to be at the heart of police work. To take three examples:

The right to legal advice


Even though access to legal advice is a fundamental due process right
which tries to ensure fairness and equality between the suspect and their
interrogators, Sanders et al’s (1989) study on the provision of legal advice
at the police station found that a variety of police practices had the effect of
discouraging suspects from seeking such advice.

The supremacy of the courts


Dunnighan and Norris (1996, 1999) have argued that the fundamental due
process principle of English law that the police must never mislead a court
has been routinely undermined in the police use of informers. They found,
from a sample of 31 police prosecution case files which had involved
official payment to informers, that in not a single case was the role of the
informer disclosed to the Crown Prosecution Service. Furthermore, one-
third of officers said they would be prepared to lie in court to protect an
informer.

Fabrication of evidence
The findings of the Independent Inquiry into the working practices of the
West Midlands Serious Crime Squad (Kaye 1991) revealed that in every
one of the 67 cases reviewed it had been alleged that officers fabricated
incriminating evidence. In 23 of these cases charges were dropped, the
judge directed acquittal, the jury found the defendants innocent or the
conviction was quashed on appeal (Kaye 1991: 72–73).

How can we explain this subversion of due process values? One answer
to the question is that such acts are the result of the aberrant behaviour
of individual officers who had gone off the rails. From this ‘rotten apple’,
perspective it is argued that any organisation employing tens of
thousands of people is bound to contain the occasional maverick. How-
ever good the recruitment, training, and supervisory systems, occasion-
ally someone will slip through the net. There are two fundamental
problems with such a position.

142
Policing and the police: key issues in criminal justice

First, unlike with most deviant or criminal acts, the malpractice


exposed in these cases does not, in any direct sense, result in personal gain.
‘Rotten apple’ theories may have utility in explaining some instances of
police corruption where the motivation is straightforwardly financial. In
cases where the deviant police behaviour is to ensure the judicial
punishment of the accused, there is, however, no direct personal gain. It is
therefore necessary to explain what motivated the individuals concerned
to commit such acts (so-called ‘noble cause’ corruption).
Second, in the light of evidence from the major miscarriages of justice, it
is not feasible to consider them as resulting from the actions of the isolated
deviant. In the Birmingham Six and Guildford Four cases, for instance, the
malpractice required the active cooperation and connivance of colleagues
and supervisory officers. These were thoroughly group affairs. Senior and
supervisory officers condoned the denying of suspects their legal rights
and participated in the physical abuse of suspects, and officers of all ranks
perjured themselves in the witness-box to support their colleagues’
malfeasance. Even those who were not actively involved were implicated
by their willingness to remain silent.
In the Birmingham Six case, it was precisely the fact that so many would
have been implicated in having participated or acquiesced in a cover-up
that was used to undermine the defendants’ case at trial and subsequent
appeal. According to the trial judge, if the Six were telling the truth the
police ‘had been involved in a conspiracy unprecedented in the annals of
British criminal history’ (Mullin 1987: 201).
The issue of police malpractice, then, cannot be understood in isolation
from the organisation in which it occurs and the role that the organisation
has in suppressing or facilitating deviant behaviour.
As Sir John Woodcock, Her Majesty’s Chief Inspector of Constabulary
at the time of the Royal Commission on Criminal Justice observed:
For many, many years, in truth and in anecdote, the judicial system
was complicit in police wrongdoing, wrongdoing that the police
were allowed to believe, firstly, was only part of a game and, second-
ly was necessary to shore up the eccentricities of the judicial system.
Police malpractice of this kind is primarily the fault and responsi-
bility of police leadership. However, such malpractice could not long
exist save in an atmosphere which tolerated it, even, might I say,
required it, and to that extent other parts of the criminal justice
system have been complicit in police misbehaviour.
(Woodcock 1992: 5; see Rose 1996: 38–41 for further such comments.)

But this perhaps does not go far enough, for it is not just individual police
officers and the police organisation which can subvert due process, but the
law itself.

143
Introducing Criminology

As McBarnet (1979, 1981) has argued, in practice the law often favours
crime control rather than due process. Thus, while many police research-
ers have described the rule-breaking and illegality of the rank and file
practices, McBarnet carefully illustrates how crime control practices were
enshrined in the law, particularly ad hoc case law, in Scotland of the 1970s
(McBarnet 1981: ch 3). The consequence was that:

the police are in a sense the ‘fall guys’ of the criminal justice system,
taking the blame for any injustices in the operation of law, both in
theory (in the assumption ... that they break the rules) and indeed, in
the law. ... The law on criminal procedure in its current form does not
so much set a standard of legality from which the police deviate as
provide a license to ignore it.
(McBarnet, 1979: 39)

Her work has a wider significance in pointing to the possibility of ‘a clear


gap between the rhetoric of legality and the actuality of law in both the
procedures laid down and the reasoning behind them’ (McBarnet 1979:
39). In our concentration on ‘police deviance’ we must not neglect the law
itself, assuming by default that it is the embodiment of the rhetoric of
legality. In England and Wales, for example, a great deal of effort has been
expended on the law of criminal procedure. As we have suggested, the
Police and Criminal Evidence Act 1984 and its associated Codes of Practice
were a major attempt to provide a set of clear, workable, fair, open and
accountable procedures for the treatment of those suspected of crime.
Opinions differ on this legislation and its impact (see, for example, Dixon
1992, 1999 on the debate about this).
McBarnet (1981) makes a further telling point: where the police
operate within what is called an adversarial system of justice (as opposed
to an inquisitorial one), this leads to a ‘winner takes all’ attitude,
which effectively militates against the police engaging in a dispassionate
search for the truth. An adversarial system, such as the one we have in
England and Wales, is one where the judge in a court of law leaves the
presentation of the evidence to two sides: defence and prosecution. This
can ‘turn a search for the truth into a contest played between opposing
lawyers according to a set of rules which the jury does not necessarily
accept or even understand’ (Royal Commission on Criminal Justice 1993:
3). In this system, the police are encouraged to identify with one ‘side’, and
direct their energies towards its support. Again, this point alerts us to the
need to be aware of the wider context within which policing takes place
when we consider issues of due process and police deviance. It is
insufficient to point simply to ‘rotten apples’ or to ‘police culture’ as
explanations.

144
Policing and the police: key issues in criminal justice

Conclusions

• The police should not be equated with policing, an activity that can be
performed by a number of agencies. The role of the police is better
thought of as the reproduction of order by authoritative intervention
and symbolic justice, rather than in terms of crime control.
• Given the constraints, police discretion is inevitable and even desirable.
Police powers fall disproportionately on certain groups in the popula-
tion. Although the situation is complex, it appears that some part of this
is discriminatory. It is misleading simply to attribute such discrimina-
tion to individual attitudes or ‘police culture’.
• While criminal justice processes are usually presented in terms of ‘due
process’ values, certain police practices have been shown to violate
such values, and to be more consistent with a ‘crime control model’.
Rather than being understood in terms of ‘rotten apples’, examples of
police malpractice in violation of due process values seem to be related
to the organisational context in which they occur, and to the wider legal
framework and the adversarial system within which they are located.

145
Introducing Criminology

Chapter 6

CCTV and crime prevention:


questions for criminology

In this chapter we want to explore how criminologists have responded to


the dramatic rise of CCTV (closed circuit television) as a crime prevention
strategy. First, we want to briefly examine the concept of crime prevention
and locate CCTV as a particular type of crime prevention activity within a
broader social and political context. Second, we want to highlight what has
often been seen as one of the core concerns of criminology: the evaluation
of criminal justice policy initiatives to provide evidence as to ‘what works’.
Finally, we want to consider the broader questions raised by CCTV,
particularly those addressed by criminologists operating from a more
radical or critical perspective.

Crime prevention

There are many ways to prevent crime and criminologists have sought to
delineate and differentiate the main strategies involved in crime preven-
tion. Although there is a variety of classifications (see Hughes 1998 and
Pease 1997), for our purposes the typology developed by Weiss (1987) is
most useful. Weiss identifies three main types of crime prevention activity:
primary, secondary and tertiary; we will examine each in turn.

Primary crime prevention is focussed on the offence rather than the offender,
and is often associated with situational crime prevention strategies which
focus on the immediate and localised context of the offence. At its
simplest, primary prevention may involve target hardening or removal.
Target removal strategies can include such measures as the switch from
public telephones that require coins to ones accepting only telephone
cards. Hardening strategies might include fitting metal grilles to shop

146
CCTV and crime prevention: questions for criminology

windows, steering locks to cars, and pavement bollards to prevent ram-


raiding. Most significant for our discussion, they include enhanced levels
of surveillance, such as by increasing the numbers of security guards, or
through the use of CCTV cameras.
Secondary crime prevention is concerned with offenders rather than offences
and seeks, by intervening in the lives of those who are most at risk of
offending, to prevent them committing crimes in the future.
Tertiary crime prevention strategies focus on reducing or preventing the
criminality of already known offenders, and this will typically involve
forms of rehabilitation programmes with convicted criminals.

These three different types of crime prevention strategies prioritise dif-


ferent aspects of the relationship between the individual and society.
Tertiary strategies have often been the province of the probation officer or
prison psychologist who, by working with individuals or small groups in
a therapeutic relationship, tries to ‘treat’ and therefore change the offender.
This might take the form of programmes of ‘anger management’ for those
convicted of domestic violence, or drug treatment programmes for those
whose offending is driven by addiction. In the main such strategies are
underpinned by a their concerns with the differences between offenders
and non-offenders which we discussed in chapter 2.
Secondary crime prevention, on the other hand, aims to intervene
before an offence has been committed, and divert potential offenders from
embarking on a criminal career. For instance, it could involve taking ‘at
risk’ teenagers on a visit to a local prison in an effort to deter them from
starting a ‘life of crime’. More broadly, it may involve creating leisure
facilities for youth so as to reduce ‘time for crime’, or setting up a job
creation programme, to counter the effects of youth unemployment, with
the aim of reintegrating the most economically and socially marginal.
These strategies tend to emphasise the social context of crime rather than
individual differences, and tend to be theoretically located in the theories
we discussed in chapter 3.
Primary crime prevention, however, is neither concerned with the
wider social structural causes of crime nor interventions aimed at funda-
mentally altering the individual. In secondary and tertiary strategies,
crime is conceptualised as being caused by a deficit, whether it be
inadequate socialisation, lack of self-control, blocked opportunities, lack
of jobs, or inadequate parenting skills. In primary crime prevention, par-
ticularly in its guise of situational crime prevention, crime is seen as
normal. Drawing on rational choice theory, crime is seen as being
committed by individuals who, having weighed up the cost of benefits of
crime, choose crime. Central to this is an evaluation by the potential
offender of two questions:

147
Introducing Criminology

• will I succeed in carrying out the crime?


• if I do succeed, will I get caught?
If the answer to the first question is ‘yes’, and the second ‘no’, for those
so motivated, crime is likely to occur. However, the aim of primary
preventative strategies in any given local context is to alter the balance of
probabilities so that the answer to the question, ‘will I succeed?’ is ‘no’ and
‘will I be caught?’ is ‘yes’.
Primary preventative strategies do not therefore try to change the basic
motivation of the offender but to increase the costs and risks associated
with committing a particular crime at a particular time. It is therefore
concerned with opportunity reduction, through target hardening and
removal, and increased chance of detection though surveillance. More-
over, crime is not seen as ‘determined’ by individual traits or social
pressures; offenders are not propelled into crime by forces outside of their
own control, but choose to commit crime, and therefore can be held
accountable for their actions. In short, situational crime prevention is
grounded in the traditions of classicism rather than biological, psycho-
logical, or social positivism, and just as the history of criminology can be
seen as a battle between these two competing visions, so too can the
history of crime prevention (Roshier 1989).
As Jock Young has argued (1994), in the post-war period (1945–1972)
the debate about crime and its control was largely dominated by what he
calls social democratic positivism. In this model it was assumed that crime
was a product of poverty and other forms of hardship and deprivation.
With the coming of the welfare state with the provision of free universal
health care and education, full employment polices, and a social security
safety net, it was often assumed that the major causes of crime would be
eradicated. Where crime still arose then rehabilitation programmes, aimed
at correcting the faults of inadequate psyches or faulty socialisation,
would mop up the residual problem cases. In this era, secondary and
tertiary strategies were in the ascendency.
But, as many now argue, history did not validate the beliefs of the social
democratic positivists. Throughout the 1950s and 1960s social conditions
improved, incomes rose, full employment was the norm, but crime, rather
than falling, continued to rise. It was not just faith in secondary crime
prevention that was undermined, but the rehabilitative ideal, embodied
in tertiary crime prevention strategies also came under attack. In the
mid-1970s several influential reports were published which showed that
rehabilitation programmes were largely ineffective (Martinson 1974;
Brody 1976; Folkard 1976). This also chimed with the changing political
climate; the New Right, championed by Margaret Thatcher in Britain and
Ronald Reagan in the US, combined economic liberalism, reduced public
expenditure and an emphasis on individual moral responsibility, with

148
CCTV and crime prevention: questions for criminology

populist law and order policies. In this context, rehabilitation could be


seen as absolving criminals from moral responsibility, and pandering to
the needs of offenders, while social intervention programmes, which
located the causes of crime in wider structural terms, could be neither
ideologically nor economically justified. Ideologically, individual moral
weakness was blamed for criminality, while economically the need to
reduce public expenditure would not permit such expensive rehabilitation
programmes.
The appeal of primary crime prevention strategies comes, then, not just
from their supposed efficacy, but also from their depoliticisation of the prob-
lem of crime. As Ron Clarke, one of the leading exponents of situational
crime prevention has noted, it relies ‘not on improving society or its in-
stitutions, but simply on reducing opportunities for crime’ (Clarke 1992: 4).
Situational crime prevention techniques do not raise awkward ques-
tions about the relationship between wider social processes and crime,
and exclude consideration of issues such as inequality, justice and fairness
and how these may contribute to crime. Thus for the New Right, com-
mitted as it was to a fundamental restructuring of economic and social
relations, which in the short term, at least, would inevitably result in mass
unemployment and a massive increase in inequality, situational crime
prevention could be seen as particularly attractive. Because of its emphasis
on free will, blame for crime could be located squarely at the door of the
individual ‘rational’ offender, rather than on structural forces. Moreover,
primary prevention does not necessarily entail large-scale public expendi-
ture programmes. Indeed, part of its great appeal is that the state can pass
on the costs of crime prevention to businesses, consumers, and private
citizens, who are urged to buy locks, bolts and alarms.
As we have seen, one of the core elements of situational crime preven-
tion strategies is increased surveillance, coupled with target hardening
and removal strategies. The introduction of CCTV seeks to influence the
decison-making of the ‘rational’ offender who, on calculating the risks,
will choose not to commit crime under the gaze of the cameras because
there will be a strong possibility of being caught. It is therefore primarily a
strategy based on deterrence, although, of course, even if it does not deter
it should presumably increase the chances of an offender being caught. It
is perhaps then the common sense simplicity of this logic, coupled with its
underlying ideological and political appeal, that accounts for the dramatic
rise in CCTV surveillance in Britain over the last decade.

The rise of CCTV

In Britain, at least in the 1990s, CCTV totally dominated the crime


prevention programme of the Home Office. Bulos and Sarno (1994) found

149
Introducing Criminology

that there were only two local authority schemes in operation in 1987. By
1994 the Home Office indicated there were 79 town centre schemes (Home
Office, 1994); by 1996 all the major cities with a population over 500,000
boasted city centre schemes, and there were in excess of 200 police and
local authority schemes operating in high streets and smaller towns
(Norris et al 1998: 255); by 1998 this had risen to at least 440 town centre
schemes (Goodwin et al 1998).
In financial terms, between 1994 and 1997, central government made
available £37 million to fund the introduction of CCTV schemes, but on the
condition that local authorities and private business also contributed an
equal amount. Indeed Goodwin et al calculated that some 78 per cent of
the Home Office crime prevention budget was committed to CCTV during
this time. Moreover, the trend does not appear to be slowing down, as in
1999 it was announced by central government that a further £170 million
would be made available to fund the introduction of new CCTV schemes
or to extend existing ones in town centres, car parks, residential
communities and other crime ‘hot spots’ (Painter and Tilley 1999: 2).
It may be thought that the rush to install CCTV during the 1990s was
based on a firm foundation of supporting research evidence to show that it
was effective. This was not so. CCTV was introduced in town centres, and
the government funded its expansion, prior to conducting any systematic
evaluation of its effectiveness in reducing crime in such locations. What
evidence did exist prior to 1994 came from small-scale evaluations on
systems in car parks (Poyner 1992), buses (Poyner 1988), housing estates
(Musheno et al 1978), football stadia (Hancox and Morgan 1975), and the
London Underground (Burrows 1979). As Short and Ditton note, the
results of these independent and competently conducted evaluations were
‘fairly contradictory regarding the effectiveness of CCTV as a crime
prevention method’ (Short and Ditton 1995: 11), with some initiatives
showing no effect (Musheno et al 1979), others suggesting high levels of
displacement, rather than an overall reduction (Burrows 1979), and others
showing clear reductions (Poyner 1988 and 1992).
However, between 1988 and 1992 the Conservative Government had
witnessed an almost unprecedented growth in recorded crime from just
under four million offences to just under six million; for the party of ‘law
and order’, this represented a major policy failure and a potential electoral
disaster. In early 1993 however, CCTV was thrust into the limelight by two
events. First, there was the tragic killing of the two-year-old toddler, Jamie
Bulger, as his abduction by two ten-year-olds was caught on camera.
Second, the two men responsible for planting a bomb outside the Harrods
department store in London were subsequently identfied from CCTV
footage. In the glare of national publicity to which CCTV was subjected in
the wake of the Bulger case, the few schemes that did exist boasted major
benefits from its introduction. It is hardly suprising that the beleaguered

150
CCTV and crime prevention: questions for criminology

Home Secretary should jump at this ‘silver bullet’ which, through its very
public introduction onto city streets, would visibly show the government
was doing something to stem the inexorable rise in recorded crime. As he
stated in May 1995:

CCTV catches criminals. It spots crimes, identifies law-breakers and


helps convict the guilty. The spread of this technology means that
more town centres, shopping precincts, business centres and car
parks around the country will become no-go areas for the criminal ...
CCTV is a wonderful technological supplement to the police.

However, the evidence for the Home Secretary’s belief in the ‘wonderful’
technology was not that of the professional and independent evaluator
but from ‘post hoc shoestring efforts by the untrained and self-interested
practitioner’ (Pawson and Tilley 1994). And as Pease has recently
observed, ‘for those exercising stewardship of public money, good
evidence about effects should be necessary before public money is spent,
although one is tempted to ask where rigorous standards went in the
headlong rush to CCTV deployment’ (Pease 1999: 53). Thus even though
hundreds of millions of pounds have been spent on CCTV over the last
decade, by business, local communities and central government, there are
still major questions about its effectiveness.

Does CCTV reduce crime? Methodological concerns

At first sight this would appear to be a simple question to ask and many
people probably think that they already know the answer. Indeed,
representatives of the police, politicians of all persuasions, and members
of the CCTV industry have consistently answered the question with a
resounding ‘yes’, and this belief has been endorsed by largely uncritical
and complacent media coverage (Norris and Armstrong 1999: chapter 4).
However, one of the key remits of any academic discipline is to challenge
taken-for-granted assumptions, and criminology has an obligation to
subject crime and its control to critical scrutiny. The first task in the process
is to analyse apparently simple questions and lay bare their underlying
assumptions in the hope that we might be able to answer them more
satisfactorily. To answer the question, ‘does CCTV reduce crime?’, it is
necessary to consider three crucial elements contained within it:
• what is meant by CCTV?
• what is meant by crime and how can it be measured?
• what is meant by a reduction in crime and what would constitute
satisfactory evidence of a reduction occurring?
151
Introducing Criminology

We will address each of these questions in turn.

What is meant by CCTV?


The first problem we must confront is: what exactly is CCTV? As Graham
(1998) has shown, CCTV is actually a very diverse phenomena, both
technically, organisationally and contextually. Technically, at its simplest a
CCTV system consists of a single static camera coupled directly to a
monitor by coaxial cable; these were the earliest CCTV systems installed in
many retail establishments from the 1960s onwards, and are still found
today in many newsagents and corner shops. A slightly more sophistica-
ted system might have a number of fixed cameras and be coupled to both
a monitor and a video recorder, enabling images of past events to be
scrutinised at a later date. This sort of system would be not untypical of
many that are found in small towns and villages throughout the United
Kingdom.
At a higher level of sophistication are systems that include pan, tilt and
zoom cameras (PTZ), which can be controlled from a central point and
used to track people and vehicles as they move through space, and zoom
in to take close-up pictures for the purposes of identification. Such high
level systems may link hundreds of cameras, both fixed and PTZ, allow for
time-lapse recording of signals from multiple video inputs, and display
the video images on a huge bank of monitors, which can be watched
generally but ‘pulled down’ to the operative’s dedicated monitor and
recorded in real time, if there is something of interest (see Constant and
Turnbull [1994] for a discussion of the technical aspects of CCTV).
It is not just in the level of technical sophistication that systems vary, but
in their organisational implementation. Systems vary in their staffing,
ownership, management and linkages. They may be staffed by police
officers, employees of private security companies, police civilian employ-
ees, or local authority employees. In operational terms some systems are
completely ‘unmanned’ and the tapes only reviewed after an incident
comes to light, while others are ‘manned’ twenty-four hours a day.
Systems also vary in their ownership and management; some are owned
and fully controlled by the local police, while others are owned, run and
housed by the local authority. In some systems the CCTV control room is
fully integrated (and housed) within the police command, control and
dispatch system, while others rely on technological linkages such as
telephone and monitors to link them to a dispatch capability.
Finally, the range of contexts in which CCTV systems are deployed is
enormous; city centres, urban high streets, market towns, and villages all
now boast CCTV systems. While city centre systems watch over largely
anonymous spaces inhabited mainly by busy commuters and pedestrians
merely ‘passing through’, village systems monitor a more stable and
intimate community with the watchers often knowing the personal
152
CCTV and crime prevention: questions for criminology

identities of those under the camera’s gaze. Moreover, CCTV has been
deployed in a variety of institutional settings, from schools to hospitals, to
football stadia and transport systems. In a recent initiative in Hull, CCTV
cameras are to be deployed in the back of taxi-cabs, in order to deter
loutish behaviour and fare evaders.
So, if we want to answer the question, ‘does CCTV reduce crime?’, we
need to be clear about what CCTV is. Clearly there is a huge variation in
technological and organisational arrangements between systems, and this
has important consequences for our ability to generalise about the
effectiveness of CCTV. This relates to what evaluators term the problem of
external validity. In the main, when researchers carry out a study they aim
to make claims that go beyond the single case of their experiment or study
so as to be able to generalise their findings to a wider community. Even if
researchers themselves are often wary about the applicability of their
findings to different settings, others may be much less hesitant.
As Jupp notes researchers have distinguished two types of external
validity, population validity and ecological validity. Population validity
refers to the extent to which the findings can be generalised to the wider
population, and ecological validity refers to the extent to which the
findings can be generalised to other contexts and settings (Jupp 1989: 55).
For instance, if a study showed that the introduction of CCTV reduced
crime by 16 per cent, we cannot simply assume that a different CCTV
system, deployed in a different place, targeting a different crime problem,
with a system of different technological sophistication would have the
same impact.

What is meant by crime and how can it be measured?


In asking the question ‘does CCTV reduce crime?’, we assume that there is
something called crime, or more accurately a crime rate, which is suscep-
tible to variation and that these variations can be accurately and reliably
measured. Crime prevention evaluations in general and CCTV evalua-
tions in particular have chosen to utilise ‘notifiable offences recorded by
the police’ as their measure of the crime rate. However, the relationship
between the crime rate, as represented by the crimes officially recorded by
the police and the ’real’ rate of criminal victimisation, is highly problem-
atic (see Coleman and Moynihan [1996] for a review of this issue).
To count as a crime by this definition, crimes have first to be reported to
the police by victims or witnesses; secondly, having been reported, they
have to be officially recorded by the police. However, as the 1997 British
Crime Survey (BCS) revealed, only half (44%) of offences on which it
collects information from victims were reported to the police, and there
was considerable variation in this figure between different offence types.
Whereas 97% of thefts of vehicles were reported to the police, only 57% of
robberies, 43% of thefts from vehicles and 35% of thefts from the person
153
Introducing Criminology

were reported (Mirrlees-Black et al 1998: 19). And we can see from Table 6.1
that not all of these were actually recorded by the police. Overall the BCS
suggests that only about half (54%) of all such offences reported to the
police are recorded, which means that the recorded crime figures only
account for a quarter (24%) of the underlying crime rate, although this
ranges from 84% in the case of motor vehicle theft to 10% for theft from the
person.
This has some highly significant implications for measuring changes to
the crime rate. This would be of little concern if there was an invariant
relationship over time between reporting and recording rates but this is
not the case. According to the BCS, between 1981 and 1997 the overall rate
of reporting BCS offences to the police has fluctuated between 36% and
49%, and between the years 1991, 1993 and 1995 the rate of reporting for
burglary from 73% to 68% to 66%. Similarly the rate of reporting theft of
and from vehicles has consistently reduced from 56% to 53% to 51%. In
Table 6.2 below we show the effect that changes in the public reporting rate
and police recording rate between the years 1991 and 1995 would have on
the trends in recorded crime.
In the context of CCTV, imagine a system being introduced to a mixed
residential and shopping area in early 1992, where the evaluation took as
its base-mark the recorded crime rate in 1991. These figures were then
compared with the figures for 1993 and 1995. If the trends revealed in the
British Crime Survey were replicated at the local level, regardless of the
impact of the CCTV system, the official police recorded crime statistics
would have shown a reduction in crime of 20%, merely because of changes
in reporting and recording practices. For the offences of burglary, vehicle
theft and bicycle theft reductions would have been 20%, 22% and 34%
respectively. Unless the impact of these changes had been taken into
account by the researchers, which they almost never are, the observed
reductions would have been attributed to the CCTV system. In other
words, the real rate of crime could have remained the same, CCTV having
no impact, and yet the evaluators would have certainly claimed that CCTV
was an unqualified success in reducing crime.

Table 6.1: Offences reported to and recorded by police in 1997

Offence % reported to police % of reported crime Overall % of crime


recorded by police recorded by police

All offences 44 54 24
Theft of vehicle 97 87 84
Robbery 57 30 17
Theft from vehicle 43 59 25
Theft from person 35 29 10

Source: Derived from Mirrlees-Black et al 1998: figures 4.2 and 4.3.

154
Table 6.2: Percentage change in British Crime Survey offences reported to and recorded by the police
1991, 1993, 1995

Offence 1991 1993 1995

% reported % reported % of total % reported % reported % of total % reported % reported % of total % reduction
recorded recorded recorded recorded recorded recorded 1991 to 1995

Burglary 73 62 45 68 60 41 66 55 36 20
All vehicle theft 56 65 36 53 60 32 51 55 28 22
Bicycle theft 69 59 41 72 48 35 63 44 27 34
All BCS offences 49 60 29 47 55 26 46 50 23 20

Source: Derived from Mirrlees-Black et al 1998: figures A4.1 and A4.4.


CCTV and crime prevention: questions for criminology

155
Introducing Criminology

Ideally then, evaluators should utilise a measure of crime which is


independent of the officially recorded police crime figures, preferably a
local victimisation survey conducted before the CCTV system is intro-
duced and then repeated twelve months and twenty-four months after
installation. This would enable a more accurate assessment to be made of
the impact on the real rate of criminal victimisation, and give an indication
of whether changes were sustained over time. In reality this is rarely, if
ever, done, since it would require that the plans for the evaluation were in
place at least eighteen months before the scheme, and involve consider-
able expense in collecting the data. In the fast-moving, and financially
constrained, world of local politics it is unlikely that system promoters
would agreed to hold back the introduction of their system for at least a
year, just for the sake of the evaluation, and agree to finance three costly
surveys.

The concept of reduction and its measurement


The question ‘does CCTV reduce crime?’, implies that we expect a
decrease; however, it is perfectly sensible to suggest that for certain
offences, particularly those which rely on predominantly police-initiated
activities, there may be an increase in recorded crime. If the cameras allow
the police to see and find evidence of crimes which would have previously
gone unreported, such as drug dealing, drunk driving and fights between
young men, then rather than a reduction in such recorded crime, we will
see an increase. This adds weight to our argument that, in order to interpet
a change in the officially recorded crime statistics as indicative of a ‘real’
change in the incidence of crime, researchers need to be aware of any
changes in police practices and public reporting behaviour. Moreover, this
is compounded by four other possible threats to validity of the crime
figures which would need to be addressed by evaluators who wanted to
make claims about the effectiveness of CCTV on the basis of changes to the
crime rate (however measured). These threats are:
• displacement
• changes to the area under surveillance
• reactivity
• other fluctuations and trends in crime rates unrelated to the influence of
CCTV
We will discuss each in turn.

Displacement
One of the first problems in assessing any crime prevention initiative is
that while it may appear that a number of crimes have been prevented, in

156
CCTV and crime prevention: questions for criminology

fact they may have merely been displaced to another area or committed at
other times or in different ways. Criminologists have identified six types
of displacement associated with crime prevention initiatives (Barr and
Pease 1990; Gabor 1978).

• temporal displacement occurs where the offence is merely committed at a


different time. For instance, CCTV may be effective at deterring crime
during the day when visibility is good, but not at night when it is
hindered by darkness and the generally low luminosity of street
lighting. Temporal displacement would occur if perpetrators switched
to committing their crimes at night when there was less chance of
detection.
• tactical displacement occurs when the method of comitting the offence
changes. For example, if cars are fitted with better security features and
stronger locks offenders may no longer break into cars and ‘hot wire’
them, but wait until the driver has opened the door and grab their keys.
• target displacement occurs when the same crime is committed against
different targets, such as if housebreakers refrain from burgling houses
with visible alarms but continue to burgle houses without alarms in the
the same area.
• functional displacement occurs where offenders may be deterred from
committing one type of crime but merely switch to another type. For
example, the presence of cameras may make street robbers switch from
‘mugging’ (which is a highly visible act) to ‘pick-pocketing’ which is
less easy to detect.
• geographical displacement occurs where the same crimes are committed
in a different geographical location. For example, the installation of a
CCTV system covering town centre car parks may lead to car crime
being displaced to residential side streets away from the cameras’ gaze.

• perpetrator displacement occurs where the crime is displaced from one


offender to another. This may occur with crimes such as drug dealing or
prostitution, where if one offender is arrested another may be ready to
take their place.

In the case of CCTV it is predominantly functional and geographical


displacement that is most likely to occur and a number of studies have
found strong evidence of displacement taking place. Skinns’ evaluation of
the Doncaster CCTV system, for example, found clear evidence of geo-
graphical displacement, for although there was a reduction in crime in the
town centre streets of 16% this was offset by the increase in crime in the
surrounding townships by 31%. When these were taken together the

157
Introducing Criminology

overall reduction in crime was only 6%. (Skinns 1998: 185). Similarly in
Birmingham, the evaluation by Brown (1995) produced strong evidence
for geographical displacement for two different offence types, ‘street
robbery and theft from the person’ and ‘theft from a motor vehicle’. In the
case of the former, Brown concluded that:

Since the installation of cameras, the incidence of these types of


offences in areas surrounding zone A has increased sharply, and by
the end of the study period, the number of offences per month is over
three times as high as when the cameras were installed.
(Brown, 1995: 35)

In Sutton the installation of the cameras led to a marked change in the


pattern of thefts in the town centre, so that while thefts on streets declined
by 7%, thefts inside commercial premises increased by 30% (Sarno, 1996).
This would suggest that there is evidence for geographic, tactical and
target displacement as it would appear that offenders switched locations,
changed targets from pedestrians to in-store customers, and switched
from purse-snatching to stealth thefts of handbags.
There are, however, serious methodological problems involved in
measuring displacement. In particular, it is very difficult in practice to
distinguish ‘displacement’ areas from ‘control’ areas. As Ditton (personal
communication) has noted: ‘The usual working distinction is superficially
geographical: that is, the adjacent area is the displacement one, and one
some way away is the control one.’ The underlying assumption is that
offenders are very geographically static, which in the age of the motor car
and metro is not very convincing. Crime could easily be displaced to areas
selected as ‘control’ ones, making invalid the usual assumption that such
areas have been unaffected by the introduction of CCTV.

Changes to the area under surveillance


One of the key problems facing the evaluator is that in the real world,
unlike the laboratory of the natural scientist, it is very difficult to hold
other variables constant until the evaluation is complete. This is common-
ly refered by statisticians as the problem of history, which Smith defines as
follows:

Over the time span of data collection many events occur in addition
to the study’s independent variable. The history factor refers to the
possibility that any one of the events rather than the hypothesised
independent variable might have caused the observed changes in the
dependent variable.
(1981: 334)

In the real world then, it is likely that while the evaluation of CCTV is
158
CCTV and crime prevention: questions for criminology

being undertaken, other changes are occurring to the town centre. For
example, in Birmingham pedestrianisation was introduced to key areas of
the city centre at the same time as the cameras were installed (Brown 1995:
37), perhaps attracting more people, but fewer cars, into the town centre,
and this in turn may have had a completely independent impact on the
crime rate. As Skinns notes in relation to Doncaster:

In the real world it is not possible for evaluators to demand that


nothing else changes in the experimental area. And indeed, in
[Doncaster] there were changes in policing styles, particularly in the
town centre and in the outlying areas; changes in parking arrange-
ments in the town centre (restricting the number of cars parked on
the street); and finally the growth of out-of-town commercial and
entertainment centres.
(1998: 185)

What impact these changes had is of course difficult to assess, but one
might speculate that if more people are going out of town to shop and to
be entertained, there might be fewer offences in the town centre.

Reactivity
A problem for all evaluators is the extent to which the very act of
evaluation itself influences the results of the study. This is generally
referred to as reactivity and can be defined as ‘any time participants
suspect or know they are being observed, experimented with, or tested
there is a chance that their behaviour may be modified by the measuring
instrument’ (Smith 1981: 335). In the case of the newly installed scheme in
Windsor and Eton it was revealed that officers would be redeployed from
other areas to cope with the expected increase in workload that would
arise from the introduction of CCTV in the town centres. The presence of
the extra officers patrolling the town centre may well have had a signifi-
cant deterrent effect on crime in its own right, thus making any claims
about the success of the CCTV system impossible to disentangle from the
effect of the increased police presence (Norris and Armstrong 1999).

Other fluctuations in the crime rate


Criminologists have for some time been aware that at the local level, say a
police beat or a town centre, there are often large fluctuations in the levels
of recorded crime, regardless of the influence of any specific crime preven-
tion measure: Paul Ekblom has argued convincingly that any reductions at
the local level have to be judged against these quasi-random fluctuations
in crimes rates. Ekblom analysed recorded street crime in 19 police beats in
the Metropolitan police area between January and June 1989 and the same
period in 1990; many beats showed massive increases and decreases over

159
Introducing Criminology

the previous year. For instance, beat 1 incurred more than a 50% reduction
in recorded crime while beat 2 had an increase of over 70% and similarly
beat 14 enjoyed a 60% reduction while beat 16 showed an increase of over
80%. There can also be fluctuations for total recorded crime within the
same beat. For instance in one police beat in the West Midlands, Ekblom
showed that recorded crime fluctuated over a three-year period from over
90 crimes per month to less than 20 (Ekblom 1992: 39).
These variations mean that if one had been measuring the impact of a
new crime prevention measure introduced in June 1988 and compared the
recorded crime figures for one year before and one year after implementa-
tion there would have been an impressive reduction by about one-third,
regardless of the measure. On the other hand if the measure had been
introduced in June 1989 there would have been a disappointing 25%
increase in recorded crime (derived from Ekblom 1992: Figure 2). As Tilley
has argued, ‘these wide natural fluctuations in local rates, especially in a
small area over a limited period ... make interpreting real effects as against
pseudo-random short-term changes very difficult’ (Tilley 1998: 142).
Given such fluctuations, if in the years preceeding the introduction of
CCTV crime had risen exceptionally in an area, one might naturally expect
a fall. Interestingly, given that the rush to CCTV was funded by a
competitive bidding process, it may well be that local partnerships only
put forward areas with ‘abnormally’ high and rapidly increasing crime
rates, ones which were likely eventually to show a decline, regardless of
any crime prevention initiative (see Ditton and Short 1999: 216–7).
It is not just small-scale local random variations that evaluators have to
contend with. There are also wider background changes to crime rates
against which any changes have to be judged. For instance, if nationally
crime trends are on a downward path then it is important isolate the
impact of CCTV from the general trend. It is perhaps arguable that one
reason for the widespread belief in the efficacy of CCTV was that the rapid
growth of the number of CCTV systems (between 1993 and 1997) occurred
at precisely the same time as the only sustained fall in recorded crime since
the 1950s.
At the more local level, such changes are also important to take into
account when judging the efficacy of CCTV: if crime falls faster in the areas
not under the watchful eye of the cameras then surely one would need to
be cautious about attributing the fall in the area under surveillance to the
impact of CCTV. This point is almost entirely overlooked by politicians,
the media, and local advocates of CCTV. For them a reduction is a
reduction full-stop, and must be attributable to the effect of CCTV. If we
take the example of Sutton, the evaluation conducted by researchers from
the University of the South Bank showed a reduction in total recorded
crime in the area covered by the cameras of 13%. However, in the police
division as a whole it fell by 17% and across the borough it reduced by 30%

160
CCTV and crime prevention: questions for criminology

(Sarno 1996: 22). On the face of it, it would appear that rather than
facilitating a reduction in crime, the introduction of CCTV hindered its
reduction. However as Norris and Armstrong have argued, in the face of a
reduction, few are prepared to accept that it may not be attributable to
CCTV:

The London Evening Standard argued in an editorial on the negative


results of the Sutton evaluation that, since the findings did not accord
with that ’older discipline called common sense’ and ‘crime pro-
fessionals consider ... [cameras] ... critically important in identifying
and deterring criminals’, the authors must be wrong. Indeed the
headline declared, in defiance of the study, ‘Why cameras deter
crime’ (Evening Standard, 3 January 1996). This approach was echoed
by a spokesman for the Association of Chief Police Officers (ACPO)
who argued that ‘it is impossible to prove one way or another
whether the cameras work’ but it was ‘common sense’ and ‘patently
obvious that if someone is going to put a brick through a window
they won’t do it in front of the cameras’.
(Norris and Armstrong, 1999: 205)

What the above discussion has highlighted is that for the criminological
evaluator, the simple statement that ‘after CCTV was introduced crime
reduced by 20%’ cannot be treated at face value and needs to be inter-
preted in the light of the various threats to validity we have outlined above.
The question of validity is absolutely central to the evaluator’s effort, since
validity refers to the ‘degree to which the researcher has measured what he
or she set out to measure’ (Smith 1981: 333) and the extent to which the
researchers are able to assert that the changes in the dependent variable
(the crime rate) are caused by the introduction of the independent variable
(CCTV) and not by other factors. This means that researchers must active-
ly seek, through the design of their evaluations, to rule out alternative
explanations.

Experimental design
The strongest form of research design to rule out alternative explanations
is by evaluators mimicking the methodology of the natural scientist and
utilising the experimental method. Classically this entails comparing
two groups: an experimental group and a control group. Ideally, the
units which comprise both groups should be chosen at random, since
this eliminates systematic bias or error. Once the two groups are allocated,
both groups are observed and measured before the experimental variable
is introduced to the experimental group, while the control group is
left untouched. Finally both groups are measured again and the results

161
Introducing Criminology

Table 6.3: Classic experimental design

Time 1 Time 2 Time 3 Time 4

Group 1 pre-test (O1) experimental post-test (O2)


treatment (X)
Group 2 pre-test (O3) no treatment post-test (O4)

compared. Any changes in the two groups are then compared and if
the results are significantly different then it is legitimate to infer that it is
the introduction of the experimental variable which caused the changes.
The importance of the control group is that is allows us to see if any
changes that did take place occurred ‘naturally’, that is not as a result of
the introduction of the experimental variable. As Campbell and Stanley
(1963: 13–16) have shown, if the procedures have been carried out
correctly, the threats to internal validity discussed above may all be ruled
out.
Of course, this strict control can only really be achieved under
laboratory conditions; however, in the social sciences, there are many who
advocate that researchers should at least strive towards the ideal of the
classic experiment by approximating, as far as possible, experimental
conditions in the field. These are generally referred to as quasi-
experimental methods which, as Jupp notes, have a long pedigree in
criminology and are often referred to as ‘field experiments’ or ‘reforms as
experiments’ and have been used to evaluate a variety of new initiatives
such as the most effective regimes for the control and treatment offenders
(see Jupp 1989), neighbourhood watch (Bennett 1990) and police patrol
strategies (Kelling 1974).
In the case of CCTV, one of the more imaginative quasi-experiments
was conducted by Beck and Willis (1999), who wanted to examine the
effect of introducing CCTV systems in the retail sector to prevent stock
loss, mainly through shop-lifting. The study aimed to assess the impact of
different types of CCTV systems on levels of stock loss in fifteen stores of a
large national UK fashion retailer. The research used a before-and-after
experimental design involving the following:

• a stock-take being carried out in each store before CCTV was installed.
• CCTV systems being introduced into each store. Three types of system
were introduced to look at the differential impact (if any) of systems
with varying levels of technical sophistication.
• a stock-take being carried out in each store after CCTV was installed to
calculate the number of units stolen and their value. The stock-takes

162
CCTV and crime prevention: questions for criminology

Table 6.4: Quasi-experimental design as used by Beck and Willis (1999)

Time 1 Time 2 Time 3 Time 4 Time 5

Group 1 pre-test experimental post-test 1 post-test 2


treatment

Group 2 pre-test experimental post-test 1 post-test 2


treatment

Group 3 pre-test experimental post-test 1 post-test 2


treatment

were carried out twice: 13 weeks after installation and then 28 weeks
after. This enabled the researchers to assess the impact in both the short
and the medium term.

There are a number of key features which distinguish this quasi-experi-


mental design from the classic experimental method. Firstly, the three
groups, which comprised in total 15 stores, were chosen from a total of 180
retail outlets of one fashion store chain. However, one of the first prin-
ciples of experimental design has been sacrificed because they do not
appear to have been chosen at random. This means that their selection
may have been biased and in some way produced a set of stores that are
atypical of the all the stores across the country, thus limiting the generalis-
ability of the findings.
Second, there is no control group, i.e. a sample of stores not subject to
experimental treatment. This is important because it is possible that there
may have been a general reduction in shop-lifting nationally, perhaps
caused by the courts getting particularly tough on shop-lifters at the same
time and therefore providing a greater deterrent. Without a control group
it is impossible to rule this out as an alternative explanation.
Third, and this is one of the study’s great strengths, by including three
types of CCTV system of different levels of technical sophistication the
authors have implicitly recognised that CCTV is not a homogeneous
phenomenon. Therefore the research design can inform us about whether
different types of system have different impacts. In this way, the study
mirrors the classic medical experiment where three groups of patients are
given different dosages of the same drug to see which is the most effective
dose. The patients are examined before the onset of the drug treatment and
at three months and six months after the prescription, in order to examine
the short- and medium-term impacts.
Fourth, and this is another strength of the study, it utilises both a short-
and medium-term measure of stock loss, thus enabling comparisons
between the two and giving a better indication of long-term trends.
163
Introducing Criminology

What then did the study find? In the short term, based on the figures
after 13 weeks, so far as the theft prevention possibilities of CCTV are
concerned, the findings were impressive. Taking all the stores together, the
average number of units lost per week fell from 72 to 52, a 28% reduction.
In total, for the 15 stores in the study, if this trend continued there would
have been savings of nearly £90,000 per year. Given that the total cost of
introducing CCTV to these stores was £180,000, it would take two years
for the savings made to pay for the capital costs of installation. In business
terms, this can be seen as an adequate but not spectacular return on the
investment but one that is probably worthwhile financially given that the
savings might be expected to continue in the third and fourth years of
operation.
But this projection is on the basis of figures collected after just three
months of operation and criminologists are well aware that the effect of
crime prevention measures often degrades over time. This frequently
seems to be due to the fact that when new schemes are introduced, there is
often an initial blaze of publicity which enhances any deterrent effects.
Over time, as potential offenders either forget or become blasé about the
new measures, they will no longer be deterred. Moreover, the professional
or persistent offenders may gradually adapt their techniques to continue
to avoid detection. For these reasons it is important that assessment about
impacts be taken over longer rather than shorter time periods.
In this study, while the second stock-take only occurred after six
months, it still allows some assessment of the medium-term effect and
whether the impact has degraded. In the twelve stores that had a six-
month stock-take, the average number of units lost per week before
the introduction of the CCTV systems was 64; six months after installation
the number had reduced, but only by one to 63. In financial terms,
this represented an average reduction in weekly loss of merely £4 and on
this basis it would take an average of 58 years to recoup the capital out-
lay.
Overall, and in the medium term, it would appear that CCTV is not a
cost-effective measure of reducing stock loss and does little to prevent the
crime of shop-lifting.
However, there is a final twist to this tale, arising from the fact that this
rather negative finding is based on the aggregated results from different
systems. The original experimental design, it will be recalled, included the
introduction of three different systems of varying degrees of technical
sophistication. At the lowest level this included a CCTV display monitor at
the entrances to the store to alert people to CCTV, twelve dummy cameras,
and no recording or monitoring facilities; the medium-level system had
entrance display monitors, between six and twelve static colour cameras,
the facility both to record and monitor the images from the cameras, but no
provision for permanent monitoring; the high-level system had entrance

164
CCTV and crime prevention: questions for criminology

display monitors, between two and four pan, tilt and zoom cameras,
between eight and twelve static colour cameras, the facility to both record
and monitor the images from the cameras, and the provision of permanent
staff to continuously monitor the screens.
The aggregate results mask considerable variation in the impact of
different systems since the high-level stores showed ‘an impressive
reduction of 26%, whilst there was an increase of 32% in medium-level
stores and an increase of 9% in low-level stores’ (Beck and Willis 1999: 260).
In financial terms the results were as follows:

For high-level systems with an average weekly reduction in loss of


£178 set against a capital expenditure of £24,000, the pay-back period
was now 2.6 years (135 weeks). For the medium- and low-level
systems, however, the pay-back period was non-existent; it could not
be calculated because the average weekly reduction in loss had
disappeared altogether.
(Beck and Willis, 1999: 261)

The strength of this study is that it allows us to give clear advice to the
financially motivated retailer, concerned with the bottom line of profit-
ability: ‘If you are going to install a CCTV system, it needs to be a
sophisticated one that is permanently monitored, otherwise your expendi-
ture will be greater than your savings’. Even then, CCTV does not offer a
magic bullet to the problems of stock loss and it will still take over two-
and-a-half years to recover the investment. Moreover this does not include
the costs of monitoring and running the high-level system, which on a
conservative estimate would be in the region of £12,000 a year. If this is
included, it would take nearly five years for the system to recover its costs
and the hard-headed business person might decide that with such a slow
rate of return, it might be more rational to just accept the losses!

Does CCTV reduce crime in town centres?


The evaluation evidence

To date there have been thirteen independently conducted ‘quasi-experi-


mental’ evaluations which can be used to inform our judgement as to the
effectiveness of CCTV in reducing town centre crime.* Collectively, these

*These studies have been conducted in Airdrie (Ditton and Short 1998; Short and Ditton
1996), Birmingham (Brown 1995), Brighton (Squires and Measor 1996, 1997), Burgess Hill
(Squires 1998c), Burnley (Armitage, Smyth and Pease 1999), Crawley (Squires 1998b),
Doncaster (Skinns 1998), East Grinstead (Squires 1998a) Glasgow (Ditton and Short 1999),
Ilford (Squires 1998d), Kings Lynn (Brown 1995), Newcastle (Brown 1995), and Sutton (Sarno
1996).

165
Introducing Criminology

studies represent the only reliable data on the effectiveness of CCTV in


town centres, since their findings are based on a minimum level of
methodological adequacy which rule out some of the major threats to
internal validity.

• They all utilise before-and-after measures, based on an analysis of


police recorded crime figures. In all cases this is not just by measuring
two distinct points of time but by a form of trend analysis, either rolling
averages or regression analysis. This enables the impact of both random
fluctuations and wider long-term trends in crime rates to be addressed,
both of which might spuriously influence the results.
• They all utilise some form of control group. This is rather different from
the classic experimental control since none of the studies used another,
similar town without CCTV as a comparison. However, by separating
out the area under surveillance and comparing it to the immediate
surrounding area and the wider area, this in effect creates a form of
control because one can compare the changes in the rate between areas
with CCTV and those without.
• They all recognised the issue of displacement and attempted to assess
the extent to which crime was simply moved from areas with cameras
to areas without cameras.
• None of the studies treat crime as merely an aggregate category, but
examine changes in the recorded crime rate for different offence types.

Some of the threats still remain:

• The problem of reactivity is rarely addressed, although the main threat


would be if the police changed their practices in a way that influenced
the results of the study. In the absence of any data suggesting that they
did, we will assume that reactivity is not a particular problem.
• The problem of changes to the area under surveillance occurring during
the time of the evaluation, which may also have impacted on the crime
rate, is only addressed by two of the studies. Again, in the absence of
any data suggesting that there were such changes, we shall assume that
this was not a particular problem.
• General changes to reporting and recording practices. Only one study
explicitly mentions changes to recording practices that may have
influenced the data. But, more importantly, only two of the studies
utilise before-and-after victimisation surveys which would allow us to
see if there had been a change in the ‘real’ rate of criminal victimisation,
rather than just a change in police recorded crime data.

166
CCTV and crime prevention: questions for criminology

The findings
In Burnley, Armitage et al (1999) found a reduction of 25% sustained over
two years. A decrease was found for every offence type measured by the
study; importantly, the fact that the reductions were sustained over a
period of two years indicated that they were not merely the result of quasi-
random fluctuations in the crime rate. There was no evidence of displace-
ment and some evidence of a diffusion of benefits. In crime prevention
terms this is undoubtedy a success; however, as we shall see, no other
study has found such consistent and positive results.
In Airdrie (Short and Ditton 1996) there was an overall reduction of
crime of 21%, which the research demonstrated was greater than one
would expect on the basis of the downward trends in the surrounding
area. The reductions were sustained over a two-year period. However,
unlike in Burnley, there were significant differences in changes to recorded
crime levels for different offences. A number of offence categories showed
increases, such as drug offences, low-level public order offences and
minor traffic violations, while crimes of dishonesty, such as housebreaking
and theft of and from motor vehicles showed a dramatic reduction of 48%.
Since these crimes of dishonesty account for about 40% of overall recorded
crime, reducing them by nearly half more than offsets the rise in other
offence types. Moreover, as the authors state, increases in these offence
categories ‘are not necessarily indicative of the failure of CCTV... and
increases in drug offences may reflect the surveillance ability of CCTV to
detect crimes that might otherwise have gone unnoticed. The same could
be said of “breach of the peace” offences, and minor traffic violations’
(Ditton and Short 1999: 206). The researchers found no evidence of
functional or geographical displacement and no evidence of a diffusion of
benefits.
These success stories are paralleled by the findings from Newcastle and
Kings Lynn (Brown 1995). In Newcastle, for example, although Brown
does not provide figures for the decrease in recorded crime as a whole, he
showed reductions in the major offence categories of burglary (–57%),
criminal damage (–34%), theft of and from motor vehicles (–49%). The
reductions were greater in the CCTV area than in the control areas. There
was no evidence of displacement but some of diffusion of benefits, and
there was some evidence that for motor vehicle crime the effects were
fading over time.
However, these rather unequivocal success stories have to be measured
against rather more mixed findings. Skinns’ evaluation of Doncaster
showed a 16% reduction which initially would seem to make the scheme
an unequivocal success. However, this reduction was offset by a
statistically significant increase for nearly all major offence categories in
the outlying townships. There was also evidence, particularly for burglary,
of a diffusion of benefits to the areas immediately surrounding the

167
Introducing Criminology

scheme. Overall, when both diffusion of benefits and displacement were


taken into account the overall reduction was only 6%. Moreover, in the
town centre, although there were reductions in recorded offences for
burglary (–25%), criminal damage (–32%), and shoplifting (–11%), all these
reductions are what would have been expected on the basis of pre-existing
trends; the only reductions which remained significant were for theft of
and from motor vehicles.
Similarly mixed evidence of displacement and/or increases in some
categories of recorded crime has been found in Ilford (Squires 1998d) and
Brighton (Squires and Measor 1996). Moreover, as Phillips points out, the
evaluations carried out by Squires in the towns of East Grinstead, Crawley
and Burgess Hill (Squires 1998a, b, c) ‘reported reductions, over and above
those in control areas, only for criminal damage’ (Phillips 1999: 134).
Other town centre studies have found CCTV to have no overall impact.
In Birmingham (Brown 1995: 46), there was a ‘failure of the camera
systems to reduce directly overall crime levels’. The only offence type that
showed a sustained but small reduction was theft of motor vehicles.
Robbery and assault with wounding increased marginally, while theft
from motor vehicles increased dramatically. Moreover, there was strong
evidence of both functional and geographical displacement.
These negative findings were repeated in Glasgow (Ditton et al 1999).
When existing trends were taken into account total recorded crime
actually rose by 9% after the cameras were installed. Again there was
variation in offence type with increases for crimes of dishonesty (+23%)
and indecency (+17%), whereas crimes involving serious violence (–22%),
vandalism (–8%), and motoring offences (–12%) showed a decrease. A
similar story is found in Sutton (Sarno 1996), where crimes fell further and
faster in the areas surrounding the CCTV system and the division as a
whole, and there was evidence of tactical displacement.
If we now return to our original question, ‘does CCTV reduce crime?’
we see that the criminological evidence is far from straightforward: the
effects are neither universal or consistent. There is evidence for CCTV
having a sustained and dramatic reductive effect in some areas, while
having a negligible impact in others. When looking at individual offence
types the picture is also unclear; for instance in Burnley and Ilford crimes
of violence decreased while in Birmingham and Brighton they increased.
Similarly in Airdrie, crimes of dishonesty decreased, while in Glasgow
they increased. Evidence of displacement was found in Doncaster and
Burgess Hill, but not in Burnley or Brighton
If we accept that the contradictory findings of these studies are not
simply a result of methodological artifacts, and actually represent a ‘real’
measure of the incidence of criminal victimisation in the areas under
study, then we can answer the question, ‘does CCTV reduce crime?’ with
both a ‘yes’ and a ‘no’. Of course for the local politician or police chief

168
CCTV and crime prevention: questions for criminology

wanting to know whether CCTV will reduce crime in their area, this is
hardly a useful reply. But it does invite us to ask rather different questions.
If CCTV did reduce crime in Burnley, why did it not reduce crime in
Glasgow? If we can answer this question, then we will be in better position
to predict whether CCTV will work in a given locale and not in others.
However, this requires a radically different methodological approach to
the one typically adopted by evaluators of crime prevention measures; this
approach, developed by Pawson and Tilley, is termed realistic evaluation
and it is to a consideration of this that we now turn.

Realistic evaluation

The sort of mixed findings that we have described for CCTV evaluations
should come as no surprise to crime prevention specialists. As Tilley (1998:
143) has noted, whenever the results of the evaluation studies are com-
pared, the results are almost always inconsistent and contradictory. For
Pawson and Tilley (1997), this considerably undermines the utility of
evaluation studies for practitioners. This is because the focus of evalua-
tions has been almost solely on outcomes (does the crime rate change?)
rather than considering the processes, or ‘mechanisms’ which might
account for the changes. The point has been forcefully reiterated by Gill
and Turbin in the context of crime prevention in the business sector, which
wishes to use the research as the basis for its security policy:
There is no guarantee that the results of one study will have any rele-
vance for a different location or context. The common sense observa-
tion that what has an impact in site A may not necessarily have an
impact in site B has, to a large extent, been ignored by previous
research that focuses largely on collecting figures to show whether
the measure has worked at all. The main issue is not so much
whether the measure worked but rather how it did so, conversely,
why it failed to work when logic indicated that it should, or as
Pawson and Tilley state, ‘what works, for whom and in what
circumstance’.
(Gill and Turbin 1999: 181)
Ironically, it is the emphasis on the quasi-experimental design by social
science evaluators which is partially to blame for this. The focus of these
designs has generally been to determine whether a specific measure
reduced crime in a specific context, and by utilising a properly constructed
experimental design this question can be answered. But what it does not
tell us is why the measure had the effect that it did. Realistic evaluation
refocuses attention on the processes that produce the particular outcomes
rather than just on the outcomes themselves. For Pawson and Tilley this

169
Introducing Criminology

requires evaluators to concern themselves with three issues: the context,


mechanisms and outcomes.

Context
Context refers to the specific features of the the particular scheme being
evaluated; this requires detailed description by evaluators and an analysis
as to how these features may impact on the outcome of the study. For
instance, consideration needs to be given to: the level of technological
sophistication of the system; the organisation of the system and how it is
integrated with deployment practice; the physical and social make-up of
the area; the patterns of use of the area and the pattern and incidence of
crime in an area.
By explicitly detailing the contexts, not only will this enable more
systematic comparison between different evaluations but it will also
facilitate an understanding of the particular mechanisms which are
triggered by different contexts.

Mechanisms
In the context of CCTV, Pawson and Tilley (1994 and 1997) and Tilley
(1998), have identified a range of potential mechanisms which may be
triggered. These include:

• Effective deployment CCTV may enable more effective deployment of


security guards/police thus deterring potential offenders by a more
targeted patrol presence on the street.
• Nosey parker CCTV may increase ‘natural surveillance’ through
increased usage of an area and thus increase the risk that offenders will
be caught.
• Active citizen CCTV may increase confidence of members of the public
to intervene, if they believe the situation is being observed and police
back-up will follow.
• You’ve been framed CCTV may generally increase potential offenders’
fears that they will be seen, caught and shamed or punished, or moved
on for misbehaviour or unwanted behaviour.
• Caught in the act CCTV may help catch offenders, who may then be
stopped, removed and punished, therefore both preventing the present
offence and deterring the individual offender from committing future
ones.
• Appeal to the cautious The presence of CCTV cameras and their
associated publicity may remind potential victims to be more cautious
in areas covered, thus lessening the opportunities for crime.
170
CCTV and crime prevention: questions for criminology

Clearly, in any context one or more of the mechanisms could be operating


to reduce crime. But the chance that any mechanism will be triggered is
largely determined by context. For instance, for the ‘You’ve been framed’
mechanism to deter potential offenders from committing crime requires
them to be aware that the cameras are potentially watching them. In
Glasgow, however, one year after the installation of the cameras, ‘only
between a quarter and a third of the ambulatory population were even
aware of their existence’ (Ditton and Short 1999: 216), whereas in Brighton
87% of those in the town centre were aware of the system (Squires and
Measors 1996). Thus the difference in the effectiveness of the two systems
may be related to the extent to which the specific context differentially
triggered the deterrence mechanism: this can only be operative if people
are aware of the system.

Outcomes
We can see that while standard evaluations have been concerned with a
single outcome, the change to the recorded crime rate, realistic evaluation
would be concerned with multiple outcomes. For example: what is the
level of public awareness of the system? Has CCTV changed the pattern of
usage of the city centre? Have deployments to incidents increased? Have
more people been arrested? and so on. All of these are, in a sense,
intermediate outcomes which will have an effect on the impact of CCTV.
And it is only by measuring these that we can can start to unpack why
CCTV has the effects that it does. For Pawson and Tilley, realistic evalua-
tion requires that researchers explicitly hypothesize which mechanisms
will be triggered in any given crime prevention context. These hypotheses
should then ‘frame the requisite data and research strategies, and thus call
upon a range of evidence entirely different from the standard compari-
sons’ (1997: 80).

It should be clear from the above discussion that the criminological


evidence relating to the effectiveness of CCTV in reducing crime does not
support the almost exponential increase in cameras on British streets as a
crime prevention measure. But perhaps this is to miss the point: the
introduction of CCTV was never dependent on it being effective. As
Webster has argued, it was more about its symbolic potential to show that
politicians at both national and local levels were responsive to citizens’
concerns about crime, and were actively doing something about them
(Webster 2000).
So far we have concentrated extensively on the methodological issues
raised by criminologists’ attempts to determine whether CCTV reduces
crime. We would justify this selective attention by arguing that issues of
effectiveness have largely dominated the the criminological and political
agenda. However, as Hughes has argued, this focus, which is mirrored in
171
Introducing Criminology

the crime prevention literature as whole, is based in a tradition of


administrative criminology which has been concerned with:

the development of a body of technical and pragmatic knowledge


aimed at helping those in power to put their ideas into practice
through technical evaluation ... . This ‘technicist’ orientation thus
sees crime as a technical and practical problem needing an admini-
strative and apolitical ‘solution’. This ‘administrative’ aim has been
prioritised over the broader critical questioning of the main
assumptions, principles and social consequences of the different
approaches to crime prevention associated with the state and
(increasingly) the private sector. As a consequence, there has been an
absence of a critical body of work on the wider politics of the
phenomenon.
(Hughes 1998: 4)

CCTV, discrimination and social exclusion

In the portrayal of CCTV by the popular media and the rhetoric of


politicians CCTV is ‘the friendly eye in the sky’, benignly and evenly
watching over the citizenry who ‘if they have nothing to hide, have
nothing to fear’. However, in busy urban streets CCTV operators are, of
course, presented with potentially thousands of different ‘suspects’
during the course of a day, and operators have to select for closer attention
those incidents and persons which may be indicative of criminality. This
issue informed the research by Norris and Armstrong, who set out to
explore the processes by which the myriad of images entering a CCTV
system are interpreted by CCTV operators to determine who should be
targeted for extended and intensive surveillance. As they show, CCTV
targeting is not an equal opportunity phenomenon. They conclude:

The sum total of these individual discretionary judgements


produces, as we have shown, a highly differentiated pattern of
surveillance leading to a massively disproportionate targeting of
young males, particularly if they are black or visibly identifiable as
having subcultural affiliations. As this differentiation is not based on
objective behavioural and individualised criteria, but merely on
being categorised as part of a particular social group, such practices
are discriminatory.
(Norris and Armstrong 1999: 150)

This has some major criminological implications, since if one social group
is being targeted disproportionately, then this will have the effect of

172
CCTV and crime prevention: questions for criminology

increasing their criminalisation as more of their potential offences are


revealed, while simultaneously lessening the criminalisation of other
groups. This point is starkly reinforced by Ditton et al (1999) who report
that, in one major city centre system, it was revealed that the technical
capabilities of the systems enabled the camera to focus in on a car’s tax
disc from several hundred metres away. It could therefore determine
whether the disc being displayed had expired. However, this was not seen
as an appropriate use of the system (Ditton et al 1999: 47 fn 55). Thus the
offences of the relatively affluent and older motorists are left unchecked
while the scrutiny of poorer working-class and ethnic minority youth is
intensified.
Moreover, for those who are constantly tracked by the cameras in city
centre space, merely on the basis of their appearance and overt social
characteristics, the CCTV gaze will not be seen as friendly and protecting
but hostile and untrusting. How else should they react? They are being
treated as a threat, as people who cannot be trusted, as persons who do not
belong, as unwanted outsiders.
Unjustifiably selective targeting may have further consequences.
Norris and Armstrong (1999) found women to be largely invisible to
CCTV operators, with women accounting for only 7% of targeted
surveillance, and they show how such targeting can be for voyeuristic
rather than protectional purposes. Moreover, as Brown (1998) has shown,
on the basis of extensive interviews in Middlesbrough regarding aspects
of gender and community safety, CCTV is likely to be of marginal signifi-
cance to women’s perception of safety within town centres, and merely
represent yet another, this time technologically mediated, male gaze.

Being seen, for women, is a condition of everyday life: their feelings


of extreme visibility in public are created by masculine regulation of
the public domain. Their exaggerated visibility creates insecurity.
More men, sitting in front of camera screens, adds visibility. It does
not necessarily add security. The kinds of behaviour which CCTV
can monitor and ostensibly provide a basis for action on are the rare
and spectacular acts of physical assaults on women in the high street.
It cannot monitor the alcohol-fuelled male gaze nor the alcohol-
fuelled male display: indeed, in one sense it is part of the male gaze,
and therefore part of the problem rather than the solution.
(Brown 1998: 218)

Brown goes on to argue that the belief in technologically driven solutions


to the problem of crime may divert attention, and funding, away from
more imaginative and appropriate ‘people-driven solutions’: safer trans-
port policies, the visible presence of capable guardians in the form of city
centre wardens, or a more visible police presence, are three such strategies.

173
Introducing Criminology

This echoes the concerns of Bannister et al (1998), who remind us that


social order in public space is, by and large, maintained by the capable
guardianship of the proprietors and users of the streets. It is highly
localised, informal and personalised and as Jacobs argues:

The first thing to understand is that public peace – the sidewalk and
street peace – of cities ... is kept primarily by an intricate, almost
unconscious, network of voluntary controls and standards among
people themselves, and enforced by the people themselves.
(Jacobs, 1961, quoted in Bannister et al 1998: 23)

There are two things to note about this. First, order is maintained not
primarily through the intervention of police or security staff (indeed their
intervention is often a sign of disorder) but by the ordinary mass of
citizenry. Secondly, that order is localised and, as such, is capable of being
sensitive to a diversity of community norms.
For Bannister et al (1998), cities are sites of difference: sites where those
of different classes, races, cultures and backgrounds intermingle. And the
encountering of difference brings with it not only excitement and stimula-
tion but also fear. Fear is not necessarily something to be concerned about,
indeed it is part of the the adventure of the city. However, while some
‘visions’ of the city celebrate and promote this aspect of metropolitan life,
other, more powerful voices envisage the need to manage this fear and
create homogeneous spaces through the exclusion of difference.
The exclusionary impulse is intimately bound up with the commerciali-
sation of city centre space and in particular the threat posed to the
commercial profitability of the town centre by out-of-town retail parks
(such as the Metro Centre in Gateshead) where private finance has created
sterile, orderly, but above all private areas for consumption. This leads to
a fortress mentality where ‘difference is not so much to be celebrated as
segregated’ (Bannister et al 1998–27). CCTV becomes part of the process
whereby difference is excluded not by targeting the criminal, but by
targeting the ‘other’: the homeless, the poor, the political activist, who do
not contribute to the commercial success of the city. This exclusionary
impulse is almost entirely overlooked by those who focus on the crime
reduction potential of CCTV.
However, for a number of radical commentators, CCTV is part of the
process whereby city centres are being transformed from democratic
spaces to which all citizens have access and in which they can freely
interact, whatever their race, class or status, to mere sites of consumerism.
As the public realm becomes increasingly privatised, as housing, parks,
leisure facilities, and shopping spaces are sold off to commercial de-
velopers, they become subject to private standards of justice and control.
As France and Wiles warn:

174
CCTV and crime prevention: questions for criminology

There is a clear danger that as mass private property increases young


people, or rather particular groups of young people, will be exluded
from many of the locations ... . Even more worrrying is that most of
the public law rights which were developed as part of the modernity
project, and which protected young people from exclusion are now
being evaded by the use of private law devices.
(France and Wiles 1998: 69)

These fears are well grounded: as McCahill (2000) has shown in his study
of CCTV in shopping malls, the exclusion of ‘flawed’ consumers is actively
promoted by the CCTV system, as it is used to systematically exclude
youth and others deemed undesirable. Moreover, it leads to a form of
private justice, where people are barred from certain spaces, on the
authority of the security guards, who then use the cameras to collectively
enforce such bans. This is achieved without any recourse to the formal
criminal justice system and therefore bypasses legal safeguards embodied
in the public justice of the courts.
This exclusionary impulse is starting to assert itself in what remains of
the public sphere, as Reeve’s study of town centre managers revealed. The
managers wanted to discourage certain people and activities within the
city centre which were seen as non-conducive to their consumer-led vision
of the desirable. A quarter wanted to discourage political gatherings, a half
to discourage youths from ‘hanging out’, and a half to prohibit begging in
the streets (Reeve 1998: 78).
As Young has argued, this exclusionary impulse is not the outcome of
over-zealous security guards inappropriately using the the system. It is
embedded in structural changes in the nature of crime control in the
transition from modernity to late modernity. While the modernist project
had faith in the ability to intervene both structurally and individually,
through secondary and tertiary crime prevention techniques, it was
predominantly inclusionary; it sought to keep the deviant and potential
deviant within the fold. In late modernity such hopes have largely been
abandoned and instead society ‘responds to deviance by exclusion and
separation’ (Young 1999: 26).

175
Introducing Criminology

Chapter 7

Criminology: some concluding


thoughts

This book began by inviting you to a party. Those who were seduced
by this invitation and are still with us might be feeling rather disappointed
by now. Perhaps anticipating party hats, games and laughter, readers have
been taken aside by two rather serious academics who proceeded
to ask a lot of rather difficult questions. Thankfully, parties don’t oftenturn
out like that. We hope that those who are still reading will agree that those
questions, although difficult, are often important and interesting ones.
One major role for criminology is to subject ‘obvious’, ‘common sense’
knowledge – the sort of thing that often enters the conversation at parties –
to critical scrutiny. As we have seen, although it may be thought obvious
that more police patrolling the streets or the presence of CCTV cameras
will inevitably reduce crime, things are more complicated than that.
Criminology subjects such ideas to rigorous enquiry, which often includes
systematic empirical research by a variety of methods. Whether or not this
qualifies criminology as a science – another difficult question that has
taken up a lot of energy over the years, often to little effect – is not an issue
that we have discussed in this book. But the striving for knowledge that
will somehow go beyond common sense, speculation, belief or assertion is
certainly something that has characterised much work in criminology, a
child of what has been called a modernist project.
In the first chapter, we began with some basic questions about crime
and the criminal. We found that there are different views about the
definition of these terms, which had some important consequences,
including for the very scope and nature of the discipline. While many
criminologists in the past did not spend too much time considering such
definitional questions, we suggested that the terms should be regarded as
problematic. According to this view, criminologists should consider the
use of these terms when they appear. Even where the definitions of crime

176
Criminology: some concluding thoughts

and the criminal are clear, there still remains the problem for criminol-
ogists of identifying crime and the criminal for research purposes. If a
legalistic position is adopted, for example, can we use official data from
the criminal justice system in order to assess the nature, extent and
distribution of crime and offenders?
We then outlined in more detail what seems to be the subject matter of
criminology, and its multi-disciplinary nature. Our position is that
criminology is a broad-ranging subject, which benefits from the insights of
a variety of disciplines and perspectives. There are, however, those
working in these areas who do not consider their work to be criminology,
and do not regard themselves as criminologists. Although the argument is
still to be heard that criminology should be abolished and the study of
crime and justice undertaken by other disciplines and perspectives, the
future of criminology looks assured. It has become institutionalised, with
apparently firm foundations in both academia and government, although
the complexion it assumes often varies with the context and the sponsor.
Finally, we tried to trace the history of criminology. Again, there were no
easy answers here, with the discussion seeming to hinge on what is meant
by ‘criminology’. Nevertheless, such histories tell us a little more about the
subject and where it (if, in view of the current fragmentation and
diversification, we can speak of ‘it’) stands today.
No introduction to criminology would be complete without consider-
ing the attempt to develop theories of crime. We began our discussion of
this in chapter 2 in looking at biological and psychological contributions to
this enterprise. While early efforts involved crude attempts to spot
biological or psychological differences between offenders and others, later
research became increasingly sophisticated in this quest. First, it stressed
the notion of a complex interaction between a range of different sorts of
factors, whether biological, psychological, social or of some other sort.
Second, it appeared to soften the deterministic tenor of some earlier
pronouncements, by stressing that such factors operated in a probabilistic
fashion – they were risk factors. Finally, it was often declared that attempt-
ing to develop a general theory of crime was a fruitless or unrewarding
task. While some tried to refashion the subject matter as anti-social
conduct or something similar, others suggested that we needed to be
much more specific in what we are trying to explain – such as by focusing
on aggression, or life-course persistent anti-social behaviour – in view of
the heterogeneity of the offender population. We saw how what we called
the new biology of crime was still engaged in the search for differences,
often on this modified basis. By contrast, rational choice, routine activities
and situational perspectives played down the idea of difference, partly
because they were more interested in those aspects (usually in the
immediate situation, rather than in the person) that could be more easily
changed in order to reduce crime.

177
Introducing Criminology

We continued our consideration of theories of crime in chapter 3, in


which we looked at the way in which sociologists and others tried to
develop an understanding of crime by reference to the social contexts and
circumstances in which offenders were located. It was a version of spot the
difference with a rather different focus. We saw how, over time, attention
began to move away from looking for the ‘causes of crime’ (some thought
that this was a question no longer worth asking) to the study of criminali-
zation. This gave importance to a whole range of new topics for detailed
study, including the police (see chapter 5). We have seen how criminology
has experienced challenges from a variety of sources, such as interactionist
and labelling perspectives, radical and Marxist approaches, feminist
perspectives, and postmodernist influences. Partly as a result of these
challenges, much of what is called criminology today is very different
from 40 years ago.
Criminology has shown a remarkable capacity to assimilate ideas from
such challenges (or to ignore them, for there are some areas of study that
have changed relatively little). Perhaps the most enduring tension in the
discipline is still that between those with an essentially applied, practical
or policy focus, with their research often sponsored by the Home Office or
other agencies, and those with a more ‘academic’ orientation, often critical
of fundamental assumptions and ideas. Those working on studies of
‘effective practice’ with offenders, for example, do not seem to have much
time for the idea that we should ‘deconstruct crime’. We also saw,
however, how even some of those who have been much influenced by the
ideas of postmodernism have been unable to abandon entirely the idea
that criminology, which came into being as part of the modernist project,
should strive for knowledge that will help us not only to interpret the
world but to change it, hopefully for the better.
We chose three examples of areas of criminological work in order to
illustrate some of the themes and perspectives in contemporary crimi-
nology. First we looked at serial murder as an example of the attempt to
study and understand a particular type of crime. We looked at the defini-
tion and measurement of the phenomenon, a common starting point in
such studies. We then saw how the attempt to explain such a specific crime
was by no means as straightforward as we might have thought. There
appeared to be considerable heterogeneity among even this bunch of
offenders. We were able show the scope and nature of contributions from
three disciplines – biology, psychology and sociology – and assessed each
in turn. We concluded by showing how what often passes as ‘knowledge’
in our society can be seen as socially constructed – that representations of
the ‘serial murder problem’ and crime in general, in the mass media and
elsewhere, can be regarded in a sceptical frame of mind, and the way in
which they are presented subject to analysis to show the interests that they
may serve.

178
Criminology: some concluding thoughts

Our chapter on the police and policing provides an introduction to the


study of one institution of the criminal justice system. We began by
questioning the common assumption that the core role of the police is, and
should be, the control of crime. We then looked at the key issues of
discretion and discrimination, suggesting that it is often a more complex
matter than is commonly realised to show that discretion is being
exercised in a discriminatory way, and that mere reference to the influence
of individual prejudice or police culture as an explanation is not good
enough. Issues of discretion and discrimination have a wider relevance
throughout the criminal justice system. Finally, we considered due process
and crime control models of the criminal justice process, and discussed
them in the context of policing. We examined how so-called ‘noble cause
corruption’ seems to occur, such as that which has contributed to some of
the major miscarriages of justice of recent years. Our conclusion, that this
is related to the organisational and wider contexts within which the police
operate, has clear implications for the wider system of criminal justice.
Our final chapter introduced the area of crime prevention, before an
examination of CCTV and whether it can be said to reduce crime. In spite
of the enthusiasm with which this technology has been embraced, the
evidence does not unequivocally justify that enthusiasm. In addition,
while attention has been focused on the technical evaluation of whether it
‘works’, there are wider questions that criminology should consider. For
example, it seems that CCTV can lead to discrimination and social
exclusion for certain groups in the population. The chapter also served as
an illustration of the procedures and problems involved in conducting
empirical research in criminology. Here, as in policing and elsewhere in
criminal justice research, there is clearly a place for detailed, observational
studies to examine the actual operation of CCTV systems, policing, courts
and prisons. These studies can be a valuable corrective to the managerial-
ist perspectives that have become dominant in criminal justice in recent
years, with their emphasis on technicist evaluation and the quantitative
measurement of performance indicators, targets and the like. As always, a
variety of methods, data, and perspectives will enrich our understanding
of crime, criminal justice and related topics.

179
Introducing Criminology

Bibliography

Abel, G., Becker, J. and Cunningham-Rather, J. (1984) ‘Complications, consent and


cognitions in sex between children and adults’, International Journal of Psychiatry
and Law, 7: 89–103.
Abrahamsen, D. (1973) The Murdering Mind. New York: Harper and Row.
Agnew, R. (1985) ‘A revised strain theory of delinquency’, Social Forces, 64: 151–67.
Agnew, R and White, H. (1992) ‘An empirical test of general strain theory’,
Criminology, 32: 555–80.
Aichhorn, A. (1955, originally published 1925) Wayward Youth. New York:
Meridian Books.
Akers, R. (1977) Deviant Behaviour: A Social Learning Approach, 2nd edn. Belmont,
CA: Wadsworth.
Akers, R., Krohn, M., Lanza-Kaduce, L., and Radesovich, M. (1979) ‘Social learning
and deviant behaviour’, American Sociological Review, 44: 635–55.
Alexander, F. and Healy, W. (1935) Roots of Crime. New York: Knopf.
Alexander, F. and Staub, H. (1931) The Criminal, the Judge and the Public. New York:
Macmillan.
Anderson, S., Kinsey, R., Loader, I. and Smith, C. (1990) The Edinburgh Crime Survey.
Edinburgh: Scottish Office.
Armitage, R., Smythe, G. and Pease, K. (1999) ‘Burnley CCTV evaluation’ in
Painter, K. and Tilley, N. (eds) Crime Prevention Studies, Vol 10: 225–251. Special
edition entitled ‘Surveillance of Public Space: CCTV, Street Lighting and Crime
Prevention’.
Atkinson, R. L., Atkinson, R. C., Smith, E. and Bem, D. (1993) Introduction to
Psychology, 11th edn. Fort Worth, Tex: Harcourt Brace.
Audit Commission (1993) Helping with Enquiries, Police Paper No. 12. London:
HMSO.
Audit Commission (1996) Streetwise: Effective Police Patrol. London: HMSO

Baldwin, J. and Bottoms, A. (1976) The Urban Criminal. London: Tavistock.


Bandura, A. (1977) Social Learning Theory. New York: Prentice Hall.
Bandura, A. (1983) ‘Psychological mechanisms of aggression’, in R. Green and E.
180
Bibliography

Donnerstein (eds) Aggression: Theoretical and Experimental Reviews, Volume One.


New York: Academic Press.
Bandura, A. (1986) Social Foundations of Thought and Action. Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
Prentice Hall.
Bannister, J., Fyfe, N. and Kearns, A. (1998), ‘Closed Circuit Television and the
City’, in C. Norris, J. Moran and G. Armstrong (eds), Surveillance, Closed Circuit
Television and Social Control. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Banton. M. (1964) The Policeman in the Community. London: Tavistock.
Barr, R. and Pease, K (1990) ‘Crime Placement, Displacement and Deflection’, in
Tonry, M. and N. Morris (eds) Crime and Justice, vol. 12, Chicago: Chicago
University Press.
Bayley, D. (1994) Police for the Future. New York: Oxford University Press.
Bayley, D. (1996) ‘What do police do?’ in W. Saulsbury, J. Mott and T. Newburn
(eds) Themes in Contemporary Policing. London: Independent Inquiry into the
Role and Responsibilities of the Police.
Beccaria, C. (1963, first published 1764) On Crimes and Punishments. New York:
Bobbs Merrill.
Beck, A. and Willis, A. (1999) ‘Context-specific Measures of CCTV Effectiveness in
the Retail Sector ‘, in Painter, K. and Tilley, N. (eds) Crime Prevention Studies, Vol
10: pp 252–269. Special edition entitled ‘Surveillance of Public Space: CCTV,
Street Lighting and Crime Prevention’.
Becker, H. (1963) Outsiders. New York: The Free Press.
Beirne, P. (1993) Inventing Criminology. Albany, NY: State University of New York
Press.
Beick, W. and Kessler, D. (1977) Response Time Analysis in Kansas City. Mo: Board of
Police Commissioners.
Bennett, T. (1990) Evaluating Neighbourhood Watch. Aldershot: Gower.
Bittner, E. (1974) ‘Florence Nightingale in pursuit of Willie Sutton’, in H. Jacob (ed)
Potential for Reform of Criminal Justice. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
Bittner, E. (1975) The Functions of the Police in Modern Society. New York: Aronson.
Bittner, E. (1978) ‘The function of the police in modern society’, in P. K. Manning
and J. van Maanen (eds) Policing: A View from the Street. Santa Monica, CA:
Goodyear.
Bittner, E. and Bayley, D. (1983) Gauging the Effectiveness of Police Work.
Unpublished manuscript.
Black, D. (1980) The Manners and Customs of the Police. London: Academic Press.
Blackburn, R. (1993) The Psychology of Criminal Conduct. Chichester: John Wiley.
Blom-Cooper, L. and Drabble, R. (1982) ‘Police perceptions of crime’, British Journal
of Criminology, 22: 184–7.
Blumberg, A. (1970) The Scales of Justice. Chicago: Aldine.
Bohman, M., Cloninger, C., Sigvardson, S. and von Knorring, A.-L. (1982)
‘Predisposition to petty criminality in Swedish adoptees’, Archives of General
Psychiatry, 39: 1233–41.
Bottomley, K. and Coleman, C. (1981) Understanding Crime Rates. Farnborough:
Gower.
Bottoms, A. and Wiles, P. (1997) ‘Environmental criminology’, in M. Maguire, R.
Morgan, and R. Reiner (eds) The Oxford Handbook of Criminology, 2nd edn.
Oxford: Clarendon.

181
Introducing Criminology

Bowlby, J. (1944) ‘Forty-four juvenile thieves’, International Journal of Psychoanalysis,


25: 1–57.
Bowlby, J., Ainsworth, M., Boston, M. and Rosenbluth, D. (1956) ‘The effects of
mother-child separation: a follow-up study’, British Journal of Medical
Psychology, 29: 211–47.
Bowling, B., Graham, J. and Ross, A. (1994) ‘Self-reported offending among young
people in England and Wales’, in J. Junger-Tas, G. Terlouw and M. Klein (eds)
Delinquent Behaviour among Young People in the Western World. Amsterdam:
Kugler.
Box, S. (1971) Deviance, Reality and Society. London: Holt Rinehart and Winston.
Box, S. (1981) Deviance, Reality and Society, 2nd edn. London: Holt Rinehart and
Winston.
Box, S. (1983) Power, Crime and Mystification. London: Tavistock.
Braithwaite, J. (1989) Crime, Shame and Reintegration. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Bridges, L. (1983) ‘Policing the urban wasteland’, Race and Class, Autumn.
Bright, J. (1969) The Beat Patrol Experiment. London: Home Office Police Research
and Development Branch, Unpublished.
Britton, P. (1997) The Jigsaw Man. London: Bantam.
Brody, S. (1976) The Effectiveness of Sentencing: A review of the literature, Home Office
Research Study No. 35, London: HMSO.
Brown, B. (1995), Closed Circuit Television in Town Centres: Three Case Studies, Crime
Prevention and Detection Series Paper 73, Home Office: London.
Brown, D. and Hogg, R. (1992) ‘Law and order politics, left realism and radical
criminology’, in R. Matthews and J. Young (eds) Issues in Realist Criminology.
London: Sage.
Brown, S. (1998), ‘What’s the Problem Girls? CCTV and the Gendering of Public
Safety’ in C. Norris, J. Moran and G. Armstrong (eds), Surveillance, Closed Circuit
Television and Social Control, Aldershot: Ashgate.
Brownmiller, S. (1975) Against Our Will. London: Secker and Warburg.
Bulos, M., Chaker, W., Farish, M., Mahalingham, V. and Sarno, C. (1995), Towards a
Safer Sutton? Impact of Closed Circuit Television on Sutton Town Centre. London:
London Borough of Sutton.
Bulos, M. and Grant, D. (eds) (1996), Towards a Safer Sutton? CCTV One Year On.
London: London Borough of Sutton.
Burgess, A., Hartman, C., Ressler, R., Douglas, J. and McCormack, A. (1986) ‘Sexual
homicide: a motivational model’, Journal of Interpersonal Violence, 1: 251–72.
Burgess, R. and Akers, R. (1966) ‘A differential association-reinforcement theory of
criminal behaviour’, Social Problems, 14: 128–47.
Burrows, J. (1979), ‘The Impact of Closed Circuit Television on Crime in the
London Underground’ in P. Mayhew, R. Clarke, J. Burrows, M. Hough and S.
Winchester, Crime in Public View, Home Office Research Study, no. 49. London:
HMSO.
Burrows, J. and Tarling, R. (1982) Clearing Up Crime, Home Office Research Study
No. 73. London: HMSO.
Bursik, R. (1986) ‘Ecological stability and the dynamics of delinquency’, in A. J.
Reiss and M. Tonry (eds) Communities and Crime. Chicago: Chicago University
Press.

182
Bibliography

Bursik, R. and Grasmick, H. (1993) Neighbourhoods and Crime. New York:


Lexington.
Burt, C. (1925) The Young Delinquent. London: University of London Press.

Cain, M. (1973) Society and the Policeman’s Role. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Cain, M. (1986) ‘Realism, feminism, methodology and law’, International Journal of
the Sociology of Law, 14: 255–67.
Cameron, D. and Frazer, E. (1987) The Lust to Kill. Cambridge: Polity.
Campbell, A. (1984) The Girls in the Gang. Oxford: Blackwell.
Campbell, D. and Stanley, J. (1963), Experimental and Quasi-experimental Designs for
Research. Chicago: Rand MacNally.
Canter, D. (1994) Criminal Shadows. London: Harper Collins.
Caputi, J. (1987) The Age of Sex Crime. London: The Women’s Press.
Carlen, P. (1992) ‘Criminal women and criminal justice’, in R. Matthews and J.
Young (eds) Issues in Realist Criminology. London: Sage.
Carlisle, A. (1998) ‘The divided self: toward an understanding of the dark side of
the serial killer’, in R. M. Holmes and S. T. Holmes (eds) Contemporary
Perspectives on Serial Murder. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Carrington, K. (1998) ‘Postmodernism and feminist criminologies’, in P. Walton
and J. Young (eds) The New Criminology Revisited. Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Chatterton, M. (1976) ‘Police in social control’, in J. King (ed) Control Without
Custody? Cambridge: Cambridge Institute of Criminology.
Chatterton, M. (1983) ‘Police work and assault charges’, in M. Punch (ed) Control in
the Police Organisation. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Clarke, R. and Hough, M. (1984) Crime and Police Effectiveness. London: Home
Office Research Study 79.
Clarke, R. (1992), Situational Crime Prevention: Successful Case Studies. New York:
Harrow and Heston.
Cleckley, H. M. (1976) The Mask of Sanity, 5th edn. St Louis: C. V. Mosby.
Cloward, R. and Ohlin, L. (1960) Delinquency and Opportunity. New York: Free
Press.
Cohen, A. K. (1955) Delinquent Boys. Glencoe: Free Press.
Cohen, A. K. (1966) Deviance and Control. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Cohen, L. and Felson, M. (1979) ‘Social change and crime rate trends: a routine
activities approach’, American Sociological Review, 44: 588–608.
Cohen, S. (ed) (1971) Images of Deviance. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Cohen, S. (1973a) Folk Devils and Moral Panics. London: Paladin.
Cohen, S. (1973b) ‘The failures of criminology’, The Listener, 8 November.
Cohen, S. (1985), Visions of Social Control. Polity Press: Cambridge.
Cohen, S. (1993) ‘Human rights and crimes of the state’, Australian and New Zealand
Journal of Criminology, 26: 97–115.
Cohen, S. (1998) ‘Intellectual scepticism and political commitment’, in P. Walton
and J. Young (eds) The New Criminology Revisited. Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Coleman, C. and Moynihan, J. (1996) Understanding Crime Data: Haunted by the Dark
Figure. Buckingham: Open University Press.
Comrie, M. and Kings, E. (1974) Study of Urban Workloads: Final Report. Home
Office Police Research Services Unit, Unpublished.
Connell, R. (1987) Gender and Power. Cambridge: Polity.

183
Introducing Criminology

Connell, R. (1996) Masculinities. Cambridge: Polity.


Constant, M. and Turnbull, P. (1994), The Principles and Practice of CCTV,
Hertfordshire: Paramount Publishing.
Cook, T. D. and Campbell, D. T. (1979), Quasi-Experimentation: Design and Analysis
Issues for Field Settings, Chicago: Rand McNally.
Cornish, D. and Clarke, R. (eds) (1986) The Reasoning Criminal. New York:
Springer–Verlag.
Crawford, A., Jones, T., Woodhouse, T. and Young, J. (1990) The Second Islington
Crime Survey. London: Centre for Criminology, Middlesex Polytechnic.
Critchley, T. (1978) A History of the Police in England and Wales. London: Constable.
Currie, E. (1985) Confronting Crime. New York: Pantheon.

Damer, S. (1974) ‘Wine Alley: the sociology of a dreadful enclosure’, Sociological


Review, 22: 221–48.
Davis, K. (1969) Discretionary Justice. Urbana, Ill.: University of Illinois.
Ditton, J. (1998), ‘Public Support for Town Centre CCTV Schemes: Myth or Reality’,
in C. Norris, J. Moran and G. Armstrong (eds), Surveillance, Closed Circuit
Television and Social Control, Aldershot: Ashgate.
Ditton, J. and Short, E. (1998), ‘Evaluating Scotland’s First Town Centre CCTV
Scheme,’ in C. Norris, J. Moran and G. Armstrong (eds), Surveillance, Closed
Circuit Television and Social Control, Aldershot: Ashgate.
Ditton, J. and Short, E. (1999), ‘Yes, It Works, No, It Doesn’t: Comparing the Effects
of Open CCTV in Two Adjacent Scottish Town Centres,’ in Painter, K. and Tilley,
N. (eds) Crime Prevention Studies, Vol 10: 201–224. Special edition entitled
‘Surveillance of Public Space: CCTV, Street Lighting and Crime Prevention’.
Ditton, J., Short, E. Phillips S., Norris, C. and Armstrong, G. (1999), The Effect of the
Introduction of Closed Circuit Television on Recorded Crime Rates and Concern about
Crime in Glasgow, Edinburgh, SCOT: Central Research Unit, Scottish Office.
Dixon, D. (1992) ‘Legal regulation and policing pratice’, Social and Legal Studies, 1:
515–41.
Dixon, D. (1997) Law in Policing. Oxford: Clarendon.
Dixon, D. (1999) ‘Police investigative procedures’, in C. Walker and K. Starmer
(eds) Miscarriages of Justice, 2nd edn. London: Blackstone.
Downes, D. (1966) The Delinquent Solution. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Downes, D. and Rock, P. (1998) Understanding Deviance, 3rd edn. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Drapkin, I. (1983) ‘Criminology: intellectual history’, in S. Kadish (ed) Encyclopedia
of Crime and Justice. New York: Free Press.
Duclos, D. (1998) The Werewolf Complex: America’s Fascination with Violence. Oxford:
Berg.
Dunnighan, C. and Norris, C. (1996) ‘A risky business: exchange, bargaining and
risk in the recruitment and running of informers by English police officers’,
Police Studies, 19: 1–25.
Dunnighan, C. and Norris, C. (1999), ‘The detective, the snout, and the Audit
Commission: the real costs in using informants’, The Howard Journal, 38: 67–86.
Durkheim, E. (1952) Suicide: A Study in Sociology. London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul.

184
Bibliography

Eaton, M. (1986) Justice for Women. Milton Keynes: Open University Press.
Edwards, S. (1984) Women on Trial. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Edwards, S. (1989) Policing ‘Domestic’ Violence. London: Sage.
Egger, S. (ed) (1990) Serial Murder: An Elusive Phenomenon. New York: Praeger.
Ekblom, P. (1992), ‘The Safer Cities Programe Impact Evaluation: Problem and
Progress’, Studies on Crime and Crime Prevention, Vol. 1. No 1.
Ekblom, P. and Heal, K. (1982) The Police Response to Calls from the Public. Research
and Planning Unit Paper 9. London: Home Office.
Elliott, D. S., Huizinga, D. and Ageton, S. S. (1985) Explaining Delinquency and Drug
Use. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
Ericson, R. (1982) Reproducing Order: A Study of Police Patrol Work. Toronto:
University of Toronto Press.
Eysenck, H. (1977) Crime and Personality, 3rd edn. London Routledge and Kegan
Paul.
Eysenck, H. ‘Personality theory and the problems of criminality’, in B. J. McGurk,
D. M. Thornton and M. Williams (eds) Applying Psychology to Imprisonment.
London: HMSO.

Farrington, D. (1997) ‘Human development and criminal careers’, in M. Maguire,


R. Morgan, and R. Reiner (eds) The Oxford Handbook of Criminology, 2nd edn.
Oxford: Clarendon.
Feldman, D. (1964) ‘Psychoanalysis and crime’, in B. Rosenberg, I. Gerver and F. W.
Howton (eds) Mass Society in Crisis. New York: Macmillan.
Feldman, P. (1993) The Psychology of Crime. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Ferri, E. (1913) The Positive School of Criminology. Chicago: Kerr and Co.
Field, S. (1991), Trends in Crime and their Interpretation: A Study of Recorded Crime in
Post War England and Wales, Home Office Research Study no 119, London:
HMSO.
Fielding, N. (1984) ‘Police socialisation and police competence’, British Journal of
Sociology, 35: 568–90.
Fielding, N. (1988) ‘Competence and culture in the police’, Sociology, 22: 45–64.
Fielding, N., Kemp, C. and Norris, C. (1989) ‘Constraints on the practice of
community policing’, in R. Morgan and D. J. Smith (eds) Coming to Terms with
Policing. London: Routledge.
FitzGerald, M. (1993) Ethnic Minorities and the Criminal Justice System, Royal
Commision on Criminal Justice Research Study No 20. London: HMSO.
Folkard, M., Smith, D. E., and Smith D. D. (1976), IMPACT Volume 2: The Results of
the Experiment, Home Office Research Study no 36. London: HMSO.
Fox, J. A. (1990) ‘Murder they wrote’, Contemporary Psychology, 35: 890–1.
France, A. and Wiles, P. (1998) ‘Dangerous futures: social exclusion and youth
work in late modernity’, in C. J. Finer and M. Nellis (eds) Crime and Social
Exclusion. Oxford: Blackwell.

Gabor, T. (1978), ‘Crime Displacement: The Literature and Strategies For Its
Investigation,’ Crime and Justice, Vol 6 No 2: 100–107.
Garland, D. (1985) ‘The criminal and his science’, British Journal of Criminology, 25:
109–37.

185
Introducing Criminology

Garland, D. (1996) ‘The limits of the sovereign state’, British Journal of Criminology,
36: 445–71.
Garland, D. (1997) ‘Of crimes and criminals: the development of criminology in
Britain’, in M. Maguire, R. Morgan, and R. Reiner (eds) The Oxford Handbook of
Criminology, 2nd edn. Oxford: Clarendon.
Gelsthorpe, L. (1997) ‘Feminism and criminology’, in M. Maguire, R. Morgan, and
R. Reiner (eds) The Oxford Handbook of Criminology, 2nd edn. Oxford: Clarendon.
Gelsthorpe, L. and Morris. A. (eds) (1990) Feminist Perspectives in Criminology.
Buckingham: Open University Press.
Giddens, A. (1990) The Consequences of Modernity. Cambridge: Polity.
Giddens, A. (1991) Modernity and Self-identity. Cambridge: Polity.
Gill, M. and Turbin, V. (1999) ‘Evaluating ‘Realistic Evaluation’: Evidence from a
study of CCTV’, in Painter, K. and Tilley, N. (eds) Crime Prevention Studies, Vol
10: 225–251. Special edition entitled ‘Surveillance of Public Space: CCTV, Street
Lighting and Crime Prevention’.
Gilroy, P. (1982) ‘The myth of black criminality’, Socialist Register. London: Merlin.
Glover, E. (1960) The Roots of Crime. London: Imago.
Goldstein, J. (1960) ‘Police discretion not to invoke the criminal process’, Yale Law
Journal, 69: 543–94.
Goodwin, M., Johnstone, C. and Williams, K. (1998), ‘New Spaces of Law
Enforcement: Closed Circuit Television, Public Behaviour and the Policing of
Public Space’, unpublished paper, Aberystwyth: Institute of Geography and
Earth Sciences, University of Wales.
Gouldner, A. (1975) For Sociology. Harmondsworth: Pelican.
Goring C. (1913) The English Convict. London: HMSO.
Gottfredson, M. and Hirschi, T. (1990) A General Theory of Crime. Stanford CA:
Stanford University Press.
Graham, J. and Bowling, B. (1995) Young People and Crime, Home Office Research
Study No. 145. London: HMSO.
Graham, S. (1998), ‘Towards the Fifth Utility? On the Extension and Normalisation
of Public CCTV’ in C. Norris, J. Moran and G. Armstrong (eds), Surveillance,
Closed Circuit Television and Social Control, Aldershot: Ashgate.
Gresswell, D. and Hollin, C. (1994) ‘Multiple murder: a review’, British Journal of
Criminology, 34: 1–14.

Hacking, I. (1990) The Taming of Chance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.


Hagan, J. (1988) Structural Criminology. Cambridge: Polity.
Hagan, J., Simpson, J. and Gillis, A. (1979) ‘The sexual stratification of social
control’, British Journal of Sociology, 30: 25–38.
Hagan, J., Gillis, A. and Simpson, J. (1985) ‘The class structure of gender and
delinquency’, American Journal of Sociology, 90: 1151–78.
Hale, R. and Bolin, A. (1998) ‘The female serial killer’, in R. M. Holmes and S. T.
Holmes (eds) Contemporary Perspectives on Serial Murder. Thousand Oaks, CA:
Sage.
Hall, S., Critcher, C., Clarke, J., Jefferson, T. and Roberts, B. (1978) Policing the Crisis.
London: Macmillan.
Hall, S. and Jefferson, T. (eds) (1976) Resistance Through Rituals. London:
Hutchinson.

186
Bibliography

Hancox, P. and Morgan, J. (1975), ‘The Use of CCTV for Police Control at Football
Matches’, Police Research Bulletin, vol. 25, pp. 41–4.
Harding, S. (ed) (1986) The Science Question in Feminism. Milton Keynes: Open
University Press.
Hare, R. D. (1991) The Hare Psychopathy Checklist – Revised. Toronto: Multi-Health
Systems.
Healy, W. and Bronner, A. F. (1936) New Light on Delinquency and its Treatment. New
Haven, Conn: Yale University Press.
Heidensohn, F. (1985) Women and Crime. Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Heidensohn, F. (1992) Women in Control? The Role of Women in Law Enforcement.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Heidensohn, F. (1996) Women and Crime, 2nd edn. Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Henderson. S. K. (1939) Psychopathic States. New York: Norton.
Henry, S. and Milovanovic, D. (1996) Constitutive Criminology. London: Sage.
Hester, S. and Eglin, P. (1992) A Sociology of Crime. London: Routledge.
Hickey, E. W. (1986) ‘The female serial murderer’, Journal of Police and Criminal
Psychology, 2: 72–81.
Hickey, E. W. (1990) ‘The etiology of victimization in serial murder’, in Egger, S.
(ed) Serial Murder: An Elusive Phenomenon. New York: Praeger.
Hickey, E. W. (1991) Serial Murderers and Their Victims. Pacific Grove, CA: Brooks/
Cole.
Hickey, E. W. (1997) Serial Murderers and Their Victims, 2nd edn. Belmont, CA:
Wadsworth.
Hirschi, T. (1969) Causes of Delinquency. Berkeley, CA: University of California
Press.
Hirschi, T. (1979) ‘Separate and unequal is better’, Journal of Research in Crime and
Delinquency, 16: 34–8.
Hirschi, T. (1986) ‘On the compatibility of rational choice and social control
theories of crime’, in Cornish, D. and Clarke, R. (eds) The Reasoning Criminal.
New York: Springer-Verlag.
Hirst, P. (1975) ‘Marx and Engels on law, crime and morality’, in I. Taylor, P. Walton
and J. Young (eds) Critical Criminology. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Holdaway, S. (ed) (1979) The British Police. London: Edward Arnold.
Holdaway, S. (1983) Inside the British Police. Oxford: Blackwell.
Hollin, C. (1989) Psychology and Crime. London: Routledge.
Holmes, R. M. and DeBurger, J. (1988) Serial Murder. Newbury Park, CA: Sage.
Holmes, R. M. and Holmes, S. T. (1998) Serial Murder, 2nd edn. London : Sage.
Holmes, R. M. and Holmes, S. T. (eds) (1998) Contemporary Perspectives on Serial
Murder. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Home Office (1967) Three Working Parties on Police Manpower, Equipment and
Efficiency. London: HMSO.
Home Office (1993) Police Reform: A Police Service for the Twenty-first Century.
London: HMSO.
Home Office (1994) CCTV: Looking Out For You, London: Home Office.
Home Office (1995) Review of Police Core and Ancillary Tasks. London: HMSO.
Home Office (1998) Criminal Statistics England and Wales 1997. London: The
Stationery Office.
Honess, T. and Charman, E. (1992) Closed Circuit Television in Public Places, Its

187
Introducing Criminology

Acceptability and Perceived Effectiveness, Home Office, Police Research Group,


Crime Prevention Unit series, Paper 35, London: Home Office.
Hooton, E. (1939) The American Criminal: An Anthropological Study. Cambridge,
Mass: Harvard University Press.
Hoyle, C. (1998) Negotiating Domestic Violence: Police, Criminal Justice and Victims.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Huff, R. (1996) Gangs in America. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Hughes, G. (1998) Understanding Crime Prevention: Social Control, Risk and Late
Modernity, Buckingham: Open University Press.

Jacobs, J. (1962) The Death and Life of Great American Cities. London: Jonathan
Cape.
James, D. (1979) ‘Police-black relations: the professional solution’, in S. Holdaway
(ed) The British Police. London: Edward Arnold.
Jamieson, R. (1998) ‘Towards a criminology of war in Europe’, in V. Ruggiero, N.
South and I. Taylor (eds) The New European Criminology. London: Routledge.
Jayewardene, C. (1963) ‘The English precursors of Lombroso’, British Journal of
Criminology, 4: 164–70.
Jefferson, T. (1997) ‘Masculinities and crime’, in M. Maguire, R. Morgan, and R.
Reiner (eds) The Oxford Handbook of Criminology, 2nd edn. Oxford: Clarendon.
Jefferson T. and Walker, M. (1992) ‘Ethnic minorities in the criminal justice system’,
Criminal Law Review, 83–95.
Jefferson, T. and Walker, M. (1993) ‘Attitudes to the police of ethnic minorities in a
provincial city’, British Journal of Criminology, 33: 251–66.
Jeffery, C. R. (1965) ‘Criminal behavior and learning theory’, Journal of Criminal
Law, Criminology and Police Science, 56: 294–300.
Jenkins, P. (1988) ‘Serial murder in England 1940–1985’, Journal of Criminal Justice,
16: 1–15.
Jenkins, P. (1994) Using Murder: the Social Construction of Serial Homicide. New York:
Aldine de Gruyter.
Johnston, L. (1992) The Rebirth of Private Policing. London: Routledge.
Johnston, L. (2000) Policing Britain. Harlow: Longman.
Johnstone, G. (1996) Medical Concepts and Penal Policy. London: Cavendish.
Jones, T., MacLean, B. and Young, J. (1986) The Islington Crime Survey. Aldershot:
Gower.
Jupp, V. (1989), Methods of Criminological Research, London: Unwin Hyman.

Kaplan, H. (1980) Deviant Behaviour in Defense of Self. New York: Pergamon.


Kaye, T. (1991) Unsafe and Unsatisfactory? Report of the Independent Inquiry into the
Working Practices of the West Midland Serious Crime Squad, London: Civil Liberties
Trust.
Kelling, G., Pate, T., Dieckman, D. and Brown C. (1974), The Kansas City preventative
patrol experiment: a summary report, Washington D.C.: Police Foundation.
Kemp, C., Norris, C. and Fielding, N. (1992) Negotiating Nothing: Police Decision-
Making in Disputes. Aldershot: Avebury.
Kiger, K. (1990) ‘The darker figure of crime: the serial murder enigma’, in Egger, S.
(ed) Serial Murder: An Elusive Phenomenon. New York: Praeger.
King, M. (1981) The Framework of Criminal Justice. London: Croom Helm.

188
Bibliography

Kinsey, R. (1984) Merseyside Crime Survey. Edinburgh: Centre for Criminology,


University of Edinburgh.
Kitsuse, J. and Cicourel, A. (1963) ‘A note on the uses of official statistics’, Social
Problems, 11: 131–9.
Klein, D. (1973) ‘The etiology of female crime’, Issues in Criminology, 8: 3–30.
Klockars, C. (1985) The Idea of Police. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
Kohlberg, L. (1964) ‘Development of moral character and moral ideology’, in M.
Hoffman and L. Hoffman (eds) Review of Child Development Research, vol 1. New
York: Russell Sage Foundation.
Kohlberg, L. (1978) ‘Revisions in the theory and practice of mental development’,
in W. Damon (ed) New Directions in Child Development: Moral Development. San
Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Kretschmer, E. (1936) Physique and Character. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner
and Co.

Landau, S. and Nathan, G. (1983) ‘Selecting delinquents for cautioning in the


London Metropolitan area’, British Journal of Criminology, 23: 128–49.
Lanier, M. and Henry, S. (1998) Essential Criminology. Oxford: Westview Press.
Lea, J. (1998) ‘Criminology and postmodernity’, in P. Walton and J. Young (eds) The
New Criminology Revisited. Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Lea, J. and Young, J. (1984) What is to be Done About Law and Order?
Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Lea, J. and Young, J. (1993) What is to be Done About Law and Order? 2nd edn.
London: Pluto Press.
Lemert, E. (1951) Social Pathology. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Lemert, E. (1967) Human Deviance, Social Problems and Social Control. Englewood
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Leonard, E. (1982) Women, Crime and Society. New York: Longman.
Levin, J. and Fox, J. A. (1985) Mass Murder: America’s Growing Menace. New York:
Plenum Press.
Leyton, E. (1989) Hunting Humans: The Rise of the Modern Multiple Murderer.
Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.
Lilly, J. R., Cullen, F. T., and Ball, R. A. (1995) Criminological Theory: Context and
Consequences, 2nd edn. London: Sage.
Lombroso, C. (1876) L’Uomo Delinquente. Milan: Hoepli.
Loveday, B. (1996) ‘Crime at the Core?’ in F. Leishman, B. Loveday and S. Savage
(eds) Core Issues in Policing, Harlow: Longman.
Lundman, R. (ed) (1980) Police Behaviour. New York: Oxford University Press.
Lustgarten, L. (1986) The Governance of Police. London: Sweet and Maxwell.
Lyon, D. (1999) Postmodernity, 2nd edn. Buckingham: Open University Press.
Lyotard, J.-F. (1984) The Postmodern Condition. Manchester: Manchester University
Press.

MacLean, B. (1992) ‘A programme of local crime research for Canada’, in J.


Lowman and B. MacLean (eds) Realist Criminology. Toronto: Toronto University
Press.
Macpherson, W. (1999) The Stephen Lawrence Inquiry. London: The Stationery
Office.

189
Introducing Criminology

McBarnet, D. (1979) ‘Arrest: the legal context of policing’, in S. Holdaway (ed) The
British Police. London: Edward Arnold.
McBarnet, D. (1981) Conviction. London: Macmillan.
McCabe, S. and Sutcliffe, F. (1978) Defining Crime. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
McCahill, M. (1998) ‘Beyond Foucault: Towards a Contemporary Theory of
Surveillance’, in C. Norris, J. Moran and G. Armstrong (eds), Surveillance, Closed
Circuit Television and Social Control. Aldershot: Ashgate.
McCahill, M. (2000) ‘The Surveillance Web: The rise and extent of visual
surveillance in a Northern City’. Unpublished PhD, Hull: University of Hull.
Maguire, M. (1998) ‘Restraining Big Brother? The Regulation of Surveillance in
England and Wales’, in Norris, C., Moran, J. and Armstrong, G. (eds), CCTV,
Surveillance and Social Control, Aldershot: Ashgate.
Maguire, M. and Norris, C. (1992) The Conduct and Supervision of Criminal
Investigations, Royal Commission on Criminal Justice Research Report No. 5.
London: HMSO.
Mahalingham, V. (1996) ‘Sutton Town Centre Public Perception Survey’, in M.
Bulos and D. Grant (eds), Towards a Safer Sutton? CCTV: One Year On. London:
London Borough of Sutton.
Mannheim, H. (1965) Comparative Criminology, vols 1 & 2. London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul.
Manning, P. (1977) Police Work. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Manning P. (1982) ‘Organisational work: structuration of the environment’, British
Journal of Sociology, 33: 118–139.
Mark, R. (1977) Policing a Perplexed Society. London: Allen and Unwin.
Martinson, R. (1974), ‘What Works? Questions and Answers about Prison Reform’,
The Public Interest, 35: 22–54.
Masters, B. (1985) Killing for Company: The Case of Dennis Nilsen. London: Jonathan
Cape.
Matza, D. (1964) Delinquency and Drift. New York: Wiley.
Mawby, R. (1979) Policing the City. Farnborough: Gower.
Mednick, S., Gabrielli, W., and Hutchings, B. (1987) ‘Genetic factors in the
etiology of criminal behaviour’, in S. Mednick, T. Moffit and S. Stack (eds) The
Causes of Crime: New Biological Approaches. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Mednick, S. and Volavka, J. (1980) ‘Biology and crime’, in N. Morris and M. Tonry
(eds) Crime and Justice, vol 2. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Merton, R. (1938) ‘Social structure and anomie’, American Sociological Review, 3:
672–82.
Merton, R. (1957) Social Theory and Social Structure. New York: Free Press.
Messerschmidt, J. (1993) Masculinities and Crime. Lanham, Md: Rowman and
Littlefield.
Messner, S. and Rosenfeld, R. (1994) Crime and the American Dream. Belmont, CA:
Wadsworth.
Michael, J. and Adler, M. (1933) Crime, Law and Social Science. New York: Harcourt
Brace Jovanovich.
Mirrlees-Black C., Budd, T., Partridge, S., and Mayhew, P. (1998) The 1998 British
Crime Survey, Home Office Statistical Bulletin, Issue 21/98, London:
Government Statistical Service.

190
Bibliography

Mischel, W. (1968) Personality and Assessment. New York: Wiley.


Moir, A. and Jessel, D. (1995) A Mind to Crime. London: Michael Joseph.
Morgan, B. (1990) The Police Function in the Investigation of Crime. Aldershot:
Avebury.
Morgan, R. and Newburn, T. (1997) The Future of Policing. Oxford: Clarendon.
Morris, T. (1957) The Criminal Area. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Muir, K. (1977) Police: Street Corner Politicians. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Mullin, C. (1987) Error of Judgement. Dublin: Poolbeg.
Muncie, J. (1999)Youth and Crime. London: Sage.
Muncie, J. (2000) ‘Decriminalizing criminology’, in G. Lewis, S. Gewirtz and J.
Clarke (eds) Rethinking Social Policy. London: Sage.
Muncie, J. and McLaughlin, E. (eds) (1996) Criminological Perspectives: A Reader.
London: Sage.
Musheno, M., Levine, J. and Palumbo, D. (1978), ‘Television Surveillance and
Crime Prevention: Evaluation of an Attempt to Create Defensible Space in
Public Housing’, Social Science Quarterly, vol. 58, no. 4, pp. 647–56.

Naffine, N. (1997) Feminism and Criminology. Cambridge: Polity.


National Deviancy Conference/Conference of Socialist Economists (eds) (1979)
Capitalism and the Rule of Law: From Deviancy Theory to Marxism. London:
Hutchinson.
Nelken, D. (1997) ‘White-collar crime’, in M. Maguire, R. Morgan, and R. Reiner
(eds) The Oxford Handbook of Criminology, 2nd edn. Oxford: Clarendon.
Nicholson, M. (1979) The Yorkshire Ripper. London: W. H. Allen.
Norris, C. (1989) ‘Avoiding trouble: the patrol officer’s perception of encounters
with the public’, in M. Wetheritt (ed) Police Research: Some Future Prospects.
Aldershot: Avebury.
Norris, C. and Armstrong, G. (1999) The Maximum Surveillance Society: The Rise of
CCTV, Oxford: Berg.
Norris, C., Fielding, N., Kemp, C. and Fielding, J. (1992) ‘Black and Blue: an
analysis of the influence of race on being stopped by the police’, British Journal of
Sociology, 43: 207–24.
Norris, C., Moran, J. and G. Armstrong (1998) ‘Algorithmic Surveillance: The
Future of Automated Visual Surveillance’, in C. Norris, J. Moran and G.
Armstrong (eds), Surveillance, Closed Circuit Television and Social Control,
Aldershot: Ashgate.
Norris, C., Moran, J. and Armstrong, G. (eds) (1998) Surveillance, Closed Circuit
Television and Social Control, Aldershot: Ashgate.
Norris, J. (1988) Serial Killers. London: Arrow.
Norris, J. and Birnes, W. (1998) Serial Killers: The Growing Menace. New York:
Dolphin.
Nye, R. A. (1984) Crime, Madness and Politics in Modern France. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.

Packer, H. (1968) The Limits of the Criminal Sanction. Stanford, CA: Stanford
University Press.
Pahl, J. (1982) ‘Police response to battered women’, Journal of Social Welfare Law, 5:
337–43.

191
Introducing Criminology

Painter, K. and Tilley, N. (1999), Editors’ Introduction: Seeing and Being Seen to
Prevent Crime, in K. Painter, and N. Tilley, (eds) Crime Prevention Studies, Vol 10
pp. 1–15. Special edition entitled ‘Surveillance of Public Space: CCTV, Street
Lighting and Crime Prevention’.
Parker, H. (1974) View From the Boys. Newton Abbott: David and Charles.
Passas, N. (1990) ‘Anomie and corporate deviance’, Contemporary Crises, 14: 157–
78.
Pawson, R. and Tilley, N. (1994), ‘What Works in Evaluation Research?’, British
Journal of Criminology, vol. 34, no. 3, pp. 291–306.
Pawson, R. and Tilley, N. (1997), Realistic Evaluation, London: Sage.
Pearce, F. and Tombs, S. (1992) ‘Realism and corporate crime’, in R. Matthews and
J. Young (eds) Issues in Realist Criminology. London: Sage.
Pease, K. (1997), ‘Crime Prevention’ in M. Maguire, R. Morgan and R. Reiner
(eds) The Oxford Handbook Of Criminology, second edition, Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
Pease, K. (1999) ‘A Review of Street Lighting Evaluations: Crime Reduction
Effects’, in Painter, K. and Tilley, N. (eds) Crime Prevention Studies, Vol 10 pp 47–
76. Special edition entitled ‘Surveillance of Public Space: CCTV, Street Lighting
and Crime Prevention’.
Phillips, C. and Brown, D. (1998) Entry into the Criminal Justice System: a Survey of
Police Arrests and their Outcomes, Home Office Research Study No. 185. London:
Home Office.
Phillips, C. (1999) ‘A review of CCTV Evaluations: Crime Reduction Effects and
Attitudes Towards its Use’ in Painter, K. and Tilley, N. (eds) Crime Prevention
Studies, Vol 10 pp. 123–156. Special edition entitled ‘Surveillance of Public
Space: CCTV, Street Lighting and Crime Prevention’.
Plummer, K. (1979) ‘Misunderstanding labelling perspectives’, in D. Downes and
P. Rock (eds) Deviant Interpretations. Oxford: Martin Robertson.
Pick, D. (1989) Faces of Degeneration: A European Disorder. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Police Foundation/Policy Studies Institute (1996) The Role and Responsibilities of the
Police: Report of an Independent Inquiry. London: Police Foundation/Policy
Studies Institute.
Policy Studies Institute (PSI) (1983) Police and People in London, vol IV, D. J. Smith
and J. Gray, The Police in Action. London: PSI.
Pollak, O. (1961) The Criminality of Women. New York: A. S. Barnes.
Poyner, B. (1988) ‘Video Cameras and Bus Vandalism’, Journal of Security and
Administration, no. 11, pp. 44–51.
Poyner, B. (1992) ‘Situational Crime Prevention in Two Parking Facilities’, in R.
Clarke, (ed.), Situational Crime Prevention: Successful Case Studies, New York:
Harrow and Heston.
Prentky, R., Burgess, A., Rokous, F., Lee, A., Hartman, C., Ressler, R. and Douglas, J.
(1989) ‘The presumptive role of fantasy in serial sexual homicide’, American
Journal of Psychiatry, 146: 887–91.
Punch, M. and Naylor, T. (1973) ‘The police: a secret social service’, New Society, 24:
358–61.

Raine, A. (1993) The Psychopathology of Crime. San Diego, CA: Academic Press.

192
Bibliography

Reckless, W. C. (1961) The Crime Problem. New York: Appleton, Century Crofts.
Reeve, A. (1998) ‘The Panopticisation of Shopping: CCTV and Leisure
Consumption’, in C. Norris, J. Moran and G. Armstrong (eds), Surveillance,
Closed Circuit Television and Social Control, Aldershot: Ashgate.
Reiner, R. (1992) The Politics of the Police, 2nd edn. London: Wheatsheaf.
Reiss, A. (1980) ‘Police brutality’, in R. Lundman (ed) Police Behaviour. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Ressler, R., Burgess, A. and Douglas, J. (1988) Sexual Homicide: Patterns and Motives.
Lexington, MA: Lexington Books.
Rice, M. (1990) ‘Challenging orthodoxies in feminist theory: a black feminist
critique’, in Gelsthorpe, L. and Morris. A. (eds) Feminist Perspectives in
Criminology. Buckingham: Open University Press.
Rock, P. (1973) Deviant Behaviour. London: Hutchinson.
Rock, P. (1997) ‘Sociological theories of crime’, in M. Maguire, R. Morgan, and R.
Reiner (eds) The Oxford Handbook of Criminology, 2nd edn. Oxford: Clarendon.
Rose, D. (1996) In the Name of the Law. London: Vintage.
Roshier, B. (1989), Controlling Crime: The Classical Perspective in Criminology,
Buckingham, Open University Press.
Rotter, J. B. (1975) ‘Some problems and misconceptions related to the construct of
internal versus external control of reinforcement’, Journal of Consulting and
Clinical Psychology, 43: 56–67.
Royal Commission on Criminal Justice (1993) Report. Cm 2263. London: HMSO.
Rozenberg, J. (1992) ’Miscarriages of Justice’ in E. Stockdale and S. Casale (eds)
Criminal Justice Under Stress, London: Blackstone.
Rubinstein, J. (1973) City Police. New York: Ballantine.
Rutter, M. (1972) Maternal Deprivation Reassessed. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Rutter, M. (1981) Maternal Deprivation Reassessed, 2nd edn. Harmondsworth:
Penguin.
Rutter, M. and Giller, H. (1983) Juvenile Delinquency: Trends and Perspectives.
Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Rutter, M. Giller, H. and Hagell, A. (1998) Antisocial Behavior by Young People.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Sanders, A., Bridges, L., Mulvaney, A. and Crozier, G. (1989) Advice and Assistance
at Police Stations and the 24 Hour Duty Solicitor Scheme. London: Lord Chancellors
Dept.
Sanders, A. and Young, R. (1994) Criminal Justice. London: Butterworths.
Sarno, C. (1996), ‘The Impact of Closed Circuit Television on Crime in Sutton Town
Centre’, in M. Bulos and D. Grant (eds), Towards a Safer Sutton? CCTV One Year
On, London: London Borough of Sutton.
Schulsinger, F. (1977) ‘Psychopathy: heredity and environment’, in S. Mednick and
K. Christiansen (eds) Biosocial Bases of Criminal Behaviour. New York: Gardner
Press.
Schur, E. (1971) Labeling Deviant Behavior. New York: Harper and Row.
Schwendinger, H. and Schwendinger J. (1970) ‘Defenders of order or guardians of
human rights?’ Issues in Criminology, 5: 123–57.
Scraton, P. and Chadwick, K. (1991) ‘The theoretical and political priorities of
critical criminology’, in K. Stenson and D. Cowell (eds) The Politics of Crime

193
Introducing Criminology

Control. London: Sage.


Sellar, W. C. and Yeatman, R. J. (1930) 1066 and All That, 6th edn. London: Methuen.
Sellin, T. (1938) Culture Conflict and Crime. New York: Social Science Research
Council.
Seltzer, M. (1998) Serial Killers: Death and Life in America’s Wound Culture. London:
Routledge.
Sharp, D. and Wilson D. (2000) ‘”Household Security”: Private Policing and
Vigilantism in Doncaster’, The Howard Journal, 39: 113–131.
Shaw, C. and McKay, H. (1942) Juvenile Delinquency and Urban Areas. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Shearing, C. and Stenning, P. (eds) (1987) Private Policing. Newbury Park, CA: Sage.
Sheldon, W. H. (1949) Varieties of Delinquent Youth. New York: Harper.
Short, E. and Ditton, J. (1995), ‘Does CCTV Affect Crime?’, CCTV Today, vol. 2, no. 2,
pp. 10–12.
Short, E. and Ditton, J. (1996), Does Closed Circuit Television Prevent Crime? An
Evaluation of the Use of CCTV Surveillance Cameras in Airdrie Town Centre.
Edinburgh: The Scottish Office Central Research Unit.
Short, J. and Strodtbeck, F. (1965) Group Process and Gang Delinquency. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Sim, J., Scraton, P. and Gordon, P. (1987) ‘Introduction: crime, the state and critical
analysis’, in P. Scraton (ed) Law, Order and the Authoritarian State. Milton Keynes:
Open University Press.
Skinns, D. (1998), ‘Crime Reduction, Diffusion and Displacement: Evaluating
the Effectiveness of CCTV’ in C. Norris, J. Moran, and G. Armstrong
(eds), Surveillance, Closed Circuit Television and Social Control, Aldershot:
Ashgate.
Skogan, W. (1990) The Police and the Public in England and Wales: A British Crime
Survey Report, Home Office Research Study No. 117. London HMSO.
Skogan, W. (1994) Contacts between Police and Public: Findings from the 1992 British
Crime Survey, Home Office Research Study No. 134. London: HMSO.
Slapper, G. and Tombs, S. (1999) Corporate Crime. Harlow: Longman.
Smart, C. (1976) Women, Crime and Criminology. London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul.
Smart, S. (1990) ‘Feminist approaches to criminology or postmodern woman meets
atavistic man’, in Gelsthorpe, L. and Morris. A. (eds) Feminist Perpectives in
Criminology. Buckingham: Open University Press.
Smith, D. (1997) ‘Ethnic origins, crime and criminal justice’, in M. Maguire, R.
Morgan, and R. Reiner (eds) The Oxford Handbook of Criminology, 2nd edn.
Oxford: Clarendon.
Smith, H. (1981), Strategies of Social Research, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall
Smith, J. (1989) ‘There’s only one Yorkshire Ripper’, in J. Smith, Misogynies.
London: Faber.
Soothill, K. (1993) ‘The serial killer industry’, Journal of Forensic Psychiatry, 4: 341–
54.
South, N. (1998) ‘Corporate and state crimes against the environment’, in V.
Ruggiero, N. South and I. Taylor (eds) The New European Criminology. London:
Routledge.
Southgate, P. and Ekblom, P. (1986) Police-Public Encounters, Home Office Research

194
Bibliography

Study No. 90. London: HMSO.


Squires, P. (1998a) The East Grinstead Town Centre CCTV Scheme: An Independent
Evaluation. Brighton: Health and Social Policy Research Centre, University of
Brighton.
Squires, P. (1998b) CCTV and Crime Reduction in Crawley: An Independent Evaluation
of the Crawley CCTV System. Brighton: Health and Social Policy Research Centre,
University of Brighton.
Squires, P. (1998c) CCTV and Crime Prevention in Burgess Hill Town Centre: An
Independent Evaluation. Brighton: Health and Social Policy Research Centre,
University of Brighton.
Squires, P. (1998d) An Evaluation of the Ilford Town Centre CCTV System. Brighton:
Health and Social Policy Research Centre, University of Brighton.
Squires, P. and Measor, L. (1996) Closed Circuit TV Surveillance and Crime Prevention
in Brighton: Half Yearly Report. Brighton: Health and Social Policy Research
Centre, University of Brighton.
Squires, P. and Measor, L. (1997) CCTV Surveillance and Crime Prevention in Brighton:
Follow-up Analysis. Brighton: Health and Social Policy Research Centre,
University of Brighton.
Stanko, E. (1985) Intimate Intrusions. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Steer, D. (1980) Uncovering Crime, Royal Commission on Criminal Procedure,
Research Study No. 7: London: HMSO.
Stevens, P. and Willis, C. (1979) Race, Crime and Arrests, Home Office Research
Study No. 58. London: HMSO.
Sumner, C. (ed) (1990) Censure, Politics and Criminal Justice. Milton Keynes: Open
University Press.
Sutherland, E. (1940) ‘White-collar criminality’, American Sociological Review, 5: 1–
12.
Sutherland, E. (1945) ‘Is “white-collar crime” crime?’, American Sociological Review,
10: 132–9.
Sutherland, E. (1947) Principles of Criminology, 4th edn. Philadelphia: Lippincott.
Sutherland, E. (1949) White-collar Crime. New York: Holt Rinehart and Winston.
Sutherland, E. and Cressey, D. (1960) Principles of Criminology, 6th edn. Chicago:
Lippincott.
Sykes, R. and Brent, E. (1983) Policing: A Social Behaviorist Perspective. New
Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.

Tame, C. (1991) ‘Freedom, responsibility and justice: the criminology of the “New
Right”’, in K. Stenson and D. Cowell (eds) The Politics of Crime Control. London:
Sage.
Tappan, P. (1947) ‘Who is the criminal?’ American Sociological Review, 12: 96–102.
Taylor, I. (1999) Crime in Context: A Critical Criminology of Market Societies. Oxford:
Polity.
Taylor, I., Walton, P. and Young, J. (1973) The New Criminology. London: Routledge
and Kegan Paul.
Taylor, I., Walton, P. and Young, J. (eds) (1975) Critical Criminology. London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Thornton, D. M. and Reid, R. L. (1982) ‘Moral reasoning and the type of criminal
offence’, British Journal of Social Psychology, 21: 231–8.

195
Introducing Criminology

Tilley, N. (1998), ‘Evaluating the Effectiveness of CCTV Schemes’ in C. Norris, J.


Moran and G. Armstrong (eds), Surveillance, Closed Circuit Television and Social
Control, Aldershot: Ashgate.
Trasler, G. (1962) The Explanation of Criminality. London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul.
Trasler, G. (1986) ‘Situational crime control and rational choice: a critique’, in K.
Heal and G. Laycock (eds) Situational Crime Prevention. London: HMSO.

Waddington, P. (1986) ‘Mugging as a moral panic’, British Journal of Sociology, 37:


245–59.
Waddington, P. (1993) Calling the Police. Aldershot: Gower.
Waddington, P. (1999) Policing Citizens. London: UCL Press.
Walker, M., Jefferson, T., and Seneviratne, M. (1990) Ethnic Minorities, Young People
and the Criminal Justice System. Sheffield: Centre for Criminological and Socio-
legal Studies, University of Sheffield.
Walklate, S. (1995) Gender and Crime. Hemel Hempstead: Prentice Hall.
Walklate, S. (1998) Understanding Criminology. Buckingham: Open University
Press.
Walton, P. and Young, J. (eds) (1998) The New Criminology Revisited. Basingstoke:
Macmillan.
Ward Jouve, N. (1988) ‘The Street-cleaner’: the Yorkshire Ripper Case on Trial. London:
Marion Boyars.
Webster, C. (2000), ‘Relegitimating the Democratic Polity: The Closed Circuit
Television Revolution in the UK’, in Horrocks, I. Moff, J. and Topps, P. (eds)
Democratic Governance and New Technology: Technologically Mediated Innovations
in Political Practices in Western Europe, London: Routledge.
Weiss, R. (1987) ‘The Community and Crime Prevention’, in E. Johnson (ed.),
Handbook on Crime and Delinquency Prevention, New York: Greenwood Press.
Werner, E. E. (1989) ‘High risk children in young adulthood’, American Journal of
Orthopsychiatry, 59: 72–81.
White, R. and Haines, F. (1996) Crime and Criminology: An Introduction. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Wikström, P.-O. ‘Delinquency and the urban stucture’, in P.-O. Wikström (ed)
Crime and Measures Against Crime in the City. Stockholm: National Council for
Crime Prevention.
Willis, C. (1983) The Use, Effectiveness and Impact of Police Stop and Search Powers,
Research and Planning Unit Paper No. 15. London: Home Office.
Wilson, J. (1975) Thinking About Crime. New York: Basic Books.
Wilson, J. and Herrnstein, R. (1985) Crime and Human Nature. New York: Simon and
Schuster.
Woodcock, J. (1992) Trust in the Police – the search for truth. International Police
Exhibition and Conference (IPEC) Seminar Paper Reprints. London: Major
Exhibitions and Conferences Ltd.

Van Maanen, J. (1978) ‘The asshole’, in P. Manning and J. Van Maanen (eds)
Policing: A View From the Street. Santa Monica, CA: Goodyear.

Yablonsky, L. (1962) The Violent Gang. London: Pelican.

196
Bibliography

Yochelson, S. and Samenow, S. (1976) The Criminal Personality. New York: Jason
Aronson.
Young, J. (1971) The Drugtakers. London: Paladin.
Young, J. (1981) ‘Thinking seriously about crime’, in M. Fitzgerald, G. McLennan
and J. Pawson (eds) Crime and Society: Readings in History and Theory. London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Young, J. (1986) ‘The failure of criminology’, in R. Matthews and J. Young (eds)
Confronting Crime. London: Sage.
Young, J. (1994) ‘Incessant chatter: current paradigms in criminology’, in M.
Maguire, R. Morgan, and R. Reiner (eds) The Oxford Handbook of Criminology.
Oxford: Clarendon.
Young, J. (1997) ‘Left realist criminology’, in M. Maguire, R. Morgan, and R. Reiner
(eds) The Oxford Handbook of Criminology, 2nd edn. Oxford: Clarendon.
Young, J. (1999) The Exclusive Society. London: Sage.
Young, M. (1991) An Inside Job. Oxford: Clarendon.

197
Introducing Criminology

Index

Anomie 61–63, 67, 80 economics of 163–165


effectiveness 150–151, 153–154
Biological approaches to effects of 169–171
criminology 28–31 evaluation methodology 151–
adoptees 28–29 165
body types 27–28 experimental design 161–165
brain 29 external validity 156
environment 29 methodological problems
epilepsy 29 151–153
genetics 28 changes to area 158–159
head injuries 29 crime rate 153–156, 159–
hyperactivity 29 161
physical characteristics 27–28 displacement 156–158
physiology 30 reactivity 159
psychology 30 realistic evaluation
twin studies 28 evaluation studies 161–165,
British Crime Survey 122, 153, 156 165–169
Burglary 123, 154, 167 history factor 158
indecency 168
Cambridge Institute of management of 152
Criminology 73 other variables 159
Car crime public awareness of 171
See Vehicle crime publicity 164, 171
Causing death by dangerous or random fluctuations 159–160
careless driving 88 robbery 168
CCTV 4, 146–176, 179 shop-lifting 162–165, 168
city centres 150, 157–160, 166– systems 152–153, 164–165, 170
169, 171, 174–175 technical aspects 152
criminal damage 167 town centre schemes 150
crime displacement 156–158 vandalism 168
crime reduction 153–171 victimization surveys 154
deployment 152 women 173
discrimination 172–175 Children 33–34

198
Index

abuse 45, 110 Epistemological relativism 83


rearing 69 Ethnic cleansing 12, 98
City structure 57 Evaluation 151–165
Conduct norms 7–8
Consumerism 83 Fear of crime 81
Control theory 67–69 Federal Bureau of Investigation
biological control theory 67 Behavioural Sciences Unit 111
psychological control theory 67 Feminism 77–79, 82, 85, 110
sociological control theory 67– feminist empiricism 78
68 knowledge 79
social bond theory 67 liberal feminism 78
social control 67 postmodern feminism 78
Corporate crime 8, 12, 60 radical feminism 78
Council housing 58 socialist feminism 78
Crime, definition of 6–13 standpoint feminism 78
prevention 46–47, 146–149
evaluation experimental design Gangs 64–67
161–165 Genocide 132, 98
Crime rates 135, 154 Global information and
random fluctuations 159–160 communication technologies 83
Crime statistics 14, 20, 52, 133
Criminal, definition of 6–13 HOLMES 113
Criminal law 13 Home Office 49, 73, 80, 8265, 102,
Criminalization 12, 72, 85, 178 112–113, 115
Criminal subculture 58 Housing market 58
Criminology Human rights 10–11, 13
classical school of 17–20
conservative criminology 51 Imperialism 10
definition 13–14 Infanticide 88
development of 16–24 Institute for the Study and Treatment
in Britain 23–25 of Delinquency 32
Italian positive school of 21–22, Institutional anomie theory 63
24 Interactionism 117–118
Lombroso 16, 21–24
moral statisticians 20–21 Juvenile delinquency 57, 64–66
neo–classicism 19
positivism 19 King Charles I 88
Critical criminology 76
Cultural goal of success 62 Labelling 12, 70–72, 74, 84
Cultural patterns 58 deviancy amplification 71
Cultural transmission 57 folk devil 71
moral panic 71, 74, 80, 111
Deconstruction 84 secondary deviation 72
Deprivation 64, 148 Law enforcement 14, 117–118
Differential association 35–36, 57 Left realism 66
Differential social organization 58 Local crime surveys 81
Domestic violence 12
Drugs, Manslaughter 88
addiction 147 Maps 57
dealing 157 Mass media 14, 64, 71, 80, 112
press reports 93
Environment 57–58 Miscarriages of justice 118, 142
Environmental crime 61 Modernist project 82–84

199
Introducing Criminology

Moral statisticians 57 spree murder 89


Mugging 71, 157
Murder 88 Neighbourhood reputations 58–59
mass murder 88–89 Neighbourhood watch 162
multiple murder 88, 92 ‘New right’ conservatism 75
serial killers 178
typology 95 Occupational crime 60
serial murder 87–115, 178 Offences,
biological approach to 99– spatial distribution 57–59
101 Offender profiling 90–91, 113
abnormal brain activity Offenders 2, 26
101 biology of 26
head trauma 100 population 54
hormone imbalance 101 psychology of 26
hypoglycaemia 101 spatial distribution 57–59
nervous system versus non-offenders 26, 43
characteristics 101
psychomotor epilepsy 101 Portman Clinic 32
serotonin level 101 Psychopathic Clinic 32
XYY syndrome 100 Peterloo 116
case studies 114–115 Police 116–147, 178
confessions 112–113 arrests 134
definition 88 Association of Chief Police
extent of 91–92 Officers 121
increases in 93–94 calls on 121–124, 136
psychological approach to children 127
101–107 corruption 142
antisocial personality crime prevention 14, 117, 120
disorder 105 crime reporting 153
dissociative disorders criminology and 117
103–104 culture 138–139
maintaining factors 105– detectives 124
106 discretion 119, 130–133, 135
multiple personality discrimination 119, 133–137
disorder 103 dispute settlement 129
predisposing factors 105 efficiency 92, 118, 132–133
psychological profiling evidence 142
113 history 116–117
psychoanalysis 102 informers 142
psychopathy 104–105 interpretational latitude 132
psychosis 103 law enforcement 121–122, 129–
situational factors 100 130
trauma–control model malpractice 119, 143
106–107 patrols 123, 176
sociological approach to 107– Police Federation 121
112 Police Foundation 126
gender 109–110 Posen Inquiry 126
insecurity 109 racism 136
mass media 111–112 resources 132
social constructionist role 119–130, 152, 154
approach 111 Royal Commission on the Police
social control agencies 117 120–121
strain theory 109 service tasks 121–122, 125–126

200
Index

stops 134 rational choice theory 47–50


subculture 135 self-concept 44–45
Superintendents’ Association self-control 44
121 socialization 38
uniform 117 social interaction 46
use of force 127–128 social learning theories 40
Policing 14, 119
black people 133–137 Rape 77
by consent 132 Radical criminologies 72–76
crime control model 141–142, feminist criminologies 77–79
145 left idealism 80–81
definition 119, 125 left realism 66, 73, 75, 79–81, 86
domestic violence 136–137 the square of crime 80
due process model 140–142, 145 Marxism 74–75
ethnic groups 137 National Deviancy Conference
intensity 137 73–74
national policing objectives 131 Recorded crime 153–154
private security industry 120 Routine activities theory 59
reactive 123–124 Royal Commission on Criminal
Police and Criminal Evidence Act Justice 135, 142
140, 144
Policy Studies Institute 126 Secondary deviation 72
Prison medical officers 31–32 Self-report studies of offending 10, 38,
Prohibition 7 58, 60, 91, 133, 135
Public order 118, 130 Sexism 10
Punishment 14, 74 Shop-lifting 162–165
Population turnover 58 Social class 58, 64
Postmodernism 82–86 Social disorganization 57, 67
Postmodernist constitutive theory 85 Social learning 69
Poverty 10 Sociology 14
Prisoners 7, 23 Sociological approaches to
Psychiatry 23 criminology
Psychology 14, 26, 30 anomie 61–64
Psychological approaches to control theory 67–69
criminology 31–50 cultural transmission 57
behaviour 32, 40, 50 deviancy amplification 71
characteristics of individuals 50 gangs 45, 64–67
cognitive approaches 41–45 labelling 70–71
conditioning 36–37, 52–53 relationships 46
egocentrism 46 social disorganization 57–58
empathy 46 social skills 46
experiences 33 strain theory 63
family background 34 subcultural theories 45, 66
hyperactivity 54 subcultures 64–65
impulsiveness 52, 54 Strain theory 63, 69, 109
learning theories 35–41, 45 Street crime 81
maternal deprivation 34 Subcultures 64–68, 80
mental processes 32 Symbolic interactionism 69–70
moral development 42–43,
personality 37, 39, 41–42 Torture 12
psychiatry 31, 50 Typologies 97–98
psychoanalysis 32–35
physiology 32 United States Department ofJustice 111

201
Introducing Criminology

Vehicle crime War crimes 98


death by dangerous or careless White-collar crime 8–9, 12, 36, 60–61,
driving 88 69
radio theft 66 Women 76–77
road tax 173 as offenders 77, 79
thefts from 153, 158, 167 crime rates 76
thefts of 167–168 in criminology 77
vehicle security 147, 157 in social control 77
Victims 14, 75 serial killer typology 96
Victimization surveys 58, 60, 82, 91, victims 77, 79, 110
133, 154
Zonal hypothesis 57

202

You might also like