Cognitive Functions of Language According To G. W. Leibniz: Halina Święczkowska
Cognitive Functions of Language According To G. W. Leibniz: Halina Święczkowska
Halina Święczkowska
University of Bialystok
1 See H. Ishiguro, Leibniz’s Philosophy of Logic and Language, second edition, Cam-
bridge University Press 1990, p. 8–16.
46
Cognitive Functions of Language according to G. W. Leibniz
3 Let us quote here the fragment of Leiniz’s manuscript which remains in Leibniz’s
Archives in Niedersächsischen Landensbibliothek in Hannover, sign. IV, VII, B, 3,16 r
where the author explains what he means by the function of sign: “La plus part de nos
raisonnemens, sur tout ceux qui s’entremelent dans les principales veues, se font par un
jeu de caractères, comme on joue du clavesin pr coustume en partie, sans que l’ame en
cela s’en apperçoive assez, et forge les raisons avec reflexion. Autrement on parleroit trop
lentement. Cela sert a mieux entendre comment (l’ame) le corps exprime par ses propres
loix tout ce qui passe dans l’ame. Car ce jeu de caractères peult aller loin et va loin
en effect, jusqu’à un point qu’on ne pourrait penser des choses abstraites sans aide de
caractères arbitraires”. Quoted after M. Dascal, Leibniz. Language, Signs and Thought,
Foreword, s. VII, John Benjamis Publishing Company, Amsterdam/Philadelphia 1990.
4 G. W. Leibniz, Unvorgeiffliche Gedancken betreffend die Ausubung und Verbessrung
der Teutschen Sprache, in: G. W. Leibniz, Collectanea Etymologica, Hanoverae 1717, § 5:
“Es ist aber bey dem Gebrauch der Sprache, auch dieses sonderlich zu betrachten, dass
die Worte nicht nur der Gedancken, sondern auch der Dinge Zeichen seyn, und dass
wir Zeichen nötchig haben, nicht nur unsere Meynung andern anzudeuten, sondern auch
unsern Gedancken selbst zu helffen. Den gleichwie man in grossen Handels-Städten, auch
im Spiel und sonsten nicht allezeit Geld zahlet, sondern sich an dessen Statt der Zeddel
oder Marcken, biss zur letzen Abrechnung oder Zahlung bedienet; also thut auch der
Verstand mit den Bildnissen der Dinge, zumahl wenn er viel zu dencken hat, dass er
nehmlich Zeichen dafür brauchet, damit er nicht nöthig habe, die Sache iedesmahl so offt
sie vorkomt, von neuen zu bedencken. Daher wenn es sie einmahl wohl geftasset, begnügt
er sich hernach offt, nicht nur in äusserrlichen Reden, sondern auch in den Gedancken
und innerlichen Selbst-Gespräch das Wort and die Stelle der Sache zu setzen”.
5 See G. W. Leibniz, New Essays Concerning Human Understanding (Ed. A. G. Lan-
gley), The Macmillan Company, London 1896, Book III, Ch. ix, p. 370.
6 G. W. Leibniz, Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe 6 Reihen, Darmstadt 1923, Berlin
1950, Leipzig 1983, later in the text referred to as AA (and quoted as volume, part, page)
VI ii, 500: “Signum est quod nunc sentimus et alioquin cum aliquo connexum esse ex priore
experientia nostra vel aliena judicamus”. See also G. W. Leibniz Opuscules et Fragments
Inédits de Leibniz, L. Couturat (ed.) Paris 1903 (later in the text referred to as C), p. 497.
7 M. Dascal, Leibniz. Language, Signs and Thought, op. cit., p. 31.
47
Halina Święczkowska
8 AA VI ii, 500.
9 AA VI i, 278: “Verba enim non tantúm signa sunt cogitationis meae praesentis ad
alios, sed et notae cogitationis meae praeteritae ad me ipsum, ut demonstravit Th. Hobbes
principio Elementorum de Corpore”.
10 T. Hobbes, De Corpore, 1,1,3 – subsequent numbers represent chapter, part and frag-
ment, in: T. Hobbes, The English works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, W. Molesworth
(ed.) London 1839–1845, vol. IV. See M. Dascal, Leibniz. Language, Signs and Thougth,
op. cit.
11 T. Hobbes, De Corpore, I, 2, 2. See M. Dascal, Leibniz. Language, Signs and Thought,
op. cit., p. 32 and following.
48
Cognitive Functions of Language according to G. W. Leibniz
For Hobbes, the difference between the signs and concepts comes down
to the difference of function.12 Signs serve to reveal our thoughts to oth-
ers whereas concepts are to refer to themselves or to recall themselves to
ourselves. Although both functions are very clearly distinguished, it appears
that they are not independent for Hobbes. The mnemonic-recalling function
of the concept is in some sense basic. While we can easily realize the con-
cepts that are not signs, or those we use only for our personal use, without
any communicative value, a reverse process is not possible. Therefore, to
have a communicative function each sign should be a concept itself or it has
to be connected with the concept which “fixes” the thought transmitted by
that sign.
Priority or superiority of the mnemonic function over a communicative
one is illustrated, according to Hobbes, by natural languages. Words or,
precisely, names have a dual function of signs and concepts, but most of
all they are concepts, and then signs. He claims that no name taken in
isolation can fulfill a communicative function. It is simply lacking. Only
when words and names come together in a sentence, they begin to fulfill
their sign function, that is, they transmit the thought of its recipient.13
It is worth noting here that Hobbes takes a particular point of view.
Signs and concepts are treated by him as tools in the development of sci-
ence and philosophy. In this sense, he concentrates rather on the language
of science than on everyday language. Of course, he also indicates the use
of language for pleasure and decoration, but it is a marginal use. However,
a social function of language, conditioned by the existence of the social con-
sensus as to how to apply signs, is nothing more but a transfer of knowledge
necessary for functioning of the society from one generation to another.14
According to Hobbes, there is a certain hierarchy of sign functions, sub-
ordinated to the development of science. In order to achieve the advance-
ment of knowledge, transmission of information is needed, because only in
12 T. Hobbes, De Corpore, I, 2, 3.
13 T. Hobbes, De Corpore, I, 2, 3: “[...] nomina per se singula notae sunt, nam cogitata
revocant etiam solas, signa vore non sunt, nisi quatenus in oratione disponuntur et partes
ejus sunt. Verbi gratia, vox homo excitât quidem in audiente ideam hominis, non tamen
(nisi quis addat, est animal, vel aliud aliquid aequivalens) significat aliquam ideam fuisse
in animo loquentis, sed voluisse eum aliquid dicere, quod potuit quidem incipere a voce
homo, potuit vero etiam a voce homogeneum. Natura itaque nominis consistit primario in
eo quod serviat quoque significandis, demonstrandisque ils rebus quas memoria tenemus”.
Let us note that Hobbes recognizes the correct unit of communication, which is a sentence,
not a name or a word. This discovery could provide a starting point for the semantics of
sentences, radically different from the traditional semantics, which focuses mainly on the
word. Unfortunately, neither Hobbes nor his succesors developed this idea.
14 T. Hobbes, Lewiathan, eBooks@Adelaide 2007, I, 4, 5.
49
Halina Święczkowska
this way the experience of the past eras can be accumulated. But fragments
of knowledge are acquired in reasoning. Therefore, it is necessary to be capa-
ble of indicating our thoughts and recalling their relationship. A hierarchy
of sign functions can be represented as follows:
– advancement of knowledge,
– information, communication,
– discovery by reasoning,
– indication and recalling thoughts.
In accordance with the above-mentioned considerations, concepts, for
Hobbes, have only the last function. This mnemonic function is essential
for the remaining ones and in this sense all the others, especially reason-
ing, depend on the use of meaningful concepts. However, concepts, though
necessary, serve a supportive role in the very reasoning. Reasoning (con-
version) directly affects ideas and thoughts evoked by concepts – (...an-
imo, sine verbis, tacita cogitationes ratiocinando addere et substrahere sole-
mus).15 The use of concepts in reasoning is therefore indispensable in the
sense that in the mind they evoke the content that is necessary to start this
process and sustain it. The reasoning in itself is a process of thinking in
which there is no room for the use of any meaningful signs.16
It is only in this context that Hobbes’s attack on algebraic symbolism
is understood. He writes in De Corpore: “The so-called ‘symbolics’ used
by many scholars who believe that it is truly analytical, is neither ana-
lytic nor symbolic. It is only a simple shortcut of mathematical accounts,
but not geometric, because it does not add anything to the learning or
teaching of geometry, and is just a quick and short summary of what has
already been discovered by geometricians. Even if the use of symbols can
facilitate the discourse of the judgements distant from each other, I am not
sure whether this symbolic discourse could be cosnidered as useful if things
corresponding to the idea are taken into account”.17 Therefore, Hobbes ar-
15 T. Hobbes, De Corpore, I, 1, 3.
16 The interpretation of Hobbes presented here is proposed by M. Dascal (Leibniz.
Language, Signs and Thought, op. cit., s. 34); it differs from the interpretation presented
by W. Kneale and M. Kneale in: Developement of Logic, The Clarendon Press, Oxford
1962, p. 312 and others assuming that for Hobbes thinking is merely an operation on
signs. The reason for these differences is a lack of certainty on this issue on Hobbes’s part.
In Leviathan, op. cit., Part I, Chapter 5, he actually presents thinking as an operation
on general names and adds that science is nothing more but the acquisition of knowledge
being the consequence derived from names in the subject. Although at the beginning of
the same part of Leviathan he shows this type of reasoning as a possible rather than
necessary characteristic of all types of reasoning. Moreover, he assumes the existence of
a purely mental discourse, different and completely independent of verbal discourse.
17 T. Hobbes, De Corpore, III, 20.
50
Cognitive Functions of Language according to G. W. Leibniz
gues that algebraic symbols allow only to shorten reasoning; their didactic
value is also questionable. A symbolic discourse is secondary to the pro-
cess of thought whose constitutive elements include ideas or performance,
and that, in his opinion, is sufficient to challenge the cognitive usefulness
of symbolism itself, its role is purely marginal. A sign does not constitute
thinking being only capable of its acceleration; a mnemonic function is its
basic function.
There is no doubt that Leibniz’s views on the functions of the language
sign were shapened by the critical analysis of Hobbes’s works. In Nova
Methodus Docendaeque Jurisprudentiae he lists mnemonics as one of the
disciplines treating about human ‘habits’ which has to do with memory.
Analitics and topos respectively deal with judging and discovering. To keep
order, he also adds methodology; all these disciplines make didactics.18 Leib-
niz accepts the existence of some objects of thought called judgements typ-
ical for men which we can recall, judge, discover and organize. Signs are
only considered in terms of recalling. Thus, the analysis of signs is treated
as part of mnemonics. It is interesting that what was said in the first edi-
tion (1667) is repeated by Leibniz in the second edition (1697). The only
novelty is the inclusion of natural languages in the semiotic systems assign-
ing them a mnemonic function as their primary function. Hence, linguistics
is subordinated to mnemonics.
However, in his studies on mnemonics Leibniz is original and goes
beyond his contemporaries. He draws attention to specific techniques of
memorizing linking the sign with the sound, encoding information with
the use of cryptograms; moreover, he analyzes signs and stylistic figures
in terms of their suitability for archiving data. The sign constitutes the ba-
sis for mnemonics, being a sensuous object remaining in a definite relation
to things.19
Symbolic thinking
51
Halina Święczkowska
discussion, he recommends the use of special signs that indicate how each
argument for and against is part of the law elements and other laws. Thus,
if the argument is based on the opposition, the suggested marking looks as
follows: )( when it relates to the similarity: (), causes: 0-; effects: -0 etc.20
The function of these signs is to point out the obvious relationship between
the premises and the conclusion, the user is experiencing this kind of ob-
vious relationship immediately, and symbolism allows him to capture all
the dependencies immediately and without any effort. The word ‘intuition’
is a key concept here which captures the essence of such an approach. The
possibility of obtaining such a result by means of the signs makes symbolsim
an essential tool of reasoning.
Leibniz explains the essence of this mechanism by referring to arith-
metic symbolism: “Suppose someone learns Arithmetic, including, e.g., the
pythagorean table. What does he learn? Does he learn something new, ex-
cept the words? When I learn that two multiplied by two is four, do I learn
more than a numeral name, whose use – afterwards – in speaking and cal-
culating is more economical? And Yet, without such words, or any other
constant signs in their places, Arithmetic would be completely useless for
us Therefore, it is true to say that he who learns only matters of reason,
theorems, and definitions, does not in fact learn anything but how to use
what is already known. Thus, nobody could calculate, especially with very
large numbers, without names or numerical signs, i.e., if he had to imagine
distinctly, for each number, all the units comprised in it. Who intended,
could imagine distinctly the units contained in 1.000.000.000.000 in a time
shorter than the age of Methuselach? And even if he could, he would forget
the first units as he progressed towards the end.”21
Therefore no long argumentation can do without the use of certain
names or symbolism. It is thanks to them, according to Leibniz, that a huge
number of things can be covered in the way that makes it possible to run
through them very quickly, which would be impossible, if their definitions
were used instead of the names and symbols. However, it is essential to
note that a necessary condition for the correctness of the whole process
of reasoning is the knowledge of the meaning of the symbols used, that
is the ability to provide their appropriate definitions. The intellectual pro-
cess, whose integral part is the operation on symbols, is called blind or
52
Cognitive Functions of Language according to G. W. Leibniz
53
Halina Święczkowska
29 List Leibniza do Jean’a Gallois z września 1677, AA II i, 381: “La veritable methode
nous doit fournir un filum Ariadnes, c’est à dire un certain moyen sensibile et grossier, qvi
conduise l’esprit comme sont les lignes tracées en geometrie, et les formes des operations
qu’on prescrit aux apprentifs en Arithmetiqve”.
30 G. W. Leibniz, New Essays..., Book IV, Ch. XVI, p. 559.
31 See Leibniz’s letter to Walter von Tschirnaus written in May 1678, in: G. W. Leibniz,
Philosophical Papers and Letters, L. E. Loemker (ed.) D. Reidel Publisching Company,
Dordrecht 1965, p. 193. See also H. Święczkowska, La perspective platonicienne sur la
langue chez Descartes et chez Leibniz, in: “Idea. Studia nad strukturą i rozwojem pojęć
filozoficznych” VII, Białystok 1996. To understand why symbolism can play such an im-
portant role in reasoning, let us refer to modern psychology and the study of memory. The
first model of memory is represented as consisting of two distinct mechanisms of storage.
One is short time memory (STM) that captures information from the senses and keeps
it for a very short period of time. This ability is limited so that the unit of information
is only stored until it is replaced by another information unit. STM capabilities are esti-
mated numerically: approximately it can accommodate seven such units. While stored in
STM, such units of information can be encoded and transmitted to another mechanism or
tool of memory – long time memory, whose possibilities are immesurably greater. If this
process of transfer has been made, units of information are stored long enough. STM is
limited to seven units of information, which are stored at the moment, but this restriction
does not apply to the amount of information the unit contains. If we refer to the informa-
tion theory, STM can accomodate not 7 bits, but rather 7 chunks of information. Bits and
chunks differ in that the chunk may comprise many bits. For example, the number of six
digits – 101101 – contains six bits of information. If each digit is considered as a separate
54
Cognitive Functions of Language according to G. W. Leibniz
bit or chunk, storing the total number covers almost the entire STM. But if you group the
numbers in pairs, each chunk now contains two bits, while STM is used only up to some
degree. See E. R. Hilgard, R. C. Atkinson, Introduction to Psychology, Harcourt, Brace
and World, New York 1967, p. 328 and following and G. R. Miller, The magical number
seven, plus or minus two: some limits on our capacity for processing information, in: The
Psychology of Communication, Allen Lane, The Penquin Press, London 1967, p. 33 and
following. Referring to this data, M. Dascal claims that the Leibnizian uno obtutu can be
identified with STM. See M. Dascal, Leibniz. Language, Signs and Thought, op. cit., p. 38.
32 Meditationes de cognitione, veritate et ideis, GP IV, 423.
33 Leibniz’s letter to des Bosses March, 1706, GP II, 305: “Utrasque enim per modum
loquendi compendiosum pro mentis fictionibus habeo, ad calculus aptis...”
34 G. W. Leibniz, New Essays..., Book III, Ch. iii, p. 311.
35 Benson Mates, The Philosophy of Leibniz. Metaphysic and Language, Oxford Uni-
versity Press, New York, Oxford 1986, p. 171 and following.
36 G. W. Leibniz, De accidentibus, in: G. W. Leibniz, Textes inédits d’apres les
manuscrits de la bibliothèque provincial de Hanovre, G. Grua (ed.), II Vol., Presses Uni-
versitaires de France, Paris 1948, Volume II, p. 574.
55
Halina Święczkowska
know it and approve or not.”37 A little earlier he notes that “it is true you
do not see justice as you see a horse, but you understand it no less, or rather
you understand it better, it is no less in acts than directness or obliqueness
is in motion, whether you consider it or not.”38 For generality depends on
the similarity of specific things and this similarity is, according to Leibniz,
reality. In similar subjects we detect their mutual feature which is noth-
ing more but an apriori possibility of their existence.39 Leibniz calls these
creatures real abstracts and they are accidens that is, entities added to the
substance.40
However, it is difficult to find Leibniz’s clear program declarations. Re-
ferring to the medieval dispute over universals, he wrote that realists’ axiom
is as good as nominalists’ axiom as long as they are properly understood.41
It is possible to get the impression that Leibniz deliberately avoids radical
decisions in the dispute regarding the ontological status of universals di-
recting his attention rather to purely grammatical or linguistic properties
of phrases which mark abstracts or universals. He wrote in Characteris-
tica verbalis: “Words are signs either concepts, as in the case of nouns, or
of modes of conceiving, as in the case of the other parts of speech. Con-
cepts are viewed either in themselves or by accident”.42 Those that are
taken in themselves, apart from the metaphysical object or subject, as well
as the time, place and event are abstract concepts (formalitates), such as
humanity, beauty and being triplelegged. Concepts taken per accidens ex-
press the convergence of many ‘forms’ in the same subject when it happens,
for example, that the same subject has poetic and juridical abilities. Thus
names, depending on the terms they cover, fall into the abstract ones, such
as ‘warmth’, ‘humanity’ and precise ones, such as ‘man’, ‘hot’.43 There-
fore one can say that the grammatical division of names into precise and
abstract ones corresponds to the semantic division of terms into per se
56
Cognitive Functions of Language according to G. W. Leibniz
and per accidens. In the table of definitions once again Leibniz defines ab-
stracts as entities (entia) which differentiate various predicates within the
same subject. Concretum is where entia are included and what contains
no contradiction.44
In his division of names into precise and abstract ones, Leibniz noticed
some ambiguity accompanying different uses of precise names. Precise names
such as ‘man’ or ‘horse’ may have different references. In Intoduction to
Nizolius, commenting on the position of nominalists on universals who, as for
instance Nizolius, claim that universals are nothing more but taking all the
entities collectively and at the same time so that they are collective wholes,
Leibniz agrees that when we say ‘every man is an animal’ it means that all
people are animals. However, in his opinion, it does not mean that universals
are collective wholes as Nizolius claims for a whole (totum) marked by the
phrase ‘every man’ has a distributive sense apart from a collective one. If,
as Nizolius wishes, the phrases ‘omnis homo’ or ‘omnes homines’ meant the
same thing as the human species, it would lead to absurd substitutions such
as ‘The human species is an animal’.45
According to Leibniz, this confusion of terms results in more serious
consequences. If universals were nothing more but a collection of individu-
als which, as Nizolius claims, being precise totals are sets in the collective
sense, it would be impossible to arrive at any knowledge on the basis of
arguments; induction becomes the only possible way to increase knowledge.
And on that basis, according to Leibniz, it is impossible to accept any per-
fect general sentence for it is necessary to stop at the judgment that all
investigated cases are such and just such. Leibniz claims that true knowl-
edge can only be achieved through the analysis of general sentences whose
truth does not depend on induction, but on a general idea or a definition
of terms. As he writes, practical and moral certainty of the sentence ‘fire
burns’ is guaranteed by the following principles: 1. If in all cases the cause
is the same, or similar, the effect will be similar or the same. 2. The exis-
tence of the thing that is not understood is not assumed. 3. Whatever is not
assumed should be ignored in practice until you can prove it.46 Defending
the so-called general rhetoric against the Aristotelian logic and Renaissance
dialectic, Marius Nizolius sought to exclude arguing as the acknowledged
way of the explanation of the nature of things (as it was taught by Aris-
totle). Nizolius wrote that if universals are false as it was said and proved,
44 C. 437.
45 AA VI ii, 430.
46 AA VI ii, 431.
57
Halina Święczkowska
one can say that the whole dialectic they support fall down with them.47
Leibniz’s answer to this question is: This is false! Nominalists as well as
others used the dialectic of Aristotle and they were right. Although there
is seldom some truth in what people attribute to things in their names, the
thing itself is always preserved when we use names to explain things.48
In other words, for arguing it would be enough if universals were pure
names of things.49
Leibniz agrees, therefore, that the names of universals may not in fact
have any relevance, but even as compendia loquendi they are helpful in
proving and explaining the properties of things. By adopting this solution,
Leibniz meant the nominalist definition of truth, especially in the version
formulated by Hobbes. Indeed, Hobbes claimed that because truths of the
mind result from definition, definitions have a purely arbitrary character;
therefore, the same character is revealed by truths. Arbitrary definitions
are nominal definitions. According to Leibniz, they refer only to the fea-
tures necessary to differentiate a given thing from other things and they
are not sufficient to obtain certain knowledge unless it is somehow known
that the defined thing is possible.50 But although the definitions of names
are dependent on our designation, the use and link of signs, according to
Leibniz, is no longer optional. There is a constant correspondence between
signs and things, which is the “foundation of truth”.51
What does it really mean that it would be sufficient for proving if uni-
versals were pure names? It seems that Leibniz assumes that proving does
not depend on the assumptions of semantic or ontological nature and can
be built on the purely syntactic basis. Definitions of names, as nominal def-
initions, would have to meet only one condition that the defined thing is
possible. Leibniz categorically states that we cannot have an idea of the
circle. We can imagine it; we can have its definition and the idea of ev-
ery property that a circle should have. But since we cannot imagine all
47 AA VI ii, 451: “Nam Si universalia ista falsa sunt, ut nos dicimus, et probaturi
sumus, continuo una cum univesalibus Cadet pene tota Dialectica, quae in illis tanquam
columinisd fundata est...”
48 AA VI ii 451: “Hoc fal sum Est. Neque enim minus Nominales quam caeteri, Di-
alectica Aristotelis usi sunt, et recte quidem. Nam etsi in nominibus saltem vera sint
quae vulgo rebus tribuebantur, salva re est; quando nominibus istis in explicandis rebus
utimur.”
49 AA VI ii, 429: “...quod Universalia non sint in rerum natura (cum tamen sufficiat
ad demonstrandum:nomina esse universalia)...”
50 Meditationes de cognitione, veritate et ideis, GP IV, 424.
51 G. W. Leibniz, Dialogus, in: G. W. Leibniz, Phiolosophical Papers and Letters
(ed. L. Loemker), D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht 1969, p. 184.
58
Cognitive Functions of Language according to G. W. Leibniz
of them simultaneously, we cannot have the idea of it. Only God has the
insight into the complex ideas of things because he can think of every-
thing at the same time. Because of its limitations, the human mind is only
capable of recognizing the essence of the circle and other complex things
only partly. But how can we be sure of the possibility of such an idea,
that is the agreement of all the ingredients present in it, if we take into
account our intrinsic limitations? Leibniz explains that “When we do not
have an idea, its functions are performed by sensual or by definition that
is, a collection of signs. The place of idea is always filled by certain per-
ception (phantasma), which is at the same time completely understood”.52
Therefore, Leibniz assumes that the possession of these sensory percep-
tions and definitions of the circle has the same value as the statement
by experience that a circular object exists. In this sense, the formation
and transformation of signs replaces the experience if it is not available.
Therefore, signs allow to present our abstract thoughts in a ‘visible’ and
‘static’ way, and their juxtaposition is purely mechanical. Thus, argumen-
tation conducted like this is a kind of calculation where definitions can
be treated as syntactic rules allowing for the replacement of one chain of
signs by the other. With this method we are able to make decisions about
possibilities or, in other words, the consistency of such terms as infinity,
perfection or set. Thus, according to Leibniz, to discover and prove the
truth the analysis of signs itself is sufficient, provided that the signs express
some thoughts.53
However, the truth obtained in this way has the status of rational truth
which, similarly to the intuitive truth, does not require any proof. It is
necessary to remember that, according to Leibniz, all rational truths refer
to the sphere of possibility. Hence it means that they are not existential
judgments. Rational truths state what would be true in any possible case,
whereas true existential judgments depend on God’s choice of some possible
world. So when we say that ‘a triangle has three sides’ we do not state that
there are triangular bodies, as well as when we predicate that ‘a man is an
animal’, we say nothing about the existence of man or animals although
surely these statements relate to beings or universals. In fact, by treat-
ing them as possibility sentences Leibniz avoids decisions regarding their
59
Halina Święczkowska
54 See Hans Burkhardt, Adam’s Mind and Body, in: M. Dascal, E. Yakira (ed.), Leibniz
and Adam, University Publishing Project Ltd., Tel Aviv 1993, p. 46.
55 AA VI ii, 453.
56 AA VI ii, 448: “Universalium igitur imaginaria realitas extra singularia a sermone
figura to orta”.
60
Cognitive Functions of Language according to G. W. Leibniz
nation of abstract terms from the language of science.57 He did not claim,
however, that they are completely useless – abstraction is not a mistake,
as long as one knows that it contains what is hidden.58 In other words, if
we use a term, we have to give its definition. Treating general and abstract
terms as compendia loquendi, Leibniz, however, assigns them a particular
function. If they are properly defined, as the signs of concepts present in
our minds, they allow us to derive the truth about the nature of things. By
“grabbing” the thought, a sign allows us to approach the idea of the thing
or even replaces it when that idea is not available. It becomes essential and
sometimes even the only tool in the process of cognition.
Signs and operations performed on them have a cognitive value only
when they reflect the inner order of the idea or ‘imitate’ it on the basis of
the assumption that the thing under consideration is possible. Nonetheless,
this condition is not always fulfilled. Indeed, there are signs and actions
that have no relation to the perfect order and these, as we know, are the
main cause of erroneous thoughts and judgments. How to get certainty that
when we make some judgment, it is compatible with any part of this inner
structure? Leibniz was aware of this difficulty when he wrote: “When I think
of something and I cannot imagine anything bigger than this, what is it
I am thinking about apart from separate thoughts about singular ideas
(things) contained in the words ‘something’, ‘bigger’, ‘imagine’, ‘no’, ‘can’ ?
Separately, I have an idea of what I call ‘something’, what I call ‘bigger’,
what I call ‘thought’ and I can think of them one after the other. But
I have no idea of all of these things together. I link only words or signs and
I only imagine that I have an idea of something of which nothing bigger can
be conceived”.59 The same problem was tackled by him in New Essays....
Analyzing the imperfection of words, Leibniz talks “of our uncertainty as to
whether ideas are consistent when experience does not provide us with them
being linked in the same subject”. In this case it is necessary to recognize
57 Leibniz was quite consistent in questioning the usefulness of abstract names, es-
pecially in philosophy. This fact could lead to assigning him a nominalistic attitude.
L. Couturat in La Logique de Leibniz, Presse Universitaires de France, Paris 1901, p. 470
argues against such an interpretation, even when it comes to early ideas of Leibniz.
C. S. Peirce shows the evolution of Leibniz’s ideas from nominalism to realism. See
M. Fisch, Peirce and Leibniz, “Journal of the History of Ideas” 33, 1972, p. 485–496.
58 G. W. Leibniz, New Essays..., Book III, viii.
59 G. W. Leibniz, Leibnitiana. Elementa..., op. cit., p. 4: “Cum cogito aliquid, quo
majus cogitare non potest, quid aliud cogito, quam separatim ideas singulorum, quae sub
his vodbus continentur, ut: aliquid, majus cogitare, non, posse. Separatim habeo ideam
eius quod voco cogitationem, itaque unum post alteram cogitans. Non ideas horum inter
se, sed postea vocabula tantum seu characteres conjungo et fingo me ideam habere eius,
quo majus cogitare non potest”.
61
Halina Święczkowska
the need for “temporary definitions of sensual things when the experience
is not sufficient to obtain fuller definitions”.60
Leibniz says that in constructing this type of definition we should take
into consideration our intrinsic imperfection, but also negligence and lazi-
ness, which, in his opinion, is a direct cause of errors.61 This ‘imperfection’
can be reducible through the analysis and definitions of the terms included
in each language. According to Leibniz, “Everything doubtless returns to
definitions which may extend even to primitive ideas. One and the same sub-
ject may have several definitions, but the knowledge that they agree with
themselves must be learned by reason, by demonstrating one definition by
another or by experience, by proving that they constantly together”.62 It
can therefore be concluded that the ability to get to know goes hand in
hand with the ability to define. Improving cognitive abilities is conditioned
by perfect mastery of the language. Bearing this in mind, Leibniz called
for the review of the German language dictionary resources, the creation
of specialized dictionaries covering the specialist vocabulary, etymological
dictionaries, and establishment of the standards of linguistic correctness.
He believed that “in time all languages of the World will be recorded and
placed in the dictionaries and grammars, and compared together: this will
be of very great use both for knowledge of things, (...) and for the knowledge
of our mind.”63
SUMMARY
This article is an attempt to critically analyze Leibniz’s views on the
cognitive value of natural language and other symbolic systems involved in
the processes of thought. Confronting his position regarding the linguistic
sign function with the position of Hobbes, Leibniz presents his own solu-
tion which is consistent with the results of modern research in the field
of cognitive psychology. Analyzing symbolic thinking, Leibniz positions it
in the context of the dispute over universals consciously avoiding taking
a position for or against. That makes him a precursor to the modern con-
cept in which the ‘realism – nominalism’ dichotomy loses its justification.
62