Alexander of Aphrodisias On Stoic Physics
Alexander of Aphrodisias On Stoic Physics
Alexander of Aphrodisias On Stoic Physics
ON STOIC PHYSICS
PHILOSOPHIA ANTIQUA
A SERIES OF MONOGRAPHS
ON ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY
EDITED BY
ROBERT B. TODD
ALEXANDER OF APHRODISIAS
ON STOIC PHYSICS
LEIDEN
E. J. BRILL
1976
ALEXANDER OF APHRODISIAS
ON STOIC PHYSICS
A STUDY OF THE DE MIXTIONE
WITH PRELIMINARY ESSAYS,
TEXT, TRANSLATION AND COMMENTARY
BY
ROBERT B. TODD
LEIDEN
E. J. BRILL
1976
ISBN 90 04 04402 7
Acknowledgements . . IX
Preface XI
PART ONE
PART TWO
PART THREE
THE DE MIXTIONE
Introduction . . . 91
Analytical Outline . 97
Text and Translation 108
Glossary of Terms . 174
Notes on the Text. . 176
Commentary . . . . 180
Texts from the de mixtione in Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta 253
Bibliographies
I. Ancient and Modern Authors. . . . . . . . . 254
2. Alexander of Aphrodisias: A Select Bibliography 261
Indices . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 264
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
211 on the basis of the dedication of the defato to Septimius and Antoninus
(de Jato 164. 3ff.) would seem to be in error. The earliest source to which I
have traced this is J. A. Fabricius, Bibliotheca Graeca (Hamburg, 1716), II,
274 (also IV, 63), followed by J. Brucker (Historia Critica Philosophiae
[Leipzig, 1742], II, 481), C. G. Zumpt (Abh. d. Akad. d. Wiss., Phil.-Hist.
Klasse, Berlin, 1843, p. 98), Zeller (p. 778), Ueberweg-Praechter (p. 564),
and Gercke (RE I-i, col. 1453). Under the influence of these handbooks it
has become dogma. Yet it must be false since Geta was created Augustus
in 209 (see S. N. Miller, Cambridge Ancient History, XII, 41) and we know
of an inscription indicating that the news had reached Athens by December
209 or January 210 (A. Birley, Septimius Severus, p. 264). Is there any reason
to assume that Alexander would have omitted Geta thereafter?
' We cannot even be certain that his Aphrodisias is the major Carian
city which has been extensively excavated in recent years, though in view
of its well-developed cultural life (see L. Robert, Antiquite Classique 35
(1966] 397-432) it probably was.
6 The main requirements are (1) a collection of the fragments of the pre-
and Brink, "Peripatos," RE Suppl. Vol. VII, cols. 938-347. More recent
literature to be noted: the studies of M. Plezia on Andronicus (De Andronici
Rhodii studiis aristotelicis); Moraux, "Xenarchos (5)," RE Suppl. Vol. IXA;
and H. Drossaart-Lulofs' edition of Nicolaus' Ile:pl qn).oaoqi(cxc;. Lynch
(Aristotle's School, ch. VI) has now argued that the Peripatetics of this
period in no sense continued the work of the original Lyceum, which he
believes ended when Sulla sacked Athens in 86 B.C.
9 The evidence on Andronicus is unclear, and he may have been 8Lcx8oxoc;
at Athens (K. Brink, RE Suppl. Vol. VII, cols. 938-940); but strongly against
this is Lynch, Aristotle's School, pp. 203-204.
SOME PRE-ALEXANDRIAN PERIPATETICS 3
(Top. 69. 15, Pr. An. I 16. 16, and Met. 85. 10) knew Eudemus' logical
treatise Ile:pl Ae~e:<i>~ (for fragments see F. Wehrli, Schute des Aristoteles, VII,
frs. 25-29).
17 Top. 549. 23-24 is the only reference to Galen where he is mentioned
as an example of an intellectual authority. There are many examples of
4 INTRODUCTION
Alexander dealing with the same topics as Galen (e.g. the locus of the rulin1
principle [iJytµovLx6v) of the soul, de an. 94. 7-100. 17; or the relation of tl
soul to the physical constituents of the body, de an. 2. 10-11. 13; see Donir
Atti d. Accad. di Torino 105 [1971] 61-107 at 98-107) but it is as difficult 1
determine Alexander's precise knowledge of Galen as it is to establish tl
nature of his Stoic sources (see Pt. 11-i passim).
18 S. Pines, Isis 52 (1961) 21-54 passim, and N. Rescher and M. Marmur
The Refutation by Alexander of Aphrodisias of Galen's Treatise on the Theo,
of Motion. Also cf. R. Walzer, Galen on Jews and Christians at pp. 48 n.
and 74 n. 2 on evidence of responses to Galen by Alexander.
19 References are most conveniently collected at PIR 2 E109. Eudemus
perhaps to be identified with the Peripatetic Euthydemus at Lucian Herm,
timus 11 (V. Nutton, Proc. Camb. Phil. Soc. n.s. 18 [1972] at p. 58). 0
Galen's social progress at Rome note especially XIV. 612ff. K. For Galen
biography, cf. the convenient outline in Bowersock, Greek Sophists, ch.
20 XIV. 626-629 K. On the date cf. Ilberg, Neue Jahrbucher 15 (1905) 281
who provides further evidence on the political figures present, as do1
Bowersock, Greek Sophists, pp. 62-63 and 82-83.
21 Galen XIV. 627 K.: ... 'AAt~&v8p<i> 'l'<i°> ilcxµcxax'llvci>, yLyvwaxov'l'L µ,
'l'Ot 'l'OU IIA&n>voc;, IXAA<X 't'o!c; , ApLO'l'O'l'EAOUc; 7tpoax£Lµev<i> µiiAAOV.
SOME PRE-ALEXANDRIAN PERIPATETICS 5
628 K could be a courtesy title. It need not imply that he was Galen's teacher
as Bowersock, Greek Sophists, p. 60 n. 50 (following PIR 2 G24) takes it.
It is certain only that he was the teacher of Flavius Boethus, and possibly
Cn. Claudius Severus (v. n. 37 below).
u XIV. 628 K.
u Cf. VIII. 711 K, where it is used similarly as a term of abuse. Galen
refers to certain sceptics and ix1top7J't'txo( who "deny that they have firm know-
ledge of their own experiences and are rightly called crude sceptics (ixypoL-
xom,pp6>vetoL)." These extreme sceptics are probably not to be associated
with any of the established schools (n. 34 below). Gercke (RE 1-i, col. 1453)
rightly points out that this incident seems to have become enmeshed in
legend among the Arabs. The Kitab Al-Fihrist (rnth cent. A.D.) reports that
Alexander of Aphrodisias called Galen "Mauleselkopf" (as translated by
A. Miiller, Die Griech. Philos. in der Arab. Oberlief., p. 23), but as Miiller
himself noted (p. 57 n. 45), there is no evidence in Greek sources of relations
between the two (cf. also nn. 17 and 18 above). On the identification of the
Aphrodisian and Damascan Alexanders in Arabic sources see also G. Stroh-
maier, Encyclopaedia of Islam, IV, fasc. 63-64 (Leiden, 1973), 129-130.
28 De A natom. A dministrat. 1-i (II. 218 K) : ... 't'ou vuv 'A6~v7)aLv ix~LOuµevou
).6youc; 8L8iiaxeLV 87Jµoa(qc.
6 INTRODUCTION
dotus, the first holder of the imperial chair in rhetoric (1tpoi.laT7J ... -njc;
'A87Jvcxlwv ve:6T7J't'oc;), while the pedagogical role of the professors forms the
whole theme of Lucian's Eunuch; cf. also Alexander de Jato 189. 4-5 on
the Stoics as teachers. Finally in dedicating Book VIII of his Onomasticon
to Commodus, Pollux complains of the pressures of teaching (YJ auvoualcx YJ
1tpoc; 't'ouc; ve:ouc;). Whatever the relation the new chairs bore to the traditional
positions of the successors, they probably introduced a new emphasis on
public teaching, derived perhaps from the Stoic emperor's own sensitivity
to pedagogy; cf. Meditations Bk. I passim for dedications to various teachers.
80 Philostratus V.S. 566; although, as Bowersock says (Greek Sophists, p.
p. 49), this shows only that "Marcus took the advice of Herodes." Since the
latter died in 178 the system of appointment referred to by Lucian (Eun. 3. 8)
whereby a candidate was "judged by the vote of the best men" (8oxLµcxa8ev't'cx
4'7Jq>ep 't'wv cxpla'l'wv) could have been in force soon after, and was possibly the
system under which Alexander of Aphrodisias was appointed. Who these
"best men" were is not known. Lesky's description (History of Greek
Literature, English trans., p. 841) of the Eunuch as a depiction of "the
struggle over the chair of philosophy at Athens (176) in all its deplorable
details" must certainly be corrected.
31 This connection might have been the following: Favorinus of Arelate
was the teacher of Herodes (Philostratus V.S. 490). and present at Galen's
anatomical demonstration was Demetrius of Alexandria, who at that time
was giving rhetorical demonstrations in the style of Favorinus (xcxTix --riiv
t8ecxv -njc; Cl>cx(3wplvou )..e~e:wc;, Galen XIV. 627 K). Probably Favorinus was dead
by 163 (C. P. Jones, CQ 17 [1967] 312 n. 5), but presumably Demetrius knew
him in his lifetime. If he and Alexander were friends our philosopher might
thereby have known the great sophist. A firmer speculation on the reasons
for Alexander's advancement might be grounded in the fact that the enthu-
siastic Peripatetic Cn. Claudius Severus (Galen XIV. 613 K) knew Alexander
(XIV. 629 K), and was possibly also present with Marcus Aurelius at Athens
in 176 when the philosophical chairs were established (Philostratus V.S. 588).
32 XIV. 620-622 K where Galen complains ot this, and a prevailing charla-
sceptical Academy that Epictetus attacked (Arrian Diss. 1-v and II-xx).
87 • See W. Schmid, RE VI-ii, col. 2081, and Galen de opt. doctr. I {I.
between the exposition of a work's goal (axo7t'6~) and value (xp~<nµov) and
oral teaching in general see K. Praechter, Byz. Zeit. 18 (1901) 525-531. There
is a hint that even earlier Alexander of Aegae (first century A. D. Peripatetic)
was interested in the question of a work's goal; cf. Simplicius Cat. 10. 19ff.
and Ueberwcg-Praechter, p. 561.
,o This is true of both the Athenian and the Alexandrian commentators
IO INTRODUCTION
of the fifth and sixth centuries; see Praechter, Byz. Zeit. 18 (1901) 529-533,
and on Proclus, A. J. Festugiere, M.H. 20 (1963) 77-100.
41 His fragments are collected by Reiland, diss. Giessen, 1925.
62 The Suidas s.v., and frequently by Eusebius who quotes him most
Aristocles has only been made Alexander's teacher by the emendation of the
'ApLa't'O't'EA'!J½ of various texts, notably Mant. 110. 4, to his name on the
ground that as a reference to the Stagirite this was unintelligible. Cf. n. 53.
46 The Suidas (s.v.) records an "Artsof Rhetoric" (TEJ(VotLp'!J't'OpLxot(} and an
Alexander's Teachers
In addition to Herminus, 49 there are two other known teachers
of Alexander of Aphrodisias who must have been active in the
latter third of the second century, if the epithet "teacher" (a~-
Max.cx1,.oi;;) implies personal contact. Sosigines 50 was a wide-ranging
scholar. As a typical Peripatetic he dealt with logic, also wrote a
treatise on vision in at least eight books, 51 and was particularly
interested in astronomical problems. The other teacher has been
only recently identified. He is Aristotle of Mytilene, mentioned
by Galen as one of the most distinguished contemporary Peripatetics
in a treatise written in the 19o's. 52 This, in Moraux's view, 53 makes
47 Fr. 4 Reiland (= Eusebius P.E. XIV. 19. 766b ff.).
'8 Fr. 6 Reiland (= Eusebius P.E. XIV. 18. 758c ff.).
° Cf. p. 3, nn. 14, 15 above.
60 See Rehm, RE Zw. Rh. III (1929) u57-u59 for details, and on the
distinction between him and Julius Caesar's advisor, see Th. Martin, Annales
de la Faculte des Lettres de Bordeaux 1 (1879) 174-187. Alexander himself
refers to him as his teacher (o 3i8iiaxotAo~ ~µwv, Meteor. 143. 13).
61 Ile:p! "Oljie:(,)~, Alexander Meteor. 143. 14.
62 Cf. Ile:p! 'EOwv, Mi.iller, Script. Min., 11, II. 4-5, and see Moraux,
AGPh 49 (1967) 177. He is termed "a leading figure in Peripatetic scholar-
ship" ((XV~p 1tpwre:uaot~ tv TTI Ile:pmotTI)'nKTI 6e:(,)p(9').
63 See AGPh 49 (1967) 176-182 for the full argument. This revised Moraux's
earlier view (Alexandre d'Aphrodise, ch. 4) that the Aristotle referred to in
various Alexandrian texts was the Stagirite, which had been criticised by
F. Trabucco, Acme II (1958) u9-126.
I2 INTRODUCTION
The Commentaries
The precise form of pre-Alexandrian philosophical commentaries
is not known to us, 57 the only extant example being the somewhat
why Alexander might not have been the pupil of Aristocles of Messenia.
Nothing however is known of the contribution of Aristotle of Mitylene to
the specifically scholarly tradition, and therefore his influence on Alexander
as against that of the known scholars, Herminus and Sosigines, might have
been slight.
67 Pre-Alexandrian commentators are quoted rather sparingly, both by
was no doubt great we cannot afford to gauge his debt to his predecessors
solely from the indices nominum.
u CAG, XI-i. Only that on Books I-IV, part of that on Book VII, and that
on Book VIII are extant.
69 Crantor was the first of many to write a commentary on the Timaeus
(Von Arnim, RE XI, col. 1586), and Eudemus seems in effect to have
written a commentary on some of the logical works and the Physics; note
the texts at Wehrli, Schule des Aristoteles, VII, frs. 9-24 and 31-123.
• 0 These were composed by the more orthodox Platonists Taurus, Atticus,
and Severus, and there is also a record of one by the Peripatetic Adrastus.
Alexander is known to have criticised Taurus' commentary-see Praechter,
RE VI-i, col. 68.
81 Demonax 56, where he is said to deserve 3excx xcxTl)yoplcxL (ten categories
evidence of these other commentaries see Zeller, p. 790 note. For literature,
see Bibliography II-2.
68 Cf. above n. 57.
87 In addition to the description of Herminus in the Demonax (n. 61 above)
144. 5, 151. 15, 210. 30, 304. 14; de sensu 101. 4; and Meteor. 5. 29.
78 These distinctions are not rigid, and are only loosely comparable
to the glossa, commentium or expositio, and paraphrasis of mediaeval commen-
tators. Sophonias, the fourtheenth-century Byzantine commentator, has
some interesting comments on the superiority of paraphrases to running
commentaries (de an., pp. 1-2 at CAG, XXIII-i).
16 INTRODUCTION
Since the de mixtione is the object of this study I shall not describe
it at any length. It seems to be a complement to Alexander's other
monographs in its critique of the physical theory that underlay
the Stoic doctrines of God, fate, providence and the soul, 79 as well
as affording the opportunity for a continuous critique of the theory
of mixture along lines we know that Alexander followed in his
commentaries on some of the physical treatises of Aristotle. It
also justified a separate discussion of two problematic Aristotelian
theories, those of mixture and organic growth.
It will be clear that there was a strong polemical element in these
treatises (<ruyypcxµ.µ.oc ..oc). 80 Alexander's main opponents are the
early Stoics, principally Chrysippus, 81 and here, as we shall see,
he joins Platonists and Christians almost to the letter in some of
his criticisms. 82 In this anti-Stoicism we can also observe his general
affinities to the contemporary philosophical culture; for while he
attacks the Stoics in the same manner as some of his contemporaries,
he also defends the Peripatetics on the very grounds on which they
were attacked by both pagan and Christian. This is true not only
of his work on providence, but in his defence of the study of logic, 83
and possibly in his explications of Aristotelian ethics. 84
206. 1, 206. 28-30 and 209. 20-210. 3 where similar wording is used, which
suggest that he shared an anti-Stoic Jons communis (see Lilla, Clement of
Alexandria, pp. 50-51, who notes the first two passages but neglects Alexan-
der). The proximity of this whole issue to contemporary philosophical
culture is indicated by the fact that the de Jato is the only work of Alexander's
that Eusebius quotes (K. Mras, Anz. d. Oest. Akad. d. Wiss. in Wien, Phil.
Hist. Klasse, 93 [1956] 215).
79 de mixt. 227. 5-10 makes this clear.
80 At Phys. 489. 20-22 Simplicius refers to Alexander's refutation of the
view that infinite body can be in place "in the work written against the
Epicurean Zenobius" {tv -roi:i; 7tpoi; 't"OV 'Emxoupe:tov Zriv6~tov civnye:ypocµµevoti;}.
If this is in fact a treatise, it is another polemic to be added to his works, but
the reference may be to a discussion in a commentary or a scholium. Alexan-
der's general critique of Epicurean physics can be traced in de mixt. 2,
Quaestiones Ill. 12, and Alexander ap. Philoponus de gen. et corr. 12. 6-25. As
for other treatises, Pr. An. I 125. 30-31 seems to refer to an independent
discussion of syllogisms, but the treatise "On Spirits" (Ile:pl 8octµ6vwv)
referred to by Michael of Ephesus Parv. Nat. 83. 27 and 84. 26 is almost
certainly spurious; see Cranz, Catalogus II, pp. 420-422.
81 See further Part 11-i on this and the general topic of Alexander's anti-
Stoicism.
88 In addition to n. 84, cf. Commentary on de mixt. 11. 225. 5-18, 226.
24-30.
83 Pr. An. I 4. 3off. and 6. 8ff. are both in effect an apologia for the study
of logic.
84 Lilla, Clement of Alexandria, pp. 68-71 shows that the idea that "virtue
2
18 INTRODUCTION
may have been paralleled in the "notes on logic" (crx_6Atix )..oytxa.) which
Alexander refers to at Pr. An. I 250. 1 -2, or the collection of explanations
of readings (Ae~e:ti;) from the de sensu quoted by a scholiast on Quaest. I. 2
(see Bruns, SA, II-ii, p. ix).
90 Manifestly II. 22, and probably I. 5, I. 15, I. 19, and III. 5.
91 This is the case with Quaestiones II. 12 which I have discussed at Philo-
logus 116 (1972) 293-305.
20 INTRODUCTION
not know whether they were written directly under his influence
or in the Peripatetic school of a later generation. All that is probable
is that they did emanate from the school, as organised in Athens
or elsewhere, since they are dominated by a polemical or apologetical
tone. Alexander's claim to them might be an indication of the
extent to which he dominated his successors. Of these very little
is known, and we must be guided mainly by guess-work. An Am-
monius is referred to by Philostratus 92 as the "best-read" {1t0Auypcxµ-
µ(X-ro;) man he knew, and he and his contemporary Ptolemaeus
are described by Longinus in Porphyry's life of Plotinus as "very
learned" {cpLAoAoyw-r(X-roL) with Ammonius being the superior of
the two. 93 These qualities might imply that they carried on into
the 22o's and 23o's the scholarly work that Alexander of Aphrodisias
had so strikingly advanced. Longinus also reports 94 that neither
wrote any technical works but only "poems and show-speeches"
(MyoL !m8ELX-rLxol), which suggests a return to that coalescence
of philosophy and rhetoric of which we saw indications in Aris-
tocles' works, and that at least seemed implied by the social circles
in which Alexander of Damascus moved. 95
Alexander of Aphrodisias' major influence on later Greek philos-
ophy was to be reserved not for the Peripatetic school, of which
he is the last significant figure, but for the long tradition of Platonist
commentators on Aristotle. He was read along with Aspasius and
Adrastus by Plotinus, 96 whom he to some extent influenced. The
new tradition was inaugurated with Porphyry's introduction and
commentary on the Categories, 97 and was continued in the Platonist
schools of Athens and Alexandria in the fifth and sixth centuries.
It is from the works of these commentators that so much of Alexan-
der's lost commentaries remains to be retrieved.
92 V.S. 618. On him see RE, 1-i, cols. 1862-1863 where the guess is made
XXIII-ii, col. 1860) with the critic of Dionysius Thrax described by Sextus
EmpiricusA .M. I. 60-61, if Sextus is to be dated ca. 100 A.D. (see F. Kudlien,
RM 106 [1963] 251-254).
94 Ap. Porphyry Vit. Plot. 20.
15 See above, pp. 6-8. Cf. also de jato 165. 5-7 where Alexander assures the
ALEXANDER OF APHRODISIAS
AND THE STOIC THEORY OF TOTAL BLENDING
1 Cf. De Fin. iv. 26. 72 and Reid's note on Acad. Post. I. iv. 17. 1. Some
recent scholarship has reemphasised these on general philosophical grounds:
see A. A. Long, BICS 15 (1968) 72-75, J. M. Rist, Stoic Philosophy, chs. 1-3.
2 See Pohlenz, Die Stoa, I, 355-357 on this and the whole topic of the
Aristotle's Categories which was known to Simplicius (Cat. 64. 24 etc.) and
therefore may well have been known by Alexander.
4 See I. Mueller, AGPh 51 (1969) 173-185, an article based on material
and 109 from all other works. This is only a rough guide since often more
than one passage is quoted in a single citation.
7 demixt. 213. 7; 216. 8, 9, 14; 218. 8, 9; and Pr. An. I. 177. 25 and 180. 36
in a recreated cosmos after the conflagration; cf. the texts from the whole
context at SVF II 624. It is questionable whether Alexander actually posses-
sed this book, since he never quotes from it again, although it deals with the
topic of fate (see the further quotation by Stobaeus at SVF II 913) which
Alexander dealt with in the de Jato. Also in his earlier reference to Chrysippus
at Pr. An. I 177. 25 (not in SVF) on the same general topic Alexander does
not include a reference to this book title.
24 THE STOIC THEORY OF TOTAL BLENDING
temporary Stoic works, but this is in such general and discursive terms that
nothing of his general practice can be gleaned.
21 E.g. Diog. Laert. VII. 199 refers to Chrysippean works of ethical
definitions (llpot). Also cf. SVF I, p. xii on the influence of a Chrysippean
summary of ethics on Diogenes Laertius. On Chrysippus' role in the tradition
of florilegia see K. Horva, RE Supplbd. 6 (1935) 80-81.
26 THE STOIC THEORY OF TOTAL BLENDING
example, 123. 36-124. 9 uses the concepts of matter and quality while 124.
9-20 presents a set of general anti-materialist arguments.
28 Some of these are discussed at nn. 234, 243 below.
29 Alexander Quaest. III. 12 which sustains the general thesis "that being
ALEXANDER AND STOICISM 27
doctrines from the system to which they belong and makes the task
of reconstructing their interrelation difficult and often highly
speculative. 3°Finally, there is the encouragement that this approach
may give to the assimilation of an opponent's terminology and
ideas; when a philosopher considers only the general character
of an opponent's thought broad similarities with his own can be
more easily recognised.
This latter aspect, whatever its cause, needs special comment.
Like many of his contemporaries Alexander freely borrowed the
philosophical vocabulary of the Stoics and others to describe
concepts peculiar to his own system. In many cases this can be
quite innocuous where the alternative term simply functions as
a description without any philosophical significance. 31 However
there are cases where such borrowing involves a significant modifica-
tion in Alexander's presentation of Aristotelian thought, and
consequently affects his view of related Stoic doctrines. A good
example of this is his ready assimilation of the language of the
Stoic doctrine of common notions which, though in the com-
mentaries serving merely as a terminological variant for (contra-
dictorily) both "general assumptions" (u1toi-~lj)€~<;, ~v8o;oc) and
axioms, is used in the de mixtione and de f ato against the Stoics.
Their doctrines of fate and mixture are then said to be against
these common notions, while the corresponding Aristotelian
doctrines are said to obey them. 32 Again the very definition of fate
in "Aristotelian" terms in the de jato 6 as nature qua efficient cause
is the result of an assimilation of the broad Stoic framework 33
for dealing with this question, as were very probably some aspects
is not infinite" (lh-t µ~ &rmpov TO 8v) has a long attack, in the manner of the
texts in the Mantissa, against various theories of the infinite. At SVF II 536
Von Arnim, rather misleadingly I think, cites 101. 10-15 and 106. 10-13 from
this text when it is clear that, despite the generality of the arguments,
Alexander's opponents are Epicureans (cf. 104. 11-13 on infinite worlds,
and cf. 101. 10-16 with Epicurus Ep. ad Hdt. 41). His error is indicative of
the dangers of using these highly general polemics as evidence.
ao On this cf. pp. 72-73 below.
31 For a discussion of one such case see my article on tmT7J3e:t6T7J<; at Acta
Classica 15 (1972) 25-35.
32 Cf. de mixt. 232. 34-233. 1 and de Jato 182. 20-22. On the whole topic
of Alexander's assimilation of these terms see my discussion at Symb. Os. 48
(1973) 62 nn. 80-85.
83 On this see G. Verbeke, AGPh 50 (1968) 81. Cf. Comm. on de niixt. II.
225. 20-27.
28 THE STOIC THEORY OF TOTAL BLENDING
34 See Comm. on de mixt. 225. 18-226. IO. Further on the de providentia see
Comm. on de mixt. IO. 223. 6-14.
35 Cf. 83. 2-8 with Aetius Plac. IV. 11. (= SVF II, p. 28. 12-19). This
(AGPh 51 [19701 258-265), but did not note how it is in large measure either
conditioned by or reflected in the assimilation undertaken at de anima
72-73. Cf. also Quaest. III. 13, a more scholastic version of the latter. On a
broadly similar critique of the Stoics in Plotinus see Graeser, Plotinus and
the Stoics, pp. 48-49.
39 On this see Long, AGPh 51 (1970) at pp. 258-262.
ALEXANDER AND STOICISM 29
' 6 8L6Aou here is unique in a physical sense. LSJ cite it in the sense of
"altogether" but at Aristotle Poet. 1460a 8 (the only passage cited) in a
temporal sense. The commoner 8L' 6Awv might well be read here; cf. note
on the text of de mixt. 221. 33.
u This book-title is mentioned only by Diogenes, and this is the only
reference to Book III. Book I is cited as a source for central physical doctrines
(the principles [VII. 139), the elements in the cosmogony [VII. 135, 142)
and the doctrine of matter [VII. 150)) while Book II dealt with epistemology
and phychology (cf. VII. 54, 55, 57 and 157). We shall show that total
blending has at least some relation to the former set of doctrines.
' 7 Translators take 1hd 1toa6v in a temporal sense: "for a while" (Hicks,
Loeb ed.), "aliquamdiu" (Cobet, Paris [18781). However if we take the phrase
as describing the limit to which the wine is extended, the sense in which ex-
tension is a physical precondition of blending is much clearer. There are
several closely related expressions in the descriptions of extension in de
mixtione 4 that must clearly be taken in a physical sense: e1tl n e).6e:'tv µ.eye:6oc;
(217. 18), €7tL TOGOUTOV )(.&ta61XL (217. 30). de; 'n)V €7tL TOGOUTOV fKTIXGLV (217. 32).
Cf. also de mixt. 6. 220. 18 (e1tl 7tA&LOV ... xe:6µ.e:vix) and 220. 20 (TTJV e,d
7tA£0V ... )(.IJGLV).
cs Literally auµ.qi6e:lpe:a6ixL means "to be destroyed along with" and else-
where "joint-destruction" is a synonym for fusion (auyx.uaLc;), a blend in
which constituents form a new compound from which they are irretrievable
(see pp. 50-51 below). Either this is an error, or as I suspect (with Hicks,
Loeb ed.) the term in fact means a blend in which constituents do not lose
their identity; cf. p. 69 n. 188 on Plutarch's use of aune:'tv to mean "blend."
" Plutarch (Sto. Rep. 1053F, de comm. not. 1084C) quotes the same book
again. The former passage deals with the doctrine of !~Le; which is, as we shall
see, relevant to our interpretation of total blending (see pp. 36ff. below).
32 THE STOIC THEORY OF TOTAL BLENDING
and IX. 384-385. Cf. also A.M. IX. 260 where a part is said to extend to
equal a whole; Iambl. In Nie. Arithm. Introd. p. 13. 17 Pistelli apropos the
division of a monad which would be extended (&v·n1tocpe:x-re:lve:a6aL) to infinity;
infinite division of a monad where iJ t1t' &1te:Lpov ail~7JaL<; ixv-rmape:x-re:lv7J-raL;
and Greg. Naz. Or. 43, p. 852e which refers to a human ixv-rLmxpbt-rocaL<;
towards God. In all these cases the emphasis is on a single entity's extension
in relation to a larger one.
A RECONSTRUCTION FROM THE SOURCES 33
which deals almost entirely with the blend of unequals; further on its whole
context see pp. 66-67 below.
u See de gen. et corr. Arn. 328a 29-33, and cf. Comm. on de mixt. 14. 231. 3.
On the Presocratic tradition of "equalitarian physics" followed by Aristotle
see G. Vlastos, CP 62 (1947) 175. As far as the term xpiicn~ goes this is a
natural requirement, for it means the tempering or evening-out of one thing
by another; cf. LSJ, xe:pciwuµL I. 3, II, and III.
57 de gen. et corr. Aro. 328a 27-28.
58 See de gen. et corr. Aro. 327b 22-27, and 328a 10-1 I. On the uniformity
(6µoLoµe:pe~) of a blend see Comm. on de mixt. 7. 221. 9-10, and on the con-
stituents being in potentiality cf. on de mixt. 15. 231. 16-19. In this account
constituents do not, of course, occupy one another's place.
59 See sect. III passim for a detailed discussion of this critique.
3
34 THE STOIC THEORY OF TOTAL BLENDING
in detail: I shall simply quote the major source for my statements from SVF
with the caveat that none of this evidence is primary and that it all deserves
the close attention that I only give to the texts dealing with total blending
in the course of this essay. I hope that my comments at sect. i, n. 9 above
are sufficient justification for the use of this evidence at all.
85 For the basic account see Diog. Laert. VII. 134 (SVF II 300); other
material is gathered at SVF II 299-328. Cf. also the Comm. on de mixt. 224.
34, 225. 3 and 225. 5-18. In the latter note and elsewhere in the commentary
A RECONSTRUCTION FROM THE SOURCES 35
could not interact with the active but merely served as its medium. 66
It is thus often described also as substance (ouo-(oc) or qualityless
matter (5):'l) from which bodies evolve. 67 The result of this physical
relation between the principles is a rational cosmos, for the active
principle can also be regarded as Reason (the Myoc;;) or God. 68
The actual physical process by which the active principle pervades
matter is explained in terms of the four elements. Probably by
developing an Aristotelian distinction 69 Chrysippus identified
Hot and Cold as active qualities, and Wet and Dry as passive. 70
In a monoqualitative theory of elements this suggests that the
passive principle could be identified with Earth and Water, and
the active with Fire and Air. 71 The latter identification seems to
&1totov oualotv, -r~v 0Al)V. Also cf. Diog. Laert. VII. 150 for matter as that from
which things come to be. At Diog. Laert. VII. 134 (SVF II 299) there is a
perplexing and unparalleled report that the Stoics distinguished between
principles and elements in that the former were incorporeal and shapeless
(liaooµa.-rouc; ... liµ6p<pouc;). The reading liaooµa.-rouc; is however suspect since
it is preserved only in the Suidas and not the manuscript tradition. If this
were correct, it would be difficult to make sense of the theory of pneuma
in which both principles are given physical properties. It is best, I believe,
to follow the manuscript reading and accept, as Alexander for example
does (de mixt. 11. 224. 31-225. 5) or Aristocles (ap. Euseb. P.E. XIV. 816d),
that the principles are bodies; this view is defended with closer reference
to the literature by H.-J. Kramer, Platonismus und Hellenistische Philosophie,
p. 108 n. 3. To argue this, it should be noted, is not eo ipso to offer an inter-
pretation of the basic doctrine of principles; cf. n. 65.
88 E.g. Diog. Laert. VII. 134, Alex. de mixt. 11. 224. 34.
89 See de gen. et corr. B2. 329b 25-33, and Joachim ad Zoe. Elsewhere he
brings out well the extent to which this can be regarded as an anticipation
of the Stoic theory: "The Hot and the Cold in combination 'work on' the
Moist and Dry with an 'immanent action' like that of Form on Matter in the
seed of a plant or animal. It is this 'immanent' operation which plays the
chief part in the production of the µtxOtv .... " (J.P. 29 [1904] 84).
70 E.g. SVF II 444 and cf. de mixt. 218. 2-6 with Comm. ad Zoe.
71 See SVF II 413 which describes the evolution of the elements from Fire.
of pneuma (de mixt. 224. 14-22 with Comm. ad loc.--cf. 225. 5-10) is a good
indication that the Stoics claimed that it did have a compound character;
cf. also Galen's criticism of it being a self-sustaining compound at SVF II 440.
73 See SVF II 448 (Alex. Mant. 131. 5-10) which refers to pneuma's
-r6vo~). See also Comm. on de mixt. IO. 223. 34-36 on pneuma's transmission
of tension.
77 At lvfant. n5. 9-10 Alexander describes tension as a "particular form"
(e:t8o~ t8wv).
78 See de mixt. 216. 15-16 (= 223. 8-9). See Comm. ad lac.
79 See SVF II 407 (Plutarch) in a discussion of the elements: also cf.
SVF II 440 (p. 144. 31, 35) where Galen uses the expression cruve:x-rtx-lJ cxt-rlcx
("cause that binds together").
A RECONSTRUCTION FROM THE SOURCES 37
°
8 Cf. the standard definition of !!;Le; as "pneuma containing body"
(1tV&uµix awµix·roc; OU\l&X'l'LX6v) at SVF II 368. Cf. pp. 40-41 below.
81 Apart from the discussions of this doctrine by Sambursky and Christen-
sen (n. 62 above) see G. Verbeke, La Doctrine du Pneuma, pp. 61-90, and
J. Gould, The Philosophy of Chrysippus, pp. 99-102.
82 8ux rrocnwv 8L'ijxov is an almost formulaic description of pneuma's motion
-e.g. see SVF II, p. 137. 30, p. 307. 8, and cf. de mixt. 216. 15.
83 Mostly simple verbs of motion are used to characterise pneuma's
movement-e.g. :xwpe:i:11 (SVF II, p. 307. 8), or 8Lepze:a8ixt (SVF II, p. 116. 12-
13); but verbs of extension do describe the motion of sensory pneumata-e.g.
8Lix-rdvm (SVF II, p. 226. 8-9), tx-rdve:a8ixL (SVF II, p. 227. 25-26). On the
relation between this form of pneumatic motion and the cosmic pneuma see
my article ":Euvev-rixaLc; and the Stoic theory of Perception," Grazer Beitriige
II (1974) 251-261. In view of the nature of the "tensional motion" it is
reasonable to assume that such language was employed to describe all
aspects of the theory of pneuma.
8 ' Pp. 32-33 above.
86 Stab. Eel. I. 154. 1-2 W (= SVF II 471); also cf. note on the text of
the verb used to describe proofs from the common notions for the differences
A RECONSTRUCTION FROM THE SOURCES 39
by offering a list of commonplace examples of bodies preserving
their qualities when expanded (217. 14-17), and, more importantly,
of bodies that are "helped" by other bodies to extend themselves
in various ways (217. 17-26). This latter causal relation is clearly
that classified elsewhere by the Stoics as a case of "cooperant
causes" (cnm:pyoc ocl·noc) where one thing can easily contribute to
produce an effect, as for example an additional hand can help
men to lift a weight. 90 The inference that Alexander (at 217. 26-32)
reports was drawn from these examples is as follows:
Since this is the case, they say that there is nothing remarkable
in the fact that certain bodies when helped by one another
are in this way united together in their entirety so that being
preserved along with their own qualities they have a complete
mutual coextension through one another (ocv·mtocpe;x-rdvea6ocL
octJ..~AoLc; 8L' /51,.c.uv /51,.oc), even if some of them are rather small
in bulk and in themselves unable both to be spread to such an
extent, and to preserve their own qualities; for in this way
also the cup of wine is mixed with a large amount of water
and helped by it to such a great extension.
The first clause presents a general inference that if bodies can be
subject to cooperative causation, then they can extend through
one another although one may be smaller than the other. The
second clause on which I shall concentrate here 91 refers to the
specific case of a wine drop being extended through water which
we have seen described by Diogenes Laertius and Plutarch. 92
It is now presented as being entailed by the various commonplace
between mixtures (cf. Comm. on de mixt. 217. 2-13). For further discussion
of this passage see my article at Symb. Os. 48 (1973) at 48-55.
90 Cf. the definition at Sext. Emp. P.H. III. 15, which refers to this par-
ticular case, with 217. 23-25, " ... and along with others we bear certain
weights of which, when left alone, we could not bear the part that befalls
us." Further on cooperant causes cf. Cicero de jato 41 (SVF II 974). Clement
Strom. VIII. ix (atSVFII 346), and cf. Sext. Emp. A .M. IX. 243 (on which see
0. Rieth, Grundbegriffe der Stoischen Ethik, p. 153).
91 Clearly the idea of mutual coextension is incompatible with the pre-
84 SVF II 366, 714-716, 1013, and III 160. This valuable evidence from
Alexander is largely overlooked in discussions of this classification; it places
the doctrine squarely in the context of orthodox Chrysippean physical theory
(cf. p. 69, n. 189 below).
85 See above, p. 35.
88 These are interchangeable terms-cf. n. 83.
87 See above, pp. 37-38.
88 227. 5-10; see Comm. on 12. 227. 9-10.
99 At Symb. Os. 48 (1973) 53-54 I argue that the relation of (1) to (2) is
42 THE STOIC THEORY OF TOTAL BLENDING
108 N. IOI.
104 Hence, even if it is Alexander's own term, the examples introduced at
217. 14-26 are well described as "suasions" (,t!a-re:u;); cf. Comm. on 217. 13.
°
111 For this reason in particular I would reject 0. Rieth's attempt (Grund-
begriffe der Stoischen Ethik, pp. 188-189) to ground this argument (at least
to 217. 14-32) in the Stoic theory of "demonstrative sign" (ev8e:txTtxov
O"Y)µe:fov) as reported e.g. at Sext. Emp. P.H. II. 97-103. Rieth's interpreta-
tion is developed without attention to the overall context of Alexander's,
and I shall not attempt to refute it in detail.
108 At Symb. Os. 48 (1973) 58-60 I develop the thesis of this paragraph
at greater length, and suggest that by the common notions (xotv11t lvvot11t)
the Stoics meant to establish simply conceptions that would demonstrate
the nature of the world-order. On some aspects of this thesis see Comm. on
de mixt. 3. 217. 2-13. This whole form of argumentation is comparable to
the allegorical interpretation of poetry that was widely practised by Stoics,
where for example poetic descriptions of relations between gods were inter-
preted as relations between natural phenomena; see the useful account given
by P. de Lacy, AJP 69 (1948) at 256-263.
A RECONSTRUCTION FROM THE SOURCES 45
107 Diodes Magnes ap. Diog. Laert VII. 52 ( = SVF II 87). See Symb. Os.
108 On this whole pattern of criticism see further below, sect. III passim.
109 Although in the structure of our reconstructed argument the motion
of pneuma through matter is derived from the blending of the wine drop with
water, it can also be said to be "illustrated" by it inasmuch as this reasoning
is a posteriori.
no See above, pp. 34-37.
111 Cf. Comm. on de mixt. r. 213. 2-13.
112 E.g. E. Oegereau, Essai sur le Systeme Sto'icien, p. 44 and G. Rodier,
113 It is attributed to Apollodorus at Diog. Laert. VII. 135 (cf. also SVF II
357, 501). Baeumker suggested that such solidity was only a relative concept
that could accommodate the relation that occurs in total blending (Das
Problem der Materie, p. 335). However E. Weil (Melanges A. Koyre, II, 565)
has argued that this definition was only designed as a contrast with the
definition required to explain the relation between the active and passive
principles described at Diog. Laert. VII. 134, which he describes as "corps-
energie" (p. 565 n. 23). This view is, I believe, essentially correct, if we will
also allow that the Stoics recognised an area in which the ordinary definition
of body applied, represented here by stage (1) of our argument. Also cf.
Appollodorus' view reported at Diog. Laert. VII. 150 where he defines
substance (oualoc) as a body that is acted-on (1toc67J-r6i:;), which supports the
view that there was this dual conception of body. (I have drawn here on
M. Reesor's suggestions at AJP 75 [1954] 56-57.) The case of fire pervading
iron (cf. n. 93 above) perhaps appealed to the Stoics as a good empirical
illustration of body pervading body, where one body, at least, could not be
conventionally described as three-dimensional.
We might also contrast the Stoic theory of tensional motion with their
general doctrine of motion as simple change of place (e.g. SVF II 492); the
former characterises the motion of pneuma, while the latter, as far as we
can judge from the scanty evidence, can only apply to the behaviour of in-
tracosmic bodies. This distinction might be derived from the two senses
of body that I have attempted to distinguish.
114 Thus scholars who claim that the Stoics did hold that two bodies
occupied the same place (e.g. Sambursky, Physics of the Stoics, pp. 15-16,
L. Edelstein, The Meaning of Stoicism, pp. 23-24) ought, I believe, to make
this distinction more firmly. Otherwise the extent to which the ancient critics
misrepresented the Stoics by taking the case of total blending as a description
of the behaviour of random three-dimensional bodies can hardly be appre-
ciated (see further below, pp. 72, 83). Needless to say, the two senses of
"body" that I advocate here do not constitute a complete interpretation of
the Stoic concept of body; that too would require a separate analysis of the
sources.
THE STOIC THEORY OF TOT AL BLENDING
115 See sect. iii below passim, and Comm. on de mixt. 6. 219. II-12.
116 Both Pohlenz (Die Stoa, I. 73) and V. Goldschmidt (Le Systeme Sto'icien
et l'ldee du Temps, p. 45) seem to regard the totality of a blend as an inte-
gration of bodies at an infinite number of points to form thereby a continuous
whole (cf. also H. Dorrie, Porphyrios' "Symmikta Zetemata", p. 25 for a
closely related view). This ignores, erroneously in my opinion, the fact that
total blending specifically occurs between a small and a large body and
that its totality is the extension of the former through the latter (cf. p. 32
above). Also see H. Wolfson (Philosophy of the Church Fathers, I2 382) who
finds a connection between total blending and infinite division at Nemesius
de nat. hom. 3. 128 Matth. although the text only refers to blending escaping
notice "because of the fineness of the bodies that are blended" (3ux -ro
Ae:1t-roµe:pec; -rwv xe:xpcxµevwv). Alexander's own discussion in de mixt. 8 of infi-
nite division in relation to total blending is, as the Commentary will show, a
scholastic exercise and not a reflection of Stoic doctrine.
117 See Sambursky, Physics of the Stoics, p. 14, where total blending is
this suggestion can be criticised along the same lines as the views discussed
in the preceding note. In general it would have been helpful if Sambursky
had clarified somewhere the relation between his separate claims that total
blending (1) gives "a firm foundation for [the] conception of hexis" (Physics
of the Stoics, p. 16), (2) is explained by the Stoic theory of surfaces (p. 96,
cf. n. 101 above), and (3) follows from their theory of continuity. All these
suggestions are probably relevant to a full interpretation of the theory of
pneuma, but only if we admit from the outset that there was some internal
structure to the Stoic physical system.
11 9 Cf. note 101 above.
119 de gen. et corr. A10 327b 31-328a 18. Alexander de mixt. 13. 228. 25-
229. 3 has a more elaborate taxonomy.
120 de gen. et corr. Arn 328a 12-15; cf. Comm. on de mixt. 2. 214. 18-28.
121 See above, p. 33 n. 58.
122 de gen. et corr. Arn 327b 23-28. Cf. Comm. on de mixt. 1. 213. 7-8, and
2a. ~Lotcpepe:LV yixp a.peaxe:L '\'Ot<; a.1to 2a. '\'WV 81: µtyvuµevwv EV O(\l'\'TI
-r~c; ~'\'WLX~<; otlpeae:ooc; 1totp1X8e:O'LV, µt~LV, awµli-rwv,
xpiiO'LV, O'IJY)(UO'LV,
2b. 1totp1X8e:O'LV µev yixp e:IvotL O'(I)· 2 b. TIX<; µev 7totpot8£0'e:L µ(~e:L<; y(ve:-
µli-rwv auvotcpl)V xot-rix -rixc; Emcpotvdotc;, a8otL ).eye:L, Mo '\'LVWV YI l(O(L 1tAdovwv
we; €7tL '\'WV O'Wpwv opwµe:v, EV oti; 1tupo( ouatwv e:tc; -rotu-rov O'UV're:8e:lµe:vwv xott
-re: xotl xpt8ott xott cpotxot xott e:t -rLVot rcotpot-rt8e:µevwv a.AA~AotLc;, C>c; tp'l)O'LV,
'\'OIJ'\'OL<; rx.llot 7totpot7tA~O'LO( 7t&pL€)(E:'\'otL xot8' &pµ~v. aw~ou0"7Jc; e:xlia'r7lc; otU'rwv
xott -rwv E7tL -rwv otlytotAWV lji~cpwv xott EV -rji 'rOLotu-rri rcotpot8eae:L xot-rix ..-lJv
&µµwv. 1te:ptypotcp'1)V 'n)V olxe:lotv oua(otv -re: l(O(L
7tOL6'r7l-rot, we; E7tL xuliµwv cpepe: e:trce:'tv
l(O(L 1tupwv ev -rji rcotp' &.ll~).ouc; 8eae:L •
(216. 17-22)
2C. µt~LV 8' e:IvotL 8uo YI l(O(L 7tAe:L6vwv 2C. -rixc; 8c!: '\'LVotc; y(ve:a8otL µ(~e:Lc;
awµli-rwv &.v-rmotpex-rotaLv 8t' /1).wv, ).eye:L, 8t' /1).wv '\'LVWV OUO'LWV -re: l(O(L
u1toµe:vouawv -rwv auµcpuwv 1te:pt otu-rix '\'WV '\'OIJ'\'(l)V rtOLO'\'~'\'(l)V &.v-rmotp&X'\'ELVO-
7t0LO'\'~'\'(l)V, we; E7tL '\'OU 1tupoc; ~)(e:L l(O(L µevwv a,).).~AotLc; µe:-rix '\'OU -rixc; E~ &.p)(~c;
'\'OU 7t&7tUpotx-rwµevou O'L8~pou, E7tL '\'OIJ- oua(otc; -re: l(O(L 1"COL6'r7l-rotc; acfi~e:LV EV -rji
'\'(l)V yixp <8t'> /1).wv y(yve:a8otL '\'WV µ(~e:L -rji '\'OL~8e:, ~V'\'LVO( '\'WV µ(~e:wv
O'WµIX'r(l)V 'n)V a.V'\'Lrtotp€X'\'otO'LV. oµo(ooc; xpiiO'LV t8Ewc; e:IvotL ).eye:L. 'n)V yixp 8uo
81: x&.1tt -rwv EV ~µ'tv IJiuxwv ~)(ELV · 8t' YI xott rc).dovwv -rtvwv awµli-rwv /1).wv
/1).wv yixp -rwv awµli-rwv ~µwv &.v-rL- 8t' /1).wv &.v'rmotpex-rotaLv a,).).~).otc;
1totpe:x-re:lvouaLV, &.pfoxe:L yixp otu-ro'tc; oil-rwc;, we; O'W~e:Lv fxota-rov O(\l'\'WV EV -r7i
A RECONSTRUCTION FROM THE SOURCES 53
awµo,; 8La awµo,;-roc; IXV'rL7t'O(piJxe:LV. µll:e:L 'rTI 'r0LO(U'r7) 'r'JV -re: obce:(o,;v oua(o,;v
xpiiaLV 81: dvo,;L AeyouaL Mo 'i) xo,;l xo,;l -rac; ev o,;u-r'ij TtOL6'0)'rO(c;, Mye:L
TtAe:L6vrov aroµii-rrov uypwv 8L' /1).rov xpiiaLv e:!vo,;L µ6vl)v -rwv µll:e:rov · dvo,;L
IXV'rL7t'O(pex-rcxaLV 'rWV 1te:pt o,;u-ra TtOL6'0)- yap f8LOV 'rWV xe:xpo,;µevrov 'rO 3uvo,;a6o,;i
-rrov urtoµe:voua&v · [omitting 154. 24- xrop(l:e:a6o,;i TtiiALV ixrt' IXAA'JAOOV, 6
155. 31 auve:xqio,;(ve:a6o,;L yap EX rijc; µ6vroc; y(ve:a6o,;L -r<T> G<J>l:e:LV EV 'rTI µ(l:e:L
xpifae:roc; 'TT)V i!:xifa-rou 'rWV auyxpo,;6ev- -ra xe:xpcxµevo,; -rac; O(U'rWV qiuae:Lc;.
'rOOV uypwv TtOL6'0)-ro,;, ofov ofvou, (216. 25-217. 2)
µeAL-roc;, iJ8o,;-roc;, ll~ouc;, 'rWV Tto,;po;TtAl)-
a(rov. /1-rL 8' ETtL 'rOLO\l'rOOV Xpifae:roV 8Lo,;-
µevoUGLV o,;[ TtOL6'0)-re:c; 'rWV auyxpo,;6ev-
'rOOV, 1tp687)AOV ex -rou TtOAAiixLc; e~
emµl)XO,:V1)ae:roc; 1X1toxrop(l:e:a6o,;L 'rO(U'rO(
ixrt' 1XAA1JArov. Mv youv a1t6yyov l)Ao;Lro-
µevov xo,;6'ij -rLc; e:tc; o!vov iJ8o,;-rL xe:xpo,;-
µevov, IXTtoxrop(ae:L -ro iJ8rop -roii o(vou,
ixvcx8po,;µ6v-roc; -rou iJ8o,;-roc; e:tc; -rov
a1t6yyov.
2d. 'TT)V 81: aurxuaLV Mo <'i\> xo,;l 2d. y(ve:a6o,;L -rac; 8e 'rLVo;c; aurxuae:L
TtAe:t6vrov TtOLO'r'J'rOOV 1te:p! -ra awµcx-ro,; 8L' /1).rov -r&v -re: ouaLwv o,;u-rwv xo,;l -rwv
µe:-ro,;~OAY)V e:tc; i!:-repo,;c; 8Lo,;qie:poUGl)c; -rou- EV O(U'rO(ic; TtOLO'r'J'rOOV auµqi6e:LpoµevroV
-rrov TtOL6'0)'rOc; yeve:aLV, we; ETtL '1-'ijc; IXAA'JAO,:Lc;, we; ylve:a6o,;( (fll)GLV ert! 'rWV
auv6foe:roc; 'rWV µuprov xo,;l 'rWV [o,;-rpLXWV [o,;-rpLXWV qio,;pµocxrov xo,;-ra auµqi6o,;paLV
qio,;pµiixrov. 'rWV µLyvuµevrov, &AAou 'rLVOc; e~ O(U'rWV
ye:vvroµevou awµo,;-roc;. (216. 22-25)
Translation
(2a) For in the opinion of mem- (2a) yet some of the mixtures of
bers of the Stoic sect juxtaposition bodies mixed in this substance
mixture blending and fusion differ.
(2b) For juxtaposition is the (2b) occur by juxtaposition,
contact of bodies at their surfaces as through two or more substances
54 THE STOIC THEORY OF TOTAL BLENDING
we see with heaps in which com and being composed into the same mass
barley and figs and other such things and juxtaposed with one another
are combined and with heaps of "by juncture" as he says, and with
stones along the shores and sand- each of them preserving the surface
grains. of their own substance and quality
in such a juxtaposition, as, one will
grant, happens with beans and wheat-
grains in their juxtaposition;
(2c) Mixture is the complete co- (2c) the third type of mixture he
extension of two or more bodies while says occurs through certain sub-
their inherent qualities remain sta- stances and their qualities being
ble, as in the case of fire and heated mutually coextended in their en-
iron, for here complete coextension tirety and preserving their original
of bodies occurs. Similarly with our substance and qualities in such a
souls; for they extend through the mixture: this mixture is blending
whole of our bodies-for it is their in the strict sense of the term. The
opinion that body extends through mutual coextension of some two or
body. even more bodies in their entirety
Blending they describe as the with one another so that each of
complete coextension of two or even them preserves their own substance
more moist bodies and their qualities and its qualities in such a mixture
[154. 24-155. 3] for they say that the -this, he says, alone of the mixtures
quality of each of the moist bodies is blending; for it is a peculiarity of
blended together appears together bodies that have been blended that
from the blend, as with wine, honey, they can be separated again from
water, vinegar, and the like. It is one another, and this only occurs
clear that with such blends the quali- through the blended bodies preserv-
ties of the bodies blended together ing their own natures in the mixture.
remain stable from the fact that they
can often be separated from one
another by an artificial device.
Certainly if one places an oil-
drenched sponge in wine blended
with water it will separate the water
from the wine as the water retreats
into the sponge.
(2d) Fusion is the alteration of (2d) Other mixtures occur by
two or even more qualities that be- total fusion with both the substances
long to bodies to create another and their qualities being destroyed
quality differing from these, as in together, as he says happens with
the composition of perfumes and medical drugs in the joint-destruction
medical drugs. of the constituents and the produc-
tion of some other body from them.
181 Cf. Alexander de mixt. IO. 223. 34-224. 6 where another kind of attempt
to rationalise the motion of pneuma through body is made. The words
A RECONSTRUCTION FROM THE SOURCES 55
illustration of mechanical separation found in the parallel text only
for its author to employ it independently in his account of the
Aristotelian theory of blending later in the de mixtione. 132 Now
both passages could be dependent on a similar source which they
have used in their own way; on the other hand, it is plausible to
suggest in principle that Alexander could have relied on a doxo-
graphic report such as that preserved by Stobaeus. We know of his
acquaintance with doxographical material in Aetius 133 and, of
course, of his use of the Peripatetic source of the doxography,
Theophrastus' Opinions of the Physicists. 134 By examining separately
the details of the two texts quoted here I shall try to show that
all the significant differences between Alexander's report and the
fragment of Arius Didymus can be explained as independent
systematisations by the Peripatetic exegete, so that it is entirely
possible that he employed this text as his source. More importantly
this analysis will draw attention to the numerous difficulties in-
volved in regarding either text as direct evidence for our knowledge
of the theory of total blending, and so prepare the way for an
attempt to integrate this evidence with the interpretation of total
blending already reached on the basis of the primary sources.
(cf. n. 127). Cf. also Pseudo-Galen de qual. incorp. XIX. 471 K (= p. 7. 20-25
Westenberger) who similarly draws a very general connection between fusion
and the formation of drugs from blends. Alexander's ignorance here is prob-
ably also reflected at de an. 24. 24-25.
THE STOIC THEORY OF TOTAL BLENDING
152 I disagree with Rist. (Stoic Philosophy, pp. 158-159) that SVF l 92
(Galen In Hippocr. de hum. XVI. 32 K, cf. Nat. Fae. I. 2, II. 5K) shows that
Zeno held that substances and qualities were capable of change. The texts
attributed to Zeno the thesis that total blends occur between such entities. As
I have argued, this is implausible (see above, p. 30, n. 44; cf. n. 154 below);
in the rest of this section I shall argue that the thesis itself is a misleading
systematisation of Stoic doctrine.
m The evolution of elements from Fire (SVF II 579-581) and the combi-
nation of elements to form compounds (SVF II 413) do not constitute an
exception. The process here is not strictly coming-to-be but the manifesta-
tion of a single physical principle in a variety of roles.
iu In Hippocr. de nat. hom. I XV. 32 K (= SVF II 463); cf. de el. sec.
Hippocr. I. 9, I. 489 K (= SVF II 464).
166 Respectively P.H. III. 57-62 andEnn. II. 7. r. 8-12.
168 We know that Galen was prejudiced towards the "Peripatetic" view
that blends occurred between qualities (cf. IV. 762 Kand X. 16 K).
167 de gen. et corr. A ro 327b 15-22. The term "substances" (oual1XL) is not
used, but only the expression "separables" (x_<slptaT&). It is left to Alexander
60 THE STOIC THEORY OF TOTAL BLENDING
(de mixt. 13. 228. 13-25) to emphasise that substances are the constituents of
blends, though whether or not without difficulty is questionable; see Comm.
on 13. 228. 10-25.
1 &8 There is no other text in Alexander that shows any awareness of the
mixture are then said to differ because of this situation (za). The
initial difficulty is to see whether it is all or part of the preceding
paragraph (r) that is regarded as explaining these processes. If we
assume that the whole phenomenon of pneuma's motion through
matter explains the three mixtures, the causal connection is very
unclear. Are these mixtures processes that occur between pneuma
and matter, as the presence of c;u-yxucrn;; (fusion) in both the descrip-
tion of matter's flexibility and the tripartite classification might
suggest? 162 If so this would be an unprecedented account of
pneuma's motion, and highly implausible as far as the case of
juxtaposition is concerned. On the other hand, could these mixtures
occur after pneuma has pervaded matter and so be processes for
which it provides the physical precondition? This, as we shall see, is
Alexander's interpretation, but it is still unsatisfactory in that there
is no reason why these particular processes should necessarily occur
as a result of pneuma's motion: as we have noted (pp. 56-57 above),
no special connection is drawn in these texts between the extension
of bodies through bodies in blending and the pneumatic motion.
It is, I believe, more informative to look at the relation between
the third sentence of part one of the doxographic report (re) and
the opening sentence of part two. Here a description of the af-
fectability of matter is immediately followed by an account of the
three types of mixture with the claim that the latter depends on
the former. We find an almost identical relation expressed in
another doxographic text at Aetius I. 24. 3. 163
Ilu0ocy6poc,:; xoct 1tocv-re:,:; /Sc;oL 1tot6YJTIJV TIJV lJA'YJV u1to-rl0e:v1"otL, xup(w,:;
ye:vfoe:L,:; xoct cp0opa:,:; ylve:c;0ocL · ex ya:p cx.MoLwc;e:w,:; Twv c;ToLxdwv
xoct 1'p01t~,:; xoct cxvocMc;e:w,:; 164 [ ye:vfoe:w,:; xoct cp0opii,:;] 165 7totpoc0e:c;LV
Xott Xpocc;(v 1'E: Xott c;uyxuc;LV y(yve:c;0otL.
162 On the various contexts in which fusion occurs cf. n. 186 below.
163 Diels, Dox. Graec., p. 320. 29-35.
164 From here to the end I cite Stobaeus Eel. I. xx. 1d3 , p. 170 24-25 W;
Pseudo-Plutarch Epit. I. 24 has only the words 'l'Ot.U'l'Ot. y!ve:cr60t.L after &v0t.Mcre:wi;.
165 Heeren regarded this as a gloss, and it is so recorded by Diels.
THE STOIC THEORY OF TOTAL BLENDING
166 This need not be significant. In the doxography the active and passive
principles were grouped along with the four elements as the principles (iip)(td)
of the Stoic system; cf. Comm. on de mixt. II. 225. 5-18.
167 Cf. Aetius Plac. I. 9. 2 ( = SVF II 324) where the Stoics are grouped
with Thales, Pythagoras, and Heraclitus with respect to their belief in the
affectability of matter {-rpe:7tnJV xoct ii,J.otwniv xoct µe:-roc(3).7lnJV xoct ~e:ucrniv
6).7)v 8t' /1).7)~ -r~v u).·'lv); also cf. SVF II 305.
168 At 2a it is only attributed to the school collectively, and its apparent
From this final discussion we can conclude that the two sources
separately analysed here are indeed the product of a complex
process of transmission. They place a description of pneuma's
motion through matter in a causal relation to a tripartite classifica-
tion of mixtures when these are clearly independent doctrines.
At the same time the details of each of our two sources are affected
both by the doxographical tradition, and, in Alexander's case, by
an apparent attempt to systematise arbitrarily a doxographic
source. The value of these texts as evidence for the Stoic theory
of total blending is therefore severely circumscribed.
As for their interrelation, enough evidence has, I think, been
produced to claim confidently that Alexander is at least dependent
on the classification of mixtures at Arius Didymus fr. 28. Whether
his attempt to systematise the relation between pneuma's motion
through matter and this classification (Alexander, I, 2a) in order
to meet the general framework of the de mixtione was a reformula-
tion of the more diffuse account in the same source is less certain.
There are other cases where he radically systematises doxographic
material to fit his needs, and so in the present instance it is entirely
possible that he followed the same practice.
A Final Reconstruction
On turning back to the preliminary interpretation of the theory
of total blending, the results of the preceding discussion seem at
first sight unpromising. In our major secondary sources total
blending is a process of mutual coextension, contrasted with two
other kinds of mixture, and yet causally unrelated to the theory of
pneuma. Earlier, on the basis of the primary sources, we agreed
that it was the extension of a small volume through a large one,
but such only as a conception analogically formed from empirical
data and thence the basis for a further analogical derivation of
pneuma's motion through matter. Yet because the latter account
s
66 THE STOIC THEORY OF TOTAL BLENDING
And this is the wonderful result for those who force bodies
into a body, and this the inconceivability of their containing
one another. For it is necessary that when bodies go into one
another [e:lc; &tJ...YJ"Aa. :x,wpouv-rwv] in blending, one does not sur-
round the other while the other is surrounded, and one receive
while the other inheres (for in this way there will not be
blending but the contact and touching of surfaces, with the
inner surface enclosed while the outer surface surrounds, while
the other parts are differentiated as unmixed and pure); but
it is necessary that when the blending that they uphold occurs,
the constituents should come to be in one another [ev cxtJ...~"AoLc;
... ylveo-8a.L] and that the same body should, in a single mass,
be surrounded by its inherence [in the other body] and sur-
round the other body by receiving it, and neither of them
should again be capable of existing [independently], when
blending forces both to go through one another [8L' cxtJ...~"Awv
8LLeva.L], and absolutely nothing be left behind but both to be
completely filled up with another. 180
180 1078B-C (Teubner, pp. 104. 20-105. 5). Cf. de mixt. 7. 221. 7-20 for a
more definite polemic against the idea that constituents of a total blend lose
their identity; cf. Comm. ad loc.
181 1078C-D (Teubner, p. 105. 5-23).
182 1078E (Teubner, p. 165. 23-28 = SVF II 480); see above, pp. 31-33.
183 Cf. also de comm. not. 37. 1078C (Teubner, p. 105. 7) where the premise
of Arcesilaus' argument against a small body blending with a larger is el
y(ip e:lcrtv a:l xp(icre:t1; 3t' 11:Awv, again an apparently general characterisation
of intermingling; and 37. 1077E-F (Teubner, pp. 103. 29-104. 3) where a
description of the extension of a small volume through a large one is said
to be propounded by "those who blend bodies with bodies as wholes with
wholes" ('t'ouc; 'l'IX crwµomx 'l'OLc; crwµa:crtv IIAoLc; IIAa: xe:pa:VVUV't'a:c;).
68 THE STOIC THEORY OF TOTAL BLENDING
This rather simple classification has been subjected to a great deal of elabo-
rate speculation. I share Graeser's view (Plotinus and the Stoics, p. 73, where
earlier literature is summarised) that SVF II 367 clearly shows that in author-
ship it is Chrysippean. On its possible relation to the tripartite classification
of mixtures, and the triad State/Soul/Nature see H. Dorrie's speculations
(they are no more) at Porphyrios' "Symmikta Zetemata", pp. 27-28.
190 Made clear by Achilles (SVF II 368) where unified bodies are described
193 More tentatively we can also speculate on the genesis of the doxographi-
cal report at Arius Didymus fr. 28. II, as a systematic description, would
gain a place in the doxography more readily than the complex argument in
III. At the same time, its relation to I had to be acknowledged, and so I and
II were juxtaposed and, as we have argued, placed in a causal relation by a
doxographic rationale. III would probably be preserved only by Stoics, and
it is from such sources that Alexander may have directly derived it; cf.
Comm. on de mixt. 4. 217. 36.
194 de mixt. 4. 218. 2-6.
72 THE STOIC THEORY OF TOTAL BLENDING
198 The general topic of ancient criticisms of total blending has been dealt
with by H. Dorrie, Porphyrios' "Symmikta Zetemata", pp. 24-35, but mainly
with reference to the Neoplatonic tradition. His discussion is also not accom-
panied by a full interpretation of the theory of total blending, nor is the
Peripatetic tradition-the importance of which he is aware (cf. p. 29 n. 1)-
examined in detail. The argument of this section, if correct, will necessitate
some revision in his views of at least the background to the later critique of
total blending; see nn. 200, 211 below. I have also discussed the topic of
"body going through body" in the Peripatetic and exegetical tradition in a
more limited context in an article on Pseudo-Alexander Quaest. II. 12 at
Philologus 116 (1972) 293-305.
188 See Diogenes Laertius VII. 184. It is plausible on chronological grounds:
Arcesilaus' dates are 316/15 to 214/40 (v. Von Arnim, RE II, col. 1164), and
Chrysippus' 281/277 to 208/204 (idem, RE III, col. 2502). The tradition that
made Arcesilaus an opponent of Zeno (Cicero A cad. I. 12. 44) is dubious, and
the text from Plutarch referred to in the next note cannot be taken as evi-
dence that Zeno propounded the theory of total blending, as some of the older
literature claimed (see K. Troost, Zenonis Citiensis de rebus physicis doctrinae,
p. 52 n. 2).
200 Plutarch de comm. not. 37. 1078C-D. There is no evidence of Carneades'
critique of total blending, and though Dorrie (Porphyrios' "Symmikta Zete-
mata", p. 29 n. 1) may be right to speculate that he did deal with it, he was
certainly not "der Ahnherr dieser Kritik." Conceivably Sextus Empiricus
P.H. III. 56-62 is derived from him; cf. n. 251 below.
74 THE STOIC THEORY OF TOTAL BLENDING
181 Hippolytus Philos. 21 (at SVF II 469), Themistius Phys. 104. 14-18
(SVF II 468), both very general accounts. On Plutarch de comm. not. 37.
1077E (SVF II 46.5) cf. the Philolo1;us article cited above (n. 198) at p. 296,
and n. 220 below. Oddly Dorrie (Porphyrios' "Symmikta Zetemata", p. 2.5
nn . .5 and 7) attributes the doctrine of body going through body to Zeno
and Chrysippus on the basis respectively of Arius Didymus fr. 38 (Dox.
Graec., p. 270. 4) and fr. 28 (Dox. Graec., p. 463. 2off. = SVF II 471; quoted
at pp . .52-.53 above). Yet neither of these texts does more than use verbs
of motion to describe the blending of the elements in the first case, and of
soul and body in the second, without even employing the expression o-wµix
3tiX O"©µIXTO~ )'.<ilpE:LV.
282 SVF II, p. 1.51. 7.
288 Decisive on this score is de mixt. 12. 227. 2 where Alexander says that
"body going through body" was not appreciated by the Stoics themselves
as the fundamental notion in their doctrines of God, fate, the soul, etc. Cf.
Comm. ad Toe.
284 Cf. pp. 32-33, 6.5-71 above. In de mixt . .5 and 6 it is clearly irrelevant
which of the two bodies goes through which, and even if a one-way process
is described in a given text it is clearly reversible. This is made quite explicit
in other arguments against the extension of a small body through a large one
which critics explicitly regarded as reversible; cf. pp. 87-88 below.
285 Comm. on de mixt. 6. 219. 11-12; cf. p. 83 below.
"BODY GOING THROUGH BODY" 75
here that this evidence is so extensive and so closely dependent on
Aristotelian texts as to leave no doubt that it was this exegetical
tradition that developed most of the arguments and paradoxes
centred around body going through body that are employed by the
ancient critics of total blending, and moreover that it is this tradi-
tion that Alexander has inherited in his critique of this theory in
the de mixtione and elsewhere.
21 ° Cf.
218. 15-16 with 218. 18-21.
211 This is the only one of these closely related passages noted by Dorrie
(Porphyrios' "Symmikta Zetemata", p. 25 n. 6) who, erroneously I believe
(cf. n. 198), regards "body going through body" as the Stoic contradiction
of this Aristotelian principle. This is a good example of speculative reasoning
establishing historical relations without close attention to the quality of the
sources.
212 It might be added to the "presuppositions of Aristotle's physics"
going through body" (ac7>µix 8Loc awµix't'o~ :x,wpe:'i:v), 216 points out
that it is entailed by Stoic materialism, and finally refers to Alex-
ander's arguments against this paradox "in a separate treatise
and in his commentaries." 216 He then quotes a long passage from
Alexander, presumably from the latter's note on Physics ~I 209a
4-7, in which an argument against bodily interpenetration through
pores is included. 217 This would seem to confirm that the roots of
the argument in de mixtione 5 and 6 do rest in the exegesis of this
Aristotelian argument. Elsewhere among the commentators The-
mistius 218 refers explicitly to the anti-Stoicism of the de mixtione
in his comment on this same text, and Philoponus 219 uses the
expression "body going through body" in the same context. Finally,
passing to a pre-Alexandrian author, we find Plutarch identifying
bodily interpenetration with the theory that body is place, an
equation that he may have derived from a Peripatetic source. 220
Before these connections can be elaborated any further we need
to establish the Aristotelian roots of the whole disjunctive argument
in de mixtione 5 and 6. For although the alternative of bodily
interpenetration through pores is broached in some of the texts just
reviewed its source is still not clear.
281 "For either bodies are not increased at all, or not by body, or it is
possible for two bodies to be in the same place (then they claim to solve a
general difficulty, but do not show that void exists) or the whole body must
be void if it is increased in every part and increased by void." This answers
the earlier argument of proponents of the void that growth occurs through
void as in the case of ash absorbing water (Phys. 213b 18-22), otherwise two
bodies will be in the same place. Cf. de mixt. 220. IO where Alexander, in a
critique of body going through body, refers to the case of ash as one which
does not prove this thesis.
222 "If [it grows] by the incorporeal there will be separable void; but it is
impossible that there be separable matter for a magnitude, as was said ear-
lier." The reference is to 320b 17-25.
223 Cf. Phys. 214b 6-9 ("Either two bodies can be in the same place ...
or the whole body must be void, if it grows throughout and grows through
void.") with Philoponus de gen. et corr. 90. 12-15 (" ... the whole body
that grows [must be] assumed to be a pore, or body [must] pervade body.").
We find the same basic alternative in Alexander's discussion of growth at
de mixt. 16. 234. 23-32.
2 2' See preceding note, and for the expression "void spaces" (xe:vci) see
de mixt. 16. 234. 29. I have discussed elsewhere the extent to which the
discussion of pores both here, and especially in dealing with the theory that
light is a body (see note 246 below), might also have been provoked by
Strato of Lampsacus' theory of interstitial xe:vci; see the Appendix to the
article on Quaest. II. 12 cited above, n. 198.
zu Joachim-presumably relying on the commentators-actually uses this
"BODY GOING THROUGH BODY" 79
alternative (on de gen. et corr. 321a 5-9). Perhaps Aristotle did imply a theory
of interstitial void in this argument, but of an entirely undefined sort.
228 That such a concept of place is implicit in these texts is clear from de
(325b 5-7), since (b) if bodies were completely divisible then there would
only be pores and no intervening solids (325b 7-9); (c) if pores are filled then
they are superfluous (326b 6-10), whereas if they are empty they must con-
tain body since pores so small as to be unable to receive body are incon-
ceivable. (a) and (b) equate Empedocles with Atomism, while (c) is directed
just against the former.
228 This can be shown by comparing (1) de mixt. 218. 33-219. 1 with 326b
6-10; (2) 219. 1-3 with 325b 5-7; and (3) 219. 3-5 with 325b 7-9. Also cf.
the texts in (3) with Phys. 214b 8-9 and Philoponus de gen. et corr. 178. 5-20
(on 326b 6) which is relevant although the commentator does not particu-
larly emphasise here that the pores are void.
80 THE STOIC THEORY OF TOTAL BLENDING
505. 23-27, de an. 343. 34-344. 4. Cf. Alexander de an. 20. 14-15.
"BODY GOING THROUGH BODY" 81
Alexander and "Body going through body" (awµ.oc 8Loc awµ.ix-roc; x_wpe~v)
Simplicius, as we saw, reported (at Physics 530. 9-30) that
Alexander dealt independently with the topic of "body going
through body" and considered Stoic materialism in terms of this
paradox. Since all the relevant commentaries of Alexander on the
Aristotelian works in which the paradox of two bodies being in
the same place occurs are lost, his contribution to its elaboration
must be gleaned from his treatises and schooltexts, principally the
Mantissa. 234 The following Alexandrian texts all contain a similar
m On this and the conjoint use of Stoic imagery in such texts see below,
pp. 87-88.
238 Plutarch de comm. not. 37. 1077 E (cf. n. 220 above); Sextus Empiricus
A.M. IX 256-257 (on his date v. Part I, n. 93). Cf. also Pseudo-Galen de qual.
incorp. XIX. 474 K ( = p. 10 Westenberger), a work of uncertain date,
though in view of its general similarities to texts by Alexander and Albinus
(cf. n. 247 below) probably to be dated to the second or early third century
A.D. Its authorship by Albinus, on the basis of a Syrian testimonium, is
argued by E. Orth, Ant. Class. 16 (1947) 113-114.
zu There are problems about the authenticity of this collection as a whole
(cf. above, Pt. I, pp. 18-19). I shall draw evidence from four texts all of
which attack various materialistic theses: (1) "that soul is incorporeal"
(113. 25-u8. 4); (2) "that qualities are not bodies" (122. 16-125. 4); (3)
"that light is not a body" (138. 4-139. 28); (4) "that body cannot pervade
body" (15-rL awµOt 8Lcx awµ0t-ro<; ci8u110t't'O\I 8L"fpmv, 139. 9-141. 28). Of these (4)
is probably derived from Alexander's lost commentary on the Physics (above,
6
THE STOIC THEORY OF TOTAL BLENDING
there any attempt to argue that the Stoic theory must be reducible
to a case of body going through body; it is simply assumed that
this is its essential thesis. As we noted at the end of the preceding
section the basic trend of the ancient criticism of total blending is
to detach it from its place in the Stoic physical system and treat
it as an isolated assertion of a physical paradox. Thus the expression
"body going through body" retains very little of the dynamic
character of the relation between bodies conveyed by the verb "to
extend through" (&v·mtocpe:x-re:lv1m) and related terms, when trans-
posed from the blend of liquids to the case of pneuma's motion
through matter. 236 Among the Aristotelian commentators "body
going through body" means nothing more than that there are
two bodies in the same place, while in Alexander we can find the
verb of going (xwpe:~v) used interchangeably with such verbs as
"to receive" (~exe:0"8ocL) or "to come to be in" (y(ve:0"8ocL ev) 237 that
convey only a minimal sense of motion.
Again, the conception of body on which these polemics rely is
the traditional one of a body as a three-dimensional solid; 238 if
our interpretation is correct, then for the Stoics the total blending
of liquids as an analogically formed conception and not an actual
case of mixture was independent of any theory of body. They could
therefore have invoked the traditional definition of body in char-
acterising relations between intracosmic bodies, while explaining
the motion of body through body in the case of pneuma's motion
through matter in terms of a set of qualitative physical concepts. 239
(2) Alexander's arguments against the view that growth is by
body occur in de mixtione 16. Since this treatise is predominantly
anti-Stoic these might also be considered part of the polemic.
However as they follow the standard pattern of a disjunction
between bodily interpenetration or motion through pores as a gloss
on de generatione et corruptione 321a 6, 240 and since de mixtione 16
238 In the course of de mixt. 5 and 6, at 218. 18 and 219. 23 for example.
Cf. also the use of verbs of motion and extension interchangeably at de mixt.
5. 218. 15-16; see Comm. ad Zoe.
237 See Comm. on de mixt. 5. 218. 17-18 on 8exe:a61xt and for ylve:a60ti iv
241 Plutarch (de comm. not. 44. 1083C-D = SVF II 762) describes Chrysip-
corporeal soul). Mant. 139. IO-II (on corporeal light) refers to the Stoic
rejection of intra-cosmic void (cf. SVF II 522-524). The attack on the doctrine
of a corporeal soul in terms of the paradox of two bodies being in the same
place, or with reference to the classification of mixtures, or both, can be
widely documented from the Neoplatonist tradition; cf. Calcidius In Tim.
221 ( = pp. 234-5 Waszink), with Waszink's note on 234. 5-6 where references
are gathered and the importance of Alexander's contribution noted. All this
does not mean that total blending was primarily designed as an explanation
of the relation of soul to body (pace Gould, Philosophy of Chrysippus, p. II2
n. 4), only that that relation was generally regarded as the philosophically
"BODY GOING THROUGH BODY" 85
Galen de qua!. incorp. XIX. 470-471 K (= pp. 7-8 Westenberger). The latter
passage examines the problem of the copresence of several corporeal qualities
in a single body in terms of the tripartite classification of mixtures (juxta-
position, fusion, blending-cf. pp. 49-65 above), and concludes that they
must be fused together in the same place. This seems to be an entirely polem-
86 THE STOIC THEORY OF TOTAL BLENDING
ical exercise, and would not sustain Pohlenz' general claim (Die Stoa, I,
72) that the particular purpose of the theory of total blending was to explain
how many qualities would be in one body. All three of the texts cited here
deserve close analysis in the context of a reconstruction of the Stoic doctrine
of quality; the general doctrine "that qualities are bodies," against which
they argue, may well have emerged, like "body going through body," solely
within an anti-Stoic tradition.
m Cf. above, p. 41.
m A vestigium from Plutarch (SVF II 433) refers to air being illuminated
xcn·cx vu~Lv ~ ljiocuaLv ("by agitation or contact"). vu~LC; ("agitation") recalls
the use of vu-r-rea8ocL to describe the agitation of the air in vision (SVF II 866,
p. 233. 29-30).
no Cf. for example the very general arguments for the corporeality of the
soul at SVF II 790, 791, and I. 518. There is, however, no clear evidence of
such arguments for the case of body going through body.
"BODY GOING THROUGH BODY" 87
its effect on polemics against the view that mixture could involve
the extension of a small volume through a very large one; for if
mixture is regarded as interpenetration, then the paradox of this
process would be its reversibility. It is exactly this argument that
we find used against the Stoics by Alexander in the Mantissa,
where he reiterates an argument found also in Sextus, and partly
echoed by Plutarch, that ridicules this reciprocal mixture of
unequal quantities by giving them a unit value, so that a small
quantity can be said to be equal to a larger, and vice-versa. 251
The Aristotelian roots of this argument would seem to be evident
from the commentators' use of the argument (attributed to pro-
ponents of the void at Physics Ll6 213b 5-12) that if solids inter-
penetrate then a very large body will occupy the place of a very
small one. 252 This could easily be adapted to meet the Stoic claim
that mixture was in fact the opposite process, and converted into
a new counter-claim that Stoic mixture involved both processes.
Later commentators, probably copying Alexander, certainly used
the example of the mixture of liquids to illustrate the mixture of
a very large with a very small body, taking the image of wine
pervading the sea used by the Stoics and making it part of their own
general arguments against body going through body. 253 Philoponus
actually employs this originally anti-Stoic argument that a recip-
rocal mixture of liquids will occur between unequal quantities if
m Cf. 1\fant. 141. 9-16 with Sextus Empiricus P.H. III. 60-61 and
Plutarch de comm. not. 37. rn78A-B. The latter deals only with the blending
of a small with a large volume, although at rn78E-F he refers in general
terms to the opposite process, the compression of many bodies into one.
Alexander's critique also shows signs of being influenced by more abstract
arguments against the contact of part with whole: cf. Mant. 141. 16-19 with
Sextus Empiricus A.M. IX. 261. Mant. 140. I0-24 and 141. 19-22 are more
general arguments against "reciprocal" blending. These particular argu-
ments could well have originated in the sceptical tradition (cf. n. 200 above)
and have been grafted onto the Peripatetic arguments against "body going
through body."
252 Discussed at pp. 80-81 above.
263 At Mant. 140. 22-23 the image of a cup of wine mixing with the sea
body goes through body, 254 but presents it as a support for the
Aristotelian text (Physics 209a 4-7) in which the paradox of two
bodies being in the same place is said to be entailed by the theory
that place is body. The Stoics have been forgotten, but a polemic
against them continues latent in Aristotelian exegesis. 255
254 Phys. 506. 2-14. That is, it employs the standard arguments referred
to in n. 251 above.
116 Another example of this is the reappearance of Alexander's general
critique of the Stoic theory of presentation (cpixv't'ixa(ix) at de an. 68. 12-18 in
Byzantine commentaries-cf. Michael Parv. Nat. (CAG XXIl-1) 3. 7-16,
and Sophonias (Ps.-Themistius) Paro. Nat. (CAG V-6) 4. 25-31.
PART THREE
THE DE MIXTIONE
INTRODUCTION
form by Gaspar Gabriel of Padua made between 1541 and 1543. Also cf.
Cranz's interesting discussion of the weltanschauung of some of these Re-
naissance translators at Amer. Philos. Soc. 102 (1958) 510-546. It should be
noted that Schegck's translation occurs as a complement to an essay entitled
de causa continente in which Alexander's critique of the Stoics is discussed
with reference to Galen's treatment of their theory of causes. It is perhaps
the earliest piece of scholarship on the de mixtione.
8 See Bruns, SA II-ii, Praef. p. xxxviii and Montanari, Atti dell'Accademia
216. 1-4. The theories of mixture held by those who believe that
matter is unified are taken up.
216. 5-14. Of these, the Stoics are the principal theorists. Despite
doctrinal differences as a result of Aristotle's influence, Chrysippus'
theory of mixture is the most widely accepted.
217. 32-218. IO. Clear evidence of this can be seen in the soul-
body relation, and parallel relations among plants and inanimate
bodies; in the relation between elements of differing density;
and in the presence of fire in iron, light in air, and drugs in
bodies.
ANALYTICAL OUTLINE 99
226. 16-24. If God is the form of matter at the time of the con-
flagration then his form will change when fire changes into other
bodies. And if this change is caused by God, he will be self-destruc-
tive, which is ludicrous.
226. 24-30. The picture of God as an active creator of the most
insignificant bodies is unworthy of our preconception of him.
226. 30-33b (+ 227. 23-25). Ifbodiesthataremixedarereciprocally
active and passive, then God will be acted on by matter.
229. 3-21. Blending only occurs among bodies that can act and
be acted on by one another. This requires that they share in the
same matter, and be mutual opposites.
229. 21-30. Opposites act and are acted on not only at their ex-
tremes, but at points between the extremes, for they have the same
form as the extremes. In general, all such interaction of opposites
depends on their sharing in the same matter, while differing only
in forms and accidental qualities.
229. 30-230. 13. The differing qualities of the four elements make
it possible for them to change into one another. A change occurs
when one opposite dominates another, and its form supervenes on it.
231. 12-29. Moist bodies are easily mixed, since they are easily
divisible, and the blend is a single body with the constituents
present in it in potentiality. Therefore the recovery of the con-
stituents is an easily effected change, being neither absolute coming-
to-be, nor the recovery of the original constituents (in that case
they would only have been juxtaposed).
r * * * 1twc; o' ocv 1tocpocoe~ocL"C'6 "t'Lc; "C'o ev TTi "C'OLotUTfl x.pocGe:L "t'wv Gwµ.oc"t'wv
EX.otG"C'OV "C'WV X.LpvotFVWV !pUl\ot"C'"C'&LV oUVotGeotL TI)V OLX.ELotV E7tL!potVELotV,
d - ,./. "). I '1-1 I > / > / <
we;
oµ.ou µ.e:v (L'YjOE: "C'O "C'U"/.OV otU"C'WV µ.6pLOV e:!votL ["C'E] x.oc0' otU"C'O x.e:y_wpLGµ.evov
5 0ot"C'epou, oµ.ou oe: !pUAIX"C"'C'ELV &X.otG"C'OV otU"C'WV "C'YJV E7tL!plXVELotV "C'YJV &otU"C'OU,
~v e:!xe: x.ocl. 1tpo -rijc; x.poc<1e:wc;; "C'OU"C'O ycxp U7tEpotLpEL x.otl. "t'CXc; ev "C'OLc; µ.u0oLc;
7totpotOO~OAOytotc;, 8 "C'L0'YjGL XpuGL7t7tOc; l>GOV ev "C'OU"C'CJ) ["C'O] OUVotG0otL "C'CX X.E-
x.potµ.evot xwpL~EG0otL 7tlXALV, "C'OU "C'E ycxp A&YELV ouvotG0otL xwpL~e:G0otL "C'CX
x.e:x.potµ.evot, <XAACX x.ocl. "C'OU (L'YjO' l>Awc; X.LpviiG0otL "C'LVot OUVotG0otL A£YELV µ.ot-
10 x.pij> 7totpotoo~6"t'e:pov x.ocl. 7totpcx "t'cxc; OC7tlXV"C'WV EVVOLotc; "C'O A&yELV oµ.ou µ.e:v
OL' l>AWV (XAA~AWV xwpe:'i:v "C'LVot GW(Lot"C'ot, we; (L'YjOE:V otU"C'WV µ.6pLOV e:lvotL x.ot0'
otU"C'6, oµ.ou o' &X.otG"C'OV otU"C'WV U7t0 -rijc; otx.e:lotc; emi:potVELotc; 7tEpLey_e:G0otL,
ui:p' ~c; 7tEpLELXE"t'O x.ocl. 1tpo -rijc; µ.t~e:wc;.
"C'E x.otl. 7t0L~ 1te:pmAox.7i E"C'L 'C'S: "C'IX~EL x.ocl. 0foe:L "t'lAAot ylve:G0otL. ei:p' ~c; 06-
213. l 1tept Kpcxo-ewc; KIXt µ(~e:wc; B: 1te:pt µ(~ewe; Ra: cf. Montanari p. 17 n. 2
213. 4 µ"1)8t Br.: µ~-re; codd. ixu-rwv Rex, cf. 213. 5, II, 12: ixu-rou codd.
n secl. Br.
213. 7 -ro seclusi, v. infra
213. 14 xwpe:rv supplevi, cf. 213. II et passim
213. 14 ou8e:µwc; scripsi: ou8e:µtiic; ABCPS, obelo not. Br.: µ"1)8e:µtiic; Ra
TRANSLATION
1 This indicates an addition to the Greek text; I have only noted the more
significant of these. Square brackets carry my own explanatory addenda.
IIO DE MIXTIONE
214 oux ,i-t·6µ.ouc;, O(J,OLO(J,e:p-ij 8e ·twoc ipocow &1mpoc e:!vocL GW(J,ot't'ot, E~ WV ~ TWV
octa6l)TWV yeve:aLc; GW(J,OCT(J)V YLVO(J,&Vl) XotTIX cruyxpLGLV XIXL cruv8e:aLV, dip'> ~c;
86~l)c; 'Avot~ocy6potc; -re: XotL 'ApyJ>..ococ; 8oxouaL ye:yovevocL • ~81) 8e nve:c; XotL
<iµ.e:p-ij TLVIX awµ.ot-rot -rixc; <ipxixc; XIXL GTOL:(E:LIX 't'WV 7tOCVT(J)V 1tpo~x8lJGIXV
5 e:L7tE:LV • eGTL 8e TLc; 86~ot XotL E~ em1te8wv nJV yeve:aLV 7tOLOUO'IX TWV GW(J,IXT(J)V
XIXL E~ <ipL8µ.wv TLc; aMl)),
II ~LO OU xe:tpov XIXL ~µ.iic; 1te:pt otutjc; 8LotAot~e:Lv XotL (J,l)VUGIXL TIX 80-
XOUVTIX ~(J,LV e:ut..oyw-re:poc Aiye:a6otL TWV 1te:pt xpixae:wc; e:tpl)(J,£V(J)V TOU 8oxe:Lv
ou-rwc; ixe:w 7tocpe:x_6µ.e:vouc; 't'IXc; otl't'Lotc;. ~l)(J,6XpL't'Oc; (J,&V oov ~youµ.e:voc; nJV
Ae:yoµ.tVl)V xpiiaLV y(ve:a8ocL XIXTIX 7tocpoc8e:aLV awµ.oc-rwv, 8LocLpouµ.eveuv TWV
20 xLpvocµ.&Vwv e:tc; (J,LXpix xoct -tjj 1tocp' OCAAl)AIX 8foe:L niv (J,L~Lv 1t0Louµ.evwv,
ou8e nJV <ipx~v !pl)GLV e:!votL 1tpoc; /XA~8e:LOCV TLVIX xe:xpocµ.evoc, rJ.AA' e:!votL nJV
8oxouaocv xpiiaLv 1tocpix8e:aLv awµ.oc-rwv <XAA~AoLc; xoc-rix (J,Lxpix aw~6v-reuv ocu-
-rwv EXOCGTOU 'OJV otxe:LotV !pUGLV, ~V E:L:(OV XIXL 7tp0 tjc; (J,(~e:Wc; • 8oxe:LV 8'
otU't'IX xe:xpiia8ocL -rcj'l niv oc!a6l)aLv 8Lix (J,Lxp6Tl)TIX -rwv 1tocpotxe:Lµ.evwv (J,l)8e:-
25 voe; ot\JTWV octa6ocve:a6ocL 8uvoca6ocL µ.6vou. !pLAIXA~8wc; -re: XotL !pLAoa6ipwc;
oux c:'>XVl)O'E:V d1te:Lv TO e:1t6µ.e:vov -rote; OUT(J) -.ixc; xpocae:Lc; AtyouaL y(ve:a8otL.
1tocpoc8foe:L 8e 't'OLIXU't'"(l -rixc; xpoco-e:LC /XVOC7tTOUO'L XIXL ol -rixc; O(J,OLO(J,E:pe:lotc; UAl)V
e:!votL -rwv ywoµ.ivwv Myov-re:c;.
there are not atoms but certain uniform and infinitely numerous
bodies from which the coming-to-be of perceptible bodies occurs
by compounding and composition, a theory that Anaxagoras and
Archelaus seem to have held; some were inspired to say that the
first-principles and elements of everything were actually certain
partless bodies, and there is one theory which makes bodies come
to be from planes, and yet another from numbers)
214. 6 now these
thinkers, as I said, not only disagree in saying that blends occur
in different ways through the implications of their different first-
principles, but there is also an internal discord among the very
ones who say that matter is unified and again among those who
say that it is divided and discrete.
214. IO The reason for such a great disagreement among them is the
difficulty of the doctrine; for given that it was clear that certain
bodies blended with one another almost all philosophers of nature
and natural change went in search of its explanation, yet since this
proved difficult to discover, and as peculiar difficulties were entailed
by each of the explanations offered, divergent theories arose.
214. 16 II So it is no less important that we too should deal with the
subject, and uncover what seem to us the more reasonable theories
expressed on blending, and explain the reasons why they seem so.
214. 18 Democritus, then, thinks that what is termed blending occurs
by juxtaposition of bodies, with the constituents being divided
into corpuscles and forming themselves into a mixture by their
positioning beside one another; he says that they are not at all
blended in reality, but that the apparent blend is a juxtaposition
of bodies with one another where each preserves in corpuscular form
its own nature, which they had even before the mixture. These
bodies seem to be blended since perception is unable to grasp a
single one of them because of the minuteness of the juxtaposed
bodies. A lover of truth and a philosopher, he did not shrink from
stating the consequence for those who say that blends occur in this
way. (It is to such a juxtaposition that those who hold that uniform
bodies are matter for what comes to be also reduce blends.)
II2 DE MIXTIONE
8
DE MIXTIONE
216 III Me:-r&A8wµ.e:v 8E E7tL -rouc; XOLVW<;; ~vwcr6ocL 't"YjV \JA'YjV Aeyov-rocc; xocl. (.LLIXV 1t&O'L
-ro'i:c; yLvoµ.evoLc; xoct 't"YjV IXU't"YjV t11to8Moc<;;, 6lv xocl. ocu-rwv 1tocp1XL't"YJO'OC(.LEVOL
't'CX E7tL7tOAIXLO't'e:p6v n xocl. 7tpo:x_e:Lp6-re:pov e:tp'YJ(.LSVOC -rcxc; (.LIXALO''t'IX 8oxouaoc<;;
l:x,e:cr6oc( -rwoc; Myou 86/;occ; E/;e:-roco-wµ.e:v 1tpo:x,e:LpLo-ocµ.e:voL. -rwv 8~ ~vwcr6ocL
5 't'YJV 5AYJV Ae:y6v-rwv 8oxouaL µ.ocALa-roc -re: xocl. 1te:pLxpoc-rwc; ot &1to -rijc; I:-ro&<;;
1te:pl. xpocae:<u<;; 8LOCAOC(.L~OCVELV. OUO"'Yj<;; 8E xocl. EV 't'OU't'OL<;; 7tOAUCf>WVLOC<;; (1.t.AAOL
ycxp l.t.AAw<;; IX\J't'WV -rcxc; xpoco-e:L<;; ylve:a8ocL ASYOUO'LV), ~ (.LOCALO''t'IX 8oxouaoc 86-
/;oc e:MoXL(.LELV 1tocp' IX\J't'OL<;; 1te:pl. xpoco-e:wc; EO''t'LV ~ U7t0 XpuO'L7t7tOU Ae:yoµ.e-
V'YJ, 't'WV ycxp µ.e:-r' IX\J't'OV OL (.LEV XpuO'L7t7t<il o-uµ.cpepoVTIXL, OL 8e 't'Lve:c; (XIJ-
IO 't'WV -rij<;; 'ApLO"'t'OffAOU<;; 86/;YJ<;; t)O''t'Epov IX.XOUO'IXL 8uv'Yj8evnc; 7t0AACX 't'WV e:t-
• • J,. , , , , \ , , , , "\., T T ' '
P'YJi-VWV U7t EXELVOU 7tEpL xpocae:wc; )((XL IXU't'OL I\EYOUO"LV. (l)V e:~c; EO''t'L XIXL
I:wo-Lyev'Yjc;, e:-roci:po<;; 'Av-rmoc-rpou. otc; O\J 8uvocµ.e:voL 7t!XV't'7) auµ.cpepe:cr6ocL
8Lcx 't"YjV EV -roi:c; l.t.AAOL<;; 8Loccpwvfocv EV 7tOAAoi:c; IXU't'OL<;; Myovnc; e:upLGXOV't'IXL
(.LIX:X,0(.LEVIX.
20 OCUTWV EV -tjj TOLOCUT"() 1tocpoc6e<m XOCTIX TI)V m:pLypoc<p~v TI)V otxdocv OUO'locv
T& XOCL 1t0L6t7JTOC, we;
€7tL XUIXfLWV <pep& &L7t&LV XOCL 1tupwv EV -tjj 7tocp' OCAA~-
Aouc; 6fo&L • ylveo-6ocL TIXc; 8e TLvocc; O'UY)'..UO'&L 8L' OAWV TWV T& OUO'LWV OCUTWV
XOCL TWV EV OCUTOCLc; 7t0LO~TWV O'UfL<p6&LpOfL€VWV OCAA~AocLc;, we;
y(veo-6ocl !pljO'LV
e:1tt Twv tocTpLxwv cpocpfL!XX<uv XOCTIX O"UfLcp6ocpow Twv fLLyvufL&vwv, &Mou TL-
25 voe; €~ OCUTWV y&VVWfLEVOU O'WfLOCToc;. TIXc; 8& TLvocc; ylveo-6ocL fLL~&Lc; A&Y&L 8L'
OAWV TLVWV OUO'LWV T& XOCL TWV TOUTWV 7t0LO~TWV OCVTL7tOCp&XT&LVOfL&VWV OCA-
A~AocLc; fl.&TIX TOU TIXc; €~ ocpx~c; OUO'tocc; T& XOCL 7tOL6nJTOCc; O"W~&LV EV -tjj fLt-
~&L -tjj TOL~8&, ~VTLVOC TWV fLL~&WV xpio"LV t8(wc; &LVOCL A&Y&L. TI)V YIXP Mo
~ xoct 7tA&L6vwv TLvwv O'Wfl.lXT<uv oAwv 8L' oAwv ocvTL7tocp&XTOCO'LV oc'M~AoLc;
30 oihwc;, we;O"W~&LV EXOCO'TOV OCUTWV EV -tjj fLL~&L -tjj TOLOCU't"fl ~v T& otxdocv
OUO'tOCV XOCL TIXc; EV ocu-tjj 7tOL6nJTOCc;, A&y&L xpio-LV &LVOCL fL6V1jV TWV fLL~&WV.
&LVOCL YIXP !8wv TWV X&XpOCfL&VWV TO 8uvoco-6ocL xwpl~eo-6ocL 7t1XALV oc1t' OCAA~-
217 AWV, 8 fL6vwc; ylv&TOCL T<j'l O'W~&LV EV -tjj fLt~&L TIX X&XpOCfL&VOC TIXc; OCUTWV
<pUO'&Lc;.
216. 22 Oe:ae:t· y(ve:aOou (codd.) -roc~ Apelt: Oecm y(ve:TixL, -roc~ Br.
Ideler: auyxuae:L~ ABCSRa: aunuae:L~ p
217. 4 Acx~e:rv -rixuTix~ coni. Br.: A1X~611-rix~ codd.
217. 5 &.pµ1)v Br. : cipµ1)v codd.
217. 6 a.AA7JAOL~ Apelt: ill71Aou~ codd.
217. 9 &.pµ1)v Br.: cipµ1)v codd.
TEXT AND TRANSLATION n7
preserving the surface of their own substance and quality in such
a juxtaposition, as, one will grant, happens with beans and wheat-
grains in their juxtaposition; other mixtures occur by total fusion
with both the substances and their qualities being destroyed to-
gether, as he says happens with medical drugs in the joint-destruc-
tion of the constituents and the production of some other body from
them; the third type of mixture he says occurs through certain
substances and their qualities being mutually coextended in their
entirety and preserving their original substance and qualities in
such a mixture: this mixture is blending in the strict sense of the
term. The mutual coextension of some two or even more bodies
in their entirety with one another so that each of them preserves
their own substance and its qualities in such a mixture-this, he
says, alone of the mixtures is blending; for it is a peculiarity of
bodies that have been blended that they can be separated again
[217] from one another, and this only occurs through the blended
bodies preserving their own natures in the mixture.
217. 2 He tries to establish that these differences in mixture exist by
means of the common notions, and says that we take these above
all as the standards of truth from nature; at least we have one
[sense-] presentation for the bodies that are juxtaposed by juncture,
another for those that are fused and destroyed together, and a
third for those that are blended and mutually coextended in their
entirety so that each of them preserves its own nature. We would
not have this difference in presentations if bodies had been juxta-
posed by juncture whatever way they were mixed. He assumes
that such a mutual coextension of constituents [of blends] occurs
as constituent bodies go through one another, so that there is no
part of them that does not partake of everything in such a product
of mixture through blending; otherwise the result would no longer
be blending but juxtaposition.
217. 13 IV The proponents of this theory forward as suasions of their
belief that this occurs the fact that many bodies preserve their
own qualities in manifestly smaller and larger masses (as can be
n8 DE MIXTIONE
16 opcxv fo'TLV E7tL 'TOU AL~(XV(l)'t'OU, oc; EV -rcj> 6uµtoca6cxL 1.e1t..-uv6µevoc; E7tL
1t1.e'i:o--rov niv cxu-rou q:mM.o-o-eL 1tot6-.ri-rcx), ht -re ..-o 7tOAAIX e!vcxL, & xcx6'
E:CXU't'IX µ~ o!cx. -re OV'TCX E7tl 't'L Et.6e°Lv µeye6oc; u1t' (1.AA(l)V ~O"l)8ouµEvcx E7t'
CXU't'O 1tp6ELO'L. 't'OV youv XPUO'OV u1t6 't'LVWV µtyvuµevwv cpcxpµcx.xwv E7tL
20 7tAELO''t'OV ):EL0"8cx( TE XIXL AE7t't'UVea6cxL, E<p' 60-ov xix8' IXU't'OV EAcxuv6µEvoc;
oux E8uVIX'TO. xcxl. ~µEL<:; 8e, & xix8' cxu-rouc; OVTE<:; oux foµev o!o( 't'E EVEp-
"(ELV, O'UV OCAAOL<:; EVEpyouµev. -rouc; TE yixp 7t0'TIXµouc; 8LCX~IXLVO!,LEV OCAA~A(l)V
ECj)CX7tTOµevoL, oOc; oux o!o( -re foµev 8LIX~IX(VELV xix8' cxu..-ouc;. xcxl. ~CX.P"IJ
't'LVIX cpepoµev µE-r' OCAAWV, 6)V 't'O Em~CX.AAOV ~µLv µepoc; µ6voL "(Ev6µevoL
25 cpepeLV OU 8uvcx.µe8ix. xcxl. ocµ1tEAOL 8e: xix8' IXU't'IX<:; fo..-cxa61XL µ~ 8uvcx.µevcxL
OCVLO''TCXV't'IXL OCAA~ACXL<:; Eµ1t1.Ex6µev1XL.
't'OU 8e:
-rou8' ou..-wc; &):eLv we; Evcxpyeo-L XPWV't'CXL µixp..-up(oLc; ..-4> TE TI)V t!iux~v t8(cxv
U7t00''t'IXO'LV txoUO'IXV, W0'7tep XIXL 't'O 8Ex6µEvov IXUTI)V o-wµix, 8L' 61.ou 't'OU
35 o-wµcx-roc; 8L~l<.eLV EV TTI µ(~eL -tjj 1tpoc; IXU't'O O'W~OUO'IXV TI)V otxEllXV OUO'LIXV
(ou8e:v "(IXp tJiux'Yjc; &µoLpov 't'OU TI)V tJiux~v lxov-roc; o-wµix-roc;), oµolwc; 8e:
&):eLv XIXL TI)V 't'WV Cj)U't'WV Cj)UO'LV, Cl.At.IX XIXL TI)V &~LV EV 't'OL<:; o-uvexoµevoLc;
218 u1to T'Yjc; i~ewc;. Cl.At.IX xixl. -ro 1tup 01.ov 8L' 61.ou xwpELv -rou o-L8~pou
At"(OUO'L, O'W~OV't'O<:; CXU't'WV e:xcx-repou TI)V OLXELIXV OUO'LIXV. xixl 'TWV O''t'OL):eLWV
8e Cj)CXO'L 't'WV 't'EO'O'CX.pwv TIX Mo, 't'O TE 1tup xcxl. 'TOV &.epcx, AE7tTOµEp'Yj 'TE
xcxl. xoucpix xixl. EU't'OVCX OV't'CX, 8LIX 't'WV Mo, y'Yjc; TE xcxl. u8ix-roc;, 7tlX):UµEpwv
5 xixl. ~cxpewv xcxl. OC't'OV(l)V OV't'(l)V 8LIX7tECj)OL'")XtVIXL /St.ix 8L' 61.wv, O'W~OV'TIX TI)V
otxdcxv cpuo-Lv xcxl. O'UVt):ELcxv cxu-rcx. 'TE xcxl. EXELVIX. 8"/JA"IJ~pux. TE 'TIX cpcx.pµixxix
XIXL TIX<:; oo-µcx.c;, ()O'IXL 't'OLIXU't'IXL, ~"(OUV't'IXL XLpvoca61XL 't'OL<:; u1t' CXU't'WV
7tCX.O'):OUO'LV, ()ACX 8L' 61.wv 7t1Xp1X't'L8eµEvcx. XIXL 't'O cpwc; 8e: ..-<j> &.epL o Xpu-
O'L1t1toc; XLpvoca61XL At"(EL. XIXL <XU'") µe:v ~ 1tepl. xpcx.o-E<i>c; 86~cx XpUO'L7t7tOU
10 TE xixl. ..-wv xcx..-' ixu-rov <pLt.oo-ocpouv-rwv.
EL µev YIXP 8LIX 1t6pwv 'TLVWV xwpe:°Lv IXU'TIX 8L' CXAA~AWV Ae-
25 ye:L, ~ xevouc; Epe:L -rouc; 1t6pouc; -rouc; 8ezoµevouc; 'TO awµix <~> lltJ..ix 'TIX
EV Tei> awµIXTL XEVCX.. e:t 8e 7tA~pELc; llAAOU 'TLVoc; awµix-roc;, EL µev U7tE~L-
6v-roc; 'TOU'TOU XIXL 7t1Xpixxwpouv-roc; tjc; xwpixc; Tei> E7te:Laxpwoµevep awµix-rL,
ou8' o(hwc; €<1'TIXL 'TO awµix, xix6o awµix, 8e:z6µe:v6v 'TL awµix EV IXU'Tci>, d
ye U7tOXWPEL 6&.-repov 6ix-repep, EL 8e u1toµevov-roc;, 1twc; o!6v n -rouc; 7tE:7tA'Yj-
30 pwµevouc; 1t6pouc; awµix-roc; EV IXU'TOLc; lltJ..o 'TL 8eze:a61XL awµix; XIXL YIXP 8ux
tjc; ixta6~aewc; yvwpLµov, O'TL µ'Yj8£ 'TIX AE1t'T6'T1X'TIX 'TOU awµix-roc; cxyydix 7tE-
7tA'Yjpwµevix o!&. 'TE £(TTL 8e~ixa6ixL awµix EV IXU'TOLc; Tei> XEXWAUa61XL xixl. E1tL-
1te:cpp&.z6ixL 'TIXc; tjc; µe:TIX<1'TCX.<1EWc; IXU'TWV o8ouc;. €'TL 8' EL 8LIX 7tE:7tA'Yj-
pwµevwv 'TWV 1t6pwv ~ 1ta.po8oc; 'TOLc; awµixaL, 1te:pLn6v EG'TL 'TO 1t6pouc; e:t-
219 VIXL AeyELV. 8exoLV'TO YIXP &v lltJ..ix awµix-rix xixl. xwpl.c; 'TWV 1t6pwv. xix66-
AOU y1Xp ~ 8LIX -rwv 1t6pwv 1ta.po8oc; ou xpiia(c; £GTLV, o!ixv CX~LOUaLv, CXAAIX
1tixp&.6eaLc;, we; IXU'TOL AeyouaL xix6' &pµ~v. e:t µ~ 'TLc; 1tiiv 'TO awµix 1t6pouc;
1toLOLlJ. oihwc; y1Xp µ6vwc; fo-rixL -ro 8LIX -rwv 1t6pwv 8Lepz6µevov 8L1X 1tixv-roc;
5 Epz6µe:vov 'TOU awµix-roc;, e:t 1tiiv e:t'Yj 1t6poc; • CXAAIX f-Ll)V ll-ro1tov 'TOU'TO. 'TLVOc;
218. 12-13 1tciacw; µiiXAov ~ T0tUT0tL<; scripsi: ou 1tcia0tL<; µ.~.-r. Br.: O\laatL<; µiiXAov
~ [ii Bruns] Tatu-ratL<; ABCPS v. infra
218. 15 a.1to8e:'t Apelt, cf. Alex. de an. 9. I, 5: 1b0tv 8e:i codd.
218. 16 ou suppl. Apelt
218. 19-20 aatip~ve:LCXV lxeL, 8L' ~V DieJs: &.ip81)a0tv E:XELV 8e:i ~V codd., obelo
not. Br. v. infra
218. 21 TL Apelt: TO codd. 6 Br.: av codd.
218. 25 ~ codd. Rex: ou Br. <~> Rex &.nix -rix codd. Rex: &.n'
ouTw Br.
218. 28 OtUTcjl scripsi, cf. 218. 18, 23: OtUTcjl codd.
219. 3 &:pµ1)v ABCS: &.pµ1)v PR: xcxTix &:pµ~v (Br.) correxi
TEXT AND TRANSLATION 121
218. IO V One might wonder how they could say that the common
notions, as the natural standards of truth, should be used in dem-
onstrating theories, and yet use every notion but these in estab-
lishing their own doctrines. Certainly their statements on blending
not only fail to be based on natural notions but are in fact as far
removed from them as it is possible to be. For bodily interpenetra-
tion with full coextension not only fails to strike us as in accord
with the common notions but is also preconceived to be impossible.
It is, indeed, a natural notion that what is full can no longer receive
anything in itself; for it is obvious that that which has space in it
capable of receiving another body cannot yet be full, and on account
of this natural and common preconception some think it reasonable
that there be something receptive of bodies which we call place.
For how could someone who did not wish to talk nonsense think
that any body, full of itself and with no empty interval in it, received
in itself another similarly full body?
218. 24 For if he says that they go through one another by means of
pores he will either say that the pores which receive the body are
empty, or that there are some other empty spaces in the body.
Now if [the pores] are full of some other body, but if this body
departs and provides space for the body that is blended in, then
the body qua body will not even in this way be receiving body in
itself, if one of the bodies withdraws before the other; but if the
body remains, how could the pores that are filled with body receive
some other body in themselves? For it is known through perception
that not even the narrowest vessels of the body can receive a body
in them when they are filled because their paths for displacement
are impeded and blocked. But again if the entrance into bodies is
through filled pores it is superfluous to say that pores [219] exist;
for bodies could then receive other bodies even without the pores.
For, in general, entrance through pores is not blending of the
kind they uphold but juxtaposition "by juncture," to use their
precise term-unless one made the whole body into pores. For only
if all of it were a pore would the body passing right through the
pores go through the whole body. But that is ridiculous, for the
122 DE MIXTIONE
6 yocp o1t6poc; (xod lx.tJ...o 't'O tx.ov xoct 't'O EX,6µ.&vov), &L y& a 1t6poc; 8Locaniµ.oc
't'L €a't'L X&VOV 't'OU ex_ov-roc; -rouc; 1t6pouc; awµ.oc-roc;. &a-r' &t 1tiiv &Ll) <1t6poc;>,
oihwc; 8' (XV oux ov &Ll) 't'L • µ.~ ov 8' ou-r' (XV XLpvcjl-ro &'t'L ou-r' (XV 1t6pouc;
<&X,OL>.
VI Et 8' oihw µ.e:v OU qiocaL 't'OC awµ.oc-roc lx.AAl)AOC 8ex_&a8ocL, xoc8o 8e:
10 µ.ea-roc &cr't'L ocu-roc, x_wp&i:v 8L' octJ...~1.wv ocu-roc qiocmv, 1tpw-rov µ.e:v Em~l)~-
aocL 't'Lc; &.v, 't'L 8~7t0't'& OU 't'O 't'U)'._OV awµ.oc [ 't'O 't'UX,OV] 7t0CV't""(l auvcxU~l)'t'LXOV 't'OU
oµ.o
t (
OU. 't'OC\ yocp
\
1toaoc\ [ 't'OC\ ] XOC't'CX\ TIJV
\
1tpoc;
\
CX/\1\l)I\CX
~"). "). ").
auv
I e \
&aLV TIJV 't'OLCXUTIJV
I
't'O E~ OCU't'WV µ.&i:~ov EXOC't'epou 7t0L&L 't'WV auyx&Lµ.evwv. ypcxµ.µ.oc( 't'& yocp
XCX't'OC <1l)µ.&'i:ov OCAA~AOCLc; auv-r&8&i:aocL 't'O µ.ijxoc; CXU~OUaLV (ou-rwc; yocp <1UV't'L-
I 5 8eµ.&vcxL E~ ocvocyxl)c; E~oua( 't'L 1tocpoc ~v OC(j)~V), E7tL7t&8oc 't'& 't'O OCU't'O 7tOL&L,
<iv xoc-roc ~v ypocµ.µ.~v auv-r&87i, -r6 <T&> awµ.oc, -rcjl-rpLX,TI 't'& xoct 7t1XV't""(l 8L&a-roc-
VCXL, xcx O e'
~ > \ ~"). ").
&OCV CXl\l\{p oµ.oLwc;
t I > - '[\
CXU't'Cp -
oL&a't'W't'L A,:: J t:- I I
<1UV't'&v I t;
fl, &c;,, ocvocyxl)c; auvcxuc;,,&L
't'OU't'O. &L 8~ 't'OU't'O µ.e:v otx&i:ov -roi:c; awµ.ocaLV xoct rnLoV OCU't'WV, ot 8e: U-
yov-r&c; awµ.oc 't'L 8Loc awµ.oc-roc; X,Wp&LV xoc1 &AOC't"t'6v 7t0't'& xoct foov 't'O E~ ocµ.-
20 (j)OLV 7tOL&LV OCVOCLpouaL 't'OU't'O, OCVOCLpoi:&v (XV ~v 't'OU awµ.oc-roc; (j)U<1LV.
auvocvcxLp&L't'OCL yocp OCVCXLpouµ.evep -rcjl £8(ep 't'LVOc; 't'O 1tpiiyµ.oc, 00 ~v t8LOV 't'O
OCVOCLpouµ.&vov.
25 a8ocL -rcjl xoct 1tpo tjc; 't'OU't'OU µ.(~&we; u1t' exdvou 7t&7tAl)pwµ.evep. 0 yocp
u1t' CXU't'OU xocnx.6µ.&voc; -r61toc; fo-rocL X&voc; 't'WV Mo awµ.oc-rwv &tc; 't'OV 8oc-
-repou X,Wpl)<11XV't'WV -r61tov. 't'L yocp fo-rocL 't'O E~ ocvocyxl)c; yLv6µ.&vov EV -rcjl
't'OU &tc; 't'O awµ.cx µ.e-rcxa't'OCV't'Oc; -r61tep; oaoc 8' cxo 7t0CALV EV -r7i 1tpoc; lx.AAl)AOC
µ.(~&L 't'WV XLpviia8ocL A&yoµ.evwv OCU~&'t'OCL, ocu-r68&v ~8l) 7tpOa7tL7t't'&L 't'O µ.l)8E:
219. 7 lacunam post &t"I) Br.: 1t6pot; supplevi: <1t6pot;, 8ttxa'n)µtt 1tiiv &v Eh)>
coni. Br.
219. 8 pr. !Iv coni. Br.: av codd. alt. ou-r' Schwartz: 8' ou8 codd.
219. 9 ~x_ot suppl. Schwartz
219. 10-II em~lJ-r~acxt -rtt; ll.v scripsi, cf. 225. 18, Alex. de an. 60. 22, Quaest.
72. 17, Metaph. 59. 28: em~lJ~OClt 'rtt; Apelt Br.: em~"l)rijacxv codd.
219. II [-ro -rux_ov] coni. ldeler Rex: -rou -rux_6v-rot; coni. Br.
2 I 9. I 2 -rix sec!. Schwartz
219. 16 <-re> Rex -rci> coni. Br.: -ro awµcx, -ro codd.
219. 29 µ"1)8t coni. Br.: µ-IJ -ro codd.
TEXT AND TRANSLATION 123
30a&µix e:!vixL 't'O a&µix 8e:8e:yµevov EV 't'IXU't'cj>, e:t ye: lx.AAYJV 't'LVOC xwpixv 1tpoa-
e;(,-Yjcpe: XIXL oux ~pxita8Yj -tjj xwp~ -tjj 't'OU t.e:yoµevou IXU't'O EV IXU't'cj> 8e-
xe:a81XL awµix't'oc;. l>'t'L 8e µ~ a&µoc EO''t'L 't'O 8e:unpov EV IXU't'c°j) 't'O 7tpW't'OV
8e:x6µe:vov ['t'O] a&µix, 8YJAOL XIXL fi ye:voµitVYj 8L1XLpe:aLc; u1t' a.AA~A(J)V 't'WV
220 XLpvixµevwv O'WµOC't'WV. IXU't'OC yocp 8L1XLpOUV't'IX 8Lt0"'t'IXV't'IXL. 8L1XLpouµe:vix 8e
xwpixv EIXU't'OLc; 7t1Xpixaxe:uoc~e:L, we; µ~ 8uvocµe:vix 8Loc auve:xouc; XIXL a.8L1XLpit't'OU
't'OU U7tOXe:Lµevou awµix't'o<; e:tc; 't'L 7tpoae:t.8dv.
219. 30 't'IXu'l'cj> scripsi, cf. Aristot. Phys. 209a 6-7 (tv 'l'IXU'l'cj> [sc. 't'6mi>J): ixu'l'cj>
codd.
219. 31 ixu'l'cj> scripsi: ixu'l'cj> codd.
219. 32 ixu't'cj> scripsi: ixu't'cj> codd.
219. 33 [To] coni. Br.
220. 1 ixu't'ix coni. Br., cf. tixu't'oii; (220. 2): '!'ix codd.
220. 3 't'L scripsi: 't'0 codd. 1tpoae:t..6eiv] obelo not. Br. qui 1tp6aw tt..6e:!v
coni. [e:!J coni. Ideler Rex
220. 4 a<7iµix, µri8ev obelo not. Br.; [d] l8e:L, <d> ev 't'L 8e:x6µe:vov a<7iµix tV
ixu'l'cj> &llo a<7iµix <µri8ev µe:i~ov y[ve:'t'ixt> coni. Br.
220. 9 li; 't'L Apelt: t<r'l'iv codd.
220. IO ou8' !v obelo not. Br.
220. 11 ixu't'oi:i; scripsi, cf. 218. 32: ixu't'cj> codd.
220. 14 µev codd. Rex: Iv Diels Br.
220. 16 1t<7li; 8' 0\J)( Diels: O~'t'Wi; 8' av codd.
220. 18 xe:6µe:vix Diels: Kixt6µe:vix codd.
TEXT AND TRANSLATION 125
received in the same place [as A, pr] is not even body, if indeed it
[BJ has occupied some other place and is not sufficed by the place
[pr] of the body [A] said to receive it [BJ in itself.
219. 32 And that the second body [BJ which receives the first body [A]
in itself is not even body is clear from the mutual division of con-
stituents; [220] for in dividing one another they create a cleavage,
and in being divided provide space for themselves because they
cannot make any advance through the underlying body that is
continuous and undivided.
220. 3 In general a body that receives another body in itself must be-
come no greater; for that is what "to receive something in itself"
means. There is no body for which the mixture of bodies preserves
a mass equal to one of the constituents; for where it seems to
remain equal there is no mixture of bodies but the cases involve
either form and matter (as soul and body) or body and quality
(as iron and heat) or a given change occurs into some other thing,
as happens with ash. But neither qualities nor forms are bodies
and certainly would not receive another body in themselves.
220. II Again if bodies were able to receive one another there would no
longer be any need of mutual-replacement for their motion; for
certainly body will not pervade body without motion.
220. 13 Furthermore, how irrational also to say that a minute body
would be made equal to and be extended with a very large one,
as when the pitcher of wine becomes equal to many measures of
water in its quantity. How absurd to attempt to establish this
through the fact that incense and bodies that are similarly in-
cinerated are seen to be melted over a considerable expanse in the
incineration; for while incense, and bodies that are similarly in-
cinerated and change into some other more attenuated body, in
126 DE MIXTIONE
20 oihwc; 'TTJV E7tL 1tMov 8qe:-r1XL x.uenv, 'rot 8e XLpvcx.µ.e:vcx. n xixl. µ.Lyvuµ.e:vix
xixl. xix-r' ixu-rouc; aw~ov-rix 'TTJV otxdixv qiuaLV XLf)VOC'rlXL, we; XIXL x.wpLa67jvixL
8uvixa61XL 7tCX.ALV. Clan ou8ev IXU'rOLt; de; 1t1Xp1Xµ.u6(ixv -rwv e1toµ.evwv ch61twv
'rOLt; xe:vwc; Ae:yoµ.evoLc; ~ -rou-rwv auvnAe:L 1tixpcx.6e:aLc;.
IO 61-wv x.piiaLc; • OU µ.~v €TL O'W~OL't'O IXV 't'OC E~ ocpx_'Yjc; O'WfLIX't'IX 't'WV µ.eµ.Lyµ.e-
vwv, ocM' E!'Y) IXV O'U"(XEX,Uµ.evoc 't'E x.ocl. auvecp8ocpµ.evoc. d 8~ ~8EL 't'OC x.w-
pLcr81J0"6µ.evoc O'W~Ecr8ocL x.ocl. µ.~ O'U"(XEX,U0"8ocL ('t'OU't'Cp yocp ~ x.piimc; X.OC't' ocu-
't'OUc; tjc; O'U"(XUO'EWc; 8LoccpepEL), ocvocyx.oci:ov 8e 't'oi:c; 8L' 61-wv µ.eµ.Lyµ.evoLc;
O'U"(XEX,U0"8ocL, oc8uvoc't'OV 't'OC 8L' 61-wv µ.eµ.iyµ.evoc X.OC't' OCU't'OUc; x.wpL~E0'60CL
15 8uvoccr8ocL.
~'t'L 8e, EL OCVIX"(X'Y) µ.ev 't'OC x.ex.pocµ.evoc 8i' 61-wv µ.eµ.i:x.8ocL, 't'OC 8e
8L' 61-wv µ.eµ.Lyµ.evoc ocMvoc't'OV µ.~ O'U"(XEX,U0"8ocL, 't'OC 8e auyx.ex.uµ.evoc n x.ocl.
O'UVEcp8ocpµ.evoc oux o!6v 't'E IXU't'OC O'W~Ecr80CL, ou8' IXV ~~ELc; O'W~OLV't'O OCU't'WV,
et ye iv µ.ev 't'L 't'O yeyovoc; EX 't'WV auyx.ex.uµ.evwv 't'E x.ocl. O'UVEcp6ocpµ.evwv.
OCVIX"(X'Y) 8e 't'O iv awµ.oc U7t:O µ.Liic;, &c; cpocmv, ~~ewe; auvex.ea6ocL, &an x.ocl.
20 X.OC't'OC 't'OU't'O !XV ocx.wpLO"t'IX OCAA~AWV d1J 't'OC x.ex.pocµ.evoc X.OC't' OCU't'OUc;.
EL ae
X.IX't'OC µ.ev 't'OC Aey6µ.evoc un:' OCU't'WV ocx_wpLO''t'OC OCAA~AWV ocvocyx.oci:ov ELVOCL 't'OC
X.EX.pocµ.evoc (ou yocp 8~ o!6v 't'E ~V 8L' 61-euv XpOCO'LV yevecr8ocL x_eupl.c; O'Ufl,-
cp8ocpO'EWc;, ocx_wpLO''t'IX 8e Cj)OCO'LV ELVOCL 't'OC O'UVEcp8ocpµ.evoc), opwµ.ev 8e en:' EVLWV
):(l)pt.~6µ.e:vcx, 3~Aov 6.l~ oUx &v ~ xpicnc; yivoL~O xcxT<i T0v U1t' ocU'TWv e:L-
25 p'Y)µ.evov 't'p6n:ov.
9
r30 DE MIXTIONE
yovuLcc, e:t ye: µ.'Y)8&v CCUTWV µ.opLOV 1tccpoc TIJV 8Lcctpe:ow XCCTCCAeAEL7tT(XL. xcct
222 lTL d E:XCCO'TOV, de; & 8L-fip'YJTCCL E:XCCO'TOV, e:x TOUT(t)V O'UVTL8e:µ.ev(t)V 7tOCALV
ytve:TCCL, EL'YJ <XV TOC OUT(t)<; 8L7Jp'Y)µ.evcc EX 8LccLptae:(t)V, oux e:x µ.e:pwv ou8e: e:x
O'(t)fJ.OCT(t)V O'Uyxdµ.e:vcc. ~ yocp 8Lcctpe:aLc; OU O'WfJ.CC, OCAAOC 1toc8oc; O'WfJ.CCTOc;.
E:7t€TCCL 8e: TOL<; Akyoumv e:1t' IX7t€Lpov TIJV TOfJ.~V xcct TO [~] &.MvccTOV Aeye:Lv
5 7tOCV't'7J 3L7Jp~a8cc( TL awµ.cc e:ve:pyd~, ouT(t)c; 8e: xcct µ.(yvua8ccL 8L' OA(t)V Tei>
de; oc1mpcc e:ve:pyd~ 8L7Jp~a8ccL TOC O'WfJ.CCTCC.
' yccp "')./-.,
EL' µ.e:v /\<, l OUO'LV €7t
\ ,,
, , (X7t£L-
pov ELVCCL 8LCCLpETOC TOC O'WfJ.CCT(X Tei> µ.'Y)8e1t0Te: e:mAEL7t€LV TIJV TOfJ.~V, oc),),'
&.e:t e:x TWV TEfJ.VOfJ.£V(t)V 1te:pLAe:t1te:a8cc( TL Teµ.ve:a8ccL 3uvocµ.e:vov, oux o!ov n
e:O"TCCL awµ.oc TL 7t0CV't'7J 8L7Jp~a8ccL we; µ.'Y)xeTL U7tOAEL7tE0"8cc( TL e:~ CCUTOU TOfJ.~V
10 &.vcc8e~cc0'8ccL 8uvocµ.e:vov. d 8e: TOUTO, ou8e1ton <XV EL'YJ TOC XLpvocµ.e:vcc 8L'
QA.(t)V xe:xpccµ.evcc, e:t ye: x(pvCCTCCL µ.e:v OCAA~AoLc;, xcct 1tccpe:XTELV€T(XL 8LccLpouv-
TCC IXAA'YJACC <oc8uvccTOV 8e: OUT(t)c; IXAA'YJACC> 8L7Jp'Y)xevccL, we; µ.~ U1t0Ae:t1te:-
(j8(XL TLV(X CCUTWV µep'Y) µ.~ 8L7Jp'Y)µ.evcc. XCCTOC yocp TOC µ.~ 8L7Jp'Y)µevcc ou8e1t(t)
&v OCAA~AoLc; EL'YJ xe:xpccµevcc.
·twlX EpOUO"LV dvocL xixl. ix8L1XLpE:TIX crwµix-.ix), ELlj IXV IXUTOLc;; TO µeye:6oc;; oux
25 EX µe;ye:6wv cruyxelµevov, 8 E7tETIXL -.cj> xixl. --~c;; ypixµµ~c;; µep-ri Aeym Tot
O"l)µei:ix.
ix)..)..'
ou8e TO 1tup -.cj> O"L8~pep, xix6oc (j)IXO"L, µlyvuTIXL, W0"7tep ou8& 't'OLc;; xuµoi:c;;
223 ou8e -.oi:c;; ~OAoLc;;. OA<uc;; yotp OCT07tOV 'TT)V UAljV -.cj> e'£8eL µtyvucr61XL MyeLV.
UAlj 8e 1tupoc;; Tot XIXL6µe;voc TE xixl. 1te1tupwµ&v1X 7t!X.VTIX, IXM' ~ µev &rp6ixp-
Toc;, ~ 8' 0\). 8Lo xixl. µexpL 7t0MOU O"~evvoµevoc TLVIX 't'IXUTO d8o~ -.cj> E~
ixpx~c;; 80VIXTIXL (j)UAIXTTELV, OU µ~v &.µdw-.oc. 7tlXVT'{l • xixl. yotp TOOTWV U7t0
5 't'OU 7tUpoc;; IXVIXALO"XETIXL TL xixl. rp6dpe't'IXL. 8Lo xixl. TIXUTIX XPOVL~OVTIX EV IXU-
-.cj> 1tAeov ix.1t6MU't'1XL -.e xixl. -.ou otxelou e'r'.8ouc;; E~LO"'t'IXTIXL.
6ep[ou crwµix-.oc;; rpOO"Lc;;, ~--Le;; 1tepL&XOUO"IX 7t<XO"IXV 'TT)V tvuMv TE xixl. 1t1X6lj'TT)V
xocl. µe-.oc~Alj'TTJV oucrlocv -tjj cruvexei: -.e xocl. 8L-rivexei: xLv~creL xocl. !x.AAon IXA-
Aol~ crxecreL 1tpoc;; IXUTot 't'ot~ de;; !x.AAljAIX 't'WV EV yevecreL crwµoc-.wv µe-.ix-
222. 25 o ... -r<j> scripsi: cj'> ••• -ro codd. Br. v. infra
222. 29 -roc suppl. Schwartz
222. 34 ofov-rru coni. Br.: o£6v -re: codd.
223. 4 &.µdw-rix Ideler: &.µe:lw -roc codd.
223. 10 <X~TIJ Ideler: ixu-ni codd.
TEXT AND TRANSLATION 133
tainly will not say that there are some minimal and indivisible
bodies) then their magnitude would not be composed of magni-
tudes-also a consequence of the theory that points are parts of
the line.
222. 26 IX How can they maintain the common preconception about
blending and say that even the State itself is mixed with the things
that have it, and that their Nature is mixed with plants, light with
air, and the soul with the body, if, that is, it is preconceived that
bodies capable of existing individually before the blend are blended?
Certainly it is for this reason that they themselves say that bodies
that have been blended can be separated again, and that they can
thereby distinguish blending from fusion and destruction. But no
State is separable from what has it so as to be capable of indepen-
dent existence, nor could the nature of plants exist apart from
them. How could one conceive of light as separable from transparent
bodies? Neither could soul be like this, as they think, if enmattered
form cannot exist apart from matter and body.
222. 35 Nor is fire mixed with iron, as they say, as not even with fluids
[223] or wood. For it is in general absurd to say that matter is
mixed with form; everything that is burnt and heated by fire is
the matter of fire, but while the former kind [of matter] is in-
destructible, this kind is not. So things that have quite considerably
deteriorated can preserve the same form that they originally had,
though they are in every respect diminished; for they are somewhat
expended and destroyed by the fire. Thus only after remaining
in [the fire] for a long time are these bodies too finally destroyed
and expelled from their own form.
223. 6 X Surely it is absurd also to claim that the whole of substance
is unified by a pneuma which pervades it completely, and through
which the whole is held together, is stable and is sympathetic with
itself? For they do not know the fundamental explanation for the
unification of the whole (this is the nature of the divine body, in
circular motion and composed of aether, which holds together and
preserves the whole by surrounding the whole enmattered, af-
fectable and alterable substance with continuous and everlasting
motion, and by causing in a fixed order the interchange of bodies
that come to be by its different states towards them at different
1 34 DE MIXTIONE
~OACX<.; EV wpLo-µev-n -r&.~e:L 7tOLouµtVi'j o-uvex_e:L xixl. O"W~e:L 't'O 7t0C\I)' 't'IXU't'i'j\l
15 µ~ ...• t86v-re:e.; EIXU't'OL<.;, µ~-re: -roi:e.; t8ouO"L\I IXXOAOU8-rjo-lXL 8uvi'j8tv-re:e.;, 8Lcx 't'O
U7t0 7t0AAW\I 't'L\l(u\l 8o~wv 1tpoe:Lt.-rjcp81XL 8e:o-µoi:e.; 't'LO"L xixl. I.JALXIXL<.; ixMixL<.; XIXL
't'LVL 1tve:uµix-rL 8Lcx 7tCX.O"i'j<.; -rije.; OUO"LIX<.; 8L~XO\l't'L IX\IIX't'L8tOtO"L\I IXU't'OU 'TT)\/ ev<uO"L\I,
~'t'L<.; 86~1X, 7tp0<.; 't'C:) xe:x_p-rjo-81XL 't'C:) 41e:u8e:i: o-wµoc 't'L 8Lcx O"WµIX't'O<.; 8L~XELV,
xixl. 8Lcx 't'W\I OCAAWV, O't'L EO"'t'L 41e:u8~e.;, ~8i'j EASYXE't'IXL • cpixve:pwe.; ycxp E\ILIX 't'W\I
20 o-wµcx.-rwv oux. otoc -re: Eve:pyd~ 't'L ()\I EX.EL\/ 7tVe:uµix EV IXU't'OL<.; • 't'O youv
u8wp 't'OO"OU't'O\I 1X1to8e:i: 't'OU E)'._EL\I 8Lcx 7tlXV't'O<.; IXU't'OU µe:µLyµevov 1tve:uµ&. 't'L,
we.; µYj8' OC\I 't'O 't'U)'._0\1 EV IXU't'C:) ytVi'j't'IXL 7tO't'E, ~ IX7t07tVLytv-roe.; EV IXU't'C:)
~ci>ou -rLvoe.; -rwv IXVl):.7tVEUO"'t'Lxwv ~ xixl. 8L' OCAAYJV oct-r(ocv 't'LVCX ye:v6µ~ov,
µYj8' E7t' o}.(yov EV IXU't'C:) 8uvoco-81XL µeve:Lv, IXAACX 7t1Xpixx_p-rjµix µe:-rcx ~LIX<.;
25 IXVIX!ptpe:o-8oc( -re: xixl. exxp(ve:o-8ixL, xocv EV ~u80 ye:v6µe:vov 't'UX.TI· 't'OU't'OU 8'
OU't'W<.; E)'._0\l't'O<.;, 7tW<.; ocv E't'L IXAi'j8e:e.; e:(i'j 't'O 7t0C\I ~vwo-8oc( -re: xixl. o-uvex_e:o-81XL,
7tVe:uµoc-r6e.; 't'LVO<.; 8Lcx 7tlX\l't'O<.; 8L~XO\l't'O<.; IXU't'OU;
7t't'OtL -roi:e.; 7t1Xp<Xxe:LµtvOL<.;, ~LIX~6µe:vov µe:v ycxp u1t6 't'L\10(; 't'O 1tve:uµoc, 8Lcx
224 'TT)\/ 1tpoe.; 't'OU't'O e:ucputocv. -rij> µi'j8e:µ(ocv IX\l't'L~IXO"L\I E)'._EL\I -rij> XL\IOU\l't'L 8L' e:u-
1t&.8e:L1X\I 8uvoco-81XL, U7t0 -rije.; &.8p6oce.; XL\l~O"e:<ue.; LO")'._UV 't'L\/Ot A0tµ~&.ve:L, e:u1toc8e:e.;
8e: ()\I XIX't'CX 'TT)\/ OLXe:LIX\I ipUO"LV. uypov 8' EO"'t'L xocl. e:u8Loc(pe:-rov, we.; xocl.
't'W\I OCAAWV, EV ote.; &v TI 't'OU't'O µe:µLyµevov, XIX't'CX 't'OU't'O µ&.t.LO"'t'IX 't'& xocl.
5 &.p(O"'t'i'j\l y(ve:o-81XL 'TT)\/ 8Loc(pe:o-LV. 8Lcx 't'OU't'O youv ot µe:v xe:v6v 't'L IXU't'O <i>~-
A... T L I , > - < ~l. -,. -,. , ,! ,
v,,O"IX\I EL\IIXL XIX ipUO"L\I 't'L\IIX IXVIX!plj, OL oi:; 7t0/\/\IX i::x_e:LV e:v IXU't'<p xe:voc.
, _ 1
223. 14 times)-not being aware of this for themselves nor, because of their
many dogmatic preconceptions about it, capable of following those
who are aware of it, they instead attribute its unity to certain bonds
and material causes, and a pneuma which pervades the whole of
substance.
223. 18 In addition to relying on the false notion that body goes through
body this theory stands refuted for other reasons, since it is false.
223. 19 Clearly some bodies are incapable of having "pneuma"* actually
present in them. Water is so far from having some "pneuma"
completely mixed with it that no "pneuma" at all would ever arise
in it, either when some animal capable of respiration was choked
within it, or when it occurred for some other reason; nor could
any "pneuma" remain in it to even a slight degree without being
immediately removed and separated by force, even if it should
chance to occur in its depths. Since this is true, how could it still
be true that the whole is unified and held together through a
"pneuma" pervading the whole of it?
223. 27 Further, it would be reasonable that whatever sort of continuity
results from pneuma should exist in all bodies. But this is not the
223. 30 case; for some bodies are continuous, others discrete. It is more
reasonable, then, to describe each as unified with itself and held
together by its own form, insofar as each has being, while their
mutual sympathy is preserved because of their participation in
matter, and because of the nature of the surrounding divine body,
rather than through the bond of pneuma.
223. 34 For what is the tension of pneuma through which things are
bound together and have continuity with their related parts, and
are connected with juxtaposed bodies? Pneuma is forced by some-
thing [224] because of its good disposition towards it to assume
some power through its motion in a mass, in that it has not capacity
to resist its mover because of its malleability, being malleable in its
own nature. 1t:is moist and easily-divided, so that with other things
with which it has been mixed division is therefore especially viable.
Hence some have thought that it was something void and of an
intangible nature, while others that there were many empty spaces
in it.
* I.e. pneuma in its literal sense of "breath"; see Comm. on 223. 19-27.
DE MIXTIONE
Xctt'
yocp et 't'OU µ~ 8tct7tL7t't'EtV, IXAAOC cruµµevetv 't'OC (jWµct-rct, ctfrrnv 't'O cruvexov
ctU't'OC 1tveuµct, 't'OC 8tct7tL7t't'OV't'ct 't'WV (jCiJ!,LOC't'CiJV 8~AOV wi; oux OCV gxot 't'O
1tveuµct 't'O cruv8eov. 1twi; 8' ocv ~v ocpx~v ~ 8tctLpemc; (jW~Ot't'O 't'WV (jCiJ!,LOC't'CiJV,
10 et ye ~ µe:v 8tcttpe(jtc; xwpt(jµ6c; EG't't 't'W'J ~vwµevwv, µevet 8e: Xct't'' ctU't'OUc;
't'OC ~vwµevct [oµo£wc; IXAA~Aotc;] 7t0CV't'ct, xocv 8tcttpe6yj; 1twi; 8' oux !XV 7t0CV't'ct
(j)ctLVOt't'O 't'OC 7tctpctxdµevct IXAA~Aoti; xctl p~8(wi; IXAA~ACiJV xwpl~e(j6ctt 8uvoc-
µevct <cruvexeG8ctt> tm' ~U't'OU xctl oµo(wi; IXAA~Aoti; ~vwG8ctt [1.eyetv]
-roi:i; cruvexfot 't'e oifot xctl xwpli; 8tcttpfoewi; µ~ 8uvctµevoti; 't'tvoi; IXAA~ACiJV
14a xwpt~VctL 1ton;
ou-r' ocv EXELVCiJV 't't e(Yj 7tp0 tji; 't'OU 7tVe:Uµct-roi; yevfoe:wc;, ou-r' OCV 't'O
7tVeuµct y(vot't'O, oux ISv"t'CiJV, E~ G>V ~ yeve(jti; ctu-rcj>. 1twi; 8' &v -rte; EV
-rcj> tliuxpci> Evepye(~ 't't 6epµov e!vctt 1.eyot; -rli; 8e: xctl ~ etc; 't'O EVctV"t'LOV
&µct XLVYj(jti; ctu-rou, xct6' ~v cruvex,_et -.ix EV oti; ocv fl, ov C>i; qict(jt, 1tVeuµct
25 Xtvouµevov
' o,;µct
~ e.,
'!:' ctU't'OU
• - -re XctL\ eti;
' ctU't'O;
• ' Xctt' Xct"t'ct' 't't' e!~ooi; XtVYj(jeCili;
'
ylve-rctt ; Xct't'' ou8e:v yocp O!6v -.· EG't'L VO~(jctL 't't &µct eti; 't'OC EVctV't'Lct
27a xtvouµe:vov xct6' ctu-r6.
224. 11 oµolw; ixn~Aot; seclusi -rcx ~vwµevcx 1tixv-rcx scripsi: -rwv ~vwµtvwv 6µ.
ixn. 1tixv-rcx codd.: mxv-rwv ~vwµtvwv, 6µ. IXAA., rrixv-rcx, ><.'t'.A. Br. v.
infra
224. 13 auvtxe:a6cxt supplevi, v. infra [Mye:tv] coni. Ideler
224. 15 -rij> suppl. Ideler
224. 24 IXU't'OU A pelt: cxu-roi:;; OU codd. auvexe:t ldeler: aUVt)(E:LV codd.
224. 25 Ktvouµe:vov Apelt: Ktvouµtvou codd. IX\J't'OU ... cxu-r6 scripsi: IXU't'OU ... cxu-r6
codd. v. infra
TEXT AND TRANSLATION 1 37
224. 6 Now if the pneuma that binds them together explains why
bodies do not fall apart but remain together, clearly those bodies
which do fall apart will not have pneuma as their binding agency.
And how would the division of bodies be at all preserved if division
is a separation of bodies that are unified, yet according to them all
of the bodies that are unified are stable even if they have been
divided? And would not all the bodies that are juxtaposed with one
another and easily separable from one another appear < to be held
together > by it and unified with one another in the same way as
continuous bodies that are incapable of ever being separated from
one another without some division?
224. 14a Another point: if pneuma is a product of fire and air and pervades
all bodies by being mixed with all of them, and by each being
dependent on it for its existence, how could it still be an uncom-
pounded body? How, if the product of uncompounded bodies
is secondary, could it be Fire and Air from the mixture of which
evolves the pneuma without which it is impossible for any body
to exist? For if pneuma comes to be from these bodies, but none
of them can exist without it, no part of them would exist before
pneuma comes to be, nor would pneuma come to be without
the existence of the bodies from which it takes its coming-to-be.
224. 22 And how could anyone say that there is something actually hot
in what is cold?
224. 23 Also, what is its [pneuma's] motion in opposite directions at
the same time, by which it holds together the bodies in which it is
present, being, as they say, pneuma simultaneously moved into
and out of itself? Now by what kind of motion does this occur,
when it is impossible to conceive of any by which something is in
itself in motion in opposite directions at the same time?
224. 27 XI Now, as I said, with this doctrine they seem, by their
inability to distinguish in theory between form and matter-in that
everything that exists has its identity in its form and differs with
respect to other things which in themselves are indistinguishable
in matter, insofar as it has form, and in that these things are pre-
138 DE MIXTIONE
31 a8otL 't'E xotl. µ.eve:Lv 't'(XU't'ot, & Ea't'L, 1tve:uµ.ot't'L we; 8toc 7tOCV't'(l)V 8t~XOV't'L <X.VOC-
7t't'ELV 't'6 't'E e:!votL EXOCG't'OU xotl. 't'O aw~e:a8otL 't'E xotl. auµ.µ.eve:LV.
otL' 't'Lot<rotL
' 't'O
8' a.v 't'Lc; e:uMywc; (XU't'WV EV't'otU8ot 't'OU Myou ye:v6µ.e:voc; xotl. 't'O Mo &.p:x,occ;
't'WV 7t0CV't'WV Myov't'otc; e:tvotL UA'YjV 't'E xotl. 8e:6v, WV 't'OV µ.ev 7t0LOUV't'ot e:!votL
225 TY)V 8e 1toca:x,ouaotv, µ.e:µ.i::x,8ott -tjj UATI A&ym 't'OV 8e:6v, 8toc 7tOC<rljc; otu-rijc;
8t~xov't'ot xocl. a:x,l)µ.ot't'L~OV't'ot ocuniv, xocl. µ.opqiouv't'ot xocl. xoaµ.01totouv't'ot 't'ou-
't'Cp 't'<j> 't'p61tep. e:t yocp 8e:oc; Xot't'' otU't'OUc; awµ.ot, 1tve:uµ.ot WV voe:p6v 't'E xotl.
&.t8tov, xotl. ~ UA'Yj 8e awµ.ot, 1tpW't'OV µ.ev fo't'otL 7tOCALV 8t~XOV awµ.ot 8toc
5 awµ.ot't'oc;, &7tEL't'ot 't'O 1tve:uµ.ot 't'OU't'O ~'t'OL 't'L 't'WV 't'Eaaocpwv 't'WV OC7tAWV fo't'otL
'
awµ.ot't'WV, ot~ XotL' <r't'OL:X,ELot
- ' <potaLV, '..Yj EX
' 't'OU't'WV
, ,
auyxptµ.ot ("·
we; 7t0U )((Xl. (XU- '
't'O l. -.L
/\l>YOUGLV. XotL' yotp ' ot1>poc;
•L XOtL' 1tupoc;' U<pL<r'
• ' t'otV't'otL ~
• ,,v ouatotV
' ' 1>:X,ELV
II. 't'Ul
7t\le:uµ.ot), ~. <e:£> 11.AAo 't'L Ell), fo't'otL 't'O 8e:i:ov (Xl)'t'Oi:c; awµ.ot 1teµ.1t't"Yj 't'Lc; ou-
a(ot :x,wpl.c; <X.1to8e:(~e:wc; 't'LVOc; xotl. 7totpotµ.u8lotc; AEyoµ.&V'Yj 't'oi:c; 1tpoc; 't'OV µ.e:'t'OC
IO 't'WV otxdwv 't't8eµ.e:vov 't'OU't'O <X.V't'LA&youaLV we; }..eyov't'ot 7totpcx.8o~ot. e:t 8e ~
't'WV 't'Eaaocpwv 't'L Ell) ~ 't'L t~ exdvwv auyxptµ.ot, fo't'otL 't'O ex -rijc; UA'Yjc;
yevvwµ.e:vov awµ.ot 1tpo 't'OU yevfo8ott 7tE<pOL't"YjXOc; 8t' otu-rijc; xotl. 't'EXVOUV
t~ txELV'Yjc; oµ.o(wc; 't'oi:c; 11.AAoLc; xotl. EotU't'6. &'t'L 't'E U<r't'Epov av o 8eoc; -rijc;
UA'Yjc; Ell), e:l ye 7t<XV µ.ev 't'O &VUAOV awµ.ot -rijc; UA'Yjc; Ua't'e:pov. 't'O yocp tX
15 -rijc; &.p:x,~c; Ua't'Epov, 0 8e 8eoc; 't'OLOU't'OV awµ.ot· OU yocp 8"1j 't'TI UATI O (Xl)-
't'6c;. 't'OLOU't'Oc; 8e WV e:l'Yj &v µ.qpt qiwv~c; &.t8toc; OtU't'OLc; µ.6v'Yjc; • EL yocp
yeyove (yeyove 8e ex -rijc; UA'Yjc;), ehe 't'L 't'6)V IX7tAWV Ea't'L awµ.oc't'WV, eln ex
't'OU't'WV auyxptµ.ot.
't'OLc; cpucreL "(LVOµ.&VOLc; y(vecr6ocL 't'IX XOC't'IX -rcx:c; -rf:xvocc;. 't'IX µev ycx:p CX7t0 -rijc;
cpucrewc; CX7tO't'eAeG(.LOC't'OC oux E7tL7tOA~c;, ex.Mex: 8L' OA(J)V eE801tOLeL't'OC( 't'S: xocl
8LOC7tAIX't"t'S:'t'OCL, xoc1 't'IX ev8ov OCU't'WV y1,,occpupw't'OC't'IX 7tS:<'f'LAO't'&)(V"fJ't'OCL, 't'IX 8& 't'WV
't'S:)(VWV 8Locµeµ6pcpw-rocL, we; E7tL 't'WV cxv8pL1XV't'(J)V E)(S:L • 't'IX ycx:p ev8ov 't'OU't'WV
25 cx8LCX7tAOCG't'OC. 8Lcx: 8~ 't'OU't'O E<'f'"IJGOCV 't'WV µev ywoµevwv XOC't'IX 't'&)(V"IJV e~-
w6ev dvocL xoc1 xexwpLcrµevov 't'O 7t0LOUV, E7tL 8& 't'WV "(LVO(.L&VWV cpucreL EV
't'TI UA7) dvocL ~v Mvocµw ~v µopcpoucrcxv 't'S: XOCL yevvwcrocv OCU't'IX.
't'OCU't'OC
8& OU)( opwµev 't'OL<; "(LVO(.L&VOLc; cruv48ov-roc. E7tL ycx:p 7t!XV't'(J)V 't'WV "(LVO(.L&VWV
cpucreL e~w6ev 't'L Ecr't'L 't'O ~v cxpx~v 't'~c; yevfoewc; OCU't'WV E)(OV xoc1 -rijc;
30 1tpw't'"fJc; EV T7i UA7) µe't'oc~oA~c; ocfoov. 't'CX 't'e ycx:p oc1tAoc crwµoc't'oc -rijc; 't'e
etc; IXM"IJAOC µe't'oc~oA~c; e~w6ev E)(S:L ~v ocMocv. 41u~Lc; ycx:p xoc1 6epµ6't'"fJc;
"fJ< "(LVOt'.,-"'J,.V"IJ OLOC
'I> '
't'"IJV
'
'C'W-
V oupocv~wv
> I
GW(.LOC'
'
t'WV ~1\/\0't'S:
.!!~ ~
OC/\/\OLOCV
'~ ~ '
1tpoc;
l
OCU'' t'O'C
crzerm -rijc; yevfoewc; OCU't'OLc; xoc1 -rijc; cp6opiic; x.oc1 -rijc; de; IXM"IJAOC (.LS:'t'OC~O-
A~c; ochLoc. CXMIX X.IXL 'C'WV (f)U't'WV XIXL 'C'WV ~cflwv lx.occr't'OV u1t6 't'Lvoc; e~w6ev
226 OV't'oc; xexwpurµevou -rijc; UA"f)c;, E~ ~c; lx.occr't'OV IXU'C'WV "(LVS:'C'IXL, ~v cxpx~v 'C'S:
-rijc; yevfoewc; AOC(.L~IXVS:L XIXL 't'IX XIX't'IX y~c; 7t"1Jyvuµevoc 7t!XV't'IX x.oc1 't'IX EV
't'OLc; (.LS:'t'ewpoLc; cruvLG't'OCµ.&VIX [xezwpLcrµevoc] XS:)(c.>pLcrµevov E)(EL 't'O 7t0LOUV.
OU'" t'S: yocp\ 't'Ol 6epµocwoµevov ' X.OCL\ oLIX
~ \ 't'OU't'O
- (.LS:'t'IXl-' IXI\/\OV OCU'
(J. ·~ ~ ,
Cl'o 6epµocLVS:L.
'
5 41uzpov 8& xoc6o 6epµoc(ve't'OCL. ex.Mex: XIXL o!c; ~ "(&VV"fJGLc; CX7t0 G7t&pµoc-roc;,
e~w6ev 't'O yevvwv 8Lcx: -rijc; 1tpofoewc; 'C'OU G7t&pµoc't'oc;. et 8' ou-rwc; 't'IX EX -rijc;
UA"f)c; yLvoµevoc y(ve't'OCL, 1t&c; (XV E't'L o 6eoc; ocfooc; e!"f) 8Lcx: 't'OU T7i UA7)
µeµ°Lz6oc( 'C'S: x.oc1 xexpiicr6ocL; 't'ou ycx:p ou-rwc; Ev 't'o°Lc; yLvoµ.evmc; cpu<reL 1tm-
ouv't'oc; IXMO 't'L 7tpW't'OV Ecr't'LV ochLOV e~w6ev ov. oMev 8& 7t0L"IJ't'LXOV 1tp&-
IO 't'OV 't'OU 6eou.
15 1twi; div ~-n ~ UAl) ocve:(8e:oi; dl) XCl'C'IX 'C'OV cxunji; Myov, e:( ye: 'C'O m.,µµe-
VELV cxu-tjj xcxl. dvcxL UATI 7tcxpix nji; OUCTY)t; EV cxu-tjj 8uvixµe:eui;;
(J.IXALO''C'Cl 8'
EV -tjj EX7tUpWO'EL cpcxlve:'t'CXL X.Cl'C' OCU'C'OUt; o8e:oi; nji; UAl)t; d8oi; ll:,v, e:( ye: EV
't'c'j> 1tup(, o µ6vov EO''C'L X.Cl'C' ClU'C'OUt; 'C'O'C'E, ~ UAl) x.ocl. o 8e:oi; [nji; UAl)t;]
O'W~OV'C'ClL µ6vot. &(l) yixp div o 8e:oi; 'C'O'C'E d8oi; 'C'O E7tl. -tjj UATI 'C'OU 1tup6i;.
20 d 8e 'C'OU'C'O, (J.E't'OC~IXAAEL 8e 'C'O 1tup di; OCAAOC 'C'LVIX O'W(J.OC'C'Cl, 'C'O d8oi; IXAAIXO"-
O'OV &(l) div o 8e:oi; cp8e:tp6µe:voi; 'C'O'C'E, e:( ye: X.Cl'C'IX cp8opixv 'C'OU 1tpou1tixp-
):OV't'Ot; e:(8oui; ~ µe:'t'oc~o)..~ e:ti; fx.)..)..o awµcx -tjj u)..TI ylve:'t'cxt. x.ocl. EL nji;
I (.I.-,- 0'
'C'OLClU't'l)t; µe:'C'Cll-'01\l)t; a
e:ui;
l
ClL'
>I
C'Loi;, ELl)
"
CXV
..
O
• 8e:ui;
l
X.Cl'C' > ClU'> C'OUt; (p 8e:tpeuv
I I
But if this is so, how could matter still be formless in its own essence,
if its being and stability is derived from the power present in it?
226. 16 Particularly in the conflagration does God appear, according to
them, to be the form of matter, if matter and God are the only
things preserved in the fire which at that time is, on their view,
the only thing existing; for God would then be the form belonging
to the matter of fire. If this is so, and if Fire changes into some
other bodies, God would be the alternating form through being
destroyed at that time, if, that is, change into another body occurs
for matter by the destruction of the preexistent form. If God is the
cause of such change he would, according to them, be self-destruc-
tive-and what view could be more absurd than this?
226. 24 Surely it demeans our preconception of the deity to say that
God pervades the whole of the matter underlying everything and
remains in it, whatever it may be like, and has as his premeditated
task the perpetual generation and moulding of anything that can
come to be from it; and for them to make God a craftsman of grubs
and gnats, simply devoting himself like a modeler to clay, and
making everything that can be created from it?
226. 30 Again, if the bodies that are being blended with one another
must be reciprocally acted on by one another (this is why neither
is destroyed, since the one acted on by the other reacts in the
process of being acted on) and if the bodies that go through one
one another are blended together, then God too would be blended
with matter, and thereby also acted on by it-from which it follows
that God is acted on while matter acts.
226. 34 XII I was provoked into this argument by denials of Aristotle's
theory of the fifth body, and ambitious attempts to resist the only
theories worthy [227] of divine things, made by opponents unaware
of even the source of the stupidity of their statements, when their
central and major philosophical beliefs depend on and take their
support from the remarkable belief that body goes through body.
For their theory of blending does not rely on something else, but
their views on the soul depend on it, and their notorious Fate and
r44 DE MIXTIONE
't'O\J't'OU 8e 't'OU awµ.cx. x.wpei:v 8Lcx. awµ.cx.-ror:,, E~ OU ax.e8ov 7t<XG'Yj(, -njr:, cpu-
GLOAoytocr:, <X.U't'OL(, ocv~p't"YJ't'OCL 't'CX. m:taµ.oc-roc, 7t<X.poc 't'E 't'CX.(, XOLVCX.(, 1tpOA~~ELr:,
AEyoµ.evou X<X.L 7t<X.pcx. -rcx.r:, OC7t<XV't'WV 86~ocr:, 't'WV (j)LAoa6cpwv, 'TT)V 7tLG't'LV xoc-r'
<X.U't'OU(, A<X.fl-~OCVEL wr:, OCV OC7t0 Evocpyour:, 't'OU 't'OV al81jpov, O't'<X.V 11 7tE7tupw-
µ.evor:, [µ.ev] µ.~ <X.U't'OV E~IX7t't'Ea6oc( -re: X<X.L 1tupoua6cx.L t.eyELV oµ.otwr:, -roi:r:,
15 o!r:, UA'YJ -rcj> 1tupL, ocMcx. 8Lcx. 1tocv-ror:, ocu-rou x.wpei:v -ro 1ttip u1toAocµ.~ocvELV µ.e-rcx.
-njr:, UA'Yjr:, EXELV'Yj(,, Ecp' ~r:, ov YEL't'VLCXG<X.V -rcj> aL8~pep E6epµ.cx.Lve 't'E X<X.L E~'Yj-
~EV <X.U't'6V.
por:, ocu-r6r:,. xcx.66aov ycx.p ~ uyp6'"Jr:, Ea't'LV EV ocu-rcj>, X<X.'t'CX. 't'OGOU't'OV UA'YJ -rcj>
228 1tupt YLVE't'<X.L, ax.A1Jp6-repor:, youv O1tupouµ.evor:, aL81jpor:, !J,E't'CX. 'TT)V a~&GLV 't'OU
IO
DE MIXTIONE
2 1tpw-rou ytve:-rocL, we; OCVIXALcrxoµev'l)c; U7t0 't'OU 1tupoc; -rijc; uypO't"l)'t'O<; -rijc; EV
ocu-rcj>, xoct E~IX7t't'E:'t'IXL 't'L µex_pLc; ocv uypo't"l)c; TI 't'L<; EV ocu-rcj>, i:>ITTte:p ouv xoct
~UAIX. OCAAIX 't'OU't'WV µev &ALc;.
5 XIII 'E1tocvlwµe:v 8e E1tl -rov E~ ocpx_~c; Myov. et yixp -rix e:lp'l)µevoc o/5-rwc;
1te:pt xpocae:wc; 7tlXV't'e:Awc; &-ro1t1X, ocvocyxoci:ov &AAwc; moc; -rixc; xpocae:Lc; y(ve:a0ocL
Mye:Lv. Ae:L7t€'t'IXL 8e 7t1Xp1X 't'IXU't'IX<;, WV &~LOV 7tOLe:La01XL Myov 't'LVIX, <~> u1t'
'ApL(J't'o-reAouc; dp'l)µeV'l] 86~oc. e:(1rwµe:v 8~ xoct 1te:pt -rocu't"l)c;, xocl. 8e:l~wµe:v
-r(c; 1to-r' Ea't'LV, E1te:l. µ'l]8e yvwpLµoc; Ea't'L 't'OL<; 7t0AAOL<; 't'WV <pLAOaO<pOUV't'(J)V
rn 8LIX auv-roµ(ocv 't'WV 1te:pl. ocu-rijc; E:Lp'l)µevwv U7t0 't'OU <pLAoao<pou.
1tpw-rov µev
oplawµe:v, 't'LVIX fo-rl.v OCAA~AOL<; XLpvifo6ocL Ae:yoµe:voc -re: xocl. 8uvocµe:voc. opL-
a0ev yixp ~(LLV 't'OU't'O cx:1tocrxe:uocae:-rocL 7tOAAIX 't'WV EVO)'._AOUV't'WV 't'OV 1te:pl.
xpocae:wc; Myov. fo-rL 8~ ~ µ"L~(c; -re: xoct ~ xpiiaLc; Ev -ro°Lc; xoc6' ocu-rix u<pe:-
a-rocvocL <pUaLV ex_ouaL. 8Lo xocl. 8oxe:L 8uvixa0ocL x.wp(~e:a0ocL 7t1XALV cx:AA~AWV
15 't'IX µe:µLyµevix ()'t'L EX 't'OU't'WV auv~A6e:v. e:t 8e µ'l)8ev &AAo x.wpLa-rov 7t1Xp1X
~v oua(ixv, OUaLWV OCV ~ (LL~Lc; -re: XIXL ~ xpiimc; e;('l). e:t 8e 't'OU't'O, oux
OCV 'Avix~ocyopocc; e:('l) XIXAwc; Aeywv, 7t0CV't'IX EV 1tiiaLV µe:µ°Lx_6ocL. OU't'E: yixp
't'IX 7tOC6'l) x.wpLa-roc, we;
xoc6' OCU't'IX e:LVOCL 8uvoca0ocL (8Lo ou8e (LL~Lc; -re: xocl.
xpocaLc; OCV e;('l) 1toc6wv 1tpoc; &AA'l)AIX, ~ 1toc6wv 1tpoc; 't'IX WV Ea't'L 1toc6'l)),
20 OCAA' ou8e 't'IX e:(8'l) 't'WV oumwv. XIXL yixp e:t OU(JLOCL xoct 't'IXU't'', ex:)..)..' OU xoc6'
IXU't'IX auvu<pL(J't'IXV't'OCL. OU yixp o!ov -re: x.wptc; \JA'l)c; e:!voct 't'L OCU't'WV. ex:)..)..'
ou8e ~ \JA'l) (LLX~. ou8e yixp OC\J't"l) x.wptc; e:(8ouc; Eve:pye:l~ 7t0't'' Ea't'LV. ou-r'
ouv EV &AAoLc; 't'L(JLV, ~ EV QU(JLOCL<; ~ (LL~Lc; 't'E: XOCL xpocaLc;, OU't'E: &AAocL 't'Lvec;
't'WV OUaLWV e:tat (LLX't'OCL 1tocpix -rixc; x.wpLa-rocc; -re: XOCL xix-r' t8(ocv u<pe:a't'OCVOCL
25 8uvocµevixc; xocl. XIX't'E:)'._OU(j0tc; 't'07tOV. 't'OLOCU't'IX 8e 't'IX awµoc-roc.
't'OU't'OU 't'OLVUV
8LwpLaµevou µe:-rix 't'IXU't'IX &~LOV Ema-rijaocL, 7t0't'E:pov 't'OCU't'OV Ea't'L (LL~Lc; -re: xocl.
xpocaLc;, ~ 8Loc<popixv ex_e:L 't'LVIX. &OLXE: 8~ 8Loc<pepe:LV, fl 't'O µev XOLVO't'E:pov
Ea't'LV ~ (LL~Lc;, ~ 8e xpocmc; [8Lxw-re:pov. 7tOLIX yocp (LL~Lc; ~ xpocaLc;. 't'WV
yocp µ(~e:wv ~ µev 't'L<; XIX't'IX 1tocpoc6e:aLV 't'WV QU(JLWV xocl. OC<p~V y(ve:-rocL, ~v
30 Myoµev [-rij½ µ(~ew½] y(veo-8ocL Xot't'a cruv8EO'LV (OU 1tao-oc µev yap cruv8em½
µ'i:~L½ • cruv8eo-L½ µev yap xocl 't'WV oµolwv 't'E xocl oµoeu~wv YLVE't'OCL, ~ 8e
µ'i:~L½ ix 8Loccpepov't'WV 't'E xocl ev 8LoccpepouO'L • 8Lo o µev 't'WV 1tupwv o-wpo½
Xot't'a µoV'YjV cruv8EO'LV, 0 8e 't'WV 7tUpwv 't'E Xotl xuocµ<uv ~8'1j -tjj O'UV8£aeL
xocl 't"YJV µ'i:~LV 1tpoo-elA'YjcpEv), ~ 8e w½ xpam½ µ'i:~L½ y(ve't'OCL, OU O"<u~oµevwv
35 €'t'L 't'WV µLyvuµevwv xocl OU't'W½ IX./\/\~AOL½ 7totpocxeLµevwv, IX.I\/\' evouµevwv
Xot't'a 't'O imoxe(µevov. 8Lo ev 't'OL½ euop(O''t'OL½ 't'E xocl uypo'i:½ ~ w½
xpam½
µ'i:~(½ EO"'t'LV. c1i0"7tep 8e OU)'., ~ 't'WV 't'U)'._OV't'WV cruv8EO"L½ µ'i:~L½ ~v. OU't'W½ ou8e
229 ~ 't'WV 't'U)'.,OV't'WV uypwv &v<um½ xpao-(½ 't'E xocl µ'i:~L½- OU yap u8wp u8ot't'L
XLpva't'ocL, xoc('t'OL evouµevov OCU't'cj'>, ou8e €/\OCLOV EAotlep, IX.I\/\' ou8e €/\OCLOV Mot't'L •
(X./\/\a 't'OU't'O µev 8La YALO")'..PO't"YJ't'OC.
evocv't'lwo-Lv ex.eL 't'wa 1tpo½ &/\/\'YjAOC. ou yap 't'o 't'ux.ov u1to 't'ou 't'Ux.ov't'o½
o!ov 't'E 7tlXO")'._ELV • ou8e yap 't'O ISµoLOV U7t0 't'OU oµolou. IX.1tot8~ yap u1t'
IX./\/\~/\WV 't'a 6µoLOC. ev 8LoccpepoUO"L yap xocl. U7t0 8Loccpepov't'WV 't'O 7t0LELV 't'E
xocl. 7t1XO")'.,ELV YLVE't'OCL. IX.I\/\' ou8e 't'a E't'Epot 7t1XV't'TJ 7t1XO")'._ELV 't'L u1t' IX./\/\~AWV.
15 ou8e yap 1toc8e'i:v o!ov 't'E cpwv~v U7t0 ypocµµ~½, 't'cj> µ'Yj8ev u1t' IX./\/\~/\WV
IX.V't'L7t1XO")'._ELV, <et µ~ 8La 't'O> XOL~V u1toxe:'i:0"8oc( 't'LVOC cpumv 't'WV EXOC't'&pwv
1toc8wv em8e:X't'LX~V. 8Lo EO''t'LV ev 't'OU't'OL½ 't'O 7t0LELV 't'E xocl. 7tlXO")'._ELV,
60-oc 't"YJV OCU't"YJV UA'YJV u1toxe:Lµ&V'YJV ex.ov't'oc evocv't'Lwo-(v 't'LVOC &):EL 1tpo½
~'YjAOC. OU't'E yap U7t0 x.pwµot't'O½ 't'O y).uxu, xoc8o y).uxu, 1tix80L 7t0't'' &v,
20 Ot>'t'E U7t0 8e:pµou 't'O ~'Yjpov, IX.I\/\' ou8e U7t0 41ux.pou 't'O uypov xoc8o uyp6v, 6't'L
µ.~ &G't'L -rcxu-rcx &.JJ,:fiAoLc; ivcxv-r(cx, a.AA' fo-rL -ro 1t0Le:Lv -re: xcxl.
2Ia mx.ax,e:LV 't'OLc; ivcxV't'LOLc; -re: xcxl. 't'OLc; µ.e:-rcx~u. OU y<ip µ.6vov 't'O 6e:pµ.ov
U7t0 't'OU 41uxpou xcxl. 't'O 41uxpov U7t0 't'OU 6e:pµ.ou µ.e:-rlX~OCAAE:'t'CXL -re: xcxl.
7t0CCJXE:L, oMe: 't'O uypov U7t0 't'OU ~l)pOu xcxl. 't'O ~l)pOv U7t0 't'OU uypou, a.AA<X
xcxl. 't'IX µ.e:-rcx~u excx-repou 't'WV ocxpeuv, ()'t'L XIX't'(X µ.L~LV EO''t'L -rcjl 1tpoc; EXOC-
25 -re:pov 't'WV ivcxv-r(euv [-ro] µ.e:-rcx~u 't'OV 6cx-repou 't'WV ivcxv-r(euv O'W~E:LV Myov.
't'OLc; y<ip 1tpoe:Lpl)µ.ev0Lc; o-uµ.~e~l)XE: ~v (XU~V l)Al)V &):OUO'LV xcxl. ivcxv't'LCuO'LV
XIX't'IX 't'O e:!8oc; &):E:LV 1tpoc; &AAl)AIX. -njc; y<ip l)Aljc; (8LOv 't'O ~v (XU~V e:!-
VCXL -rwv ivcxv-rleuv im8e:x-rLx~v. 1tocv-rcx y<ip -roc iv ye:vfoe:t -re: xcxl. cp6op~
o-wµ.cx-rcx inl. -njc; cxu-njc; a.AA~AoLc; &O''t'LV l)Aljc;, ~ ae: 8Lcxcpopa; IXU't'OLc; XIX't'OC -re:
30 e:!8") xcxl. o-uµ.~e:~l)XO't'IX 1tix.6lj.
-re: XIXL 6e:pµ.6v (iv 'C'OU't'OLc; y<ip 7t0CALV 't'O e:!vcxL -rcjl &.epL), 't'O 8e: 41uxpov -re:
xcxl. uypov (-rcjl y<ip iS8cx-rL iv 't'OU't'OLc; 't'O e:!vcxL), 't'O ae: ~l)pOv -re: xcxl. 41uxpov
5 (-roLOU't'OV y<ip ~ y~). &c; &):OV't'(X 8Lcxcpopocc; -re: xcxl. ivcxV't'LWO'e:Lc; 1tpoc; OCAAljACX,
1t0Louv-roc -re: xcxl. nocax,ov-rcx e:tc; OCAAl)AIX 1t0Le:L -r<ic; µ.e:-r0t~0Mc;, -njc; iSAl)c; µ.e:-
-rcx~cxAAOUO'l)c; e:tc; 't'O 't'WV 7tOLOUV't'CuV xpcx-rouv. ()'t'IXV yocp 't'L (XU't'WV 7tAE:OVOC-
O'(XV 't'Lvoc; 't'WV ivcxv-r(CuO'LV E):OV't'CuV 1tpoc; (XU't'O XCX't'LCJXUTI 't'CXLc; ivcxV't'LWO'E:O'L
't'CXLc; iv cxu-rcjl inl. 't'OO'OU't'OV, we; (J.7t0~0CAAOUO'IXV ~v U7tOXe:Lµ.evl)V l)Al)V, ~v
IO 1tp6-re:pov e:!xe: 7t0LO't'l)'t'IX µ.e:-rcxAcx~e:LV 't'O 't'OU XpiX~O'IXV't'Oc; e:!8oc;, 't'O't'e: y(ve:'t'CXL
't'OU µ.e:v 0\)'t'(u µ.e:-rcx~OCAAOV't'Oc; cp6opoc, yeve:o-Lc; 8e: <'t'OU> e:tc; 0 yevove:v ~ µ.e:-rix-
t-'01\lj. (XL' µ.i;;v
(J, ">' .I.
ouvT
ye:v1>0"e:Lc;
L e \ -
XCXL\ cp opcxL 't'CuV o-euµ.ix-reuv I
(XL' YLV () µ.e:VIXL X(X't'(X\
µ.e:-rix~oA~v ~v xcx-r<i -ro 1t0Le:Lv -re: x0tl. nocax,e:Lv -rou-rov y(vov-r0tL -rov -rp61tov.
XIV 'Em:l. 8e &).J..o yeve:<rn; x.otl. <p8opix, x.otl. l}.))..o x.piiO'L~ (~ "(IXP x.piiO'L~ O'Cu~oµe-
15 vwv TLVWV <p8op1X e:!votL 8ox.e:i: • oun "(IXP U7t0 TOU hepou <p8otpev-.o~ x.otl. µe:-
Tot~IXA.AOVTO~ e:£~ TO x.pot't"YjO'otV x.piiO'L~, CX.A.AIX <x.otl.> TOU µev otU~l)O'L~, TOU 8e
<p8opix - 8LO ou8e ~ TpO<p~ A&ye:TotL KLpviia8otL KotL Tcj> Tpe:<pOIJ.&VCf> - OUT', e:£
cx.µ<p6-.e:pot 7totVTIX7totO'LV <p8otpe:Llj TIX µLyvuµe:vot, TWV µe:µLyµevwv x.piiO'L~ ~--L •
O'W~O!J.&VWV yixp TLVWV <p8op1X ~ x.piiO'L~), cx.x.6Aou8ov <iv e:llj ~V -rij~ Kp!XO'EW~
20 1tpo~ ~v yeve:O"LV n x.otl. <p8opocv e:!1te:i:v 7totpot~OA~V.
e:£~ 8ix-.e:pov µe:8(a-.ota8otL x.otl. µe:TotAotµ~ocve:tv TIX~ EVotVTLWO'e:L~, x.ot8' &~ 1tot-
25 8ov CX.7t&~ot/l.e: T&Ae:ov, &~ e:!x.e: 1tpo TOUTOU, E7tL 8e TWV KLpvotµevwv OU TOU-
TOV ~--L y(ve:TotL TOV -.p61tov. ex.A.A' lhotv 7tAELW awµotTot TOU 7tOLe:i:v x.otl. 7tlX-
O-XELV u1t' CX.AA~/1.WV ~x.ov-.a. 8uvotµLv CX.AA~AOL~ GUV&A.8TI, ~X.TI 8e OUTW~, w~
µ~ U7te:pex_e:Lv KotTIX TIX~ EVotVTLWO'EL~ &).J..o /1Uou 8uvoto-8otL w~ <p8e:"i:potv otU-
TO e:t~ ~v EotUTOU µe:TotO'-rijO'otL (j)UO'LV, -.6-.e: Trt.UTot 8LIX ~v TWV 8uvotµevwv
30 L0'6Tl)Tot, x.ot8' &~ 7tOLe:i: x.otl. 7t1XO"X,EL, oµo(w~ u1t' CX.AA~AWV CX.VTL7tlXO"XOVTot
L 6 ,, > (.l. , , I , , r
µi:;x_pL TOUTOU 7tp ELO'LV, e:w~ ot7tOt-'ot/\OVTot KotTot Tot~ e:votVTLWO'EL~ Tot~ U1te:po-
f I ,
X,1X~, 8L' &~ l-.e:poc -.e: ~v CX./1.A~AWV x.otl. EVotVTLot, IJ,LotV E~ IX7totO'WV TWV 8uvixµe:wv
ye:vv~O'e:L 7tOL6Tl)Tot, Evw8e:L<rlj~ x.otl. IJ,Lii~ ye:voµ&Vlj~ -rii~ cx.µ<po-.epOL~ ~ 7t0CO'LV
ot\JTO"i:~ UAlj~ U7tOKEL!J.&Vlj~-
xpii(nc; OU YLVE:'t'(XL xwpL<:; uyponi't'oc:;. EVOU't'(XL yix.p 't'IX. uypoc GUV't'L8eµe:voc )((Xt
231 ou <pu"Aocmm 't'IX.<:; otxe:locc:; Em<pocve:lixc:;, Mv µ~ TI y"ALa-x_p6v. ll't'ocv 8~ 't'o'i:c:;
)((X't'OC ~v UAYJV 8Loc ~v uyponi't'(X XIX't'IX. ~v 1tocpoc8e:ow evouµevoLc:; 0'6>(.L(X(JLV
1tpooij )((XL 't'O EV(XV't'LWO'LV exe:LV taoxpoc-rij 1tpoc:; &A"AYJAOC, YLVE:'t'(XL (XU't'OL<:; )((X't'IX
't'IX.<:; 7tOL6'"l't'OC<:; 't'E: )((XL 8uvocµe:tc:; EVWO'L<:;, 61te:p EO''t'LV ~ xpiiaLc:;. EXOC't'e:pov yix.p
5 't'WV OU't'W<:; EXOV't'WV 8Loc µev ~v EVU7tocpxouaocv EV (XU't'OL<:; EVOCV't'LWO'LV )((XL
~v -rijc:; UAlj<:; XOLVWVL(XV (.LE:'t'(X~OCAAE:L 't'e: )((XL 1toca-x_e:L, 8tix. 8& ~v taoni't'(X 't'WV
E:V(XV't'LC.UO'E:WV
' ' OUK
' E:7tL
' ' 't'OO'OU't'OV
- 7t0LE:L- niv
' (.LE:'t'OCt,-0/\ljV,
A , ' we:;
' 't'(XU't'UV
' l ye:vi;;avlXL
L-D.
8oc't'ep<f> 8oc't'e:pov. CX.V't'LTtOCa-x_ov yix.p 't'O 7tOLOUV U7t0 't'OU TtOCa-x_OV't'O<:; 1tpoc:; (XU-
't'OU )((XL µ~ µevov 0(.LOLOV (XU't'<j'>, 7t(XUE:'t'(XL 't'OU 7t0LE:LV &'t'L 8uvoca8ocL 1tpo 't'OU
ro xpoc-rijaocL 1'i"Ae:ov ocu't'ou.
TYJV OLXe:LIXV OCVIX't'ptxEL q,uaw, OU 't'OU 1tp6't'Epov ClV't'O<; 158ix't'oc; ~ otvou [ 't'OU]
25 EXXpLvoµevou 7tlXALV (ou8e yotp TYJV ocpx~v fow~E't'O EV 't'cj> µ(yµix't'L, 7t1Xpoc-
6E(nc; yotp &v, OU xpii(nc; ~v • EV yotp 't'OL<; XExpixµevoLc; ~v n xixt oµoLoµE-
pec; 1tiiv 't'O YEYOVO<; EX -rijc; xpoccrEwc;), oc"'>J..ot 8uvixµevou [ OC7t0] 't'OU 't'OLOU't'OU
xplX(l,IX't'O<;
' EL<;
' uowp
~~
<"fl"" owov>
T [ µEv
I ]
pqtoLwc;
' ~·
µE't'IXi--lXI\/\ELV
A ,-,. .,. <XIXL>
I
µE't'IX-
(.1. 1-,.-,. > l > 61 > > I I
1-'IXI\/\OV't'O<; EL<; 't'o 't'"IJV IXPX"IJV µl) µLX t;V EX 't'OLOU't'WV Em 't'OLIXU't'"fl<; 7t0LO't'"IJ't'O<;.
I I I I I
XExpixµevwv.
not because the original water and wine is separated out again
(they were not, that is, preserved in their original state in the
mixture, since that would just be juxtaposition and not blending;
for where bodies have been blended the whole product of the blend
is one and uniform) but through such a blend being easily able to
change into water < or wine>, < and> changing into what was
not originally mixed from such [constituents] with such a quality.
231. 30 For just as a heated stone cast into milk, a uniform body con-
taining in potentiality something both moist and solid, separates
each of them from it, and in some way creates them, making the
one into cheese, the other into whey, not through separating a
part actually inherent in the milk but by creating each of them
[232] from every part, so must the action of the sponge dipped into
the pitcher holding wine blended with water be understood; for
by its own quality it creates from the whole mixture the water
that can be easily purified by it, and reconstitutes it as separate
through the extent and nature of its power.
232. 6 For as the onset of a slight fermentation in must, which
is a uniform body, creates and separates from the whole of it both
air and wine (clearly these bodies were not in it in actuality before-
hand, since it is impossible that air should actually be contained
by water, as we said just above, but the product is separated out
as a whole just when the fermentation takes place); so must it
be understood that agents which separate constituents from which
blends have been formed also do not separate what is actually
inherent in [blends] but cause an alteration by a specific force,
and actualise bodies that as a result of blending are present in
them in potentiality.
232. 13 Just as in the preceding cases there is a superficial coming-to-be
of something (for it is not through the milk changing into qualities
opposite to its own that it becomes one part whey one part cheese,
but rather the bodies present in potentiality in it in such a way
that they require slight assistance to reach actual being, come into
actual being), so must the change that also occurs in the case of
bodies that have been blended be understood.
DE MIXTIONE
&1te:'t'0tL 8e: -tjj E7tL 't'WV xe:xpetµevwv 't'OLOtU't"() µe:-r0t~o"A7i [~] 't'O
8L0txp(ve:a80tL 8uv0ta80tL 8oxe:i:v OtU't'OC, O't'L xetl. niv &p:x,~v EX µ(~e:wc; -roLou-rwv
20 ~ yeve:(nc; -ri;> 't'OtU't'Ot 7tOC!1X,OV't'L awµet't'L. xetl. Ea't'LV O :x,wpLaµoc; "Ae:y6µe:voc;
't'WV xe:xpetµevwv ou-re: oµowc; -ri;> E7tL 't'WV &.tJ..~"Amc; 1t0tp0txe:Lµ&vwv, oih'
OtO -ri;> 7t0CALV 't'WV XOt't'OC q:i6opocv xetl. yeve:mv xetl. TYJV de; 't'OUVOtV't'LOV µe:-ret~O-
A~V <X.7tOXpLVoµevwv, we; E~ u80t-roc; opwµe:v de; 1X&p0t yLvoµev-riv 1X1t6xpLaLV,
&tJ..' Ea't'L 't'O yLv6µevov µe:-ret~U 't'OU't'WV. oihe: yocp Eve:pye:(~ EVU1tocp:x,ov-r0t
25 8L0tXptve:'t'0tL OUT€ de; 't'OUVOtV't'LOV -ri;> U7tOXe:Lµ&v<p µe:-r0t~octJ..ov-r0t IX7t0Xptve:'t'OtL.
E7tL µe:v yocp 't'OU't'WV 't'OtU't'OV XOt't'OC 't'O d8oc; µeve:L µe:-roc TYJV 1X1t6xpLaLv 't'O
U7tOµ&VOV -ri;> 1tpo 't'OU, µ6vov XOt't'IX 1toaov EAOt't"t'OUµe:vov, E7tL 8e: 't'WV xe:xpet-
µevwv ou:x. oµo(wc;, -ri;> gXOta't'OV 't'WV ()V't'WV 8uvocµe:L EV -ri;> EX 't'OU xpocµet-
'
-roe; ye:yov6't'L awµet-rL ' ' 6OtL, µe:-retr'<M\/\OV
e:xxpLVOt(j A.l-.-. e:Lc;
' TYJV
' 't'e:I\ELOTYJ't'Ot,
-. ' .J''jc;
.. 0tq:>7l-
'
30 pe6Yj 8Loc 't'OU E7t' '£a-ric; OtU't'OC IXV't'L1t0t6e:i:v u1t' IXAA~AWV, 8L' 8 1toc6oc; xetl.
E7tl. -rou-rwv -ro :x,wp(~e:a80tL X0t't'Y)yope:i:-r0tL.
XLpvetµevwv e:xix-re:pov E7tL -rijc; olxdetc; ouatetc;, ~ u1t' &.tJ..~"Awv yLvoµ&vl) 8Loc-
xpLaLc; OtU't'WV xetl. IX7t0 -rijc; 't'WV :x,pwµoc-rwv 8L0tq:>opiic; y(ve:'t'OtL yvwpLµoc; •
uypoc yocp ()V't'Ot xetl. e:u8L0tlpe:-r0t xetl. &v6µoLOt U7t0 Tljc; 7tAl)y"Yjc; -rijc; XOt't'OC TYJV
E1tt:x,umv 60t-r&p<p 6ix-re:pov &.p:x,~v "A0t~6v-r0t -rou 8L0tLpe:i:v &"A"Al)"A0t, /Sv-ret xetl. IXVL-
10 a6ppo1t0t, e:1 ou-rwc; 't'U:X,OL, 't'O µe:v ~0tpu-re:pov OtU't'WV 8L0tLpouv q:iepe:'t'OtL XIX't'W,
't'OU 8e: xouq:io-repou 't'OC µ6pL0t U7t0:X,WPOUV't'Ot -roi:c; ~0tpu-rep0Lc; Em1to"A"Yjc; OtU-
't'WV a7te:u8e:L ye:vea80tL. ~v -romx~v µe:-roc~MLV OtU't'WV fo't'YjaL q:i6ixvoua0tv ~
XOt't'OC 1t1X6'1) µe:-ret~OA~, e:vouaOt OtU't'OC -tjj XOt't'OC 7t0CV't'Ot oµoL6TYJ't'L, 8 xetl. OtU't'O
't'TI /Sljie:L y(ve:'t'OtL yvwpLµov.
232. 18 fi secl. Apelt Br., om. F, Montanari p. 36
233. 3 't'IX suppl. Br. 8uxipouv-ra Schwartz: 8tatpti-ra! codd.
233. 4 tu1tcx6£G't'tpcx F, Montanari p. 37, Apelt Br.: ix1ta6fonpa codd., cf. 224. 2
233. 8 yixp F, Montanari p. 37, coni. Br.
TEXT AND TRANSLATION 1 59
24a 1tOL~O'O!LIXL 8e 'TOV Myov E1tL 'TWV xup(wc; IXU~ea61XL Aeyoµevwv' E1tL
25 'TOU'T(J)V YIXP xixl. ~ oc1top(ix 1tp6eLO'LV. fo-rL 8e 'TIXU'TIX 'TIX 8LIX 'TOU -rpecpea81XL
~V 1tpoa6~X'YjV AIXµ~ocVOV'TIX. -rpecpe'TIXL 8e <lO'IX ~V 6pe1t'TLX~V f:')(eL MvotµLV
EV IXU'TOL<;, 'TOLIXU'TIX 8e 'TIX (j)U'TIX xixl. 'TIX ~cj>IX. OO'IX 8~ 'TOL<; oihwc; IXU~IXVO-
• , , !:', -,. /....,
L.
µi:;voLc; U1t1Xp')(eL XIXL' UO'IX
l!
oeL
~ ~ -,. ,
(flU/\IX'T'TeLV '
-rouc; 1tepL' IXU<,ljO'ewc; /\v r OV'TIX<;,
ocvocyxlj 'TIXU'TIX 1tpw-rov Ex6fo61XL • 'TIXU'TIX YIXP ~µLv l>V'TIX yvwpLµIX O'UV'Te-
30 A&O"eL 1tpoc; ~v 'TWV plj6'YjO"Oµevwv XpLO'LV.
233. 15
YJ codd. Von Arnim: et Br.
233. 16
oti1~7Jatc; secl. Br. <y!vETott &>au El> Von Arnim
233. rrpoUrrcxpx_ov-rt A 2Ra: urrcxpx_ov-rt A1BPSC Br. v. infra
17
233. 18
µ-IJ Br.: µ!otv codd.
233. 23
cpEp' Efaw Schramm: cptpE xot! wv codd.: xot! wv obelo not. Br. qui
cpEp' EfowµEV coni.
233. 28 udp)(.Et Br.: urrcxp)(.Etv codd. 8Ei Ideler: 8-IJ codd.
233. 32 ou suppl. Br.; fortasse <ou> XIXTIX µ6ptov <Tt> <xot6'> coni. Br., cf.
XIXT!l lTciV 234. 26
234. 2 -rotu-rov Apelt: -rp!-rov codd.
TEXT AND TRANSLATION 161
233. 14 XVI As they support the notion of body going through body
by also invoking the growth of animals through nutriment (for
growth does< occur> by the addition of nutriment in every part,
< so that if> things that grow do grow in all parts, nutriment
would be assimilated by the preexisting body in all its parts; but
it is impossible for the implanted [nutriment] to be totally assim-
ilated except throughout the whole body and in every part; yet
if the nutriment pervades the whole body as a body, it will be
held necessary that body go through body if only in this way can
growth through nutriment occur throughout the whole of the body
that is nourished), yet because nourishment and growth do not
occur in this way (for nothing impossible happens), let me then
state and explain Aristotle's doctrine of growth and nutriment.
233. 24a I shall devote the discussion to those things that are strictly
speaking said to grow, for with them we shall certainly make
progress with our problem. Now these are bodies that grow through
being nourished, and only bodies with their own nutritive faculty
are nourished, namely plants and animals. First, then, we must
describe the character of things that grow in this way, and what
must be retained by a theory of growth; for since these [facts] are
known to us they will contribute to our assessment of the theory
to be forwarded.
233. 30 Everything that grows grows only when something enters it
from outside, if indeed it grows through being nourished, and
furthermore is < not> added to in part. For growth is not in an
individual [feature] for bodies that grow by nature, as it is with
things to which something is affixed externally [234] (when some-
thing grows its foot will not grow by itself!), but there is in fact
proportional addition to all parts. Now the body that grows remains
the same and preserves its own nature when added to; for if what
is said to grow is not stable the result will not be growth < even
II
162 DE MIXTIONE
5 yLv6µ.evov <et X(XL> de; /lyxov µ.e-r(X~IXAJ.&L µ.el~ov(X (8Lix -rou-ro yixp ou-re -rwv
xLpv(XµkV(J)V 't'L (XU~ecr8(XL A&"(&'t'(XL <ou-re -rwv > µ.e-roc~octJ..6v-r(J)v de; /1,J..o 't'L
awµ.(X ov E7t' /lyxou µ.el~ovoc;, we; opwµ.ev yLv6µ.evov E7tL -rijc; E~ u8oc-roc; de;
ixepot µ.e-rot~OAljc;, w' EV't'(XU6ot µ.ev yeveaLc; xoct cp6opoc, u8oc-roc; µ.ev cp6opoc,
yeveaLc; 8e cx.epoc;, EXEL 8e µ.°L~lc; 't'€ xoct xpiiaLc;), OU't'€ 't'O -rux_ov 't'WV etc; TYJV
IO (XU~l)GLV GUV't'&AOUV't'(J)V (XU~€'t'otL, cx.tJ..ix 't'O G(J)~6µ.ev6v 't'€ ot\.l't'WV X(Xt u1toµ.evov,
X(Xt l-rL TY)V otU~'l)'t'LX~v n X(Xt 6pe1t't'LXl)V lx_ov Mvocµ.Lv EV (XU't'cj>. 8Lix 't'(XU't'(X
yixp oux_ ~ -rpoq:>l) (XU~(Xv6µ.evov, xoc(-roL X(Xt (XUTYj awµ.(X X(Xt yLvoµ.ev"l -rijc;
(XU~~ae(J)c; (XL't'L(X, cx.tJ..' 4> ~ -rpOq:>l) 1tpoaxpLV€'t'(XL, ~ µ.ev yixp (l,€'t'(X~OCAML,
't'O 8e aW~€'t'(XL • X(Xt ~ 6pe7t't'LXl) 8uv(Xµ.Lc;, ~ (l,€'t'(X~A'l)'t'LXl) 81) X(Xt 1tpoaxpL-
15 't'LXl) -rijc; -rpocpljc;, fo-rtv EV 't'OU't'Cf>.
8e 't'O (XU~6µ.evov (XU~€'t'(XL, c'J>a-re X(X't'IX 1tiiv X(Xt 1tpocr8~X'l)V A~tjl&'t'(XL, cx.tJ..'
et awµ.(X ov X(X't'IX 1tiiv e:(Xu-ro TYJV 1tpo~X'IJV t..(Xµ.~ocveL, 8e~aeL 8Lix 1t(Xv-roc;
(XU't'O x.(J)pouv 't'O 1tpoa-rL6eµ.evov (XU't'cj> (-rou-ro 8' fo-rtv ~ -rpocp~) TY)V (XU~'l)-
aLV (XU't'OU 7t0L&Lcr8(XL. et yixp Aey€L 't'Lc; 8Loc 't'LV(J)V xevwv yevecr8(XL TY)V 8(0-
234. 5 <e:l x0tb coni. Br. qui lacunam posuit µe-r0t~&lle:L coni. Br.:
µe:TIX~!XAAE:LV codd.
234. 6 <oil-re Twv> coni. Apelt Rodier
234. 7 hL"l coni. Br.: ix codd.
234. IO u1toµevov Br., cf. 236. 1, 5: u1toxe:lµevov codd.
234. 14 31) Br.: 3e codd.
234. TouTrov suppl. Br.
15
234. rrpoaTL6e:µevci> Br.: rrpoaTL6e:µevou codd.
16 TO suppl. Diels
234. <ou> coni. Apelt
19
234. )..eyouaL xe:vov TL ltOLELV ixcpropLaµevov (-rov Montanari) e:l ye: TO µcv
20
1XU~7l6£v µe:l~ov0t XIXTEJ(EL T61tov F, Montanari p. 39, cf. Aristot. de gen.
et corr. 32m 6: )..eyouaL XIXTEJ(&Lv T6rrov codd., obelo not. Br.: )..eyouaL
<To 0tu~'ija0tv 0tuTo µl) )..eye:Lv> XIXTEJ(e:Lv T61tov · [ ou] coni. Br.
234. 24 3e A pelt: Te codd. iv supplevi, cf. 219. 23, 24, 27: yw6µe:vov awµIXTL
codd., obelo not. Br.: 3e:x6µevov awµ& TL coni. Br.: rrpoayLv6µevov
awµIXTL Schramm
TEXT AND TRANSLATION
30 8ov -rijc; -rpoqiijc;, cxvocyxl) -rou-rep Myetv, 1tocv -ro -rpeqi6µevov awµot elvotL xe-
v6v, et xot6' 8 µev ~ 1tocpo8oc; -rijc; -rpoqiljc;, xevov Xllt't'OC 't'OU't'O, Xllt't'OC 7tOCV't'llt
8' IXU't'OU ~ 1tocpo8oc; -rijc; -rpoqi~c;. et 8~ Xllt't'OC 7t0CV't'llt lltt>~e't'otL.
-rcj> 8~ µe1.-
1.ov-rL (j)UAOC't"t'eLV -re 't'OC -roi:c; IXU~otvoµevoLc; U7tocpx_ov't'ot xotl. MaeLV 't'OC CX.7t0-
pouµevot IXVIX'(KIXLOV 1tpw-rov, -.( 7tO't't Ea't'L 't'O IXU~oµevov Aot~ei:v, xotl. Xllt't'OC
235 7t0Lllt µ6ptot 't'WV IXU~oµevwv -rijc; 1tpoa6~Xl)c; '(LVO(.LtVl)c; 't'OC 61.ot lltt>~e't'otL. e1tel.
-ro(vuv ev -roi:c; IXU~O(.LtvOLc; Ea't'L 't'WV µepwv 't'OC µev ocvoµotoµeplj, 't'OC 8e
oµotoµep~ {xotl. cxvoµotoµep~ µev -roc ex 8totqiep6v-rwv µepwv auvea-rw-rot, we;
1tp6aw1tov xotl. x_elp, oµotoµeplj 8e aocp~ -re: xotl. oa-roc, µuc; xotl. ot!µot xotl.
5 (j)Atlji, xotl. 61.wc; WV 't'OC µ6pLot -roi:c; 6AoLc; fo-.l. auvwvuµot), xotl. <ruyxeL't'IXL ex
't'WV oµotoµe:pwv 't'OC IXVO(.LOLO(.Le:p~. ocAA' OUK CXVOC7tlltALV (ou yocp ex
1tpoaw-
7tOU ~ aocp~. ocAA' ex aotpxwv -re xotl. 0<1't'WV 't'O 1tp6ac.mov), ~ lltt>~l)<1Lc; Xllt't'OC
~v -roi:c; oµotoµeptaL 1tpoa6~Xl)V y(ve-rotL. 't'OU't'OLc; yocp IXU~oµevoLc; fae-rotL
xotl. ~ 't'WV IXVO(.LOLO(.Lepwv e1t(8oaLc;. OU yocp ~ 1tpoaxpLVO(.LtVl) -rpoqi~. 1tp6-
IO (1(J)7t0V ~ x_el.p '(LVO(.LtVl), 1tpoaxp(ve-rotL, ocAA' etc; aocpxot xotl. 0<1't'OUV xotl. 't'WV
&AAwv oµotoµepwv ~Xllta't'OV µe-rot~OCAAOU<10C Te xotl. 1tpoaxpLVO(.LtVl) 't'OU-
't'OLc; -rijc; 't'OU 7tlltV't'Oc; IXU~~ae:wc; awµot-roc; ott-.lot y(ve-rotL. et -ro(vuv ~ µev
lltt>~l)<1Lc; 't'OU IXU~otvoµevou a<u~oµevou -re xotl. µevov-roc;, llt\J~E:'t'IXL 8e 't'OC O(.LOL-
oµe:plj, 8~AOV 6-rL 't'IXU't'llt aw~e:a6ot( -re: xotl. µeveLV 8ei:.
ocx61.ou6ov -rolvuv
15 't'OU't'OLc; t8ei:v, 1twc; 't'Lc; Mywv u1toµevew 't'IXU't'Cl IXAl)6euaeL. xot6o yocp U7tO-
µeveLV ot6v -re 't'IXU't'ot, Xllt't'OC -rou-r' IXU't'WV XIXL ~v llt\J~l)<1LV IXVIX'(KIXLOV e!votL
Mye:w. 7tOCV 8~ 't'O e~ 1)Al)c; -re: xotl. e:!8ouc; auyxelµevov xot6' exoc-repov 't'WV
e~ WV Ea't'LV e:lvotL Atye-rotL • xotl. yocp Xllt't'OC ~v 1)AljV xotl. Xllt't'OC 't'O e!8oc;.
ex 't'OU't'(J}V 8e xotl. 't'OC oµotoµeplj, xot6' & Atyoµe:v ~v 't'WV ~ci>wv lltt>~l)aLV
20 y(vea6otL. 8to xotl. 't'IXU't'' ~x_eL 't'O 8tn6v. xotl. Atye:-rotL ~Xllt<1't'OV IXU't'WV 7t0't'£
µev Xllt't'OC ~v 1)Al)V, 7t0't'£ 8e Xllt't'OC 't'O e:t8oc;. 6-rotv µev yocp Atywµev ~v
aocpxot pe:i:v xotl. e:lvotL ev auvex_e:i: IX7tOXp(aeL -re xotl. 1tpoaxp(aeL, Xllt't'OC ~v
1)Al)V ~v aocpxot 't'IXU't'llt 7tOC(1)'_eLV Atyoµe:v, 6-rotv 8' ot?i 7t<X.ALV Atywµev ~v
aocpxot ~v IXU~V µeveLV, IXU't'O 't'O e!8oc; xotl. ~v Xllt't'OC 't'O e!8oc; aocpxot
25 Aot~6v-rec; 't'IXU't'llt otu'tjj µotp-rupouµev. 7t0CV't'llt yocp 't'OC ev 1)ATI 't'O elvotL ~x.ov-
't'llt Xllt't'OC µev ~v 1)AljV fJ.AAO't'e &Al.ct y(ve't'otL, 8toc 't'O µ~ µeveLV 't'IXU't'l)V
Xllt't'llt' 't'UV
l otpL
• 6µuv
l (.LLIXV,
I auvex_wc;
- Xllt't'llt' 't'llt' µ 6pLot µe-rott'tl.JV\OU<11XV
(.I.L"\ "\ 1
-re XIXL'
respond that the whole body that is nourished is void, if the passage
of the nutriment occurs only where it is void and if this passage
is over all [parts], given that it grows in all [parts].
234. 32 If we would retain the character of bodies that grow and also
solve these difficulties, we must first consider the nature of the body
that grows, [235] and in what parts of growing bodies whole units
235. 1 grow when an addition is made. Since some of the parts of bodies
that grow are non-uniform, like face and hand, while flesh and
bones are uniform, and marrow, blood, and vein, and in general
things whose parts bear the same name as the whole), and the
non-uniform parts are composed from the uniform, while the con-
verse is not true (for flesh is not composed of the face, but the face
of flesh and bones) then growth occurs by an addition to the uniform
parts. For when these grow, an addition to the non-uniform parts
also follows, since the nutriment that is assimilated is not assimi-
lated by becoming face or hand but by changing into flesh and
bone and each of the uniform parts, and through being assimilated
by them causes the growth of the whole body. If, then, growth is a
characteristic of a body that is preserved and stable as it grows,
and if it is the uniform parts that grow, clearly they must be
preserved and stable.
235. 14 We must next see how it could be true to describe them as stable
when it must be granted that they can only grow insofar as they
can be stable. Now the whole compound of form and matter is said
to be with respect to each of the things of which it is composed-
matter and form, that is. These are also the components of the
uniform parts by which we say that growth occurs in animals, 'SO
that also have this dual aspect. Now each uniform part is described
variously by its matter and by its form. When we describe flesh as
fluid and in a state of continual dispersal and assimilation, we say
that the flesh is affected in this way with respect to its matter.
Again when we describe flesh as remaining the same, we base this
attribution on the form itself and the flesh qua form. Indeed every-
166 DE MIXTIONE
YLVOµevrJV &llo-re: &llYJV, XOt't'ot 8e: 't'O e:Woc; EV 0tu-r<i> X0t-r' cxpL8µ.ov Ex0ta't'OV
µ.eve:L. XOt't'ot yotp 't'O e:'!:8oc; ii aotp~ ii OtUTYj X0t-r' cxpL8µ.ov µ.eve:L. xocv 't'O µ.e:v
30 cx1toppqj njc; U7tO~e:~AYj(J,tvYjc; UAYjc; OtU't], 't'O 8e: Emppqi, fo-r' &v 't'L !W'TI
0tunjc; EV 0tu-r<i>, <pUAcx.aae:L 't'O njc; aetpxoc; e:'!:8oc;, -tjj XOt't'ot 8ux8oaw µ.ovn
xwAuov 0tu-rou niv 1t0tv-re:Aij ip8opixv. ou yotp -ro dvetL -tjj aetpxt Ev -r<i> -r6-
a<i>8e: µ.e:yt8e:L, o OU 't'OtU't'O µ.eve:L 8Lot TY)V njc; UAYjc; puaw, cxll' EV -r<i> d8e:L
-r<i> -roL<i>8e:, o-retu-rov µ.tve:L, fo-r' ocv aw~YJ't'OtL 't'L njc; a0tpx6c;.
ou-rwc; 't'OLVUV
236 't'OU't'WV Ex_6v-rwv, xe:Lµ.evou 8e: XOtL 't'OU 't'O 0tU~0tv6µ.e:vov 8e:rv U7tO!WJE:LV, OCV
µ.i:;v
J..
XOt't'O' t 't'Y' jV UI\YjV
d~
't'Lc; ~J...-f ...D, \ - ' >!I:' >
I\C. f fj YLVE:cruOtL 't'YJV 't'Yjc; aetpxoc; OtU<,YJGLV, OtVOtLpYJaE:L
f
't'O 't'O OtU~6µ.e:vov 't'O OtU't'O aw~6µ.e:vov X0t-r' cxpL8µ.ov OtU~e:a80tL (OtUTYj yotp
&llo-re: &AAYJ), e:t 8t -rLc; XOt't'ot -ro e:1:8oc; AtyoL niv OtU~YJaLv y(ve:a80tL, ouxt't'L
5 OCV O Myoc; E(J,1t08L~OL't'O. 't'OU't'O yotp U1toµ.eve:L, 't'OU 8e: tmoµ.evov-roc; ~v.
xe:Lµ.evou 8e: 't'OU 't'ot OtU~0tv6µ.e:v0t XOt't'ot 't'O e:1:8oc; OtU~e:a80tL, E7tL 't'OU't'OLc; !~LOV
t8e:i:v, 1tc7>c; njc; -rou 0tu~ov-roc; 0tu-r0t 1tpoaxp(ae:wc; 0tu-rorc; ywoµ.tvYjc; 0tu~e:'t'0tL.
e:t µ.e:v oov XOt't'ot TYJV UAYJV ii OtU~YJaLc; -re: XOtL ii 1tp6axpLaLc; Ey(ve:-ro, cxvety-
XOtLOV ocv ~v Atye:w -r<i> XOt't'ot 1tciv µ.6pLov 0tu~e:a80tL -rot 0tu~0tv6µ.e:v0t AtyOV't'L,
10 XOt't'ot 1tcia0tv niv UAYJV ye:vta80tL niv 1tpoa6-JixYJV niv cx1to njc; -rpoipijc;, ~-rLc;
oux &llwc; E8uV0t't'O ytve:a80tL (njc; ye: UAYjc; njc; 0tunjc; U7tO(J,E:VOUaYJc;),
<~> awµ.0t-roc; x_wpouv't'oc; 8Lot GW(J,Ot't'oc;, e:! ye: ac7>µ.0t ii -rpoip~ • E7te:l 8e: XOt't'ot
-ro e:1:8oc; ii OtU~YJaLc;, ouxt't'L cxv0tyx0tiov, e:t xett x0t-r0t 1tciv -ro e:1:8oc; 0tu~e:-
-r0tL, 't'OU't'O y(ve:a80tL GW(J,Ot't'Oc; x_wpouv-roc; 8Lot GW(J,Ot't'Oc;. oMe: yotp TY)V
15 cxpx_~v 1tpo01tixpx_ov U1toµ.eve:L, i:>a-re: y(ve:a80tL -r<i> OtU~OV't'L awµ.0t-rL 8L' OtU't'OU
TY)V o86v, cxllot y(ve:'t'OtL µ.e:v "1j -rpoip~ njc; aetpxoc; UAYJ, 1tpoaxpLVO!WJYJ 8e:
XOt't'ot !UPYJ 't'LV0t -tjj njc; 1tpoU1t0tpx_ou(JYjc; l-rL, µ.e:vOU(JYjc; -re: XOtL 't'O e:1:8oc; ipe:-
pou(JY)c;, e:t µ.e:v e:!Yj EAIX't"t'WV ~ ((J'tj njc; cx1toppe:0U(JY)c;, aw~e:L [OU] µ.6vov -r6,
235. 30 ia-r' &v -rt µtv7l coni. Br., cf. 235. 34, Alex. Quaest. 13. 32, Aristot. de
gen. et cOYr. 322a 24: fo-rt µevov codd., obelo not. Br.
235. 32 au-roii Apelt: au-ro codd.
235. 32-33 EV -ri;i -roo-i;i3e: F, Montanari p. 37, Apelt Br. Rodier: cv-ro~ -r6o-<i> 3e
codd.
235. 33 8 ou Apelt: ou codd.
235. 34 8 Apelt Rodier: ou codd.
236. 9 -ri;i Apelt: -ro codd.
236. 12 71 suppl. Ideler
236. 13 e:l xal Ideler: dvat codd.
236. 17 -re: Rex: 3e codd. Br.
236. 18 ac!i~e:t ldeler: ac!i~EtV codd. ou om. F, Montanari p. 37, Rex, cf.
µ6vov ac!i~e:t, 236. 25
TEXT AND TRANSLATION
thing that has its being in matter undergoes various changes in its
matter because it does not remain one in number, but continually
changes its parts and assumes varying states, while in form every-
thing is stable in number; for as regards the form flesh remains the
same in number, and if one part of its supporting matter disperses
while another accedes then, as long as some matter remains in it,
it preserves the form of the flesh and prevents its total destruction
by the stability of its distribution. For the being of flesh does not
lie in the extent of its magnitude which does not remain the same
on account of the fluidity of the matter, but in the sort of form it
has, which remains the same as long as any flesh is preserved.
235. 34 If this is so, [236] and if it is established that the body that grows
must be stable, then to say that the growth of flesh occurred with
respect to the matter would abolish the principle that what grows
will grow while remaining the same in number (for matter is dif-
ferent at different times); but our theory would no longer be hin-
dered by the claim that growth occurred with respect to the form, for
form is stable and [growth], as we saw, indeed involves that which
is stable.
236. 6 Since it has been established that things that grow grow in their form
it is worth seeing how in this case they grow through assimilating
the body that causes their growth. Now if growth and assimilation
occurred with respect to matter one would have to say to the view
that things that grow grow in every part, that addition from nutri-
ment occurs in the whole of matter, and at least while the matter
remains stable, it could only occur by body going through body, if
nutriment is body. But since growth occurs with respect to form it
cannot occur by body going through body, even if body grows with
respect to the whole form.
236. 14 For matter is not at all stable in a preexistent state so that the
body causing growth passes through it, but nutriment becomes mat-
ter for flesh and by being mixed in specific parts with the [matter]
of the still preexistent flesh which is both stable and contains the
form, then (r): when the nutriment is less than or equal to the
deteriorating flesh it preserves only the thing by which it is assimi-
168 DE MIXTIONE
cj> 1tpocrxp(ve-r0tL, -rpecpoucror. or.u-ro xor.l. xwMoucroc 1tiiv 8Loc<popl)8°YjvocL -re xocl.
20 cp8ocp'YjvocL 8Loc TI)V cruvi::x.'Yj pucrLV, 6-rocv 8e 7t}.e(wv ~ U7t0 njc; 8p&7t't'LX°Yjc; 8u-
vocµ.i::wc; XOt't'&pyoc~oµ.ev1) -re xor.l. 1tpocrxpLvoµ.tvl) 1JA1) njc; €7tlXVIXALcrxoµ.tv1jc; -re
xocl. <X.1topp&OUCJ'l)c;, 't'O't'& 1tpoc; -rcj> -rpecp1::cr80tL 't'O U7tox&tµ.i::vov xor.l. IXU~&'t'IXL, njc;
µ.ev oucr(occ; 't'OU crw~ov-roc; etc; 't'O dvoc( 't'& xocl. crw~i::cr8ocL Cl'UV't'&AOUCJ'l)c; -rcj>
-rpecpoµ.evep, njc; 8e 7t0Cl'O't'l)'t'Oc; etc; IXU~l)Cl'(V -re xocl. µ.eyi::8oc;. 8Lo 6-rocv µ.ev
25 evepY7i xor.80 -rpocp~, 't'O't'e µ.6vov Cl'W~&L 't'O U1toxdµ.1::vov, 6-ror.v 8e xocl. we;
7t0~, 1tpoc; -rcj> crw~eLV xor.l. cruvocu~eL.
µ.foep 't'O 't'OU 7tlXV't'Oc; xoc-rex.ov-roc; µ.foov -re xor.l. xev-rpov, &v ~ocpoc; e1t' ocu-
't'TI 't'L
µ.ei:~ov -re8-,j XIX't'OC 8oc-repov ~µ.Lcr<patLpLOV, OU 8toc njc; 1tpoU1tocpx_oUCl'l)c;
y'Yjc; 8Loc8ue-rocL 't'OU't'O njc; EV -rcj> µ.foep (l,&VOUCJ'l)~. we;
njc; t8(occ; po7t'Yjc; 't'O
rn xev-rpov ~X,eLV XIX't'OC 't'O 't'OU 7tlXV't'Oc; µ.ecrov, CT.AA' &vw8i::v <EV> -r7i 1tpoU1t0tp-
11xoucrn in (.L&XPL TOO'OIJTOU TO 1tpo (XUTOU µ.6pLO\I -rijc; yijc; 1tpow8e:i:, ewe; (X\I TO
ye:v6µ.e:vov Tou -rijc; yijc; ~cx.pouc; x.tvTpov 3Loc '"l" 1tpoa81ptljV Tou ~cx.pouc; ytv'1)-
TOCL X.IXTOC <TO> TOU 7t(X\ITOc; µ.taov (TOUTO yocp X.IXTOC q>UO'LV TOLc; ~IXptO"L TE: x.oct
X.CX.TW ipe:poµ.tvoLc; O'W(J.OCO'LV • 00 yLvoµ.evou x.ixt TO ax'Yjµ.oc &µ.ix ~ yij q>U-
15 ACX.O'O'E:L TO O'q)OCLpLx.6v, 8 dxe: )(.(XL 1tpo Tou}, oihwc; U7tOAlj7tTtoV X.IXL &7tL TW\I
oµ.oLoµ.e:pwv [ytve:a8ocL], TWV (XU~oµ.evwv 3Loc TYJV CX.7t0 -rijc; Tpoq>'Yjc; 1tp6ax.pL-
O'LV, e:u8u T7i 1tpoax.ptae:L TE: )(.(XL e~O(J.OLWO'E:L 1tpoc; TO Tpe:ip6µ.e:vov -rijc; Tpoq>'Yjc;
1tocp' IXUTWV TWV µ.e:pwv TOU Tpe:q>oµ.evou 1tp6ao86v TL\l(X ytve:a8ocL )(.(XL (J.E:TCX.-
O'T(XO'L\I &AAou 1tpow8ouvToc; &>.Ao, ewe; (XV TO 7tOCV, ev <t> 1tp0Te:pov ~\I ax~-
20 (J.OCTL, ev TOUT<p K(XL µ.E:TOC TYJV CX.7t0 -rijc; Tpoip'Yjc; 1tpoa8~X.lj\l ytvljTIXL.
we;
yocp IXU~E:T(X( TE: )(.(XL q>UACX.O'O'E:TIXL TOC TW\I oµ.oLoµ.e:pwv TOU Tpe:q>oµ.tvou ax~-
(J.OCT(X ev TTI TW\I oµ.oLoµ.e:pwv (XU~~O'E:t, oihwc; KIXL TOC TWV cx.voµ.otoµ.e:pwv
U7tOAlj7tTtov ipuAcx.aae:a8ocL 0-X~(J.OCTIX -rijc; KIXTOC µ.6pLoc 1tpoax.ptvoµ.tvljc; ocuToi:c;
Tpoq>'Yjc; u1to -rijc; ev ocuToi:c; 8pe:1tTLK'Yjc; 3uvcx.µ.e:wc; etc; 7tCX.VTOC IXUTOC cx.yoµ.tvljc;
25 cx.v1XA6ywc;. x.oc8' ~\I CX.VIXAoytocv (J.E:TCX -rijc; TOU O'W(J.IXTOc; O'WT'1jp(occ; eX.OCO'TOV
(XUTWV 7t(X\I (XU~E:T(XL, )(.(XL 3e:i: TO yLv6µ.e:vov U7t0 -rijc; ipuae:wc; TE: KIXL 8pe:7tTL-
x.'Yjc; 3uvcx.µ.e:wc; Toi:c; 3Loc -rijc; Tpoq>'Yjc; ocu~ocvoµ.evotc; u1t0Aoc~e:i:v 6µ.otov dvoct,
we; (XV et <iS3wp ~> o!v6v TLc; £7tt\10~0'1Xt 3tcx. Ttvoc; O'WA'Yjvoc; q>e:p6µ.e:vov, q>UACX.O'-
O'OVTOc; µ.ev TO ax'Yjµ.oc TOCUT6v, 3t' uyp6T'1)T(X 3e )(.(XL (J.OCAIXK6T'1)TOC, gT(X\I µ.ev
30 fAOCTTO\I 1l TO 3t' (XUTOU ipe:p6µ.e:vov uyp6v, O'UO'TE:AAoµ.tvou TE: )(.(XL TO ax'Yjµ.oc
£7tL £Acx.TTO\lt O'W~OVTOc; l>yx.ep, lhixv 3e 7tAE:LO\I fl TOUTO, cx.ve:upuvoµ.evou TE:
7tCX.VT1) )(.(XL µ.E:L~O\IIX TO\/ />yx.ov Aocµ.~cx.\10\/TOc;. we; yocp &7tL TOU O'WA'Yjvoc; TOU
TOtOUTOU OU TO iS3wp TO IXU~(Xv6µ.e:v6v EO'TLV, g ye TYJV cx.px.~v ou3e u1toµ.tve:t,
238 cx.AAoc &>.Ao Tt y(ve:TIXt, )(.(XL 7t0T£ µ.ev 7tAtOV, 7tOT£ 3e lAIXTTOV, TO 3' &7tL
T<j> iS3ocTt ax'Yjµ.cx. £0'TL TO µ.tvov x.ocL '"l" e1t(3oa(v -re: KIXL '"l" O"UO"TOA~v Aocµ.-
~cx.vov, oiSTwc; U7tOAlj7tTtov y(ve:a8ixt KOCL £7tL TWV ixu~ocvoµ.evwv ipuae:t • '"l"
µ.ev iSAljV, eip' fie; TO (XU~oµ.e:vov e:!3oc;, &AAoTe: &AAljV E:LVIXt 3e:i:v 3toc Toce;
237. II 7tpo Cl\l't"OU scripsi, cf. 237. 1-2: 7tp0 Cl\l't"OU Apelt: 7tpoc; ClU't"O codd. Br.
237. 13 <To> coni. Br.
237. 16 ylvca8cx1 sec!. Br.
237. 19 &llou 1tporo8oiivToc; F, Montanari p. 37, Apelt Br.: ix).).' ou 7tpoo8oiivToc;
codd.
237. 21 6µ01aµepwv A pelt: ixvoµo,oµcpwv codd.
237. 24 cxuTo!c; [sc. µoploic;) scripsi, cf. 234. 14-15: cxu-tjj [sc. Tpocp"ij] codd. Br.
237. 26 8c! Apelt Rodier: 8ux codd.
237. 28 <IS8rop -i\> coni. Diels, cf. uyp6v 237. 30
237. 31 't"OUTO Rex: TOOTC!lV codd. Br.
238. 4 8c!v coni. Br.: 8c! codd.
TEXT AND TRANSLATION 171
the part in front of it just until the centre of the weight of the earth
produced by the additional weight is aligned with the middle of the
universe; {for this is natural with heavy bodies that move down-
ward, and when it occurs the earth preserves the spherical shape
237. 15 that it also had previously). Now just the same must be understood
to apply to the uniform parts that grow through the assimi-
lation of food, where the absorption and assimilation of nutriment
by the body that is nourished immediately causes a forward move-
ment from the actual parts of the body that is nourished and a
change of position, with various forward motions until after the
addition of nutriment the whole body has the same shape that it
formerly had.
237. 20 Indeed just as the shapes of the uniform parts of the body that
is nourished grow and are maintained by growth in these parts, so
must it be understood that the shapes of the non-uniform parts are
maintained when nutriment is assimilated part by part and distrib-
uted to all of them proportionately by their nutritive faculty. Each
of them grows as a whole by this proportion, while they preserve
the body that they are in, and we must understand that the case
of bodies that grow through nutriment by the agency of nature and
237. 28 the nutritive faculty is like conceiving of <water or> wine moving
along a channel which maintains the same shape, but because of its
elasticity and pliancy is compressed and maintains its shape in a
smaller volume when the water moving along it is less than its
volume, but when this is greater, it expands in every direction and
assumes a larger volume. As with such a channel the water is not
what grows, as it does not remain at all stable [238] but assumes
varying volumes, but the shape containing the liquid is what is
stable and what assumes expansion and contraction-so too must
the process involved in natural growth be understood: that while
the matter to which the growing form belongs must vary at different
172 DE MIXTIONE
5 O"Uvexei:i:; cbtoxpl<mi:;, 't'o 8e e!8oi:; 't'o µevov e1tl. -tjj i>).:n -tjj peoua-n ocvoc).6ywi:;
't'cj> O"<s>A:Yjvoi:; o-x~µom µetouo-8oct µev, O't'(XV EAIX't''t'(l)V ~ i>AYJ ytVYj't'OCL, (XU~e-
o-8oct 8e, 7tA.e(ovoi:; tji:; )((X't'IX 't'YJ" i>AYJV 1tpoo-xp(o-ewi:; YLVOµtVYji:;, !J.e't'IX tji:;
't'Ou o£xe£ou 0-X~!J.OC't'oi:; O"<s>'t'Yjp(oci:;. 't'O yixp E7tL 1tA.efovt i>ATI 't'OCU't'OV e!8oi:;
µe'i:~ov 't'OU e1t' EAIX't''t'OVL, wi:; )((XL 't'O o-x-Yjµoc 't'OU O"<s>A'Yjvoi:;, 't'OU 8t' uyp6't'Yj't'(X
10 O"Uµµe't'OC7tL7t't'OV't'oi:; 't'cj> 8t' ocu't'ou peov't'L.
oi>'t'<ui:; 8e
ywoµtvYji:; tji:; (XU~~O"e<ui:; o!µoct qiocvepov eLV(XL 't'O µYj8e 't'YJ" (XU~YJO"LV O'UV-
't'eAeLV 't'o'i:i:; o-wµoc 8tix o-wµoc't'oi:; xwpe'i:v Myouo-w 1tpoi:; 't'YJ" )((X't'(XO"Xeu~v 't'OU
1tocpoc86~ou n xocL 8ocuµoco-'t'ou 86yµoc't'oi:;.
elasticity uyp6nic;
enmattered form lvut..ov e:?8oc;
exist independently (individ- u<pe:a't'ixvoct xoc8' ocu't'ix (xoc't'' t8locv)
ually)
fusion
growth oc();l)aLc;
joint-destruction auµ.qi8ocpaLc;
by juncture xoc8' ocpµ.~v
juxtaposition 1tocpix8e:aLc;, 1tocpoc't'l8e:a8oct
magnitude µ.eye:8oc;
malleable e:.'.moc8~c;
matter /form ut..l)/e:!8oc;
mixture µ.i:;tc;, µ.(yvua8oct
nature <puatc;
[process of] nourishment, (thing ..o't'pt<pe:a8oct (..oTpe:<p6µ.e:vov)
that is nourished)
notion (common, natural) lvvotoc (xoLv~, qiuaLx~)
nutriment, nutrition 't'pO(j)~
nutritive faculty 8pe:1t't'LX~ 8uvocµ.tc;
GLOSSARY OF TERMS 175
passing-away cp8opoc
preconception 1tpOAYJljlL<;
preexist 1tpou1t1Xp):E:LV
sense-presentation (after Sand- <potV't'ot(J(ot
bach, in Long ed. Problems
in Stoicism, p. 10)
reduction-to-the-elements OCV0t(1't'OLxe:twaL<;
standards of truth xpLTI)pLot -rij<; OCA.Yj8e:lot<;
State l~L<;
substantiality U1t0(1't'0t(1L<;
tension 't'OVO<;
(reciprocal) interaction, 1tOLE:LV 't'E: xotl. 1tlXC1):E:LV (u1t' OCA.-
(be acted on) A.~A.(J)V), (1t1XC1):E:LV)
218. 12. The claim that the Stoics use every notion but the common
notions is certainly borne out elsewhere in the work; cf. 220. 23-29,
222. 26-29.
220. 27. I read otu-ro'r:c; since two or more bodies must be extended
"through one another" (cf. 216. 16, 217. 29) or as "whole through
whole" (cf. 218. 16 and Mant. 140. ro). For otu-ro'r:c; = ixi.A~i.oLc; cf.
220. 2 above, and cf. 220. l (otu-roc) and 220. II (otu-ro!c;) where by
emendation the same sense is achieved in a context similarly dealing
with bodily interpenetraJ:ion.
221. 33. This independent use of ocll~i.wv is suspect and 8L' oi.ou is
unparalleled in Alexander in this sense. xpocae:Lc; 8Loi.ou at Diog.
Laert. VII. 151 is also questionable, as we have seen (p. 31 n. 45).
'Yi falls foul of the eve:pye:l~ in both clauses which indicates that they
must be parallel. This parallelism moreover begins at oUT(l)t:; 8e
xixt x.T.A., which should not be bracketed as it is by Bruns, and
lies between the actual division of any body (-n c;wµix) and the total
mixture of bodies (c;wµixTix) so divided. This connection is reas-
serted at 222. 17 when the inquiry into this aspect of the relation
between mixture and division is resumed after the only alternative
to it, that of an uncompleted infinite division, has been dismissed
at 222. 6-13.
222. 15. As with the argument discussed in the preceding note the
present argument can only be valid if we read 8rnp'Yja6ixL for 8LixL-
pe:i:a6ixL. The reading in the manuscripts says that constituents form
an infinite number of completely divided bodies by being able to
undergo a process of division (8LixLpe:fo6ixL) rather than, as we would
expect from the conclusion (xixT' ixuTouc;; etc.) and from OL7Jp'1)µtvov
(line 15), by being able to reach a state of complete division. With
this reading e:t oe MyoLe:v (222. 14) introduces exactly the opposite
hypothesis to that of an uncompleted infinite division furnished by
e:t µev yixp Atyouc;Lv X.'t'.A. at 222. 6ff.
The palaeographical possibility of the change proposed in this
and the preceding note rests on the standard confusion of H and EI.
This could have resulted in a corruption to 8L'1)pe:Lc;8ixL and its sim-
plifying emendation to 0LixLpe:La61XL.
222. 25. Aristotle, de gen. et corr. A2 316a 29-30 suggests that it
follows from points being parts of the line that a magnitude is
composed of non-magnitudes, and not vice-versa.
224. II. oµo(wc;; cxAA~AoLc;; needs to be qualified as at 224. 13 by Toi:i:;
(jl)Ve:"J_eaL x.T.A. Here it is gratuitous. For the word order of my
emended Tix ~vwµevoc 1tix.vTix cf. 233. 31.
224. 13. It would be contradictory in this argument to say that
pneuma separated bodies and hence I add c;uvexe:c;8ixL. For the
conjunction of c;uvexe:a6ocL and ~vc7ia6ocL cf. 223. 31.
224. 24-25. Cf. Von Arnim (SVF II, p. 146. 10) where the change to
ixuTou and ixuTo is made tacitly. lSv too must agree with pneuma
rather than being followed by a comma as Rodier suggested. The
12
178 DE MIXTIONE
evepye:tocv) fLE:'t'OC~OA.~V, 5aoc ye: OCU't'WV (Br.) 't'OLOCU't'OC xwpe:"i: µ.~ 1t(XV't'TI
xwpLG't'OC -re: xoct 1te:1te:pocaµ.evoc (Schramm).
233. 17. -ro u1t&pxov awµ.oc is unusual. The normal equivalents for
-ro ocu~6µ.e:vov are -ro u1toxe:tµ.e:vov (e.g. 236. 22) or 1tpo01t(Xpxe:w in the
present participle qualifying a relevant noun (e.g. UAYJ at 236. 17,
or µ.eye:8oc; at Philop. de gen. et corr. 87. 6) or in the form -ro 1tpo01tocp-
xov (Philop. rr8. 23). It may be best to follow A2 and Ra.
COMMENTARY
Chapter 1
213. 4-5. "in a uniform body" (oµou µ~v ... oµou 8e). Cf. 213. 10-
12, Plutarch de comm. not. 37. 1078B (p. 104. 29 Teubner), and
note on 7. 221. 9-10 where Alexander reduces total blending to a
DE MIXTIONE
214. ro-16. Cf. de Jato 165. 25-27 for a similar formulaic description
of prevailing dissension at the opening of a work.
Chapter 2
214. 18-28. (214. 18-25 = DK 68A 64). This "Democritean" theory
would seem to be based on the unattributed theory that blending
is relative to perception mentioned by Aristotle at de gen. et corr.
Aro 328a 8-16. Cf. especially 214. 19-20, 22-23 with 328a 7-8, and
see Joachim on 328a 1-2. There is no record of it being propounded
by Democritus, and since its presence here is simply to fulfill
Alexander's programme (213. 15-17) that theories of matter have
corresponding theories of mixture, this is not good evidence for
attributing it to him.
214. 23. " ... its own nature, which they had even before the mix-
ture" (tpoow, ~v e:!zov x<Xt rtpo -rij~ µ.[~e:w~). Cf. exactly the same
expression used of constituents' surfaces at 213. 6, 13 in the descrip-
tion of the presence of constituents in a "Stoic" blend. Here the
preservation of "natures" is an aspect of juxtaposition; the earlier
text would seem, as we have said (on 213. 2-6), to be setting up the
Stoic theory of blending for the argument reducing it to juxta-
position that we eventually find at 7. 220. 35-221. 7.
214. 26. "the consequence" (',o Ertoµ.e:vov) simply being that mixture
is relative to perception. Epicurus tried to evade it (28-29) by
making mixture the juxtaposition of atoms which, presumably,
necessarily escape perception (cf. Alex. Quaest. III. 12, 105. 13)
whereas the Democritean corpuscles just happen to be imper-
ceptible, but might be accessible to the proverbial Lynceus (de gen.
et corr. Aro 328a 15).
214. 27-28. It is not clear whether the juxtaposition of homoio-
merous bodies is blending, or, as at 214. 2, coming-to-be. If the
former, then we would need evidence that Anaxagoras believed
that corpuscles were juxtaposed in blending in some different way
from the composition (m.Jv8e:cn~) by which they formed compounds.
Similarly with the attempt to line up the theory that matter is
composed of partless bodies behind the "Epicurean" theory of
blending at 215. 22-23. The whole distinction between coming-to-be
and blending is, as we have seen (on r. 213. 20), unprecedented for
the proponents of this theory of matter.
COMMENTARY r85
Philop. de gen. et corr. 193. 28-29 (on 327b 31££., and probably
derived from Alex. ad loc.-possibly itself a source of the present
passage). Philo (at SVF II, p. 188. 6) reports Chrysippus as using
the expression "fire that reduces the order of the universe to itself"
(To (X.V(XO"t"OLX&LW(JCXV 'TT)V 8Lcxx6aµ."l)(JLV &Le; CXUTO 1tup), and it may well be
a Stoic technical term.
215. 13-14. "for mixture should occur between bodies that are
preserved" (~ yocp µ.i:~Lc; aw~oµ.evwv ye:vfo8cxL 8oxe:i:). In an Aristotelian
blend constituents were present in potentiality but "their power is
preserved" (aw~&TcxL ... ~ Mvcxµ.Lc; cxuTwv, de gen. et corr. Aro 327b
30-31). Cf. also on 230. 14-15.
215. 16-17. "by their particular composition and interlinking (-tjj
I. 213. 20-21 where this ex-
1toL~ (J1Jv8fo&L TE xcxl. 1t&pm1,.ox7i); cf.
pression describes, in part, the coming-to-be of secondary bodies
from atoms for both the Atomists and Epicurus. It shows again
how forced is the attempt to distinguish between their respective
theories of mixture in this chapter.
215. 26-27. "By juxtaposition of parts" (xcx-roc 1tcxpoc8&aLv µ.e:pwv)
refers to the "Democritean" theory at 214. 18-28, and "by mixture
of atoms" (µ.i:~Lv h6µ.wv) to the "Epicurean" (214. 28-215. 8). There
is no evidence that there was also a separate theory of mixture qua
juxtaposition of planes, or partless bodies, to complement the
explanation of coming-to-be (yeve:mc;) in terms of these principles
at 214. 1-5. Alexander would have had to be as arbitrary as he is
in the cases of Democritus and Epicurus (cf. on 214. 18-28 and 214.
28-215. 8) if this were to be established.
215. 30. "not a demonstration of great learning" {e1tl8e:L~Lc; taTop(cxc;).
This perhaps means that the erudition of a commentary is not to
be expected; but cf. de jato 165. 5-7 and p. 20 n. 95.
Chapters 3 and 4. The commentary on these chapters has been
largely preempted by the discussion in Pt. II-ii. On 3. 216. 14-217. 2
see especially pp. 54-65, and on chapter 4, pp. 68-71; for a general
analysis of this whole text see pp. 54-65.
Chapter 3
216. 1-4. "matter is entirely unified" (xowwc; ~vwa8cxL niv /J).."l)v). That
is "matter is unified as common to [or shared in by] all the bodies
COMMENTARY
for which it is a substrate" (cf. u1toxe:"i:a6ixL at r. 213. 16; 13. 229. 16).
This language may derive from Aristotle de gen. et corr. B5 332a 18
where the elements are said to have a UA'YJ xoLv~ ("common matter").
At Quaest. II. 28 there is an interesting discussion of the sense in
which matter is "common" to forms as compared to the sense in
which genus is common to species. For UA'YJ described as xoLvov
u1toxe:L-rou 1tiiaw in an Aristotelian context see Ps.-Ocellus 16. 23
Harder.
In the de mixtione Alexander initially attempts to group the
Stoic and Aristotelian theories of blending as both being dependent
on a theory of unified matter; r. 213. 15-18 and 214. 8-IO refer back
to the general description of the main difference between these two
theories at 213. 2-15. In the present chapter the description of
matter being unified by pneuma at 216. 14-15 picks up 216. 1 and
4-5. However this glosses over the important difference in the sense
of "unified" (~vwa6ocL) in each of these cases. In the former unifica-
tion is the result of a physical force pervading matter, whereas in
the more general description unification is an inherent property
of matter. It is the latter sense which emerges clearly in Alexander's
description of matter's relation to the constituents of blends in
ch. 13 (229. 9, IO, 16; cf. 14. 230. 20-21, 231. 6) where bodies are
said to share in (xoLvwve:i:v) the same matter; matter's unity is
simply its being the identical substrate for different forms. Hence at
IO. 223. 32-34 Alexander can suggest that pneuma's function of
unifying matter (he mentions its creation of sympathy between
bodies-cf. 216. 16-17 below) is best explained by "the sharing of
bodies in matter" (oLix niv TYj~ UA'YJ~ xowwvlixv) ; here the Aristotelian
sense of matter as a common substrate is opposed to the Stoic
notion of matter being unified by something. This establishes the
distinction implicit in the present text, and may explain why in
ch. 13-15 in the exposition of the Aristotelian theory of blending
no mention is made of the Stoics, and of the conflict between those
who held the same theory of unified matter referred to at 1.
214. 8-9.
Marcus Aurelius does refer to "one common substance" (µ[ix
oidix xow~) at XII. 30, and xoLvo~ is widely used by the Stoics to
describe the Myo~ or principle of universal order (SVF IV, Index
s.v.). However it is always implied that this common factor is a
result of a force creating a relation between things rather than, as
in Alexander's Aristotelian usage, a common substrate for bodies.
188 DE MIXTIONE
217. 2 "their own natures" (q,ucmc;); cf. 217. 7. This use of q,uau:;
in the sense of form is Aristotelian; cf. Met. Z6 1031a 30, 1031b 1;
also 16. 234. 3 where a body undergoing growth is said to preserve
its OLXE:L(X q,uo-u:;.
217. 11-12. "in such a product of mixture through blending" (e:v
-rcj) -roLou-rep xe:xp(Xµ.evep µ.lyµ.(X-rL). An odd expression, but logical if we
recall that mixture (µ.~~Le;) is presented in this chapter as a generic
notion so that the result of a blend can be termed a blended mixture.
Chapter 4
217. 13. "suasions" (1tla-re:Lc;); cf. 217. 2. That is, these are not
formal proofs, but like the non-demonstrative rhetorical arguments
to which the term applies very often in Aristotle, e.g. Rhet. 1355b 35.
It is not a Stoic term and has almost certainly been imposed by
their Peripatetic critic. Cf. its use at de Jato 202. 2. This is a slight
revision of my suggestion at Symb. Os. 48 (1973) 50 n. 18.
217. 14. "the proponents of this doctrine" (ot 1tpo'CO"t'ocµ.e:voL -rijo-8e:
-rijc; 86~l'Jc;). At 3. 217. 2-13 Chrysippus was the subject carried over
from 3. 216. 14-15, where he was, arbitrarily I believe (see p. 64
n. 175), made the author of the whole tripartite classification of
mixtures. The switch here is almost certainly due to Alexander's
use of a new source-see on 217. 36-the later reference to Chrysip-
pus at 218. 8-9 notwithstanding (cf. note ad lac.).
217. 24. "the part that befalls us" (-ro e:m~ocAAov ~µ.~v µ.epoc;). Farqu-
harson (II, p. 722) compares this with Marcus Aurelius VII. 7
where -ro e:m~ocAAov is used more generally than here. Like Marcus
II. 1 and VI. 14 this seems to be an ethical version of the notion
of cooperative causation that we have located in this argument;
cf. above, pp. 39ff.
217. 33. "clear evidence" (e;v(Xprij µ.(Xp-rupL(X) is probably Alexander's
expression; cf. defato 186. 23. It is vague in meaning and conceals
the precise logical relation of 217. 34-218. IO to the preceding
analogical argument. As I suggest above (pp. 41-44), this
evidence is, for the most part, to be regarded as a set of inferences
from the case of a wine drop's extension through water.
217. 33-218. 1. "soul ... Nature ... State" (41ux_~, q,uo-Lc;, !~Le;). On
this tripartite classification see above, p. 41 n. 94. It is criticised
at 9. 222. 26-34.
DE MIXTIONE
217. 36. "for there is nothing in the body possessing the soul that
does not partake of the soul" (ou8e:v yocp tjiux_~<:; &µ.mpov -r-ou niv
tJiux.~v ex_ov-r-oi:; crwµ.0t-r-oi:;). Cf. Hierocles IV. 6-8 Von Amim on the
relation between soul and body: w<:; µ.'1j8e: -r-ouMx_LO"t'ov -r-ou µ.(yµ.0t-r-oc;
µ.epo<:; ~<:; 01to-r-epou 0tu-r-wv cxµ.oLpe'Lv µ.e-r-ox_~<:; (trans. above, on I. 213.
2-13). In view of this general similarity of expression (cf. 217. IO-
II and note on 218. 8 below; also cf. Hier. IV. 4-5 with Alex. de an.
13. 19, 14. 23, and IV. IO-II with Alex. Mant. II7. 9-II), and of
the general relevance of Hierocles' description of total blending at
IV. 5-IO Von Amim to Alexander's critique (see on 213. 2-13), it
is quite likely that Alexander's source for ch. 4 was a Stoic scholastic
COMMENTARY 1 93
Chapter 5
218. II. "the common notions." Alexander's implication (by our
reading of the text) is that the notions employed by the Stoics are
not in fact "common," since bodily interpenetration is not con-
ceivable {1tpoElA'l)1t't'0tL, 218. 17). For a notion to be common or
natural for Alexander it must be a direct reflection of experience;
he demands, in effect, that the common notions be principles of
common sense, and uses the Stoic terminology in this way in several
other places (e.g. de jato 165. 15-see further Symb. Os. 48 [1973]
62 nn. 83, 84). This completely rejects the analogical argument in
chapter 4 in which the notion of a body extending over another
body was not formed directly from experience, but by analogy
from certain causal relations manifest in experience. If my inter-
pretation is correct (see p. 41 n. 99 above) the common notions
serve as a synthesis of experience (in this sense they are natural)
from which the theory of extension of body through body can be
derived. It is in principle impossible for such analogical argumenta-
tion to directly reflect experience as Alexander demands. As we
see in ch. 15, Alexander himself has the problem of explaining the
sense in which constituents are in potentiality in a blend by analogy
with the fact that they are easily separable; he leaves exactly the
same gap between experience and theory that here he refuses to
allow the Stoics in insisting that bodily interpenetration be based
on naive common sense (see notes on 15. 231. 12-29, and 232. 32-
233. 2). Also important is Alexander's use of the terms "common
notions," "preconception" {1tp6A'IJ'f/L<;), "common preconception,"
"natural notion" as precise equivalents-cf. 2. 215. IO, 32; here at
218. 14-15, 17; 7. 220. 25; 9. 222. 26; II. 227. II; 13. 233. r. I have
argued (Symb. Os. 48 [1973] 51-54) that the common notions are
distinct from the two equivalent terms "preconception" and
"natural notion," and that this difference can be gleaned in part
from ch. 4 (cf. p. 45 n. 107 above).
218. 15-16. " ... bodily interpenetration with full coextension" {',6
n yixp awµ.oc 8Lix O'Wfl-Ot't'O<; x_eupEL'V oAov OA<p 1t0tpEX't'EL'V6µ.Evov ••. ) • A
clear illustration of how the theoretically rich notion in the verb
describing extension is simplified by the general verb of motion;
cf. 217. 9-10 for a similar juxtaposition.
218. 16. "fails to strike us" {<ou> 1tpo0"1t(1t't'EL). For 1tpo0"1tl1tnLv used
particularly of sense-presentations (q>0t'V't'0tal0tL) of states of affairs
196 DE MIXTIONE
218. 17-24. "It is, indeed, a natural notion ... " The general claim
is that if body cannot be received by body then it is received by
place, which is defined as "receptive of body" (c;wµoc-.oc; 8e:,mx6v,
218. 21). It might appear that Alexander is somehow endorsing
the interval theory of place, especially when he refers in 218. 23
to "empty interval" (xe:110-v 8ufo"t"Y)µoc). This cannot be so; this
theory is refuted by Aristotle at Phys. ~4 2IIb 18-212a 4 before
he establishes his theory that place is the limit of the surrounding
body, and we find the argument at 2IIb 19-25 repeated at Alex.
Quaest. III. 12. 106. 10-13 (anti-Epicurean in this context rather
than anti-Stoic as implied by SVF II 536). It is rather that the
logic of the present argument leads him to suggest that if a body
cannot go through a body then it must enter spaces or intervals
which in the opinion of some (8oxe:i: TLc;Lv, 218. 20) can be defined
as place qua receptacle. This then demands an analysis of what
possible receptacles could explain bodily interpenetration which
218. 24-219. 9 provides. Alexander is simply following a general
notion to its logical limits and can therefore introduce ideas required
by the argument rather than ones he, or for that matter his op-
ponents, would endorse. Thus while the Stoics defined place as
occupied interval (e.g. SVF II 503, 504) this is irrelevant to the
present argument since they could not have considered the pos-
sibility of bodily interpenetration through pores. It is probably
COMMENTARY 1 97
Chapter 6
219. 9-22. This argument is the corollary of 5. 218. 17-18. If a solid
cannot receive a solid in itself, then when compounded with one
an increase must occur. Alexander now proves this in detail in the
face of the possibility, presented by the notion of bodily inter-
penetration, that there is no such increase. The cases in which this
happens are then seen not to involve relations between bodies; see
220. 6-II.
219. II-12. "why any given body does not contribute to an in-
crease in the size of a similar body in all dimensions" (-r£ 8~1to-re ou
't'O 't'U"J..OV O'W(.LOC [-ro 't'U"J..OV] 7t0CV't"(l O'UVOCU~1J't'LX6v 't'OU OfLOLOU). This is the
general form of an argument we find particularly applied to the
theory that light is a body to yield the paradox that light should
increase the size of its medium: see Mant. 124. 13-14, 16-20, 123.
12-20 and cf. Ps.-Galen de qual. incorp. (XIX. 473 K = Westen-
berger, p. 9. ro-16); see also Mant. II6. 1-2 (with reference to the
thesis that the soul is a body), and II6. 13-15 (regarding corporeal
virtues).
The definition of body as a three-dimensional solid (here at 219.
16-17) on which the arguments of this chapter depend is assumed
in these other texts, and occasionally made explicit (cf. Nemes. de
nat. hom. 2. 71 Matth., and Plot. VI. 1. 26 [ = SVF II 315]). It was,
of course, standard: see Aristot. Top. 142b 25, Phys. 204b 20, and
de caelo 268a 2, 268b 14, and 298b 3 where body and magnitude
are equated; cf. also Aetius I. II. 1, Ar. Did. at Dox. Graec., 449. 6-
II, and the Stoic definitions at SVF II 357, and III, p. 259. 24-26
(Apollodorus). As we have argued (above, pp. 47-48) the Stoics
could accommodate this definition insofar as it applies to intra-
cosmic bodies; indeed, they must have, or else there would have
been no need to prove the extension of body through body by
analogy with actual phenomena, as in de mixt. 4; it would have had
actual exemplifications, as Alexander demanded (see note on
5. 218. II). An alternative Stoic definition of body was only neces-
COMMENTARY 1 99
sary, we have argued, for the relation between pneuma and matter,
and this was provided by appropriate characterisations in terms of
a qualitative physics.
219. 19. "makes the compound both less somehow and equal. .. "
(e1-ocn6v 1to't"e: xoct foov TO e~ &.[i.cpoi:v 1tme:i:v). Less than and equal to
the constituents, that is. If A goes through B, and occupies its
place, then the compound AB is less than A + B, but equal to B
in this case, and to A if the process is reciprocated, and if we assume
A and B to be of different size. If they are of equal size, AB would
anyway be equal to A or B taken separately. Alexander develops
paradoxes of such reciprocal equalisation in ridiculing the Stoic
view that in total mixture a small body is blended with a large one;
see M ant. 140. 10-25, 141. 6-22. Particularly relevant to the present
passage is 140. 15-18.
219. 20-22. "for the subject ... is abolished along with its abolished
proprium." This applies the principle of "joint abolition" (cruvocvoc(-
pe:crLc;) : when something definitionally prior to something else is
abolished it leads to the accompanying abolition of that thing; see
Aristot. Top. 123a 14, 141b 28-29, and cf. Alex. Top. 127,
23-26 and 236. 20-21. The de Jato contains a number of uses of the
principle; e.g. 180. 3-4, 184. 20, 196. 3-7, 206. 30, 209. 8-9, 209. 30-
31, 211. 22-28.
12. 227. 30; and at de an. 20. 14-15; cf. also Plut. de comm. not. 37.
1078B.
219. 24. "occupies no additional place ... " (µ'1)8ev0t 1tpocre:mA0tµ~ocve:w
rlAAov -.61tov). Cf. Simplic. Phys. 591. 21-22 for a similar expression
used of a body in motion. There is no parallel in Aristotle for this
or the EmAocµ~ocve:LV at 16. 234. 2I.
219. 22-28. Cf. Philop. de gen. et corr. 90. 17-20 for an identical
argument. At M ant. 141. 4-8 Alexander argues that if soul and body
occupy the same place, and soul is separated from body, then it
will either occupy void (xe:v6v) or always be in a body; the first
alternative implies that it has left a place empty.
219. 28-32. This argument seems to rest on a paradox expressed in
rather compressed terms. I think it can be rationalised as follows.
If A and B are totally blended then they occupy the same place;
but if, per impossibile, an increase occurs when they are so blended
then B cannot be in A's place but must occupy another place.
However by the definition of total blending it can only occupy A's
place. Therefore nothing (no body) occupies this other place. This
amounts to an elaborate way of saying that the total blending of
bodies is incompatible with their being aggregated into a larger
compound (cf. 219. 19-20). If that occurred then the increase in
size would not be evident; the body causing it would not be body.
219. 32-220. 3. This argument may be clarified by this diagram:
A A
B B B
d1 d2
If A is being blended with B and is received at d 1 and d 2 , then
insofar as B receives A it does not do so qua body. For a division
is not a body; cf. 8. 222. 3 for this point in a different context.
220. 3-11. This anticipates the argument in ch. 9 that the total
mixture of bodies is in fact explaining what must be seen as the
relation between form and matter; cf. 222. 35-223. 6. For the
example of the ash (220. 10) see Aristot. Phys. ~6 213b 21. Propo-
nents of the void argued that growth occurs as water sinks into ash
because it contains interstitial void, and it is impossible for two
COMMENTARY 201
220. 17-18. "the fact that incense and bodies that are similarly in-
cinerated." This strictly empirical analysis of the example of heated
incense cited from the Stoic argument at ch. 4 (217. 15-17) tries to
establish its irrelevance as a foundation for the notion that a body
can preserve its qualities when extended. This is an ad hominem
point; several other illustrations of a less questionable nature were
provided in ch. 4 (217. 19-26), and only if Alexander showed that
the notion of a body in some way extending itself is inconceivable
under any conditions would the basis for the whole analogy drawn
in that argument be undermined.
202 DE MIXTIONE
220. 18. "over a considerable expanse" (e:1tl 1tAe'i:ov). Cf. e:1tl 1tA&ov at
220. 20, and e:1tl -roaou-rov at 4. 217. 30; see p. 31 n. 47 above.
220. 23. "association" (1tocpcx6emc;). For 1tocpoc-rl8ea6ocL in this sense
cf. Plato Phaedo 65e 8, and Plut. de comm. not. 1081C.
Chapter 7
220. 23-29. This reintroduces the notion, ridiculed in ch. 1 (213.
2-8), that constituents can be totally blended yet maintain their
original qualities, and be separated from the blend. It was later
repeated without critical comment in the definition of total blending
at 3. 216. 25-217. 2 (cf. 217. 9-12, 27-31); now Alexander returns to
it in the light of the tripartite classification of mixtures offered in
ch. 3 and shows that blending must in fact be one of its limiting
cases, juxtaposition (220. 37-221. 7), or fusion (221. 7-25). Only the
former ensures that constituents preserve their original character,
while only in the latter process are they totally mixed; yet juxta-
position is not total blending, and bodies cannot be separated from
a fusion as must be the case with constituents of a blend.
This sentence shows very clearly how the polemic against "body
going through body" is separate from that directed against total
blending, as defined in chs. 3 and 4. 220. 23-26 summarises the
successful critique in chs. 5 and 6, while 26-29 begins an attack on
the specific details of the theory of total blending. Again (cf. on
1. 213. 13) we see the use of "body going through body" as an
independent notion entailed by total blending rather than an
integral part of the theory. See also on 227. 2.
220. 37-221. 7. The earlier emphasis (cf. on 1. 213. 2-13) on the
preservation by constituents of their surfaces now pays dividends;
for when juxtaposition is defined as surface contact (216. 20), and
total blending is said to involve the preservation of surfaces (213. 5,
12), it necessarily follows that such blending is juxtaposition. If
the particular expression "preserving surfaces" were Stoic it is
strange that it is omitted in the formal exposition of the classifica-
tion of mixtures in ch. 3, and only used in these two polemical
contexts.
221. 7. " ... that mixture and blending are distinct" (&no qiocal
µ'i:~Lv xocl &">J.o xpiiaLV e!vocL). "Mixture" here is used where we would
expect "juxtaposition," and we can only assume that Alexander
COMMENTARY 203
has slipped into the usage we find in both Menon (Anon. Lond.
XIV. 20-23 Diels), and Philo (at SVF II, p. 153. 29). Elsewhere
(at 228. 27-28) i.r.i:~tc; is a generic term for Alexander; cf. p. 56 n. 142
above. This text probably refers back in particular to 3. 217. 7-13
where emphasis is laid on the difference in the Stoic theory between
blending and juxtaposition.
221. 7-20. This argument reduces total blending to fusion; for since
the constituents of a total blend have now been shown to be pre-
served only if they are juxtaposed (i.e. not blending) then they are
blended only if they are destroyed. Both Plutarch (de comm. not.
37. ro78B-C [cf. p. 69] and 40. ro80F-ro81A) and Ps.-Galen (de
qual. incorp. 471 K [pp. 7. 20-8. 7 Westenberger]), though with
much less explicit argumentation, regard the only form of total
blending beyond juxtaposition as fusion. They may have been
drawing on an argument, such as the present one, in which the
stages of this reduction were made clear.
221. 17. "then not even their States would be preserved." When
bodies are totally blended and fused they lose their "states" (~~e:tc;),
and the product of this blend is a unified body with a specific
"state" (i~ic;). Alexander's ad hominem point here rests on a standard
definition of i~tc; as that by which a body is held together, e.g.
SVF II, p. 124. 19-21. It is paradoxical, he is saying, for a body to
lose this in a blend, but necessary that a blend with a "state" be
indissoluble and its constituents inseparable.
The argument shows very clearly the effect of taking the tri-
partite classification of mixtures in ch. 3 as a description of the
204 DE MIXTIONE
Chapter 8
221. 25-28. This chapter is derived from Aristotle's claim (de gen.
et corr. Aro 328a 24, 328b 17) that only moist and easily divided
bodies (eu8uxtpe-rix) can be blended; cf. below 13. 228. 36 and 14. 231.
12-13. As a result, before bodies are fully blended they are juxta-
posed as corpuscles (328a 33-328b 2; cf. 14. 231. 13-14), and their
divisibility facilitates the blending in which a single unified body
is formed. Here this causal relation between bodily division and
blending is applied to the Stoic theory of total blending, and an
exhaustive survey is made of all possible types of division in order
to show that this theory is not satisfactorily explained by any of
them. The discussion assumes, as was argued in the second part of
ch. 7 (221. 7-25), that a total blend for the Stoics must be a unity,
much as it was for Aristotle (hence the significance of 221. 9; cf.
note ad lac.); for the whole chapter neglects the Stoic claim (216.
3-31) that the constituents are preserved in a blend, presumably on
the basis of the argument at 7. 220. 37-221. 7.
221. 26. "particularly in liquids" (ev 't"OL~ uypoL~ .•. µiALCJ't"IX). Cf.
de gen. et corr. Aro 328b 3, and 13. 230. 34-36 below.
221. 32-33. "thus blending would again occur by juxtaposition."
Cf. the earlier arguments leading to this conclusion at 7. 221. 5-6
and 5. 219. 1-3.
221. 34-222. 3. This idea that bodies can be divided into incor-
COMMENTARY 205
222. 7. "through the division never letting up ... " (Tei'> µ.'1)8e1to't"&
emA&L7t&Lv niv Toµ.~v). The Stoic and Aristotelian theories of infinite
division were very close, and 222. 6-8 expresses a general view
compatible with both. For the Stoics see for example SVF II 482.
The only difference was that for Aristotle (Phys. r6 passim) the
infinite was in potentiality, a concept not invoked by the Stoics
(see my discussion at Apeiron 7 [1973] 23 nn. 13, 14). If Alexander
were arguing explicitly against the Stoics at this point rather than
against one of the theoretically possible forms of infinite division
he would presumably reject it for this reason; this appears to happen
in some of the commentators' arguments against other theories of
infinite division (see on 222. 17-22 below).
which it is divided" (el ye di; & -reµve-roct -rL xoc1 auyxefo0ocL ocu-ro ex
-rou-rwv &vocyxociov). Cf. 222. 1-2, and 222. 24-25. This principle of
simple addition is thus applied to an infinite series just as it might
be to a finite series. Cf. Jackob Bernoulli (quoted by Vlastos,
Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, VIII, 371): "If ro members are
present [in an infinite progression] the roth necessarily exists, if
roo then necessarily the rooth, ... if therefore their number is
infinite then the infinitieth member must exist." So by the principle
that Alexander cites, a body is as large as its constitutive units;
if these are infinitely numerous, it is infinitely large.
222. 21-22. "and this would result in there being still further
additional infinites" (auµ~octvoL-ro <Ir> cx.v o{hw xoc1 7tAELw ocv dvocL
awµocToc &AA.oc !11teLpoc). If the sum of an actual infinite set of bodies is
an infinite body, why should there be further infinite bodies, when
the original set of which the first body is the sum is, by definition,
complete? For Alexander must mean not that these additional
infinite bodies will simply be further constituents in a blend, but
that they are the logical consequence of there being a single infinite
body.
A possible Aristotelian source is Phys. rs 204a 20-28 where it
is argued that an infinite body will be divided into infinites, so that
the same body will be many infinites-which is impossible (1toAA.a
8' !11teLpoc dvocL -ro ocu-ro &ouvoc-rov, 204a 25-26). The logic behind this
is not developed; Aristotle simply says that if air is part of air,
so infinite is part of infinite. As far as the present text goes, nothing
more profound may be implied. There are however arguments
against Anaxagoras by Simplicius (Phys. 172. 28-31) and Alexander
(ap. Simplic. Phys. 173. 20-27) that there will be additional infinites
(and indeed an infinite number) if each of the infinitely numerous
homoiomerous bodies is itself infinitely divisible. Thus a theory of
infinite divisibility is criticised because it entails both that a body
is infinitely large (as the sum of an infinite number of parts), and
that these can also be infinitely divided (ex hypothesi) to produce
further infinites, and eventually an infinite number of infinites.
This reasoning would be inappropriate to the present text with-
out attributing to the Stoics the theory of infinite division as an
unending process ruled out at 222. 6-13. For only this could serve
as the premise for the conclusion that there are additional infinites.
Yet if Alexander is not adding this further paradox because it was
COMMENTARY 209
316a 30-34 (cf. Simplic. Phys. 142. 6-rn), as probably does the
reference to indivisible bodies (222. 23-24); for the whole argument
quoted at de gen. et corr. A2 316a 14-316b 14 is designed to dem-
onstrate the necessity of such bodies (see Furley, Two Studies,
pp. 90-94).
Chapter 9
222. 27-28. "State ... Nature ... soul." On this triad see p. 41
with n. 94 above. Cf. its description at 4. 217. 33-218. 1, the text
against which the first part of this chapter (26-35) is directed in
the light of the general principle that constituents are separable
from a blend (cf. I. 213. 7-8; 3. 216. 32-217. 2; 7. 220. 34ff.).
222. 31-32. "But no State is separable from what has it." Cf.
Dexippus Cat. 50. 31-32 (= SVF II 46!) for the same point. In
Alexander's case it may simply reflect de gen. et corr. Arn 327b 16-
17: "nor in general are qualities and states capable of being mixed
with things" (ou8' /S)..wc; -rix 1toc0'YJ xoct -rixc; l~etc; o!6v -re µeµ'i:x6oct -ro'i:c;
1tp&.yµoccnv).
222. 32. "capable of independent existence" (xoc6' ott>'TTjV dvocL
8uvoca6oct). Here used synonymously with xoc-r' t8locv U'f'E<r't'a.voct (222.
29), just as 13. 228. 18 (xoc6' ocu-rix dvocL Mvoca0oct) is with 228. 14-15
(xoc6' ocu-rix U'f'EO"-ra.vocL). This shows clearly the sense in which U'f'EO"-ra.voct
refers to the being of substances. Cf. on 4. 217. 33-34.
222. 35. "enmattered form" (!vu)..ov d8oc;). This expression is
widely used by Alexander to characterise form in its individuating
aspect. Cf. de an. 16. 2 where soul is described as here; also Met.
373. 22-24. (On form, on the other hand, as universal, and hence
immaterial [&.U)..oc;] see de an. 87. 5-23, where this universality is
grounded in the activity of the intellect; cf. J. Owens, Amer. Philos.
Quart. 3 [1966] 167-169, who discusses this topic in Aristotle).
Enmattered form complements Alexander's notion of matter as a
common factor shared by all individual bodies: see on IO. 223. 30-
34, and cf. Quaest. II. 28. 78. 1-3. There are useful discussions of it
by C. Baeumker, Problem der Materie, pp. 296-297, and by P.
Merlan, Monopsychism, Mysticism, Metaconsciousness, pp. 16-17.
222. 36-223. 6. This is a theoretical analysis of the illustration of
fire totally pervading iron at 4. 218. 1-2, complementing the strictly
empirical analysis at 12. 227. 13-228. 4. It applies the concepts of
COMMENTARY 2II
form and matter to the proof for total blending that in ch. 4 im-
mediately succeeds those discussed in the same terms in the first
part of the present chapter (26-35).
The train of thought in this passage is slightly difficult to follow.
After saying that fire is not mixed with bodies, Alexander states
that in general matter is not mixed with form (cf. also 13. 228. 21-
22). Now the relation of fire to iron is not that of form to matter
but of quality to body, and for that reason cannot be mixed with it
as 6. 220. 8-9 shows. 223. 2-3 is then rather perplexing. Fire is said
to have matter in the sense that bodies that are burnt are its
matter, but what does the further claim &.tJ...' ~ µ.ev oc,:p8cxpToc;;, ~ 8' ou
("the one is indestructible, the other not") mean? It must, I think,
refer to two kinds of matter, both matter in general and the matter
of fire just described to us. Alexander must then be saying that
matter in its relation to form cannot be destroyed except where,
as when being burnt, it is a material body. That is, he is drawing the
simple "classical" distinction between primary and proximate
matter, which we find more explicitly established elsewhere; see
de an. 2. 25-7. 8, and cf. especially the distinction between~ xup[euc;;
UAY) (matter in the strict sense) and ~ 1tpoo-ex.~c;; UAY) (proximate
matter) at de an. 4. 22-27. 223. 3-6 then simply describes how such
proximate matter is destroyed and eventually loses its form, sup-
porting 223. 1-3. If this happens fire cannot be mixed with a body;
it can simply destroy proximate matter, without affecting the
fundamental metaphysical relation between matter (qua primary
matter) and form.
223. 6. " ... and expelled from their own form" (Tou otxdou d8ouc;;
e~LO'TIXTIXL). Cf. Alex. Quaest. 53. 5. This is probably derived from
expressions such as e~to-Tcxo-8cxL ex -njc;; ,:puo-eeuc;; (e.g. Aristot. Phys.
07 261a 20) or -njc;; ouo-[ixc;; (Top. 145a 4, IO), though it has no precise
Aristotelian parallel. For a general survey of such language in
Aristotle see G. Else, Aristotle's Poetics-The Argument, p. 496 n. 30.
Chapters IO and II. The discussion of the Stoic doctrines of pneuma
and God in these chapters seems to constitute a digression from
the main object of the work, the search for a theory of blending
that accords with our natural intuitions (2. 215. 30-32). It is not
clearly justified until the beginning of chapter 12 (226. 34-227. 1)
where Alexander says that it was provoked by denials of Aristotle's
doctrine of aether, the substance of the heavenly bodies, which is
212 DE MIXTIONE
light of the alternative Stoic doctrine; see further notes to 223. 30-
34, and 11. 224. 30-32, 225. 18-226. IO, 226. 24-30, 226. 30-34. En
route I shall also try to indicate the significance of the de mundo
for Alexander's conception of providence. He seems to have known
this work, and probably regarded it as authentic-see Moraux,
Hermes 95 (1967) 160 n. 2.
223. 7-9. "that the whole of substance is unified by a pneuma ... "
cf. 3. 216. 14-17. A genuinely historical critique of pneuma's rela-
tion to matter would perhaps deal with the sense in which it creates
a unified substance "in which" bodies can be mixed together (see
3. 216. 17), instead of simply comparing it with the fifth body.
223. 10-14. The broad duality established here between the fifth
body and matter seems to reflect the doxographic presentation of
Aristotelian principles (cx.pzixl). Cf. Aet. I. 3. 22, Epiphanus (Dox.
Graec., p. 592. 10-14), and Hermias (Dox. Graec., p. 653. 31); in
the latter the aether and the four elements are contrasted, in Stoic
terms, as active and passive principles. See also Sext. Emp. P.H.
III. 31 and A .M. X. 316 where the four elements and the xuxAocpop"Y)-
TLxov o-wµix (circular-moving body) are described as principles.
Although Alexander was aware of the more orthodox descriptions
of the relation of the heavenly bodies to the four elements (see 11.
225. 30-35 with note) he might find it convenient in a popular
treatise such as the de mixtione to present Aristotelian doctrine
in these simplified terms, particularly in order to point up a contrast
with the Stoics (see on 223. 11-12). Cf. his use of the sculptor-
statue example at defato 3 to illustrate the four causes; although
misleading as an exposition of Aristotle (see R. Sprague, The
Monist 52 [1968] 298-300) it was a convenient illustrative device
in an admittedly pedagogical work. Probably drawn from some
doxographical source (cf. Sen. Ep. 65. 2-10, Clem. Alex. Strom.
VIII. 9 [ = Stahlin-Freuchtel, III, p. 98. 3-5]), it no more rep-
resented his considered analysis of Aristotle's text than the present
description.
224. 6-14a. There are, I think, three separate points here, developing
the argument at 223. 27-30. (1) (6-9) Pneuma, by definition,
causes the stability of bodies (cruµµeveLV, cf. 223. 8, 216. 16), but
as a matter of fact some collapse and therefore cannot be held
together by it. (2) (9-n) Unified bodies are in fact divided, but
this would be impossible if they were all similarly unified. (3) (n-14)
If all bodies are similarly unified, then it would be impossible to
distinguish those that are, in fact, divisible (juxtaposed bodies)
from those that are not. Conceivably (3) was derived from the Stoic
distinction between juxtaposed bodies formed e:x 8Leo--rw-r(l)v, and
~v(l)µevoc (see pp. 69-70 above), but could have been arrived at
simply on general grounds. Like 223. 27-30 this whole argument
criticises pneuma in the same general common-sense manner as the
arguments against body going through body in chs. 5 and 6.
Chapter II
224. 27. "as I said." I.e. at 10. 223. 30-34.
224. 30-32. "and in that these things are preserved and stable, as
they are, [they seem] to attribute the preservation, being, and
220 DE MIXTIONE
stability of each of them (-r6 -re: e:!v1u exoccr-rou xocl. -ro crw~e:cr6oct -re: xixl.
cruµµeve:Lv) to a pneuma which allegedly pervades everything."
The language used here to describe individual identity is Alexander's
own. Although cruµµeve:Lv ("stability") perhaps has a technical sense
for the Stoics (see on 216. 15-16) Alexander uses it himself (at de
an. 15. 21, 21. 20) to describe individual substantiality (Aristot.
Met. M2 1077a 24 is only loosely comparable). For the combination
of crw~e:cr0ocL and e:!vocL ("stability" and "being") see de an. 75. 31,
and for crw~e:cr0ocL and cruµµevm Alex. ap. Simplic. de caelo 83. 30-32.
The notion of preservation strongly suggests the idea of providence,
and its usage here may be intended to reflect such texts as de mundo
(genuine for Alexander) 399b 9-n or 400a 4 where God is said to
cause the preservation (cr(J)niptoc) of the universe. See the fragment
of Alexander's de providentia at Cyril Adv. Jul. (PG 76 625c) where
divine providence is said to be responsible for the preservation and
coming-to-be (cr(J)nip[oc and yeve:crL,:;) of terrestial bodies, and their
eternal continuation in form (xoc-r' e:!80,:; &.(8Lov 8Locµov~v). Preserva-
tion and stability are elsewhere connected in contexts where some
form of providential control of the universe is being described: see
Ps.-Ocell., p. 13. II, 16 Harder; Cleomedes I. 3, p. 28. 20 Ziegler;
Clem. Alex. Strom. VII. rr. 12-13; and cf. Alex. Meteor. 6. 15-17
where the heavenly bodies are said to be the cause of the universe's
being and eternal stability (-rou -re: e:!vocL xixl. nji:; ocL8tou 8Locµov'Yji:;).
The present text would therefore seem to continue the pre-
occupation with the issue of the providentially guaranteed status
of bodies clearly raised in the earlier comments on matter and form
as alternatives to pneuma at ro. 223. 30-34; cf. also on 16. 235. 12-
14.
224. 33. "reasonably." This because the Stoic doctrine of active
and passive principles, God and matter, described here at 224. 33-
225. 3, precisely embodies the error expressed in Aristotelian terms
in the preceding sentence (224. 27-32). Two of the subsequent
arguments in this chapter (226. ro-24) take up the critique of God's
relation to matter in its terms.
224. 34. "two universal principles matter and God" (-ro Mo ocpxcx.i:;
-r&v 1tocv-r(J)v . . . e:!vocL UA'1)V -re: xocl. 0e:6v). For similar testimonia see
SVF II 300, 301, 304, and cf. p. 35 nn. 65-67 above. For a recent
discussion of the whole doctrine of principles which argues that it
originates in the physical theory of the early Academy, see H.- J.
COMMENTARY 221
Secondly the relation between the four elements and the two
principles was not always clear. In the doxography, for example,
they are listed in parallel (Aet. I. 3. 25), and Sextus Empiricus
(P.H. III. 31) merely lists the elements as principles and dismisses
"the mysterious qualityless matter." Though elsewhere the elements
are said to be generated from matter when it is acted on (e.g. Sext.
Emp. A.M. X. 312 [ = SVF II 309], cf. SVF II 316) it would be
easy to confuse matter itself with the elements (as Alexander does)
and to argue that God is simply composed of them. This problem
would be compounded by the doctrine of pneuma in which a distinc-
tion was drawn between active and passive elements. In the note
on IO. 224. 14-22 we argue that these were not the elements gen-
erated from matter and serving as constituents in the cosmogony.
But it would be easy and natural for a critic to take the elements in
only one sense, and thus see pneuma as composed of matter like
any other compound.
Our text is the product of both kinds of misunderstanding.
At 225. 5-10 God's relation to the elements is seen much as pneuma's
at 224. 14-22 (cf. 225. 6-8 for the comparison with pneuma). At
225. u-17 the general relation between God and matter is criticised
(as later at 226. 10-16) as it is conveyed by the description of the
principles at 224. 34-225. 1; the references to the elements at 225.
IO-II and 17-18 are not important for this main point, and merely
repeat 225. 5-6.
225. 8-ro. "the divine body will be a fifth substance for them."
An ironic consequence in view of the claim that the Stoics in fact
ought to invoke this concept-see ro. 223. 30-34. Cf. Plot. VI. r.
26. 20-22 for a general argument that if God is a body, composite
in substance but without matter, the Stoics will have to introduce
another matter, that of God. Since the overall context employs
the concepts of form and matter, this particular argument may
have emanated from Peripatetic sources. See further Graeser,
Plotinus and the Stoics, pp. 91-93.
225. IO. "with appropriate support" (µe:Toc Twv otxdwv). Von
Arnim's addition of oc1to8d~e:wv (SVF II, p. u2. 38) is unnecessary.
Rex's "im Zusammenhang mit seinen eigenen System" is loose,
but conveys the essential meaning.
225. 16-18. "he would be eternal for them in name alone." That
is, God would not be independently eternal (cf. 225. 4), but only
COMMENTARY 223
rijc; 6e:lcxc; 1tpot-~41e:wc;). Cf. de Jato 202. 25-26 where, with reference to
the Oedipus story, Alexander asks who, by telling this, 1te:pt 6e:w-J
e:uae:~e:i:c; 8tMmm 1tpot-~41e:tc;. Cf. also Quaest. II. 21. 69. 30-31.
1tp6t-7J41tc; is undoubtedly used here in the sense of common notion;
cf. above on 2. 215. ro.
226. 29. "of grubs and gnats" (crxwA~XW'J n xcxt eµ1tl8w-J). These are
the lowest form of animal life, spontaneously generated from matter
(e.g. Aristot. Hist. An. Ar 487b 5). Cf. their employment in an
argument against Platonic ideas by Alexander at Met. ro4. r6-r8.
Like xopcmt-cx6oc; (lit. "maker of small-puppets" [x6pot]) this sym-
bolises the extreme level of detail to which God's influence extends
in the Stoic doctrine.
226. 30-33b (+ 227. 23-25; see the apparatus). There must (cx.-JOC"'(Xl),
226. 3r) be interaction between constituents of a blend only because
for Alexander, like Aristotle, "action" and "being acted on"
(1tote:i:-J, 1tocax_e:L-J) are reciprocal relations; cf. further 229. 3-6 where
this is described as part of the Aristotelian theory of mixture. In
Alexander's own description of the active and passive principles
at 224. 34-225. 3 it was evident that this relation was non-reciprocal
(cf. also above p. 35 with n. 66), so that the whole argument here
is an illegitimate restatement of the Stoic doctrine in Aristotelian
terms. Cf. also Sext. Emp. A.M. IX. 254 for a general argument
that the copresence of the active and passive principles means that
they will interact. This argument could well be one form of a more
general critique of the Stoic theory of providence, that it would
involve God being dependent on mortals: see Quaest. II. 2r. 68. 19-35,
and cf. the Arabic ms., Thillet, p. 319. Note de prov. ap. Cyril Adv.
Jul., PG 76 596B for a general statement that God will be providen-
tial only because he can be so. Presumably in this way Alex-
ander's final theory evaded the danger of a reciprocity between
God and the lower world leading to his dependence on it, as envis-
aged by the present argument.
Chapter r2
226. 35-227. 1. "the only theories worthy of divine things." Cf.
Alex. de providentia at Cyril Adv. Jul., PG 76 628D-629A, and
74rAB for expressions of the value of revering "the divine" (Tix
6e:i:cx, TO 6e:i:o-J), and attaining happiness by contemplation of "divine
things."
228 DE MIXTIONE
Chapter 13
228. 5. "our original statement." See on I. 213. 2.
228. 10-25. This general account of the constituents of blending
is derived from de gen. et corr. Arn 327b 12-23. The constituents of
mixtures must be substances, Alexander sees, if they are to be
separable from one another (228. 14-15). There is almost a play
230 DE MIXTIONE
228. 13-14. "now mixture and blending occur among things that
are naturally independent substances" (ev -roii;; xix6' ixu-rcx uq>ea-rcxvixt
q>uaw txouat). Cf. 228. 24-25 and on 4. 217. 33-34 above. The present
translation is clearly justified by the conclusion of this section,
228. 22-25.
COMMENTARY 231
228. 17. "Anaxagoras." Cf. de gen. et corr. Aro 327b 19-20 where
there is a general reference to the doctrine of everything being mixed
with everything.
228. 20-21. "For even if they are also substances, they do not exist
with equal independence" (xocl. ycxp et oucrloct xocl. 't"OCU't' , &AA.' ou xoc6'
ocu't'cx cruvuq>lo-Tocv't'oct). Here, I think, Alexander is pointing out that
although substance may be defined as form (cf. Aristot. Met. Z17)
this does not mean that forms are independent of substances, for
there is still, as the next sentence (228. 21-22) makes clear, a
dependency of form on matter. Thus to say that form is substance
is not to say that there is "an independent substance along with"
(cruv-) substance itself. This usage differs from the simple sense of
"coexist" that we find, for example, at Philop. de gen. et corr. 301.
27-28 where place is said to coexist with the body occupying it
('t'c°j) crwµ.oc't't cruvuq>lcr't'oc't'oct) and not to be independent (~xet xoc6'
eocu..ov 61tocp~tv) ; for in this case coexistence is exactly the sort of
interdependency that Alexander claims for form and substance by
denying their joint independence in the present text.
228. 27-28. "mixture is the more generic, blending the more spe-
cific." Cf. Aristot. Top. 122b 25ff. for this distinction. On Aristotle's
terminology in general see Joachim, JP (1904) 73-74, and on his
use of classifications of mixtures in other contexts see M. J. Aubon-
net, Actes du VIJe Congres de l'Assoc. G. Bude, Paris (1964), p. 300.
The distinction between composition and mixture (30-34) cor-
responds to that drawn between composition and juxtaposition by
Galen de const. art. med. I. 241-242 K. Alexander also uses µ.~~tc;
(mixture) for juxtaposition at 7. 221. 7, though if it is a generic
term (as here and in ch. 3) it should not have been used in such a
subordinate classification. Cf. p. 56 above.
228. 36. " ... among easily-bounded and moist bodies." In addition
to being easily-divided (see note on 8. 221. 25-28) constituents of
a mixture must have fluid surfaces. Cf. Aristot. de gen. et corr. 328b
3 where this type of substance is regarded as a species of divisible
bodies; cf. also 328a 17, and 14. 231. 12-13 below.
229. 3-21. For the main theme of this paragraph see Aristot. de gen.
et corr. Aro 328a 18-28.
229. 3. "because of its viscosity" (8tcx yAtcrxponi't'oc). Cf. 231. 1, and
Aristot. de gen. et corr. Aro 328b 4-5 where however no examples
232 DE MIXTIONE
Chapter 14
230. 16. "the one increasing and the other passing-away." Cf. de
gen. et corr. Aro 328a 24-26 where such increase is said to occur
only when vastly unequal quantities are mixed. The illustration of
this at 328a 26-28 as the submersion of a wine drop in innumerable
measures of water is apparently directly contradicted by the Stoic
theory of total blending (see above, p. 33).
236 DE MIXTIONE
231. ro. "Blending, then, can be defined ... " This provisional defi-
nition of the process of blending omits to describe either the precise
nature of the product or to explain in what sense the constituents
are present in the blend. The latter point is taken up in ch. 15 but
the former is never explored. It is simply assumed that the unified
bodies created by blending are uniform (homoiomerous)-see 15.
231. 26-27-without the question of the formation of the homoiom-
erous bodies (flesh, blood, bone, etc.-cf. de gen. et corr. B7) being
explored (cf. on 13. 229. 30-230. 14).
Chapter 15
231. 12-29. The separability of constituents from a blend was not
discussed by Aristotle, but merely asserted as a consequence of
the candidates for blending being substances-see note on 13. 228.
10-25. Alexander is forced to deal with it because of his critique of
the Stoics. At I. 213. 6-13 he claimed that a theory of blending
which held that constituents were separable but not completely
mixed was superior to the Stoic view that they were totally mixed
and separable. Again in ch. 7 he argued that for the Stoics blending
must be fusion if it is to be total blending, and will therefore make
238 DE MIXTIONE
23r. 16-19. "a body not in actuality any of the bodies that
have been mixed ... " This describes in metaphysical terms the
product of blending characterised in physical terms at lines 13-16,
It is the basis for a similar description of the separation of con-
stituents at 23r. 24-29, where it is inferred that the bodies separated
are not the original constituents but the product of an easily-
achieved change into a similar body not identical with them. The
DE MIXTIONE
form (e.g. de an. 23. 17-18) and actuality-evepye:L0t (de an. 43. 7-8).
Hence 't'tAe:oi; ("complete") at 14. 230. 23, 25 and 231. IO would
mean both physical and metaphysical completeness. But cf. further
on 232. 29.
231. 29-33. "a heated stone cast into milk." For this case cf. Aristot.
Meteor. 38ra 7 and 384a 21-25 with Alexander ad loc. Also see
Galen nat. Jae. I. 15 (II. 58K) where it is used as an analogy in a dis-
cussion of the passage of blood through the kidneys. It is probably
copied from Galen by Athenagoras de ress. 6; see L. Barnard,
Latomus 31 (1972) 426.
232. 2-5. "the action of the sponge." This example would seem to
be borrowed from an account of the Stoic tripartition of blends:
see Stob. Eel. I. 17, p. 154. 8-II W (= SVF II, p. 153. 21-23), and
Philo de conj. ling. 184 (= SVF II, p. 153. 36-39). Sambursky, Isis
49 (1958) 332-333 has a brief discussion of it. It is one example of
Alexander's dependency on, and transformation of, the former text
(see above pp. 55-65). Cf. also Nemesius de nat. hom. 3, p. 128
Matth. where this example serves to illustrate the preservation of
constituents in a blend below the level of perception, a theory
attributed to Democritus by Alexander at 2. 214. 18-28.
232. 6-IO. "the onset of a slight fermentation in must." There
is a general reference to the heating of must (yAe:uxoi;) at Aristot.
Meteor. 380b 31-32.
232. 9a. "just above." I.e. at IO. 223. 20-25. Here (at 232. 8 and 9)
I translate 1tve:uµ0t (pneuma) as "air", its meaning in that earlier
"realistic" argument where in the context of the general polemic
against pneuma I transliterated it (with inverted commas) "pneu-
ma"; see note on ro. 223. 19-27.
232. 20. "the body that was affected by them ... came to be" (~
yeve:cni; Tei> 't'0tu't'0t 1tixo-:x,ov't'L o-wµ0tTL). That is, the compound is created
by the interaction of the constituents and can therefore be described,
albeit loosely, as coming-to-be by being acted on by them.
Similar language is used to describe the formation of pneuma as
a compound from fire and air at IO. 224. 20; see also 232. 13 where
Alexander speaks of the process (yeve:o-Li;) of separation, and cf. de an.
19. 27, 29, 32. This usage reflects the fact that blending has to be
described as a form of change, yet all the relevant vocabulary
16
DE MIXTIONE
232. 31-233. 2. The theory of blending must accord with (r) the
basic principles of Aristotelian physics-presumably the theory of
the elements and powers, the concepts of matter and form, and
actuality and potentiality; (2) "how bodies change and come to
be," referring presumably to the distinction drawn in ch. 14 between
absolute coming-to-be and the particular change involved in
blending; and (3) the common preconceptions about blending-
cf. 215. 31-32 where these were invoked as a general criterion for
any theory of blending. (3) ought also to apply to the analogical
arguments at 231. 29-232. 18, given the relation that they have to
Stoic argument from the common notions in ch. 4 (see note to
231. 12-29). Alexander however is probably only referring to
general principles such as the preconceptions that a mixture be
unified (215. IO-II), and the natural notion that body does not go
through body (218. 17-18). As ch. 4 itself shows he does not seem
to have appreciated the role of the common notions in an argument,
and is content to take them over in the loose sense of general
principles-see on 5. 218. 11. It is also, as we have seen, questionable
how far Alexander's account is satisfactorily related to (r) and (2);
on the former see notes on 13. 228. 10-25, 229. 18-30, and 15. 231.
16-19, and on the latter on 14. 230. 14-24.
233. 2-14. This text is rather irrelevant here. It simply points
to the empirical verifiability of blending in its initial stage when
bodies divide one another, and belongs with the general comments
on this at the beginning of ch. 15-231. 12-18. It adds nothing new,
though it reemphasises Alexander's concern to establish an em-
pirically based theory, evident also from the analogical argument
for the nature of constituents' presence in a blend at 231. 30-232. 18.
Cf. the reference to surface contact at 233. II-12 with the general
principle that constituents are juxtaposed, i.e. in surface contact,
before being fully blended; see 14. 231. 1-2, II and note on 231. 2.
Chapter 16
The principal justification for this long chapter being in the de
mixtione is that it deals with the paradox of body going through
body. Alexander says that some thinkers have tried to explain
organic growth in this way (233. 14-24) and must be refuted. This
he does very briefly at 234. 23-32 in an argument that elaborates
Aristotle's point (at de gen. et corr. A5 321b 15-16) that growth
244 DE MIXTIONE
cannot occur by body since this will mean that two bodies occupy
the same place (cf. also de gen. et corr. Arn 327b 14 where Aristotle
makes the very general point that nutriment is not mixed with a
body). The remainder of the chapter is a long paraphrase of Aris-
totle's discussion of growth in A5 with only two further brief
references to the notion of body going through body at 236. 12-14,
238. 20-23. There is also a brief reference to the fact that growth is
not blending or coming-to-be (234. 5-9) which links it to the
discussion in ch. 14 (cf. 230. 17), and the analogical arguments of
ch. 15 (231. 30-232. 18) are closely followed in form at 237. 5-
238. IO. Apart from this, the present chapter must be considered an
appendix to the de mixtione. As we have argued above (pp. 83-84)
it is certainly not anti-Stoic, and in view of the independent discus-
sion of "body going through body" in the exegetical tradition must
owe its place here to Peripatetic concerns.
The commentary, as with chs. 13-15, will deal principally with
Alexander's contribution rather than the Aristotelian theory of
growth itself on which Joachim's commentary on de gen. et corr. A5
goes into great detail. See also the notes in W. J. Verdenius and
J. H. Waszink, Aristotle on Coming-to-be and Passing-away. Like
chs. 13-15 this discussion is undoubtedly closely related to Alex-
ander's lost commentary on the de generatione et corruptione (see
Additional Note at the end of this chapter). In a long paraphrastic
note on A5 of the Aristotelian work Philoponus includes all the
salient points of our text in roughly the same order (de gen. et corr.
102. 31-108. 17); some parallels are noted in the commentary,
though I have not made a detailed comparison. Like much of that
work it was undoubtedly derived from Alexander (see Kroll, RE,
IX-ii, col. 178).
Other relevant Alexandrian texts are the discussion of the
nutritive soul in de anima 33. 13-38. II apropos Aristot. de an. B4;
Quaest. I. 5, a more abstract discussion than that offered here at
235. 14-238. IO of why growth occurs in the form and not the matter;
the so-called de augmento, a Latin text translated from the Arabic
by Gerard of Cremona (see Cranz, Catalogus, I, 88-89), which
provides an orthodox defence of Aristotle's theory. It is ultimately
derived from Alex. Quaest. I. 5. On the relevant Arabic manuscripts
see A. Dietrich, Nachr. Gott. Akad. (1964), p. 98, and A. Badawi,
La Transmission de la philosophie grecque au monde arabe, p. 96.
The heterodox theory of growth attributed to Alexander by
COMMENTARY 2 45
234. 17-23. "It is not by the incorporeal." This is derived from the
brief Aristotelian argument against growth by the incorporeal at
de gen. et corr. A5 321a 6-7: "If then by the incorporeal there will
be separable void (xwptcrTov xev6v )- but it is impossible that there
be separable matter for a magnitude." Taking only the first clause
Alexander has interpreted "separable void" to mean the non-
occupancy of place by the cause of growth. Although this argument
is only applied to the body that causes growth (To ocu~"ijcrocv, 234. 21)
it would equally apply to the body that grows, if it were said to be
incorporeal.
235. I. "whole units" (Toc o).oc). Growth is in all parts (see 233. 16,
19-21, 234. 1-2); therefore whatever grows must grow as a whole.
235. 12-14. "preserved and stable" (crw~ecr6oct T& xoct µevew). Cf.
234. IO and 236. 23, and see note on II. 224. 30-32 where we show
that this language is particularly applied to a body's form, and
probably carries providential overtones. I ts use in the present text
anticipates the argument beginning at 235. 17 which shows that
growth must be in the form.
COMMENTARY 247
235. 14-236. 5. Cf. de gen. et corr. A5 321b 19-28. At Met. Z16 1040a
5-16 the parts of animals are ruled out as substances. Joachim
(on de gen. et corr. 321b 19-22) accuses Alexander of interpreting
Aristotle as talking about form and matter in abstraction from the
living organism. Yet_ he does make references to the nutritive
faculty of organisms (cf. on 233. 26-27), which is more than Aristotle
does in de gen. et corr. A5. Joachim (on 322a 31-33), wrongly I
believe, takes the term MvixµLc; (322a 28-29) to refer to the nutritive
soul, but in the context it is only an alternative for d8oc; (cf. de
gen. et corr. Arn 327b 31) and used as it is with reference to the
analogy of an expanding duct (cf. on 237. 28-238. 10) has no
biological connotation. The abstractness of Alexander's account is
no greater than Aristotle's and, like his authority, he treats form
throughout this chapter as the form of a given quantity and not
as the nutritive soul of an organism, the view for which Joachim
(on 321b 16-17) argues speculatively.
235. 33. "prevents its total destruction." Cf. Alex. Quaest. I. 5. 13.
11-16 and Philop. de gen. et corr. 106. 3-11 for the aporia that if
growth is in form then it is conceivable that all the matter will be
dispersed and a separate form left behind. Both solve it by stating
essentially the same theory of controlled dispersal outlined here at
lines 29-33.
236. 14-15. "For matter is not at all stable in a preexistent state ... "
(ou8e yixp 'TT)V ix.px~v 1tpoU1tocpxov {moµevEL). 1tpoU1tOCPXELV ("preexist")
seems to have been a quasitechnical term to describe the state of
the substrate to which nutriment is added. See 236. 17, Philop. de
gen. et corr. 118. 23, and cf. on 237. 8-9. The only precise Aristote-
lian precedent would seem to be Rhet. 1419b 22 (~ -rwv o-wµoc-rwv
DE MIXTIONE
237. 5-238. 10. On this analogical reasoning see note on 15. 231.
12-29. Though not derived from Stoic sources like those at 15. 231.
30-232. 18 the validity of these analogies is again no greater than
that of the Stoic argument from the common notions in ch. 4. They
merely sustain a theory already established in abstract terms (at
235. 17-236. 5) by clarifying the particular process of growth
prescribed by that theory. They are a posteriori suasions rather
than directly informative analogies.
237. 6-7. "both in its own nature and by its own middle" (..cj>
t8£<i> µfoci>)- The first expression is explained at 237. 13-14 (cf.
Aristot. de caelo 297a 16-17 and Alex. de jato 185. 28-31). The second
may refer to the fact that because of its particular composition a
given mass of earth will not move to the exact centre of the universe
but to the centre peculiar (t8Lo~) to it. This is the explanation
forwarded by Alex. ap. Simplic. de caelo 546. 15-23 for the earth
not being exactly spherical. Earth is "non-uniform" (ocvoµowµep-ri~)
and therefore different quantities of it will have impulses towards
slightly different centres: "heavy bodies aim to occupy the middle
by the middle of their individual impulse ("t'ij> nj~ po1t~~ nj~ otxe:(oc~
µfoci>) not by the centre of the magnitude [of the earth]" (546.
20-21).
DE MIXTIONE
237. 8-9. "this would not sink through the preexisting earth" (ou
8ta: -rijt; npoUnixpx_ou(TYJ<; yijt; 8tix8ueTixL). The use of npoUmxpx_eLV here
and at line ro is influenced by the earlier account of growth; see
above on 236. 14-15. For the contrast between "sinking-through"
and proportional growth made in the context of a general descrip-
tion of growth see Philop. de gen. et corr. rr7. 24-rrS. 2. 8tix8ueG6ixt
is the commentator's term for the process that would lead to an
additional weight displacing the earth from the centre of the uni-
verse and not combining with it to form a single body with one
centre; it has no Aristotelian precedent.
237. 26-27. "by the agency of nature and the nutritive faculty"
(uno -rijt; IPUO'E6><; "t'E xixl -rijt; 6pE7t"t'LX!/j<; 8uvixµewt;). Cf. Philop. de gen.
et corr. ro8. 8-12 where the assimilative power of the nutritive
faculty is explained as the action of nature in maintaining the
shapes of an organism's parts by effecting a proportional distribu-
tion of nutriment.
237. 28-238. ro. "wine moving along a channel." This example is
almost certainly a supplement to de gen. et corr. A5 32rb 24-25
where the absorption of water in a measure that retains its shape
is offered as an analogy for the proportionality of growth. This must
also be true of Philoponus' more elaborate example of a duct of
skin (a@A'Y)V 8epµixTtvot;) expanding and contracting when different
amounts of water are present in it but always maintaining the same
shape; see de gen. et corr. 105. 22-26, 107. 27-31, and ro8. 12-14.
At Aristotle de gen. et corr. A5 322a 27-31 we have the case of a
duct (ixuMi;) absorbing liquid only in virtue of Joachim's emenda-
tion of the &U).oi; ("immaterial") of the manuscripts. The word tibia
occurs in a sixteenth-century translation, but &U).oi; was the reading
in the manuscripts known to Alexander and Philoponus; see the
latte::- ad loc.
Phloponus (de gen. et corr. ro6. 12-17) offers a further illustration
of g owth in form by referring to the way that a shadow thrown
1
acre--~ a moving river preserves its shape while the water flows.
237. Jg. "because of its elasticity and pliancy" (8t' uyp6"t"YJTIX xixl
µix).cc,:6"t"YJT1X). As Philoponus emphasises (de gen. et corr. ro8. 3-9,
rr7. 27-29) it is through their moistness (uyp6"t"Y)t;) that organic
bodies assimilate food. Perhaps in Alexander's commentary this
was also stressed when the present example was used. However in
COMMENTARY 25r
238. 15-16. "by passing through the vessels that belong to them"
(8Loc TW'V &.yye:lwv tpe:poµt'VYJ TW'V X(X8YJXO'VTW'V ETT' (Xl)TCX.). For X(X8~xe:L'V
ETTL TL in this sense see Alex. de sensu 41. 2-5. For &yye:t(X = qiM~e:<;
("blood-vessels") see on 5. 218. 31.
238. 17-20. "and we must conceive of the process ... " For these
two examples see de gen. et corr. A5 322a 9-11. Alexander separates
the example of fire from the point that Aristotle derives from it
(322a rr-16)-that nutriment and the growing flesh must be to-
gether, because if they were apart new flesh would grow, and this
would be coming-to-be, just as an already existing fire may either
be kindled (growth) or logs may be set on fire (coming-to-be).
Alexander only makes this point in general terms at lines ro-13.
de mixtione SVF
I. 213. 2-8 II. 481
3. 216. I-I4 II. 470
3. 216. 8-14 III. p. 258 (Sosigenes)
3/4. 2I6. 14-218. IO II. 473
6. 219. 16-20 II. 466
7. 220. 37-221. 3 II. 481
8. 221. 16-19 II. 474
IO. 223, 25-224. 4 II. 441
IO. 224, 14-26 II. 442
II. 224, 32-225. IO II. 3ro
II. 225, 18-27 II. 1044
II. 226. I0-2I II. ro47
II. 226. 24-30 II. ro48
12. 226. 34-227. I7 II. 475
16. 233. 14-24 II. 735
16. 234. 23-32 II. 735 2
BIBLIOGRAPHY I
1. ANCIENT AUTHORS
(a) Collections
1. INDEX OF NAMES
3. INDEX LOCORUM
(References in brackets are to the SVF volume and text)
Alexander 5. 7-8 232
6. 16-20 239
De Anima 6. 17-19 225
2. IO-I I. 13 3m7 7. 9-11. 13 232-233
2. 25-7. 8 211 7. 13-14 233
3. 7-13 224 8. 22-9. 3 235
4. 9-10 225 9. 14-23 239
4. 11-18 239 13. 19 192
4. 22-27 211 14. 23 192
INDICES 267
17. 15-18. IO (cf. II. 394) 26n24 De Mixtione (in Pts. I and II)
19. 21-30 219 213. 15-18 64m73
19. 27, 29, 32 241 214. 6-IO 64m73
19. 32-33 57m45 216. 1-2 64m74
19. 34-36 219 216. 14 22n7, 34n61
20. 9-1 I 197 216. 14-217. 2 52-65
20. 14-15 80,200 217. 2-9 66m78
20. 17-18 241 217. 9-13 68m84
20. 23 224 217. 13-14 42n100
26. 15-17 (II. 786) 24m7 217. 18, 30, 32 3m47
33. 13-38. II 2 44 218. 2-6 35n70, 7m194
33. 16-34. 26 248 218. 15-16 83n236
35• I 248 218. 15-18 77n220
35. 9- 1 7 2 45 218. 18 83n236
43. 7-8 241 218. 21-24 77n220
68. 12-18 88n255 218. 25-26 75n208, 85n246
68. 15-16 23nm 218. 33-219. 5 79n228
69. 20 15n71 219. 1-3 85n246
71. 10-15 (II. 70) 189 219. 23 83n236
72. 13-73. 13 28n36 219. 16-19 83n238
75. 31 220 220. IO 78n221
83. 2-8 28n35 220. 18, 20 3m47
87. 5-23 210 221. 7 56m37
90. 1-9 192 223. 9-17 6on160
94. 7-100. 17 3m7 223. 18 72m95
94. 26-95. 6 251 223. 27-29 63m70
223. 30-34 6on160
De Fato 223. 34-224. 6 54m31
164. 3 ff. I 224. 14-22 35n71
164. 15 6n29 224. 24-25 37n85, n86
165. 5-7 2on95, 186 224. 34 35n68
165. 15 195 225. 4-5 72m95
165. 25-27 184 227. 2 74n203
168. 3-18 224 227. 5-10 17
168. 3-5 215 232. 34-233. I 27
169. 23-26 223 238. 23 84
178. 8-9 188
180. 3-4 199 In De Sensu
182. 20-22 27n32 IO. 2 12n57
184. 3 196 29. 12-30. I 201
184. 3-4 199 41. 2-5 251
184. 20 199 63. 23 203
186. 6-7 196 64. 2-15 236
186. 23 191 64. 15, 25 203
189. 4-5 6n29, 25n20 64. 22 236
189. 9 228 73. 19-21 233
196. 3-7 199 73. 24 2 44
204. 20-21 188 IOI. 4 15n75
2o6. 30 199
209. 8-9 199 In Metaphysica
209. 30-31 199 36. 25-27 185
211. 17 (III. 283) 24m4 59. 6 12n57
211. 22-28 199 75. 26 15n75
268 INDICES