Hellenistic Poetry PDF
Hellenistic Poetry PDF
http://hdl.handle.net/11245/2.62781
File ID uvapub:62781
Filename Thesis
Version final
Copyright
It is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or
copyright holder(s), other than for strictly personal, individual use, unless the work is under an open content licence (like
Creative Commons).
imperial villa at Boscotrecase at the Metropolitan Museum, New York. (Rogers Fund,
1920 (20.192.17)
From the description: “The painting seen here combines two separate incidents in the
life of the monstrous, one‐eyed giant, Polyphemus. In the foreground he sits on a
rocky projection guarding his goats and gazing at Galatea, the beautiful sea‐nymph
with whom he is hopelessly in love. Behind and above to the right, he is seen again,
hurling a boulder at the departing ship of Odysseus, who has escaped with his men
in one panel was a bold innovation when these were painted.”
Source:
http://www.metmuseum.org/works_of_art/collection_database/greek_and_roman_art/
wall_painting_polyphemus_and_galatea_in_a_landscape/objectview
POETRY AS WINDOW AND MIRROR
HELLENISTIC POETS ON PREDECESSORS, CONTEMPORARIES
AND THEMSELVES
ACADEMISCH PROEFSCHRIFT
ter verkrijging van de graad van doctor
aan de Universiteit van Amsterdam
op gezag van de Rector Magnificus
prof. dr. D.C. van den Boom
ten overstaan van een door het college voor promoties
ingestelde commissie,
in het openbaar te verdedigen in de Agnietenkapel
op donderdag 23 april 2009, te 14:00 uur
door
Julia Jacqueline Hermina Klooster
geboren te Amsterdam
Promotiecommissie
Promotor: Prof. dr. I.J.F. de Jong
Co‐promotor: Prof. dr. A. M. van Erp Taalman Kip
Overige leden: Prof. dr. M.A. Harder
Prof. dr. R. Hunter
Prof. dr. A.P.M.H. Lardinois
Prof. dr. W.G. Weststeijn
Faculteit der Geesteswetenschappen
Acknowledgements
My first introduction to Hellenistic poetry was through the Idylls of Theocritus, in a seminar
taught by Marietje van Erp Taalman Kip. I immediately fell under the spell of this delicately
ironic bucolicist and soon afterwards gladly discovered his contemporaries: fascinating,
complex Apollonius, witty, learned Callimachus and the epigrammatists with their
tantalizing vignettes. Reading these poets made me wish to write a PhD‐thesis in classics, if
only to learn more about them.
There was indeed a lot to learn in the process of writing a thesis, more than I had
imagined‐‐and certainly not only concerning Hellenistic poetry. The greatest lesson learned
may be that I have only begun to understand how much more there is yet to learn. One of
the pleasant things I also found, however, is that though the writing of a thesis may be a
solitary and absurdly difficult business at times, it is not something you do all by yourself.
Many people have helped me in many ways and it is with pleasure that I acknowledge their
support and assistance here. My first and greatest thanks go to my supervisors, Marietje van
Erp Taalman Kip and Irene de Jong.
Marietje not only introduced me to Theocritus, but also encouraged me to undertake
this project in the first place, helping me draught the original plan for the thesis. Throughout
the years she has remained a committed and critical reader of my work. Her dedicated and
accurate supervision has saved me from innumerable mistakes while our many discussions
over coffee in Café Van Zuylen significantly improved my ideas. Most importantly, her
philological rigour was an incentive to do the best I could, while her friendship and sincere
encouragement remained a constant support.
Irene proved a keen and critical reader and a helpful and kind supervisor. I have
benefited from her enormous scholarly experience combined with common sense. In
particular, the structure of my texts was often improved by her incisive remarks. The fact
that she has always taken generous time to read my work and discuss it with me, from the
first naive draughts to the final painstaking revisions is something I appreciate greatly.
Needless to say, all remaining mistakes are entirely my own responsibility. Finally, I am
deeply grateful for her confidence in my abilities and the opportunity she has offered me to
continue working in an academic environment.
There have been numerous others besides, both institutions and individuals who
contributed in some way to the realization of this project. The Institute for History and
Culture (ICG) of the University of Amsterdam generously provided the funding. Burcht
Pranger, Paul Koopman and the staff of the ICG followed my progress with friendly interest
and on numerous occasions lent a helping hand when it came to the more concrete problems
of funding etcetera.
The Dutch graduate school for classics OIKOS not only offered an exciting curriculum
of courses and excursions but also enabled me to discuss and present my work in a mixed
setting of young colleagues and senior scholars. The Master classes in Rome and Athens, as
well as the visit to the Annual Meeting of the American Philological Association in icy
Montréal were memorable experiences in a scholarly education. Besides being a lot of fun,
they taught me important things about the academic world and its sometimes bewildering
ways. It is especially Ineke Sluiter, the energetic and inspiring academic director and founder
of OIKOS who I wish to thank here for offering me (and many other PhD‐students besides)
the invaluable opportunities that this graduate school creates.
Numerous good things were the result of OIKOS‐activities. One was the “Young
Hellenists’ seminar” instigated by Christiaan Caspers, in which Annemarie Ambuehl,
Stoeppelkamp, Rolf Strootman, Lina van ‘t Wout and myself spent many an hour in
animated discussions of each others’ works. Another was the organization of the Athens
Masterclass in 2007 with Frederik Bakker, Mariska Leunissen and Caroline Trieschnigg, who
besides being a brilliant team also became a group of dear friends.
The Fondation Hardt generously offered three weeks scholarship in idyllic
Vandoeuvres with its excellent library. The Amsterdamse Hellenistenclub and the OIKOS‐study
group “Van Alexandrië tot Rome” have repeatedly lent a critical if willing ear to presentations
of my work. In the graduate seminar Oikidion I could discuss my work with younger
colleagues.
Some people besides my supervisors have been kind enough to read earlier versions
of my work. Martine Cuypers spent a breathless four hours with me revising and greatly
improving my first draught for the application for funding in Leiden. Although it was not
accepted at the time, it proved very helpful for the later version which was accepted in
Amsterdam. Professor Jan Maarten Bremer kindly read and commented on the earliest
versions of chapters 2 and 3, besides setting me on the trail of Posidippus, an interest
pursued with rewarding results. Gregory Hutchinson took the time to read my synopsis and
discuss the ideas underlying my thesis with me over lunch in Exeter College. Annette
Harder provided useful comments on an early draught of chapter 1, while René Nünlist
meticulously commented on draughts of chapters 1, 2 and 3, offering many suggestions for
improvement.
Others helped in other ways: Silvia Barbantani sent me a copy of her article on
Hellenistic epigrams which I was unable to obtain through the library of Amsterdam
University. Rosa Knorringa agreed to read with me the semi‐final versions of various
chapters, pointing out to me where the text still needed editing. My colleague Mathieu de
Bakker generously offered to take over some of my classes on top of his own busy schedule
when the final deadline for the manuscript was rapidly approaching. Rodie Risselada did the
same for the organization of the Varia Colleges, when another deadline came in sight, the
birth of my dear Julia. To my delighted surprise, the students of the course Greek IB treated
me to a delicious apple‐pie when I had finally managed to finish the revision of the
manuscript.
Then there are the friends I made during these years at University: I have already
mentioned many of my OIKOS colleagues who contributed to making academic life
agreeable and friendly for me. It was also always a pleasure to find my roommates, in their
changing constellations, on entering room 337. Besides our laughs, we shared the grief over
the tragic death of our colleague Guus van der Kraan. A small but lasting consolation is the
beautiful little book we managed to produce together from the text of his Master’s thesis.
Janneke van der Heide discussed the joys and despairs of thesis‐writing (and much else
besides) with me over countless cups of appalling university coffee or nice white wine. It
was great to share my fascination with Hellenistic poetry with the students of the Hellenistic
reading group. Finally, I am proud that my friends Tessa de Leur and Marije de Bie agreed to
be my paranimfen in the defense ceremony. They have always showed their interest and care
for my work and well‐being in the kindest ways.
My most heartfelt thanks however belong to my family and loved ones: to my dear
parents, who have always stimulated me to study the subject I liked, and have encouraged
and supported me in many ways through good times and bad. The loving care they have
taken of little Julia when I was in the final (and sometimes near‐desperate) stages of the
writing process is an unforgettable gift.
Finally, it is practically impossible to express what I owe to David. Countless were
the inspired hours we spent discussing poetry (or merely some Grand Theory of
Everything); many the sunny afternoons, at the side of some river, reading (could you
believe it?) Theocritus. If it had not been for your love, encouragement and‐‐justly famous‐‐
enthusiasm, your tolerance, sincere interest and confidence in me at even the most difficult
times, I am sure this book would not have been written. It is to you, dimidium animae meae,
and to our lovely daughter that I dedicate it.
POETRY AS WINDOW AND MIRROR: HELLENISTIC POETS ON PREDECESSORS,
CONTEMPORARIES AND THEMSELVES
TEXTS, TRANSLATIONS AND CONVENTIONS 1
INTRODUCTION 5
1 Poets of the Past 9
2 Poets of the Present 11
3 Self‐representation in the Age of the Book 14
4 Some Remarks on Methodology 16
CHAPTER 1: HISTORICAL POETS REPRESENTED: POETIC PREDECESSORS IN
EPIGRAM
1.1 Introduction 21
1.2 Greek Poets and their Predecessors 22
1.3 Royal Patronage and “Cultural Memory” 24
1.4 Which Poets and what Past? 27
1.5 Poetical Predecessors Represented in Epigram 28
1.5.1 Poetic Practice: Singing and Writing 30
1.5.2 The Text as Monument 32
1.5.3 Biographical Readings 40
1.6 Conclusion 45
CHAPTER 2: HISTORICAL POETS AND CONTEMPORARY POETRY: COMING TO
TERMS WITH POETIC MODELS
2.1 Introduction 49
2.2 Meeting Ancient Poets 51
2.2.1 Timon, Xenophanes and Pyrrho in Homer’s Hades 52
2.2.2 Hipponax in Callimachus’ Iambi 53
2.2.3 Hipponax in Herondas’ Mimiambi 57
2.3 Ancient Poets as Paradigm 59
2.4 A Biased Reading of Ancient Poets 65
2.5 Avoiding Ancient Poets 68
2.5.1 Dangers of Imitating Homer 68
2.5.2 Dangers of Liking Antimachus 73
2.6 Conclusion 75
i
CHAPTER 3: INVENTION OF TRADITION IN HELLENISTIC POETRY:
APPROPRIATION OF MYTHICAL POETS
3.1 Introduction 77
3.2 The Greeks and the Mythical Poets 79
3.3 Orpheus in Greek Tradition up to the Hellenistic Era 81
3.4 Orpheus in the Argonautica 83
3.5 Orpheus and the Hymnic Argonautica 88
3.6 Theocritus and the Origins of Bucolic Poetry 92
3.7 Antiquity’s Views on the Origins of Bucolic Poetry 97
3.8 Daphnis in Idyll 1 99
3.9 Allusive Narrative in other Ancient Poetry 103
3.10 Daphnis in the other Idylls 105
3.11 The Identities of Daphnis and Comatas 108
3.12 Echoes and Correspondences: a World of Song 110
3.13 Conclusion 112
CHAPTER 4: THE MUSES’ BIRDCAGE: POETIC CRITICISM OF CONTEMPORARIES
4.1 Introduction 115
4.2 Competition and Strife in Pre‐Hellenistic Poetic Culture 116
4.3 Bourdieu’s Field of Cultural Production 119
4.4 Callimachus and Apollonius: How (not) to write an Epic? 121
4.5 The Aetia‐Prologue: Polemic or Preaching to the Converted? 126
4.6 The Telchines and the Lyde 133
4.7 Criticism of Contemporaries in Callimachus’ Iambi 136
4.8 Criticism in Some Epigrams 139
4.9 Conclusion 142
CHAPTER 5: BIRDS OF A FEATHER: POETIC PRAISE FOR CONTEMPORARIES
5.1 Introduction 145
5.2 Reading the Signs in Aratus’ Phaenomena 146
5.3 The Mirror of Immortality 152
5.4 Inviting Comparison 156
5.5 Eliciting Praise 159
5.6 Conclusion 161
ii
CHAPTER 6: POETIC IDENTITIES: SPHRAGIS‐EPIGRAMS VERSUS ROLE‐PLAYING
6.1 Introduction 165
6.2 Sphragis in Epigrams: Succinct Self‐portraits 168
6.3 Asclepiades, Hedylus, Posidippus: Eros, Bacchus and the Poet 169
6.4 The Seal or Testament of Posidippus 175
6.5 Leonidas: Dignified Poverty 180
6.6 Nossis: Positioning a Woman’s Poetic Perspective 183
6.7 Callimachus: Ironic Self‐criticism 188
6.8 Role‐playing versus Self‐representation 190
6.9 Conclusion 195
CHAPTER 7: ALLUSIVE NAMES, ELUSIVE POETS: ALIASES AND ALTER EGOS IN
SPHRAGIS‐POETRY
7.1 Introduction 197
7.2 Puns and Etymology 198
7.3 Wordplay in Hellenistic Sphrageis 201
7.4 Theocritus, Simichidas and Lycidas 205
7.5 Conclusion 217
CHAPTER 8: QUESTIONING THE MUSE: AUTHORITY AND INSPIRATION IN THE
AGE OF THE MUSEUM
8.1 Introduction 219
8.2 Homeric Scholarship and Hellenistic Poetry 222
8.3 Overview of other Passages featuring ὑποφήτης 223
8.4 The Μοῦσαι ὑποφήτορες of Apollonius 227
8.5 Apollonius’ View on Poetic Inspiration 232
8.6 Parallels to Apollonius’ Representation of the Muses 234
8.7 The Theocritean Passages 236
8.7.1 Idyll 16: Κλέος and Prophecy 236
8.7.2 Idyll 17: Immortal Fame for an Immortal King 239
8.7.3 Idyll 22: Rewriting the Poetic Past 242
8.8 Conclusion 245
SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION 249
APPENDIX: LIST OF HELLENISTIC EPIGRAMS ON POETS 259
BIBLIOGRAPHY 265
NEDERLANDSE SAMENVATTING 279
iii
iv
TEXTS, TRANSLATIONS AND CONVENTIONS
1. TEXTS
Adler, A. (1967; 1971) [1928; 1931; 1933; 1935] Suidae Lexicon, 4 vols., Leipzig
Allen, T. W. (1931) Homeri Ilias, vols. 1‐3, Oxford
Austin, C., Bastianini, G. (2002) Posidippi Pellaei quae supersunt omnia, Milano
Beckby, H. (1957‐1958) Anthologia Graeca: Griechisch‐Deutsch, München
Bernabé Pajares, A., Olmos, O. (eds.) (1996) Poetarum epicorum graecorum testimonia et
fragmenta, Leipzig
Burnet, J., (1967) [1907] Platonis opera, vol. 5. Oxford
Cunningham, I. C. (1971) Herodas: Mimiambi, Oxford
Diels, H., Kranz, W. (1966) [1951] Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, vol. 1, Berlin
‐‐‐ (1966) [1952] Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, vol. 2, Berlin
Drachmann, A. B. (1: 1969; 2: 1967; 3: 1966) [1: 1903; 2: 1910; 3: 1927] Scholia vetera in Pindari
Carmina, 3 vols., Amsterdam
Gow, A. S. F. (1952) Theocritus, vol. I: Text, Cambridge
Gow, A. S. F., Page, D. L. (1965) The Hellenistic Epigrams, vols. I: Text and II: Commentary,
Oxford
Kaibel, G. (1965; 1966) [1887; 1890] Athenaei Naucratitae Deipnosophistarum libri xv, 3 vols. 1‐2;
3, Leipzig
Kassel, R. (1968) [1965] Aristotelis de arte poetica liber, Oxford
Kidd, D. A. (1997) Aratus: Phaenomena, Cambridge
Kock, T. (1880) Comicorum Atticorum fragmenta, vol. 1. Leipzig
Legrand, P.‐E. (1960) Hérodote. Histoires, vol. 4, Paris
Lloyd‐Jones, H., Parsons, P. (1983) Supplementum Hellenisticum, Berlin
Long, H. S. (1966) [1964] Diogenis Laertii Vitae Philosophorum, 2 vols., Oxford
Maehler, H. (2003) Bacchylides: Carmina cum fragmentis, München
Maehler, H., Snell, B.) (1971) Pindari carmina cum fragmentis, pt. 1, 5th edn., Leipzig
‐‐‐ (1975) Pindari carmina cum fragmentis, pt. 2, 4th edn., Leipzig
Martin, J. (1974) Scholia in Aratum vetera, Stuttgart
Page, D. L. (1967) [1962] Poetae melici Graeci, Oxford
Page, D. L. (1975) Epigrammata Graeca, Oxford
Pertusi, A. (1955) Scholia vetera in Hesiodi opera et Dies, Milano
Pfeiffer, R. (1949) Callimachus, vol. 1, fragmenta, Oxford
‐‐‐ (1953) Callimachus, vol. 2, Hymni et Epigrammata, Oxford
Powell, J. U. (1981) [1925] Collectanea Alexandrina, Oxford
Radt, S. (1977) Tragicorum Graecorum fragmenta, vol. 4. Göttingen
Ross, W. D. (1964) [1959] Aristotelis ars rhetorica, Oxford
Vian, F. (1974) Apollonios de Rhodes. Argonautiques, Tome 1 Chant 1‐2. Texte établi et commenté
par F. Vian et traduit par E. Delage, Paris
‐‐‐ (1980) Apollonios de Rhodes. Argonautiques, Tome 2 Chant 3. Texte établi et commenté par F.
Vian et traduit par E. Delage, Paris
‐‐‐ (1981) Apollonios de Rhodes. Argonautiques, Tome 3 Chant 4. Texte établi et commenté par F.
Vian et traduit par E. Delage et F. Vian, Paris
Voigt, E. M. (1971) [1963] Sappho et Alcaeus, fragmenta, Amsterdam
1
Von der Mühll, P. (1962) Homeri Odyssea, Basel
Wendel, K. (1967) [1914] Scholia in Theocritum vetera, Leipzig
‐‐‐ (1974) [1935] Scholia in Apollonium Rhodium vetera, Berlin
West, M. L. (1966) Hesiod: Theogony, Oxford
‐‐‐ (1972) Iambi et elegi Graeci, vol. 2 (Simonides, Archilochus, Hipponax), Oxford
‐‐‐ (1978) Hesiod: Works & Days, Oxford
Young, D., Diehl, E. (1971) Theognis, Leipzig
2. TRANSLATIONS
Austin, C., Bastianini, G. (2002) Posidippi Pellaei quae supersunt omnia, Milano
Freese, J. H. (1926) Aristotle: The Art of Rhetoric, London
Gow, A. S. F. (1952) Theocritus: vol. I: Text and Translation, vol. II: Commentary, Oxford
Gutzwiller, K. J. (1998) Poetic Garlands: Hellenistic Epigrams in Context, Berkeley & Los
Angeles
Kidd, D. A. (1997) Aratus: Phaenomena, Cambridge
Most, G. (2006) Hesiod: Theogony, Works and Days, Testimonia, Cambridge Mass.
‐‐‐ (2007) Hesiod: The Shield, Catalogue of Women, Other Fragments, Cambridge Mass.
Nisetich, F. J. (2001) The Poems of Callimachus, Oxford
Race, W. H. (1997) Pindar: Olympian Odes; Pythian Odes, Cambridge Mass.
‐‐‐ (1997) Pindar: Nemean Odes; Isthmian Odes; Fragments, Cambridge Mass.
Seaton, R. C. (1912) Apollonius Rhodius: Argonautica, Cambridge, Mass.
Translations are my own, unless otherwise noted. Sometimes existing translations have been
used and adapted, mostly to modernize the English (turning didst into did etc.). Other
reasons for adapting are indicated in the notes.
3. ABBREVIATIONS
AB Austin, C., Bastianini, G. (2002) Posidippi Pellaei quae supersunt omnia,
Milano
Bernabé Bernabé Pajares, A., Olmos, O. (eds.) (1996) Poetarum epicorum
Graecorum testimonia et fragmenta, Leipzig
DK Diels, H., Kranz, W. (1966) [1951] Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, vol. 1,
Berlin
‐‐‐ (1966) [1952] Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, vol. 2, Berlin
Drachmann Drachmann, A. B. (1: 1969; 2: 1967; 3: 1966) [1: 1903; 2: 1910; 3: 1927]
Scholia vetera in Pindari carmina, 3 vols., Amsterdam
DNP Cancik, H., Schneider, H., Landfester, M. (eds.) (2008) Der Neue Pauly,
Brill Online
GP Gow, A. S. F., Page, D. L. (1965) The Hellenistic Epigrams, vols. I: Text and
II: Commentary, Oxford
Kock Kock, T. (1880) Comicorum Atticorum fragmenta, vol. 1. Leipzig
2
LSJ Liddel, H. G., Scott, R., Jones, H. S., McKenzie, R. (1968) A Greek‐English
Lexicon, Oxford
Maehler Maehler, H. (2003) Bacchylides: carmina cum fragmentis, München
Snell‐Maehler Maehler, H., Snell, B.) (1971) Pindari carmina cum fragmentis, pt. 1, 5th
edn.,Leipzig
‐‐‐ (1975) Pindari carmina cum fragmentis, pt. 2, 4th edn., Leipzig
OLD R.C. Palmer (1968) Oxford Latin Dictionary, Oxford
PMG Page, D. L. (1967) [1962] Poetae melici Graeci, Oxford
Powell Powell, J. U. (1981) [1925] Collectanea Alexandrina, Oxford
Pf. Pfeiffer, R. (1949) Callimachus, vol. 1, fragmenta, Oxford
‐‐‐ (1953) Callimachus, vol. 2, Hymni et Epigrammata, Oxford
Radt Radt, S. (1977) Tragicorum graecorum fragmenta, vol. 4. Göttingen
SEG J.J.E. Hondius (1923 etc.) Supplementum epigraphicum graecum, Leiden
SH Lloyd‐Jones, H., Parsons, P. (1983) Supplementum Hellenisticum, Berlin
Snell‐Maehler Maehler, H., Snell, B.) (1971) Pindari carmina cum fragmentis, pt. 1, 5th
edn.,Leipzig
West West, M. L. (1972) Iambi et elegi Graeci, vol. 2 (Simonides, Archilochus,
Hipponax), Oxford
Standard abbreviations as found in LSJ and OLD apply for ancient authors and works; for
journals l’Année Philologique (Marouzeau) is followed.
3
4
INTRODUCTION
Twenty years ago, Hellenistic literary studies were in a sorry state, judging by the
introduction of Gregory Hutchinson’s 1988 book Hellenistic Poetry:
The celebrated poets of the third century BC have not received much literary
treatment; what is sadder, they seem fairly seldom to be read with much enjoyment
and understanding. (...) Here stands the great bridge between the literatures of
Greece and Rome; yet it seems only rarely to receive more than a swift and very
limited inspection. (Hutchinson, 1988: 1) 1
Far from being neglected, today Hellenistic poetry is almost over‐studied, so much so in fact,
that the 2004 Groningen workshop on Hellenistic poetry resorted to a conference on
Hellenistic poets “beyond the canon.” Whereas the great third‐century poets Apollonius,
Callimachus, and Theocritus would have qualified as such for most readers twenty years
ago, this category is now reserved for such authors as Crates of Malles, Hermesianax of
publications in the field of Hellenistic literature is increasing rapidly, and the on‐line
Hellenistic Bibliography by Martine Cuypers currently includes more than 20,000 titles.
So, why another book on Hellenistic poetry? And why on the poetics, surely the most
eye‐catching aspect of Hellenistic poetry? In the first place, it was simply a question of
personal inclination: Hellenistic poetry strikes a chord with me, and I wished to learn more
about it. But more importantly, the questions this book aims to answer about Hellenistic
poetry have not been fully studied, nor have they been approached from the angle that I
shall propose.
Let me begin by setting out these questions. My study started out as an enquiry into
the representation of the poet in early Hellenistic poetry, that is to say, the extant works of
the Greek‐speaking poets of the third century BCE. 3 The initial query was: how do these
1 This would seem to be a slight rhetorical exaggeration; Hellenistic poetry was certainly not invisible
before 1988, although it is true that in particular the last twenty years have seen a great boom in
Hellenistic scholarship. For this study I have not been able to take into account any literature that
appeared in 2007 or later.
2 The Groningen Hellenistic workshops have greatly contributed to the opening up of the subject in
general.
3 The corpus of poets discussed includes Callimachus, Apollonius, Theocritus, Aratus, Herondas,
Hermesianax, Timon of Phlius, Phanocles, and the epigrammatists Leonidas, Asclepiades, Posidippus,
Hedylus, Nossis, Alexander Aetolus, Dioscorides, Alcaeus of Messene, Mnasalces, Crates, Damagetus,
5
poets represent themselves as poets? In my search for an answer, I came across the following
passage:
Qui est poète doit confesser la poésie, sagt Paul Valéry. Die Frage was ein Dichter sei,
haben immer und zuerst die Dichter selbst beantwortet—durch ihr Werk. Am Anfang steht
die Dichtung, die Poetik ist sekundär. Die Frage kann weder theoretisch gestellt werden, noch
theoretisch beantwortet werden, und so sind denn auch zu allen Zeiten die Antworten so
verschieden gewesen wie die Dichtung selbst. (Maehler, 1963: 1)
This sounds like common sense: in order to find out what poets think about their profession,
look at their poetry. But, as most scholars would agree, this is more complicated for
Hellenistic poets than for poets of other periods in Greek literary history because the
Hellenistic era differs from what went before in that poets of the archaic and the classical age
wrote about their own profession only occasionally and only in select passages, whereas
Hellenistic poets seem to have constantly reflected on poetics, poets and, poetry from all
ages. Orpheus, the legendary bard, is an important character in Apollonius’ epic Argonautica;
Callimachus’ Iambus 1 presents the poet Hipponax as a speaking persona; numerous
epigrams represent and evaluate the great poets of the early Greek literary tradition and
frequently criticize or praise contemporary colleagues. It seems reasonable to suppose that
this is done to reflect on the author’s own position as a poet. Therefore the question how
Hellenistic poets viewed themselves as poets is only part of the broader question of how they
viewed poets in general and in history.
Can this preoccupation with poetics be explained by the nature of Hellenistic poetry
and the circumstances under which it came into existence? Some aspects of this poetry
suggest this and consequently have invited critical attention time and again. Foremost are its
striving for new and unexpected combinations of various generic elements (Kroll’s famous
Kreuzung der Gattungen), 4 its treatment of old myths in new (narrative) ways, its strong
emphasis on the human and un‐heroic element or on romance, and its somewhat ironic or
intellectual distance from its subject matter. As opposed to classical drama, for instance, this
poetry seems hardly occupied with social or political issues. This has led some critics to see
Hellenistic poetry as a kind of “modernist” Spielerei, an experimental art for art’s sake written
Nicaenetus of Samos, Simias of Rhodes and Theodoridas of Samos. I have chosen not to discuss
Nicander and Lycophron, because there are convincing arguments that they belong to a different era,
cf. respectively Magnelli (2007: 185‐204), Kosmetatou (2000: 32‐53).
4 Kroll (1924).
6
in an ivory tower, which frivolously mixes in random elements from earlier poetry in order
to create surprise effects: 5
Als ernsthaft galt die Befassung mit Wissenschaft, nicht mit Dichtung. Diese war zum Spiel,
zur paidia geworden. Ihr traditioneller Stoff wurde nicht mehr ernst, sondern sentimental
oder ironisch, also spielerisch behandelt. Der Dichtung fehlte die frühere gesellschaftliche
politische Bedeutung, insbesondere ihre Funktion im Kult, sie war also Spiel. Formal verlegte
sie sich’s aufs Experiment, auf spielerisch Versuchen. Zu solchem Spiel haben sich
Hellenistische Dichter denn auch bekannt. (Muth, 1966: 259)
Of course such a verdict contains elements of truth, but it obscures the fact that some archaic
or classical poetry is also playful, full of surprise effects, and preoccupied with the personal
rather than the political and also consists of disparate generic elements. 6 Still, it may be
claimed that Hellenistic poetry, in a self‐conscious manner, takes these characteristics one
step further.
How can this palpable if subtle difference be explained? Traditionally, scholars have
rightly pointed to the societal and cultural changes that came over Greek society after the
conquests of Alexander the Great for an explanation:
Now for the first time the Greeks were convinced that the old order of things in the
political as well as in the intellectual field, their whole way of life, indeed, was gone
forever. They became conscious of a definitive break between the mighty past and a
still uncertain present. (...) The new generation of about 300 BC living under a new
monarchy realized that the great old poetical forms also belonged to ages gone
forever. (Pfeiffer, 1968: 87) 7
It would however appear that, precisely because the Hellenistic Greeks recognized the
differences between their way of life and the great past, they also sought continuity with this
past. 8 One well‐known example is in the establishment of the famous Library of Alexandria
by Ptolemy Soter. All important texts of the Greek literary heritage were kept there to be
studied by scholar‐poets such as Callimachus and Apollonius; it literally brought the literary
heritage of Greece to a new seat, in Alexandria. 9
5 Cf. e.g. Howald (1923: 137): “Die alexandrinische Kultur is nicht zu verstehen wenn man sie Ernst nimmt.”
Further: e.g. De Marco (1963: 353), Weingarth (1967:48), Snell (1975 [1946]: 284), Schwinge (1986: 76).
6 E.g. the Homeric Hymns, Pindar’s epinicia, Euripides’ dramas, Sappho’s lyric poetry, recently the new
Simonides‐fragments of the so‐called Plataea‐elegy respectively.
7 Cf. e.g. Bulloch (1989: 542), Fantuzzi and Hunter (2004: 17‐26).
8 Contra e.g. Radke (2007), who argues that Hellenistic poetry attempts to present itself as radically
new and the past as something definitively closed off.
9 Cf. e.g. Blum (1991: 104‐105). Of course, mutatis mutandis the same applies to the other great libraries
of the age, such as the one in Pergamon.
7
The changes from small‐scale polis to mass society, from democracy to monarchy, also
brought along changes in the way poetry functioned in society; it was no longer
predominantly a public art nor an indispensable means of providing social cohesion. These
facts, as Pfeiffer notes, naturally also had their effect on the work of the scholar‐poets. Living
in a changed world yet confronted daily with the legacy of the past, they sought to come to
terms with it and learn from it in their own writings.
The new writers had to look back to the old masters (...) not to imitate them—this was
regarded impossible or at least undesirable—but in order to be trained by them in
their own poetical technique. Their incomparably precious heritage had to be saved
and studied. (Pfeiffer, 1968: 87) 10
The Hellenistic poets’ difference with what went before, then, paradoxically seems to lie in
their awareness of this difference, the self‐consciousness which resulted from their critical
study of the great texts of the past. If we wish to know how they saw themselves as poets,
therefore, the first thing to take into account is their relationship to the past.
One way in which their poetry expresses this is sophisticated and extensive
intertextuality with and allusions to the poetic texts that were studied in the Library. This
tendency is to blame for much of the bad press Hellenistic poetry used to get as being
pedantic, derivative, and overly intellectual:
Si la création du Musée seconda les efforts des érudits et l’éclosion des travaux individuels,
elle ne put ni faire naître des génies, ni inspirer des oeuvres nationales. Ce fut une renaissance
mais aussi un déclin. Il y eut beaucoup de gens de lettres, mais peu de grands écrivains,
beaucoup de livres, mais peu de chefs‐d’ oeuvre. Ce siècle, si remarquable par l’érudition ne
produisit qu’une littérature de second ordre. (Couat, 1882: Préface) 11
However, in a world that has gotten used to allusion in the works of (post‐) modern authors
like T. S. Eliot, James Joyce, or Derek Walcot, the relentless erudition of Hellenistic poetry is
appreciated rather differently. No longer victim to reductive attempts at Quellenforschung,
allusion and intertextuality are now recognized as aesthetic ideals in their own right and
form a topic that receives scholarly comment as a matter of course. 12
10 Cf. e.g. Hunter and Fantuzzi (2004: 1‐37).
11 Cf. e.g. Rose (1960: 314).
12 Because of the presence of specialized commentaries that treat the subject extensively and also
because it is such a vast and hard to delimit subject, I have chosen in general to discuss this aspect of
Hellenistic interaction with the past only marginally, except in one case where, as I argue, a Homeric
hapax legomenon is employed by Theocritus and Apollonius to pronounce on their status as poets in
relation with the poetic practices of the past (Chapter 8).
8
1. Poets of the Past
Yet, there is another way in which Hellenistic poets reveal their wish for continuity with the
past that is even more relevant to my initial question of how they represent themselves. It
concerns the way they introduce poets of the past as “characters” in their poetry. Such poetic
predecessors appear in Hellenistic poetry strikingly often and play an important and novel
role in it, as is recognized by Fantuzzi and Hunter:
In the Hellenistic Age (...) we find that another figure takes his place beside the divine
inspirer, or at times as a substitute for him in the role of ‘guarantor’ of the origin of
the work. The conventional role of acting as a source of inspiration may well be left to
the Muses, but now an illustrious predecessor often steps in to teach the new poet the
ropes and how to proceed to construct the work he has undertaken or else he verifies
and ratifies the correctness of the method that the new poet has followed. (Fantuzzi
and Hunter, 2004: 1) 13
This is well illustrated with an example from the poetry of Callimachus. Several passages in
his Aetia have been marked out as vital for understanding his views on poetry; most
importantly the so‐called Prologue (fr. 1 Pf.) and the Dream (fr. 2 Pf.), both found near the
opening of the poem. As the complex Prologue will be discussed in detail in Chapter 4, we
may leave it aside for the moment and turn to the Dream. Although little of this passage is
left, a combination of testimonia and fragments suggest that in it Callimachus recounted how
he was transported in a dream from Libya to mount Helicon, where he met the Muses, who
answered his questions on the origins (aitia) of sacrifices and cults. Their explanations form
the subject of the Aetia. 14 Of course, a poetical investiture on Helicon by the Muses
immediately calls to mind another ancient poet: the author of the Theogony, Hesiod, who is
indeed duly referred to in the most substantial fragment of the passage:
13 Besides Fantuzzi and Hunter (2004), the most important studies focusing on the appearance of
(poets of) the past in Hellenistic poetry are: Gabathuler (1937) a complete if somewhat dated overview
of Hellenistic epigrams on poets; Bing (1988) which focuses on the shift from orality to literacy and the
way it affects the representation of poets in Hellenistic poetry; Bing (1991), which treats some
epigrams ascribed to Theocritus on the poets of the past from the angle of ancient biography;
Barbantani (1991), which describes the representation of the canonic lyric poets in Hellenistic epigram;
Hunter (1996), which discusses the way archaic lyric forms are reinterpreted and recycled in
Theocritus’ poetry; Radke (2007) which reverts to the point of view that Hellenistic poetry represents a
complete break with tradition; Morrison (2007), which treats the narrator in archaic and Hellenistic
poetry; due to their recent appearance, I have regrettably not been able to take these last two studies
fully into account.
14 The seminal study on this passage is Kambylis (1965); see Benedetto (1993) for a more recent
overview of scholarly work on this passage.
9
ποιμ⌋ένι μῆλα νέμ̣⌊οντι παρ’ ἴχνιον ὀξέος ἵππου
Ἡσιόδ⌋ῳ Μουσέων ἑσμὸ⌊ς ὅτ’ ἠντίασεν
μ]έ̣ν οἱ Χάεος γενεσ̣[... (fr. 2.1‐3 Pf.)
When the group of the Muses met the shepherd Hesiod as he was pasturing his sheep
near the footprint of the swift horse [...] the creation of Chaos…
It would appear that Callimachus alludes to a poet of the past at the beginning of his poem
to identify his aims as a poet. But how and why is Hesiod, the archaic hexameter poet of a
genealogy of the gods, the model for Callimachus, the sophisticated Hellenistic librarian and
author of learned elegy on the origins of obscure cults, which contains panegyric of the
Ptolemies?
Perhaps Hesiod’s importance as a model should be sought in the tension between his
likeness with and his difference from Callimachus. To start with the likeness, the Theogony,
by virtue of being a genealogy of the gods, might be called an aetiological explanation of
how everything in the cosmos came into existence. As has been pointed out, 15 the central tale
of Prometheus teaching mankind to sacrifice to the gods (and cheat them out of the best bits
of the victim by burning only the fat) is an aetiological story about forms of sacrifice (the
main theme of the Aetia). Yet, unlike Hesiod, Callimachus is not a rough Boeotian shepherd
who claims that he ran into the Muses on Helicon and started singing their praises in what
must surely have appeared to a third‐century audience in Alexandria as a crude hexametric
fallen flat with his sophisticated readers.
To indicate his distance from the model, Callimachus therefore presents his Hesiod‐
like meeting with the Muses as taking place in a dream, that is, at a remove from reality.
Hesiod is a model, but not one that is imitated in every detail; he cannot be, since the times
the poets lived in are so different. At the same time, the choice to name a model at all is a
sign that Callimachus wishes to forge continuity with the past despite this difference. What
this example demonstrates is that how Callimachus represents Hesiod should be considered
to learn more about the way he perceives himself as a poet.
Fantuzzi and Hunter (2004: 54).
15
Although of course this begs the question whether Hesiod truly was what he claims to be in the
16
Theogony; at any rate, in his day this apparently seemed a plausible way of representing oneself.
10
This theme, the various ways in which predecessors serve as a “window and mirror”
for Hellenistic poets, will form the subject of the first part of this book. The observation in
itself may not be entirely new, 17 but by bringing to bear upon it theories from the field of
social sciences, in particular Assmann’s concept of “cultural memory” and Hobsbawm’s
“invention of tradition,” I attempt to bring out the cultural conditions influencing issues of
creative reception, (problematic) literary appropriation, and the wish for continuity with the
tradition more clearly. In doing so, I also treat material that has not been considered from
this angle before. This enables me to analyze the differences between the various forms of
introducing the poets of the past. The mere dropping of a name has a different significance
and effect than the introduction of a poet as a speaking character in his own poetry. What are
the underlying reasons for these diverse strategies and what the effects?
I will also put the question whether there is a distinction between the representation
and employment of historical poets, like Homer and the tragedians, and mythical poets, like
Orpheus (in the Argonautica of Apollonius) and Daphnis (in the Idylls of Theocritus) and how
it can be defined and explained. Which category of poets is more suitable for aims of literary
appropriation and why will turn out to be of vital interest.
2. Poets of the Present
Although Hellenistic poets were constantly exploring their relationship with the past, it
would surely go too far to say that they were not interested in their own time and
surroundings, even if their poetry has often—and not entirely incorrectly—been considered
a rarefied art for art’s sake, written in an ivory tower, for a select company of cognoscenti:
Diese Literatur redet nicht zu den Vielen, ihr Reichtum an Voraussetzungen erschliesst sich
allein dem Kenner, und ihre Sprache meidet es ebenso, Formeln der tradition unverändert zu
übernehmen, wie sie sich vom Alltag distanziert. (...) Man ist unter sich, und die raren Dinge
die man sich zu erzählen hat, vertragen keine Lauten Töne. (Lesky, 1971: 788)
17 As noted, the fact that the literature of the past plays an important role in the combination of
tradition and innovation that characterizes Hellenistic poetry has especially been argued by Fantuzzi
and Hunter (2004). However, they devote only one section of a chapter (pp. 1‐17) to the phenomenon
of poetic predecessors as models in Hellenistic poetry. Recently, Radke (2007) has argued on the
contrary that Hellenistic poets deliberately closed the past off from their own era, in order to free the
way for their own innovative poetry.
11
It is undeniable that expressions of aesthetic preference suggestive of such a picture are
frequently found, in particular in Callimachus’ poetry (e.g. in the Prologue of the Aetia, fr. 1
Pf.; the Hymn to Apollo, 102‐end; the Iambi). Complete poetic wars have been reconstructed on
the basis of these expressions. Thus, “the most famous literary quarrel in antiquity” (Rose,
1960: 325) allegedly took place between Callimachus and Apollonius. It was supposedly
concerned with the question of whether epic poetry on heroic themes could still be written in
the third century, as Apollonius had done in the Argonautica. More recent scholarship
recognizes the difficulty of proving the existence of the quarrel and proposes that
Callimachus’ expressions should be considered from a rhetorical or strategic point of view as
a means of creating a position vis à vis his readers. 18 But although the reality of the quarrel
the evidence usually adduced), the persistence with which it has been propounded does
raise some questions. Why is the tone of Callimachus’ declarations of aesthetics throughout
so aggressive? Why has the story of the quarrel been accepted so readily by generations of
scholars? Moreover, even if there were no actual quarrel, it may still be assumed that the two
poets had an opinion about each other’s works. Or was there perhaps something else at
stake?
To answer such questions, it must be realized that the Alexandrian Library provided
the link not only with poets of the past, but necessarily also with living contemporaries and
their works. It is reasonable to assume that this particular social context was a formative
influence on Hellenistic poetry, especially as the Library, the Museum and their fellows were
in some way subsidized by the Ptolemaic court and hence dependent on its favors.
Scholarship has always taken into account the fact that much Hellenistic poetry was
produced at, or for the benefit of, a court, but the questions that have usually been studied in
this context concentrate on its portrayal of royal ideology, and its “propagandistic”
qualities. 19 What has not been asked is how the competition between the poets at court may
18 E.g. Lefkowitz (1981), who treats the matter from the point of view of biographical fictions in the
Vitae of the Greek poets; Cameron (1995), whose revisionary book tends to read all of Callimachus’
poetry with an eye on its rhetorical effects rather than as pronouncing on actual matters of poetical
debate; Schmitz (1999), who applies modern literary theory to an analysis of the Prologue of the Aetia,
and reaches broadly the same conclusions.
19 Cf. e.g. Weber (1993) who tries to identify elements of Ptolemaic ideology or propaganda in
Hellenistic Poetry in general; Effe (1995: 107‐123) discusses possible ambivalences in panegyric poetry;
12
have influenced the nature of their poetry. Focus on this rivalry produces a somewhat
different picture of the declarations of aesthetic principle that are rife in the poetry of the age.
This is the angle from which I choose to approach the interaction of contemporary poets in
Chapters 4 and 5. Grounding my observations by referring to modern sociological models, I
will argue that the social space in which Hellenistic poetry was composed, that is to say the
field of tension between poets, colleagues, audiences, and patrons, could be described, in
terms of the modern sociologist Pierre Bourdieu, as a “field of cultural production.”
Although the negative and aggressive statements in this field have usually
commanded more attention, I will also focus on the instances in which allegiance or praise
are expressed with regard to the poetics of a contemporary; evidently they too form an
integral part of the dynamics of Hellenistic poetic interaction. To illustrate this, another text
concerning Callimachus and Hesiod may be cited. This is AP 9.507, the difficult epigram by
Callimachus in praise of Aratus’ Phaenomena. (The specific problems of text and
interpretation will be discussed more fully in Chapter 5).
Ἡσιόδου τόδ’ ἄεισμα καὶ ὁ τρόπος∙ οὐ τὸν ἀοιδὸν
ἔσχατον, ἀλλ’ ὀκνέω μὴ τὸ μελιχρότατον
τῶν ἐπέων ὁ Σολεὺς ἀπεμάξατο. χαίρετε, λεπταὶ
ῥήσιες, Ἀρήτου σύντονος ἀγρυπνίη. (AP 9.507)
This song and its style are Hesiod’s; not that the man from Soloi [has imitated] the
poet entire, although it must be admitted that he has imitated the sweetest part of his
verses. All hail, refined discourses, product of Aratus’ intense sleeplessness.
Callimachus here compliments Aratus for following Hesiod while not imitating him in every
particular. Of course, the procedure he praises here is remarkably similar to what he has
done in the Aetia. By paying Aratus this compliment, Callimachus both points to his own
poetics and creates an allegiance with the popular and successful author of the Phaenomena.
This means that the epigram can and should be used to learn more about Callimachus´ view
of his own poetics. At the same time, it also shows something about his way of maneuvering
among contemporaries in the cultural context of his own era.
Blum (1991) and Erskine (1995) explain the foundation of the Library and the Museum of Alexandria
as a Ptolemaic bid for the heritage of Alexander the Great, i.e., Greek paideia; Hunter (2003) discusses
questions of ideology in Theocritus’ Encomium of Ptolemy Philadelphus (Id. 17). Yet another approach is
Stephens (2003), who reads Hellenistic court poetry looking for Egyptian elements, which, according
to her were included to legitimize the Ptolemaic rule towards the Egyptian populace.
13
3. Self‐representation in the Age of the Book
The “Age of the Book” is what Rudolf Pfeiffer called the Hellenistic era; an important
statement with repercussions both for the perception and practice of poets and their readers.
In the first place, Hellenistic poetry was written primarily to be read rather than performed.
As Graham Zanker observes, “Reading is a solitary process that removes the reader from the
world around him. He lives instead in the world of the author and communicates only with
him.”(1987: 197). This means that the author of a written text has different, perhaps more
sophisticated, means at his disposal for communication with the reader than a speaker: a
reader may turn back to passages he has already read and thus grasp intertextual allusions
and other literary niceties more easily than a listener. However, the fact that he is writing for
readers also means that the author has to make sure the reader understands who is
communicating with him through the medium of written text as opposed to speech. The
reader cannot see him, only form an image of him on the basis of the text. Self‐representation
is therefore important in written poetry as a means of identifying the author as author
towards the reader.
By the Hellenistic age, as Peter Bing recognizes in his 1988 study, authors had become
readers, namely of texts of the past, more consciously than ever before. This means that the
Muse who inspired them was a “well‐read Muse.” She was not, as in Homer, omniscient
through her divine presence at the legendary occasions she described to the poet, but,
figuratively, through her wide browsing in the library. 20 In other words, Hellenistic poets
were heavily dependent upon written sources, both literary and scholarly, for their
inspiration. Often they implicitly or explicitly acknowledged the fact that these texts formed
their primary inspiration. In what way did this influence their self‐representation? Is the fact
that their art is embedded in the culture of reading and writing a discernible element in their
self‐representation?
To answer such questions I will analyze so‐called sphragis‐passages, where poets
characterize themselves and their works. Such passages occur particularly frequently in
epigrams, which were mostly gathered in poetry books by the Hellenistic age. Kathryn
Gutzwiller was the first to suggest that these epigrams should be read in the (reconstructed)
context of their original collection. If so, it seems plausible that sphragis‐epigrams served to
20 Bing (1988): The Well‐Read Muse, Present and Past in Callimachus and the Hellenistic Poets.
14
introduce the poet’s persona, the presupposed speaker in many of a book’s epigrams, to the
reader in such collections. 21 These self‐representations in epigram should be related to the
fictive epitaphs for dead poets, discussed in the first chapter: sphrageis often assume the form
of fictive epitaphs. Looked at from this angle, these epigrams suggest the way Hellenistic
poets wished to enter the literary tradition they were so acutely aware of.
Broadcasting a poetic identity to a reader who has no direct contact with the author,
many of the sphragis‐epigrams sketch succinct self‐portraits that are meant to be immediately
recognizable. Yet, the opposite may also be found: Hellenistic poets occasionally like to pose
alternative names (e.g. Callimachus’ “patronymic” Battiades) or the creation of enigmatic
alter egos (e.g. Simichidas in Theocritus’ seventh Idyll). The instances named here have
invited a great amount of critical attention that has however failed to provide completely
convincing solutions. 22 The name Battiades harbors more significance than a mere
patronymic, and the figure of Simichidas is more complex than an alter ego.
Moreover, the wider phenomenon as such has not been analyzed satisfactorily. Why
do Hellenistic poets create such riddles about their identity? What does this reveal about
their poetics? The matter was approached in the nineteenth century by Reitzenstein with his
Masquerade Bucolique theory, which reads Theocritus’ poetry as a great charade in which all
major Alexandrian poets are dressed as herdsmen, 23 but this idea lacks any basis in
Hellenistic poetry or history, as has been duly recognized. To follow Treu (1963), who claims
that such riddles qualitate qua defy our attempts at interpretation, on the other hand, seems
too bleak a prospect. Trying to find a middle way, I will concentrate in particular on the
meta‐poetic meanings of the enigmatic forms of sphragis.
Besides unambiguous identifications and enigmatic alter egos, there are also poems
in which the first–person speakers are in no way identifiable with the author, most notably in
the so‐called mimetic Hymns of Callimachus. These poems resemble mimes in that there is no
external narrator but a first‐person speaker, apparently involved at the moment of speech in
the procedure of the festival of a particular god. The mimetic element of these poems has
21 Gutzwiller (1998) Poetic Garlands: Hellenistic Epigrams in Context.
22 On Callimachus, see in particular White (1999: 168‐181); the bibliography on Theocritus’ seventh
Idyll comprises over 200 titles. A good overview of the most important currents in the interpretation of
the identities of Simichidas and Lycidas is provided by Hunter (1999, introduction to Idyll 7).
23 Reitzenstein (1970 [1893]: 233‐4).
15
received a good deal of attention, mostly focusing on the way in which Callimachus invites
his readers to participate actively in imagining the context that is hinted at in the text (the so‐
called technique of the Ergänzungsspiel, which is also found in Callimachus’ epigrams). 24
What has not been asked is whether this practice may be related to the particular
circumstances under which Callimachus worked, that is, as a scholar‐poet in the Library of
Alexandria. I will argue that this is the case and show that ultimately the practice is a
manifestation of Callimachus’ own perception of his position in literary tradition.
Scholarly occupation in the library also influenced the way in which Hellenistic poets
represented the issue of revealed knowledge derived from the Muses. If Callimachus could
not or did not wish to claim that he had actually met these goddesses on Helicon, the
question arises how he and his learned colleagues did view and represent inspiration. It
comes as no surprise that texts from the literary past played a great role in this matter; as
noted, the Hellenistic Muse was a well‐read lady. The last chapter discusses a specific case
that illustrates this particularly well. It is concerned with the use that Apollonius and
Theocritus make of the Homeric hapax legomenon hypophetes and its variant hypophetor in
contexts addressing questions of inspiration and poetic authority. Although the use of this
rare word by both poets has been noted and discussed, 25 scholars have not drawn
conclusions about the representation of poetic inspiration and authority that may be reached
when all passages in which these words occur are connected.
4. Some Remarks on Methodology
It might be asked if looking at Hellenistic poetry merely to shed light on the question of how
Hellenistic poets represent the profession of the poet is not a reductive way of reading.
Evidently, this poetry was not written only to comment on poetry or poets. That being said,
it has to be admitted that Hellenistic poetry is particularly self‐conscious and that most poets
of this period reveal themselves as true poets’ poets: poetics are a recurrent and emphatic
preoccupation. As I hope to have made clear, this book will try to place these poets in their
historical context to achieve a greater understanding of precisely this preoccupation. The
24 The term Ergänzungsspiel is Bing’s (1995: 117‐123). The process has been analyzed for the Hymns by
Hopkinson (1984), Harder (1992: 384‐394), Depew (1993: 57‐77).
25 Most commentaries on either poet have commented on the occurrence of the word, with different
degrees of accuracy and insight; besides there is the excellent article by González (2000: 270‐292).
16
reason for this, is that I believe that it is an interpreter’s duty, if she wishes to appreciate
what she reads at all, to form some kind of understanding of the background against which a
literature has come into being. But this is a difficult matter, as for instance Stephen
Greenblatt recognizes:
If interpretation limits itself to the behavior of the author, it becomes literary
biography and risks losing a sense of larger networks of meaning in which both
author and his works participate. If, alternatively, literature is viewed exclusively as
the expression of social rules and instructions, it risks being absorbed entirely into an
ideological superstructure. Finally, if literature is seen only as a detached reflection
upon the prevailing behavioral codes, a view from a safe distance, we drastically
diminish our grasp of art’s concrete functions in relation to individuals and to
institutions, both of which shrink into obligatory ”historical background” that adds
little to our understanding. We drift back toward a conception of art as addressed to a
timeless, cultureless, universal human essence, or alternatively as a self‐regarding
autonomous, closed system‐‐in either case, art as opposed to social life. (Greenblatt,
1980: 4)
So how should literary expressions from a world so different from ours be approached?
Owing to the lack of substantial or detailed historical data about the Hellenistic period, 26
information about the socio‐cultural background is to some extent sketchy and theoretical.
This causes a dilemma: ignore the background completely or try to make some sense of it,
with the risk of projecting one’s own concerns on it? The first possibility seems unattractive,
so I have chosen the arguably more problematic second approach. Clearly, I do not wish to
apply theory wherever concrete historical facts are lacking, nor do I wish to base dangerous
generalizations about “the spirit of the age” on elements I perceive in the texts themselves.
Yet, I do think it useful and necessary to ground the recurrent characteristics that
involuntarily strike any reader of Hellenistic poetry in some kind of grander explanation,
since it would seem otherwise as if each individual work of poetry discussed here had
randomly come into existence in a vacuum.
This is why I have tried to shed new light on well‐known elements of Hellenistic
poetry by viewing them from the angle of a comprehensive socio‐historical frame inspired
by modern theorists such as Bourdieu, Hobsbawm, and Assmann. I realize that, in doing so,
I am liable to invite the criticism that this is anachronistic or a case of “the Emperor’s new
Of course the great work of Fraser (1972) offers a veritable treasure‐trove of what we do know about
26
Hellenistic poets at the court of the Ptolemies, but regrettably much of this information derives from
untrustworthy sources (anecdotes from later authors or late antique Vitae).
17
clothes,” a fancy way of dressing up of what everyone has already noticed. For one thing, I
hope the results of my approach may justify my choice of method. For another, I feel that it is
impossible to look at literature thinking one can truly retrieve in a positivist way “wie es
eigentlich gewesen” just as it is irresponsible to treat it as if it came into being in a vacuum.
Projecting a modern viewpoint on ancient matters is defensible, or indeed indispensable, in
some cases. It may help to view contours of an age that had not seemed clearly defined until
that moment. Bourdieu’s theories have been developed with an eye on twentieth‐century
French cultural life; Hobsbawm concentrates on nineteenth‐century cultural institutions, and
Asssmann’s theory of cultural memory was developed in relation to the analysis of early
Jewish communities but later applied to ancient Egyptian society. Yet, as the last example
shows, the strength of these theories is that they focus on universal elements in civilized
society and may therefore be used as hermeneutic tools for the analysis of very different
situations.
With relation to literature, it is salutary to realize that, to some extent, every period in
time molds the authors it reads into a reflection of its own image by a selection of elements it
recognizes, or it creates a negative image of itself by singling out what it perceives as strange.
We may indeed wonder if the Hellenistic authors would recognize themselves in the modern
image I will sketch of them, aided by sociological models and theories. In answer to this, the
metaphor of the literature of the past as a window and mirror may once more be called to
mind. Although the view from the window always remains more or less the same, every
viewer sees another reflection in the mirror. In other words, although the literary past has
unchangeable qualities, there is always an element of appropriation in later generations’
approach to it. To analyze the unchangeable facts about a literature that distinguish it from a
later reader’s world, this reader cannot help but involuntarily highlight elements of himself
and his surroundings in it. The perfect example of how this works may be found in the
example addressed earlier: Callimachus’ Hesiod is not the Hesiod of seventh‐century BCE
Ascra, nor that of, say, a modern scholar like Martin West. Still, despite the individual
differences in emphasis, all of these Hesiods possess something of an unalterable core.
As a modern classical scholar, I believe it is essential to put the questions of how and
why the poetry of poets who have been dead for more than two thousand years is still read.
As stated before, I did so at first because I wished to learn about a literature that I intuitively
18
appreciated. I now realize that what I learned in the process of writing this dissertation
concerns modern ways of viewing Hellenistic poetry as much as it concerns Hellenistic
poetry. Yet, to my mind, this is a legitimate approach to literature. Frankly, it seems like one
of the more realistic ones. I hope that this book may be of use to others wishing to learn
about Hellenistic poetry, as well as to those who wish to see what it looks like from the point
of view of the twenty‐first century.
19
20
CHAPTER 1:
HISTORICAL POETS REPRESENTED: POETIC PREDECESSORS IN EPIGRAM
1.1 Introduction
The foundation of the Ptolemaic Library and Museum made Alexandria into the intellectual
center of the Hellenistic world, a shrine of Greece’s literary and intellectual heritage, towards
which scrolls from all over the known world gravitated, just like the scholars and poets who
studied them. An epigram on the new Posidippus Papyrus (P. Mil. Vogl. VIII 309), as Peter
Bing argues, illustrates the idea that Greece’s literature had traveled from its old home to the
harbor of Alexandria. It describes the dedication of a lyre brought to land by “Arion’s
dolphin” on the coast of Alexandria and a song (?) about it at the shrine of Arsinoe
Philadelphus, the wife and sister of Ptolemy II.
Ἀρσινόη, σοὶ τ̣ή[̣ ν]δε λύρην ὑπὸ χειρ[.......]
φθεγξαμ[ένην] δελφὶς ἤγαγ’ Ἀριόνιο[ς∙]
ο̣ὐ̣ρ̣ῆ̣ι̣ ἕ̣λ’ οὐ [βλάψ]α̣ς ἐκ κύματος ἀλλ’ ὅτ[ε σώσας]
κεῖνος αν[....]ς λευκὰ περᾶι πελά[γη]
—πολλὰ πο[εῖ φιλ]ότητι καὶ αἰόλα—τῆι π̣[ανοδύρτωι
φωνῆι π[ῆμ’ ἔλ]ακον καινὸν ἀηδον[ίδες.]
ἄνθεμα δ’, [ὦ Φιλ]ά̣δελφε, τὸν ἤλασεν [......]ιων,
τόνδε δέ̣[χου, .]ύσου μείλια ναοπόλο̣[υ.] (AB 37)
To you Arsinoe, this lyre, which the hands [of a bard] made resonant, was brought by
Arion’s dolphin. With its tail, it lifted it from the wave without [damage], but when
[after saving it][unexpectedly] it goes on its journey through the white sea ‒ it does
many various things through [kindness] ‒ with [all‐plaintive] voice, the nightingales
lamented the novel [calamity]. As an offering, [O] Brother‐ [loving one] receive this
[...] which [A]rion brought forth, a present from [.]ysus the temple guard. 1
Bing suggests:
The poem represents a striking example of how an object, the lyre, may be made to
embody the cultural historical heritage and become (quite literally) the vehicle by
which that heritage is transmitted to a new place. (…) The epigram clearly alludes to
the legend of Arion, “the best singer in the world” (…) by describing how his
lyre‒together with the tradition it evokes‒came to Egypt. Thus the poet links the
third‐century BC shrine of Arsinoe to one of the great figures of archaic poetry from
1 This translation, based on the text and translation of Austin and Bastianini, is more or less exempli
gratia. Some notes on the text: 1 fin. χειρ[ὶ μελωιδο]ῦ? χειρ[ὸς ἀοιδο]ῦ vel χειρ[ὸς ἀδηλο]ῦ Austin | 3
Austin | 4 ἀν[ιηθεὶ]ς brevius spatio ἀν[ωΐστω]ς fort. longius | 5‐6 Austin|6 κανον pap.| 7 [οἶμον
Ἀρ]ίων e.g. Austin| 8 Λ]ύσου, Μ]ύσου, Ν]ύσου aeditui nomen μιλια pap.
21
the seventh century and with him to the rich tradition of Lesbian lyric including
Terpander, Sappho and Alcaeus. (…) That is, (…) emblematic of the Ptolemies’ claim
to be the true inheritors and guardians of the literary legacy of Hellas, in particular
here the great tradition of Lesbian song. The Lesbian lyre has passed on; today its
home is Egypt. (Bing, 2004: 128‐130) 2
A similarly striking interest in the continuity with and renewal of the Greek literary heritage
is evident in many other poetical expressions of the Hellenistic age. The aim of this chapter is
to provide a discussion of how Hellenistic epigrammatists, prominently amongst them the
Alexandrians, viewed and handled poets of the Greek past. Before doing so, I will cast a
swift glance at the history of the Greek poets’ interest in the literary past and also address the
particular drives underlying Ptolemaic interest in it.
1.2 Greek Poets and their Predecessors
Preoccupation with the literature of the past is of course not an exclusively Hellenistic
phenomenon, even if its intensity may be peculiar to this age. The early Greeks already
honored poets of the past as sages and artists, as various texts, portrait statues, and vase
paintings from as early as the sixth century BCE affirm. 3 They might be regarded as positive
examples, a standard by which one’s own works might be measured and which provided
instruction. 4 Other critical assessments, in both the negative and neutral senses of the term,
are also common in archaic poetry: in N. 7.20‐23, Pindar attributes the undue admiration
2 Cf. Austin and Bastianini (2002: 60): Arsinoae Philadelpho lyram, quam ab undis delphinus servaverat, et
carmen Arionium (v 7 s.) dedicat fani sacerdos. Bing furthermore links this passage with Phan. fr. 1
Powell, where the severed head and lyre of Orpheus undertake a similar sea journey. They reach
Lesbos and there become the fountainhead of lyric poetry.
3 The exceptional status of poets is also demonstrated by the cults that many of them enjoyed, cf. Clay
(2004).
4 For instance, Aeschylus claimed that his tragedies were “only slices from the banquet of Homer”
(Ath. 8.347); Antiphon remarks upon the usefulness of knowing the ancient poets (P. Oxy. III 414 coll.
i‐iii); Critias’ comments on Anacreon emphasize the immortal charm of his poetry (Ath. XIII 600D‐E).
See on the topic of portrait statues of the ancient poets in particular Schefold (1965) and Zanker (1995),
who argues for a relationship between portraiture and biographical interests (1995: 145).
5 N. 7.20‐23: ἐγὼ δὲ πλέον’ ἔλπομαι / λόγον Ὀδυσσέος ἢ πάθαν / διὰ τὸν ἁδυεπῆ γενέσθ’ Ὅμηρον∙
/ ἐπεὶ ψεύδεσί οἱ ποτανᾷ <τε> μαχανᾷ / σεμνὸν ἔπεστί τι∙ σοφία / δὲ κλέπτει παράγοισα μύθοις. (I
believe that Odysseus’ story has become greater than his actual suffering because of Homer’s sweet
verse, for upon his fictions and soaring craft rests great majesty, and his skill deceives, with
misleading tales, transl. Race).
22
2 he disparages the vicious poetic attacks of Archilochus. 6 It is clear that poetry of the past
for Pindar provides a rubric for assessing the qualities of later works, including his own. His
remarks thus shed light on key elements of his own poetics: poetry should combine an
elevated style with truth and praise of valor and exceptional feats. Assessments of ancient
poetry, then, were always potentially formative in the production of new poetry.
An interest in poets of the past as historical persons also developed early on in Greek
history; this resulted in biographies. 7 The general idea behind ancient biographical writing is
expressed in maxims like “talis oratio, qualis vita,” 8 which can be understood as a moral
admonition as well as a hermeneutic device: since little documentary evidence about the
lives of ancient authors was available, their writings often served as sources of information. 9
Together with random items of fantasy, gossip, and anecdote, this information formed the
basis of biographical writing, of which traces are found in the Vitae and Scholia.
This writing of biographical essays gained new momentum in the Hellenistic era,
when Greek literature and information relating to it were gathered and studied
professionally on a previously unequaled scale. Scholars working in the Library of
Alexandria sought biographical data to attach to their editions of and works on the poets. 10
This information found its way into the poetic production of the time, since the poets in
question were often the selfsame scholars who had gathered the data. In this way, two
6 P. 2.54‐6: εἶδον γὰρ ἑκὰς ἐὼν τὰ πόλλ’ ἐν ἀμαχανίᾳ / ψογερὸν Ἀρχίλοχον βαρυλόγοις ἔχθεσιν /
πιαινόμενον∙ (For standing at a far remove I have seen Archilochos the blame often in straits as he fed
on dire words of hatred, transl. Race).
7 Tatian (2nd cent. CE) names as the first researchers on the poetry and life of Homer Theagenes of
Rhegium, Stesimbrotus of Thasos, Herodotus, and Antimachus of Colophon (31 p 61, 16 Schw.).
Hellanicus of Lesbos (fifth cent. BCE) is considered by some the true father of literary history (cf.
Lanata 1969: 234). According to Proclus he wrote on the life and dates of e.g. Hesiod, Homer, Orpheus
and Terpander (schol. in Hesiod. Op. 631). Other early “literary historians” are Damastes (fifth cent.
BCE) (Vit. Hom. Rom. p. 30, 24.), and Glaucus of Rhegium (fifth cent. BCE) (Plut. de mus. 4 p. 1132E; 7 p.
1133F).
8 Seneca (Ep. 114), cf. Cicero (Tusc. 5.47).
9 E.g. the identification of Demodocus, the Phaeacian singer with Homer and hence his representation
as a blind bard, or the remarks in the Pindar‐scholia on Pindar’s quarrels with Bacchylides and
Simonides as extrapolated from references to “silly crows” in his odes. On the development and
characteristics of ancient biographical writing, see Bruns (1896), Leo (1901), Momigliano (1971),
Lefkowitz (1981).
10 E.g. Callimachus’ Pinakes (Blum 1991), Grapheion (fr. 380 Pf.), Mouseion (Pfeiffer 1949: 339);
Apollonius’ studies on Archilochus, cf. Pfeiffer (1968: 141), Fraser (1972: II 653, nn. 38‐9). On ancient
literary scholarship in general, see Pfeiffer (1968). More recently e.g. Bing (1993b: 619‐631), Rossi (2001:
86‐91); on the study of Homer’s texts, see Rengakos (1993; 1994; 2001).
23
practices, one of poets evaluating their predecessors as poets and one of scholars studying
and commenting upon poetry and poets of the past, flowed together.
1.3 Royal Patronage and “Cultural Memory”
The scholars and poets in the Library of Alexandria, who largely worked under the aegis of
royal patronage, thus seem emphatically engaged with their relation to the literature of the
Greek past. 11 Their attitude is probably representative of what happened across the other
royal libraries of this time. 12 How may this preoccupation be explained?
Alexandria was a relatively new city, which had been founded by the recently
deceased and immediately legendary Alexander the Great, whose aim had arguably been to
spread Greek culture throughout the known world. Being a harbor, Alexandria literally
looked towards Greece and the Mediterranean, at that time dominated by the Greeks, both
economically and culturally, rather than to the Egyptian mainland. 13 So, although her
inhabitants came from all over the world, the dominant culture was Greek. Yet, unlike many
of the earlier Greek settlements, Alexandria was not a colony tied to a single mother city by
established cultural traditions, legends, and habits. All of Greece was, in a sense, the mother
city of Alexandria. 14 She became the capital and seat of a new Macedonian royal house under
Ptolemy Soter, a former general of Alexander and one of the most successful of the successor
kings. Ptolemy’s ambition seems to have been to found a dynasty and to proclaim himself
11 On Hellenistic patronage see e.g. Fraser (1972: I, 305‐336), Bulloch et al. (1993), Weber (1993), Erskine
(1995: 38‐48), Strootman (2007: 189‐246). Callimachus and Apollonius enjoyed the royal support of the
Ptolemies, like Aratus and Euphorion at the court of Antiochus. It is likely that Theocritus, Posidippus
and Herondas (successfully or otherwise) sought some form of Ptolemaic patronage. In other cases
this is doubtful, e.g. Leonidas, Nossis.
12 The rivalry between the libraries of Alexandria and Pergamon was notorious, cf. Platthy (1968: 144‐
48).
13 Cf. Fraser (1972: I, 3‐37), cf. the later expression “Alexandria ad Aegyptum” (Alexandria near Egypt),
which implies it was not seen as an Egyptian city. Although, as underwater archaeology in the
Alexandrian harbor has shown, the Ptolemies did depict themselves in pharaonic guise for the benefit
of their Egyptian subjects, Alexandrian poetry (presumably aimed at a smaller, more elitist subculture
of Greeks) hardly even acknowledges the fact that Alexandria is situated in Egypt (and if it does,
Egyptians are named in a pejorative sense, cf. Theoc. Id. 15. 46‐50). However, for arguments in favor of
the presence of Egyptian cultural elements in Hellenistic poetry, see Stephens (2002: 235‐263); (2003,
passim); (2005: 229‐249), Hunter (2003). The main objection to this mode of reading is that it fails to
make clear who the intended beneficiaries of the alleged Egyptian elements in this poetry are and
why.
14 Cf. Fraser (1972: I, 3‐37), Weber (1993: 81).
24
the rightful inheritor of Alexander’s legacy. 15 It was presumably to this end that he took
charge of the embalmed body of Alexander and moved it from Memphis, the previous
capital of Egypt, to new‐founded Alexandria, much nearer to the old Greek world. The
guardianship over Alexander’s earthly remains symbolized the guardianship over his
imperial legacy. It is attractive to interpret Ptolemy Soter’s interest in preserving Hellenic
Museum, also as claims to the inheritance of Alexander, to Greek paideia. 16
His son Ptolemy Philadelphus, who had been educated by the learned scholar‐poet
Philitas, was an even more consummate lover of Greek literature, as the flowering of poetry
and scholarship under his reign testifies. By eagerly supporting the Library, the Museum and
its researchers, he continued what his father had begun and made Alexandria the intellectual
center of the Hellenistic world. 17
If the possession of the Greek literary heritage symbolically represented the
guardianship of Greek paideia, then it followed that its possessors were the inheritors of
Greek (cultural) hegemony. 18 Who mastered it and was able to deliver the right
interpretation or emulation of its texts was a true Greek. This sufficiently explains the
Ptolemies’ well‐documented interest in the learnedness they fostered in the Museum and the
Library and their willingness to inject considerable financial support into these institutions. 19
15 E.g. Id. 17.16‐32. Ptolemy Soter is sitting on Olympus together with Alexander, and both are
identified as great‐grandsons of Heracles. In the same poem, the emphasis is on the fact that Ptolemy
Philadelphus is so like his father (17.40‐44; 52‐57).
16 On the establishment of the Library and the Museum, see Pfeiffer (1968: 127), Fraser (1972: I, 321,ff.),
Weber (1993: 74‐82), Tanner (2006: 79‐95), Euseb. HE 5.8.11, Plut. Non posse suaviter vivi secundum
Epicurum 13.1095d. On the peripatetic influence of Demetrius of Phaleron on its organization: Plut. De
exilio 601; Reg. Apophth. 189d. On Aristotle as inspiring the Ptolemies to collect books, see Str. 13.1.54.
17 For a contemporary reference to Ptolemaic patronage of literature, cf. e.g. Theoc. Id. 17.111‐116.
Other poems clearly written with an eye to Ptolemaic patronage are e.g. Herond. Mim. 1, Call. Aetia,
Theoc. Id. 14, 15, 17, perhaps also 24 and 18, cf. Griffiths (1979: 51‐107) and a number of the epigrams
by Posidippus on Ptolemaic monuments and victories in horse races.
18 Cf. DNP s.v. Mouseion: “In the Hellenistic context, the generous patronage [sc. of literature,
scholarship and science] of a monarch became a manifestation of his royal authority.” See on this topic
e.g. Erskine (1995: 38‐48). Further references and bibliography in Fraser (1972: I, 305‐336), Weber
(1993), and Strootman (2007: 202‐216).
19 Cf. e.g. Timon SH 786 (cf. Ch. 4.1), Philostrat. Soph. 1.22.3 sketches the same image for the time of
Hadrian, saying that the Museum constituted a “banquet hall comprising the most eminent guests
among the Greeks.” Several other anecdotes reflect the kings’ lively interest in scholarly activities
(Ath. 11,493e‐494b; 12,552c). The ties between court and Museum were close: the princes’ tutors
usually were the directors of the Library as well (cf. P. Oxy. 1241 for a list of names). For the physical
25
Naturally, this environment left its mark upon the poetry and poetic concerns of the
poets affiliated to such institutions. The Greek literary heritage was emphatically their
domain and point of reference. 20 Indeed, they were presumably warmly encouraged to
produce new poetry that reflected (on) the past splendors of Greek culture. It is therefore no
surprise if Hellenistic poets stressed continuity with their poetical forebears rather than
discontinuity. 21 It follows, then, that the characteristics they emphasized in the
representation of their predecessors both reveal something about the way they saw their
poetic past and the way they (wished to) see themselves. Ancient Greek poetry provided
them with a window and a mirror, an object to reflect upon and reflect oneself in at the same
time.
It is enlightening to relate this Hellenistic, and more in particular Alexandrian,
interest in the Greek Cultural legacy to Jan Assmann’s theories on the concept of “Cultural
Memory.” 22 According to Assmann, social groups, especially when severed from a
continuous cultural past, have a tendency to create or reinforce their own identity by means
of a collective memory determined by the consciously or unconsciously posed question:
“What is it that we as a group should remember?” In answering this question, they select
and create distinctive memories of a shared past to which certain events and texts are central.
These are constructed as Erinnerungsfiguren (i.e., symbolical commemorative tropes) with
sacred, religious, or festive characteristics, such as a calendar with sacred holidays or a
festival commemorating the foundation of a city. Ancient texts and the societal values
deriving from them, such as the Torah, Bible, Homer’s Iliad and Odyssey and Hesiod’s
Theogony, play a great role in such collective memory. The fact that the interpretation or
significance of such ancient texts and festivals often is no longer self‐evident calls for
specialized exegetes who assume responsibility for the cultural heritage. These may be poets,
priests, sages, scholars, teachers or the like. They influence the collective cultural memory
through Textpflege and Sinnpflege, the establishment and interpretation of canonical texts and
connection between Museum, Library and the court, cf. Str. 17.1.8, who claims these institutions were
part of the royal grounds. See further Pfeiffer (1968: 127), Weber (1993: 87‐90).
20 Cf. e.g. Callimachus’ Πίνακες; Tzetzes names Alexander Aetolus, Lycophron and Eratosthenes as
working in the Library (Prol. ad Arist. Pb 119).
21 Cf. Fantuzzi and Hunter (2004: vii‐viii); contrast e.g. Bing (1988), Radke (2007) who argue that the
Hellenistic poets felt a distinct rupture with previous Greek literary culture.
22 See for a synopsis Assmann (1997: introduction).
26
the control and interpretation of ritual. This is similar to what was done in the Alexandrian
Library. The texts studied and created here provided both the court and the scholar‐poets
with important items with which to construct their identities and celebrate and justify their
Greekness. References to the poetry of the past might therefore appeal to a shared
knowledge and thus create a feeling of belonging. But, as we shall see, they often also took
the form of allusion to obscure facts and complex tongue‐in‐cheek appropriation of literary
tradition, aimed at providing only those in the know with a sense of belonging to an
intellectual elite. Greek literature thus became both a common ground and a playground of
the literati.
1.4 Which Poets and what Past?
If Hellenistic monarchs and the poets in their service were occupied with the intellectual
tradition of the great Greek past, who did they focus on and how did they view them? It is
generally believed that, to a Hellenistic scholar looking at the past, a kind of watershed
would seem to have occurred in the fifth century, dividing the poetry modern scholarship
considers “archaic” (broadly speaking, up to the century) from the “Atheno‐centric” (i.e.,
classical) poetry of the fifth century. For one thing, Hellenistic poets did not write for the
benefit of a democratic polis, but for that of elitist royal courts. The poetic diversity at these
courts will moreover have resembled that of the Archaic age rather than that of the classical
era:
The triumph of Athenian culture could have been seen as the death knell for the rich
tapestry of poetic forms to be found in the centuries before that triumph. (...) The
variety of geographical centres for poetry in the Hellenistic world, the ever increasing
importance of patronage and the burgeoning number of poetic festivals, competitions
and opportunities for epideixis in the Hellenistic age may well have seemed more like
the picture of poetic production which emerged from archaic texts than the rather
monolithic image projected by the later fifth century in which the predominance in
the field of Attic tragedy and comedy drove other high poetry from the field.
(Hunter, 1996: 3) 23
23 Cf. Cameron (1992: 305‐312). Still, this representation needs some nuance: although the fifth‐century
Athenian cultural dominance may look monolithic to the modern eye, the Hellenistic Greeks must
have been aware that various literary cultures had existed at royal courts in the classical era too. Hiero
I of Syracuse commissioned poetry from Pindar, Bacchylides, and Aeschylus; Archelaus of Macedon
apparently had ties with Euripides. Drama, moreover, was not the only viable form of poetry, even if
it is the form best preserved.
27
Indeed, as their poetry shows, it was the archaic, or pre‐Athenian age the Hellenistic poets
looked to principally. Even so, they must have realized that this era also presented important
differences with their own poetic practices. For one thing, in the days of ancient (choral)
lyric, poetry, melody, and dance had been an indissoluble complex, as the complicated
meters and stanzaic structures attest. This had gradually changed; music and poetry had
become increasingly separate areas. 24 Predominant in Hellenistic poetry were the recitative
elegiac distich, iambus and hexameter, even if Callimachus and Theocritus occasionally
imitated the complex meters of archaic lyric. 25 This means that the compositional practice of
a Hellenistic poet was more limited than that of an archaic lyric poet: texts as such were
much more the central concern of the former than of the latter.
showed more resemblance to the Hellenistic mode of working than classical, in particular
Athenian, poetry did. This might explain why most poets represented in the Hellenistic
epigrams, which form the focus of this chapter, belong to the “pre‐Athenian” age. There is
also a number of epigrams on poets belonging to a more recent past, the fourth century,
when literary sensibilities had presumably evolved in the direction of those found in
Hellenistic poetry. But, as was to be expected, Athenian poets of the fifth century are
underrepresented. 26 (For the corpus of the epigrams discussed, see the Appendix.)
1.5 Poetical Predecessors in Epigram
From a literary‐historical point of view, the early Hellenistic period could be considered
paradoxical. On the one hand, the giants of Greek literature such as Homer, Archilochus, and
24 As early as the late fifth century, there was a gradual dissolution of song culture, which was
replaced in part by a book culture and in part by a music culture dominated by virtuoso musicians;
the development is discussed by Herington (1985).
25 Theoc. Id. 28, 29, 30; Call. fr. 226, 227, 228, 229 Pf. Papyrus finds of the third century attest that
musical notation was not the default expectation in the preservation of archaic lyrical poetry, cf.
Hunter (1996: 5, n. 19). For a recent overview and discussion of the material, see Prauscello (2006).
26 Dramatists of the Hellenistic age may of course have had an interest in the dramatic productions of
the fifth century, although no epigrams of their hand survive, cf. Fantuzzi and Hunter (2004: 404‐437).
Epigrams discussing Athenian playwrights are AP 7.410 (Thespis); 7.411 (Aeschylus); 7.37, 7.21, 7.22,
(Sophocles); 7.46 (Euripides); 13.29 (Cratinus). It should be remarked that the first three form part of a
series, written by Dioscorides, who is a generation or two later than the avant‐garde Hellenistic poets
such as Callimachus, and has a predilection for antiquarianism.
28
Pindar were geographically, linguistically and chronologically remote from the age of the
Alexandrian Library. Yet, the texts and biographical data of these poets had never been
studied so closely and documented so professionally, made available to so many people or
preserved for future generations in such a secure way as precisely in this age. 27 The two sides
of this paradox are visible in the epigrams written in this period. Epitaphs or dedications on
statues of predecessors who had been dead for hundreds of years became popular, testifying
to the perception that the literary past existed as a kind of monument, something dead, yet
alive: for these epitaphs on long‐dead poets actually demonstrate the vivid interest and
admiration they still aroused. 28 Another aspect of this admiration of the past was the revival
of dead poets through ethopoiia, allowing them to speak for themselves in new poetry. This
might be interpreted as a metaphor for the fact that the literary heritage was so close to the
Hellenistic poets that it was in fact internalized, digested, and incorporated into their own
poetry. They spoke with the voices of the dead, or vice versa (cf. also Chapter 2).
From a literary point of view, it is easy to see the attraction of such epitaphs and
inscriptions. An epitaph is the ideal place to express a brief and final verdict about an
individual’s personality and life; an inscription on the base of a statue likewise furnishes
concise and essential information to the viewer about the subject depicted. In both cases, the
challenge is to condense the characteristics of the poet in question as wittily and recognizably
as possible.
From the fifth century BCE onwards, such literary epigrams had already been written
in books rather than on stone. They presented the fictitious variations on the original
dedications and epitaphs. By the Hellenistic period, epigram had become a popular literary
genre, improvised at symposia and collected, or even written directly, in books. 29 That the
epitaphs and purported inscriptions to be discussed here were of an exclusively literary
nature is reasonably certain. As Peter Bing argues, it is the exception rather than the rule that
27 On the greatness of the Alexandrian Library: Ath. 5.203d‐e; the Letter of Aristeas claims that
Demetrius of Phaleron began with 200.000 scrolls and hoped to see the collection grow to at least
500.000; similarly Gell. NA 7.17.3. By the time the library was burnt down in 48/47 BCE by Caesarean
troops, Ammianus Marcellinus claims 700.000 scrolls were lost in the fire (22.16.13), although Seneca
estimates that there were only 400.000 (Tranq. 9.5). See in general Parsons (1967), Canfora (1989),
McLeod (2004).
28 Cf. Bing (1988, passim).
29 A parallel development is that of erotic epigram out of skolia (drinking songs) and erotic elegies
originally orally improvised and recited at symposia. See on the topic e.g. Reitzenstein (1893),
Wilamowitz (1924: I, 130‐1), Gutzwiller (1998), Fantuzzi and Hunter (2004: 283‐291).
29
genuine inscriptions were cited on papyrus in antiquity. 30 This means that epigrams that
claim to be inscriptions are really literary, whether referring to actual monuments or statues
or not.
Three topics frequently recur in these succinct characterizations of ancient poets: the
description of poetic practices (singing versus writing), the material form texts take when
conserved on scrolls (e.g. in the Alexandrian Library), and the reconstruction of the character
of an ancient poet as based on his writings. These items will be addressed in the following
sections.
1.5.1 Singing and Writing
If Hellenistic poets argued from their own practice, they would no doubt have imagined
their predecessors as writers. Nevertheless, the ancient texts they studied may have
suggested otherwise. What can epigrams tell us about this? In the first place, the Muses,
originally patronesses who guaranteed the knowledge of the oral poet, are of great
importance in the descriptions of poets of the past in Hellenistic epigram. 31 In these
epigrams, however, this presence of the Muse does not symbolize the traditional divine
guarantee of the factual knowledge of poets; rather, it provides an emphasis on the (divine)
charm and excellence of their poetry as “works of art,” as expressions like “Cecropian star of
the tragic Muse” and “holding the brightest torch of the Muses,” suggest. 32 We could say
that the Muses are used as a kind of shorthand to denote that the subject of the epigram is
poetry.
When it comes to naming the profession of the poet, Hellenistic poets seldom call
their predecessors ποιητής (“maker; poet,” an expression which connotes writing as an
30 Bing (2002: 38‐66); Obbink agrees: “The burden of proof lies on the shoulders of those who would
claim that any of the epigrams that purport to be inscribed on an object were actually so inscribed, to
show that they were ever actually cited from such a source.” (2004: 19)
31 The Muses are named in the following Hellenistic epigrams in combination with the poets stated
between brackets: AP 7.1, 7.2, 7.5, 9.24 (Homer); 7.9, 7.10 (Orpheus); 7.12, 7.13, 9.190 (Erinna); 7.19,
7.709 (Alcman); 7.21, 7.22, 7.37 (Sophocles); 7.25, 7.31 (Anacreon); 7.35 (Pindar); 7.55 (Hesiod); 7.407,
9.189 (Sappho); 7.664 (Archilochus); 9.63 (Antimachus); 9.184, 9.571 (nine lyric poets); 12.168
(combination of poets).
32 AP 7.21, Simias on Sophocles; AP 9.24, Leonidas on Homer, respectively.
33 Cf. Ford (1981) on the development, connotations and use of the term ποιητής.
34 For a detailed overview of the distribution of terms indicating singing and writing, see Appendix.
30
question how they envisaged the poetic practices of composition and performance of their
ancient predecessors. Did they consciously ask questions about the mode of poetic
composition at all? The first fact to be noted in this context is that it is mostly the archaic lyric
poets who are usually described as “singers/bards.” This is easily understandable: these
poets described their own activities in terms of singing, their actual mode of performance.
The stanzaic structure of their compositions would have revealed to the Hellenistic poets
that they had indeed been performed in song with musical accompaniment. That these songs
had at some point been written down is clearly not the focus of interest in epigram. It was
probably assumed that this had been done by the lyric poets themselves.
It is far harder to determine whether Hellenistic poets thought an epic poet like
Homer composed in writing or orally, instigated by the Muse. If they looked at the contents
of Homeric epic, they might have come to the latter conclusion. The description of the art of
the ἀοιδοί Demodocus and Phemius, who were believed to constitute self‐representations of
Homer, does not reveal any connection with writing. 35 Yet, the immense Iliad and Odyssey,
with their intricate and subtle compositions, had existed as literary texts at least since the
Pisistratean recension (sixth century BCE) and were extensively analyzed by Hellenistic
scholars. How did they imagine these texts had come into being, as oral or written
compositions? 36 Did they even ask this question? It seems doubtful. The following epigram
description of Homer without any evident feeling of contradiction:
Τοῦ Σαμίου πόνος εἰμὶ δόμωι ποτὲ θεῖον ἀοιδόν
δεξαμένου, κλείω δ᾿ Εὔρυτον ὅσσ᾿ ἔπαθεν
καὶ ξανθήν Ἰόλειαν· ῾Ομήρειον δὲ καλεῦμαι
γράμμα. Κρεωφύλωι, Ζεῦ φίλε, τοῦτο μέγα. (AP 7.80)
I am the work of the man from Samos, who once received the divine bard in his
home, and I sing of Eurytus’ hardships and blonde Ioleia and I am called a writing of
Homer. For Creophylus, dear Zeus, that is grand.
35 Writing hardly figures at all in the epics. Of course, Hellenistic scholars may have argued that the
Iliad and the Odyssey represented a world that was a distant past already to their composer. This could
have explained the absence of writing to them.
36 Evidently, there could be a middle way, in which improvised texts were dictated, gathered and
perhaps in some way revised, but this idea is not testified before Cicero, so it is doubtful whether it
occurred to Hellenistic poets. Cf. Havelock (1986: 12).
31
In the first line, Homer is referred to as θεῖος ἀοιδός (divine bard). The bestower of this
epithet, as the ancient reader was expected to gather from hints (2‐3), is the (now lost) epic
poem Oechalias Halosis. This work was wrongly ascribed to Homer (3‐4) in Callimachus’
time, as he claims. Instead, Callimachus thinks the true author of the poem was a certain
Creophylus of Samos, a contemporary of Homer. According to the epigram, Creophylus had
only received Homer in his home; apparently this has somehow caused the false ascription. 37
The last phrase of the epigram contains the literary pointe: it is an honor (too great an honor
even, perhaps) for a work of Creophylus to be called a writing of Homer.
The Oechalias Halosis is referred to as a γράμμα. 38 This seems to imply that
Callimachus regards writing as the normal practice of Homer and his contemporaries,
whereas he also calls Homer “divine bard.” 39 Apparently, the question of writing versus oral
composition is simply not considered relevant. Despite the cultural shift from orality to
literacy and all it entailed for the preservation and availability of knowledge, 40 neither this
nor any other epigram reveals an awareness of a possible opposition between oral
performance (or composition) and writing. They appear alongside each other, referring to
the same poets without contradiction. This epigrammatic practice is comparable with the
paradoxical Hellenistic way of portraying Homer (who, as tradition had it, was blind!) in
statuary as reading from a scroll. 41 Writing was clearly the default expectation in poetic
composition and was unconsciously projected back upon the poets of the past, even if they
were called singers.
1.5.2 The Text as Monument
37 Cf. Suda s.v. Κρεώφυλος, and the comments of Gow and Page (1965: II, ad loc.).
38 For the meaning of γράμμα indicating a work composed in writing, cf. AP 9.598 (Pisander); AP
9.184 (Anacreon) and LSJ s.v. III, 3, although here, interestingly, no references to works of poetry are
given. Hesiod is portrayed as writing in Hermesian. fr. 7.24‐5 Powell.
39 For Homer as an oral bard cf. AP 7.1; Theoc. Id. 7, 16, 22; Hesiod was apparently also envisaged as a
singer (AP 7.55).
40 On this shift and its meaning for classical and in particular Hellenistic literary culture, see Havelock
(1963; 1986) and Bing (1988).
41 Zanker suggests that this is a projection of the activities of the contemporary Homeric scholars onto
Homer himself (1995: 166, fig. 88c). The question he does not raise is whether they would have been
aware of this fact.
32
Whether referred to as singers or writers, the emphasis in Hellenistic epigrams on dead poets
is specifically on the enduring quality or fame of their achievements, 42 through which an
author is sometimes even claimed to live on eternally. 43 A key issue connected with this
theme is the material form of the achievements: in a number of cases, this is explicitly a
written text on a scroll, not mere “song.” This contrasts with the way in which archaic poets
usually put immaterial fame in song (κλέος) over material monuments as a guarantee for
immortality. 44 It seems that, through the widespread materialization of song in its written
form in the Hellenistic age, the ideas of immaterial fame in song versus a material monument
occasionally merge in the concept of the immortality of the words of a poem written on a
scroll.
Apart from actual poetic compositions (i.e., preserved works of the literary tradition),
literary “inventions” (of a new poetic form or genre) ascribed to legendary inventors (the
topos of the πρῶτος εὑρετής) could also grant some kind of immortality, usually of a vaguer
and more disputable kind. To illustrate this, an epitaph for Orpheus (AP 7.9 Damagetus), the
pre‐historical and legendary singer/musician, whose legacy was disputed, may be compared
with an epitaph on the historical dramatist Sophocles (AP 7.21 Simias), whose works
indisputably survived. The following epigram describes the grave of Orpheus:
᾿Ορφέα Θρηικίηισι παρὰ προμολῆισιν Ὀλύμπου
τύμβος ἔχει, Μούσης υἱέα Καλλιόπης,
ὧι δρύες οὐκ ἀπίθησαν, ὁτῶι συνάμ᾿ ἕσπετο πέτρη
ἄψυχος θηρῶν θ´ ὑλονόμων ἀγέλα,
ὅς ποτε καὶ τελετὰς μυστηρίδας εὕρετο Βάκχου
καὶ στίχον ἡρώιωι ζεύκτον ἔτευξε ποδί,
ὅς καὶ ἀμειλίκτοιο βαρὺ Κλυμένοιο νόημα
καὶ τὸν ἀκήλητον θυμὸν ἒθελξε λύραι. (AP 7.9)
A tomb in the Thracian foothills of Olympus contains Orpheus, son of the Muse
Calliope, whom the oaks did not disobey, whom the lifeless rocks and the tribe of the
wood‐dwelling animals followed willingly, who once invented the mystic rituals of
Bacchus and joined the stichic line to the heroic meter, who swayed both the grim
will and unchangeable heart of inexorable Clymenus with his lyre.
42 E.g. AP 7.2, 7.5, 9.24 (Homer); 7.54 (Hesiod); 9.63 (Antimachus); 7.664 (Archilochus); Ath. 13.696, AP
7.407 (Sappho).
43 E.g. AP 7.12 (Erinna); 7.25 (Anacreon); cf. more indirectly AP 7.408, 7.536, 13.3 (Hipponax). The fact
that even in death Hipponax is dangerous implies that his legacy is immortal.
44 E.g. Simon. PMG 531 (on the dead of Thermopylae), on which see Ford (2002: 105‐111); see for
further instances in archaic lyric Nünlist (1998: 115).
33
The poem lists Orpheus’ accomplishments and achievements: he was able to charm nature
and is called the inventor of Bacchic mysteries and of “the line that was added to the
hexameter” (i.e., the pentameter, significantly placed in the pentameter itself), a novel claim.
His powers are emphasized by the choice of objects of enchantment (oaks, rocks, and wild
animals with their topical connotations of immobility, toughness, and savageness) and the
adjectives describing them. 45 The list ends with Orpheus’ victory in swaying the adamant
will of Hades (Clymenus) by his music. Significantly, however, no immortality is granted to
Orpheus by virtue of any surviving works. 46 This suggests an ironic contrast between the
great power he possessed when living (he even persuaded the god of the underworld) and
its complete annulment at his death. The attribution of the pentameter and the institution of
the Bacchic mysteries constitute a claim to remembrance, but Orpheus’ enchanting songs are
lost, while only an (imaginary) tomb remains. However, it should be noted that this
description of the tomb is written in elegiac distichs, the meter Orpheus had invented, so
that, paradoxically, he lives on in poetry after all, if not his own.
The following epigram by Simias, describing the tomb of Sophocles, provides a clear
contrast to the vague description of Orpheus’ possible legacy:
Τόν σε χοροῖς μέλψαντα Σοφοκλέα, παῖδα Σοφίλλου,
τὸν τραγικῆς Μούσης ἀστέρα Κεκρόπιον,
πολλάκις ὃν θυμέλῃσι καὶ ἐν σκηνῇσι τεθηλὼς
βλαισὸς Ἀχαρνίτης κισσὸς ἔρεψε κόμην,
τύμβος ἔχει καὶ γῆς ὀλίγον μέρος, ἀλλ’ ὁ περισσὸς
αἰὼν ἀθανάτοις δέρκεται ἐν σελίσιν. (AP 7.21)
You who sang in the choruses, Sophocles, son of Sophillus, you who shone as the
Cecropian star of the Muse, who were so often crowned with winding Acharnian ivy
in the orchestra and on the stage, a tomb now holds you, and but a little piece of the
earth, but the rest of the ages sees you in your immortal papyrus‐columns. 47
45 Cf. A.R. Arg. 1.26‐28. The epithet ἀκηλήτος is notable, as κηλεῖν (to enchant) is frequently found as
a metaphor to describe the effects of poetry on an audience. Cf. Nünlist (1998: 132‐3).
46 There are other epitaphs in which there is no explicit mention of works, while Hellenistic poets did
know them (e.g. AP 7.1 Homer; 7.55 Hesiod). However, the point in Damagetus’ epitaph depends on
the irony that Orpheus was so powerful (because of his music) during his life, while after death he is
gone and all his music with him. Moreover, unlike Hesiod’s and Homer’s works, the authenticity of
any legacy of Orpheus was doubted in antiquity, cf. Ch 3.2.
47 For the problems of interpretation, see Gow and Page (1965: II, ad loc.). That this is the approximate
meaning of the passage is however quite certain.
34
The poem laments the fact that a great man like Sophocles should have gone the way of all
flesh and died (1‐5). 48 Up to this point, the scheme is quite similar to that of the epigram
describing the tomb of Orpheus: the poet was exceptional during his life, but now he is dead
and gone. However, the pointe of this poem is that Sophocles’ fate differs from that of other
humans because of his literary achievement. Sophocles lives on thanks to the preservation of
his writings; the epigram itself forms living proof of the immortalizing powers of the written
word.
A comparable idea, but elaborated with a remarkably different emphasis, is found in
Posidippus’ epigram on the hetaera Doricha, a contemporary of Sappho:
Δωρίχα, ὀστέα μὲν σὰ πάλαι κόνις ἦν ὅ τε δέσμος 49
χαίτης ἥ τε μύρων ἔκπνοος ἀμπεχόνη,
ἧι ποτε τὸν χαρίεντα περιστέλλουσα Χάραξον
σύγχρους ὀρθρινῶν ἥψαο κισσυβίων·
Σαπφῶιαι δὲ μένουσι φίλης ἔτι καὶ μενέουσιν
ὠιδῆς αἱ λευκαὶ φθεγγόμεναι σελίδες
οὔνομα σὸν μακαριστόν, ὃ Ναύκρατις ὧδε φυλάξει
ἔστ’ ἂν ἴηι Νείλου ναῦς ἐφ’ ἁλὸς πελάγη. (Ath. 13.696/GP XVII/122 AB)
Doricha, your bones were dust long ago, and the band of your hair and your
perfume‐breathing shawl, wherewith you once wrapped the charming Charaxus,
skin to skin, until you took hold of the morning cups. But the white columns of
Sappho’s lovely ode are still here and they will go on celebrating your most fortunate
name, which Naucratis will thus treasure as long as ships sail from the Nile on the
waves of the sea. (transl. and text Austin and Bastianini)
In this poem, it is not the death of the poet that is contrasted with the immortality of her
poetical legacy, but that of the subject of her poetry, Doricha. Athenaeus, who preserved the
epigram, explains that Doricha enticed Sappho’s brother, Charaxus, when he was sailing to
Naucratis in Egypt for business. He claims that Sappho speaks ill of Doricha for preying on
Charaxus’ purse. 50 Surprisingly, there is no sign in the epigram of Sappho’s negative
treatment of Doricha, such as can indeed be found in what is left of her work. It merely
claims that Doricha’s fortunate name has been immortalized by Sappho’s “white columns,”
48 This is a recurrent theme, cf. e.g. AP 7.1, 7.2 (Homer).
49 The MS reading of this first line is problematic: Δωρίχα, ὀστέα μὲν σ´ ἁπαλὰ κοιμήσατο δεσμῶν.
Austin’s text (with emendations of Casaubon, Jacobs and Meineke) is printed here.
50 Ath. 13.69.1: διὰ τῆς ποιήσεως διαβάλλει ὡς πολλὰ τοῦ Χαράξου νοσφισαμένην. (She slanders
[Doricha] in her poetry as having stolen a lot of Charaxus’ possessions). This is confirmed by Sappho
fr. 15b Voigt and by Hdt. 2.132, where Doricha is however called “Rhodopis.”
35
which, to one unaware of the contents of Sappho’s poetry looks like a compliment. 51
However, on closer inspection, the treatment of Doricha in the epigram itself could be called
scathing. Posidippus describes how all her physical charm (implied in the images of the hair‐
ribbon, the fragrant shawl, and the skin‐to‐skin contact with which she enticed Charaxus), on
which her fame depended, has disappeared.
The pointe of the epigram is therefore that immortality can only be achieved by
(becoming the subject of) poetry, no matter how powerful charm may be–and no matter
what this poetry precisely states. Dead as she is, Doricha has therefore become doubly
immortal: once in Sappho’s poetry and now again in Posidippus’ epigram. 52 This is a double‐
edged compliment: on the one hand, the mere fact that Sappho names Doricha could be seen
as an honor. The mention of Doricha by Sappho in itself demonstrates the once‐considerable
power of her charm; it was great enough to make Sappho seriously worry about the fate of
her brother. 53 But Sappho also gave Doricha a negative reputation; now Posidippus refers
back to Sappho’s judgement and moreover confirms Doricha’s irrevocable death. There is
some irony in immortalizing someone in such a way. 54
A complex variation on the theme of enduring remembrance in written poetry and
the interplay between fame, memory, and material monuments is seen in Callimachus’ Aetia,
fr. 64 Pf. (Selpulchrum Simonidis), a fragment that alludes to the form and conventions of
sepulchral epigrams. 55 In it, the dead poet Simonides complains that a certain Phoenix, a
Sicilian general, had his grave at Acragas razed and used the stone to fortify the city walls:
Οὐδ’ ἄ]ν τοι Καμάρινα τόσον κακὸν ὁκκόσον ἀ[ν]δρός
κινη]θεὶς ὁσίου τύμβος ἐπικρεμάσαι∙
καὶ γ]ὰ̣ρ̣ ἐμόν κοτε σῆμα, τό μοι πρὸ πόληος ἔχ[ευ]αν
51 Gabathuler (1937: 51‐2) claims that the epigram was meant as a real and therefore honorary
inscription for a monument in Naucratis, glossing over the negative tone of Sappho’s writings on
purpose, cf. also Gow and Page (1965: II, 498).
52 Ath. 13.69.15 claims Posidippus moreover devoted much attention to her in his lost Aethiopia, which
may have been an elegiac or epic poem. This does not necessarily imply a positive evaluation.
53 As Rosenmeyer (1997: 132) suggests, the epigram may also play on the fact that Egypt, in particular
Naucratis, was an important export‐centre of papyri. Perhaps the ships sailing down the Nile in the
final lines were therefore ships laden with papyrus, on which new editions of Sappho’s poetry might
appear, celebrating/reviling Doricha.
54 Cf. Theogn. 237‐54: Cyrnus receives fame by being named in Theognis’ poetry; yet, Theognis accuses
him in the same poem of being unfaithful. This reputation will therefore constitute his immortal fame
(or rather notoriety). Cf. Helen foreseeing that she and Paris will be subject of song for generations to
come, because of the evil fate Zeus has given them (Il. 6.358).
55 Cf. Harder (1998: 95‐115).
36
Ζῆν’] Ἀκραγαντῖνοι Ξείνι[ο]ν̣ ἁ̣ζόμενοι,
ἶφι κ]ατ’ οὖν ἤρειψεν ἀνὴρ κακός, εἴ τιν’ ἀκούει[ς
Φοίνικ]α̣ πτόλιος σχέτλιον ἡγεμόνα∙
πύργῳ] δ’ ἐγκατέλε̣ξ̣ε̣ν ἐμὴν λίθον οὐδὲ τὸ γράμμα
ᾐδέσθη τὸ λέγον τόν [μ]ε Λεω̣πρέπεος
κεῖσθαι̣ Κήϊον ἄνδρα τὸν ἱερόν, ὃς τὰ περισσά
καὶ] μ̣νήμην πρῶτος ὃς ἐφρασάμην,
οὐδ’ ὑμέας, Πολύδευκες, ὑπέτρεσεν, οἵ με μελάθρου
μέλλοντος πίπτειν ἐκτὸς ἔθεσθέ κοτε
δαιτυμόνων ἄπο μοῦνον, ὅτε Κραννώνιος αἰαῖ
ὤλ̣ισθε̣ν μεγάλους οἶκος ἐπὶ Σκοπάδας. 56 (fr. 64 Pf. Selpulchrum Simonidis)
Not even if you were to disturb Camarina would you incur such a grave danger as in
disturbing the grave of a holy man. 57 For my own grave, which the Acragantines had
erected to honor Zeus Xeinios, was once demolished with brute force by an evil man;
you may have heard of Phoenix, the pitiless general of that city. He embedded my
stone into the fortifications and ignored the inscription that says that I, the son of
Leoprepes, a citizen of Ceos, lie here, a genius, and the first to invent the art of
memory. 58 Nor did he fear you both, Polydeuces, who once, when the roof was about
to collapse, made me go outside, the only one of the banquet’s guests, when the
Crannonian home, alas, collapsed on the great Scopadae.
As noted, the fragment employs the characteristic topoi of epitaphs, in that it states name and
patronymic, place of origin and exceptional achievements (8‐10). At the same time, this alerts
the reader to a problem: the grave is gone and the poet who lay buried under it is dead, so
how can he be speaking here, and from where does his voice emerge? This is not an
inscription that purports to speak in the voice of the deceased, 59 since the inscription itself is
gone. The odd truth is that the dead poet Simonides actually speaks about the disappearance
of the monument that was to keep his remembrance alive. 60 The passage thus delivers a
56 For lines 10‐14, cf. Cic. De Or. II 352, cf. Ch. 2.3.
57 A reference to the proverb “Disturb not Camarina,” cf. Pfeiffer (1949: ad loc.): the inhabitants of
Camarina had received an oracle forbidding them to relocate the homonymous lake near their city;
else, they would risk utter destruction. Presumably, in the rest of fr. 64, Simonides narrated how the
removal of his tomb had similar or worse consequences for the Sicilian general Phoenix. This Phoenix
is unknown, as is the attack that brought him to embed the tomb of Simonides in the walls of Acragas.
Perhaps Φοίνιξ is a name based on a misunderstood reference to the Phoenicians, who repeatedly
invaded Sicily, cf. D’Alessio (1996: 470).
58 Cf. the intriguing fr. 4 (West): μνήμην δ’ οὔτινά φημι Σιμωνίδηι ἰσοφαρίζειν, / ὀγδωκονταέτει
παιδὶ Λεωπρέπεος. (I say that no one may rival Simonides, the eighty‐year‐old son of Leoprepes, in
memory).
59 Cf. e.g. AP 7.28 (Anacreon).
60 For a similar paradox, cf. AP 7.479, the epitaph of the philosopher Heraclitus by Theodoridas of
Samos. This forms an example of the self‐conscious literariness of Hellenistic epigram by proclaiming
the fact that it is a fictitious inscription: it has been so worn away as to become unreadable.
37
sophisticated paradoxical comment on the power of poetry and on Simonides’ opinions
about the superior conserving power of poetry over material objects.
To better appreciate the intricacies of this paradox, some facts about Simonides need
to be called to mind. In the first place, this poet was famous in antiquity for his epitaphs,
encomia, and dirges on the (heroic) dead, by which he ensured their immortal κλέος
one of Simonides’ more famous poems, his commentary on an alleged epitaph of King
Midas. In this epitaph, a bronze statue makes the following claim:
χαλκῆ παρθένος εἰμί, Μίδα δ᾿ἐπὶ σήματι κεῖμαι.
ἔστ᾿ ἄν ὕδωρ τε νάηι καὶ δένδρεα μακρὰ τεθήληι,
ἠέλιός τ´ ἀνιὼν λάμπηι λαμπρά τε σελήνη,
[καὶ ποταμοί γε ῥέωσιν, ἀνακλύζηι δὲ θάλασσα,]
αὐτοῦ τῆιδε μένουσα πολυκλαύτωι ἐπὶ τύμβωι
ἀγγελέω παριοῦσι, Μίδας ὅτι τῆιδε τέθαπται. (Diog. Laert. 1.89‐90) 62
I am a bronze maiden and sit on Midas’ grave. As long as water will flow and tall
trees shall grow and the sun rise and shine, like the gleaming moon, [and rivers shall
stream and the sea break at the shore,] I will remain here on this much‐lamented
tomb and announce to the passers‐by that Midas lies buried here.
Simonides considered this claim unacceptable and he countered it in his own poetry, with a
pun (μωροῦ φωτὸς ἅδε βουλά, “this is the thought of a foolish man”) on the name of the
alleged composer of the epitaph, one of the canonical seven sages, Cleobulus (lit. “of the
famed counsel”):
τίς κεν αἰνήσειε νόωι πίσυνος Λίνδου ναέταν Κλεόβουλον
ἀενάοις ποταμοῖς ἀνθεσί τ´ εἰαρινοῖς
ἀελίου τε φλογὶ χρυσέας τε σελάνας
καὶ θαλασσαίαισι δίνηις ἀντιθέντα μένος στάλας;
ἅπαντα γάρ ἐστι θεῶν ἥσσω· λίθον δὲ
καὶ βρότεοι παλάμαι θραύοντι· μωροῦ φωτὸς ἅδε βουλά. (PMG 581)
Who in his right mind would praise that inhabitant of Lindus, Cleobulus, who set
against the everstreaming rivers and the flowers of spring and the force of the sun
and the golden moon and the eddies of the sea the force of stone? For everything
must yield to the gods; and stone may even be broken by the hands of mortals. That
is the thought of a foolish man.
61 Cf. e.g. Theoc. Id. 16, Ch. 2.3.
62 Pl. Phaedr. 264d preserves a slightly different version.
38
It is plausible that through his denial that monuments of stone may endure Simonides
implies that poetry lasts longer. 63 The claim of the bronze maiden was in all likelihood
known to him only as a poem, whether written down or circulating in oral form; he himself
probably never saw the actual grave of Midas (which would have been in Phrygia), complete
with its bronze maiden. Indeed, it is questionable whether such a grave of the legendary king
actually ever existed, and, more to the point, whether it still existed in the time of Simonides.
If not, Simonides’ poem becomes an ironic comment on the fact that the Midas epitaph was a
paradox in the form he knew it: it claimed immortality for a monument that was not (or no
longer) anywhere to be seen. Thus, it had already proven its own claim false and shown that
poetry was more powerful than a material monument.
Presumably, Callimachus was aware of Simonides’ musings on the subject of the
perishability of graves and monuments. He may have particularly enjoyed the irony in
Simonides’ attack of the Midas epitaph, 64 since disconnectedness of an inscription from its
original monument likewise forms the departing point for relating the story of how
Simonides’ own grave was demolished and how the physical monument for his existence
thus ceased to exist, inscription and all. In an ironic way, Simonides’ attack on the claim that
physical monuments outlast everything is vindicated by Callimachus. At the same time, the
paradoxical situation imagined also forms a tribute to the lasting fame of Simonides’ poetry
as such. Simonides’ own fame outlives the physical monument that was intended to keep it
alive. This enables him to speak in Callimachus’ poetry about the disappearance of his own
grave hundreds of years after his actual demise. The fame of the poet and his grave are not
forever lost; they still exist in poetry, only, paradoxically, not Simonides’ own. 65
63 Cf. Snell (1938: 175), Segal (1998: 134). Ford (2002: 105‐107) refers to Fränkel (1975: 430) who is more
cautious.
64 Callimachus may have known other epitaphs by Simonides and drawn a similar conclusion from
the fact that he, in Alexandria, knew the texts that were originally meant as markers on graves, e.g. AP
7. 249: Ὦ ξεῖν’, ἀγγέλλειν Λακεδαιμονίοις, ὅτι τῇδε / κείμεθα τοῖς κείνων ῥήμασι πειθόμενοι.
(Stranger, report to the Spartans that we lie here, having obeyed their orders). This epigram enacts the
disconnecting of the actual message of the monument from its monumental context by asking the
passerby to take the report with him, to the Spartans.
65 Cf. Call. AP 7.80 on the death Heraclitus and AP 7.46 (anonymous) on the grave of Euripides.
Perhaps Callimachus knew that many epigrams were falsely ascribed to Simonides. If so, he may even
have been delivering a subtle comment on this fact by “pretending to be Simonides” in his own
poetry.
39
Like the epigrams discussed in this section, this last example testifies to a strong
awareness that the immortality of poets depended on their literary legacy. This continued to
speak long after death had silenced their mortal mouths, and could be revived by later poets
who knew their works. This was mainly possible because of the efforts of the founders of the
great libraries of the age and the diligent librarians and scholars who worked in them,
keeping the literary legacy alive and reviving it, as the text of the Aetia is doing in a typically
subtle Callimachean way.
1.5.3 Biographical Readings
The ancient Vitae of the Greek poets partly came into existence in the same period as the
epigrams discussed above and are the fruit of the same scholarly preoccupations. They often
contain a great deal of information borrowed indirectly or directly from the poets’ own
texts. 66 In the case of lyric poets, this transference of information from poems to biography is
facilitated by the fact that they regularly used first‐person verbal forms (lyric “I“), which
of Archilochus and Hipponax were known for their biting scorn, vulgar language, and
representation of repulsive subjects. 68 The result was that the aggressive character of these
poets’ poems was uncritically taken as a reflection of their personalities. Moreover, it was
taken for granted that every situation described in their poetry was autobiographical.
How this mode of reading found its way into the poetry of the Hellenistic age can be
seen in the reception of the anecdotal tradition regarding Archilochus. Dioscorides imagines
what the daughters of Lycambes, speaking from the grave after hanging themselves from
66 See on this Bruns (1896), Momigliano (1971), Lefkowitz (1981).
67 See on this process, and antiquity’s failure to distinguish between author and persona Clay (1998: 9‐
40).
68 On the way in which Archilochus’ poetry influenced his own notoriety, see Ael. VH 10.13 citing
Critias (= Crit. test. 88 B 44 DK): “No‐one would have known that Archilochus was the impoverished
son of a slave woman named Enipo, that he picked fights, slandered friend and foe, was an adulterer
and, worst of all, threw away his shield to flee in battle, had he himself not told us so.” Critias
concludes: “οὐκ ἀγαθὸς ἄρα ἦν ὁ Ἀρχίλοχος μάρτυς ἑαυτῶι, τοιοῦτον κλέος ἀπολιπὼν καὶ
τοιαύτην ἑαυτῶι φήμην.” (So, Archilochus was not a good witness to his own character, leaving
behind such fame and such a reputation for himself).
40
shame over Archilochus’ allegations about their unchaste behavior, might say to defend
themselves: 69
Οὐ μὰ τόδε φθιμένων σέβας ὅρκιον, αἵδε Λυκάμβεω,
αἳ λάχομεν στυγερὴν κλῃδόνα, θυγατέρες,
οὔτε τι παρθενίην ᾐσχύναμεν οὔτε τοκῆας
οὔτε Πάρον, νήσων αἰπυτάτην ἱερῶν·
ἀλλὰ καθ’ ἡμετέρης γενεῆς ῥιγηλὸν ὄνειδος
φήμην τε στυγερὴν ἔφλυσεν Ἀρχίλοχος.
Ἀρχίλοχον, μὰ θεοὺς καὶ δαίμονας, οὔτ’ ἐν ἀγυιαῖς
εἴδομεν οὔθ’ Ἥρης ἐν μεγάλῳ τεμένει.
εἰ δ’ ἦμεν μάχλοι καὶ ἀτάσθαλοι, οὐκ ἂν ἐκεῖνος
ἤθελεν ἐξ ἡμέων γνήσια τέκνα τεκεῖν. (AP 7.351)
No, by the respectable oath of the dead, we, the daughters of Lycambes, who have
received a hateful reputation, did not in the least shame our maidenhood, nor our
parents, nor Paros, steepest of the holy islands. No, it was Archilochus who poured
onto our family horrible slander and hateful shame. We did not meet Archilochus, by
the gods and the divinities, in alleyways, or in the great precinct of Hera. For, if we
had been lascivious and foolish, he would not have wanted to have lawful children
with us.
Archilochus’ poetry is here turned upon itself: his alleged wish to marry one of the girls is
used as an argument against his own accusations. The girls point out that he would never
have wanted to marry them if they had really been all he has made them out to be.
Archilochus appears in the epigram as unreasonable, spiteful, and dangerous. Yet, one might
say that the girls’ denial of the allegations testifies to the power of his poetry. Even if untrue,
the effect of his words apparently was such that it killed, since they speak from the grave,
where they ended up after hanging themselves from shame.
An epigram attributed to Theocritus 70 has a different tone than the predominant
appraisal of Archilochus’ character as exemplified by the previous epigram: 71
Ἀρχίλοχον καὶ στᾶθι καὶ εἴσιδε τὸν πάλαι ποιητάν
69 The best surviving witness to these allegations is the Cologne Epode, on which see e.g. West (1974),
Van Sickle (1975: 125‐165), Henderson (1976: 159‐179), Slings (1987: 24‐51) and, with an emphasis on
the issue of the identity of the speaker, Slings (1990: 1‐30).
70 On the disputed attribution of these epigrams, see Rossi (2001). For convenience’s sake, I call the
writer of these epigrams Theocritus.
71 For a negative evaluation of his character, e.g. also Pi. P. 2, 100‐1; Crit. test. 88 B 44 DK; AP 7.69‐71,
7.674, 9.185, and Call. fr. 380 Pf. On the appraisal of Archilochus and Hipponax in the Hellenistic age,
see Degani (1973: 79‐104), who, however, constructs some indefensible literary quarrels on the basis of
positive and negative evaluations of these poets.
41
τὸν τῶν ἰάμβων, οὗ τὸ μυρίον κλέος
διῆλθε κἠπὶ νύκτα καὶ ποτ’ ἀῶ.
ἦ ῥά νιν αἱ Μοῖσαι καὶ ὁ Δάλιος ἠγάπευν Ἀπόλλων,
ὣς ἐμμελής τ’ ἐγένετο κἠπιδέξιος
ἔπεά τε ποιεῖν πρὸς λύραν τ’ ἀείδειν. (AP 7.664)
Stop and look at Archilochus, the ancient poet of the Iambi, whose immense fame
went both to the east and unto the west. The Muses and Delian Apollo must certainly
have loved him, if we consider how melodious and capable he was in composing
poetry and singing to his lyre.
This is one of the few poetical testimonies in the tradition about Archilochus that does not
explicitly mention his unpleasant character. 72 A possible explanation for this anomaly is that
this epigram could be an actual honorary inscription for a statue of Archilochus. That would
naturally not be the place to mention unpleasant characteristics of the poet. However, this
explanation is improbable for several internal and external reasons. 73 A more convincing
suggestion, therefore, is that the poem, which omits the most common item about
Archilochus as a poet, does so on purpose to deliver a subtle comment on the predominant
way of judging him.
The last three lines state that Archilochus was loved by the Muses and Apollo and
sang and played the lyre ably. This kind of praise looks so bland and undistinguished as to
fit practically any lyric poet, but in fact it constitutes a rather pointed allusion to the oracles
that Apollo at Delphi gave Archilochus’ father regarding his son. 74 The average reader’s
expectation to hear of Archilochus’ many vicious attacks is thwarted. The erudite reader,
however, may have noticed that the poem does in fact reveal a thorough knowledge of
Archilochus and his poetry. Apart from the reference to the oracle, the remarkable meter, an
Archilochian followed by an acatalectic and a catalectic iambic trimeter, is another hint to this
72 Another candidate is Posidipp. AB 118 (SH 705), which calls Archilochus “the Parian Nightingale.”
The fragmentary state of this poem makes it impossible to ascertain whether the reference was wholly
positive.
73 There is no mention of ethnic or patronymic, nor of the location or dedicators. Moreover, this
epigram is part of a collection of similar epigrams by Theocritus, which is in all likelihood entirely
literary. The other poems display a similar kind of criticism of the literary biographical tradition cf.
Bing (1988b: 117‐123), Rossi (2001: 329‐330). On the general likeliness of “inscriptions” found in
poetry‐collections being anything other than literary, see Bing (2002: 38‐66).
74 Cf. Gerber (1999: 23), test. 3 and 18: “Ἀθάνατός σοι παῖς καὶ ἀοἱδιμος, ὦ Τελεσίκλεις, ἔσται ἐν
ἀνθρώποισιν…”(Your son, Telesicles, will be immortal and subject of song among men...).
42
effect. 75 Clearly then, the author of the epigram must know all about Archilochus and hence
about his reputation. The mention of the “widespread fame” of Archilochus (2‐3) gains ironic
weight in this light, since every reader would know that the negative reputation of
Archilochus formed a large part of this fame. However, this epigram apparently wishes to
redirect attention to the fact that Archilochus’ great ability as a poet is at the basis of it. This
poetic talent is alluded to throughout, in particular by the mentions of Apollo and of the
Muses’ preference for him. If Archilochus had not possessed his talent, his reputation would
not have spread around the world. Theocritus found it more interesting to stress this point
than harp once more upon the negative reputation of Archilochus. In an understated way, he
thus subtly attacks the facile approach of summarizing a poet’s character in epigram that was
so common in his day.
A comparable process may be witnessed in Theocritus’ epigram on Anacreon, in
comparison with the traditional approach as represented by Leonidas. 76 The epigrams by
Leonidas both invite a passer‐by to look at the same (imaginary?) statue of Anacreon:
Πρέσβυν Ανακρείοντα χύδαν σεσαλαγμένον οἴνωι
θάεο †δινωτοῦ στρέπτον ὕπερθε λίθου†
ὡς ὁ γέρων λίχνοισιν ἐπ᾿ ὄμμασιν ὑγρὰ δεδορκώς
ἄχρι καὶ ἀστραγάλων ἕλκεται ἀμπεχόναν
δισσῶν δ᾿ ἀρβυλίδων τὰν μὲν μίαν οἷα μεθυπλήξ
ὤλεσεν ἐν δ᾿ ἑτέραι ῥικνόν ἄραρε πόδα.
μέλπει δ᾿ ἠὲ Βάθυλλον ἐφίμερον ἠὲ Μεγιστᾶν
αἰωρῶν παλάμαι τὰν δυσέρωτα χέλυν·
ἀλλά πάτερ Διόνυσε, φύλασσέ μιν, οὐ γὰρ ἔοικεν
ἐκ Βάκχου πίπτειν Βακχιακὸν θέραπα. (Pl. 306/GPXXXI)
Look at old Anacreon, shaken in a disorderly manner by wine, †in a distorted
attitude on the rounded basis†, 77 (see) how the old man, with lascivious eyes casting
languishing looks, wears his mantle trailing on his ankles. Of his two boots, he has
lost one, wine‐struck as he is, while in the other one his shriveled foot still sticks. He
is singing of desirable Bathyllus or of Megistes, strumming his lovelorn lyre with his
hand. Come, Father Dionysus, take care of him, for it is not right that a servant of
Bacchus should be felled by Bacchus.
Ἴδ’ ὡς ὁ πρέσβυς ἐκ μέθας Ἀνακρέων
ὑπεσκέλισται καὶ τὸ λῶπος ἕλκεται
75 The epithet ἐμμελής could point to the fame Archilochus had gained as an innovator of music, cf.
Rossi (2001: 327‐328).
76 As suggested by Bing (1988b: 117‐123) and Rossi (2001: 180‐183).
77 On the difficulties of interpreting this phrase, cf. Gow and Page (1965: II, ad loc.).
43
ἐσάχρι γυίων, τῶν δὲ βλαυτίων τὸ μέν
ὅμως φυλάσσει θἄτερον δ᾿ ἀπώλεσεν.
μελίσδεται δὲ τὰν χέλυν διακρέκων
ἤτοι Βάθυλλον ἢ καλὸν Μεγιστέα.
φύλασσε Βάκχε, τὸν γέροντα μὴ πέσηι. (Pl. 307/GPXC)
See how old Anacreon is tottering from the wine, and how his mantle is dragged
down to his legs; of his shoes, although he still has one left, the other he has lost.
While he strums his lyre he is singing of Bathyllus or of beautiful Megistes. Take care,
Bacchus, that the old man doesn’t fall.
The portrayal of Anacreon here is not meant as flattering, as is confirmed by the fact that Pl.
307/GPXC is written in iambi, the meter of invective and comic abuse. Two main
characteristics of Anacreon’s poetry, the symposiastic and the erotic, combine to form a
grotesque picture; the Dionysiac mysteries with which he was sometimes connected are
ridiculed in the same breath. 78 Scholars have repeatedly asked whether these descriptions
fitted any actual representation of Anacreon in statuary. This question has so far been
answered in the negative, 79 which implies that Leonidas tried to imagine how Anacreon
might be most satisfactorily represented in statuary on the basis of his well‐known
reputation. 80 What outer characteristics would a man present who apparently wrote
obsessively of love and symposia? The result is a caricature. 81 This caricatural depiction of
Anacreon appears to be exactly what the following epigram by Theocritus subtly criticizes.
Θᾶσαι τὸν ἀνδριάντα τοῦτον, ὦ ξένε,
σπουδᾷ, καὶ λέγ’ ἐπὴν ἐς οἶκον ἔνθῃς·
“Ἀνακρέοντος εἰκόν’ εἶδον ἐν Τέῳ
τῶν πρόσθ’ εἴ τι περισσὸν ᾠδοποιῶν.”
προσθεὶς δὲ χὤτι τοῖς νέοισιν ἅδετο,
ἐρεῖς ἀτρεκέως ὅλον τὸν ἄνδρα. (AP 9.599)
78 Cf. Diosc. AP 7.31, with Gow and Page (1965: II, ad loc.) on this Dionysian connection.
79 Cf. Rossi (2001: 180‐3).
80 Representation of Anacreon started not long after his death. Ar. Thesm. 160‐3 represents him as
effeminate, Pl. Phaedr. 235 ironically as an expert in love. Critias emphasizes Anacreon’s love for
sympotic revelry; he only mentions women as the objects of Anacreon’s erotic poetry (B1 D‐K).
Contemporary vase painting (490‐450 BCE) shows Anacreon as a komastēs dressed in sumptuous
oriental gear, cf. Schefold (1965: fig. 1b; 2a; 3a). An exceptional statue on the Acropolis represents
Anacreon in heroic nudity, a komastes, but demonstrating signs of moderation and restraint (Schefold:
1965, fig. 7). Zanker argues that Anacreon is deliberately made into a paragon of Pericles’ political
thought here (1995: 29‐38), cf. Barbantani (1993: 48, n. 137), Rossi (2001: 102‐6; 280‐3).
81 Cf. the anonymous epigram AP 7.28. Here Anacreon’s only epithet is οἰνοπότης; the fact that he was
a poet is not even mentioned.
44
Look at that statue, stranger, with attention and say when you get back home: “I saw
a statue of Anacreon in Teos, the best if ever there was, of the singers of yore.” If you
add to this that he took delight in boys, you will accurately describe the whole man.
Theocritus ironically invites the passer‐by to stop and look seriously (σπουδᾶι) at a statue.
the epigram prevents the illusion that the statue actually is the man represented. This
impression was deliberately created in the Leonidean epigrams (cf. Πρέσβυν Ανακρείοντα/ὁ
πρέσβυς Ἀνακρέων). No actual description of the (in all probability fictive) statue ensues, so
choice after the explicit invitation to “look seriously.” The ironic pointe of the epigram
follows in the last two lines: “If you add to this that he took delight in the young, you will
accurately (ἀτρεκέως) describe the whole man.” Bing remarks that Theocritus’ learned
readers would certainly have realized that the biographical allusion of the epigram, although
representing an important aspect of the literary interests and themes of the poet, could not in
any way be said to describe the whole man in an accurate manner. 82 Rossi adds that in this
way Theocritus attacked the limited manner of considering the famous poet in contemporary
biographical writing. 83 Instead, I suggest that the undescribed statue referred to in
Theocritus’ epigram may be the cliché depiction evoked in Leonidas’ epigram. If the implied
statue of Theocritus’ epigram was that of a drunk and singing Anacreon (as his readers
would no doubt expect), one would only need to add that he loved boys (the one thing
subtly criticizes the facile and trite way of depicting the ancient poets by enumerating clichés
about their poetry,which supposedly accurately (ἀτρεκέως) reflected their character. He
points out that poets should be considered more seriously (σπουδᾶι) by their readers.
But why might he have felt that to identify a poet with his work was too simplistic?
This feeling may bear a relation to the fact that many of the Hellenistic poets (certainly
82 Bing (1988b: 121).
83 Rossi (2001: 284‐5).
84 Cf. also Theoc. AP 13.3, which qualifies the general caricature of Hipponax as a vicious character, to
be feared even beyond death (as found in AP 7.408 and 7.536). In AP 13.3, Hipponax is only dangerous
for people with a bad conscience.
45
including Theocritus) 85 experimented with various roles and voices in their own poetry. 86
Naturally, any poet who realized that it was not hard to take on an entirely different
personality in poetry would have been aware of the problems caused by the effort of pinning
down a poet on what he relates in a first person narrative.
1.6 Conclusion
The image of the poets of the past found in Hellenistic epigram suggests certain tendencies
in the Hellenistic perception and hence representation of predecessors. The general tone of
the epigrams confirms that poets of the past were held in high esteem, even if their
idiosyncrasies sometimes lent themselves to caricature (Anacreon) or expressions that appear
to hint at moral condemnation (Hipponax and Archilochus).
The Muses figure prominently and unquestionedly in the epigrams. In general, they
are brought in as a means to underline aesthetic qualities rather than a claim to knowledge
about the past. That poetry had been originally an oral performance art or even a musical art
was suggested to the Hellenistic poets by the terms archaic poets used to speak about their
métier; this is echoed in their epigrams. It is however difficult to ascertain whether they
thought epic poets like Homer composed their poetry orally or through writing. They refer to
the poetry of these ancient poets with words denoting written texts (γράμμα vel sim.) as well
as with words belonging to the field of (orally composed) song/poetry (ἀοιδή etc.),
suggesting that they do not feel a strong contradiction between these two concepts.
The emphatically material, written‐down shape poetry often takes on in the
Hellenistic age is nevertheless a phenomenon which visibly determines the way Hellenistic
poets conceptualize poetic immortality. The old ideal of κλέος, fame in (oral) song is
superseded by the feeling that it is specifically the written word that may time and again be
brought to life. Dead poets continue to speak with their ipsissima verba, if these have been
recorded and transmitted (cf. the topos of the speaking scroll, Ath. 13.696). Hellenistic poets
85 Leaving the mimes apart for the moment, the voice of the hymnic narrator in Id. 22 is obviously
different from that of the lovesick narrator in Id. 12, or that of the encomiast of Id. 16 and 17; the
identity of Simichidas (Id. 7) will be discussed in Ch. 7.4.
86 The best example of this practice is Callimachus, whose hymnic narrators differ not only among
themselves (some even appear to be women), but also e.g. from the learned narrator of the Aetia and
the various narrators of the Iambi (cf. e.g. Harder 2004: 63‐83). This practice is discussed in Ch. 6.8.
46
even feel that, because of these recorded words, it is possible to engage in a literary dialogue
with them (e.g. Dioscorides’ ethopoiia of the daughters of Lycambes). The lack of a record of
the authenticated speech of legendary poets, on the other hand, appears to give them a
somewhat different, arguably more uncertain status, as in the case of Orpheus. Callimachus
cleverly turns this whole idea of poetry as a medium for the preservation of fame on its head
by making the dead Simonides lament the loss of his grave and hence epitaph‒but he does so
in a poetical work (viz. the Aetia).
The possibility of living on in one’s writings is connected to the thought that the
content of poetry is a reflection of the character and experiences of its dead authors. This
provides the living with the possibility to know them, judge them, imagine what they might
have said (ethopoiia) and distil their essence in caricature. This last practice, however, seems
to have given rise to a kind of counterreaction (notably in some epigrams attributed to
Theocritus), perhaps because there were poets who knew from their own experience that
thoughts and feelings expressed in poetry are not necessarily identical to those of the author,
that there is a sieve through which poetry filters reality and a practical distinction between
author and role.
All in all, the way predecessors are dealt with in epigram reveals an awareness of the
paradox that they are both dead and immortal. They are at the mercy of their readers, yet
their texts hold their own and cannot be belied. The poetic text emerges as supremely
important: it is all that is ultimately left of a poet and his life; it is the substance of Greek
cultural memory.
47
48
CHAPTER 2:
HISTORICAL POETS AND CONTEMPORARY POETRY: COMING TO TERMS WITH
POETIC MODELS
2.1 Introduction
The previous chapter showed how Hellenistic epigrammatists reflected on the poetic
practices of their predecessors. It emerged from this discussion that to them, the literary past
was undeniably present, especially in the form of the written word, which constituted the
monument to character and existence of these poets. This chapter will now answer the
question how they were used and acknowledged as models in Hellenistic poetry, and what
possible problems of appropriation lurked in this process.
On the surface, it was a natural and traditional thing for Hellenistic poets to ground
their poetic practice in that of their predecessors. For whenever Greek poets did not credit
their ability to craft poetry to the Muses, Apollo or an inborn talent, 1 they attributed it to
what they had learned from their poetic predecessors, as for instance the following fragment
from Bacchylides’ Paeanes illustrates. 2
Ἕτερος ἐξ ἑτέρου σοφὸς
τό τε πάλαι τό τε νῦν.
[Οὐδὲ γὰρ ῥᾷστον]
ἀρρήτων ἐπέων πύλας
ἐξευρεῖν. (Paean., fr. 5 Maehler)
One poet learns his wisdom from another,
Thus it was and thus it still is,
[For it is not at all easy to find]
The gates to words that have never been spoken.
1 Cf. e.g. Od. 22.347‐8 (Phemius): αὐτοδίδακτος δ’ εἰμί, θεὸς δέ μοι ἐν φρεσὶν οἴμας / παντοίας
ἐνέφυσεν. (I am self‐taught and the god has planted all kinds of song‐paths in my heart).
2 Cf. Lanata (1963: 102) on Paean. fr. 5 Maehler. She furthermore follows Jebb (and the ancient
scholiasts) in positing that it is humorously aimed at Pi. O. 2.86‐88: σοφὸς ὁ πολλὰ εἰδὼς φυᾷ∙
/ μαθόντες δὲ λάβροι / παγγλωσσίᾳ κόρακες ὣς ἄκραντα γαρυέτων Διὸς πρὸς ὄρνιχα θεῖον∙ (Wise
is he who knows many things by nature, whereas learners who are boisterous and long‐winded are
like a pair of crows that cry in vain against the divine bird of Zeus. transl. Race). On the alleged
quarrel between Pindar and Bacchylides, see Lefkowitz (1981). For the feeling that a poet may learn
from another poet, cf. further e.g. Antiphon (P. Oxy. 3.414 coll. 3): καὶ ποιητής μοι δ[οκ]εῖ ἀπὸ
ποι[ητοῦ ἀ]μείνων ἄν γενέσθαι... (and I think that a poet may become better by learning from
another poet...) as cited by Lanata (1963: 217).
49
Indeed, it is generally acknowledged that imitatio and aemulatio characterize a large part of
ancient literary production. In pre‐Hellenistic Greek culture, the literary past was generally
seen as the standard against which one’s own poetic production had to be measured. Ideas
about poetic genre were influenced by the literal view of poetry as a tradition, a “handing
down” of what constituted a fitting, beautiful, and worthwhile combination of meter and
subject matter (τὸ πρέπον). This kind of reasoning may ultimately have been responsible for
the development of (unwritten) generic codes. 3 Certain subject matter became associated
with specific forms because “it had always been;” hexametric verse came to be coupled
mainly with dignified, serious subjects and iambic verse mainly with comedy or invective
and license. This view of poetry implied that tradition could and indeed should be used to
justify individual poetic choices: the way things had been done frequently became the way
they had to be done. 4
There is no indicaton that ideas regarding the intrinsic value of the literary past
fundamentally changed in the Hellenistic era, although this time of great cultural and
political changes necessarily also saw changes in the field of poetry. Old literary forms were
infused with new elements, resulting in what might be called new “genres” responding to
the changed circumstances. 5 Yet, despite this, the past continued to possess authoritative and
legimitizing functions; it was eminently present, even if very different from the present. This
is where tensions arose: how could Hellenistic poets establish continuity while responding to
new circumstances, and creating new forms of poetry?
3 Cf. Harvey (1955: 157‐175), Rossi (1971: 69‐94).
4 Innovation also provided possible variations on established themes and forms, even if the post‐
romantic admiration of individual originality in poetic production was unknown to the ancient
Greeks. The real exception to confirm the rule is Timotheus fr. 20 PMG: οὐκ ἀείδω τὰ παλαιά, / καινὰ
γὰρ ἀμὰ κρείσσω∙ / νέος ὁ Ζεὺς βασιλεύει, / τὸ πάλαι δ’ ἦν Κρόνος ἄρχων∙ ἀπίτω Μοῦσα παλαιά.
(I do not sing of old things; for what is new is also better. Young Zeus is king, while in the old days
Cronos was the ruler. Be gone, old Muse.) Indeed, his dithyramb (Persae) on recent political events
was exceptional in his era (fifth cent. BCE).
5 Traditionally this development was subsumed under Kroll’s (somewhat problematic) term
“Kreuzung der Gattungen.” See on the topic in particular Hunter (1996) and Fantuzzi and Hunter (2004:
1‐17).
50
2.2 Meeting Ancient Poets
The ancient poets who could serve as models were, as the numerous epitaphs composed in
their honor stress, long dead by the Hellenistic age. Although their legacy was to some extent
accessible for scrutiny and discussion among the learned Hellenistic poets, many factual
questions about the ancient poets’ works and lives remained that could only have been
answered by the dead poets themselves. In some epigrams, as we saw, this problem is solved
by giving a voice to the deceased or his works (ethopoiia, as in Callimachus’ epigram on the
Oechalias Halosis, AP 7.80, cf. Ch. 1.5.1). A comparable, if more complex, problem faced
writers of innovative poetry based on ancient models: standing on the shoulders of giants,
they produced their new works by combining disparate generic elements into new forms.
Did they imagine their predecessors would have approved of the new lease on life they gave
to ancient literary forms? Else, how did they justify divergences from the model, particularly
modifications of style, genre, or subject?
A possibility was to defer authority to the gods of poetry, as Callimachus does by
introducing Apollo and the Muses in the Aetia prologue to support his predilection for
subtle, innovative poetry on a small scale. 6 To corroborate the same preference, however, this
fragment also employs human poets as examples (Mimnermus and probably Philitas). 7
Apparently, in the learned surroundings of the Alexandrian Library, poetry could no longer
depend on divine authorization alone; both divine authority and predecessors were called
upon to validate Hellenistic practice. 8 The question is how this latter justification could be
made convincing. For instance, how did Callimachus convince his readers that he was
justified in writing Iambi as Hipponax had done (cf. Iamb. 1, fr. 191 Pf.)? He could have
merely named the dead poet as an example, as he does with Mimnermus and Philitas in the
Aetia prologue. 9 But an even better defense of one’s right to write in the style of a
predecessor, as he apparently realized, was the “support” and “appearance” of the dead
6 Aetia fr. 1.21‐28 Pf.; cf. Call. H. II, 105‐113.
7 Cf. Pfeiffer (1949: ad fr. 1.8‐9).
8 Cf. Fantuzzi and Hunter (2004: 1‐17).
9 An interesting variant of this procedure seems to have been presented in Iamb. 13 (fr. 203 Pf.), where
Callimachus defends his imitation of Hipponax. The diegesis says he was accused of polyeideia,
“writing in many genres,” cf. Scodel (1987: 208), Acosta‐Hughes (2001: 81). In order to justify this
poetic practice he adduces Ion of Chios: so he uses one model (Ion) to justify his choice to follow
another model (Hipponax).
51
author. The ensuing sections analyze this case and other Hellenistic solutions to the problem
of claiming authority by incorporating a predecessor.
2.2.1 Timon, Xenophanes and Pyrrho in Homer’s Hades
If a Greek writer or scholar wished to question a deceased poet in order to support his own
views, books were really the only place to look for an answer. However, a playful alternative
to this was found by Aristophanes in his Ranae. There, a katabasis to Hades is undertaken by
Dionysus to enable a dialogue with and between the dead poets Aeschylus and Euripides in
order to decide whose style should be favored in tragedy. With similar aims, the third‐
century BCE satirist and sceptic Timon of Phlius also appears to have described a katabasis in
his Silloi, books 2 and 3. 10 He gave these books the form of an emphatically Homeric Nekyia, 11
in which Xenophanes, a philosopher‐poet from the sixth century BCE, guided him through
Hades and showed him the dead philosophers endlessly quarreling over useless and even
detrimental “opinions” (δόξαι). Timon presumably chose Xenophanes as his guide through
Hades for two reasons: Xenophanes also wrote a collection or poem entitled Silloi and his
writings revealed a mindset akin to that of the later sceptic philosophers. 12
The ultimate goal of Timon’s journey through Hades is a meeting with his dead
master, the sceptic philosopher Pyrrho (fourth‐third century BCE). He is the only one among
the dead exempt from the plague of conflicting and useless opinions: 13
ἀλλ’ οἷον τὸν ἄτυφον ἐγὼ ἴδον ἠδ’ ἀδάμαστον
πᾶσιν, ὅσοις δάμνανται ὁμῶς ἄφατοί τε φατοί τε,
λαῶν ἔθνεα κοῦφα, βαρυνόμεν’ ἔνθα καὶ ἔνθα
ἐκ παθέων δόξης τε καὶ εἰκαίης νομοθήκης. (783 SH)
But such as I saw him [sc. Pyrrho], not puffed up with arrogance and not oppressed
by all those things by which the nameless and the famous are equally oppressed, the
10 Fr. 775 ff. SH. On Timon of Phlius and the Silloi, see further Diog. Laert. 9.111‐112, SH app. ad fr. 775,
Long (1978: 68‐92), Bing (1988: 71), Fantuzzi and Hunter (2004: 6).
11 For the Homeric tone of the fragments, e.g. fr. 775 SH: ἕσπετε νῦν μοι ὅσοι πολυπράγμονές ἐστε
σοφισταί... (Tell me now, all ye troublemaking sophists...) a clear reference to Il. 2.484. Whereas the
Muses are omniscient, the sophists are merely πολυπράγμονες.
12 Xenophanes did make some positive claims about the nature of the physical world in his Περὶ
Φυσέως (frs. 19‐34 DK), but he also states that mortals can obtain no knowledge about the gods (fr. 34
DK).
13 Cf. fr. 782 SH: οὐκ ἂν δὴ Πύρρωνί γ’ ἐρίσ<σ>ειεν βροτὸς ἄλλος. (No other mortal would quarrel
with Pyrrho).
52
weightless tribes of men, weighed down on all sides by the sufferings of false opinion
and useless legislation.
So in this text, which employs the format of a Homeric Nekyia, Timon wishes to ratify the
sceptic view of life held by his teacher (and presumably by himself). A crucial element in this
setup that seems to have gone unnoticed until now is that, in itself, this whole idea is
evidently an immensely ironic paradox. To describe existence beyond death in Hades in
Homeric language in order to endorse a sceptic view of life is extremely odd. The afterlife is
a subject about which no sceptic could ever seriously claim to know anything. Xenophanes,
moreover, was a critic of Homerʹs theology, 14 a believer in a mainly material reality, 15 and
something of a sceptic avant la lettre with regard to metaphysical phenomena and the
afterlife. 16 Casting him as the guide through a Homeric Hades is therefore an incongruous
way of dealing with his opinions. However, this is done in a work called Silloi, a title
pointedly shared with a work by this same Xenophanes. Moreover, it is clearly done with the
aim of ridiculing all non‐sceptic philosophy. The joke must be on the quarreling dead
philosophers, then, not on Xenophanes.
The tensions in this text strangely undermine and strengthen its message
simultaneously. The afterlife is not something Xenophanes, Timon, or his teacher Pyrrho
acknowledged certainty about; yet Timon places himself in a position of superior knowledge
by casting himself in the role of explorer of Hades. By putting the quarreling philosophers
there, he therefore playfully reveals the ridiculousness of their claims to know anything at
all, including life and death. All of this is done in order to endorse the sceptic views of his
teacher and mock all other philosophy. Thus, he subverts both the Homeric and the
Xenophanic subtexts to authorize his own and his master’s views. All in all, this presents a
striking way of manipulating the literary tradition for one’s own purposes.
2.2.2 Hipponax in Callimachus’ Iambi
In Callimachus’ Iambus 1 (fr. 191 Pf.) things are the other way around: a dead poet returns to
Earth of his own accord. Here, the sixth‐century iambic poet Hipponax arrives in Alexandria
14 Cf. e.g. frs. DK 10, 11.
15 Esp. De Natura frs. 27, 29, 33 DK.
16 Esp. fr. 34 DK, on the impossibility of knowledge about the gods; but also AP 7.20, a dig at
Pythagoras’ belief in reincarnation.
53
to scold the bickering scholars. 17 The whole poem is spoken in his voice; to emphasize his
authority as “the real thing,” he is made recognizable by means of idiosyncratic expressions,
Ionic dialect, and the meter in which the Iambus is written (scazontes). 18 His sudden arrival
implies that the situation among scholars has become so desperate that intervention of the
notorious dead iambist is necessary. 19 As epigrammatic tradition had it, Hipponax was
dangerous even after his death, 20 so readers of this poem would have been prepared for
some sharp invective. As it happens, Hipponax states he has returned to lecture the
Alexandrian scholars on the virtue of modesty and make them stop their jealous quarreling.
To this end, he tells them the tale of the Cup of Bathycles, which was to be given to the
wisest man in the world (fr. 191. 32‐77 Pf.). This golden cup was first handed to Thales of
Milete, who handed it on; it then made the rounds of the rest of the Seven Sages before
finally returning to Thales, who dedicated it to the god Apollo. 21
At first sight, this mild and moral story seems uncharacteristic of the waspish
Hipponax of old. Indeed, Hipponax claims that he and his interests have changed: “I am not
bringing an Iambus singing of a Bupalean battle” (3‐4), he says, referring to the sculptor
Bupalos whom he was said to have driven to suicide by his verse. 22 This presumably means
he is no longer an advocate or representative of crude personal invective, but rather a
harbinger of peace.
If Callimachus introduces a peaceful Hipponax, does that reflect on the new iambic
style he wishes to advocate? Is he presenting himself as the bringer of a peaceful, moral, and
modest genre that causes no personal harm? If so, he does not live up entirely to his
promises, as a look at some other Callimachean Iambi shows–as far as it is possible to make
out their contents from the fragments. Although perhaps in a different tone than Hipponax’
17 Cf. diegesis VI 6: Ὑποτίθεται φθιτὸν Ἱππώνακτα συγκαλοῦντα τοὺς φιλολόγους εἰς τὸ
Παρμενίωνος καλούμενον Σαραπίδειον∙ ἥκουσι δ’ αὐτοῖς κατ’ εἴλας ἀπαγορεύει φθονεῖν
ἀλλήλοις. (It features the dead Hipponax, who convenes the philologists to the so‐called Sarapideum
of Parmenion. When they appear in droves, he forbids them to envy each other).
18 On the characteristic way Hipponax expresses himself here, see e.g. Clayman (1980: 55), Bing (1988:
65), Kerkhecker (1999: 19‐21), Acosta‐Hughes (2002: 21; 36‐40).
19 Cf. Kerkhecker (1999: 15).
20 AP 7.405; 7.408; 7.536; 13.3.
21 Hipponax told this story in one of his own poems, cf. Depew (1992: 319).
22 See Suda 2.665.16; Plin. N.H. 36.11. The name Bupalos appears in West frs. 17, 18; 19; 20.2, 86.18; 98.3,
4, 15; 121, perhaps also 77.4; 79.12, cf. Degani (1991 ad loc.).
54
Iambi, 23 Callimachus still presents his reader with invective. Scholarly quarrels, erotic rivalry,
and literary debate are major concerns of the collection. 24 How can this contradiction be
explained? Why does Callimachus introduce Hipponax in such a way and then not follow
him in his own poetry?
Although Hipponax’ initial story certainly is of an exemplary moral character, the
way he illustrates the need for it nevertheless seems embedded in abuse directed at fellows
of the Museum (who, by the way they are described, may have been individually
recognizable to their contemporaries). He vehemently attacks the Alexandrian scholars’
behavior towards each other: some tell‐tale phrases occur at the end of the fragment (fr.
191.78‐95). According to Hipponax, the situation in scholarly Alexandria is so grave that
anyone in his right mind is considered “crazy like Alcmeon” by the others (78‐79), while
nasty practices like plagiarism and backbiting abound (80‐86) 25 and violent and analphabetic
charlatans threaten the true poet (87‐91), who is poor (92‐3). 26 So, all considered, it seems
invective poses as morality in Hipponax’ words; he does not truly abstain from quarrelsome
insults himself either.
Another point of interest is Callimachus’ manipulation of the speaking situation he
has created in this poem. Callimachus himself is probably supposed to be part of Hipponax’
quarreling audience. So, when Hipponax commands the gathered scholars to “write the
story (which he is going to tell them) down”(fr. 191.31 Pf.), he alerts the reader to the fictional
nature of his own “direct speech.” The poem purportedly presents a written report of this
speech of Hipponax; indeed, it is the report by Callimachus as any reader could see, since his
name would figure on the scroll of the Iambi. 27 In other words, Callimachus places himself in
a privileged position: he recounts an event that a great number of scholars are said to have
witnessed—and at which they were abused–without admitting that it is fictional and
controled by himself alone. Why does he do this and what does he gain by it?
23 It is often claimed that Callimachus’ Iambi are different from Hipponax’: less personal invective,
more moral exhortations, cf. e.g. Jung (1929: 24), Fraser (1972: I, 733‐4), Kerkhecker (1999: 293‐4),
Acosta Hughes (2001: 21). Not so e.g. Clayman (1980: 58‐9).
24 Iambi 2 (fr. 192 Pf.), 4 (fr. 194 Pf.) and 13 (fr. 203 Pf.).
25 So Pfeiffer (1949: ad loc.).
26 This may refer to Callimachus himself, who often claims his poetry earns him nothing, cf. fr. 193 Pf.,
AP 12.150.
27 Cf. Kerkhecker (1999: 34), Harder (2001: 415), Acosta‐Hughes (2002: 59).
55
It was characteristic for iambic poets to choose a “mask” to voice their own
potentially controversial opinions; 28 it would seem that this technique is used here in a
sophisticated way. In the poem, it is Callimachus who describes Hipponax as voicing
complaints about the quarreling philologists’ behavior. Yet, Callimachus himself was
presumably one of the most vociferous of this quarrelsome lot, judging by the other Iambi
and passages from his other poetical works. 29 By hiding behind Hipponax’ broad back,
however, he remains scot‐free: putting on the mask of Hipponax, Callimachus censures the
quarrelsomeness of the others. He goes even further and indulges in some samples of
invective and quarrelsomeness himself.
simultaneously exploiting and continuing its traditions. Like Hipponax, Callimachus is
quarrelsome, as the other Iambi illustrate. Yet, he uses his (quarrelsome) model Hipponax as
a counsel against such quarrelsomeness. Real iambic poets never change, apparently; even
when advising against aggression they become aggressive. Perhaps Callimachus’ intricate
method is an implicit acknowledgement that every appropriation of poetry of the past
essentially turns the dead poet into the living poet’s personal mouthpiece. It is only too easy
for Callimachus to make Hipponax teach a moral lesson to his contemporaries and insult
them, while remaining scot‐free himself. If he chooses to behave in a manner that would
displease the Hipponax he has created himself, this Hipponax will not return to censure him.
28 Cf. Arist. Rhet. 3.1418b28‐33: εἰς δὲ τὸ ἦθος, ἐπειδὴ ἔνια περὶ αὑτοῦ λέγειν ἢ ἐπίφθονον ἢ
μακρολογίαν ἢ ἀντιλογίαν ἔχει, καὶ περὶ ἄλλου ἢ λοιδορίαν ἢ ἀγροικίαν, ἕτερον χρὴ λέγοντα
ποιεῖν (...) καὶ ὡς Ἀρχίλοχος ψέγει. ποιεῖ γὰρ τὸν πατέρα λέγοντα περὶ τῆς θυγατρὸς ἐν τῷ
ἰάμβῳ “χρημάτων δ’ ἄελπτον οὐθέν ἐστιν οὐδ’ ἀπώμοτον,” καὶ τὸν Χάρωνα τὸν τέκτονα ἐν τῷ
ἰάμβῳ οὗ ἀρχὴ “οὔ μοι τὰ Γύγεω.” (In regard to moral character, since sometimes, in speaking of
ourselves, we render ourselves liable to envy, to the charge of prolixity, or contradiction, or, when
speaking of another, we may be accused of abuse or boorishness, we must make another speak in our
place (...) Archilochus uses the same device in censure; for in his iambics he introduces the father
speaking as follows of his daughter: “There is nothing beyond expectation, nothing that can be sworn
impossible” and the carpenter Charon in the iambic verse beginning: “I [care not for the wealth] of
Gyges.” transl. Freese).
29 E.g. Aetia fr. 1 Pf.; Hymn II (105‐113); fr. 398 Pf., an answer to AP 9.63 (in praise of the Lyde of
Antimachus) by Asclepiades, cf. the Scholia Florentina to Aetia fr. 1 Pf. These texts, as well as the
quarrel between Apollonius and Callimachus are discussed in Ch. 4.
56
2.2.3 Hipponax in Herondas’ Mimiambi
Another example of a Hellenistic poet’s encounter with a poet of the past (again, Hipponax)
is found in Herondas’ Mimiamb 8, which is generally recognized as a metapoetic poem. The
speaker, who may be identified with Herondas’ poetical persona, recounts a dream to one of
his slaves, Annas, 30 in which he met with some hostile goatherds and an old man. Joining the
goatherds in a game of ἀσκολιασμός (jumping on a wineskin filled with air), he emerged as
the winner. The description of the game suggests a characterization of Herondas’ own poetry
with its mixture of violent slapstick and bawdy humor: π̣άντα δ’ ἦν, Ἀνν[ᾶ, / εἰς ἒν γέλως
τε κἀνίη[......]ε̣ντα (43‐44: The whole scene, Annas, was a mixture of laughter and pain...). 31
Afterwards, the old man aggressively claims Herondas’ prize, a goat, or at least half
of it. The arbiter, a young man (whom some critics identify with Dionysus, patron god of
dramatic poetry), 32 tells them to divide the prize. In the last lines of the poem, consisting of
the interpretation of the dream, Herondas apparently claims that his poetry, modeled on that
of Hipponax (named here for the first time), will be attacked by critics but nevertheless bring
him great fame: 33
τὰ μέλεα πολλοὶ κάρτα, τοὺς ἐ̣μ̣οὺς μόχθους,
τιλεῦσιν ἐν Μούσηισιν (...)
..]κλέος, ναὶ Μοῦσαν, ἤ μ’ ἔπεα κ[
.]εγ’ ἐξ ἰάμβων, ἤ με δευτέρη γν[
.]... μετ’ Ἰππώνακτα τὸν παλαι[
.. τ]ὰ κύλλ’ ἀείδειν Ξουθίδηις †επιουσι†. (Mim. 8.71‐2; 76‐79)
Many will tear hard at my songs, at which I have toiled, with the Muses. ... fame, by
the Muse, my poetry ... either from the Iambi, or second ... after Hipponax of yore ... to
sing the crooked verses for the Ionians. †...†
It is generally assumed that the angry old man who claims half the prize is identified as
Hipponax by the speaker Herondas in his (partly lost) explanation of the dream (66‐79). This
30 Another dream leading to a “poetic investiture” by the Muses, was described in Call. Aetia (fr. 2 Pf.),
cf. Kambylis, (1965: 93‐106); on speculation and scholarship on this dream, see Benedetto (1993).
31 Cf. Hutchinson (1988: 237).
32 E.g. Hutchinson (1988: 237). The prize of a goat seems to point in this direction (cf. the peripatetic
explanation of the word τραγῳδία) as does the jumping on the wineskin.
33 The poem has often been read as a “masquerade,” cf. Reitzenstein’s interpretation of Theoc. Id. 7
(Ch. 7.4). Knox reads it as a polemic against Call. Iambi (1985: 107‐119). Other interpretations have
identified the goatherds as bucolic poets (e.g. Theocritus) and the young man (Dionysus) as Ptolemy
Philadelphus.
57
raises the question why Hipponax is so angry with someone who claims to follow him as a
model. One solution is to attribute his anger to the fact that Herondas has modified
Hipponax’ genre (Iambi) by mixing in dramatic elements (hence the name Mimiambi). 34 This
would mean that Hipponax is angry because his example is not being followed in the right
way by Herondas. If this is correct, the poem in fact describes an attempt at appropriation of
the literary past gone awry. The dead poet Hipponax subverts the frame his follower
Herondas tries to put him in by behaving aggressively towards him.
It might however more attractively be argued that Hipponax is paradoxically
validating Herondas’ claim by his presence. To support this, it may be pointed out that the
behavior of Herondas at the beginning of the poem closely resembles that of the old man in
the dream (Hipponax). 35 In the dream, Hipponax threatens:
ἔρρ’ ἐκ προσώπου μή σε καίπ̣ερ ὢν πρέσβυς
οὔληι κατ’ ἰθὺ τῆι βατηρίηι κό[ψω. (Mim. 8.56‐7)
Get out of my sight, so I don’t hit you hard with my cruel stick, old man though I
be. 36
“Herondas,” on waking, had uttered a similar if differently worded threat towards one of his
slaves:
τ]ό̣ν̣θ̣ρυζε καὶ κνῶ, μέχρις εὖ παραστά[ς σοι
τὸ] βρέγμα τῶι σκίπωνι μαλθακὸν θῶμα[ι. (Mim.8.8‐9)
Yes, go on sleeping and snoring until I stand over you and crush your forehead to a
pulp with my stick.
This near‐quotation illustrates how Hipponax’ threat towards Herondas has taught him how
to behave as a iambic poet (viz. aggressively). The fact that Hipponax and Herondas
ultimately display the same behavior illustrates that Herondas qualifies as a real iambic poet
in the vein of Hipponax. Verbal aggression and threats are the means through which
Hipponax in this poem chooses to invest his imitator as a poet. His behavior should therefore
not be interpreted as a condemnation of Herondas’ poetry by Hipponax, but rather as an
34 Rosen reads the askoliasmos (on which see Latte, 1958), as a symbol for this dramatic ingredient
incorporated into Herondas’ Mimiambi (1992: 205‐216). The presence of Dionysus as a judge and the
award of the goat would point in the same direction.
35 Cf. Hutchinson (1988: 237, 239 n. 39).
36 This last phrase is in fact a literal quotation from one of Hipponax’ poems, Hipp. fr. 20 West:
δοκ<έω>ν ἐκεῖνον τῆι βα{κ}τηρίηι κόψαι.
58
example which Herondas duly follows. This is similar to the way Callimachus employs
Hipponax in his Iambi. Both poets introduce the poet of invective as abusive, but consider his
insults an invitation to abuse others in their own poetry. Callimachus is the more
sophisticated of the two because he makes Hipponax’ condemnation of invective an
invective in its own right aimed at others, while he himself emerges scot‐free.
2.3 Ancient Poets as Paradigm
Theocritus 16 also evokes past masters as models for new poetry but in a way that is not so
“close and personal” as the previous examples. Idyll 16 is a poem full of Pindaric
reminiscences 37 that was ostensibly written to obtain a commission for more poems from
Hiero II, the future tyrant of Syracuse, Theocritusʹ city of origin. It presents a meditation
upon the history and mechanisms of patronage poetry, implicitly offering Hiero II the same
relationship with Theocritus that the celebrated tyrant of Syracuse, his namesake Hiero I, had
enjoyed with the great poets of his own era, prominently among them of course Pindar. 38
This same Pindar, the obvious if implicit model of the poem, disliked talking about
material rewards for poetry and euphemized his aversion in terms like φιλία and χάρις
(friendship, graceful reciprocity). His distaste for the coupling of money and poetry is
famously illustrated by Isthmian 2, a relevant subtext for Id. 16:
Οἱ μὲν πάλαι, ὦ Θρασύβουλε,
φῶτες, οἳ χρυσαμπύκων
ἐς δίφρον Μοισᾶν ἔβαι‐
νον κλυτᾷ φόρμιγγι συναντόμενοι,
ῥίμφα παιδείους ἐτόξευον μελιγάρυας ὕμνους,
ὅστις ἐὼν καλὸς εἶχεν Ἀφροδίτας
εὐθρόνου μνάστειραν ἁδίσταν ὀπώραν.
ἁ Μοῖσα γὰρ οὐ φιλοκερδής
πω τότ’ ἦν οὐδ’ ἐργάτις∙
οὐδ’ ἐπέρναντο γλυκεῖ‐
αι μελιφθόγγου ποτὶ Τερψιχόρας
ἀργυρωθεῖσαι πρόσωπα μαλθακόφωνοι ἀοιδαί.
νῦν δ’ ἐφίητι [τὸ] τὠργείου φυλάξαι
ῥῆμ’ ἀλαθείας [ ... ] ἄγχιστα βαῖνον,
37 Cf. Clapp (1913: 310‐316), Gow (1952: II, introduction to Id. 16), Hunter (1996: 82‐90).
38 Hunter (1996: 82).
59
“χρήματα χρήματ’ ἀνήρ”
ὃς φᾶ κτεάνων θ’ ἅμα λειφθεὶς καὶ φίλων.
ἐσσὶ γὰρ ὦν σοφός. (I. 2.1‐11)
The men of old, Thrasybulus, who used to mount the chariot of the golden‐wreathed
Muses, taking with them the glorious lyre, freely shot their honey‐sounding hymns of
love at any boy who was beautiful and had the sweetest bloom of late summer that
woos fair‐throned Aphrodite. For at that time the Muse was not yet greedy for gain,
nor up for hire. Nor were sweet soft‐voiced songs with their faces silvered over being
sold, from the hand of honey‐voiced Terpsichore. But now, she bids us heed the
Argive adage, which comes closest < ... > to truth: “Money, money makes the man,”
said he who lost his possessions and friends as well. But enough, for you are wise.
(transl. Race)
The ancient scholia understood Pindar to be referring here to his predecessors, the lyric poets
Alcaeus, Ibycus, and Anacreon, who wrote their love songs inspired by the grace of beautiful
youths, without any consideration of monetary gain. 39 Pindar expresses regret that such a
pure motivation has been replaced by a concern for profit, and the scholia inferred that
Pindar blamed Simonides for this. 40
To demonstrate a somewhat similar idea about poetry and its rewards, Theocritus
uses three other poets in Id. 16: Simonides and Homer, whom he both names, and Pindar, to
whom he merely alludes. In the first part of the poem (1‐70), he implies that whereas poetry
used to be a favor (in Homer’s times), poets need to ask their patrons for a material reward
in the present age (since Simonides invented the union of poetry and money). 41 In the second
half (70‐109), Homeric κλέος (fame in song) is combined with the Simonidean model of
39 Cf. schol. vet. Drachmann ad I. 2.1b. ταῦτα δὲ τείνει καὶ εἰς τοὺς περὶ Ἀλκαῖον καὶ Ἴβυκον καὶ
Ἀνακρέοντα, καὶ εἴ τινες τῶν πρὸ αὐτοῦ δοκοῦσι περὶ τὰ παιδικὰ ἠσχολῆσθαι. (This refers to
Alcaeus and Ibycus and Anacreon as well as others that may have occupied themselves with paidika
before.) It may however be noted that strictly speaking these erotic poets were not Pindar’s real
predecessors in the field of epinicia. On the introduction of money as a means to commission poetry,
see Von Reden (1995: 30‐50).
40 Cf. schol. vet. Drachmann ad. I. 2.9: νῦν, φησί, μισθοῦ συντάττουσι τοὺς ἐπινίκους, πρώτου
Σιμωνίδου προκαταρξαμένου. οὐδ’ ἐργάτις, ὅ ἐστιν αἰτοῦσα μισθὸν ἐφ’ οἷς ἔπραττεν. ἔνθεν καὶ
Καλλίμαχός φησιν “οὐ γὰρ ἐργάτιν τρέφω / τὴν Μοῦσαν, ὡς ὁ Κεῖος Ὑλίχου νέπους.” λέγοι δ’ ἂν
πρὸς Σιμωνίδην ταῦτα, ὡς φιλάργυρον διασύρων τὸν ἄνδρα. (For nowadays, he [Pindar] says, they
compose their epinician odes for money, since Simonides first started this practice. “No working
[Muse]” that is, one who asks money for what she does. Hence Callimachus says: “For I do not feed a
working Muse, like the man from Ceos, the grandson of Hylichus. (fr. 222 Pf.)” [Pindar] might be
saying that about Simonides, blaming him for being miserly.)
41 Tradition described Simonides as a miser and the inventor of paid‐for poetry, cf. Bell (1978: 29‐86),
Gerber (1997: 246).
60
κλέος for money, and an ideal merging of these two attitudes is implicitly found in Pindar,
who emerges as the ideal model for patronage poetry. 42
In the first 70 lines, Theocritus addresses the world at large, especially misguided
people who are unwilling to spend their money on poetry. In lines 5‐13, Theocritus relates
how he sends out his “Graces” (personifications of his poems) only for them to return home
graceless since they earn no reward (8‐10: σκυζόμεναι: with long faces; πολλά με
τωθάζοισαι: continually blaming me; ὀκνηραὶ: intimidated). 43 The implication is that the
χάρις (charm) of poetry can only come into its own when appreciated and rewarded
(χαρίζεσθαι). The most important characteristic of χάρις, then, is reciprocity. In this respect,
χάρις resembles the working of κλέος, the other main theme of the poem.
Finally, the Graces return moodily to the box Theocritus keeps them in (10‐12:
ὀκνηραὶ δὲ πάλιν κενεᾶς ἐν πυθμένι χηλοῦ / ψυχροῖς ἐν γονάτεσσι κάρη μίμνοντι
βαλοῖσαι, / ἔνθ’ αἰεί σφισιν ἕδρη, ἐπὴν ἄπρακτοι ἵκωνται). At the basis of this image is a
famous anecdote about Simonides. When asked to write a song for χάρις (equivalent to Latin
gratis), this poet apparently replied that he kept two boxes, one for χάρις and one for money.
The one containing χάρις was always empty, when he opened it in case of need. 44 Theocritus
has cleverly turned this bon mot around, 45 so the point becomes that χάρις (grace; his poems)
without χάρις (thanks, reward, appreciation) is useless.
At this point (14), Theocritus begins to explain what has gone wrong in the present
day. People are unaware that, given the human condition, κλέος is the single most important
thing to obtain. They misunderstand the true meaning of κέρδος (profit), thinking that
money, not generously spent but jealously guarded, is profitable:
(...) οὐ γὰρ ἔτ’ ἄνδρες ἐπ’ ἔργμασιν ὡς πάρος ἐσθλοῖς
αἰνεῖσθαι σπεύδοντι, νενίκηνται δ’ ὑπὸ κερδέων
πᾶς δ’ ὑπὸ κόλπου χεῖρας ἔχων πόθεν οἴσεται ἀθρεῖ
ἄργυρον, οὐδέ κεν ἰὸν ἀποτρίψας τινὶ δοίη
ἀλλ’ εὐθὺς μυθεῖται∙ “ἀπωτέρω ἢ γόνυ κνάμα∙
42 Griffiths (1979: 32, quoting von Holzinger 1892: 194) points out the subtlety of not naming what is
the central model for this poem.
43 Merkelbach (1952: 312‐327) suggests that the Graces reminded the ancient reader of bands of
children going around the doors begging for sweetmeats. Hunter thinks they reminded him of the
anecdotes told about Homer’s life as a traveling bard (1996: 94).
44 Cf. T‐scholien 104 and Stob. 3.10.38.
45 Hunter (1996: 100): in the anecdote χάρις is what the mean patron offers the poet, in Id. 16 the poet
sends χαρίτες to mean patrons.
61
αὐτῷ μοί τι γένοιτο.” “θεοὶ τιμῶσιν ἀοιδούς.”
“τίς δέ κεν ἄλλου ἀκούσαι; ἅλις πάντεσσιν Ὅμηρος.”
“οὗτος ἀοιδῶν λῷστος, ὃς ἐξ ἐμεῦ οἴσεται οὐδέν.”
Δαιμόνιοι, τί δὲ κέρδος ὁ μυρίος ἔνδοθι χρυσός
κείμενος; οὐχ ἅδε πλούτου φρονέουσιν ὄνασις,… (16.14‐23)
No more, as before are men eager to win praise for glorious deeds, but are enslaved
by gain; and each, his hand within his purse‐fold, looks to see whence he may win
money and will not rub the very rust from it to give another, straight answering
rather: “the knee is closer than he shank; may somewhat befall me myself,” or: “the
gods reward the poets,” and “who would listen to another? Homer is enough for all,”
“he is the best of poets who shall get naught of me.” Fools, what gain is it, the gold
that lies uncounted in your coffers? Herein is not, to thinking men, the profit of
wealth... (transl. Gow, adapted)
The miserly contemporaries are also impervious to poetry’s true nature and function and
foolishly believe that poets need no money (19, 21) 46 and that Homer is enough for all (20). 47
Theocritus therefore explains in Pindaric manner how best to spend one’s money (24‐29): 48
spend some on yourself and some on the bards (ἀοιδῶν, 24), treat many of your kin and
many others well, be pious towards the gods, be a good host, and, most of all, honor the holy
priests of the Muses (Μοισάων δὲ μάλιστα τίειν ἱεροὺς ὑποφήτας, 29). 49
What happens if one fails to spend money on poetry is then demonstrated: the lack of
money on poetry! (30‐33) 50 To illustrate this, Theocritus provides some examples from the
past, a “history of poetry” as Griffiths calls it, which is determined by the fact that “the
further Theocritus gazes into the past, the less he sees of poetry’s historical context and the
more he feels its essence” (1979: 31). In other words, the link between poetry and κλέος
46 This refers to an anecdote about Simonides. One day the Scopadae refused to pay Simonides for a
song composed in their honor because it paid to much attention to the Dioscuri, saying: “Let them pay
the other half.” Thereupon a mysterious young man called Simonides outside, and the banquet hall in
which all had been seated collapsed. Simonides interpreted this as a sign that the Dioscuri had saved
him and had so repaid him for his tribute to them (Cic. De Or. 2.352).
47 This refers to an anecdote about Xenophanes complaining to Hiero (I) of Syracuse that he could not
make a living for himself and his two slaves out of his poetry. Hiero answered: “Well, that Homer you
despise so much is able to feed more than ten‐thousand, even now that he’s dead.”(Plut. Reg. Apophth.
175c).
48 The relevant subtext is Pi. P. 1.90‐98, advising Hiero I not to economize, in order to gain a good
reputation beyond death (cf. Hunter 1996: 86‐7).
49 On the Homeric hapax ὑποφῆτης, see Ch. 8.
50 Cf. Pi. I. 1.66‐68: εἰ δέ τις ἔνδον νέμει πλοῦτον κρυφαῖον, / ἄλλοισι δ’ ἐμπίπτων γελᾷ, ψυχὰν
Ἀΐδᾳ τελέων / οὐ φράζεται δόξας ἄνευθεν. (But if a man keeps wealth hidden inside and attacks
others with laughter, he does not consider that he is paying up his soul to Hades, devoid of fame).
62
keeps being emphasized, while the relation between poetry and monetary rewards fades into
insignificance in the far past, the age of the traveling bards and Homer (48‐57). The message
of this “history of poetry,” is that Homer is not a valid example for modern poets (cf. 20: ἅλις
πάντεσσιν Ὅμηρος). Poetry may not have changed intrinsically, but the times have. This is
why Simonides (34‐47) is emphatically named, the poet who enjoyed the questionable fame
of being the first to establish a relationship between praise poetry and money. He was a
“divine poet” (θεῖος ἀοιδὸς ὁ Κήιος 44, the epithet it usually reserved for Homer!) but had
to live with the realities of his age: for money, he provided his patrons, the Scopadae and the
Creondae, with an extremely valuable gift, κλέος (36‐44). Hence, Simonides represents the
model of the two seemingly incompatible sides of poetry: the unpleasant, base monetary
aspect and the divine, eternal κλέος it provides.
After Simonides’ example, Theocritus once more travels back further into the past, to
the bards of the epic cycle (48‐50). 51 They sang of the heroes of the Trojan War, such as the
again fall outside the Simonidean system of κλέος. They did not pay a singer to sing of them,
but their deeds were exceptional. So, the fact that their names have remained again serves
solely to illustrate that κλέος is the best thing attainable for humans and that it depends
entirely on singers.
Next comes a reference to Homer’s Odyssey (51‐57): Odysseus would have been
forgotten, like Eumaeus, the swineherd, Philoetius the cowherd and old King Laertes, if it
had not been for the songs of Homer (57). Here the simplicity of the majority of the
characters selected (a swineherd, a cowherd and an old nobleman on a small island) and the
reach of the fame they achieved seem at the furthest remove from each other and therefore
provide the most striking example of the power of poetry. 52 In the lines that follow,
Theocritus once more recapitulates the essence of all these examples (58‐9): “From the Muse
comes noble fame for humans, and the possessions of the dead are wasted by the living.”
Ergo, one should spend money on poets.
After this, he shifts to a different paradigm and enters the Pindaric realm, which is
much less straightforward. The possession of wealth is here opposed not to fame beyond
Τhe example of Cycnus is from the cyclic poems, cf. Gow (1952: II, ad loc.).
51
These examples may have been chosen on purpose to underline Theocritus’ claims as a bucolic poet
52
who would provide κλέος even to the humble themes he specialized in, cf. Gutzwiller (1983: 227).
63
death, but to “appreciation and the affection of people” (τιμήν τε καὶ ἀνθρώπων φιλότητα,
66). Monetary rewards and wealth are not mentioned anymore. Instead, great deeds are now
recognized as vital for attaining fame. Any poet who will be received κεχαρισμένος (with
warm welcome, 68) will be glad to sing of the Achilles‐ or Aias‐like Hiero II (74), who will
chase the Carthaginians and bring a reign of peace to Sicily (76‐90, a brief reworking of Pi.
P.1, in honor of Hiero I). The days of Homer almost seem to have returned, but with the
genteel and graceful touch of Pindaric reciprocity. Song and κλέος will be Hiero’s reward for
the establishment of peace (90‐103).
The ending of Id. 16 thus becomes a subtle Umwertung aller Werte. Κλέος is no longer
dependent on money but on χάρις, in the triple sense of thanks due to Hiero for his great
deeds, graceful reception (χαρίζεσθαι) of the poet, and glamorous charm (χάρις), which
Theocritus’ compositions will bestow on Hiero. Nor is κλέος any longer solely a possession
with special value after death; it is enriched with χάρις (in all senses of the word) and
therefore valuable during life. This is why the Muses, who traditionally guaranteed κλέος
for ages to come (cf. 1‐2:), are united in the end with the Graces, who provide the human
present (cf. 4: ἄμμες δὲ βροτοὶ οἵδε, βροτοὺς βροτοὶ ἀείδωμεν) with charm and glamor (108‐
9: τί γὰρ Χαρίτων ἀγαπητόν / ἀνθρώποις ἀπάνευθεν). The final lines (103‐109) are a close
reworking of a Pindaric hymn to the Graces (O. 14, 3‐9), 53 whereas the beginning (5‐13)
featured the Graces in the adaptation of a Simonidean anecdote. Poetry, no longer
encumbered by financial concerns, is all heavenly χάρις at this point.
εἷς μὲν ἐγώ, πολλοὺς δὲ Διὸς φιλέοντι καὶ ἄλλους
θυγατέρες, τοῖς πᾶσι μέλοι Σικελὴν Ἀρέθοισαν
ὑμνεῖν σὺν λαοῖσι καὶ αἰχμητὴν Ἱέρωνα.
ὦ Ἐτεόκλειοι Χάριτες θεαί, ὦ Μινύειον
Ὀρχομενὸν φιλέοισαι ἀπεχθόμενόν ποτε Θήβαις,
ἄκλητος μὲν ἔγωγε μένοιμί κεν, ἐς δὲ καλεύντων
θαρσήσας Μοίσαισι σὺν ἁμετέραισιν ἴοιμ’ ἄν.
καλλείψω δ’ οὐδ’ ὔμμε∙ τί γὰρ Χαρίτων ἀγαπητόν
ἀνθρώποις ἀπάνευθεν; ἀεὶ Χαρίτεσσιν ἅμ’ εἴην. (16.101‐109)
O. 14, 3‐9: ὦ λιπαρᾶς ἀοίδιμοι βασίλειαι / Χάριτες Ἐρχομενοῦ, παλαιγόνων Μινυᾶν ἐπίσκοποι, /
53
κλῦτ’, ἐπεὶ εὔχομαι σὺν γὰρ ὑμῖν τά <τε> τερπνὰ καί / τὰ γλυκέ’ ἄνεται πάντα βροτοῖς, / εἰ σοφός,
εἰ καλός, εἴ τις ἀγλαὸς ἀνήρ. / οὐδὲ γὰρ θεοὶ σεμνᾶν Χαρίτων ἄτερ / κοιρανέοντι χοροὺς / οὔτε
δαῖτας... (O Graces, much‐sung queens of shining Orchomenos and guardians of the ancient Minyai,
hear my prayer. For with your help all things pleasant and sweet come about for mortals, whether a
man be wise, handsome, or illustrious. Yes, not even the gods arrange choruses or feasts without the
august Graces... transl. Race).
64
I am but one, and the daughters of Zeus love many another beside; and may they all
be fain to sing of Sicilian Arethusa with her warriors and the spearman Hiero. O
Graces, goddesses whom Eteocles adored, O you that love Minyan Orchomenus
hated by Thebes of old, when no man summons me, I will abide at home, but to the
houses of them that call I will take heart and go, together with our Muses. Nor will I
leave you behind, for without the Graces what has man desirable? With them may I
ever dwell. (transl. Gow)
These lines suggest that Theocritus has become one of the many singers beloved by the
Muses, who will hymn the Homeric‐Pindaric hero (αἰχμητὴν, spearswinger, 103) 54 Hiero,
and Syracuse. The transformation is complete: κλέος and χάρις are united as they should be
(107‐108) and reciprocity (in the form of a reward for a poet who bestows κλέος) is elegantly
reacknowledged as the condicio sine qua non of poetry (106‐107). Poets need patrons as much
as patrons need poets. 55 The Idyll exquisitely illustrates how the reputations and works of
poets of the old days can be exploited in an erudite and subtle way to propose, authorize,
and justify a new paradigm for the interaction between Hellenistic poets and their
(prospective) patrons.
2.4 A Biased Reading of Ancient Poets
The discussion of Id. 16 has shown how the works and lives of poets of the past could be
made to meet the needs of modern poets through an emphasis on (or the literal quotation of)
certain characteristic elements of their poetry and items from the anecdotal tradition about
their lives. By these means, they are customized for the new social context of the Hellenistic
world, in this case the personal situation of Theocritus. Considering their function in this
poem, it is to be expected that these examples do not grossly distort the reputation or the
nature of the poetry of the model poets beyond recognition.
On the contrary, a complete distortion of literary and philosophical history can be
found in Hermesianax’ Leontion (fr. 7 Powell), in which all the poets and philosophers named
are claimed to have written their works merely as “allegories” of or testimonies to their love
54 The word is also used of Ptolemy Philadelphus in Id. 17.56. It is found both in Homer (Il. 3.178,
describing Agamemnon) and in Pindar (P. 4.12, N. 5.7, describing Jason and the sons of Aiacus
respectively). Theocritus implies that Hiero will have a model in the subjects of these poets, and
specifically in the patrons of Pindar’s poetry.
55 Cf. de Jong (2004: 179‐186).
65
affairs. 56 The whole exercise looks like an elaboration upon the theme “Love teaches one to
be a poet,” 57 but it is unlikely that this was the reading of ancient poetry (or philosophy) that
Hermesianax seriously proposed. To name but some of the more outrageous examples,
according to Hermesianax, Homer really composed the Odyssey because he was hopelessly in
love with Penelope (λεπτὴν ᾗς Ἰθάκην ἐνετείνατο θεῖος Ὅμηρος / ᾠδῇσιν πινυτῆς εἵνεκα
Πηνελόπης, Homer put tiny Ithaca in his songs because of trustworthy Penelope, 29‐30) and
Hesiod wrote his Γυναικῶν Κατάλογος (Ἠοῖαι) out of love for the girl Ehoia: 58
Φημὶ δὲ καὶ Βοιωτὸν ἀποπρολιπόντα μέλαθρον
Ἡσίοδον πάσης ἤρανον ἱστορίης
Ἀσκραίων ἐσικέσθαι ἐρῶνθ’ Ἑλικωνίδα κώμην∙
ἔνθεν ὅ γ’ Ἠοίην μνώμενος Ἀσκραϊκὴν
πόλλ’ ἔπαθεν, πάσας δὲ λόγων ἀνεγράψατο βίβλους
ὑμνῶν, ἐκ πρώτης παιδὸς ἀνερχόμενος. (Leontion, fr. 7.22‐26 Powell)
And I claim that Hesiod, too, the shepherd of all history, leaving behind his Boeotian
homestead, came to the Heliconian village of the Ascraeans as a lover. And from that
moment he suffered much in his wooing of Ascraean Ehoia and wrote all his books
hymning her, ever starting over from that first girl.
These are statements no one could be expected to take seriously; rather they pose as clever
and playful distortions serving to justify and authorize Hermesianax’ choice to write erotic
elegy. He positions himself in a long “tradition” of erotic poets of his own creation. 59
Hesiod’s thematic catalogue‐poem Ehoiai, which featured the loves of gods for mortal
women, serves as the main model of the present catalogue of loves. The girl Ehoia, who, as
Hermesianax implies, furnishes the title, addressee, and recurrent “apostrophe” of Hesiod’s
poem, likewise functions as a model for Leontion, the beloved addressee who lends her
name to Hermesianax’ own poem. The love of the gods for mortal women and the heroic
56 Caspers (2006: 21‐42) emphasizes the “allusive” nature of these allegories; the fragment often echoes
the vocabulary of the poets mentioned, or alludes in other ways to their poetry.
57 Cf. Nicias fr. 566 SH, allegedly in response to Theocritus Id. 11.
58 The other couples are: Orpheus and Argiope, Musaeus and Antiope, Mimnermus and Nanno,
Antimachus and Lyde, Alcaeus and Anacreon rivaling for the love of Sappho, Sophocles and Theoris,
Euripides and a servant of Archelaos, Philoxenus and Galatea, Philitas and Bittis, Pythagoras and
Theano, Socrates and Aspasia, Aristippus and Lais.
59 Cf. Phanocles’ Ἐρῶτες ἢ Καλοί (fr. 1 Powell). The genre of (elegiac) catalogue poetry was popular in
the third century, cf. the anonymous “tattoo‐elegy” (Huys, 1991), Arai (Curses) by Moero, and Ibis by
Callimachus, which provide catalogues of legendary examples for punishments and insults.
66
offspring that resulted from these couplings are reflected by the desire of the poets for their
beloveds and the poetry this generated. 60
The idea that poetry is the allegorical expression of real experiences, as posited in the
Leontion, is related to the biographical mode of reading, which deduces a poet’s character
and way of life from his poetry (cf. the epigrams in the previous chapter). 61 However, in
Hermesianax’ case, the presupposed relation between a poet’s life and work is not a
straightforward one. Hermesianax interprets the classics, searching for hidden clues from
which he reconstructs the stories of numerous love affairs, as the example of Hesiod’s love
for “Ehoia” illustrates. In this aspect, his mode of reading is similar to (or perhaps a parody
of) that of the allegorical interpreters of ancient epic, who strove to find the deeper truth
under the words of the poets, their so‐called ὑπόνοια. 62 The Leontion thus testifies to the belief
that literature depicts reality through a distorted lens. Hence, it is implied that literature
demands an informed (or biased?) reader to reveals its deeper meanings, such as, in this
case, that all poets wrote out of love. 63
In the process, Hermesianax is actually reversing this allegorical mode of reading: in
order to understand the alleged facts in the Leontion (“all poets wrote out of love”), the
reader has to be aware of the true facts of Greek literary history, for instance, that “Ehoia”
was not a girl, but the recurrent phrase opening a new passage in Hesiod’s Catalogue of
Women. Being able to recognize the many distorted allusions to the life and works of the
poets of the past is essential in order to unravel the logic of Hermesianax’ fictions (or the
method to his madness). The Leontion thus demonstrates on two levels the idea that all
literature, no matter how fantastic, is ultimately reducible to the true events that lie at the
60 For the idea of poetry as spiritual offspring, cf. Pl. Symp. 209c‐d.
61 The formula at the beginning “Οἵην μὲν” (cf. 85) reads like a reference to the Megalai Ehoiai. Some
examples in the fragment conform to the logic that “name of the work = name of beloved” viz. Nanno,
Lyde, Bittis. In others the explanation of the love affair is sought in well known anecdotes or legends
about a poet or philosopher (e.g. Orpheus’ love for Argiope), historical closeness (Alcaeus and
Anacreon rivals for Sappho’s love, Socrates in love with Aspasia, Aristippus in love with the famous
courtesan Lais). In some cases, the explanation remains obscure (Euripides, Sophocles, Pythagoras).
62 See on ancient allegory and its history in general Struck (2005) and (2005b: 147‐166). Porter (1992: 67‐
115) discusses Crates of Malles’ (third cent. BCE) allegorical exegesis of Homer. An earlier example is
Metrodorus of Lampsacus (fifth cent. BCE) fr. 61,3 DK. His interest is the true meaning of Homer’s
gods. The Derveni papyrus exemplifies allegorical interpretation of Orphic hymn.
63 Note the emphasis on knowing in the fragment, e.g. 49, 73, 75, cf. Caspers (2006: 24): only the
educated reader could be expected to understand the subtle allusions in the apparently trivial stories.
67
basis of its conception. 64 Explicitly (and playfully), it claims that love is at the basis of all
great Greek poetry. Implicitly (and factually), it forces the reader to realize that all of these
outrageous claims have their basis in deliberately misinterpreted facts: whereas it is true that
Homer wrote about Ithaca and Penelope, it is presumably not true (nor was it generally
believed) that he did so out of love for Penelope.
On another level, the fact that Hermesianax presents all great poets from the Greek
tradition as erotic poets (albeit in disguise) evidently serves to justify his own choice of erotic
elegy as a genre. In last instance, it may be asked if this biased and willful reading of Greek
literature as one great erotic elegy intends to ridicule the process of choosing models to
reflect the poet’s own image or, as the case might be, distorting them somewhat to do so.
Perhaps Hermesianax aimed to highlight the dangers of misinterpretation that can be
incurred by literary appropriation through playful exaggeration of this principle.
2.5 Avoiding Ancient Poets
In a few cases, an ancient poet is advised against as a model. According to generations of
early modern scholarship, the most notable case in point was Homer. They assumed that
Callimachus rejected Hellenistic writers of heroic epic who tried to imitate, or emulate
Homer, such as Apollonius (cf. Chapter 4). It is however the question whether Callimachus
actually warned against “Homeric” poetry in particular, and if he did, why. Let us cast a
brief glance at some passages relevant to this issue.
2.5.1 Dangers of Imitating Homer
To begin with, the end of Callimachus’ Hymn II has often been read as a deprecation of poets
who follow Homer:
ὁ Φθόνος Ἀπόλλωνος ἐπ’ οὔατα λάθριος εἶπεν∙
“οὐκ ἄγαμαι τὸν ἀοιδὸν ὃς οὐδ’ ὅσα πόντος ἀείδει.”
τὸν Φθόνον ὡπόλλων ποδί τ’ ἤλασεν ὧδέ τ’ ἔειπεν∙
“Ἀσσυρίου ποταμοῖο μέγας ῥόος, ἀλλὰ τὰ πολλά
λύματα γῆς καὶ πολλὸν ἐφ’ ὕδατι συρφετὸν ἕλκει.
Δηοῖ δ’ οὐκ ἀπὸ παντὸς ὕδωρ φορέουσι μέλισσαι,
A concept also found for instance in the contemporary Dionysius Scytobrachion’s rationalized
64
reading of the Argonautic quest, cf. Rusten (1982). Cf. Euhemerus and his rationalizing treatment of
myth, explaining away from religion all that was supernatural.
68
ἀλλ’ ἥτις καθαρή τε καὶ ἀχράαντος ἀνέρπει
πίδακος ἐξ ἱερῆς ὀλίγη λιβὰς ἄκρον ἄωτον.”
χαῖρε, ἄναξ, ὁ δὲ Μῶμος, ἵν’ ὁ Φθόνος, ἔνθα νέοιτο. (Hymn II, 105‐113)
Envy whispered into Apollo’s ear: ”I don’t like a poet who does not sing as much as
the sea.” Apollo kicked Envy aside and said, “The Assyrian river rolls a massive
stream, but it’s mainly silt and garbage that it sweeps along. The bees bring water to
Deo not from every source, but only where it bubbles up pure and undefiled from a
holy spring, its very essence.”(transl. Nisetich)
Williams here understands the enigmatic reference to “the sea” as an allusion to Homer,
explaining the passage as follows:
Phthonos’ complaint is that Callimachus does not emulate even the length of Homer’s
poems (...) Apollo, expressing of course Callimachus’ own views, rejects the
suggestion that poems which are merely lenghy are by that token “Homeric” (...)
Callimachus’ own goal is to emulate and recreate Homer in a more meaningful and
original way than merely to reproduce slavishly the external dimensions of his epic.
(Williams, 1978: 85‐89) 65
This (i.e., “to reproduce slavishly the external dimension of epic”) is in turn often interpreted
as a covert reference to the practices of Apollonius, whose lengthy and apparently Homeric
Argonautica would be the real target of Apollo’s and hence Callimachus’ mudslinging. 66 As
Cameron and Köhnken make clear, however, there are no cogent reasons to believe that this
passage contains an allusion to Homer. For one thing, the metaphor of Homer as “the sea,” is
not attested before Hellenistic times, which would make Callimachus the first to use this
rather oblique way of referring to him. The issue here is rather one of “size” as such. 67 All
that this text makes clear is that Callimachus advises against writing long poems for the sake
of size, not necessarily against writing Homeric poems. While it is true that the Iliad and the
65 Williams is supported by Giangrande (1980: 57‐67) and Asper (1997: 120‐125). Full bibliography on
the passage up to 1989: Lehnus (1989: 233‐41). Williams’ claim is disputed by Köhnken (1981: 411‐ 422)
and Cameron (1995: 404‐407).
66 Cf. e.g. Kahane (1994: 121), with bibliographical references. Strootman (forthcoming, 2009) on the
other hand proposes a novel interpretation: the Assyrian river (the Orontes rather than the Euphrates
as is generally believed) is an implicit reference to the court of the Sassanids in Assyria and hence to
poets who were working under their patronage. The remark of Apollo implies that they write
ponderous and unrefined poetry. Ultimately, this constitutes an implied compliment to the literary
taste of Callimachus’ own patron, who appreciates small and refined poetry. This interpretation
certainly provides an elegant explanation for the choice of the Assyrian river. Strootman does not need
to bring in Homer to make his point.
67 Köhnken (1981: 411‐422) and Cameron (1995: 404‐407), cf. Traill (1998: 215‐222). For the frequent
opposition of big and unrefined versus small and elegant in Callimachus (without specific references
to Homer), see. Asper (1997: 135‐153).
69
Odyssey were, for a long time, not only the greatest but also probably among the most
sizeable poems in Greek literature, this does not necessarily mean that Homer’s poetics are
being criticized.
The next alleged reference to Homer and the dangers of imitating him is found in the
Aetia prologue itself, where Apollo counsels against driving along the “broad way,” a phrase
understood as referring to epic poetry in the vein of Homer. The phrase in question is found
in lines 25‐28:
καὶ γὰρ ὅτε πρώτιστον ἐμοῖς ἐπὶ δέλτον ἔθηκα
γούνασιν, Ἀ[πό]λλων εἶπεν ὅ μοι Λύκιος∙
“.......]... ἀοιδέ, τὸ μὲν θύος ὅττι πάχιστον
θρέψαι, τὴ]ν̣ Μοῦσαν δ’ ὠγαθὲ λεπταλέην∙
πρὸς δέ σε] καὶ τόδ’ ἄνωγα, τὰ μὴ πατέουσιν ἅμαξαι
τὰ στείβειν, ἑτέρων ἴχνια μὴ καθ’ ὁμά
δίφρον ἐλ]ᾶ̣ν μηδ’ οἷμον ἀνὰ πλατύν, ἀλλὰ κελεύθους
ἀτρίπτο]υ̣ς, εἰ καὶ στειν̣οτέρην ἐλάσεις.” (fr. 1. 21‐28 Pf.)
For, the very first time I put a writing tablet on my knees, Apollo Lycius said to me:
“[Remember, dear] poet, to [fatten] the victim for me as much as you can, but, my
friend, to keep the Muse elegant. [And I’m telling you another thing]: take the roads
that are not open to hackneys and do not drive your [chariot] in the ruts of others and
not over the broad way, but on [untrodden] paths, even if that means driving along a
narrower lane.”
For this passage, a Pindaric subtext was found, namely in the (problematic) text of Paean 52h
Snell‐Maehler: 68 Ὁμήρου [δὲ μὴ τρι]π̣τὸν κατ’ ἀμαξιτόν / ἰόντες, ἀ̣[λλ’ ἀλ]λοτρίαις ἀν’
ἵπποις (Not going through the worn wagon tracks of Homer, but drawn by another’s
indirect reference to Homer. However, as Asper has pointed out, the supplement of the
Pindaric Paean is far from secure. 69 It seems Snell and Maehler, in their search for a
supplement, were influenced by the supplement of Aetia prologue 28 and thought they had
found a precedent for Callimachus’ anti‐Homer polemics in Pindar. It is clear at any rate that
the advice of Apollo at Aetia fr. 1.28 implies the same stance towards poetics as the god
expresses at the end of Hymn II: a preference for small, delicate, and refined poetry rather
68 Asper (1997: 64‐72) denies that the metaphor of the road points back to any one particular poetic
text; it was widespread.
69 Asper (1997: 66‐69). The problems of the supplement are manifold: ἀμαξιτός is feminine and
τριπτός is always of three endings; moreover the π of τριπ]τός in Pindar is far from certain.
70
than poetry on a grand scale, perhaps including but certainly not limited to Homeric
imitation.
Finally, it has often been argued that Theocritus was a supporter of these
“Callimachean poetics” on the basis of “his” verdict on the followers of Homer. In reality, the
opinion at stake is expressed by the goatherd poet Lycidas, who speaks to the young
aspiring poet Simichidas in Id. 7 as follows:
ὥς μοι καὶ τέκτων μέγ’ ἀπέχθεται ὅστις ἐρευνῇ
ἶσον ὄρευς κορυφᾷ τελέσαι δόμον Ὠρομέδοντος,
καὶ Μοισᾶν ὄρνιχες ὅσοι ποτὶ Χῖον ἀοιδόν
ἀντία κοκκύζοντες ἐτώσια μοχθίζοντι. (Id. 7.45‐48)
For much I hate the builder who seeks to raise his house as high as the peak of mount
Oromedon, and much those cocks of the Muses who lose their toil with crowing
against the bard of Chios. (transl. Gow)
Lycidas explicitly criticizes the mistaken idea that Homer’s poetry could and should be
imitated. The result of such imitatio Homerica is inevitably liable to uncomplimentary
comparison with the original; in a sense, it is as ridiculous as a house that strives to be as
high as a mountain. More to the point, however, is the fact that in the context of Idyll 7
Lycidas’ interlocutor Simichidas, the young and aspiring poet, has just expressed his
conviction that he is “not yet” as good as Asclepiades and Philitas, two established great
names of the early Hellenistic age (39‐41). 70 What Lycidas is also implying, therefore, is: “be
careful to whom you compare yourself.” 71 Seen in this light, the phrase expresses Lycidas’
verdict on the poetic capacities of Simichidas rather than the value of Homer’s poetry.
To recapitulate, whether or not a warning against imitating Homer should be sought
in Callimachus’ poetry is difficult to establish, but the idea that new poetry should be on a
small scale and innovative and not follow the “well‐trodden paths” appears to be shared by
both Callimachus and Theocritus, as their common imagery of big (and ridiculous and
unrefined) versus small (and modest and elegant) suggests. If Callimachus is indeed
advising against imitations of Homer, it is presumably because Homer is so great; like
Theocritus, he fears the result of an unsuccessful imitation of Homer.
70 Cf. Segal (1974: 128‐136).
71 More on this passage in Ch. 5.4.
71
This fear is easy to comprehend. It is probably no exaggeration to say that the
consensus about Homer’s prime importance and greatness is constant throughout Greek
history, even if occasional criticism may have been leveled at the historical truth of his
poems. The fact remains that Iliad and Odyssey together formed the greatest and most central
poems in the Greek language. To try and rival a classic so ingrained in Greek consciousness
was not only a supreme sign of hubris, it was also completely ridiculous. It might be possible
to study Homer in a philological context but not to imitate him, let alone hope to emulate
him on his own terms.
There is, however, one interesting exception to confirm this general rule: in one
epigram the 300 (hexameter) verses of Erinna, a poet from the comparatively recent past, are
said to equal Homer. From this example, it may be concluded that comparison with Homer
is only possible when the comporanda are so different as to have virtually nothing in common:
Λέσβιον Ἠρίννης τόδε κηρίον∙ εἰ δέ τι μικρόν,
ἀλλ’ ὅλον ἐκ Μουσέων κιρνάμενον μέλιτι.
οἱ δὲ τριηκόσιοι ταύτης στίχοι ἶσοι Ὁμήρῳ,
τῆς καὶ παρθενικῆς ἐννεακαιδεκέτευς∙
ἣ καὶ ἐπ’ ἠλακάτῃ μητρὸς φόβῳ, ἣ καὶ ἐφ’ ἱστῷ
ἑστήκει Μουσέων λάτρις ἐφαπτομένη.
Σαπφὼ δ’ Ἠρίννης ὅσσον μελέεσσιν ἀμείνων,
Ἤριννα Σαπφοῦς τόσσον ἐν ἑξαμέτροις. (AP 9.190, anonymous)
This is the Lesbian honeycomb of Erinna; and if it be small, well, it is all put together
from the honey of the Muses. Her three hundred verses equal Homer–and that for a
girl of only nineteen years old. She, the servant of the Muses, stood bound to the
spindle and the loom out of fear of her mother. And as much as Sappho surpasses
Erinna in melic poetry, so much Erinna surpasses Sappho in hexameters.
Homer was the undoubted non plus ultra of Greek poetry; Erinna reputedly a girl of nineteen
who had written 300 lines lamenting her dead childhood friend Baucis. The feminine,
unassuming pathos of Erinna’s poetry is here provocatively set off against the war‐and
adventure‐ridden, all‐encompassing heroic poetry of Homer. Her few lines, the epigram
claims, rival Homer for quality. The comparison is unlikely, and preference for the scanty
lines Erinna left over the universally acknowledged founding text of Greek culture signifies
both a marginal taste and a deliberate provocation. 72 These appear to be implicitly admitted
For praise of Homer in Hellenistic epigram: AP 7.1, 7.2, 7.4, 7.80, 9.24, on which see in particular
72
Skiadas (1965).
72
by the author because he also compares Erinna to Sappho, to whom she is much more
similar (hence the epithet “Lesbian” qualifies Erinna’s work). One element in the comparison
to Sappho suggests a possible reason why the comparison with Homer was broached: both
Homer and Erinna wrote hexameters. All other factors considered, the difference could not
have been greater and hence the comparison more unexpected.
2.5.2 Dangers of Liking Antimachus
The category of “predecessors not to be imitated” also contains poets nearer to the
Hellenistic era, such as Antimachus of Colophon, criticized by Callimachus in fr. 398 (cf.
below), as a writer of obtuse and unclear poetry. 73 Apart from the question of his poetic
merits (which are hard to evaluate, owing to the state of his works), 74 his proximity to
Callimachus’ own time and practice might have been reason for Callimachus to criticize
Antimachus. Alan Cameron claims it may be that Callimachus regarded Antimachus as an
imitator of Homer in the wrong mode; Antimachus was apparently prone to literal citation
of Homer to an extent that is not found and perhaps therefore unacceptable in Hellenistic
poetry. As has been demonstrated, Callimachus certainly did not reject Homer per se but may
have loathed dull imitatio Homerica all the more. Moreover, since both poets wrote
conspicuously learned elegies (the Lyde and the Aetia, respectively), there may have been
another reason why Callimachus found so much fault with Antimachus. Maybe he found
that Antimachus’ practice was was too close to his own, but in a manner which he could not
appreciate.
On the other hand, it appears that Antimachus was not rejected wholesale by the
Hellenistic poets (cf. Asclepiades AP 9.63, Posidippus AP 12.168). 75 In an earlier generation,
he was apparently admired. 76 In Asclepiades’ epigram AP 9.63, the elegiac Lyde, Antimachus’
most famous poem declares herself to possess undying fame, thanks to her author:
73 On Antimachus in general, see Wyss (1936) and Matthews (1996).
74 Antimachus appears to have been a learned poet, writing in a mannered style, with preference for
obscure words; characteristics he shares with some of the Hellenistic poets, e.g. Callimachus. On
Callimachus’ evaluation of Antimachus, see Brink (1946: 11‐26), Krevans (1993: 141‐161), Cameron
(1995: 301‐309).
75 Posidippus names Antimachus in one breath with Mimnermus, whom Callimachus names as his
model in Aetia fr. 1 Pf.
76 Cf. Brink (1946: 11‐26).
73
Λύδη καὶ γένος εἰμὶ καὶ οὔνομα· τῶν δ’ ἀπὸ Κόδρου
σεμνοτέρη πασῶν εἰμι δι’ Ἀντίμαχον.
τίς γὰρ ἔμ’ οὐκ ἤεισε; τίς οὐκ ἀνελέξατο Λύδην,
τὸ ξυνὸν Μουσῶν γράμμα καὶ Ἀντιμάχου; (AP 9.63)
Lyde am I, by descent and by name, and thanks to Antimachus I am more famed than
all the descendants of Codrus. For who has not sung of me? Who has not read the
Lyde, the joint writing of Antimachus and the Muses?
Lyde, who had introduced herself in the first line as a woman, finally reveals herself for what
she is: “the joint writing (γράμμα) of Antimachus and the Muses.” She has become a lady of
letters in the most literal sense. The clever tournure, turning a woman into a book in the
course of four verses, reflects what Antimachus has done with his love for Lyde in the course
of the long process of writing his poetry. This is exactly what Callimachus seizes upon when
he ridicules the Lyde (fr. 398 Pf.). 77 His words cleverly parody the first line of Asclepiades:
Λύδη καὶ παχὺ γράμμα καὶ οὐ τορόν (Lyde, a thick and inarticulate book). The fact that the
book is immediately called (or calls itself, perhaps) a book (γράμμα) in Callimachus’
fragment might express his opinion that it did not have and never had had any life in it. The
scathing verdict that it is a piece of “thick/fat” (παχὺ) and “inarticulate” (οὐ τορόν) writing
demonstrates that Callimachus regarded it as nothing more than a piece of faulty
craftmanship. 78 He consciously subverts the image conjured up by Asclepiades’ praise that
Lyde was “a living woman turned poetry.”
Antimachus, then, is a model whose merits were still subject of debate at the time of
early Hellenism; could and should he serve as the model for Hellenistic poetic practice?
Callimachus thought this was not the case, and regrettably it is impossible to form an
opinion on his verdict, since history has deprived us of a possibility to form a clear image of
this intriguing poet.
77 On the controversy over Antimachus’ Lyde and Callimachus’ role in it, see e.g. Brink (1946: 11‐46),
Krevans (1993), Cameron (1995: 303‐339), the revisionary reading of Stephens (2005: 229‐236).
78 Krevans (1993: 157‐8) argues that the qualifications παχύς and οὐ τορός probably mean “verbose,
florid” and “metrically rough.” However, apart from these more technical‐rhetorical meanings, they
could also mean “fat/thick and inarticulate,” so the personification intended by Asclepiades would be
retained. See further Asper (1997: 160‐189).
74
2.6 Conclusion
This chapter has exemplified and analyzed some of the manifold ways of dealing with the
“cultural memory” of Greek poetry found in the works of Hellenistic poets, who imitate,
emulate, and alter their models. Sometimes a predecessor is introduced to underscore the
authority of a modern poet trying his hand at an old genre or creating a new one while
basing it (and himself) on old examples. Together with the genre, he literally wishes to bring
its originator back to life. At the same time, however, it is difficult to manage these poetic
models because they are the voices of authority.
It is less risky to choose a more indirect way of incorporating the models: not giving a
predecessor his own voice but naming him and referring to well chosen anecdotes from his
life instead. This is how Theocritus Id. 16 justifies his novel position of praising poet in the
age of paid poetry. Alternatively, models could be mutilated and reformed into a reflection
of the modern poet himself, as Hermesianax does in order to construct a long and venerable
tradition of erotic poetry inspired by a beloved (Leontion fr. 7 Powell). This is evidently not a
serious way of authenticating a new genre.
Finally, there is the issue of predecessors better avoided as models. These may be
either categorized hors concours, like Homer, or open to much criticism because are not yet
embedded in the established tradition, like Antimachus. This does not mean they are
unadmired or not imitated, but modeling poetry on them risks incurring the danger of
opposing critics.
This demonstrates that for poets of the early Hellenistic era there were many ways of
dealing with and regarding the past. However, one thing was clear: the past was always
present, and poets had to come to terms with it. Scholarly interest and the wish to find a
plausible model for poetry in changed circumstances inform the assimilations, critiques, and
reflections upon the cultural heritage that was gathered and considered as such for the first
time. Ultimately, the dictum taken from Bacchylides’ paean, “one poet learns from another,”
is still, or indeed, more than ever, valid in the Hellenistic period. The poets of the past taught
the Hellenistic poets who they were and how and what they should write. Metaphorically
speaking, they were the true Muses of the Hellenistic era; it was their cult that was celebrated
in the Museum of Alexandria.
75
76
CHAPTER 3:
INVENTION OF TRADITION IN HELLENISTIC POETRY: THE APPROPRIATION OF
MYTHICAL POETS
3.1 Introduction
As the previous chapter has demonstrated, (false) ascription of poetical ideas to poets of the
historical era, whose works were still there to be read, seems to have been recognized as
problematic in Hellenistic poetry. It may be asked how this issue was handled in the
Hellenistic treatment of mythical poets, whose works were no longer extant, or at best of
doubtful authenticity. There are clear differences in the way these poets are approached, as
this chapter will show through a discussion of two poets and their way of handling this
issue, Apollonius and Theocritus.
I will begin with the case of Apollonius’ Argonautica, focusing on his portrayal of the
mythical bard Orpheus. Orpheus’ introduction at the top of the catalogue of Argonauts as
the son of the Muse of epic, Calliope, has usually been interpreted as signifying that he is of
paramount importance to the subsequent narrative. 1 The entry in the catalogue introducing
him reads as follows:
Πρῶτά νυν Ὀρφῆος μνησώμεθα, τόν ῥά ποτ’ αὐτή
Καλλιόπη Θρήικι φατίζεται εὐνηθεῖσα
Οἰάγρῳ σκοπιῆς Πιμπληίδος ἄγχι τεκέσθαι.
αὐτὰρ τόνγ’ ἐνέπουσιν ἀτειρέας οὔρεσι πέτρας
θέλξαι ἀοιδάων ἐνοπῇ ποταμῶν τε ῥέεθρα∙
φηγοὶ δ’ ἀγριάδες κείνης ἔτι σήματα μολπῆς
ἀκτῇ Θρηικίῃ Ζώνης ἔπι τηλεθόωσαι
ἑξείης στιχόωσιν ἐπήτριμοι, ἃς ὅγ’ ἐπιπρό
θελγομένας φόρμιγγι κατήγαγε Πιερίηθεν.
Ὀρφέα μὲν δὴ τοῖον ἑῶν ἐπαρωγὸν ἀέθλων
Αἰσονίδης Χείρωνος ἐφημοσύνῃσι πιθήσας
δέξατο, Πιερίῃ Βιστωνίδι κοιρανέοντα. (Arg. 1.23‐37)
First then let us name Orpheus whom once Calliope bare, it is said, wedded to
Thracian Oeagrus, near the Pimpleian height. Men say that he by the music of his
songs charmed the stubborn rocks upon the mountains and the course of rivers. And
the wild oak‐trees to this day, tokens of that magic strain, that grow at Zone on the
Thracian shore, stand in ordered ranks close together, the same which under the
1 Orpheus’ position in the catalogue (1.23‐34) and its implications have been remarked upon by
practically everyone studying the Argonautica from antiquity (scholia) to modern times. For
bibliography, see Scherer (2002: 115, n. 386), Cuypers (2005: 58).
77
charm of his lyre he led down from Pieria. Such then was Orpheus whom Aesonʹs
son welcomed to share his toils, in obedience to the behest of Chiron, Orpheus ruler
of Bistonian Pieria. (transl. Seaton)
Strange as it may seem, however, this introduction seems to bear little relevance to the actual
feats of Orpheus in the rest of the epic. Although it is claimed here (ἐνέπουσιν, 4) that
Orpheus enchanted inanimate nature with his songs, and material remains (the oaks
standing in neat rows at cape Zone) are adduced as proof, Orpheus never explicitly performs
a similar miracle in the epic. 2 So what exactly is the meaning of this place of honor in the
catalogue of heroes? Scholars have often speculated that Apollonius wanted to identify
himself as narrator with Orpheus: Orpheus should be regarded as an intra‐textual alter ego
of the poet. Alternatively, they see in Orpheus the representation of the ideal singer, or a
man of brain (as opposed to a man of brawn like Heracles), or an Apollo‐like figure bringing
order and harmony (as opposed to the chthonic force embodied by Medea). 3 These
interpretations are of course not mutually exclusive and indeed help clarify the position he
takes in the epic as a character.
In this chapter, I will investigate in particular the claim that Orpheus should indeed
be interpreted as a text‐internal alter ego of the narrator/poet Apollonius. I will concentrate
in particular on the question which of Orpheus’ characteristics are highlighted and what this
can tell us about Apollonius’ own persona.
The case of Orpheus and Apollonius is not unique. The second part of the chapter
on and legitimize his poetical choices. It is my contention that a similar background informs
the choices of both poets for mythical singers. A brief glance at the position mythical poets
took in Greek culture and in particular Hellenism will illuminate this.
2 Orpheus comes closest to truly miraculous enchantment in 1.678‐9: the peaceful (enchanted?) fishes
swimming in the wake of Argo. The character of this scene is discussed by Levin (1971: 220), Vian
(1974: 77), Zanker (1987: 68), Clare (2002: 235). Another ambiguous scene is 2.159‐63, on which see
schol. ad 2.162‐3, Cuypers (1997: ad 2.162‐3), Clare (2002: 237‐8).
3 Identification with narrator: Fränkel (1968 ad 1.23), Hunter (1993: 120‐121), Cuypers (2004: 58); ideal
singer: Busch (1993: 301‐324); man of brain: Lawall (1966); Apollo‐related, bringer of harmony and
order: Clare (2002, passim). Scholarly attention has further focused on the cosmogony in 1.494‐511 and
its philosophical, theological and literary sources, especially Nelis (1992: 153‐170). See Scherer (2002:
115 n. 387) for further bibliography on Orpheus in the Argonautica.
78
3.2 The Greeks and the Mythical Poets
Cicero was certain there had been poets before Homer. He gives the following reason for this
assumption:
Nihil est enim simul et inventum et perfectum; nec dubitari debet quin fuerint ante Homerum
poetae, quod ex eis carminibus intellegi potest, quae apud illum et in Phaeacum et in
procorum epulis canuntur. (Brutus, 71)
For nothing is at the same time invented as it is perfected, and we need not doubt
that there were poets before Homer, as can be gathered from those lays in his works
which are sung at the banquets of the Phaeaceans and the suitors.
Broadly speaking, this was also the Greek point of view: 4 the Greeks told stories about
genealogies or miraculous deeds of pre‐Homeric bards such as Orpheus, Musaeus and
Linus. The status of these poets’ “works” was (and in Orpheus’ case remains) complicated.
Throughout antiquity, they occupied a different position than works ascribed to Hesiod and
Homer, who were generally believed to have been historical personages and were seen as
authors of a fixed corpus. The character and social function of works of historical and
mythical poets also differed. Whereas Homer and Hesiod had produced canonical works of
literature that were widely available and performed at public festivals, the so‐called Orphic
writings 5 “aspire to be more than poetry: an esoteric knowledge, revelation rather than
literature.” 6 Consequently, their place was at mystic rites in a select company of initiates
rather than at public festivities, and they were not used as educational texts in schools,
unlike Homer’s and Hesiod’s works.
The mythic or legendary status of poets such as Orpheus, Linus, and Musaeus
influenced the approach to their supposed works. Deliberate misattributions that endowed
what were actually new poems with an air of venerable antiquity and/or revelatory authority
can be traced as far back as the sixth century BCE; 7 false attributions to Orpheus and
4 Cf. e.g. Arist. Po. 1448b28‐30: τῶν μὲν οὖν πρὸ Ὁμήρου οὐδενὸς ἔχομεν εἰπεῖν τοιοῦτον
ποίημα, εἰκὸς δὲ εἶναι πολλούς, ἀπὸ δὲ Ὁμήρου ἀρξαμένοις ἔστιν. (We cannot name a similar poem
of anyone before Homer, although it is likely that there were many, yet we must start with Homer...).
5 The term is used widely here. De facto, there is little difference between writings attributed to
Orpheus and Musaeus, except that Orpheus was more popular, cf. West (1983: 39).
6 Burkert (1985: 296).
7 West (1983: 5).
79
Musaeus were taken for granted by Plato and Aristotle. 8 In addition, as mythical poets could
easily and safely be credited with controversial poetic ideas, they were ideal figures to be
cast as prōtoi heuretai: 9 there was no written proof to the contrary, which gave them a protean
quality. 10 The era and profession of the legendary bards moreover implied to later Greeks
that they were related more closely to the gods than contemporary humans were, 11 as they
were supposed to have lived in the heroic age and, as poets, were thought to enjoy
privileged relationships with the gods. 12 Orpheus, for example, was usually called the son of
the Muse Calliope or Polyhymnia and/or of the god of poetry, Apollo. 13 Poets who were so
close to the gods and to the origins of poetry were naturally considered endowed with great
authority in poetical matters. 14
The absence of a clearly established written legacy and a venerable position in
matters concerning poetry made mythical bards into ideal objects for interpretation,
projection, and appropriation by later poets. Focusing on Apollonius and Theocritus, this
chapter argues that these Hellenistic poets sought to establish their poetic authority by
taking recourse to such mythical poets. This may be explained as an example of what social
historian Eric Hobsbawm has called “the invention of tradition:”
8 Pl. Resp. 364e2‐365a3, cf. Arist. fr. 7 Rose (1, 5.1410b 28): “ἐν τοῖς Ὀρφικοῖς καλουμένοις ἔπεσι” (fr. F
3a sup.): “λεγομένοις” εἶπεν ἐπειδὴ μὴ δοκεῖ Ὀρφέως εἶναι τὰ ἔπη, ὡς καὶ αὐτὸς ἐν τοῖς περὶ
φιλοσοφίας λέγει∙ αὐτοῦ μὲν γάρ εἰσι τὰ δόγματα, ταῦτα δέ φησιν Ὀνομάκριτον ἐν ἔπεσι
κατατεῖναι. (“In the so‐called Orphic poems…” He says “so‐called” because he does not believe that
the poems are by Orpheus, as he says himself in his On Philosophy; for the teachings are Orphic, but
these things, he says, have been versified by Onomacritus). Cf. Cic. De Nat. Deor. 1.38: Orpheum poetam
docet Aristoteles numquam fuisse et hoc Orphicum carmen Pythagorei ferunt cuiusdam fuisse Cercopis. On the
identity of early forgers of Orphic texts and their motives, cf. West (1983: 15).
9 On the concept of the prōtos heuretēs, see Kleingünther (1933), cf. DNP s.v.: “Ihre heurēmata sind von
Beginn an ausgereift, so daß Erfinder nicht nur die »ersten«, sondern gleichzeitig die »besten« sind.”
Gutzwiller (1991: 4): “Origin implies the source, the first time that establishes the pattern for all time,
the authorizing event and so the authority… The appeal of origins is (...) that of value; the first is
inherently the best, because it sets the standard by which the thing begun is measured ever after.”
10 The (false) ascription of poetical innovations to a venerable forebear was more of a problem in the
case of poets of the historical era, whose works were still there to be read, cf. Ch. 2 passim.
11 Kleingünther (1933: 26), Sperduti (1950: 209 et passim). For the Hellenistic idea that former
generations held direct converse with the gods, cf. Arat. Phaen. 100‐136.
12 According to tradition, many of them had bonds of direct kinship with the gods, cf. Pl. Resp. 366b1:
οἱ θεῶν παῖδες ποιηταί (poets are the children of the gods).
13 See Kern ([1922]1972) test. 22‐23.
14 E.g. Sperduti (1950: 209‐240); for the idea that music and poetry were originally creations of the gods
themselves, see esp. 210‐213. E.g. Pi. fr. 31 Snell‐Maehler: Zeus created the Muses and Apollo
especially to praise the cosmos in words and music; H.H. 4.420‐423 describes the invention of the lyre
by Hermes; Pi. P. 12.6ff describes the invention of the flute by Athena.
80
The peculiarity of invented traditions is that the continuity with [the past] is largely
factitious. In short, they are responses to novel situations, which take their form of
reference to old situations. (…) There is probably no time and place with which
historians are concerned that has not seen the “invention” of tradition in this sense.
However, we should expect it to occur more frequently when a rapid transformation
of society weakens or destroys the social patterns for which the old traditions had
been designed, producing new ones to which they were not applicable, or when such
old traditions and their institutional carriers and promulgators no longer prove
sufficiently adaptable and flexible or are otherwise eliminated; in short, when there
are sufficiently large and rapid changes… (Hobsbawm, 1983: 1‐4)
It is generally acknowledged that the early Hellenistic era was indeed a period of rapid
found in this era, in literature, religion and court ritual amongst others. 16 The main use to
which invented traditions are put, according to Hobsbawm, is “the establishing or
legitimizing of institutions, status, or relations of authority” (1983: 7). Something similar is
done by the Hellenistic poets to establish and legitimize their authority as poets in the
venerable continuum of Greek poetical culture. How this applies to the character of Orpheus
in the Argonautica will be the subject of the following section.
3.3 Orpheus in Greek Tradition up to the Hellenistic Era
In order to appreciate the associations Orpheus carried for readers of Apollonius’
Argonautica, one must be aware of the way he was viewed by the Greeks in general. He
enjoys a special position in Greek culture, being neither a fully legendary or divine figure
(e.g. Heracles or Dionysus) nor a plausible historical author (such as Homer or Solon). As
Martin West puts it: “The stories portray him not as a distant forerunner of Homer, but a
singer of a different type: one who can exercise power over the natural world and who can
countermand death itself, a “shamanistic” figure... “ 17
15 Cf. e.g. Fraser (1972: I, introduction), Bing (1988), Hunter (1996: 1‐3), Fantuzzi and Hunter (2004: viii;
17‐26).
16 Cf. the remarkable popularity of aetiology in Hellenistic poetry, which illustrates how the search for
(fictitious/factitious) origins to ground contemporary usage (some no doubt of rather recent origin) in
a venerable shared past takes a great flight. For more remarks on the importance of the past in
Ptolemaic ideology and hence in Alexandrian literature, see Ch. 1.3.
17 Such shamanistic features are e.g. his enchantment of nature, his ability to travel into the realm of
the dead and communicate with the souls of the dead (West 1983: 4‐5).
81
Four basic elements in the myth of Orpheus have been attested since classical times: 18
1) he was a singer and lyre player able to enchant inanimate and animate nature; 19 2) he was
an Argonaut; 20 3) he (successfully or otherwise) prevailed upon the powers of the
netherworld to release his wife; 21 4) he was killed by Maenads or Thracian women, in some
versions because they considered him the inventor of pederasty, in others because he refused
to honor Bacchus. 22
Although the myth surrounding him is therefore more or less consistent, Orpheus
remains controversial in many respects. Plato places him before the Trojan war. 23 Herodotus,
on the other hand, maintains that Orpheus is to be dated after Homer and Hesiod (Hist.
2.53). Aristotle did not even believe Orpheus had ever existed (cf. note 8). It is no surprise,
then, that the problems of authentication of Orphic writings are widely acknowledged. The
problematic Orphic corpus known to the classical and Hellenistic ages consisted of
Theogonies, hymns, oracles, and ritual verse relating to the afterlife and the mysteries that
allowed initiates access to it. 24 Different from the Orphic myth, however, it does not show
great consistency in beliefs or phrasing.
In Hellenistic poetry (third century BCE onwards), the basic image of Orpheus
remained substantially the same as in the classical age. There is however a novel, playfully
romanticized, approach to the myth of his love for his wife or his pederasty. These items in
his biography make him an excellent candidate for featuring as a kind of prōtos heuretēs of
heterosexual or homosexual erotic elegy/lyric monody, as in Hermesianax’ elegiac catalogue
of poets and their beloveds, Leontion (fr. 7.1‐14 Powell) and Phanocles’s Ἔρωτες ἢ Καλοί (fr.
1 Powell, an elegiac catalogue of homosexual loves).
18 The very first mention in Greek literature (Ibycus, sixth cent. BCE) already calls Orpheus
ὀνομάκλυτος, famous (fr. 25 PMG). All ancient testimonia regarding Orpheus may be found in Kern
(1972 [1922]); on Orpheus in general see also Guthrie (1952 [1935]), Robbins (1982), West (1983),
Burkert (1985: 296‐301), Segal (1989), Massaracchi (1993), Bernabé (2007).
19 E.g. Bacch. 289b; Aesch. Ag. 1630; Eur. Ba. 562; IA 1211‐1213, cf. Kern test. 47‐55.
20 Simon. fr. 567 (cf. 544‐8, 576, 595 PMG); Pi. P. 4.176; Herodorus 31F 42‐43. An alternative tradition
claimed Philammon was the Argo’s musician (Pherec. 3F26, cf. scholia ad Arg. 1.23). On the Sicyonian
treasury at Delphi (570‐560 BC), Argo is represented with two singers aboard, one identified as
ΟΡΦΑΣ (Mus. 1323‐1323a1210).
21 Eur. Alc. 357‐9, Pl. Symp. 179d, Isoc. Busiris 8.
22 Pl. Symp. 179d, Resp. 620a. Orpheus’ death at the hand of Maenads because of his refusal to honor
Bacchus also seems to have been the theme of Aeschylus’ Bassarae.
23 Pl. Leg. 677d; on Orpheus in Plato see Masaracchi (1993: 173‐195).
24 See in general West (1983).
82
3.4 Orpheus in the Argonautica
As noted, Orpheus is introduced quite emphatically at the top of the Catalogue of Argonauts
by Apollonius. This raises the expectation that his actions will be of paramount importance
to the epic. Yet, at first sight his importance is not so easy to define. He either sings or
instigates the foundation of new cults, but these actions hardly classify as heroic feats in the
traditional sense. Only when he saves the Argonauts from the Sirens does his presence on
the Argo seem fully justified (4.902‐909). 25
Since Orpheus is predominantly represented as a singer by Apollonius, it seems a
natural start to analyze his performances in this field closely. They comprise the following
passages: 26
(a) 1.494‐515: cosmogony/divine succession song
(b) 1.540: rowing song
(c) 1.569‐72: song for Artemis
(d) 2.161‐2: song to honor victory of Polydeuces over Amycus
(e) 2.685‐93: song for Apollo
(f) 4.902‐909: song against the Sirens (unclear what kind of song)
(g) 4.1158‐60 and 1193‐6: songs for the wedding for Jason and Medea
Considering the evident interest of Hellenistic scholarship in the historical development and
classification of poetry, it is profitable to ask what kind of songs Orpheus is presented as
singing and why, as well as how the Alexandrians would have classified them. 27 Some of the
passages fail to indicate whether a song (in the sense of melody and lyrics) is performed or
what kind of song it might be. These are items (b) (the “rowing song”) and (f) (the “song
25 Cf. schol. ad Arg. 1.23: ζητεῖται δέ, διὰ τί Ὀρφεὺς ἀσθενὴς ὢν συνέπλει τοῖς ἥρωσιν. (It is asked
why Orpheus, weak as he is, sailed along with the heroes). The explanation is extrapolated from
Apollonius’ own text: ὅτι μάντις ὢν ὁ Χείρων ἔχρησε δύνασθαι καὶ τὰς Σειρῆνας παρελθεῖν
αὐτοὺς Ὀρφέως συμπλέοντος. (Because Chiron, being a seer, prophesied that they could even pass
by the Sirens if Orpheus sailed along).
26 Other, dubious candidates are 1.1134‐7 (the dance for Rhea) and 4.1409‐1422 (prayer to the
Hesperides). The first is like a Pyrrhiche (armed dance); it is not certain whether Orpheus performs
music on this occasion; in the second case it is certain that he does not, but the passage resembles the
ὕμνος κλητικός, cf. Ardizzoni (1967: ad Arg. 4.1141). Prayer and hymn are often hard to distinguish,
cf. Furley and Bremer (2001: 3).
27 Suda s.v. Απολλώνιος states that Apollonius was head librarian of the Alexandrian library, so he
would have been interested in development and classification of poetry from a professional point of
view.
83
against the Sirens”). The rowing song (b), if indeed a song, must have concentrated on
rhythm rather than text. Orpheus here functions as the “keleustēs” of the Argonauts, ensuring
that their rowing will be orderly. It is noteworthy that the rowing of the Argonauts to
Orpheus’ accompaniment is compared to a dance for Apollo in the preceding lines. 28 As has
often been observed, this implies that the whole journey of the Argonauts is in some sense a
ceremony in honor of the god Apollo, just as the song of this entire exploit, the Argonautica, is
presented as a hymn in his honor (cf. below on Arg. 1.1‐4). This creates an implicit connection
between the author of the poem, Apollonius, and the musician who accompanies the rowing
Argonauts, Orpheus. The comparison moreover lends both Orpheus’ performance and the
act of rowing a religious aura thus emphasizing the association between Orpheus and
Apollo.
The musical performance that is aimed against the Sirens (f) is characterized as
κραιπνὸν ἐυτροχάλοιο μέλος ἀοιδῆς (a swift strain of rippling song). 29 This does nothing to
help classification; it might just be a more vigorous version of the rowing song (b). The last
phrase of the passage παρθενίην δ’ ἐνοπὴν ἐβιήσατο φόρμιγξ (and the lyre overcame their
maiden voice, 4.909) implies that the sound of the lyre is more important than any vocal
performance by Orpheus. The type of music is really irrelevant anyway, since the
performance’s sole function is to deafen the Argonauts to the dangerous voices of the Sirens.
28 Arg. 1.536‐541: οἱ δ’, ὥστ’ ἠίθεοι Φοίβῳ χορὸν ἢ ἐνὶ Πυθοῖ / ἤ που ἐν Ὀρτυγίῃ ἢ ἐφ’ ὕδασιν
Ἰσμηνοῖο / στησάμενοι, φόρμιγγος ὑπαὶ περὶ βωμὸν ὁμαρτῇ / ἐμμελέως κραιπνοῖσι πέδον
ῥήσσωσι πόδεσσιν— / ὧς οἱ ὑπ’ Ὀρφῆος κιθάρῃ πέπληγον ἐρετμοῖς / πόντου λάβρον ὕδωρ, ἐπὶ δὲ
ῥόθια κλύζοντο... (And just as youths set up a dance in honor of Phoebus either in Pytho or haply in
Ortygia, or by the waters of Ismenus, and to the sound of the lyre round his altar all together in time
beat the earth with swiftly moving feet; so they to the sound of Orpheus’ lyre smote with their oars
the rushing sea‐water and the surge broke over the blades... transl. Seaton).
29 Arg. 4.902‐909: (...) ἀπηλεγέως δ’ ἄρα καὶ τοῖς / ἵεσαν ἐκ στομάτων ὄπα λείριον∙ οἱ δ’ ἀπὸ νηός /
ἤδη πείσματ’ ἔμελλον ἐπ’ ἠιόνεσσι βαλέσθαι, / εἰ μὴ ἄρ’ Οἰάγροιο πάις Θρηίκιος Ὀρφεύς,
Βιστονίην ἐνὶ χερσὶν ἑαῖς φόρμιγγα τανύσσας, / κραιπνὸν ἐυτροχάλοιο μέλος κανάχησεν ἀοιδῆς,
/ ὄφρ’ ἄμυδις κλονέοντος ἐπιβρομέωνται ἀκουαί / κρεγμῷ∙ παρθενίην δ’ ἐνοπὴν ἐβιήσατο
φόρμιγξ. (And suddenly to the heroes too, they sent forth from their lips a lily‐like voice. And they
were already about to cast from the ship the hawsers to the shore, had not Thracian Orpheus, son of
Oeagrus, stringing in his hands his Bistonian lyre, rung forth the hasty snatch of a rippling melody so
that their ears might be filled with the sound of his twanging; and the lyre overcame the maidens’
voice. transl. Seaton). Kyriakou (1995: 190‐205) and Hunter (1996: 146‐147) propose to interpret this
passage as a meta‐poetical statement in which Orpheus stands for “new music” drowning out
Homeric epic; I prefer to follow Knight (1995) and read the passage as a reworking of and reaction to
the Homeric passage, cf. Klooster (2007: 185‐200). For the significance of the Homeric Sirens, cf.
Gresseth (1970: 203‐218) and Pucci (1979: 121‐132); on Sirens in general, Hofstetter (1990).
84
As in the case of the rowing song, however, its purpose is to create order, or at least
counteract the power of the Sirens, who threaten the success of the journey.
The other songs (a, c, d, e, g) are more promising: they are united by a number of
prominent characteristics. Items (a) (c) and (e) all have religious contents. Item (a) is a
cosmogony/divine succession song; 30 (c) and (e) are both hymns to Apollo and to his sister
Artemis. Item (g) refers to the epithalamia/hymenaea (wedding songs) for Jason and Medea; 31
these may also be said to contain a religious aspect since they address invocations to
Hymenaeus (4.1197) and Hera (4.1199). 32 Item (d) finally celebrates the victory of one of the
Dioscuri (Polydeuces) over Amycus, King of the Bebrycians, in a boxing match. This is once
more a celebration of victory of order and civilization (in the figure of Polydeuces) over
barbarian custom (in the form of Amycus); we will return to this passage below. In
conclusion, the uniting characteristics of the songs are religious context and lyric
accompaniment. In addition, the word ἐμμελέως (harmonious) returns in passages (b), (g),
and (d) describing the actions of the Argonauts. It suggests harmony (a form of order, cf. LSJ
s.v. ἐμμελής II).
Now a number of questions suggest themselves. Why do Orpheus’ performances
share the characteristics detailed above? Is Orpheus presented as the prōtos heuretēs of the
poetic forms he is performing (as in the contemporary works of Phanocles and Hermesianax,
cf. previous section)? And how do his performances fit in with the alleged identification of
Orpheus and Apollonius’ poetical persona? To answer this, it would be helpful to know how
Alexandrian contemporaries of Apollonius, and hence Apollonius himself, would have
regarded Orpheus’ songs. Although little direct evidence regarding Alexandrian poetic
taxonomy survives, it is possible to form a reasonably plausible picture by looking at
theories of previous and later thinkers.
Orpheus’ songs are religious lyric music. How would they have been classified? In
Plato’s writings, there is a main distinction between secular (ἐγκώμια) and religious poetry
30 On possible points of contact with Orphic lore, cf. West (1983: 116). There also appears to be
Empedoclean influence underlying the form of the cosmogony here, cf. scholia ad loc. and Levin (1971:
217).
31 The fact that the epithalamium was sung twice caused Fränkel to excise lines 4.1193‐6. Ardizzoni
(1967 ad loc.) points out that there are two kinds of epithalamia: the katakoimetika (on the eve of the
wedding) and the orthria or diegertika (to raise the newlyweds). This suggests that Apollonius was
aware of the finesses of tradition.
32 On the hymnic features of epithalamia, cf. Furley and Bremer (2001: 32).
85
(ὕμνοι, Resp. 607a5). However, in the Leges, there is a different distinction, namely between
(hexameter) hymns proper (ὕμνοι) and genres such as paeans, dithyrambs, and nomes: 33
(…) καί τι ἦν εἶδος ᾠδῆς εὐχαὶ πρὸς θεούς, ὄνομα δὲ ὕμνοι ἐπεκαλοῦντο∙ καὶ
παίωνες ἕτερον, καὶ ἄλλο, Διονύσου γένεσις οἶμαι, διθύραμβος λεγόμενος. (Leg. 700b1‐5)
For there was a type of song that consisted of prayers to the gods and they were
called “hymns”; and “paeans” were another type, and there was another, about the
birth of Dionysus, I think, called the “dithyramb.”
The Alexandrian scholar Didymus (second century BCE) adheres to the first distinction,
using the term ὕμνος for the genus of religious song and particular names (paean, etc.) for
the species or subcategories. 34 It is probable that the Alexandrian contemporaries of
Apollonius would have followed this latter system of categorization, 35 which means that
they would have considered the majority of Orpheus’ songs as types of hymn: religious song
praising the gods
Returning to the first question posed above, it is now clear why Orpheus should be
represented as performing these songs: this is entirely in line with the traditional Greek idea
that the first poetry was composed as praise of the gods. Orpheus’ concerns are the origin of
the cosmos and the gods and their praises. This will prove important for answering the
question of how Orpheus is related to Apollonius’ persona.
The second question was whether the poet casts him as the prōtos heuretēs of the songs
he performs. 36 Overall, it does not appear that Apollonius had any special interest in
presenting him thus, with one possible exception, namely the song Orpheus sings to
celebrate Polydeuces’ victory in the boxing match (item d). This holds, as I argue, some
special clues. It is sung to celebrate a victory in a boxing match; the term Apollonius uses to
describe it, however, is ὕμνος (hymn). This has caused surprise and misunderstanding, 37
since, as we saw, in ancient poetic taxonomy, “hymn” primarily indicated “a song in honor
of a god” while here the Argonauts sing in honor of their crewmember Polydeuces, whom
33 Cf. Proclus (Phot. Bibl. 320a19‐20), who states that the hymn proper (kuriōs hymnos) is sung round the
gods’ altar to the accompaniment of the lyre.
34 So Didymus, quoted by Orion (p. 155‐6) and Proclus Phot. Bibl. 320a12‐17.
35 Cf. Furley and Bremer (2001: 14).
36 Orpheus is not presented as first kitharistēs ever either, cf. the references to Amphion (Arg. 1.740).
37 The scholiast thinks a ὕμνος has to praise an Olympian god, since he interprets “the Therapnaean
son of Zeus” as Apollo (schol. ad 1.162‐3), like Färber (1932: 81). However, the phrase must indicate
Polydeuces, the son of Zeus, who was born and had a cult in Therapnae, Sparta (cf. Vian 1974 ad loc.).
86
they do not revere as a god elsewhere. 38 However, as Hermann Fränkel (1968, ad loc.)
suggests, the passage should perhaps be interpreted as describing the origins (aitia) of
epinician ode. Apollonius would have been aware that these odes often contained hymnic
elements praising gods or heroic athletes, especially the Dioscuri and Heracles. 39 He sought
to explain this fact by making Orpheus, a contemporary of these heroes, the inventor of the
genre, the singer of a proto‐epinician hymn. It is unclear whether this was his own invention
or that he was adopting received opinions unknown to later scholars. At any rate, it seems
clear that Apollonius portrays Orpheus as the inventor of epinician odes hymning heroes. So
there is another item that can be added to the list of characteristics defining Orpheus and his
music: the invention of epinician song, which praises heroes in a particularly hymnic
manner.
Besides his songs, Orpheus’ non‐musical actions are also important to the success of
the expedition on a number of occasions. The common denominator of these actions is once
more a religious component. In them, Orpheus functions as the mediator between the
Argonauts and the gods who helps to establish or restore the (disturbed) relationship
between humans and the divine world, often by introduction of a new cult. He is a kind of
priest who knows intuitively at which moment what kind of religious action is required
(dedication, prayer, apotropaic dance) to recreate the correct harmony between the divine
and the human world. Once more, then, religion and order seem at the basis of his actions.
Contrary to the seers who join the Argonautic quest (Idmon, Mopsus and Phineus), Orpheus
is no real prophet: he does not explicitly know or predict the will of the gods but can only
guess at it. However, this he does well, which gains him a position of great importance in the
community of the Argonauts. Significantly, in half of the occasions, the god to whom tribute
is paid is Apollo. Orpheus founds an altar to Apollo at Thynia (2.685‐93) and on different
occasions dedicates his lyre and a tripod to him (2.928‐9. 4.1547‐1459 resp.). He clearly is the
most important god to the expedition in the perception of Orpheus. 40 This he also appears to
be in the perception of the narrator who addresses the poem to him:
38 Cf. Pl. Resp. 607a: ὕμνους θεοῖς καὶ ἐγκώμια τοῖς ἀγαθοῖς. (Hymns for the gods and encomia for
noble men, cf. Leg. 822b).
39 The term “Castor‐ or Iolaos‐song” is used by Pindar (P. 2.69; I. 1.16), cf. Robbins (1997: 244).
40 The other occasions are: initiation of the Argonauts in the rites of the Cabiri (1.915‐7); instigation of
armed dance in honor of Great Mother (1.1134); prayer of appeasement to the Hesperides (4.1409‐
1422).
87
Ἀρχόμενος σέο Φοῖβε παλαιγενέων κλέα φωτῶν
μνήσομαι οἳ Πόντοιο κατὰ στόμα καὶ διὰ πέτρας
Κυανέας βασιλῆος ἐφημοσύνῃ Πελίαο
χρύσειον μετὰ κῶας ἐύζυγον ἤλασαν Ἀργώ. (Arg. 1.1‐4)
Beginning with you, Phoebus, I will recall the famous deeds of men born in olden
days, who steered Argo of the good rowing benches through the mouth of Pontus
and through the Cyanean Rocks on the behest of King Pelias, in search of the Golden
Fleece. (transl. Seaton)
It is through Apollo’s oracle that the expedition was set going, as the narrator reveals at the
beginning of his poem (Arg. 1.4, 8): before departure (1.359‐362 and 1.440‐7, through the
mouth of Idmon) it was prophesized that the Argonauts would accomplish their task if they
sacrificed to Apollo.
Concluding: Orpheus is a singer of hymns and the inventor of hymnic epinicia
praising heroes, with an especial interest in Apollo. This importance of Apollo will prove to
be another key to the portrayal of Orpheus and hence his function as alter ego of Apollonius,
as the next section will argue.
3.5 Orpheus and the Hymnic Argonautica
So what relevance does the portrayal of this epitome of religious poetic art and prophetic
insight have for the self‐representation of Apollonius’ poetic persona? The peculiar
beginning of the epic (Arg. 1.1‐4) cited above holds a clue. The significance of this hymnic
invocation to Apollo at the beginning of the epic Argonautica has been interpreted in various
ways. It has mostly been read as a reference to the traditional practice of starting an epic with
a hymn to a god (prooemium), as is the alleged function of the Homeric Hymns, 41 or the hymn
to the Muses at the beginning of Hesiod’s Theogony. 42 If this were true, the hymnic proem
would in the Argonautica’s case have been shortened to the mere invocation in the first line.
However, as was demonstrated, the god Apollo plays a key role in numerous instances in
41 Thuc. 3.104.4, a discussion of the relevance of this passage for the Homeric Hymns can be found in
Richardson (1974: 3‐5).
42 Hunter (1996: 49‐51) remarks upon the remarkable popularity of hymns in Hellenistic poetry, e.g.
Call. Hymns; the hymnic opening of Arat. Phaen.; Cleanthes’ Hymn to Zeus. Theocr. Id. 17 also plays
with the format of hymn; Id. 22 is a hymn, Id. 24 probably had a hymn‐like ending. The song about
Daphnis in Id. 1 is also called a hymn. This preference for hymns may have been influenced by the
god‐like status of the King (esp. Call. Hymn I and IV, Theoc. Id. 17, 22 and 24).
88
the Argonautica and is mentioned by name in a variety of contexts. This suggests that he is
continually important in the background and that this epic is, in a sense, both about him and
in praise of him. 43 The hymn‐like ending of the Argonautica, saluting the Argonauts as
μακάρων γένος (best translated as “race of gods” 4.1773‐81) 44 is also remarkable. It is
unparalleled in extant epic. 45 Yet, surely it goes too far to claim, as some have done, that the
whole Argonautica is intended as one long hymnic proem. 46 I would rather argue that the
incorporation of hymnic elements indicates that Apollonius wanted to relate his own epic
song to the songs of Orpheus, which, as we have seen, are predominantly hymn‐like and
often related to the worship of Apollo.
To make this more compelling, the invocation of Apollo at the beginning of the epic
should be taken into account. This passage, as many scholars have acknowledged, should be
connected to Orpheus’ own hymn to Apollo (2.702‐713), in which the voices of the narrator
and Orpheus blend so completely as to become indistinguishable:
(...) σὺν δέ σφιν ἐὺς πάις Οἰάγροιο
Βιστονίῃ φόρμιγγι λιγείης ἦρχεν ἀοιδῆς∙
ὥς ποτε πετραίῃ ὑπὸ δειράδι Παρνησσοῖο
Δελφύνην τόξοισι πελώριον ἐξενάριξεν,
κοῦρος ἐὼν ἔτι γυμνός, ἔτι πλοκάμοισι γεγηθώς
(ἱλήκοις∙ αἰεί τοι, ἄναξ, ἄτμητοι ἔθειραι,
αἰὲν ἀδήλητοι, τὼς γὰρ θέμις, οἰόθι δ’ αὐτή
Λητὼ Κοιογένεια φίλαις ἐνὶ χερσὶν ἀφάσσει).
πολλὰ δὲ Κωρύκιαι νύμφαι, Πλειστοῖο θύγατρες,
θαρσύνεσκον ἔπεσσιν, “ἵη ἵε” κεκληγυῖαι∙
ἔνθεν δὴ τόδε καλὸν ἐφύμνιον ἔπλετο Φοίβῳ. (Arg. 2.702‐713),
And with them Oeagrusʹ goodly son began a clear lay on his Bistonian lyre; how once
beneath the rocky ridge of Parnassus he slew with his bow the monster Delphyne, he,
43 Cf. Cuypers (2004: 44): “Apollo is the cause of the poem’s action, the cause of its narration and the
divine model of its main hero (Jason is associated with Apollo throughout the poem).” The name
Apollo recurs 21 times (bk 1: 307 360, 403, 410, 502, 759, 966, 1181, 1186; bk 2: 493, 686, 700, 927, 952, bk
3 1283; bk 4: 528, 612, 1218; 1548, 1714, 1759) while the epithet Phoebus returns seventeen times (bk 1:
1, 301, 353, 536, 759, bk 2: 216, 506, 702, 713, 847, bk 4: 529, 1490, 1493, 1550, 1702, 1717,1718) and
Paiēōn once (4.1511). Apollo plays hardly any role in book 3 (Medea’s love, the events in Colchis); this
fits the fact that Orpheus too is virtually absent in this book.
44 Cuypers (2004: 45); cf. on the similar phrase in Theoc. Id. 17, Fantuzzi (2001: 232‐241).
45 It does however find a striking parallel in the elegiac “New Simonides” (P. Oxy. 3965), which ends as
a hymn to the hero Achilles. See on this poem Boedeker and Sider (2001).
46 Cf. Hunter (1996: 46): “…the Argonautica of Apollonius is framed as a “Hymn to the Argonauts,”
that is, a hymn on the traditional “Homeric” model in which the central mythic narrative has been
greatly extended, but in which the hymnic frame remains.”
89
still young and beardless, still rejoicing in his long tresses. (May you be gracious!
Ever, O king, be your locks unshorn, ever unravaged; for so is it right. And none but
Leto, daughter of Coeus, strokes them with her dear hands.) And often the Corycian
nymphs, daughters of Pleistus, took up the cheering strain crying “Healer”; hence
arose this lovely refrain of the hymn to Phoebus. (transl. Seaton, adapted)
The passage begins as indirect discourse (Arg. 2.704‐5) but soon “slips into” direct address of
the god (Arg. 2.708). Thus, the distinction between the voices of the narrator and Orpheus
becomes difficult, if not impossible, which makes this one of the most significant
performances of Orpheus, if he is to be considered Apollonius’ text‐internal alter ego. 47
Orpheus is singing a hymn to Apollo, like the narrator of the Argonautica, 1.1‐4. He moreover
provides aitia for aspects of the cult of Apollo‐Paieon (2.711‐13), which again makes him
resemble the narrator, who recounts aitia for cults on numerous occasions in the epic. The
resemblances are enforced by the blending of voices with the result that both the narrator
and Orpheus seem simultaneously to be hymning Apollo.
A significant parallel for the hymn‐like ending of the epic in honor of the Argonauts
may be found in another performance of Orpheus, the epinician hymn for Polydeuces (2.161‐
2), singled out above. There, a (semi) mortal was given divine honor in song. This is
comparable to the explicit poetic aims of the Argonautica; the “men born long ago,”
(παλαιγενέων ... φωτῶν Arg. 1.1) whose deeds are sung of to honor Apollo, have become
“heroes”, a “race of gods” honored for their own sake in the process of the narration:
Ἵλατ’ ἀριστῆες, μακάρων γένος, αἵδε δ’ ἀοιδαί
εἰς ἔτος ἐξ ἔτεος γλυκερώτεραι εἶεν ἀείδειν
ἀνθρώποις... (Arg. 4. 1773‐5).
Be propitious, heroes, race of the gods, and may these songs grow sweeter to sing for
men from year to year...
The two dominant features of Orpheus’ portrayal, his hymnic interest in particularly Apollo
and his invention of an epinician hymn celebrating heroes, therefore emphatically return in
Apollonius narrating persona, which has recently been characterized as follows:
By assuming the role of a hymnic narrator, Apollonius underscores that the
Argonautica’s narrative goal is praising: praising both the gods and the “famous deeds
of men born long ago.” This double goal (simultaneous celebration of human exploits
and the gods) is shared with the victory odes of Pindar, whom we may regard as a
model for the Argonautica’s narrator. (Cuypers, 2004: 45)
47 Cf. Hunter (1993: 150‐1), Cuypers (2004: 59).
90
It may now however be added that Apollonius’ choice to endow his epic with these striking
formal characteristics of hymn may indicate that he wished to return to Orpheus’ preferred
genre, the songs of praise for the divine and for heroes, hymn. 48 Thus, with the form of the
Argonautica and his representation of Orpheus, Apollonius points to the beginnings and
original function of poetry: religious song that brings order and harmony to the world. In
doing so, at the same time he creates something seemingly new by combining generic
elements of two types of poetry which had in his day become distinct: epic and hymn.
The fact that this “epic hymn” should be dedicated to Apollo is unsurprising: Apollo
is the god of seers who set the expedition of the Argo in motion by his oracle and the god of
singers and poets who can appropriately be invoked at the beginning of any poetical
undertaking. 49 The importance of Apollo to the narrator of the Argonautica is reflected in the
close relationship Orpheus enjoys with this god. Orpheus forecasts his intentions accurately
and sings his praises.
And yet, at the occasion just discussed, Orpheus (or is it the narrator?) appears to
make a small mistake in his hymn to the god (Arg. 2.708‐10, the fact that he says Apollo’s
hair is still unshorn, while it is always unshorn). 50 While it is impossible to determine whether
this error should be attributed to Orpheus or the narrator, it is reminiscent of the narrator’s
own frequent professions of ignorance concerning events in the narrative, all of which were
predicted and set in motion by the oracles of Apollo.
I would suggest, therefore, that Apollonius (perhaps even playing on the meaning of
his name and his function as a ”priest of the Muses and Apollo” in the Museum of
Alexandria, cf. Chapters 7 and 8 respectively) wished to present himself as a latter‐day
embodiment of the Apollo‐related singer/religious expert Orpheus. 51 Like Orpheus, who is
48 Such praise was what the Greeks considered to be the original function of poetry, as is for instance
stated in the testimonium about Pindar fr. 31 Snell‐Maehler. This one‐sentence report says that Pindar
recounted the origin of all song thus: at the marriage of Zeus, or his ascendancy to power, Zeus asked
the gods what was needed to complete the cosmos and they asked for Muses to provide music and
words, to serve as “kosmos” (adornment, final ordering), cf. Snell (1975 [1946]: 94‐5), Ford (2002: 143).
49 The importance of Apollo (and the Muses) for the narrator is topic of Ch. 8.4‐5.
50 Cf. Cuypers (2004: 59‐60).
51 For the religious overtones of the Museum and its employees, see Fraser (1972: I, 324), Weber (1993:
353), (Too 1998: 119). The function Apollonius held as head of the library was called ἐπιστάτης or,
significantly, ἱερεῦς. Diod. Sic. calls the Alexandrian Library “sacred” (1.49.3). For the idea that
Orpheus in particular resembles the wise counselor‐type alter ego, as found in Hesiod, cf. Cuypers
(2004: 59, n. 30).
91
not entirely able to grasp the intentions of Apollo at the time of the events yet has a divinely
guided intuition, Apollonius has difficulty establishing their true narrative, which he
dedicates to the god who originally set them in motion and inspires him to sing of them
many centuries afterwards. Considering the resemblances and correspondences between the
narrator and the character Orpheus, the relevance of Apollonius’ Orpheus to Apollonius’
poetical persona becomes clear: his Orpheus is an illustration of Apollonius’ ideas about the
origins and aims of poetry and the role of religion in it. His ancient authority legitimates
contemporary poetical practice, especially Apollonius’ own.
3.6 Theocritus and the Origins of Bucolic Poetry
Since antiquity, the search for the origins of bucolic poetry has been a favorite scholarly
pursuit. 52 This ongoing interest can be partly explained by the fact that the first bucolic
poems known to us, those of Theocritus, 53 “inscribe within themselves a sense of tradition.” 54
Of course, there may have been singing rustics before Theocritus in historical reality as well
as in literary fiction, yet bucolic poetry as such remains a Hellenistic invention that must be
ascribed to Theocritus alone. This section will therefore analyze the way in which he creates
the impression that he works in a long standing tradition of singing herdsmen, illustrating
how he hints that he is following time‐honored practices and emulating predecessors while
actually establishing the tradition at the moment he is writing about it.
The first question that should be addressed is: what exactly is “bucolic poetry?” 55 It
would seem that this term goes back to passages in the Idylls themselves in which the
characters refer to their songs as βουκολικὰ ἀοιδά (bucolic song, Id. 1, 7). Bucolic
(βουκολικός) 56 literally means “related to ox herd/cowherd” (βουκόλος), but what exactly
52 Cf. Wendel (1914: 1‐13: Prolegomena), Reitzenstein (1893), Rosenmeyer (1969: Ch. “Beginnings”),
Halperin (1983), Nauta (1990), Gutzwiller (1991), Hunter (1999, 5‐12), Bernsdorff (2001).
53 The earliest collections that included Theocritus’ poetry (together with that of Moschus and Bion)
were called βουκολικά, cf. Nauta (1990: 117‐137) with bibliography. This is also the title Vergil
adopted for his pastoral poems, otherwise known as the Eclogues.
54 Hunter (2004: 83); on the topic of “beginnings,” see Gutzwiller (1991: 1‐5).
55 For the distinction bucolic versus pastoral, see e.g. Rosenmeyer (1969), Halperin (1983). Suffice it to
say that pastoral developed from bucolic.
56 For the connotations of βουκολικός, cf. Proleg. D8: τὰ τῶν ἀγροίκων ἤθη ἐκμάσσεται αὕτη ἡ
ποίησις, τερπνῶς πάνυ τοὺς τῇ ἀγροικίᾳ σκυθρωποὺς κατὰ τὸν βίον χαρακτηρίζουσα. (This kind
92
does “bucolic song” amount to? What are its particular formal and content‐related
characteristics? Is it a genre? An initial methodological problem is the distinction between
”the songs represented in the poems” and “the poems as written by Theocritus.” For the time
being, the term ”bucolic poetry” will be taken to mean both the Theocritean poems featuring
(singing) herdsmen and, within these poems, the songs that these herdsmen sing. 57
The use of hexameter, not a lyric but an epic metre, is prevalent in both the Idylls and
the songs of the herdsmen. The Idylls and the herdsmen’s songs moreover both contain a
high quantity of Doricisms sometimes mixed with epic Ionic forms. The Doricisms can
probably best be explained as a rendering of the dialect that was spoken in Theocritus’
hometown, Syracuse (a Corinthian colony), and perhaps more broadly in the region of south‐
eastern Sicily. 58 For contemporary audiences not from this area, however, they may have
carried associations with the choral lyric of tragedy or Pindaric epinician. Significantly, this
dialect and metre also occur in Idylls not featuring herdsmen. 59
A remarkable trait that calls attention to Theocritus’ role as author in fashioning the
written form and content of the poems is the artificiality and intertextuality of the language
of the Idylls. They employ an idiom that is wholly constructed and could never have been
spoken by the rural inhabitants of Sicily; 60 it is a bewildering mixture of high‐flown, allusive
Homerisms and down‐to‐earth, everyday colloquialisms. 61 The strange clashes between the
two stylistic levels within the idiom, and between the elevated metre and common subject
of poetry mimics the characters of rustics, characterizing the boorishness of those in the countryside
very charmingly and true to life). For βουκόλος as lowly slave, cf. Pl. Ion 540c.
57 The herdsmen regard the songs they perform as bucolic song (βουκολιάσδεσθαι or βουκολικά
ἀοιδά, cf. Id. 1.64 etc.; 7.36, 5.44, 5.69).
58 Ruijgh’s thesis (1984) that this dialect is an imitation of Cyrenaic elitist idiom cannot be considered
proven, in view of Theocritus’ Syracusan origin, cf. Hunter (1999: 21‐24). Still, the presence of Cyrenaic
forms in Theocritus’ Doric remains tantalizing, cf. Dover (1971: xxxvi‐xlv).
59 Excluding the Aeolic Idylls 28, 29, 30.
60 On the problems of establishing linguistic variants in the Idylls, cf. e.g. Dover (1971: xxxi‐xlv). He
names as sources for Theocritus’ diction: epic, Syracusan poets (Epicharmus, Sophron), choral lyric (in
particular Pindar, but possibly also the lost works of Simonides and Stesichorus) and individual Doric
dialects of Theocritus’ own time.
61 See Dover (1971: li), colloquialisms esp. in 5 and 10 (oaths and proverbs: e.g. 5.23: ὕς ποτ´ Ἀθαναίαν
ἔριν ἤρισεν… (the pig once challenged Athena...); 5.26‐7: τίς τρίχας ἀντ ἐρίων ἐποκίξατο; τίς δὲ
παρεύσας / αἰγος πρατοτόκοιο κακάν κύνα δήλετ’ ἀμέλγειν; (Who shears hairs for wool, or chooses
to milk a filthy bitch when a goat with her first kid stands ready? transl. Gow); Homerisms: e.g. 7.137:
κατειβόμενον κελάρυζε, 7.139: ἔχον πόνον, 11.27: ὁδὸν ἁγεμόνευον). For the idea of such
Homerisms as “genre‐markers” that simultaneously indicate the reference to and distance from the
original, cf. Zanker (1998: 225‐7).
93
matter emphasize the utter artificiality of the poetic world created by Theocritus. 62 It is
impossible to believe that ancient herdsmen spoke in this way; the reader is constantly
referred to the author who presents them as speaking thus. 63 At the same time, the epic
metre brings into question the position these poems take in the tradition of Greek heroic
poetry and the intertextuality is a warning that this poetry is not a product of spontaneous
creation on the hillsides of Sicily, but rather of a learned and playful reception of disparate
elements from the Greek literary heritage. 64 Once more, it should be pointed out that these
features are found not only in the bucolic Idylls, but are also shared by other works,
including the (urban) mimes 2, 14, and 15.
In bucolic song, one theme predominates: (unrequited) love (Id. 1, 3, 6, 7, 10, and
11). 65 Other recurrent motifs are the locus amoenus, described with the employment of many
would furthermore appear that in Greek poetry before Theocritus literary renderings of
rustic song had often been associated specifically with Sicily and the legendary herdsmen (in
particular the Cyclopes and Daphnis) inhabiting this island. 67 This geographical setting
reappears in some of the bucolic poems (Id. 1, 6, and 11).
Returning to the question of the definition of bucolic poetry, it may now be stated
that it is artificial, intertextual, and sophisticated poetry by or about herdsmen in an elevated
language, style and meter, meant to collide with its subject matter, recounting the
experiences (of unrequited love) of simple countrymen. It is written in hexameter, employing
62 On the Hellenistic tendency to combine low subject matter with elevated style/genre (esp. epic), see
Zanker (1987: 139‐44).
63 Cf. Gutzwiller (1991: 5): “To ignore the part played by transformation in giving these speech acts [sc.
of simple herdsmen] literary form is to miss something even more fundamental to pastoral than to
other genres, the tension between what is being represented and the act of representation.”
64 E.g. the description of the goatherd’s cup (Id. 1.28‐60) is usually considered a reference to the shield
description in Il. 18 or the [Hesiodic] Scutum. Id. 11 also contains several allusions to Hom. Od. 9, e.g.
lines 50‐54; 61; 79. See e.g. Hunter (1999 ad loc.).
65 This is also the predominant theme of urban or mythical poems 2, 13, 14. However, see Stanzel
(1995: 146): “Theokrits Hirtendichtung ist in einem konstitutiven Sinn Liebesdichtung oder erotische Poesie.”
66 They share this feature with the mythological Id. 13 and 22, cf. Rosenmeyer (1969: 179‐206), Hunter
(1999: 12‐16). On Theocritus’ interest in botany and the idea that he may have been a botanist, see
Lindsell (1937: 78‐93), Lembach (1970).
67 In Homer, the Cyclops is not localized, but in later tradition, he was supposed to have lived on Sicily
near Etna. In Od. 9 Polyphemus is a herdsman, although he is hardly a musical personage; Eur.
Cyclops (set on Sicily) features a distinctly bucolic song (42‐81); cf. the song of the chorus in Ar. Plut.
290‐315 (presumably a parody of Philoxenus’ dithyramb, which portrayed the Cyclops as a singer,
PMG 817). Daphnis is usually a Sicilian herdsman, cf. e.g. Diod. Sic. 4.84.
94
a mixture of Doric and Ionic forms, and reveals a geographical connection with Sicily. Of all
these characteristics, the only one that distinguishes bucolic poetry is that it deals with
(singing) herdsmen. Can this poetry be called a genre in its own right? A complicating factor
is the circumstance that the whole collection of Theocritus’ poetry, including the “urban
mimes” (2, 14, 15), the mythological poems (13, 18, 22, 24, 25, 26), the encomia (16, 17), and
the pederastic poems (12, 29, 30, 31), was apparently known under the title Βουκολικά in
antiquity. 68 Apart from this, there is the tricky definition of “genre,” always a problem, not
least when it comes to the Hellenistic period. 69
To start with, it is reasonably certain that in antiquity, the Idylls 70 were regarded as a
subspecies of epic on formal grounds (meter). 71 This approach took no account of the (non‐
heroic) content or of formal elements such as dramatic representation of dialogue 72 and
Doric dialect. In antiquity, apparently, Theocritus’ poems could simply be called both
“bucolic” and “epic.” There are two possible explanations for this. The poems could have
come to be called bucolic after their most distinguishing examples: poems about herdsmen.
The name would then be a kind of metonymia, a pars pro toto approach to the whole collection.
The other, more ingenious, explanation derives the name of the collection from the
identification of Theocritus the poet with the pseudo‐herdsman Simichidas of Id. 7. This
would automatically turn all Theocritus’ poetry into bucolic poetry, viz. poetry by a
herdsman. 73 Although the simpler explanation is more compelling, it cannot be ruled out
that perhaps both may have been true at different moments in time. A convoluted
presentation playing with the implications of this equivocation of songs by or about
herdsmen can be found in Id. 1 and 7, the two poems generally recognized as programmatic
for Theocritus’ poetry. They are both bucolic poems which feature bucolic poets singing
68 The name Eidyllia was given to the collection only later, in the scholia. On testimonia for ancient
collections of Theocritus’ poetry and their titles, see Gutzwiller (1996: 119‐148).
69 Cf. Nauta (1990: 121, n. 25): “eine Analyse des Hellenistischen Gattungssystem (...) ist ein Desideratum.”
Cf. also Harder’s preface to Genre in Hellenistic Poetry (1998). Cf. Hunter (1999: 5); Fantuzzi and Hunter
(2004: 1‐17). On genre in general, see Harvey (1955: 157‐175), Rossi (1971: 60‐94), Zetzel (1983: 83‐105).
On the contradictio in terminis of the expression “new genre,” see Gutzwiller (1991: 4).
70 Except Id. 28‐31, which are in lyric meters and use Aeolic dialectal forms.
71 Cf. Stanzel (1998: 143‐165).
72 That is, without the intervention of a third person narrator.
73 Nauta (1990: 117‐137), cf. the (Byzantine) poem addressing the poet as a herdsman by the vocative
Σιμιχίδα Θεόκριτε (Wendel 1914: 333). Earlier readers may have seen that Simichidas, often
interpreted as alter ego of Theocritus in Id. 7, is not unambiguously a herdsman (he comes from town)
but rather a poet posing as one cf. Giangrande (1968: 491‐533).
95
about ... bucolic poets. 74 This is a meaningful mise en abyme, as I will argue below.
Furthermore, the circumstance that many of the poems are mimetic and not embedded in a
narrative frame (1, 3, 4, 5, 10) blurs the distinction between the level of the poet (Theocritus)
and his characters: these poems pretend to be direct reports of the songs of the rustics. Thus,
they are indeed bucolic songs in both senses of the words.
If not a real genre, then, at least Theocritus created a new form or style of poetry in
which he brought the theme of country‐life, formerly only marginally treated in elevated
poetry, to prominence. 75 However, he implies that this new poetry is really derived from
Sicilian herdsmen (Id. 1, 5, 6, 7). While this is possibly partially true, the bucolic Idylls owe
much to Greek literary tradition as well. 76 In sum, he himself is the historical inventor of
what came to be known as bucolic poetry. He fashioned this poetry from elements of high
literature and low subject matter and influences from folk song. Yet, he contrives the
impression of working in an age‐old tradition with mythical predecessors, such as Daphnis,
Comatas (Id. 7), and (to a lesser extent) the Cyclops Polyphemus, who are at the same time
presented as traditional subjects of bucolic song. The following sections will undertake an
inquiry into the credentials of the alleged mythological forebears of Theocritus’ poetry and
the way they are used to create the sense of tradition that his new poetry so obviously
breathes.
3.7 Antiquity’s Views on the Origins of Bucolic Poetry
74As noted, Simichidas (Id. 7) is not unambiguously a herdsman, and his song is not bucolic, in that it
does not deal with herdsmen. However, Lycidas in the same Idyll is unmistakably a herdsman and his
song does treat singing herdsmen (Comatas, Daphnis). More on Lycidas and Simichidas in Ch. 7.4.
75 Some more or less “pastoral” predecessors could be sought in Homer’s Cyclops and Eumaeus;
Stesichorus allegedly wrote on Daphnis (see next section); furthermore Eur. Cyclops, Old comedy (e.g.
Cratinus’ comedy Goats, fr. 14 Cock; passages from Aristophanes), passages from tragedy (e.g. Eur.
Antiope, featuring the shepherd‐musician Amphion, Alexander, in which Paris is a herdsman),
Philoxenus’ dithyramb Cyclops or Galatea, and the (lost) works of Philitas, allegedly Theocritus’
teacher. Clearchus (third cent. BCE) mentions a certain Lycophronides, who wrote a dithyramb about
a goatherd in love (Ath. 14.619c‐d). Finally Sositheus, an Alexandrian dramatist (third cent. BCE)
wrote Lityerses, a kind of satyr play involving Daphnis, a maiden kidnapped by a pirate, and Heracles
(see Rosenmeyer 1969: 39, n. 36). There clearly were many poets working with pastoral subject matter,
yet none of them wrote “bucolic poetry” proper.
76 A much‐debated topic, cf. e.g. Rosenmeyer (1969: 30‐34) with bibliography. The evaluations range
from “Theocritus’ poetry is such as he might really have heard on the shores of Sicily,” to “The raw
desperadoes of the wilderness were not likely to furnish him with poetry.” It seems impossible to
deny any influence of folk‐song, but the intrinsically literary and sophisticated character of
Theocritean poetry must be remembered.
96
The scholia to the Idylls are preceded by a late antique or Byzantine essay that attributes the
invention of bucolic poetry to certain cults of Artemis in Laconia or Sicily. 77 This appears to
have no basis in the surviving poetry of Theocritus, nor can Artemis 78 or cultic thiasoi of
bucolic initiates be found in any other later bucolic poetry. Nowadays, received opinion is
that this theory was the scholarly response to the peripatetic explanation of the development
of tragedy out of obscure rural cults. 79
heuretēs for bucolic song; naturally, this would be a herdsman. The names encountered most
frequently in this connection are Diomus, Menalcas and Daphnis. 80 . Of these, the relation
between Daphnis and Theocritus’ Idylls is most important and complicated. Later writers tell
aetiological stories about this legendary herdsman, for instance Diodorus Siculus:
(...) μυθολογοῦσι γεννηθῆναι τὸν ὀνομαζόμενον Δάφνιν, Ἑρμοῦ μὲν καὶ Νύμφης
υἱόν, ἀπὸ δὲ τοῦ πλήθους καὶ τῆς πυκνότητος τῆς φυομένης δάφνης ὠνομάσθαι
Δάφνιν. τοῦτον δ’ ὑπὸ Νυμφῶν τραφέντα, καὶ βοῶν ἀγέλας παμπληθεῖς
κεκτημένον, τούτων ποιεῖσθαι πολλὴν ἐπιμέλειαν∙ ἀφ’ ἧς αἰτίας βουκόλον αὐτὸν
ὀνομασθῆναι. φύσει δὲ διαφόρῳ πρὸς εὐμέλειαν κεχορηγημένον ἐξευρεῖν τὸ
βουκολικὸν ποίημα καὶ μέλος, ὃ μέχρι τοῦ νῦν κατὰ τὴν Σικελίαν τυγχάνει
διαμένον ἐν ἀποδοχῇ. μυθολογοῦσι δὲ τὸν Δάφνιν μετὰ τῆς Ἀρτέμιδος κυνηγεῖν
ὑπηρετοῦντα τῇ θεῷ κεχαρισμένως, καὶ διὰ τῆς σύριγγος καὶ βουκολικῆς
μελῳδίας τέρπειν αὐτὴν διαφερόντως. λέγουσι δ’ αὐτοῦ μίαν τῶν Νυμφῶν
ἐρασθεῖσαν προειπεῖν, ἐὰν ἄλλῃ τινὶ πλησιάσῃ, στερήσεσθαι τῆς ὁράσεως∙
κἀκεῖνον ὑπό τινος θυγατρὸς βασιλέως καταμεθυσθέντα, καὶ πλησιάσαντα
αὐτῇ, στερηθῆναι τῆς ὁράσεως κατὰ τὴν γεγενημένην ὑπὸ τῆς Νύμφης
πρόρρησιν. (4.84.3‐5)
77 Wendel (1914: 2) Prolegomena B. These accounts formed the basis for Reitzenstein’s idea of the
bucolic masquerade (1893: 233‐4).
78 Although, as we shall see, Artemis does figure in Diodorus Siculus’ account of the originsof bucolic
poetry.
79 See Hunter (1999: 6, n. 20) for bibliography on the critical consensus.
80 Halperin (1983: 80). Diomus is referred to in Ath. (14.619ab) as a character in a play by Epicharmus
(the fifth cent. BCE Sicilian comic poet). The βουκολιασμός mentioned in connection with him was
apparently a kind of song sung by herdsmen. It is impossible to establish if there is a connection
between this Diomus‐figure and Theocritean herdsmen. The information only shows that singing
herdsmen were not alien to Sicilian literary tradition. The shepherd Menalcas, according to Clearchus
of Soloi, a contemporary of Theocritus was loved by a lyric poetess, Eriphanis who pursued him
singing, “High are the oaks, Menalcas,” (Ath. 14.619c‐d) giving rise to bucolic song. It is unclear
whence Clearchus derives this information. This may well have been his invention, but, in any case,
the story attests once more to the interest in the origins of bucolic at Theocritus’ time.
97
They tell the legend that [in that place] the man named Daphnis was born, a son of
Hermes and a nymph and that he was named Daphnis after the great amount of thick
laurel that grew there. He was brought up by the nymphs and acquired enormous
herds of cows and was greatly concerned with them, which is why he was called
“The Cowherd.” Being by nature favored with an extraordinary talent for music, he
invented the bucolic poem and melody, which, up to the present day, is present as a
tradition they received from him. And they tell that this Daphnis went hunting with
Artemis, gladly helping the goddess and that he pleased her exceedingly with his
Syrinx and his bucolic song. They also say that one of the nymphs who fell in love
with him foretold that he would be robbed of his sight if he ever made love to
another woman. And indeed, made drunk by a daughter of some king and having
made love to her, he was robbed of his sight according to the prophecy of the nymph.
A similar story is told by Aelian, who continues:
ἐκ δὲ τούτου τὰ βουκολικὰ μέλη πρῶτον ᾔσθη, καὶ εἶχεν ὑπόθεσιν τὸ πάθος τὸ
κατὰ τοὺς ὀφθαλμοὺς αὐτοῦ. καὶ Στησίχορόν γε τὸν Ἱμεραῖον τῆς τοιαύτης
μελοποιίας ὑπάρξασθαι. (VH 10.18)
As a result of this, bucolic song was sung for the first time and its subject was what
happened to his eyes. Stesichorus of Himera (PMG fr. 279) began this kind of lyric.
The meaning of these last phrases is not clear. 81 Do they imply that Daphnis sang his own
Daphnis before Stesichorus wrote a poem about it? 82 Whatever the more likely
interpretation, bucolic poetry was probably assigned two fountainheads in this passage: a
mythological one in Daphnis and a historical one in Stesichorus. Once again, the distinction
between poetry about herdsmen and poetry by herdsmen is blurred. As Halperin remarks à
propos of such stories:
in the Hellenistic period, and a post‐Hellenistic tradition connecting Daphnis (and other
81 Cf. Dover (1971: lxv), Hunter (1999: 65). Halperin interprets the verb ὑπάρξασθαι as “to inherit”
(1983: 79).
82 Or perhaps Stesichorus sang of how he lost his own eyesight, as was related in connection with the
Palinode about Helen (fr.15, 16 PMG), cf. Pl. Phaedr. 243a5?
83 Cf. Hunter (1999: 67): “In the Hellenistic age, traditional tales, like the story of Daphnis, were
commonly fashioned into aetiologies for ritual practice; bucolic song is the recurrent commemoration
of the pathos of Daphnis...” Cf. Hobsbawm’s definition (1983: 7) of the function of “invented
tradition.”
98
Sicilian herdsmen) with these origins. It is worthy of note that the important character of the
goatherd Comatas, who is sung of by Lycidas in the seventh Idyll as a legendary singer, is
not mentioned in this enquiry into the origins of bucolic song. Does this imply that he is
Theocritus’ invention? 84 With this question at the back of our minds, an attempt to explore
Theocritus’ stance regarding the origins of bucolic poetry may be undertaken.
3.8 Daphnis in Idyll 1
As is generally recognized, Idylls 1 and 7 seem to propose a meta‐poetic enquiry into the
nature of bucolic poetry. 85 Idyll 1 is a mime set in a timeless pastoral landscape (in all
likelihood on Sicily) 86 in which two herdsmen exchange compliments, gifts, and songs. The
bucolic song is performed by the shepherd Thyrsis, who “is wont to sing the woes of
Daphnis and is come to mastery in bucolic song,” according to his interlocutor, the nameless
goatherd (19‐20). This implies that the sufferings of Daphnis were an established subject of
song (it almost sounds like a title) and that bucolic song was a broadly practiced form in
which Thyrsis has reached mastery. It is important to keep this in mind in the ensuing
discussion of the song of Thyrsis.
Thyrsis’ song is framed by a changing refrain calling on the Muses to begin, continue,
and end the bucolic song (ἄρχετε βουκολικᾶς / πάλιν ἄρχετ’ / λήγετε ἀοιδᾶς, 64‐142).
Above, the version of the story of Daphnis as it has come down in tradition has been
discussed, in which the cowherd Daphnis is untrue to a nymph to whom he has made a vow
of chastity and as a result is punished with blindness and somehow dies. It is, however,
remarkably unclear whether this is the version in the first Idyll. Despite assurances to the
contrary, 87 the song in this poem is told in an allusive way and hard to comprehend fully. 88
The main difficulties involved center around the questions of how and why Daphnis met his
end.
84 The scholia are contradictory on this point, cf. below.
85 See on this topic in particular Seeck (1975: 195‐211), Cairns (1984: 89‐113), Goldhill (1991: 225‐240),
Hunter (1999: 148‐149).
86 Cf. Id. 1.65, and allusions to geographical points of reference in Thyrsis’ song, passim.
87 Lawall (1967: 26‐7).
88 Gow (1952: II, 1), Ogilvie (1962: 106‐110). Recently, with different conclusions Goldhill (1991: 242‐
243), Hunter (1999: 67).
99
Before addressing these, the way the narrative is recounted in Thyrsis’ song must be
considered. The introduction to the story recounts how Daphnis is “wasting away”
(ἐτάκετο, 66), a phrase which triggers the expectation that he is languishing from the pangs
of unrequited love. 89 It is then related how, before he dies, gods and men come to enquire
into the cause of his suffering and offer help, commiseration, or comment upon it. The series
of visitors who come to see Daphnis represents a range of understanding: complete
ignorance as to what causes Daphnis’ suffering (humans, who ask what the matter is, 80‐1),
are awkward in love (δύσερως); the girl is looking for you but you do not go to her,” 82‐93)
and (apparent) knowledge (Aphrodite: “You said you would vanquish Eros, but now he has
vanquished you,” 97‐8). Aphrodite’s remarks are singled out by the fact that Daphnis deigns
to answer only when addressed by her; they appear to stand on a familiar footing and know
a great deal about each other’s affairs. After this, Daphnis “goes to the stream and the waters
close over his head” (140‐1). There are three possible explanations for the difficulties
encountered when trying to square Theocritus’ reading with the account of post‐Hellenistic
tradition:
1) Id. 1 more or less follows the tradition represented by Aelian and Diodorus, but in
an obscure way;
2) Theocritus follows a now unknown variant tradition that was either known or
unknown to most of his contemporaries;
3) Theocritus has made up a new story on the basis of the legendary Sicilian
character Daphnis, 90 which was either fully comprehensible or incomprehensible
to a contemporary audience.
Apart from Ogilvie, practically no scholars embrace the first hypothesis; indeed, it has little
to recommend itself and can be discarded here. 91 The other two demand closer inspection. In
particular, the likelihood that contemporary audiences would, in these cases, have been able
89 Cf. other instances of the verb, e.g. in Theoc. Id. 2.29; 82.
90 Like his contemporaries Hermesianax (schol. ad Id. 8.93) and Sositheus (Servius ad Verg. Ecl. 8.68).
91 Ogilvie (1962: 106‐110). Ogilvie’s reading is forced on a number of points. In the first place, he fails
to recognize the role of Aphrodite, whom he denies is guilty of Daphnis’ sufferings. Another point is
his forced reading of δύσερως (1.85) as “in love with the wrong object” and not “cursed in love,
gauche.” This finds no echo in the use in Theocritus’ other Idylls (6.6‐7). On the Theocritean topos of the
δύσερως goatherd, see Stanzel (1995: 48‐50).
100
to grasp the song of Thyrsis in all its detail needs to be weighed, as it has obvious
consequences for the analysis of Theocritus’ presentation of bucolic tradition.
In the narrative Theocritus presents, there are two possible readings of the visits of
men and gods; the choice between them dictates whether this narrative can be understood
on its own terms, even if it does not conform to the traditional account. One interpretation
takes every utterance of the gods at face value. This is the reading proposed by Lawall
(1967), who sees in Daphnis a kind of bucolic Hippolytus determined to remain chaste, even
in the face of (his own) consuming passion. 92 Even if this interpretation is correct,
comparison with the other versions shows that this was not, in any case the traditional
account. Lawall’s appraisal is based on the assumption that Priapus’ remark, that “the girl”
(ἁ κώρα, 82) is looking for Daphnis, is correct. Since Daphnis does not reply to Priapus’
remarks and Hermes is not aware of any details of the situation, there is no compelling
reason to assume that this is in fact so. Even if he should be correct: who is “the girl?” Is she
the nymph to whom Daphnis pledged faithfulness? The princess who seduced him? Another
(mortal/immortal) girl he is in love with but cannot or will not be with? And what does
Aphrodite’s statement that Daphnis had vowed “to vanquish Eros” refer to in combination
with this girl? Of course, all kinds of explanations can be crafted to fit all kinds of mythical
parallels, even perhaps the one later represented in Diodorus and Aelian, but that is the
point: which of these vaguely familiar stories is being related? Finally, what happens when
Daphnis dies also remains ambiguous:
(...) τά γε μὰν λίνα πάντα λελοίπει
ἐκ Μοιρᾶν, χὠ Δάφνις ἔβα ῥόον. ἔκλυσε δίνα
τὸν Μοίσαις φίλον ἄνδρα, τὸν οὐ Νύμφαισιν ἀπεχθῆ. (1.139‐141)
But all the thread the Fates assigned was run, and Daphnis went to the stream. The
waters closed over him whom the Muses loved, nor did the Nymphs dislike him.
(transl. Gow)
Various explanations, once more, have been provided to clarify this mysterious reference.
Does Daphnis drown himself (by accident or on purpose)? Does the angry (water) nymph
drown him? 93 Does he change (melt away) into a river or fountain, like his fellow
92 Cf. Hutchinson (1988: 149).
93 Like Hylas in 13? So e.g. Prescott (1899: 121‐140).
101
countryman Acis? 94 Or is “the river” an unusual way referring to the river of the dead, the
Acheron? 95 Without wanting to discuss the likelihood of these suggestions, it is clear that
interpreting this song is a complicated matter. Yet, in the Idyll itself, there is no sign that the
goatherd, the interlocutor and addressee of Thyrsis, has any difficulty understanding the
account. Indeed, as pointed out earlier, he seems perfectly familiar with it (cf. 1.19).
This, then, leads to the other reading, the one that accepts that “Theocritus has veiled
the whole story in a cloak of allusive obscurity.” 96 Taking stock of the difficulties in making
the story (which seems so provokingly familiar) into a fitting one, it seems plausible that
Theocritus wanted his readers to be tantalized by this allusive account of Daphnis’ story.
Given the way the Daphnis narrative is poetically balanced by the ekphrasis of the goatherd’s
cup (“too much” information 97 against “too little” information), this idea begins to look even
more attractive. 98 The possibilities that either Theocritus invented the story himself or used a
audience would not have been familiar with this recondite Sicilian lore, so this distinction is
minor. But what was Theocritus’ motivation for relating the story, or, rather, having Thyrsis
relate it, in such an allusive way? Looking for parallels is the best way to find an answer to
this question.
94 Cf. Zimmerman (1994: 133), who compares Daphnis to a kind of liquefying Narcissus, cf. Hunter
(1999: 67).
95 This may well be the right interpretation. Van Erp Taalman Kip (1987: 249‐51) points out that in 1.71
Daphnis is explicitly said to be dead, when the animals come to mourn at his feet, so he cannot have
walked to the stream. For the unusual reference to Acheron, see the parallels adduced by Gow (1952:
II, ad loc).
96 Phrasing Ogilvie (1962: 108); so e.g. Gow (1952: II, 1), Hunter (1999: 67). Segal (1981: 36): “Such a
distortion of the myth in a poet as learned and sophisticated as Theocritus cannot but be intentional.
The effect of departing from the received legend while subtly hinting at it, as Priapus’ speech seems to
do, forces the reader to explore further. The very mystery of Daphnis’ end may be the most essential
element in the poem.”
97 In particular the description of the woman and the two young men (1.33‐37), which, in the typical
mode of ekphrasis, describes things that are strictly speaking, invisible.
98 Cf. e.g. Goldhill (1991: 142), Hunter (1999: 62‐3).
102
3.9 Allusive Narrative in other Ancient Poetry
It is revealing to consider allusive narratives known from other ancient poetry. Frequent
examples can be found, for example, in the choral lyric of Pindar. 99 One of the many is the
following, in which Hieron I, tyrant of Syracuse, is compared to Philoctetes:
φαντὶ δὲ Λαμνόθεν ἕλκει
τειρόμενον μεταβάσοντας ἐλθεῖν
ἥροας ἀντιθέους Ποίαντος υἱὸν τοξόταν∙
ὃς Πριάμοιο πόλιν πέρσεν, τελεύτα‐
σέν τε πόνους Δαναοῖς,
ἀσθενεῖ μὲν χρωτὶ βαίνων, ἀλλὰ μοιρίδιον ἦν. (P. 1.52‐55)
They tell that the godlike heroes came to fetch him from Lemnos, wasting from his
wound, Poias’ archer son, who destroyed Priam’s city and ended the Danaans’ toils,
he walked with flesh infirm, but it was the work of destiny. (transl. Race)
Without awareness of the story of Philoctetes, the reader must wonder why he was wounded
and how, what his relation to Lemnos was, and how he (with only his bow) destroyed the
city of Priam. The great difference between this allusive narrative and the one in the first Idyll
is its familiarity. Not many in ancient Greece would have been ignorant of the basic elements
of the myth of Philoctetes. Of course, examples of Pindar’s tendency to adapt or manipulate
a well‐known story to fit his own purposes, as he does in O. 1.35‐41 concerning the story of
Tantalus and his son, have also survived. The fact remains that the audience could be
expected to appreciate Pindar’s additions or conversions, despite or perhaps rather because
of their knowledge of the main line of the famous narrative. Indeed, Pindar sometimes
explicitly calls the reader’s attention to the fact that he is deviating from the traditional
version of the myth: “Son of Tantalus, I shall tell your story contrary to my predecessors...”
(υἱὲ Ταντάλου, σὲ δ’ ἀντία προτέρων φθέγξομαι, O. 1.36). 100
How do these examples compare to the narrative in Idyll 1? As pointed out, the
audience of Thyrsis (the goatherd) within the text apparently experiences no difficulties of
comprehension (cf. 1.19), while the modern reader does. Neither is the reader (ancient or
modern) alerted to the possibility that this is a variant of a traditional tale. It must be taken
99 Cf. Pi. I. 4.36‐39 (the death of Ajax): ἴστε μάν / Αἴαντος ἀλκάν, φοίνιον τὰν ὀψίᾳ / ἐν νυκτὶ ταμὼν
περὶ ᾧ φασγάνῳ μομφὰν ἔχει / παίδεσσιν Ἑλλάνων ὅσοι Τροίανδ’ ἔβαν. (Surely you know of Ajax’
bloodstained valor, which he pierced late at night on his own sword, and thereby cast blame upon all
the sons of the Hellenes who went to Troy. transl. Race).
100 Cf. Pi. O. 9.35‐40; N. 7.22‐27; 8.32‐37; Stesich. Palinode (fr. 15, 16 PMG).
103
for granted that (at least within the fiction of the poem) this is a similar situation to the one I
described with regard to Pindar P. 1. In other words, the reader is invited to believe that an
the impression of the venerable antiquity and familiarity of a story in which the particulars
need no repeating. While the story of Daphnis in Theocritus’ version therefore may be
traditional version. It sounds familiar despite the elusive details. Theocritus’ ancient readers,
in asking themselves why they could not understand this story, would in all likelihood have
assumed that it was because they were not part of the same rural community to which the
herdsmen belong.
The technique used in Id. 1, pretending there is an established, ancient version of the
similar means for authenticating and authorizing newly invented stories. 104 Within
Theocritus’ own poetry, the best parallel can be found in Id. 22, where the story of the
Dioscuri is told in a version markedly different from earlier known traditions: Castor and
Polydeuces both survive the fight with Idas and Lynceus, whereas they do not, or at least not
however, in Homer’s Iliad, the Dioscuri are explicitly dead and buried (Il. 3.236‐44),
presumably because of their fight with Idas and Lynceus. Rather than attributing this
discrepancy to an “unfortunate” mistake on the part of Theocritus, like Gow, it is better to
say that Theocritus wants his own poetical treatment of the Dioscuri to be contrasted with
101 The only candidate for an older version appears to be Stesichorus, but the details in Ael. VH 10.18
suggest that he told a different version.
102 E.g. Pi. O. 7.54‐7, a new account of the origins of the Isle of Rhodes, attributed to “the ancient
reports of men.”
103 E.g. Pl. Tim. 21a: “Having heard an old story from a man who was not young.”
104 Cf. Pfeijffer (2004: 221), with reference to Verdenius (1987: 74). Call. fr. 612 Pf. (ἀμάρτυρον οὐδὲν
ἀείδω, I sing nothing without testimony) might be an ironic reference to this practice.
105 E.g. Pi. N. 10, Cypria fr. 8 (Bernabé) and Il. 3.236‐44. Cf. Gow (1952: II, 383‐4), Sens (1997: ad 210‐11).
See on this passage further Ch. 8.7.3.
106 The idea that Theocritus here refers to the (short) Homeric Hymns concerning the Dioscuri, or the
(non‐Homeric) Cypria, rather than to the Iliad is unattractive, cf. Sens (1997: 218‐9).
104
the brief handling they receive in the Iliad. 107 In the process, he ironically pretends to be
deriving the authority for his tale from a venerable source, namely Homer. This looks similar
to the story of Daphnis as told by Thyrsis in Id. 1. Although it is not explicitly traced back to
ancient sources, as in the examples from Pindar, Plato, and Id. 22, the context certainly
implies that it is a classic of the rustic world. 108
3.10 Daphnis in the other Idylls
Starting from the assumption that Theocritus’ poems were read as a book in antiquity, in
which cross‐reference was an important hermeneutic tool for the comprehension of single
the Idylls that also presuppose knowledge of his fate.
The first is a brief one in Id. 5, where a certain Lacon, one of two bickering goatherds
I believe you” (αἴ τοι πιστεύσαιμι, τὰ Δάφνιδος ἄλγε’ ἀροίμαν, Id. 5.20). Clearly both
herdsmen know to which unpleasant event this refers, so the reference presumably functions
as a proverbial expression. Later, the other herdsman Comatas declares, “The Muses love me
much better than the singer Daphnis” (ταὶ Μοῖσαί με φιλεῦντι πολὺ πλέον ἢ τὸν ἀοιδόν /
Δάφνιν, Id. 5.79‐80), once more suggesting a proverbial expression.
The third reference appears in Id. 7, when Lycidas, a goatherd/poet who is
represented as a contemporary of Theocritus, 111 sings how Tityrus, a rustic musician, will
sing of Daphnis:
(...) ὁ δὲ Τίτυρος ἐγγύθεν ᾀσεῖ
ὥς ποκα τᾶς Ξενέας ἠράσσατο Δάφνις ὁ βούτας,
χὠς ὄρος ἀμφεπονεῖτο καὶ ὡς δρύες αὐτὸν ἐθρήνευν
Ἱμέρα αἵτε φύοντι παρ’ ὄχθαισιν ποταμοῖο,
εὖτε χιὼν ὥς τις κατετάκετο μακρὸν ὑφ’ Αἷμον
ἢ Ἄθω ἢ Ῥοδόπαν ἢ Καύκασον ἐσχατόωντα. (7.72‐77)
107 Hutchinson (1988: 163, n. 33). For an overview of other explanations, none of them particularly
convincing, see Sens (1997: 219).
108 For the idea that the “fragmentation” of the Daphnis narrative “hints towards a pastoral world”
(without however elaborating on what this entails), cf. Goldhill (1991: 242).
109 Gutzwiller (1996: 119‐148).
110 They do not represent mythical figures; cf. the reference to Thurii (72), a colony that was founded in
the fifth century BCE.
111 Cf. the references to Philitas and Asclepiades (7.40), poets slightly older than Theocritus.
105
And close at hand Tityrus shall sing how once Daphnis the neatherd loved Xenea,
and how the hill was sorrowful about him and the oaktrees which grow upon the
river Himeras’ banks sang his dirge when he was wasting like any snow under high
Haemus or Athos or Rhodope or remotest Caucasus. (transl. Gow)
Once more, only snatches of the story are accessible: Daphnis’ “wasting,” his love for the girl,
here called Xenea, and the grief (Sicilian) nature showed at his suffering. The temptation to
combine the information found here with that of Id. 1 could not be greater, but it does not
Tityrus, Lycidas, and presumably also to Simichidas, who is after all the audience of Lycidas’
song in Id. 7 and shows no problems of comprehension. Moreover, the setting of this Idyll on
Cos in the eastern Mediterranean and not in Sicily implies the widespread familiarity of the
Idylls thus manage to convey the illusion of a fully rounded bucolic world endowed with its
own traditions and cultures that are well known to its inhabitants. In this way, Theocritus
provides his poetic creation with credibility and a sense of tradition. The Daphnis myth is
particularly suitable to this venture, drawing as it does on a possibly pre‐existent yet largely
unfamiliar myth.
A different case, however, is the other theme of Tityrus’ imagined song, the
legendary goatherd‐musician Comatas:
ᾀσεῖ δ’ ὥς ποκ’ ἔδεκτο τὸν αἰπόλον εὐρέα λάρναξ
ζωὸν ἐόντα κακαῖσιν ἀτασθαλίαισιν ἄνακτος,
ὥς τέ νιν αἱ σιμαὶ λειμωνόθε φέρβον ἰοῖσαι
κέδρον ἐς ἁδεῖαν μαλακοῖς ἄνθεσσι μέλισσαι,
οὕνεκά οἱ γλυκὺ Μοῖσα κατὰ στόματος χέε νέκταρ.
ὦ μακαριστὲ Κομᾶτα, τύ θην τάδε τερπνὰ πεπόνθεις∙
καὶ τὺ κατεκλᾴσθης ἐς λάρνακα, καὶ τὺ μελισσᾶν
κηρία φερβόμενος ἔτος ὥριον ἐξεπόνασας.
αἴθ’ ἐπ’ ἐμεῦ ζωοῖς ἐναρίθμιος ὤφελες ἦμεν,
ὥς τοι ἐγὼν ἐνόμευον ἀν’ ὤρεα τὰς καλὰς αἶγας
φωνᾶς εἰσαΐων, τὺ δ’ ὑπὸ δρυσὶν ἢ ὑπὸ πεύκαις
ἁδὺ μελισδόμενος κατεκέκλισο, θεῖε Κομᾶτα. (7.78‐89)
Pace Ogilvie (1962: 106‐110).
112
Cf. Dover (1971: lxiv), noting moreover the Cydonian (i.e. Cretan) origin of Lycidas. He suggests
113
Theocritus is implicitly paying himself a compliment and compares this to the fact that in Call. AP
7.518 Cretan herdsmen sing of Daphnis’ fate; this would constitute a compliment by Callimachus to
Theocritus.
106
And he shall sing how once a wide coffer received the goatherd alive by the impious
presumption of a king; and how the blunt‐faced bees came from the meadows to the
fragrant chest of cedar and fed him on tender flowers because the Muse had poured
sweet nectar on his lips. Ah, blessed Comatas, yours is this sweet lot, you too were
closed within the coffer; you too, fed on honeycomb, did endure with toil the
springtime of the year. Would that you had been numbered with the living in my day
so that I might have herded your fair goats upon the hills, and listened to your voice,
while you, divine Comatas did lie under the oaks or pines, and made sweet music.
(transl. Gow adapted)
Who is this Comatas? 114 Apparently, he is another mythical singer of bucolic poetry, a
legendary rustic character closely linked to the Muses. He is an example of how music and
herdsmen are intimately related, illustrating the essentiality of music for the herdsmen’s life:
his own life was saved by it through a miracle of nature. In this sense he looks like a foil to
Daphnis, who could not be saved, even by music, no matter what miracles nature generated
at his death. 115
Although Comatas’ name is not attested elsewhere, the scholia ad 79c are aware of a
story closely resembling what is found here and attribute it to a certain Lycus of Rhegium, a
83 to the effect that Theocritus has “made this story up himself” (πέπλασται τἁ περἰ τοῦ
Κομάτα ὑπὸ Θεοκρίτου, 83) or has “transferred” (μετήνεγκεν, 79c) “elements of the
Daphnis‐legend to it” (καθάπερ ὁ Δάφνις ἱστορεῖται, 83). Once more then, the story is an
obscure variant of a local myth (at best) or, alternatively, an invented story formed out of
familiar mythical elements presented as traditional lore, supposedly well known to the
the story of Daphnis, who may have had a somewhat wider familiarity, provides the tale of
the former with greater credibility.
114 I do not agree with Radt (1971: 254‐55) and Hunter (1999: 176), who, based on the recurrent καί (84),
think “the goatherd” (78) and “Comatas” refer to two distinct individuals. The connection (καί) is
rather between Comatas and Daphnis, who was apparently also exposed in a chest and fed by bees (cf.
schol. ad 83), or between Comatas and other examples from myth (Danae was closed in a chest, Iamos,
son of Euadne was fed by bees; cf. Dover ad 83). Gow (1952: II ad 83) also takes “the goatherd” to refer
to Comatas.
115 This opposition will be treated below in the final interpretation of the figures of Daphnis, Comatas,
and Polyphemus and their interrelations.
116 Schol. ad 78/9 b, cf. the discussions of Gow (1952: II, ad loc.), Dover (1971) and Hunter (1999: ad loc.).
117 Cf. Wilamowitz (1924: II, 14): “Die Komatasgeschichte war den Zuhörern Theokrits vermutlich neu.”
107
3.11 The Identities of Daphnis and Comatas
Related to the tantalizing recurrent allusions to Daphnis addressed above, the recurrence of
identical names is a puzzling and often remarked upon characteristic that connects many of
the Idylls. 118 Is the mythical cowherd Daphnis in Id. 1 identical to the (contemporary?)
cowherd Daphnis in Id. 6, 119 described as a young boy “with half‐grown beard” (2‐3)?
Similarly, the goatherd Comatas in Lycidas’ song in Id. 7 seems a legendary, even divine,
figure close to the Muses, while the goatherd Comatas in Id. 5 is involved in a vulgar
shouting match. Yet, are they the same? 120 These recurrent names, I submit, are not
coincidences that demonstrate a lack of fantasy on the part of Theocritus but serve as a way
to provide unity. 121
To understand this, it is important to remember that Theocritus is often interested in
the fate of his mythical protagonists “before they entered traditional myth.” This can be seen
in the case of young Polyphemus (Id. 6 and 11 recount an episode before book 9 of the
Odyssey, when he is in love with Galatea “with the down on his lips,” cf. Id. 6.2‐3) and in the
wedding song for that soon‐to‐be notorious young couple Helen and Menelaus (18). It is
therefore not unlikely that Daphnis in Id. 6 is the same Daphnis as the one in Id. 1, only
before his sufferings befell him. The interpretation that identifies Daphnis of Id. 1 with the
singer in Id. 6 is made even more attractive by considerations of content. There are numerous
thematic correspondences between Id. 1 and Id. 6. Whereas Daphnis in Id. 6 plays the role of
giver of advice in amorous matters to Polyphemus, in Id. 1 he is himself a victim of love; Id.
6, with Cyclops playing hard to get, is a comic reflection of the (apparently) self‐imposed and
fatal abstinence of the lovelorn Daphnis in Id. 1. 122
118 See e.g. Wilamowitz (1906: 136), Lawall (1967: esp.69), Ott (1969: 121), Dover (1971: lvi and 140),
Schmidt (1987), Bernsdorff (1994: 40), who is uncertain about Id. 5; Stanzel (1995: 40‐1), Hunter (1999:
245), who only sees Daphnis of 1 and 6 as identical, not Comatas of 5 and 7. Gow (1952: II, ad loc.) is
silent on the subject, but appears to assume the identity of Daphnis in Id. 1 and 6, if not of Comatas in
Id. 5 and 7.
119 He is explicitly called “The cowherd” (ὁ βουκόλος) in 6.1; 86; 113; 116; 120‐121.
120 To these examples, which are the most interesting to the discussion, could be added Amaryllis
(serenaded by the shepherd in 3 and referred to as dead in 4.36‐40); Aratus (the addressee of Id. 6 and
referred to in Simichidas’ song in Id. 7 as an unhappy lover).
121 With regard to Daphnis, esp. Bernsdorff (1994: 38‐51) and Hunter (1999: 245); with regard to
Comatas esp. Schmidt (1987); this latter identification has found no wide acceptance.
122 This furthermore implies that Id. 1 is linked to Id. 11 by way of Id. 6, cf. Hunter (1996: 245‐248),
Fantuzzi and Hunter (2004: 150‐151).
108
Along the same lines, it has been argued that the “divine poet” Comatas in Id. 7
(whose origins are unclear and, in all likelihood, lie at least partly in Theocritean invention)
is identical to the foulmouthed goatherd/slave with that name in Id. 5. 123 This latter
identification, however, has not found wide acceptance because of the discrepancy between
case of Daphnis, the recurring name is nonetheless significant. It might be argued that the
two versions of Comatas possess the complementary aspects which taken together make up
the essence of bucolic poetry. In this, they are like many of Theocritus’ character‐couples:
Daphnis is a tragic lover, Polyphemus his comic counterpart; Lycidas’ song in Id. 7 is full of
name “Comatas” comes to bear a double meaning: it represents both the elevated legendary
goatherd and the down‐to earth contemporary one. In this, it is indeed symbolic of bucolic
poetry, which derives much of its distinctive character from the (often surprising) clash of
such opposites.
Theocritus’ way of referring to time in the Idylls helps to blur the distinctions between
herdsmen arises from this vagueness. The majority of Theocritus’ time‐indications belong to
the category “once” (πότε, πόκα, ἦς χρόνος ἁνίκ´), which does not refer to an equidistant
particular period (e.g. Id. 1 and 3).
A second reason for the semblance of timelessness in Theocritus’ bucolic world is the
general lack of references to historical, political, or mundane events that would allow the
123 Schmidt (1987) makes a case for the identification. Segal already pointed to the possibility (1981:
36).
124 E.g. Stanzel (1995: 43): “Von der Personenzeichnung des fünften Eidyllions her scheint es mir jedenfalls
nicht gerechtfertigt, das Attribut göttlich aus dem siebten Gedicht auf diesen Hirten zu übertragen.”
125 For the creative principle of combining opposites in bucolic poetry, cf. Ott (1969).
126 Cf. Klooster (2007: 97‐115).
127 In Id. 7, “there was a time when” (ἦς χρόνος ἁνίκ´) refers to an episode within the lifetime of the
narrator, Simichidas, who is firmly situated in Theocritus’ contemporary world by his references to
Asclepiades and Philitas (39‐40). Whereas πόκ´ in 18.1 (the epithalamium of Helen) refers to the heroic
times just before the outbreak of the Trojan War, it remains unclear whether πότε in Id. 6.2 refers to
the age of heroic legend or not. More remarks on the expression below, Ch. 7.4.
109
dramatic date of the poems to be fixed. 128 Against a background of unchanging nature and
the unchanging ways of the countryside, the adventures of unchanging herdsmen are
narrated. This exemption from the passage of time must be the reason for the deliberate
chronological vagueness of the Idylls: it does not greatly matter whether the stories occurred
in Theocritus’ day and age or in an unspecified mythological past thousand years earlier. In
the world of herdsmen nothing much changes; the rustic world is a continuum.
3.12 Echoes and Correspondences: a World of Song
So how does this web of recurring personages and the overall impression of timelessness
affect the way in which Theocritus positions his bucolic poetry in literary history?
Considering the lack of temporal differentiation, the question of the identification of the
herdsmen Daphnis and Comatas in Id. 1, 6, 5, and 7 can be seen from a new angle; it does not
greatly matter whether they are exactly identical, as they are, at any rate, greatly alike.
unchanging continuum in which the constant factors determining human life are love and
song. Thus, Polyphemus in Id. 11 is hardly different from Bucaeus in Id. 10, or from
Theocritus the poet and his contemporary addressees in this respect, a thought that is
worded most memorably in the address to Nicias in Id. 13: 129
Οὐχ ἁμῖν τὸν Ἔρωτα μόνοις ἔτεχ’, ὡς ἐδοκεῦμες,
Νικία, ᾧτινι τοῦτο θεῶν ποκα τέκνον ἔγεντο∙
οὐχ ἁμῖν τὰ καλὰ πράτοις καλὰ φαίνεται ἦμεν,
οἳ θνατοὶ πελόμεσθα, τὸ δ’ αὔριον οὐκ ἐσορῶμες∙ (1‐4)
Not for us alone, Nicias, as once we thought, was Love begotten by whosoever of the
gods begat him, nor does fair seem fair first to us, who are mortal and see not the
morrow... (transl. Gow; the poem continues to describe the love of Heracles for the
beautiful Hylas, an example from the heroic age.)
Theocritus then, represents himself and his contemporaries as similar, at least in this respect,
to the characters he represents in his poems. This collapsing of different levels of the poem
128 Stanzel (1995: 38‐44). The exceptions have already been mentioned, viz. the references to Thurii
(5.70) and to Philitas and Asclepiades (7.40).
129 This poem does not qualify as “bucolic,” but a similar conclusion may be drawn from the
introduction to Id. 11. Gutzwiller (1991) shows that there is always an element of “analogy” in the
Idylls; i.e., what happens in the narrative introduction is in some way supposedly similar to what
happens in the main body of the song.
110
(of author and personage, of the question whether bucolic poetry is poetry by herdsmen or
about herdsmen) is brought about in many other ways besides. Thus in Id. 1, Thyrsis, the
bucolic master, sings of Daphnis, the original subject/singer of bucolic song. In Id. 7, Lycidas,
the modern bucolic poet and, of course, a character of Theocritus’ own bucolic poetry, sings
of Tityrus, who also sings of Daphnis and of Comatas, another subject/singer of bucolic song.
He even wishes Comatas might have been alive in his own day. In Id. 6, Theocritus the poet
sings of Daphnis. In this respect then, he is like Thyrsis and Lycidas. He is even very like
Lycidas in another respect: both sing songs about herdsmen singing songs about herdsmen.
This Chinese‐box effect dazzles the reader and results in blurring the distinction
between the narrating voices. 130 In the mimetic Id. 5, moreover, Theocritus presents the
character Comatas as if he were among the living; he at once makes the wish of Lycidas (Id. 7)
come true and is himself like Lycidas in the choice of his topic. The fact that he is able to
imagine what Comatas would be like if he were a contemporary, places him both close to
Comatas, the “divine” subject of Lycidas’ song and close to Lycidas himself, who also tries to
imagine this. 131 At the same time, the unpleasantness of the character of Comatas in Id. 5
makes Lycidas’ wish in Id. 7 appear in a comic light.
The young Daphnis in Id. 6, in his turn, sings of the Cyclops Polyphemus in love, as
does Theocritus, in Id. 11. Therefore, Theocritus is also like Daphnis. In turn, Daphnis is
simultaneously unlike and like Polyphemus in his struggle with unrequited love (Id. 1 and
7). Finally, in Id. 11 the poet/herdsman Polyphemus, trying to cure his love with song, is
extraordinarily like Theocritus and his contemporaries in this respect: Theocritus explicitly
says so in the opening of this Idyll.
At this juncture, it becomes apparent that what Theocritus presents in the bucolic
Idylls is a world held together by analogies, correspondences, mise en abyme, interrelations,
echoes, and oppositions. His intricate juggling creates the impression that he is part of and
deeply imbedded in a vital Sicilian bucolic tradition; he seems close to its origins by his
marked resemblances to its mythical originators. These mythical originators, on the other
hand, are such that they could well be present in Theocritus’ day, up on the hillsides of
Sicily. Together, they form a continuum that appears like a closed and rounded world full of
130 Goldhill (1991: 245) terms this polyphony.
131 On the direct apostrophe of Comatas at the end of Lycidas’ song, cf. Ch. 7.4.
111
ancient but ever‐renewed traditions and songs. It is a world of timeless poetry at once
generated by poetry and echoing with it.
The truth of the matter, of course, as argued earlier, is that Theocritus is himself the
actual originator of the bucolic genre. Up to a certain point, he created the origins of bucolic
himself by writing about them. That he makes the correspondences between his alleged
ancestors and himself so close and that he presents these ancestors so ambiguously as being
both subject and author of bucolic song should tell us enough: a major subject of bucolic song
is the origin of bucolic song. This is what Theocritus is showing by his invention of traditions
and by inextricably entangling himself in the web of corresponding songs.
3.13 Conclusion
In this chapter, the potential for Hellenistic poets to exploit mythical poets for the creation
and authorization of new poetry has been illustrated with two examples. The openness to
interpretation, combined with venerable authority of characters such as Orpheus and
Daphnis provided the authors who used them as their models and mirrors with particular
possibilities for legitimizing their own poetical choices, inventions, and personae. Crucially,
this process permitted them to endow their characters with features that best mirrored their
own objectives. This process was enabled by the flexibility of Greek mythological material
and the respect the Greeks had for anything ancient. These characteristics provided the
perfect circumstances for the flourishing of “invented tradition.”
Written works formed no obstacle to this enterprise: in the case of Daphnis, there
were no ipsissima verba. In the case of Orpheus, these were highly controversial but, if they
had to be taken into account, they at least revealed a close connection to the divine hymnic
origins of poetry. The myth of Daphnis, though probably of local fame, was used in an
allusive way by Theocritus as a kind of universal classic of the bucolic world he was creating
in his Idylls. This lent credibility and substance to this world of which his readers were no
part; Theocritus could tell Daphnis’ story in such a way as to make his readers feel they were
listening to a familiar story, while at the same time tantalizing them with the fragmentary
and allusive quality of his account.
Orpheus, on the other hand, was broadly famed throughout the Greek world. The
characteristics Apollonius chose to attribute to him, which mainly focus on his close
112
relationship to the divine world and Apollo in particular, were welcome tools for the
creation of an eminently authoritative reflection of his own poetical persona and practices.
The means by which these correspondences between the narrator/creator of the new poetry
and their mythological alter egos/forebears are implied, are manifold, subtle, and
cumulative. They pervade the works of Theocritus and Apollonius like a slight strain, a motif
that repeats and echoes just audibly enough to be picked up by the perceptive reader and be
construed as a pedigree for their poetry.
113
114
CHAPTER 4:
THE MUSES’ BIRDCAGE: POETIC CRITICISM OF CONTEMPORARIES
4.1 Introduction
Although Hellenistic poets were strongly influenced by their predecessors, as the previous
chapters have shown, it would go too far to say that they had no eye for contemporary
colleagues. Numerous poetical testimonies show that they reflected and commented upon
them as well. How these comments function and what drives underlie them, are the topics of
the next two chapters.
Before starting the discussion of this topic, it is important to recognize that literary
criticism is rarely a question of aesthetic judgment alone; it is embedded in the societal
values and interests of the community in which it is formed. 1 In the case of the Alexandrian
poets, this community primarily consisted of the select company of scholars and poets in the
library and museum of the Ptolemies and the friends, family, and guests of the monarch. 2
Most Alexandrian poetry, like a good deal of Hellenistic poetry in general, was therefore in
all likelihood (financially) encouraged by the court and meant to please it. 3 Hellenistic poets
must have been continually aware of the necessity to garner the favor of patrons, particularly
when interacting with their contemporaries, who were presumably both colleagues and
rivals. 4 The fragment of Timon of Phlius referenced in the title of this chapter is usually
quoted to illustrate this: 5
1 Cf. e.g. Eagleton (1985); contra e.g. Schwinge (1986), who believes that Hellenistic poetry should be
read as pure art for art’s sake. Nowadays this is a minority view.
2 Alexandria is the literary community about which most is currently known. Other literary societies at
other courts would presumably provide a similar picture. At any rate, Alexandria was the largest
centre of learning and culture. It attracted more scholars and poets than other courts, such as
Pergamon.
3 Weber shows that this does not imply that Hellenistic poets wrote propagandistic poetry in a
modern sense; on the methodological problems of defining “propaganda” in antiquity, see Weber
(1993: 400‐417), Enenkel and Pfeijffer (2004: 1‐13).
4 This has not always been sufficiently recognized in scholarship, although recently there is an
awakening of interest in this aspect of Hellenistic poetry, cf. Weber (1993), Too (1998), Stephens (2005),
Strootman (2007: 189‐246). These studies do not, however, treat the specific topic of the interaction
between poets. For other Hellenistic references to Ptolemaic patronage, cf. e.g. Theoc. Id. 17.111‐116,
where Ptolemy II is praised for his εὐεργεσία towards poets.
5 The passage in Ath. 1.22d, where these lines are cited, indicates that the fragment refers to the
Alexandrian Museum; it is however not certain that poets are primarily meant; the scholarly
occupations may have afforded even more scope for argument and quarrels.
115
πολλοὶ μὲν βόσκονται ἐν Αἰγύπτῳ πολυφύλῳ
βιβλιακοὶ χαρακῖται ἀπείριτα δηριόωντες
Μουσέων ἐν ταλάρῳ…(SH 786)
In Egypt of the many tribes, many bookish scribblers are being fed, endlessly
wrangling in the Muses’ birdcage …
Besides illustrating the importance of royal patronage for the philologoi and poets of the
Museum, it is taken to imply that mutual relations at this institution were not always of a
peaceful nature; endless cackling and crest picking apparently went on amongst its fellows. 6
Such aggression, which is often considered characteristic of this period (particularly
Callimachus is notorious for his polemical persona) is the focus of this chapter. The
professions of friendship and admiration also found in the poetry of this age are addressed
in the next.
4.2 Competition and Strife in Pre‐Hellenistic Poetic Culture
Before the “Muses’ birdcage” of the Hellenistic era can be explored, the tradition of literary
competition in which it stands deserves some comment. Hesiod’s description of Ἔρις (Strife)
is an excellent starting point for a first enquiry into possible drives underlying the interaction
between poets:
Οὐκ ἄρα μοῦνον ἔην Ἐρίδων γένος, ἀλλ’ ἐπὶ γαῖαν
εἰσὶ δύω∙ τὴν μέν κεν ἐπαινήσειε νοήσας,
ἣ δ’ ἐπιμωμητή∙ διὰ δ’ ἄνδιχα θυμὸν ἔχουσιν.
ἣ μὲν γὰρ πόλεμόν τε κακὸν καὶ δῆριν ὀφέλλει,
σχετλίη∙ οὔ τις τήν γε φιλεῖ βροτός, ἀλλ’ ὑπ’ ἀνάγκης
ἀθανάτων βουλῇσιν Ἔριν τιμῶσι βαρεῖαν.
τὴν δ’ ἑτέρην προτέρην μὲν ἐγείνατο Νὺξ ἐρεβεννή,
θῆκε δέ μιν Κρονίδης ὑψίζυγος, αἰθέρι ναίων,
γαίης [τ’] ἐν ῥίζῃσι καὶ ἀνδράσι πολλὸν ἀμείνω∙
ἥ τε καὶ ἀπάλαμόν περ ὁμῶς ἐπὶ ἔργον ἐγείρει∙
εἰς ἕτερον γάρ τίς τε ἴδεν ἔργοιο χατίζων
πλούσιον, ὃς σπεύδει μὲν ἀρόμεναι ἠδὲ φυτεύειν
οἶκόν τ’ εὖ θέσθαι∙ ζηλοῖ δέ τε γείτονα γείτων
εἰς ἄφενος σπεύδοντ’∙ ἀγαθὴ δ’ ἥδε βροτοῖσιν.
καὶ κεραμεὺς κεραμεῖ κοτέει καὶ τέκτονι τέκτων,
καὶ πτωχὸς πτωχῷ φθονέει καὶ ἀοιδὸς ἀοιδῷ. (Op. 10‐25)
6 See on this fragment and its translation in particular Mineur (1985: 383‐385).
116
So there was not just one birth of Strifes after all, but upon the earth there are two
Strifes. One of these a man would praise once he got to know it, but the other is
blameworthy; and they have thoroughly opposed spirits. For the one fosters evil war
and conflict—cruel one, no mortal loves that one, but it is by necessity that they
honor the oppressive Strife, by the plans of the immortals. But the other one gloomy
Night bore first; and Cronus’ highthroned son, who dwells in the aether, set it in the
roots of the earth, and it is much better for men. It rouses even the helpless man to
work. For a man who is not working but who looks at some other man, a rich one
who is hastening to plow and plant and set his house in order, he envies him, one
neighbor envying his neighbor who is hastening towards wealth: and this Strife is
good for mortals. And potter is angry with potter and builder with builder, and
beggar begrudges beggar, and poet poet. (transl. Most)
Hesiod distinguishes bad Strife, which engenders aggression and destruction, from good
Strife, which ensures cultural and economical progress by inciting envy of others’ success
and hence competition (19‐23).7 He apparently sees the latter as an active force in the
development of song, as it may be inferred that the professional envy that poets feel towards
each other pushes them towards better composition and performance. The mechanism
posited in this passage seems to be confirmed by the observation that several early Greek
poets use the perceived defects of their predecessors or contemporaries to draw attention to
their own superior poetic judgment and qualities. This is demonstrated for instance in
Pindar’s and Aristophanes’ well known criticism of other poets. 8
Alternatively, poets may claim to be the object of envy (presumably of their
colleagues), for only what is excellent is envied, as Pindar states:
πολλὰ γὰρ πολλᾷ λέλεκται, ν<εα>ρὰ δ’ ἐξευ‐
ρόντα δόμεν βασάνῳ
ἐς ἔλεγχον, ἅπας κίνδυνος∙ ὄ‐
ψον δὲ λόγοι φθονεροῖσιν,
ἅπτεται δ’ ἐσλῶν ἀεί, χειρόνεσσι δ’ οὐκ ἐρίζει. (N. 8 18‐24)
For many things have been said in many ways, but to discover new ones and put
them to the touchstone for testing is sheer danger, since words are dessert to the
envious, and envy fastens always on the good, but has no quarrel with lesser men.
(transl. Race)
7 Cf. Hdt. 3.80.3: envy is natural to man and has been so from the beginning. On the Greek concept of
envy, see Walcot (1978), Konstan and Ruthers (2003).
8 E.g. Pi. N. 4.6, N. 7.15‐24, O. 2.87‐8; the scholia claim that Pindar is quarreling here with Bacchylides
and Simonides. P. 2.55, N. 7.21 respectively invite comparison between Archilochus’ and Homer’s
poetry and Pindar’s own. Aristophanes’ parabaseis (e.g. Ach. 629; Eq. 507; Nub. 518; Vesp. 1015; Pax 734;
Ran. 12) criticize his colleagues in the field of comedy.
117
As Hesiod saw correctly, then, this all works on the principle of competition: a poet gains
status if he is better than a colleague or predecessor or if he is object of envy. Thus early
poetic criticism often involved poets positioning themselves against others.
In addition to being influenced by such mechanisms of personal competition and
strife, criticism over time acquired theoretical, often aesthetic or moral, foundations. Literary
criticism in the modern sense (i.e., the systematic interpretation and evaluation of literary
texts) became a discipline in its own right in the time of the sophists, such as Gorgias. It was
laid down in treatises (e.g., Aristotle’s Poetics and Rhetoric) and presumably formed the
subject of many of the (now lost) writings of scholars in the Museum and Library of
criticism little is known. What remains is fragmentary, taken from tattered papyruses or
from paraphrases in later grammarians. A category apart is formed by the badly damaged
Herculaneum papyri of Philodemus’ On Poems; yet most theories discussed in this work
seem to have little in common with what can be seen in Hellenistic poetic practice. 11 Other
critical treatises that contain or reflect Hellenistic theories are from later periods and
therefore contaminate these theories with earlier and later views, making them hardly useful
for judging Hellenistic criticism. 12
This lack of independent information about Hellenistic criticism explains why
analyses of meta‐poetic and critical expressions in Hellenistic poetry itself have been
9 On criticism until Plato, see e.g. Harriott (1969), Kennedy (1989), Ford (2002); on Greek literary
criticism in general, see Verdenius (1983). Examples of (lost) Hellenistic criticism are Callimachus’
Pinakes, cf. Blum (1991); Grapheion (fr. 380 Pf.) and Museum cf. Pfeiffer (1968: 339); Apollonius’ studies
on Archilochus, cf. Pfeiffer (1968: 141), Fraser (1972: II, 653, nn. 38‐9). On ancient literary scholarship in
general, see Pfeiffer (1968). On Hellenistic scholarship, see Bing (1993: 619‐631), Rossi (2001: 86‐91),
Rengakos (1993; 1994; 2001), with special reference to the study of Homer’s texts.
10 Cf. Str. 14.657 on Philitas: ποιητὴς ἅμα και κριτικός. This combination had never been applied to
anyone before; the stress in the expression falls on ποιητής, cf. Pfeiffer (1968: 89).
11 Cf. Janko (2003: 120‐165). The main concern of the critics who Philodemus discusses is εὐφωνία (the
pleasantness of sound, putting sound over content). This is presumably an Epicurean tenet, related to
the idea of ψυχαγωγία (poetry’s ability to enchant the soul). Only a certain Heracleodorus named by
Philodemus has something in common with Hellenistic poets. He rejects the (Aristotelian) notion that
genre is linked to style and word‐choice. This resembles the views expressed on polyeideia in Call.
Iamb. 13 (fr. 203 Pf.). However, Janko dates him after Callimachus. See also Fantuzzi and Hunter (2004:
449‐461), who do find some subtle likenesses between tenets discussed by Philodemus and general
“poetics” discernible in Hellenistic poetry.
12 E.g. Demetrius’ On Style (first cent. CE, according to Schenkeveld 1964: 135‐148), Horace’s Ars
Poetica, the works of Dionysius of Halicarnassus (first cent. CE), Quintilian’s Institutio Oratoria (idem),
or Pseudo‐Longinus’ On the Sublime (third cent. CE), Photius’ Bibliotheca (ninth cent. CE), discussing
the ideas of the Alexandrian scholar Didymus (second cent. BCE).
118
attempted time and again. Since this poetry frequently self‐consciously addresses poetics,
often while demonstrating them, the approach initially seems promising. This explains the
large corpus of scholarship dedicated to the aesthetic views of the man generally considered
the arbiter elegantiarum of the Hellenistic period, Callimachus. 13 When examined, the
aesthetic points of view expressed in his poetry (most importantly the Aetia‐prologue and
Hymn II) reveal that he disliked long bombastic works and preferred elegant poetry on a
small scale. All in all this seems a bit disappointing and rather unsurprising, since it reflects
the exact image of the poetry he himself produced. An analysis of the rhetorical strategy
underlying his expressions is more instructive.
In the ensuing, I discuss some Callimachean passages from such a rhetorical and
strategic point of view. Besides I will analyze the famous debate allegedly instigated by
Callimachus on how (not) to write poetry. To structure observations on these issues,
reference will be made to the theory of the Field of Cultural Production as established by
Pierre Bourdieu. While the relative scarcity of material prevents sociologists from composing
twentieth‐century France, Bourdieu’s theory will, as I hope to show, nevertheless shed new
light on the social aspects of Alexandrian poetry. 14
4.3 Bourdieu’s Field of Cultural Production
Pierre Bourdieu’s sociological theory centers on the idea that art is not a category on its own,
separate from society. It is therefore not simply a disinterested expression of ideas and
emotions on the part of an artist, who is a lone genius. 15 Nor is it a product that can be
described as the outcome of rigidly determined social‐historical processes, as Marxism, for
instance, assumes. Bourdieu contends that the art world (like the fashion world, academic
world, and clerical world) has its own economic laws similar to those in the world at large.
13 The scholarly discussion following the discovery of the papyrus containing the Aetia prologue (1928)
is described by Benedetto (1993), with ample bibliography. He also discusses the “quarrel between
Callimachus and Apollonius.” Eichgruen (1961) and Cameron (1995) are examples of monographs
dedicated to Callimachus’ quarrels and critics.
14 For a study of Roman literary patronage in the age of Domitian, employing the principles of
Bourdieu’s theory, see Nauta (2002). Of course, testimonia for this era are much richer than for the
Hellenistic period.
15 For a comprehensive overview, see e.g. Bourdieu (1993).
119
He calls these “fields of cultural production” and maintains that each one operates by its
own rules and should be studied in its own right, paying attention to its specific
idiosyncrasies. Yet, it is also true that all fields operate on a similar set of principles.
The interaction between actors in a particular field determines how the “symbolic
capital” that circulates is divided. These actors include artists, patrons, “brokers” who
introduce artists to powerful and wealthy patrons, public opinion, art galleries, publishers,
and critics. 16 The acquisition of symbolic or “cultural” capital (e.g. recognition by peers as a
distinguished artist or the power to decide “who’s in and who’s out”), can lead to the
acquisition of real, monetary capital. It is clear that competition determines the economic
laws operative in the field of cultural production, but not always in obvious ways. For
instance, Bourdieu claims that elite, avant‐garde, or experimental art is sometimes
the literary world of twentieth century France, this entailed that the avant‐garde artist
generally received no share, or a relatively small share of monetary capital. Popular art was,
on the same logics, considered despicable, whereas the artist who was only considered a
genius by few, or hoped to be so by future generations, emerged as the real winner, and thus
came in possession of cultural capital of a specific type. By this kind of reasoning the avant‐
garde artist and his select public “distinguished” themselves from the broad masses.
“Distinction” is a form of cultural capital: a distinctive taste (e.g., for avant‐garde art)
proclaims membership to an elite social or intellectual category; it can only be obtained by
the happy few.
In Alexandrian literary culture, the cultural elite that appreciated avant‐garde poetry
were presumably primarily formed by the fellows of the Museum and Library and by royal
society (i.e., the king and his family, friends and courtiers). Elitist avant‐garde poetry created
for a select public would therefore presumably obtain cultural capital as well as monetary
capital, or at least the material benefits of royal patronage. This makes the logic of the
Alexandrian Field of Cultural Production somewhat different from Bourdieu’s standard.
16 Some of these categories are anachronisms in the Hellenistic era (e.g. publishers, art‐galleries, critics
in the modern sense of the word). However, there were patrons (the court elite), literary scholars, and
guilds of (dramatic) poets to foster and promote literature, cf. Weber (1993: 122‐182).
120
4.4 Callimachus and Apollonius: How (not) to write an Epic?
A fitting beginning to an analysis of the Alexandrian Muses’ Birdcage against this theoretical
background is the discussion of the most famous example of “Strife” in Hellenistic poetry. It
has long been received opinion in scholarship that the two major Alexandrian poets,
Callimachus and his student (μαθητής, Vitae) or friend (γνώριμος, P. Oxy. 1241) Apollonius,
quarreled. 17 However, there are no unequivocal ancient sources that describe the dispute or
explain what it was about.
Let me start with the first issue. The story of the quarrel can be traced to the
(probably unreliable) anonymous Vitae of Apollonius, which mention his departure to
Rhodes after an unsatisfactory public reading of the Argonautica. 18 The text of the relevant
passage in the first Vita reads:
οὗτος ἐμαθήτευσε Καλλιμάχῳ ἐν Ἀλεξανδρείᾳ ὄντι γραμματικῷ, καὶ συντάξας
ταῦτα τὰ ποιήματα ἐπεδείξατο. σφόδρα δὲ ἀποτυχὼν καὶ ἐρυθριάσας παρεγένετο
ἐν τῇ Ῥόδῳ κἀκεῖ ἐπολιτεύσατο καὶ σοφιστεύει ῥητορικοὺς λόγους, ὅθεν αὑτὸν καὶ
Ῥόδιον ἀποκαλεῖν βούλονται. (Vita β, 4‐9)
He was a student with Callimachus, the grammarian, in Alexandria and, after having
composed these poems [i.e., the Argonautica], he gave a public reading of them. But
seriously failing to obtain success and therefore very much ashamed, he went to
Rhodes and became a citizen there and taught rhetoric, and this why they like to call
this same man “of Rhodes.”
The passage makes no mention of any quarrel between Callimachus and Apollonius. That
Apollonius’ lack of success had anything to do with Callimachus must have been read into it
only later, in connection with other texts. One of these is an epigram containing an attack on
Callimachus, which was purportedly written by Apollonius:
Καλλίμαχος τὸ κάθαρμα, τὸ παίγνιον, ὁ ξύλινος νοῦς
αἴτιος ὁ γράψας Αἴτια Καλλίμαχου. (AP 11.275)
17 So e.g. Rose (1960: 325): “Apollonius clearly had a following, although Kallimachos remained the
leader of orthodox literary opinion, and the two poets did not spare each other ... the most famous
literary quarrel in antiquity.” Cf. Lesky (1971: 819), Fraser (1972: I, 749‐54), Green (1997: introduction).
The Latin poets, many of them imitators of Callimachus, do not mention the quarrel.
18 On the untrustworthiness of the Vitae of Apollonius, see Lefkowitz (1980: 1‐19), Cameron (1995: 214‐
219).
121
Callimachus, the piece of waste, the insipid joke, the wooden mind is guilty, he who
wrote the Aetia of Callimachus. 19
As Wilamowitz recognized, the presupposed situation of the epigram is that Apollonius,
when asked who was guilty of his banishment to Rhodes, gave this answer. 20 However, there
is severe doubt that this epigram should be attributed to Apollonius of Rhodes, considering
the addition in the MS of the Palatine Anthology of the cognomen ΓΡΑΜΜΑΤΙΚΟΥ (The
Grammarian) instead of the expected ΡΟΔΙΟΥ (of Rhodes). 21 That the epigram is found in
the eleventh book of the Palatine Anthology amidst satiric epigrams from the Imperial Age
also lessens its value as trustworthy evidence.
Another text (probably the latest chronologically) regarding the matter, is found in
the Suda’s remark concerning Callimachus’ enigmatic (lost) invective poem Ibis. 22
Ἴβις ἔστι δὲ ποίημα ἐπιτετηδευμένον εἰς ἀσάφειαν καὶ λοιδορίαν, εἴς τινα Ἴβιν,
γενόμενον ἐχθρὸν τοῦ Καλλιμάχου. ἦν δὲ οὗτος Ἀπολλώνιος, ὁ γράψας τὰ
Ἀργοναυτικά. (Suda s.v. Καλλίμαχος, 15‐16)
Ibis is a poem written with the intention of obscurity and blame against a certain Ibis,
who had become an enemy of Callimachus. And this was Apollonius, the one who
wrote the Argonautica.
According to the Suda then, the Ibis was written to attack Apollonius. This implies that the
poem was another expression of the literary quarrel between the two contemporaries. Alan
Cameron however persuasively argues that the second half of the explanation (“And this
was...”, ἦν δὲ οὗτος...) is a later interpolation and therefore presumably guesswork. Ibis is the
only title in the Suda’s lemma on Callimachus’ works that is explained at all, which of itself
should raise some suspicion. It is very likely that no one knew who was referred to by “Ibis,”
certainly not the tenth‐century CE scribe of the Suda (or an even later interpolator). It may
19 It is explained by Ferguson (1970: 66) as follows: Καλλίμαχος: / Κάλλυσμα: τὸ κάθαρμα /
Καλλώπισμα: τὸ παίγνιον / Καλόπους: ὁ ξύλινος [ποῦς] νοῦς. (Callimachus: Kallysma: piece of filth;
Kallopisma: joke; Kalopous: wooden [leg] mind); i.e., the epigram pretends to be based on an
alphabetical dictionary.
20 Wilamowitz (1924: I, 96‐7). However, he did not believe that the epigram was written by Apollonius,
and placed it in the tradition of rhetorical exercises in ethopoiia, cf. e.g. AP 7.351 (on the daughters of
Lycambes).
21 Cf. Cameron (1995: 227‐228). He relates it to (late) epigrams disparaging the style of Callimachus,
e.g. AP 11.321, 11.322 (1995: 229).
22 Suda s.v. Καλλίμαχος. Below, I discuss inferences drawn from Callimachus’ own implicit poetic
utterances, which never refer to any “enemy” by name, cf. on this aspect of Hellenistic poetics Treu
(1963: 273‐290).
122
indeed have been the case that the poem was a literary exercise in curse poetry, which would
mean that the person attacked never even existed. 23 Unfortunately, there is little other
information about Callimachus’ Ibis apart from this mention and hardly any about the extent
of its resemblance to Ovid’s extant poem of the same name. 24 A final verdict on the
probability that it dealt with Apollonius cannot be reached therefore.
Recently, some scholars have tried to draw the diegesis to Callimachus’ Iambus 5, into the
debate about the quarrel. It forms the synopsis to one of the more heavily tattered Iambi, of
which the contents are hard to make out. The text states:
Since the Iambus itself is in such poor condition, it is not easy to establish what this diegesis
refers to. Was there an unnamed schoolmaster attacked in Iambus 5? If so, do some critics
identify him with Apollonius and others with a certain Cleon? 25 Or was there a schoolmaster
whom Callimachus called “Apollonius” but who was a certain Cleon in reality? 26 And what
does the phrase “abusing his own pupils” (τοὺς ἰδίους μαθητὰς καταισχύνοντα) refer to?
Based on the information in the diegesis, unsurprisingly, the Iambus has been held to attack a
schoolmaster for the erotic abuse of his pupils. 27 Emanuele Lelli however has recently
proposed a different interpretation: the diegesis’ phrasing should be read in terms of literary
23 So Housman (1921: 67‐8), Cameron (1995: 228). Cf. e.g. the Hellenistic catalogue poems Arai (Curses)
by Moero and the anonymous Tattoo‐elegy (on which see Huys 1991). These too appear to be mere
literary exercises in invective, not aimed at anyone in particular.
24 Except Ov. Ib. 55‐60: Nunc quo Battiades inimicum devovet Ibin / Hoc ego devoveo teque tuosque modo. /
Utque ille, historiis involvam carmina caecis: / Non soleam quamvis hoc genus ipse sequi. / Illius ambages
imitatus in Ibide dicar / Oblitus moris iudiciique mei. (Now, as Battiades cursed his enemy Ibis, I will curse
you and yours in the same way. And like him I have involved my poem with hidden matters: I have
followed him, though I am unused to this sort of thing. Its convolutions are uttered in imitation of
those in Ibis, oblivious of my own custom and taste.) See on the possible likeness between the two
poems Housman (1921: 67‐8), La Penna (1957) introduction, Cameron (1995: 228).
25 So D’Alessio (2000: 106‐7), Lelli (2004: 114‐15).
26 So Cameron (1995: 229).
27 So first (before the diegesis had been found): Coppola (1933: 167), afterwards: Clayman (1980: 29‐33),
Kerkhecker (1999: 136‐7), Acosta‐Hughes (2002: 251‐2), Fantuzzi and Hunter (2004: 14). The verb
καταισχύνω can be used of sexual abuse (LSJ s.v. 2, e.g. Lys. 1.49.5).
123
polemic: the word “schoolmaster” is employed as a deprecatory term to belittle literary
pretence. This extremely speculative hypothesis aims to assert once more that there was a
quarrel between Apollonius and Callimachus about (epic) poetry. The weak point in Lelli’s
reasoning is evidently that there are no arguments whatsoever to assume that this Iambus is
indeed about a literary quarrel rather than about a schoolmaster abusing his pupils. The
assumption that the fifth Iambus attacked the Argonautica of Apollonius, then, does not
appear likely.
Clearly, the evidence that Apollonius and Callimachus quarreled is scanty, but, if
they did, what was supposed to have been at issue? An answer to this has generally been
sought in Callimachus’ own works, in particular the Aetia‐prologue (fr. 1 Pf.). The main
theme of this fragment is the objection to long and unrefined poetry on hackneyed themes. 28
Its polemic tone makes it attractive to be connected with the alleged quarrel. This has led to
the idea that Callimachus disliked Apollonius’ epic, as being too long, unrefined and treating
hackneyed subject matter. 29 Along an entirely different line of reasoning, scholars have
argued that one should not try and find a historical basis for the quarrel but look at it in
different terms, namely as fitting certain recurrent patterns of anecdotic biography. 30 It is
schematic, conventional lines; the insertion of a quarrel is a standard way of expressing the
assumed relationship of rivalry between two contemporary authors. An excellent
comparison for this process can be found in the way the scholia describe the relation between
Pindar and Simonides or Bacchylides. 31 These three contemporaries all wrote epinician
poetry, sometimes even for the same patrons. The scholiasts therefore assume that they were
rivals and that they quarreled. And so obscure references to “a pair of unwise crows that
cackle against the divine bird of Zeus” in Pindar’s poetry (O. 2.87‐88) are interpreted in the
scholia as referring to Bacchylides and Simonides, attacking Pindar.
28 Cf. e.g. Aetia fr. 1 Pf.; Hymn II (105‐113); AP 12.43. Cameron argues it is unlikely that the elegiac Aetia
was criticizing epic (1995: 337‐8).
29 Cf. e.g. Eichgruen (1961), Lesky (1971: 729‐30), Fraser (1972: I,636ff.), Arrighetti (1989: 157), D’Alessio
(1996), Lelli (2004: 78‐82).
30 Cf. Wehrli (1941: 14‐21), Lefkowitz (1980: 1‐19), Lloyd‐Jones (1984: 58‐9).
31 Lefkowitz (1980: 1‐19) argues that Callimachus and Apollonius deliberately created a rivalry on the
model of famous examples like these. Examples of representing contemporaries in the same field as
rivals are the Certamen Homeri Hesiodique and Ar. Ran. (Aeschylus and Euripides). Vita Aeschyli cap. 8,
mentions the rivalry between Sophocles and Aeschylus over tragedy and between Simonides and
Aeschylus over elegy.
124
Another line of approach keeps the idea of the quarrel intact but denies that it was
about poetry. This argument is as follows: Apollonius’ epic poetry is nothing if not
Callimachean in its aesthetic aims (polished, extremely refined, not really long compared to
for instance Homeric epic; a new approach to heroic subject matter). 32 Consequently, there
must have been another ground for quarreling. Fraser, for example, wildly speculates that
Apollonius’ humble Egyptian origin must have been at the bottom of it; this earned him the
scorn of the aristocratic, Greek‐Cyrenaic Callimachus. 33 This kind of conjecture of course
remains impossible to prove.
The recent return to the idea (not shared by many scholars) that the quarrel in fact
does focus on the right way to compose epic poetry is based on a new evaluation of
Callimachus’ Iambi (esp. 4 and 5). Since Apollonius and Callimachus were both masters of
the art of epic and agreed in general lines about the way to renew it, their quarrel, as
defenders of this theory claim, must have concentrated on the finer poetic details. 34 If so, it is
hard to see how modern scholars, more than two thousand years later and with little more to
go on than the implicit poetic remarks of Callimachus and their own evaluation of
Apollonius’ style, could hope to unearth this discussion.
Rounding up these considerations, it is time to reach a conclusion and to formulate
my own hypothesis about these matters. In the first place, the texts usually adduced do not
appear to justify the claim that Callimachus quarreled with Apollonius and do not suggest
what this quarrel was about. Considering that Apollonius’ epic shows definite signs of
Callimachean influence, 35 it seems unlikely that Callimachus objected to Apollonius’ poem
32 E.g. Lefkowitz (1981: 133‐135), Margolies (1995), Cuypers (2004: 43‐63).
33 Fraser (1972: I, 753‐4) bases this on the fact that the ibis (hence the title of the poem Ibis) is an
indigenous Egyptian bird; from this he deduced that Apollonius had a native Egyptian background.
34 Arrighetti (1989: 157), D’Alessio (1996: ad loc.), Lelli (2004: 78‐82). The latter claims they quarreled
about the merits of the Argonautica and the Hecale on the following grounds: 1) Length: Apollonius
adhered to the length of three tragedies and a satyr play for his epic, unlike Callimachus. 2) Unity:
Apollonius chose a grand unified theme for his epic; Callimachus chose a futile, un‐heroic element of
myth (Hecale). 3) Character: Apollonius’ epic is “tragic” whereas Callimachus’ epic is elegiac‐comic
(Hecale). Most of these assumptions cannot be proven: ad 1): It is unknown whether the length of the
Argonautica was coincidence or planned; it is unknown how long Hecale was (cf. Hollis 1990: 3‐7). Ad
2): The unity of the Argonautica is not of the kind that Aristotle meant (cf. Hunter, 1993: appendix). Ad
3): This might be granted, cf. Callimachus’ objections against poems about “deeds of heroes and
kings” (Aetia). However Apollonius’ Jason and Medea are not traditional heroes; cf. e.g. Lawall (1966:
121‐169).
35 E.g. the numerous aetiological explanations, the fact that Callimachus also treated the myth of the
Argonauts (cf. Aet. frs. 7‐21 Pf.), the innovative style in general. This approach presumes, as most
125
for being at odds with his own poetic credo of elegance, refinement, and the novel treatment
of traditional subject matter. Therefore, I would prefer to propose an altogether different
approach. It was natural for later readers to suppose that a quarrel between Callimachus and
Apollonius rather arose out of the (uncomfortably) close similarity of style and subject matter.
Like Pindar and his “rivals,” Callimachus and Apollonius worked in the same environment
for the same patrons and wrote poetry in similar styles on the same subjects. Later
generations may have felt this situation was bound to end in quarreling. 36 In Bourdieu’s
terms, it was attractive to assume that two actors operating in the same field of cultural
production, striving for the same cultural capital, dependent on the same recipients, would
end up as rivals. This has been garbled into a story about a quarrel on poetic differences. The
polemical persona that speaks from so much of Callimachus’ poetry did the rest.
4.5 The Aetia‐Prologue: Polemic or Preaching to the Converted?
The most notorious instance of this polemical persona of Callimachus appears in the Aetia‐
prologue (fr. 1 Pf.). However, if we can no longer connect this text to an alleged quarrel
between Apollonius and Callimachus, it is unclear which dispute it references, if any. It has
often been read as a forestalling of expected criticism on the Aetia (or Callimachus’ poetics in
general) from a rivaling poetic faction. 37 Recently, the historical realities behind the polemics
presented in the prologue have, like the quarrel between Apollonius and Callimachus,
become subject to doubt: was Callimachus as beleaguered by critics as he would have his
readers believe? 38 Is it necessary, or even possible, to identify the critics whom Callimachus
(like the Scholia Florentina on the Aetia) calls the “Telchines?”
scholars from antiquity onwards do, that Callimachus is the elder of the two and therefore more likely
to have influenced Apollonius, cf. e.g. Fraser (1972: I, 627, 631‐2, 635, 751, 776, 783).
36 Cf. Lefkowitz (1980: 1‐19). It could be objected that there is also a great similarity between
Theocritus (esp. Id. 13 and 22) and Apollonius, while here ancient tradition makes no mention of a
quarrel. However, presumably Theocritus was not linked to the Alexandrian Museum. It might also
be argued that his poetry was rather different from that of Apollonius, in not containing a full‐blown
epic, like e.g. Callimachus’ Hecale was.
37 Cameron (1995: 104‐133) thinks the reference is strictly to the Aetia; Fraser (1972: I, 754‐6, 760) thinks
it refers to Callimachus’poetics in general; this has long been the dominant view in histories of Greek
literature.
38 Most explicitly Lefkowitz (1981: 120‐125), Cameron (1995: passim), Asper (1997: 247), Schmitz (1999:
151‐178).
126
The answer to both questions partly depends on which readers Callimachus
envisaged for the Aetia. 39 It may be confidently asserted that this poem was meant primarily
for court circles, since the Ptolemies figure prominently in it. 40 Its secondary audience would
have been broader: anyone able to appreciate Callimachus’ style of writing. This would have
included his educated Greek‐speaking contemporaries in Alexandria and abroad, and
eventually, later generations. 41 As it seems inherently likely that appreciation of his work
would not have been limited to an inner circle, references to “literary adversaries” would
have had to be comprehensible for them, too, and cannot have been entirely esoteric.
It could be asked, a fortiori, why the Ptolemies, the most important members of
Callimachus’ intended audience, would have lent their support to a poet who was obscure,
controversial and continually occupied with personal literary feuds when they could have
had any poet at their command. Surely, the esoteric detail of literary quarrels in which rivals
needed to be identified from obscure clues would have held little interest for them and can
therefore hardly be expected to have featured in a poem that sang their praises, as the Aetia
does. On the other hand, supporting an excellent poet who stated that his elitist aesthetics
were not to be grasped by all may have appealed to their expectations and given them the
pleasurable sense of possessing a distinguished taste. The question must therefore be
repeated: was Callimachus what he wants the reader to believe he was, a truly controversial
poet admired by few and envied, attacked, and misunderstood by many? It may well be that
this is a convenient and flattering exaggeration, perhaps even a partial fiction, designed to
enhance the sense of “exclusive taste” in order to please his patrons. Whether or not “the
Telchines” attacked in the Aetia–prologue actually are the individuals identified by the
Scholia Florentina becomes of secondary importance in this light. What counts is that
39 In the ensuing, I will use the word “readers” to indicate the recipients (contemporary or otherwise)
of Callimachus’ poetry; this does not mean that I think Callimachus never recited his poetry.
40 E.g. The Lock of Berenice (fr. 110 Pf.). For Callimachus’ relation with the Ptolemaic court, see e.g.
Fraser (1972: I; 663, 789‐90), Weber (1993: 122‐149), Cameron (1995: 3‐71), Stephens (2004: 161‐176).
Weber argues that such an audience would have comprised an educated elite from several Greek
poleis consisting of intellectuals, friends of the King, high military officers, rich merchants, aristocratic
guests and ambassadors of other Kings.
41 Even Callimachus’ larger readership will presumably have been a relative minority. However,
estimates of ancient literacy are greatly at odds; for arguments in favor of a relatively high rate of
literacy in Hellenistic Egypt, see Cameron (1995: 47‐53). For Callimachus also having future
generations in mind, cf. fr. 7.13‐4 Pf.
127
Callimachus can boast of envious opponents, like Pindar once did, and thus paradoxically
heighten his own standing as a poet. 42
This insight enhances the importance of analyzing the Telchines’ portrayal as literary
opponents. Taking the Aetia prologue as a primary example and providing parallels from
other poems, I will illustrate how Callimachus manipulates his readers, making them an
offer they cannot refuse. 43 The attempt to gain distinction in the field of cultural production
will prove to be an important factor determining this rhetorical strategy.
To return to the initial problem, approaching it in terms of rhetorical strategy (rather
than historical investigation), we may now ask: who is Callimachus addressing in the
prologue to his Aetia and how does he address them? It is necessary to look at the text in its
entirety to answer this.
......]ι μοι Τελχῖνες ἐπιτρύζουσιν ἀοιδῇ,
νήιδες οἳ Μούσης οὐκ ἐγένοντο φίλοι,
εἵνεκεν οὐχ ἓν ἄεισμα διηνεκὲς ἢ βασιλ[η
......]ας ἐν πολλαῖς ἤνυσα χιλιάσιν
ἢ .....].ους ἥρωας, ἔπος δ’ ἐπὶ τυτθὸν ἑλ[ίσσω (5)
παῖς ἅτε, τῶν δ’ ἐτέων ἡ δεκὰς οὐκ ὀλίγη.
......].[.]και Τε[λ]χῖσιν ἐγὼ τόδε∙ “φῦλον α[
.......] τήκ[ειν] ἧπαρ ἐπιστάμενον,
......].. ρ̣εην̣ [ὀλ]ιγόστιχος∙ ἀλλὰ καθέλκει
.... πολὺ τὴν μακρὴν ὄμπνια Θεσμοφόρο[ς∙ (10)
τοῖν δὲ] δ̣υ̣οῖν Μίμνερμος ὅτι γλυκύς, αἱ κατὰ λεπτόν
......] ἡ μεγάλη δ’ οὐκ ἐδίδαξε γυνή.
.....]ο̣ν ἐπὶ Θρήϊκας ἀπ’ Αἰγύπτοιο [πέτοιτο
αἵματ]ι̣ Π̣υ̣γ̣μαίων ἡδο̣μ̣έ̣νη [γ]έρα[νος,
Μασσαγ̣έ̣τ̣αι καὶ μακρὸν ὀϊστεύοιεν ἐπ’ ἄνδρα (15)
Μῆδον]∙ ἀ̣[ηδονίδες] δ̣’ ὧδε μελιχρ[ό]τεραι.
ἔλλετε Βασκανίης ὀλοὸν γένος∙ αὖθι δὲ τέχνῃ
κρίνετε,] μὴ σχοίνῳ Περσίδι τὴν σοφίην∙
μηδ’ ἀπ’ ἐμεῦ διφᾶτε μέγα ψοφέουσαν ἀοιδήν
τίκτεσθαι∙ βροντᾶν οὐκ ἐμόν, ἀλλὰ Διός.” (20)
καὶ γὰρ ὅτε πρώτιστον ἐμοῖς ἐπὶ δέλτον ἔθηκα
γούνασιν, Ἀ[πό]λλων εἶπεν ὅ μοι Λύκιος∙
“.......]... ἀοιδέ, τὸ μὲν θύος ὅττι πάχιστον
θρέψαι, τὴ]ν̣ Μοῦσαν δ’ ὠγαθὲ λεπταλέην∙
πρὸς δέ σε] καὶ τόδ’ ἄνωγα, τὰ μὴ πατέουσιν ἅμαξαι (25)
τὰ στείβειν, ἑτέρων ἴχνια μὴ καθ’ ὁμά
Cf. Lefkowitz (1981: 1‐19).
42
The following builds upon some important insights formulated by Asper (1997: 246‐247) and
43
Schmitz (1999: 151‐178).
128
δίφρον ἐλ]ᾶ̣ν μηδ’ οἷμον ἀνὰ πλατύν, ἀλλὰ κελεύθους
ἀτρίπτο]υ̣ς, εἰ καὶ στειν̣οτέρην ἐλάσεις.”
τῷ πιθόμη]ν∙ ἐνὶ τοῖς γὰρ ἀείδομεν οἳ λιγὺν ἦχον
τέττιγος, θ]όρυβον δ’ οὐκ ἐφίλησαν ὄνων. (30)
θηρὶ μὲν οὐατόεντι πανείκελον ὀγκήσαιτο
ἄλλος, ἐγ]ὼ δ’ εἴην οὑλ̣[α]χύς, ὁ πτερόεις,
ἆ πάντ⌋ως, ἵνα γῆρας ἵνα δρόσον ἣν μὲν ἀείδω
πρώκιο⌋ν ἐκ δίης ἠέρος εἶδαρ ἔδων,
αὖθι τ⌋ὸ̣ δ̣’ ⌊ἐκ⌋δύοιμ⌊ι⌋, τό μοι βάρος ὅσσον ἔπεστι (35)
τριγ⌋λ̣ώ̣⌊χι⌋ν̣ ὀλ⌊οῷ⌋ νῆσος ἐπ’ Ἐγκελάδῳ.
....... Μοῦσαι γ⌋ὰρ ὅσους ἴδον ὄθμα⌊τ⌋ι παῖδας
μὴ λοξῷ, πολιοὺς⌋ οὐκ ἀπέθεντο φίλους.
.............]σε̣[..]πτερὸν οὐκέτι κινεῖν
.............]η̣ τ̣[ῆ]μ̣ος ἐνεργότατος. (40) (Aetia fr. 1 Pf.)
The Telchines, ignoramuses, who are no friends of the Muses, often grumble at my
poetry, because [I don’t write] one continuous poem about kings’ [deeds], in many
thousands of lines, [or about] the heroes [of yore], but unfold my poetry in small
stretches like a child (5), though the decades of my years are not few. But I say this to
the Telchines: “You [...] tribe, who only know how to eat your own heart out, yes,
indeed he [or: I] was a man of few verses, but bountiful Demeter outweighs by far the
long (10) [...] and of the two [books] Mimnermus [wrote], not the Big Woman, but the
delicate [...] show that he was sweet. Let the crane that revels in the [blood] of
Pygmies fly a long stretch to Thrace from Egypt and let Massagetae shoot from a long
way off at the [Mede] (15). Yet [nightingales] are sweeter this way. Be gone, you
wretched race of the Evil Eye and from now on [judge] artistry by its craftsmanship,
not with the Persian yardstick. And don’t expect me to bring forth a loudly roaring
song. The thunder belongs to Zeus, not to me.”(20) For, the very first time I put a
writing tablet on my knees, Apollo Lycius said to me: “[Remember, dear] poet, to
fatten the victim as much as you can, but, my friend, to keep the Muse slim. And I’m
telling you another thing: take the roads that are not open to hackneys, (25) and do
not drive your [chariot] in the ruts of others, and not over the broad way, but on
[untrodden] paths, even if that means driving along a narrower lane.” [Him I
obeye]d, for we sing among those who love the shrill sound [of the cicada], but not
the braying of asses. (30) Let [another] swell till he grows indistinguishable from the
long eared beast; I’d rather be the small one, the winged one, yes, indeed, that I might
sing and feed on dew, the food from the air divine and shed old age that weighs
upon me, as heavy as the Three Cornered Isle weighs on Enceladus. (35) [But no
matter]: for upon who the Muses in childhood looked with no unfriendly gaze, they
won’t neglect them when they are grey. [...] no longer stirs its wing, then most
energetically [...]. (40)
Callimachus opens by referring to the Telchines in the third person, which immediately
makes clear that they are not the addressees of the prologue, but rather its subject. Educated
129
contemporaries of Callimachus would have known that the “Telchines” were mythical
wizards with associations of malevolence and envy. 44 But modern readers also easily
understand without this detailed knowledge that the Telchines are to be understood as
Callimachus’ rightful enemies. They are unintelligent creatures (νήιδες, 2) and no friends of
the Muses, the goddesses of poetry (2) with whom Callimachus professes to be closely
associated (37), or Apollo (22‐28). Since the Telchines are disqualified as unperceptive
readers of poetry, his readers will want to feel that they are more discerning than these
creatures, even if Callimachus does not directly tell them so. The Telchines function as foils. 45
In the sequel, the readers are again invited, this time in a positive way to identify
with Callimachus’ ideal audience: “We sing for those who love the sweet sound of the
cicada, but not the loud braying of asses” (29‐30). 46 When confronted with this easy
dichotomy, no one would care to be among those who prefer the braying of asses to the
cicada’s music. In both instances, Callimachus manipulates his readers’ self‐esteem in order
to assure their sympathy. 47 He maneuvers them into the role of the ideal audience.
Apart from assuring his audience’s sympathy in this way, Callimachus moreover
contrasts the alleged opinions of the Telchines with his own poetic practices and with the
instructions he has received from the god of poetry, Apollo. 48 As relayed by Callimachus,
their charges amount to the following (I paraphrase): lack of unity, lack of elevated subject
matter, and lack of length, resulting in incoherent, whimsical, and short poems.
Callimachus’ defense against this criticism is the following: you are just envious
(7/8); 49 I know short poetry that is better than long poetry (examples, 9‐16); 50 One should
44 The Telchines are chthonic wizards (Hesych. s.v. Τελχῖνες associates their name with θέλγειν, to
bewitch), connected with metallurgy, envious of sharing their professional knowledge, and generally
linked with envy, spite and the evil eye (Suda s.v. Τελχῖνες, Ov. Met. 7.366). They brought up
Poseidon on Rhodes (Diod. Sic. 5.55.3), which might be interpreted as providing a connection with
Apollonius; except he was not of Rhodian origin, but went to Rhodes late in life. Presumably the
epithet “Rhodian” was given after his death, to distinguish him from the later Alexandrian librarian
also called Apollonius (“the Eidographer,” cf. P. Oxy. 1241).
45 Cf. Schmitz (1999: 162‐163).
46 Schmitz (1999: 163) uses the term “implied reader.”
47 For examples of this tactic, cf. e.g. Pi. N. 4.36‐43; P. 1.81‐85; P. 2.88‐end; O. 2.87‐8, cf. Lefkowitz (1981:
120‐121).
48 The epithet Lycius is relevant, since according to Serv. Aen. 4.377, it is linked with the god as
destroyer of the Telchines. Apollo features as champion of Callimachus’ poetics too in Hymn II, 105‐
113.
49 For the implication of jealousy in 8: τήκ[ειν] ἧπαρ ἐπιστάμενον, cf. Pfeiffer (1949: ad loc.), cf. also
line 17, where the Telchines are addressed as the hateful children of Βασκανίη (the Evil Eye).
130
judge poetry by its craftsmanship, not by its length (17‐8); don’t expect loud and booming
poetry; it is not my job (19‐20). By accusing the Telchines of envy, he implies that their
criticism is not based on aesthetics but rather on (professional) rivalry: they object to his
success, rather than to his style. As Glenn Most has remarked with reference to Pindar’s
frequent mention of this emotion, “Envy is the necessary concomitant of great deeds; its
presence is a proof of the greatness of outstanding success just as its absence is an indication
of mere mediocrity.” 51 This observation sheds an interesting light on the representation of
the Telchines’ judgment; actually, by implication, it reverses it. By claiming that the Telchines
are envious of his poetic achievements, Callimachus wishes to make his readers think that he
must be really good.
Reinforcing this indirect appeal, he addresses their unfair criticism by demonstrating
that long poetry is not necessarily better than short poetry with examples from earlier elegiac
poetry (Mimnermus, Philitas). Length (the Persian schoenus) is no criterion for judging
poetry; craftsmanship (τέχνη) is. This claim is patently obvious, as it would be ridiculous to
consider length a concern of literary criticism, but it also implies that Callimachus’ poetry
would fare well in an assessment of craftsmanship. Next, he says he will not “thunder like
Zeus” (i.e., produce bombastic poetry), 52 implicitly connecting a bombastic style to the kind
of poetry that the Telchines accuse him of not writing.
It is noteworthy that Callimachus does not answer the remaining charges himself.
The lack of unity and triviality of the subject matter are apparently harder to counter than
the (absurd) claim that a poem should be long in order to be good. 53 So divine authority is
introduced. Apollo himself gave Callimachus two pieces of advice when he was young (I
paraphrase): “A sacrificial animal should be fat, but the Muse should be slender. Take the
roads that are not open to all” (23‐28). Both components are metaphorical and, coming from
50 The possible supplements to lines 9‐12 are a veritable can of worms. I favor Cameron’s reading,
based on the remarks of Bowie (1986: 13‐35): the poets referred to are Philitas and Mimnermus; their
short poems appear to be contrasted favorably to their long ones.
51 Most (2003: 139). Considering the frequency with which Callimachus refers to the envy his poetry
has roused this is an important statement. E.g. Hymn II, 105‐113 and. AP 7.525,4, where the coupling of
Φθόνος (Envy) and Μῶμος (Blame) implies that any blame of Callimachus’ poetry can only be the
result of envy.
52 Cf. Ar. Ran. 814 on Aeschylus’ style; Ar. Ach. 530‐1 on that of Pericles’. In itself thunder coming from
Zeus is respectable; when it comes from someone trying to imitate him, it becomes hubristic.
Callimachus thus implicitly accuses the Telchines of impious expectations.
53 Cf. the criticism of Φθόνος in Hymn II, 105‐113, where length is the single criterion too.
131
Apollo, one might be tempted to say, slightly oracular. This indeterminacy of Apollo’s
guidance is purposeful. The opposition between the fat sacrificial animal and the slender
Muse refers to the opposition between big and small poems. The adjective qualifying the
Muse, λεπτός, moreover, is a keyword in Hellenistic poetic discourse 54 meaning not only
“slim, thin” but also “refined, elegant, delicate.” Similarly, πάχυς means “physically thick”
as well as “(mentally) thick, obtuse, slow‐witted.” 55
Although the poem did not start out with the idea that small equals refined and big
equals unrefined per se, this is where Calllimachus has now maneuvered his readers: first
purely quantitative terms, they have surreptitiously metamorphosed into qualitative terms
small, difficult paths. 57 This debated phrase seems to refer to what might be termed
“originality” or the “avant‐garde.” Apollo’s precept probably serves to justify Callimachus’
implying that it is equal to elegance and justifies the lack of unity and serious subject matter
as “original and out of the ordinary,” “following of the untrodden paths.” A divine sanction
thus rests on the poetics that Callimachus claims to embrace.
Now, Callimachus has put forward two points of view regarding poetry: that of the
envious demonic Telchines and that of Apollo, god of poets. Even disregarding their views,
this opposition does not represent a difficult choice. It is entirely justified that Callimachus
should follow the latter (“Him I obeyed”, 29 [τῷ πιθόμη]ν). He restates his credo for
reinforcement: “We wish to sing among an audience that prefers the shrill sound of cicadas
to the braying of asses” (29‐30); “I would rather be a refined cicada than a puffed up ass, so
54 The first to remark on this was Reitzenstein (1931: 23‐70). For the topic of λεπτότης, see Ch. 5.2.
55 Cf. Asper (1997: 135‐153). The adjective returns in fr. 398 Pf., to characterize Antimachus’ Lyde, cf.
Krevans (1993: 149‐161).
56 Cf. Apollo’s answer to Φθόνος’ criticism, Hymn II, 105‐113. Here too greatness is linked with filth
(the Assyrian river) and shortness with purity (springs of water from which offerings to Demeter can
be fetched). Call. AP 9.566 links brevity with victory in dramatic contests. Cf. Asper (1997: 198).
57 The image of the untrodden road as metaphor for refined if underestimated poetry returns in Call.
AP 9.565. Asper (1997: 64‐72) shows that the metaphor of the road does not derive from one particular
poetic text, e.g. Pi. Paean 7b, as has often been claimed, or Hesiod Op. 290‐292.
58 He favors disjunctive and allusive narrative (e.g. Acontius and Cydippe, Aetia fr. 67‐75 Pf.) chooses
humble subjects (e.g. Hecale) and quaint angles (e.g. Molorchus’ invention of the mousetrap, fr. 54‐59
Pf.). Harder suggests that “untrodden paths” refer to Callimachus’ novel use of narratological devices
in the Aetia (1990: 287‐309).
132
that I might feed upon dew and shed old age“ (31‐36). Once more, the suggestion of small
(cicada) versus big (ass) is connected to inherent positive or negative stylistic qualities,
respectively, this time expressed through metaphors of sound. 59
Finally, the poet professes that he is old and tired, but that it does not matter as long
as he enjoys the sympathy of the Muses (37‐8). With a nod to the Telchines, “no friends” of
these goddesses (2), the text seems to have come full circle. After this, the fragment breaks
off. On the basis of the London Scholium, Pfeiffer suggests that Callimachus went on to praise
the Muses and Queen Arsinoe, wife of Ptolemy Philadelphus, here (1949 ad fr. 1.40 ff.).
The arsenal of rhetorical strategies deployed to convince the addressees that
Callimachus’ is the only feasible kind of poetry is not mean: it consists of false oppositions,
the aesthetics of exclusivity, the argument of authority, and the suggestion that the poet is
envied for his excellence by malevolent creatures. Reviewing scholarship of the past, it
appears this strategy has worked remarkably well in many cases. Callimachus has often been
taken at his word as a lone warrior for the cause of good taste, threatened by insipid
criticasters who prefer bombast and antiquated poetic forms. 60 Many have admired
Callimachus’ brave and lonely stance—and perhaps themselves for admiring him.
This circular admiration is exactly what Bourdieu describes with the term
“distinction.” The rhetoric of the Aetia‐prologue creates a position of exclusivity not only for
the author, but also for all who profess to enjoy his poetry. Distinction is impossible where
there is no disagreement of tastes; therefore the Telchines, historical or not, are a welcome
and necessary foil. They embody the positive aspect that Glenn Most finds present in
otherwise despicable envy, “… the acrid smoke which may well sting our eyes but is
nonetheless the irrefutable and hence not entirely unwelcome proof of the existence of the
blazing fire of an almost superhuman success.” 61
4.6 The Telchines and the Lyde
As has been demonstrated, whether or not the Telchines existed in historical reality is a
relatively unimportant issue for assessing the rhetorical strategies of the Aetia‐prologue.
59 Asper (1997: 197‐180).
60 E.g. Ziegler (1934), Brink (1963: 71), Smotrytsch (1963: 249‐256), Lohse (1973: 20‐43).
61 Most (2003: 139).
133
What comes across perfectly without this certainty is the (deliberately constructed) image of
an exclusive, elitist, and excellent poet who writes for a select readership appreciative of a
level of sophistication inaccessible to the masses. Nevertheless, the identification of the
Telchines has been attempted since antiquity and like the quarrel of Callimachus and
Apollonius, deserves some comments here.
The fragmentary Scholia Florentina identify the Telchines as follows:
Διονυσίοις δυ[σ]ί, τῷ ελ̣
[ ]νι κ(αὶ) τῷ ϊλ̣ειονι κ(αὶ) Ἀσκλη‐
[πιάδῃ τῷ Σικε]λίδῃ κ(αὶ) Ποσειδίππῳ τῷ ονο
[ ].υρίππῳ τῷ ῥήτορι κ(αὶ) Αν̣α̣
[ ]βῳ κ(αὶ) Πραξιφάνῃ τῷ Μιτυ‐
[ληναίῳ, τοῖς με]μφομ(έν)ο[ι]ς αὐτοῦ τὸ κάτισ̣‐
[χνον τῶν ποιη]μάτ(ων) κ(αὶ) ὅτι οὐχὶ μῆ̣κος ηρ̣α... (PSI 11.1219, fr. 1 Pf.)
[It is aimed at vel sim.] the two Dionysii, the one known as ... and ... the (?) 62 one, and
Asclepiades also known as Sicelidas, and Posidippus the ... , and the orator …yrippus
and Ana… [Two fragmentary names] …, and Praxiphanes of Mytilene, as the ones
attacking the futility of his poems, and because [they have vel sim.] no length... 63
Because of the presence of Asclepiades and Posidippus, the reception of the elegiac poem
Lyde of Antimachus (fifth‐fourth century BCE) has generally been connected with this issue.
These epigrammatists both praised the Lyde in their epigrams (AP 9.63; AP 12.168
respectively.), while Callimachus ridicules it with a dig at Asclepiades’ epigram (fr. 398
Pf.). 64 This has generally led to the conclusion that all Telchines must have been poets and
critics who, like Asclepiades and Posidippus, appreciated the Lyde and attacked Callimachus
for writing elegiac poetry that did not conform to the example set by Antimachus. 65
However, as has most forcibly been argued by Alan Cameron, 66 the relationship
between the Scholia Florentina, Asclepiades’ and Posidippus’ epigrams and Callimachus’
62 See Pfeiffer on the possible adjective (1949: ad loc.).
63 Apart from Asclepiades, Posidippus and Praxiphanes, it is impossible to identify the individuals
named. Apollonius cannot be fitted into any of the lacunae, cf. Pfeiffer (1949: ad loc.), Fraser (1972: I,
747, 749, 750‐1; II, 1052, n. 251).
64 See Ch. 2.5.2. The Lyde was popular, as the epigrams of Asclepiades and Posidippus attest. The latter
also wrote an epigram on a theme drawn from it (SH 703). Lyde also figures in Hermesianax fr. 7.41‐6
Powell. Cameron (1995: 485‐7) moreover wants to restore Λύδη in a corrupt epigram by Hedylus (Ath.
11.45.17‐45) and Crates (AP 11.218) implies that Antimachus is better than Choerilus; however, see
below on this epigram.
65 Although other conjectures have been made, e.g. by Musti (1999) who (unconvincingly) relates the
Telchines to the Homeric Sirens, and thus to Homeric epic.
66 Cameron (1995, 236‐387).
134
fragment is unclear. The epigrams and fragment make it seem likely that Callimachus
disagreed with Asclepiades and Posidippus about the merits of Antimachus’ poetry. Yet, it is
improbable that Callimachus named his opponents in the now lost parts of the Aetia, so the
Scholia Florentina presumably arrived at their identification through educated guesswork.
This was based on the epigrams, which indeed suggest that Callimachus had a literary
disagreement with Asclepiades and Posidippus, and on Callimachus’ now lost polemic
treatise entitled Against Praxiphanes, which apparently also discussed the appreciation of the
Lyde. 67
The fact that the Aetia was an elegiac poem makes it inherently likely that any polemic
in its prologue would indeed have concerned elegiac poetry, as the Lyde was. 68 So the idea of
combining the information from the epigrams with the Aetia prologue is not so far‐fetched,
especially when Cameron’s ingenious interpretation of Asclepiades AP 9.63 is taken into
account. Here Lyde claims: “I am more exalted than any woman descended from Codrus,
thanks to Antimachus” (τῶν δ’ ἀπὸ Κόδρου / σεμνοτέρη πασῶν εἰμι δι’ Ἀντίμαχον, 1‐2).
This likely refers negatively to Callimachus’ character Cydippe (Aetia fr. 75.32 Pf.), who is “a
woman descended from (the legendary Athenian King) Codrus,” one of the few known to
literature. The implication would be, then, that Asclepiades wrote his epigram (AP 9.63) not
only to praise the Lyde but also to disparage the Aetia. 69
All considered, it seems probable that there was a contemporary debate on elegiac
poetry, centering on the appreciation of Antimachus’ Lyde. It is possible that this debate
involved a comparison between the Aetia and the Lyde. Whether it was waged in
Callimachus’ Aetia‐prologue remains unclear, but, if it were, I hope to have shown that
Callimachus probably tried to trump it by presenting his attackers as insipid and envious
demons and the poetics they defended as bombastic, vulgar and old‐fashioned. In itself, the
67 See Brink (1946: 11‐26) on the identity of Praxiphanes and the contents of this treatise, which
apparently criticized Plato as a poor judge of poetry for liking Antimachus (fr. 589 Pf.); it also seems to
have praised Aratus (fr. 460 Pf.). See further Pfeiffer (1968: 136), Fraser (1972: I, 749), Lefkowitz (1981:
126), Krevans (1993: 149‐161) and Cameron (1995: 301‐309).
68 Cf. Krevans (1993: 149‐161), Cameron (1995: 263‐387). This is also implied by the fact that fr. 1 Pf.
names the elegists Mimnermus and Philitas as models. The Aetia and the Lyde were probably both
long elegiac poems consisting of interwoven shorter tales, written in a learned, bookish style.
Antimachus was a scholar and editor of Homeric epic and in this aspect he seems to have been a kind
of precursor of the Hellenistic poets, which may explain his popularity in this era. On Antimachus
(fragments and testimonia) see Wyss (1936) and Matthews (1996).
69 Cameron (1995: 304‐305).
135
choice to address the question in his poetry shows his awareness of the benefits of what
Bourdieu would later term “distinction.” Through criticism (even of his own fabrication), his
prestige paradoxically flourished.
4.7 Criticism of Contemporaries in Callimachus’ Iambi
The text of the Aetia‐prologue, though corrupt at places, allows the modern reader to follow
the rhetorical strategies employed by Callimachus to persuade his audience of the validity of
his poetic choices; the second Hymn (to Apollo) permits the same. 70 This is not the case with
the majority of the Iambi. Although some appear to engage in polemics on contemporary
poetics, it is often difficult to ascertain what Callimachus actually wrote and even more so
what he meant to convey. Sometimes the diegeseis are of some help, but the danger of reading
one’s own preoccupations into the Iambi rather than those of Callimachus looms large. 71
Complicating it further, the Iambi almost certainly constituted a poetry book assembled by
Callimachus himself. 72 This means that the poems were presumably arranged in such a
manner as to comment upon and enhance each other’s meanings. It is hard, if not impossible,
to reconstruct these interrelations—let alone the meanings they might have conveyed—with
confidence from the scraps that survive.
What can, however, be concluded with some degree of certainty from the diegeseis in
combination with the comparatively intact texts of Iambi 2 and 4 is that a (jocular) verdict on
some contemporary poets and their idiosyncrasies is being pronounced. Iambus 2 relates the
fable of how humans received the voices of animals, naming some examples:
70 Cf. Williams (1971: ad 105‐113).
71 This is for instance the problem with Lelli’s interpretations (2004). He often makes claims that are
impossible to verify on the basis of the surviving material, e.g. that Iamb. 3 and 5 are meta‐literary
discussions, contrary to what the diegeseis state. Of Iamb. 3 remain only four complete lines (of at least
40), of Iamb. 5 twelve (of at least 70), cf. Pfeiffer (1949). Kerkhecker (1999) and Acosta‐Hughes (2002)
provide many useful insights on the Iambi, yet raise almost as much questions as they answer.
72 Cf. Acosta‐Hughes (2002), Kerkhecker (1999).
136
All the other animals spoke the same language as humans until the swan went on
diplomatic mission to ask the gods for the banning of old age and a fox dared to say
that Zeus’ rule was unjust. From that day, [Zeus] gave their voices to humans, and
they became talkative. And Eudemus, [Callimachus] says, received the voice of a dog,
and Philton of a donkey, to mock them.
The text of the Iambus itself further states that X [unreadable name] received the voice of a
parrot (fr. 192.11 Pf.) and the tragedians the voices of the animals in the sea (12). This
presumably ridicules the persons involved as incapable poets, though it is not easy to
establish the exact shades of the mockery. 73 The attribution of the fable to Aesop (fr. 192 Pf.
15‐17) and the claim that his outspokenness caused him to receive a hostile reception in
Delphi might imply (and self‐referentially illustrate) that it is better to avoid taking
responsibility for attacking rivals by name. 74
In Iambus 4, an unnamed speaker (according to the diegesis, the persona of
Callimachus) addresses a certain Simos and, apparently to teach him a lesson, relates how an
arrogant and aggressive laurel and a modest olive tree were once discussing who was best.
The olive tree is on the point of winning when a bramble tries to intervene, saying “cease
before we become objects of fun for our enemies.” It is snubbed by the laurel.
Διεφέρετο ὁ ποιητὴς πρός τινα τῶν ἐφαμίλλων∙ Σῖμος δέ τις παρατυχὼν
παρυπέκρουεν ἄμφω παρενδεικνύμενος ἴσος εἶναι. Θρᾷκα δέ φησιν αὐτὸν
καθεστάναι <—> παιδοκλέπτης ἐστί. καὶ γὰρ τὸν αἶνον παρατίθεται ἀκόλουθον,
ὡς ἐν Τμώλῳ <δάφνη καὶ> ἐλαία διεφέροντο ὑπὲρ πρωτείων (παρεπεφύκεσαν δ’
ἀλλήλαις̣), διεξῄεσαν δὲ τὰ προσόντα ἑαυταῖς χρήσιμα. ἐπὶ πλεῖον δὲ
διαφερομένων ὑποτυχοῦσα βάτος παλαιά∙ “πέπαυθε πρὶν εἰ μὴ ἐ[π]ίχαρτοι
<τοῖ>ς δυσ[μ]ενέσι γενώμεθα” (π[αρ]επεφύκ̣[ει δ’ αὐ]τ̣αῖς). [πρ]ὸς ἣν
ἀποβλέψασα [.........] ἡ δά[φν]η “ὦ κακὴ λώβη”, φη[σίν], “⌊ὡς δὴ μ⌋ί’ ἡμέ⌋ων καὶ
σ⌊ύ; ...] (Diegesis VII/fr. 194 Pf.)
The poet was arguing with one of his rivals; a certain Simos, who happened to pass,
chided them, thus implying to be their equal. [Callimachus] calls him a Thracian <...>
he is a stealer of boys. And indeed he adds the following fable, how in Tmolos a
<laurel and> an olive tree were arguing about who was best (because they stood next
to each other) and enumerated their useful qualities. When they continued arguing,
an old bramble butted in: “Stop before we become the laughing stock of our
enemies.” (For it grew next to them). Looking down on it [...] the laurel says: “You
wretch, so you too are one of us now, are you?”
Cf. Acosta‐Hughes (2002: 182‐189).
73
Cf. Ar. Rhet. 3.1418b28‐33: the assuming of a mask if one wishes to say something unpleasant that
74
may reflect badly on the speaker is typical of iambic poetry, cf. Ch. 2.2.2.
137
At first glance, the moral of the fable recounted by the speaker to Simos seems to be: “Don’t
pretend to be able to judge an argument of your betters.” Considering the diegesis, the subject
of the poem may be literary polemic, although Simos is apparently also called a “stealer of
boys” (cf. diegesis), which would rather point towards an erotic quarrel. Perhaps the two
were even combined, but Arnd Kerkhecker rightly expresses his doubts on the matter:
The diegesis does not specify the nature of the rivalry and it seems natural to accept
the stock image of a Callimachus engaged in poetic feuds. And yet, precisely because
this assumption is so natural, it could be mere guesswork. The text of the poem is
almost complete and there is nothing to suggest a debate of poetic principles. The
point of the quarrel is not spelt out. (Kerkhecker, 1999: 112)
It may be more rewarding to consider the structure of the poem and make sense of the
rhetorical strategies employed in it. First, it should be asked which character in the fable
represents the point of view of the speaker. There is the striking fact that the aggressive
echoes the words the speaker uses to snub his interlocutor Simos. The speaker’s ironic
question, “So you are one of us then, are you?” (Εἷς—οὐ γάρ;—ἡμέων; 1), attacks the
presumption of Simos, who counsels against fighting amongst equals. In the laurel’s words
to the bramble in 102‐103, it returns: “You wretch, so you too are one of us now, are you?” (ὦ
κακὴ λώβη, ὡς δὴ μί’ ἡμέων καὶ σύ;). Does this mean the speaker of the Iambus is to be
equated with the laurel, the apparent loser of the quarrel? If so, the whole poem would
appear to be an intricate form of self‐irony on the part of the speaker, “Callimachus,” who
recognizes that all his quarrels can only end in self‐defeat. 76
The bramble seems wiser and more reasonable with its counsel against fighting
amongst equals, and thus even resembles Hipponax as he was presented in Iambus I (cf.
Chapter 2.2.2). 77 Is his perhaps rather the point of view that should be attributed to
Callimachus the author? Finally, the ploy the olive tree uses to win the duel is to quote a
conversation it allegedly overhears between two chattering birds in its leaves. In it, the
achievements of the olive are praised and the laurel is disparaged. 78 This not only
75 This seems to be the conclusion of the Iambus, but since the text is fragmentary this is not entirely
certain.
76 Cf. Kerkhecker (1999: 115).
77 The parallelism of the poem implies that butting in in a quarrel of superiors may also have been
Simos’ “fault.”
78 Beginning in line 61 and presumably continuing all through the speech of the olive, i.e., up to 90.
138
remarkably resembles the iambic practice of expressing personal opinions through a mask in
order to avoid reaping the blame for them, which is what Callimachus did in Iambus 1 (by
making Hipponax his mouthpiece, cf. Ch. 2.2.2) and in Iambus 2 (by attributing his own
insulting remarks about other poets to Aesop). It is also reminiscent of the way Callimachus
uses the authority of Apollo in the Aetia‐prologue and Hymn II (105‐113) to justify his poetic
choices.
All in all, what becomes clear about the tactics of (literary?) feuding in the Iambi is
that they are part of a teasing game of hide and seek, in which it is hard to pin down the
speaker who pronounces the invective. The collection looks more like a self‐conscious essay
in the intricacies of (iambic) charade and a comment upon rhetorical strategies that
Callimachus employs elsewhere than a serious attack on literary opponents.
4.8 Criticism in some Epigrams
The characteristic uniting the remaining examples of blame and criticism found in this
period is their focus on the way in which contemporary poets followed the example of a
particular poetic model; this is the element singled out for criticism. Clearly it was
considered important to be aligned with the right models, or, conversely, to follow these
models in the right way. If a Hellenistic poet did not succeed in doing so, he was liable to
grave criticism or even ridicule. Yet, as will appear, in many of these instances too, the social
backgrounds of criticism and blame play a role under the surface.
An epigram by Theodoridas of Samos criticizes his contemporary Mnasalcas’ choice
of models:
Μνασάλκεος τὸ σᾶμα τῶ Πλαταιΐδα
τῶ ’λεγῃοποιῶ∙
ἁ Μῶσα δ’ αὐτῶ τᾶς Σιμωνίδα πλάθας
ἦς ἀποσπάραγμα
† καινα τε καὶ γὰν † κὰπιλακυθίστρια
†διθυραμβοχάνα†∙
τέθνακε, μὴ βάλωμες∙εἰ δέ κε ζόεν,
τύμπανόν κ’ ἐφύση. (AP 13.21) 79
A note on the text: καινα τε καὶ γὰν was emended by Toup and Jacobs into “κενά τε κλαγγὰν,”
79
which is translated here. On line 8, cf. Page (1975): “omnino non intellegitur; desideratur sententia
ἀπετυμπανίσθη ἄν.”
139
This is the tomb of Mnasalces son of Platais, the poet of elegy. His Muse was a chip
off the block of Simonides and consisted of emptiness, clatter and dithyrambic
hollering. He is dead, let us not throw stones; but if he would be alive… [obscure
threat]
Despite the textual and interpretational problems, it is clear that this epigram condemns
what was in the eyes of Theodoridas a specific literary fault of Mnasalcas. He is ridiculed as
an uncritical epigone of Simonides who produced poetry in a bombastic style, full of
ridiculous compounds—presumably imitated by the ones in the epigram itself. The main
criticism is lack of originality. Similar accusations regarding the composition of unoriginal
poetry are not frequently found in Hellenistic literary criticism. 80 In general, imitation was
not considered a bad thing, provided it added something to the model or modified it in some
unexpected way. However, this was apparently what Mnasalces failed to do, and this is why
the author of the epigram thinks of him as (metaphorically?) dead and buried, and threatens
him with obscure punishments in the last lines.
The following intriguing epigram of a certain Crates appears to address a similar
issue with regard to the poetry and models of Euphorion: 81
Χοιρίλος Ἀντιμάχου πολὺ λείπεται∙ ἀλλ’ ἐπὶ πᾶσιν
Χοιρίλον Εὐφορίων εἶχε διὰ στόματος
καὶ κατάγλωσσ’ ἐπόει τὰ ποήματα καὶ τὰ Φιλητᾶ
ἀτρεκέως ᾔδει∙ καὶ γὰρ Ὁμηρικὸς ἦν. (AP 11.218)
Choerilus is no comparison with Antimachus. Yet, Euphorion always had his mouth
full of Choerilus and he made tongue‐twisting poems and knew all about Philetas.
No wonder, since he was a Homerist.
On a first reading, this epigram seem to focus on Euphorion’s (wrong) choice in literary
matters, favoring Choerilus over Antimachus as a model, and writing (overly) difficult
poetry in the vein of the learned Philitas, presumably full of Homeric hapax legomena.
However, as Gow and Page state, “Crates is interested in the names, not the identities of the
poets,” 82 so that, as a literary statement, the epigram may not have made much sense in the
80 Some instances are aimed more generally at the inadvisability of imitating Homer (cf. Ch. 2.5.1).
Dioscorides praises Machon because he is not unoriginal, while reverting to the style of classical
comedy (AP 7.708).
81 Gow and Page (1965: II, 222): he was either the philosopher Crates of Mallus who was active, like
Euphorion, at the Pergamene court of Antiochus, or a contemporary homonymous poet of epigrams,
cf. Diog. Laert. 4.23.
82 Gow and Page (1965: II, 222).
140
eyes of contemporaries. There is a hidden (and rather insipid) meaning to the epigram: all
convey a reference to χοῖρος (female genitals, cf. LSJ s.v. II), whereby the first phrase,
especially εἶχε διὰ στόματος (“he had his mouth full of”), gains a completely different
meaning. The name “Philitas,” when connected in the poem with κατάγλωσσα ποήματα
(“tongue‐twisting poems”), 84 suddenly reveals its etymological link with the verb φιλῶ (“to
kiss”). Even venerable Homer is brought into this obscene pun: his name is implied to be a
composite of ὁμοῦ (together) and μηρός (thigh). 85
What is the aim of this irreverence? Did Crates perhaps mean to imply that the false
etymologies, or puns, reveal a deeper truth about these poets, especially Euphorion? 86 Gow
and Page think that the epigram mainly constitutes “an attack on Euphorion’s morals” and is
“damaging to his character.” They are probably correct, since the epigram does not seem to
aim at serious criticism of Euphorion’s poetic style and there is no evidence that Euphorion
wrote “licentiously”(Gow and Page ad AP 11.218,3). As Jerker Blomqvist phrases it, ”The
personal involvement of the author manifests itself in the fact that the real motive behind the
attack is obscured by the actual contents.” 87 In other words, as a literary attack it makes no
sense, so there must have been personal reasons involved.
Considering Blomqvist’s remark on the epigram, it is attractive to speculate about
possible professional envy in order to interpret the attack. The poets involved in this
particular example of mud‐slinging both appear to have had a connection with the
Pergamene court of King Antiochus, which could boast an important library and scholarly
community. The Suda claims Euphorion was made director of the library by Antiochus, so
perhaps this was a good enough reason for Crates to be envious.
Another epigram that looks like a reverent epitaph for this same Euphorion by his
contemporary Theodoridas of Samos is usually read in a similar vein:
Εὐφορίων, ὁ περισσὸν ἐπιστάμενός τι ποῆσαι,
83 Except, apparently, those of Antimachus and Euphorion, cf. Gow and Page (1965: II, ad loc.).
84 Normally meaning “full of recondite words” but here assuming an unexpected relation to the word
for tongue‐kissing (cf. LSJ s.v. καταγλωττίζω).
85 The verb ὁμηρίζω is used with the same intended equivoque in Ach. Tat. 8.9.
86 Whose name is not punned upon. Etymology and puns on poets’ names are discussed in Ch. 7.
87 Blomqvist (1998: 51). The allegation may be that Euphorion owed his wealth to Nicia, the wife of the
King of Euboea (cf. Suda s.v. Εὐφορίων), who may be the “rich old woman” with whom he is said to
have lived (Plut. Mor. 472D).
141
Πειραϊκοῖς κεῖται τοῖσδε παρὰ σκέλεσιν.
ἀλλὰ σὺ τῷ μύστῃ ῥοιὴν ἢ μῆλον ἄπαρξαι
ἢ μύρτον∙ καὶ γὰρ ζωὸς ἐὼν ἐφίλει. (AP 7.406)
Euphorion, who understood how to write brilliant poetry, lies by these Peiraic dams.
But you must dedicate to the initiate a pomegranate or an apple or a myrtle. For
when he was still alive he also loved these things.
An actual literary feud between Euphorion and Theodoridas seems in fact supported by
Clement of Alexandria’s reference to Euphorion’s “Writings aimed at Theodoridas” (πρὸς
Θεωδορίδαν ἀντιγραφαί, Strom. 673P). This is what has induced scholars to see another
scurrilous attack on Euphorion in the epigram. 88 Once more; the play is on the double entendre
in apple and myrtle, attested as references to female genitals. 89 This is no real epitaph, then,
but another attack on Euphorion’s “morals.” The fact that it “buries the author alive” may
have been an additional joke. 90
4.9 Conclusion
This chapter has aimed to show that envy, strife, and the wish for Bourdieuian “distinction”
in the field of cultural production may be considered important motives for delivering or
pretending to receive criticism and blame among colleagues in Hellenistic poetry. Because of
his wish for distinction, Callimachus would not have been content if his intellectual and
difficult poetry would have been instantly acceptable to everyone. This induced him to
create a poetic persona in the Aetia‐prologue that makes him appear like a threatened
specimen, an elitist, misunderstood dissenter, fighting for a high aesthetic cause. Although it
is not altogether implausible that some did indeed criticize his poetic choices, the fact that he
chooses to elaborate upon it in the opening of a poem addressed to the court makes it clear
that he at least intended to make the most of this—in all likelihood not very threatening—
opposition.
88 Cf. Gow and Page (1965: II, ad loc.).
89 In all likelihood, the pomegranate also shares a similar connotation, although it is not attested as
such, see Gow and Page (1965: II, ad loc.).
90 At the time of writing Euphorion was presumably still alive, cf. the fact that the Suda names Syrian
Apamea rather than Peiraeus as his burial site (Gow and Page 1965: II, 545). Gow and Page suggest
Πειραϊκοῖς should be connected with πεῖρα, πειράομαι, πειράζω in their erotic sense. The same line
may also refer to the word σκέλος (leg), since Euphorion apparently had ugly or crippled legs
(κακοσκελής, cf. Suda).
142
Another matter is whether Callimachus quarreled with his pupil Apollonius. This can
certainly not be proven on the basis of the evidence usually adduced. What does seem likely
is that, if they did quarrel, it would have been due to poetic similarity and possibly
professional rivalry, as both were employed in the Museum and presumably supported in
their poetical production by the monarch. The perception of this closeness in itself may even
have led to the invention of the quarrel by later scholars.
That Callimachus disagreed with Asclepiades and Posidippus about the appreciation
of Antimachus’ Lyde seems more likely. Whether this also means that Asclepiades and
Posidippus are necessarily to be identified amongst the Telchines attacked in Callimachus’
Aetia‐prologue is another question. As my analysis of this text has demonstrated, it is at least
clear that the Telchines, whoever they may represent, are welcome foils, introduced to set the
poet Callimachus apart and emphasize his (enviable) excellence.
When it comes to criticizing the choice of a contemporary’s poetic models, several
reasons may underlie the criticism. One epigram (AP 13.21) authentically attacks the choice
of poetic models of a contemporary. The obvious point here is the unacceptable practice of
insipidly following the classic models (Mnasalces is accused of being “a chip off the block of
Simonides”). Clearly this is not a good thing; indeed, when looking at Hellenistic poetry in
general, imitation for the sake of imitation is hardly found. Of course, this does not prove
that Theodoridas’ allegation was true to fact.
Crates’ epigram on Euphorion also appears to attack a particular aspect of the poetics
of imitation (AP 11.218), the point of criticism being the choice of inferior (and perhaps too
artificial and obscure) models. The real significance of the epigram (as supported by its
counterpart by Theodoridas, AP 7.406) however reveals itself to be totally different: it is an
allegation about Euphorion’s sexual mores for wholly inscrutable and presumably personal
reasons. It can be assumed that a personal feud was behind the quarrel; it charades as
literary criticism, but involves no such thing.
All in all, it would appear that so‐called aesthetic value judgments and the quarrels
about them are not always what they seem in Hellenistic poetry. More often than not,
unstated reasons for disagreement lurk behind the dismissal of another poet’s poetic or
aesthetic choices. Callimachus is the champion of exploiting–real or imagined–criticism; by
incriminating his alleged detractors, he emerges triumphantly from the fray in the Muses’
143
birdcage. The massive scholarship on Callimachus’ quarrels is testimony to the effectiveness
of his manipulative strategy.
144
CHAPTER 5:
BIRDS OF A FEATHER: POETIC PRAISE FOR CONTEMPORARIES
5.1 Introduction
The Alexandrian Museum may have been satirized as a “birdcage” full of squabbling birds,
but animosity amongst contemporaries is not the whole story. Persisting in Timon’s bird‐
metaphor, it might be said that the Hellenistic literary birds of a feather also often did what
they are proverbially held to do, that is, “flock together.” In other words, there are several
instances of compliments and praise among contemporaries to be found. Surprisingly
perhaps, this is unique: in pre‐Hellenistic Greek poetry, it is virtually impossible to find
explicit praise from a poet for a contemporary. 1 Either such poetry expresses or implies a
negative evaluation of a contemporary or predecessor or it explicitly praises predecessors. 2 This
lack of explicit praise may be explained by the fact that the eventual positive evaluation of
poets derived from the success they enjoyed, which preserved them for the appreciation of
later generations. A need for explication of this success was perhaps not strongly felt; it may
have seemed self‐evident. 3 In addition, it was easier to provide an opinion on the (well‐
known) poetry of the past. Praise of a contemporary has a different status than praise of a
predecessor who has already entered the canon; for instance, it may be riskier (cf. the
appreciation of Antimachus in Hellenistic poetry as discussed in Chapter 2). Assmann’s
theory of cultural memory (cf. Chapter 1.3) is once more relevant: whereas the value of what
is recent and belongs to “living memory” is often subject to discussion, what has receded
into the past and become part of the established tradition is less likely to be so.
As stated however, the situation in Hellenistic poetry was different. Examples of
praise as well as criticism directed at contemporaries are preserved to an extent that is
unequaled in earlier Greek literature. In this chapter, instances of Hellenistic poetic
expressions of praise will be analyzed for what they reveal about their writers. Although
1 See the collections of critical statements on poetry in e.g. Lanata (1963), Maehler (1963), Harriot
(1969), Gundert (1978), Ford (2002).
2 One example of pre‐Hellenistic praise of a contemporary can be found in the epigram by Plato (if he
is really the author) on Aristophanes (14 DK/Vita Aristophanis): Αἱ Χάριτες τέμενός τι λαβεῖν ὅπερ
οὐχὶ πεσεῖται / ζητοῦσαι, ψυχὴν ηὗρον Ἀριστοφάνους. (The Graces, seeking a shrine that would not
fall, found the soul of Aristophanes).
3 On the elusive beginnings of ancient literary criticism in general, cf. Kennedy (1989: ix) Dover (1993:
33), Ford (2002: 1‐3).
145
they might seem to be no more than natural responses elicited by a satisfying work of art, the
act of versifying praise in one‘s own poetry proclaims a feeling of allegiance to the praised
poetics. Thereby, it throws light on the poetics of the praising voice itself. Praise, like blame,
implies the choice of a position in the discourse on poetics and in the field of cultural
production (cf. Chapter 4.3).
5.2 Reading the Signs in Aratus’ Phaenomena
Immediately after appearing, Aratus’ Phaenomena, a didactic poem in archaic language
dealing with the heavenly bodies, became a great success. 4 Aratus presents his poetic
venture as a way of translating the omnipresent signs of Zeus (especially the heavenly
bodies) into language comprehensible to humans. Possibly as early as Aratus’ own lifetime,
the Phaenomena had already become so popular they were even read in schools. 5 This may
come as a surprise, since, as Neil Hopkinson (1988: 138) politely puts it, “many modern
readers find the Phaenomena unexciting.”
The raison d’être of the poem was a royal request. King Antigonus Gonatas of Pella in
Macedonia had asked Aratus to versify a prose treatise by Eudoxus of Cnidus, an
astronomer. This treatise was called either Katoptron (Mirror) or Phaenomena. When Aratus
had finished, the monarch reputedly punned: “εὐδοξότερον ποιεῖς τὸν Εὔδοξον ἐντείνας
τὰ παρ’ αὐτῷ κείμενα μέτρῳ.” (You make Eudoxus even more famous, now that you’ve
versified his material). 6
Phaenomena’s popularity. The three Hellenistic epigrams in praise of it all focus on its
elegance or refinement, using forms and compounds of the adjective λεπτός. 7 This is no
4 For its popularity, cf. the contemporary epigrams of praise (below) and the later Latin translations
and commentaries (Cicero, Germanicus, Avienus; a distinct influence of Phaen. 758‐1152 on Vergil’s G.
1.351‐460). Callimachus moreover praises Aratus in his prose treatise Πρὸς Πραξιφάνην (Vit. Arat. 1=
Schol. Vet. in Arat. 9.8 Martin = fr. 460 Pf.), cf. Sale (1965: 160‐4).
5 The oldest papyrus of the Phaen. (v. 480‐494), P. Hamb. 121 (first half second cent. BCE), is an
anthology for use in the schools, cf. Fantuzzi in DNP (s.v. Aratus).
6 Cf. Vit. Arat. 1.8.5‐10. Phaen. 19‐757 is based on Eudoxus; the meteorological part (Phaen. 758‐1154) is
related to a Pseudo‐Theophrastean treatise (Περὶ Σημείων, On Wheather Signs).
7 The epigrams are AP 9.507, by Callimachus; AP 9.25 by Leonidas and SH 712 = Vit. Arat. 1.10.4‐7 by
“King Ptolemy.” On the former two epigrams see below; the latter epigram runs: Πάνθ᾿ Ἡγησιάναξ
τε καὶ Ἕρμιππος <τὰ> κατ’ αἴθρην / τείρεα καὶ πολλοὶ ταῦτα τὰ φαινόμενα / βίβλοις ἐγκατέθεντο
146
coincidence, since Aratus himself had apparently called one of his (no longer extant) poetic
anthologies Κατὰ λεπτόν (SH 108‐9). He moreover alludes to the quality of λεπτότης
(refinement) with the acrostic λεπτή in Phaen. 783‐787, a passage describing the appearance
of the moon: 8
Λεπτὴ μὲν καθαρή τε περὶ τρίτον ἦμαρ ἐοῦσα
Εὔδιός κ’ εἴη, λεπτὴ δὲ καὶ εὖ μάλ’ ἐρευθὴς
Πνευματίη∙ παχίων δὲ καὶ ἀμβλείῃσι κεραίαις
Τέτρατον ἐκ τριτάτοιο φόως ἀμενηνὸν ἔχουσα
Ηὲ νότου ἀμβλύνετ’ ἢ ὕδατος ἐγγὺς ἐόντος. (Phaen. 783‐787)
If she is slender and clear about the third day, she will bode fair weather; if slender
and very red, wind; if the crescent is thickish, with blunted horns, having a feeble
fourth‐day light after the third day, either it is blurred by a southerly or because rain
is in the offing. (transl. Kidd)
This passage constitutes a double proclamation of the ideal of λεπτότης. It spells the word
Λεπτὴ in the acrostic and at the same time illustrates exactly what this ideal implied: the
subtle and able versification that allowed the double (or triple) incorporation of the word. 9
The text with its acrostic shows that Aratus expects the reader to read carefully.
It is generally recognized that the word λεπτός and its cognates are of crucial
importance in the critical discourse in Hellenistic poetry, as for instance its prominent
position in Callimachus’ prologue to the Aetia (fr. 1 Pf. 11‐12 and 24‐5) demonstrates. 10
†ἀπὸ σκοποῦ δ´ ἀφάμαρτον† / ἀλλ᾿ ὅ γε λεπτολόγος σκῆπτρον Ἄρατος ἔχει. (Hegesianax and
Hermippus and many others put the heavenly bodies, those constellations, in books †and missed the
mark, but Aratus of the subtle discourses holds the scepter). It is unclear which Ptolemaic king is
meant; he receives the sobriquet Physkōn (Potbelly). Fraser (1972: II, 1090, n. 459) and Gabathuler
(1937: 94‐5) think this is not a contemporary of Aratus, since they date Hegesianax (line 1) after Aratus.
Page (1981: 84) and Cameron (1995: 323) however think it must be Ptolemy Philadelphus.
8 This interpretation is not accepted by Jacques (1960: 48‐50), who explains the acrostic as a reference to
the (accidental) acrostic in the opening lines of Il. 24: λευκή. However, since Aratus named a collection
of his own poetry Κατὰ λεπτόν, it seems hard to believe he was not aware of the meta‐poetic
significance of the word. Phaen. contains one other certain acrostic (802‐806): ΠΑΣΑ, identified by
Levitan (1979: 55‐68). Hutchinson (1988: 215 n. 4) thinks that still another may have been attempted
unsuccessfully at 808‐812: ΣΕΜΕιΗ (the diphthong Ει‐ opens the fourth line); he reads this as a neuter
plural. Bing (1990: 281, n. 1) suggests taking it as fem. sing. and reading all the acrostics together as:
ΛΕΠΤΗ ΠΑΣΑ ΣΕΜΕιΗ. On acrostics in antiquity in general, see Courtney (1990: 3‐13).
9 Cf. Cicero on Ennius’ acrostic: tum vero ea quae acrosticis dicitur, cum deinceps ex primis versus litteris
aliquid conectitur, ut in quibusdam Ennianis Q. ENNIUS FECIT. Id certe magis est attenti animi quam
furentis. (Cic. De div. II 111, emphasis added).
10 Cf. Ch. 4.5. Cameron (1995: 23) adds that Phaen. 783‐787 contains two other words that frequently
return in Callimachean critical or meta‐poetic contexts: καθαρή (AP 9.566; Hymn II, 105‐113) and
παχίων (fr. 398 Pf.; fr. 1 Pf.). Other occurrences of λεπτός in Callimachus are hard to interpret: Hymn
147
Although it is unclear whether Callimachus or Aratus was first to use the adjective in a meta‐
poetic sense in Hellenistic poetry, the connection between the two poets is undeniably
present. 11 Apart from the question of priority, it is evident that λεπτότης was perceived as a
central quality of Aratus’ poem, as the epigrams in its praise illustrate. They deserve a
detailed analysis, starting with a complex epigram of Callimachus:
Ἡσιόδου τόδ’ ἄεισμα καὶ ὁ τρόπος∙ οὐ τὸν ἀοιδὸν
ἔσχατον, ἀλλ’ ὀκνέω μὴ τὸ μελιχρότατον
τῶν ἐπέων ὁ Σολεὺς ἀπεμάξατο. χαίρετε, λεπταὶ
ῥήσιες, Ἀρήτου σύντονος ἀγρυπνίη. (AP 9.507)
This song and its style are Hesiod’s; not that the man from Soloi [has imitated] the
poet entire, although it must be admitted that he has imitated the sweetest part of his
verses. All hail, refined discourses, product of Aratus’ intense sleeplessness. 12
Aratus is apparently praised as a ζηλωτὴς Ἡσιόδου (emulator of Hesiod): 13 the Phaenomena
are a Hesiodic song (ἄεισμα) in an improved Hesiodic style (τρόπος). Indeed, the poet is
complimented for not imitating Hesiod entire, but only the sweetest part of his poetry.
Callimachus’ salutation of the work of Aratus as the product of “intense sleeplessness”
appears to point both to long night hours of deep concentration necessary for the production
of such a polished and learned poem and to the expectation that an astronomical poem like
the Phaenomena would have been written at night in order to observe the stars. 14 Since Aratus
III, 243; Iamb. fr. 197.42 Pf.; Lyr. fr. 228.14 Pf.; Hec. frs. 254; 274; fr. incertae sedis 383.15 Pf. On the
importance of λεπτός as a critical term in Hellenistic poetry, see e.g. Reitzenstein (1931: 23‐70),
Cameron (1995: 324‐328; 330‐31; 488‐93); Asper (1997: 135‐199).
11 Cameron (1995: 325): Callimachus borrowed the term from Aratus. Contra Jacques (1960: 53);
Schwinge (1986: 15‐16); Bing (1990: 282). Ultimately, the term would seem to derive from fifth cent.
poetic/intellectual discourse, e.g. Ar. Av. 318, Acharn. 445, Plato Resp. X 607b, as Reitzenstein (1931: 25‐
30) points out.
12 Some notes on the text and on the translation: I follow–where possible–the original MS reading of
the AP, without the conjectures of Scaliger, Ruhnken and Blomfield. My translation of line 1 follows
Cameron (1995: 223), who translates οὐ τὸν ἀοιδὸν / ἔσχατον as: “not the poet entire.” Contrast e.g.
Wilamowitz (1924: I, 206) and Reitzenstein (1931: 42), who translate οὐ τὸν ἀοιδῶν ἔσχατον “not the
best of poets,” i.e., not Homer. For ἀπομάσσομαι (3) meaning “to imitate, to model,” cf. e.g. AP 9.594
on a portrait of Socrates, and LSJ s.v. απομάσσω III, Med. The phrase ἀλλ’ ὀκνέω μὴ (2) is
problematic and very rare, cf. Gow and Page (1965: II, ad loc.) who propose: “it must be admitted that”
or “although.” On the phrase σύντονος ἀγρυπνίη, see Lohse (1967: 379‐381) and Hose (1994: 196‐199).
13 So Vit. Arat. 1.5, discussing the question whether Aratus followed Homer or Hesiod. Perhaps this is
a reference to the astronomical works attributed to Hesiod in antiquity (DK Hes. frs. 1‐8). A more
general reference to the style and didactic mode of Op. and Theog. is also possible. The remark has
greatly influenced modern interpretation of the epigram, esp. the phrase τὸν ἀοιδὸν / ἔσχατον, on
which see previous note.
14 Cf. Cinna fr. 11 as cited by Pfeiffer (1953 app. crit.): Haec tibi Arateis multum invigilata lucernis carmina.
148
was no true astronomer but depended on Eudoxus for his astronomical facts, this ambiguity
is pointed and humorous. 15
the acrostic ΛΕΠΤΗ in Phaen. 783‐787, but also identified a surprising pun at the opening of
this poem. 16 The opening lines of the Phaenomena read: Ἐκ Διὸς ἀρχώμεσθα, τὸν οὐδέποτ’
ἄνδρες ἐῶμεν / ἄρρητον. (Let us begin from Zeus, whom we mortals never leave
unmentioned). At first sight, ἄρρητον (unmentioned, unfamed) constitutes an allusion to the
opening of Hesiod’s Opera et Dies (ῥητοί τ’ ἄρρητοί τε, 4), the recognized poetic model of the
Phaenomena:
Μοῦσαι Πιερίηθεν, ἀοιδῇσι κλείουσαι,
δεῦτε Δί’ ἐννέπετε, σφέτερον πατέρ’ ὑμνείουσαι.
ὅν τε διὰ βροτοὶ ἄνδρες ὁμῶς ἄφατοί τε φατοί τε,
ῥητοί τ’ ἄρρητοί τε Διὸς μεγάλοιο ἕκητι. (Op. 1‐4)
Muses of Pieria, singing your lays, come here and tell of Zeus, hymning your
father, through whom all men on earth are spoken of or left in silence, famed or
unfamed, through the will of mighty Zeus.
However, the word also puns on the name of the author, Aratus, by connecting his own
name (Ἀράτος / Ἀρήτος) to the root ῥη‐, (to speak) through paronomasia. The adjective
ἀρρητός can be read as a “variant” of this name. By punning in this way, Aratus once again,
in a more subtle way, alludes to a feature of Hesiod’s Opera et Dies. For in this subtext, a
similar “etymology” is constructed, namely on the name of Zeus (root Δι‐), the god “through
whom” (ὅν τε διὰ / Διὸς μεγάλοιο ἕκητι) everything happens. 17 The intertextual allusions
thus convey both that the Phaenomena stem from the Opera et Dies and that the poet Aratus—
one of the ἄρρητοί, the “unfamed/unmentioned,” 18 Aratus modestly suggests that he
declines fame while paradoxically hinting at his own name at the same time.
15 Cameron (1972: 169‐170), Hopkinson (1988: 137‐8).
16 Bing (1990: 281‐5).
17 Cf. West (1978: 139) on this passage.
18 For the meaning of the adjective, Schol. 3a: ὅν τε διὰ βροτοί: ἤτοι δι’ ὅντινα τρόπον οἱ ἄνδρες, οἱ
ὁμοίως πάντες βροτοὶ καὶ φθαρτοὶ ὄντες, οἱ μὲν ἐκ τούτου εἰσὶν ἄφατοι καὶ ἀνονόμαστοι, οἱ δὲ
φατοὶ καὶ ὀνομαστοὶ πανταχοῦ, ὁμοίως ῥητοὶ καὶ ἔνδοξοί τινες τῶν ἀνθρώπων, ἄλλοι δὲ ἄρρητοι
καὶ ἄδοξοι καὶ μηδόλως ὀνομαζόμενοι καὶ φημιζόμενοι διὰ τὸ ταπεινόν. (That is, for what reason
men, who are all human and mortal, partly, stemming from him, are of no concern and unnamed,
while others are famed and of great repute everywhere, and likewise, some people are named and
149
Callimachus, in his praise of the Phaenomena, points to Aratus’ pun in two ways. First
his epigram uses the uncommon “Ionic” form of the author’s name, Ἀρήτου, which is
deliberately saved for the last line. 19 Secondly, the epigram also alludes to it by calling the
Phaenomena “λεπταὶ / ῥήσιες”, once more playing on the root ῥη‐. This expression stands
out as an odd way of referring to a work of poetry. 20 By pointing at these refinements in the
Phaenomena, Callimachus clarifies what “imitating the sweetest part of Hesiod’s verse” (2‐3)
amounts to: the opening lines of the Phaenomena show a truly refined reworking of Op. 1‐4.
They refer to Hesiod and his pun on Zeus by punning on the name of the author, Aratus,
while paradoxically omitting it. Truly, Hesiod pales in comparison.
Callimachus was not the only one to spot both of these intricacies in the Phaenomena;
the contemporary epigrammatist Leonidas of Tarentum alludes to them too: 21
Γράμμα τόδ’ Ἀρήτοιο δαήμονος, ὅς ποτε λεπτῇ
φροντίδι δηναιοὺς ἀστέρας ἐφράσατο,
ἀπλανέας τ’ ἄμφω καὶ ἀλήμονας, οἷσι τ’ ἐναργὴς 22
ἰλλόμενος κύκλοις οὐρανὸς ἐνδέδεται.
αἰνείσθω δὲ καμὼν ἔργον μέγα, καὶ Διὸς εἶναι
δεύτερος, ὅστις ἔθηκ’ ἄστρα φαεινότερα. (AP 9.25)
This is the writing of learned Aratus, who once with subtle intellect showed where to
find the primeval stars, the fixed and the moving both, in whose circles the bright
revolving heaven is bound. He must be praised as one who has perfected a great
work, and let it be said that he comes next after Zeus, he who has made the stars
brighter.
Here, the expression λεπτῇ / φροντίδι refers to Aratus’ acrostic ΛΕΠΤΗ. The final verses of
the epigram (αἰνείσθω ... Διὸς εἶναι / δεύτερος) once more points to the pun in Phaen. 2:
Aratus is “second to Zeus” figuratively as well as literally. In one sense, Zeus put the stars in
famous, and other unnamed and unknown and nowhere mentioned or named, because of their
unimportance). Cf. also scholia 3b‐4a.
19 Contrast the spelling in the epigram of Ptolemy and the Vitae, cf. Cameron (1995: 322‐3).
20 The juxtaposition of the allusions to the acrostic and the pun on Aratus’ name suggests that both
may have been read as instances of sphragis, i.e., of Aratus’ personal mark on the poem. LSJ s.v. ῥήσις
only gives instances of the word as referring to speech or prose. Perhaps the pun (ῥήσις–ἄρρητον–
Ἀρήτου) is moreover echoed by one on Hesiod’s name (Ἡσιόδου–ἄεισμα‐‐ἀοιδὸν), cf. Bing (1990: 283,
n. 3), since this may in antiquity have been etymologized as deriving from ἱέναι ἀοιδήν, cf. West (1966
ad Th. 22) and Nágy (1979: 96‐7).
21 Cf. Bing (1990: 281‐285). The question is whether Leonidas is imitating Callimachus’ epigram.
Cameron (1995: 323) denies the connection between Callimachus and Leonidas.
22 Beckby’s text reads οἷσιν ἐναργὴς (3), which Gow and Page consider incomprehensible. They
suggest following Kaibel’s conjecture, which is printed here.
150
the heavens as signs for mankind and Aratus made them comprehensible; 23 in another,
Aratus’ name (once more referred to in the Ionic form, 1) comes after that of Zeus in Phaen. 2.
Leonidas contrives yet another pun in the conclusion of the epigram (6). It centers on the title
Phaenomena, implying that Aratus has made the stars “brighter” or “more apparent”
(φαεινότερα) by writing about them. This could mean both that Aratus’ explanation makes
the names and effects of constellations devised by Zeus “more comprehensible” and that the
Phaenomena of Eudoxus, on which Aratus based his own poetry, have now become “better
known” (φαεινός is the Greek equivalent of Latin clarus). 24
What is the aim of all these allusions? Both Leonidas and Callimachus wish to
demonstrate that they are clever readers of a clever poem. They go to some lengths to show
that they understand the message conveyed by the Phaenomena, namely that “signs” should
be noticed. 25 For indeed, this is the primary theme of the Phaenomena: the constellations are
set in the heavens by Zeus as signs to be used by humans (especially farmers and seamen)
who, if they “read” them correctly, will greatly benefit from their message. On a poetic level,
Aratus enacts this message by incorporating subtle signs, such as acrostics and puns
designed to be noticed by the reader, in his text. Callimachus and Leonidas, in turn, align
their epigrammatic poetry with the poetry of the admired and praised Aratus, the paragon of
λεπτότης, by including their own “signs” in the form of references to Aratean puns and
acrostics. 26
Considering this, it is ironic that Leonidas appears to make a significant blunder in
his praise of the Phaenomena. Contrary to Leonidas’ claim (3), Aratus expressly says he does
23 Cf. especially the programmatic passages in Phaen. 5‐6: Ὁ δ’ ἤπιος ἀνθρώποισι / δεξιὰ σημαίνει.
(And in friendly manner he points out to mankind the favourable signs); Phaen. 15‐16: Ἐμοί γε μὲν
ἀστέρας εἰπεῖν / ᾗ θέμις εὐχομένῳ. (In answer to my prayer to tell of the stars in so far as I may,
guide all my singing).
24 Cf. Gow and Page (1965: II, 396), who refer to the pun allegedly contrived by Antigonus:
“εὐδοξότερον ποιεῖς τὸν Εὔδοξον.”
25 Cf. Bing (1990: 285) quoting Phaen. 1101‐3: Οὕτω γὰρ μογεροὶ καὶ ἀλήμονες ἄλλοθεν ἄλλοι /
ζώομεν ἄνθρωποι∙ τὰ δὲ πὰρ ποσὶ πάντες ἑτοῖμοι / σήματ’ ἐπιγνῶναι καὶ ἐς αὐτίκα ποιήσασθαι.
(So it is that we suffering restless mortals make a living in different ways; but all are only too ready to
recognize signs that are right beside us, and adopt them for the moment, transl. Kidd).
26 This may be connected with the fact that both epigrams seem to be conceived as tags appended to
the actual scrolls of the Phaen. (note the recurrent deictic pronoun τόδε): they propose and enact a
mode of interpretation to the reader.
151
not discuss the planets or “wandering stars” (ἀλήμονας), only the fixed constellations. 27 It is
tempting to conclude that Leonidas read the Phaenomena “at best inattentively.” 28 Despite
this fact, he evidently was aware of the intricacies of the Phaenomena and the reputation it
enjoyed in well‐informed circles. Perhaps he wished to create the impression that he too
belonged to them. 29
We can see that Leonidas and Callimachus both aim to associate themselves with the
poetics of a successful contemporary. They attempt this by imitating the praised poetic ideals
in the expression of admiration itself. Admirer and admired end by becoming, so to speak,
equal; the admired aesthetics informs the expression of admiration itself and becomes a self‐
advertisement of the poet who praises. Hence, these expressions underscore the praising
poet’s own authority to praise.
5.3 The Mirror of Immortality
A similar principle may also be observed where immortality is claimed for the works of a
contemporary, as the following epigram by Callimachus illustrates:
Εἶπέ τις, Ἡράκλειτε, τεὸν μόρον, ἐς δέ με δάκρυ
ἤγαγεν∙ ἐμνήσθην δ’, ὁσσάκις ἀμφότεροι
ἥλιον ἐν λέσχῃ κατεδύσαμεν. ἀλλὰ σὺ μέν που,
ξεῖν’ Ἁλικαρνησεῦ, τετράπαλαι σποδιή∙
αἱ δὲ τεαὶ ζώουσιν ἀηδόνες, ᾗσιν ὁ πάντων
ἁρπακτὴς Ἀίδης οὐκ ἐπὶ χεῖρα βαλεῖ. (AP 7.80)
Someone told me of your fate, Heraclitus, and made me shed a tear. And I
remembered how often the two of us sank the sun with our talk. But you, I suppose,
Halicarnassian friend, are four times turned to dust. Yet your nightingales live, on
which Hades who takes all, will not lay his hands.
27 Aratus Phaen. 454‐461: οὐδ’ ἔτι θαρσαλέος κείνων ἐγὼ∙ ἄρκιος εἴην / ἀπλανέων τά τε κύκλα τά τ’
αἰθέρι σήματ’ ἐνισπεῖν. (I am not at all confident in dealing with them [i.e., the planets]. I hope I may
be adequate in expounding the circles of the fixed stars and their guide‐constellations in the sky;
transl. Kidd).
28 Gow and Page (1965: II, ad loc.). Kaibel (1894: 122) thinks Leonidas has not read it at all and took
over the praise directly from Callimachus. Cameron (1995: 324) argues for some knowledge of the text
on his part.
29 Alternatively, Leonidas may have been subtler than he seems on this interpretation, and actually
referred (jokingly?) to the two lines that Aratus does spend on describing his unwillingness to write
about the planets.
152
The apostrophe of Callimachus’ friend dramatizes the tension between the living memory
and the reality of death. In Callimachus’ perception, it is as if Heraclitus were still there to be
addressed. 30 The epigram elaborates on this motif by telling how the two companions used
to “put the sun down” with their conversations. But now the sun has set forever on one of
them.
The topic of immortality is addressed in the reference to the undying “nightingales”
of Heraclitus. 31 It has been asked whether these “nightingales” were mere (unwritten) songs
or written poems. 32 Since Callimachus wrote his thoughts on (im) mortality down, it would
seem that he thought that putting poetry in writing was a reliable way of protecting it
against the hands of Hades (6). 33 By implication, it is likely that his friend’s poetry was
written down as well. The presupposed situation of the epigram may therefore be that, on
hearing of his friend’s death, Callimachus took out his copy of Heraclitus’ poetry to prolong
their conversation and concluded that Heraclitus had left behind immortal words that still
spoke for him. Indeed, even from the vantage point of today, Heraclitus lives on, if not in his
own “nightingales:” Callimachus’ epigram still testifies to his immortality and praises the
enduring quality of his friend’s poetry. Yet, the epigram also implicitly pronounces on
Callimachus’ own immortality.
Another epigram by Callimachus makes a similar point about poetic immortality
more emphatically:
Ἦλθε Θεαίτητος καθαρὴν ὁδόν∙ εἰ δ’ ἐπὶ κισσὸν
τὸν τεὸν οὐχ αὕτη, Βάκχε, κέλευθος ἄγει,
30 The epigram captures, as Walsh (1990: 1‐3) notes, a sample of “audible thought.” Hunter (1992: 123)
moreover notes that this poem marks a stage in the development of epigram from inscriptional to
pure literary form: “Now there is no tombstone and no corpse, merely memory.”
31 It is unclear whether this was the title of a collection of poems, cf. Gow and Page (1965: II, 192),
following Stadtmüller, or perhaps rather a metaphorical reference to Heraclitus’ poetry in general (cf.
AP 9.184 on Alcman; Hesychius too glosses ἀηδόνα· ὠιδήν), but this does not influence the point.
Diog. Laert. (9.17) identifies our Heraclitus as ἐλεγείας ποιητὴς Ἁλικαρνασσεύς εἰς ὅν Καλλίμαχος
πεποίηκεν οὕτως... (A Halicarnassian elegist on whom Callimachus composed the following lines...),
cf. Strabo (14.656).
32 Russell (1981: 35) and Gutzwiller (1998: 206‐207) both argue that the epigram illustrates that
Callimachus believed the only survival beyond physical death lies in the written‐down word.
However Hunter (2007): “There is no way of ascertaining that Heraclitus’ “nightingales” should be
understood as written‐down poems. They may have been mere “songs,, remembered by his friend
Callimachus.” However, one epigram of Heraclitus (AP 7.465) survives, and the qualification Diog.
Laert. (ἐλεγείας ποιητής) also points to writing.
33 Cf. the topic of the epigrams discussed in Ch. 1.5.2.
153
ἄλλων μὲν κήρυκες ἐπὶ βραχὺν οὔνομα καιρὸν
φθέγξονται, κείνου δ’ Ἑλλὰς ἀεὶ σοφίην. (AP 9.565)
Theaetetus went along the pure road. And if that path does not lead to your ivy,
Bacchus, well, the heralds will but for a brief moment proclaim the names of others,
but his skill Hellas will proclaim forever.
A certain Theaetetus, who apparently competed in a Dionysiac festival, did not win popular
acclaim for his poetry. 34 Callimachus turns this fact into a positive qualification. Other poets
may enjoy their “fifteen minutes of fame” through the proclamations of heralds; Theaetetus
will be esteemed forever by the whole of Hellas. This is a prophecy of immortality gained
through poetry and proclaimed in poetry, namely the poetry of Callimachus. He poses as a
discerning connoisseur of poets who proceed along the “pure road.” This expression
strongly recalls the advice of Apollo to the young Callimachus in the prologue to the Aetia: 35
πρὸς δέ σε] καὶ τόδ’ ἄνωγα, τὰ μὴ πατέουσιν ἅμαξαι
τὰ στείβειν, ἑτέρων ἴχνια μὴ καθ’ ὁμά
δίφρον ἐλ]ᾶ̣ν μηδ’ οἷμον ἀνὰ πλατύν, ἀλλὰ κελεύθους
ἀτρίπτο]υ̣ς, εἰ καὶ στειν̣οτέρην ἐλάσεις. (fr. 1.25‐8 Pf.)
“And I’m telling you another thing: take the roads that are not open to hackneys, and
do not drive your [chariot] in the ruts of others, and not over the broad way, but on
[untrodden] paths, even if that means driving along a narrower lane.”
As the previous chapter argued, such claims of exclusivity were aimed at gaining distinction
in the Bourdieuian sense of the word. In praising Theaetetus, then, Callimachus produces, as
Alan Cameron puts it, “a mini encomium of another poet that turns out to be a statement of
34 Theaetetus was not necessarily a dramatic poet, since dithyrambs and other kinds of poetry were
also performed at Dionysiac festivals, cf. Cameron (1995: 59, n. 126 citing Fraser 1972: I, 619, 231). Gow
and Page (1965: II, ad loc.) assume, pointing to the tense of the opening verb, that Theaetetus has
switched from performance poetry to another less public kind. In fact, the AP contains six epigrams
ascribed to a certain Theaetetus (cf. Gow and Page 1965: II, 520 ff.). It is not entirely certain that this is
the same man.
35 One may further think of AP 12.43: οὐδὲ κελεύθῳ / χαίρω, τίς πολλοὺς ὧδε καὶ ὧδε φέρει. (The
path that brings many hither and thither does not please me). The expressions have usually been
interpreted as pointing back to Pindar (O. 6.23; I. 5.23: καθαρή κέλευθος); (Paean 7b 11: τριπ]τόν καθ´
ἁμαξιτόν). Asper (1997: 29, n. 34), however, notes that the interpretation of the phrase in Pindar is
very problematic, cf. Ch 2.5.1. He interprets the metaphor in AP 9.565 as coming from the field of
religious initiation (1997: 53‐56): Theaetetus’ poetry stands to vulgar poetry as the mystic initiate of
Bacchus (who will be immortal in the next world) to the uninitiated. Callimachus and Theaetetus are
represented as initiates in the same mystic ritual.
154
[his] own views on poetry.” 36 At the same time, he arrogates the judgment of taste that
decides who will be immortal and who will not by declaring that all Hellas will forever
praise his work. This praise will therefore last eternally, like the positive judgment on
Theaetetus’ (i.e., by implication, Callimachean) poetics. Together, they determine the
evaluation of Greek poetry: the fates of Theaetetus and Callimachus are firmly bound
together by this epigram. Prophesying future fame for another poet on these conditions is
equivalent to auguring future acclaim for oneself.
speculative–reading of this epigram in combination with two further epigrams by
Callimachus that also address participation in Dionysiac competitions:
Μικρή τις, Διόνυσε, καλὰ πρήσσοντι ποιητῇ
ῥῆσις∙ ὁ μὲν “Νικῶ” φησὶ τὸ μακρότατον∙
ᾧ δὲ σὺ μὴ πνεύσῃς ἐνδέξιος, ἤν τις ἔρηται
“Πῶς ἔβαλες;” φησί∙ “Σκληρὰ τὰ γιγνόμενα.”
τῷ μερμηρίξαντι τὰ μὴ ἔνδικα τοῦτο γένοιτο
τοὖπος∙ ἐμοὶ δ’, ὦναξ, ἡ βραχυσυλλαβίη. (AP 9.566)
The words of a successful poet are but few, Dionysus, “Won,” he says at most. But
when someone asks a poet whom you do not favor with inspiration, “What luck?” he
answers, “Things are going badly.” May that be the answer of him who has pondered
unfairness; but may I, O lord, be ever short‐syllabled.
Εὐδαίμων ὅτι τἆλλα μανεὶς ὡρχαῖος Ὀρέστας,
Λεύκαρε, τὰν ἁμὰν οὐκ ἐμάνη μανίαν
οὐδ’ ἔλαβ’ ἐξέτασιν τῶ Φωκέος ἅτις ἐλέγχει
τὸν φίλον∙ ἀλλ’ αἰ χ´ ἕν δρᾶμ’ ἐδίδαξε μόνον,
ἦ τάχα κα τὸν ἑταῖρον ἀπώλεσε∙ τοῦτο ποήσας
κἠγὼ τοὺς πολλοὺς οὐκέτ’ ἔχω Πυλάδας. (AP 11.362) 37
Orestes of old was lucky that, although he was mad in all other respects, Leucarus, at
least that madness of mine did not seize him and he did not apply the ultimate test of
friendship to the Phocian [i.e., Pylades]. No, had he but staged one drama, truly, he
would have soon lost his friend. By doing this I too have lost all my Pyladeses.
36 Cameron (1995: 60). He moreover argues that σοφίη is another reference to Callimachean poetics (cf.
fr. 1 Pf. 17‐18: αὖθι δε τέχνηι / κρίνετε μὴ σχοίνωι Περσίδι τὴν σοφίην: judge by art, not with the
Persian yardstick), and of Pindaric descent. This seems to be taking the allusion a bit to far, since
σοφίη is a common term in archaic poetry since Solon in connection with poetry and remains so in
Hellenistic poetry.
37 I follow the text of Gow and Page, which differs at some points from that of Beckby: ἁμὰν (2,
Schneider) instead of μὰν (P) or λίαν (Beckby); αἰ χ´ ἕν (4) instead of αἰ χἤν (Davies); τοὺς πολλοὺς
(6) instead of τὼς πολλὼς (Wilamowitz). For the interpretation of the epigram, cf. Davies (1925: 176).
155
The first epigram seems to presuppose that Callimachus participated in the Dionysiac
competitions 38 and that he prays for victory. The phrase “he who has pondered unfairness,”
according to Gow and Page (1965: II, ad loc.), might refer to a specific individual rival but, as
they admit, the reference of the phrase is unclear. The next epigram might describe the
problems clinging to poetic competition between friends: it can easily turn to rivalry and
hostility. 39
Returning to the connection with AP 9.565, it is remarkable that Callimachus appears
to wish for the glory of winning a competition (AP 9.566) but consoles Theaetetus for losing
by implying that the verdicts of juries in such competitions are ephemeral and cannot
compete with the eternal judgment of Hellenic taste (AP 9.565). 40 Supposing that all three
could be read as a series, perhaps the third epigram (AP 11.362) addresses the problem
caused by the contradictory assertions of the other two. It could be argued that Callimachus
thus demonstrates what happens in a poetic competition between friends: when his friend
Theaetetus loses, he commiserates and deprecates the importance of such victories (AP
9.565). When Callimachus himself wins in a similar contest, he is happy (AP 9.566); suddenly
victory is important, whereas losing is a fate that is wished upon “someone who has
one to lose one’s friends (AP 11.362). However, as stated, a combined reading of the three
poems must remain mere conjecture.
5.4 Inviting Comparison
Theocritus’ Id. 7 arguably contains a parody on the implicit “claims of allegiance” to a poetic
ideal such as we saw at work in the epigrams of Callimachus and Leonidas praising Aratus.
In this poem, the young and inexperienced singer Simichidas tries to persuade the goatherd
38 That is to say, if like most commentators assume, the speaking persona is “Callimachus the poet.”
The Suda ascribes to Callimachus satyr drama, tragedy and comedy. None of this alleged dramatic
output survives.
39 Gow and Page (1965: II, 211) suggest combining AP 9.566 and AP 11.362.
40 The address to Dionysus seems to fortify the link between the two epigrams. AP 9.565 and 9.566 are
consecutive in the Anthologia Palatina; this may, but of course need not, imply that they were
consecutive in a Callimachean poetry book. Gutzwiller (1998: 304) argues that the two poems may
originally have formed part of a (Meleagrean, i.e., first cent. BCE) section on poetic victory in book 6,
but later have been repositioned by the Byzantine scholar Cephalas.
156
poet Lycidas, 41 whom he clearly expects to be the lesser singer, to join him in a singing
competition with the following quasi‐modest words:
(…) Λυκίδα φίλε, φαντί τυ πάντες
ἦμεν συρικτὰν μέγ’ ὑπείροχον ἔν τε νομεῦσιν
ἔν τ’ ἀματήρεσσι. τὸ δὴ μάλα θυμὸν ἰαίνει
ἁμέτερον∙ καίτοι κατ’ ἐμὸν νόον ἰσοφαρίζειν
ἔλπομαι. (…)(7.27‐31)
Lycidas, all men say that among the herdsmen and the reapers you are by far the best
of pipers, and much it warms my heart to hear. And yet, in my thought, I fancy
myself your equal. 42
Some lines later, he continues:
καὶ γὰρ ἐγὼ Μοισᾶν καπυρὸν στόμα, κἠμὲ λέγοντι
πάντες ἀοιδὸν ἄριστον∙ ἐγὼ δέ τις οὐ ταχυπειθής
οὐ Δᾶν∙ οὐ γάρ πω κατ’ ἐμὸν νόον οὔτε τὸν ἐσθλόν
Σικελίδαν νίκημι τὸν ἐκ Σάμω οὔτε Φιλίταν
ἀείδων, βάτραχος δὲ ποτ’ ἀκρίδας ὥς τις ἐρίσδω. (7.37‐41)
For I too am a clear voice of the Muses and all call me the best of singers. But I am
slow to credit them, by Jove. For in my own esteem I am as yet no match in song
either for the great Sicelidas from Samos or for Philitas but vie with them like a frog
against grasshoppers. (transl. Gow adapted)
Apart from the claim that “all praise him as the best poet” (37‐8), paradoxically, it is the
expression οὐ ... πω ... ἐρίσδω (“I am as yet no match”) that best reveals Simichidas’ high
opinion of himself. 43 For he hereby invites comparison with two of the most famous singers
of an earlier generation of Hellenistic poetry: the epigrammatist Asclepiades of Samos (here
called Sicelidas) 44 and Philitas, the former tutor of Ptolemy Philadelphus, a poet greatly
admired in elitist poetic circles. 45 Later on, Simichidas will even brag that the fame of his
41 On the identification of Simichidas and Lycidas, see Ch. 7.4.
42 Especially the qualification of Lycidas as syrinx player (who punctuates his rural song with piping,
pointedly contrasted with ἀοιδόν, 38) gives away Simichidas’ real opinion of Lycidas, cf. Hunter
(1999: 160), who notes that Simichidas considers Lycidas “a rural nobody.”
43 Dover (1971: 147), Segal (1974: 128‐136). On Simichidas’ feigned modesty, cf. also Effe, (1988: 97‐91),
Hunter (1999: 144‐199, passim), Fantuzzi and Hunter (2004: 134‐5).
44 For the identification, cf. Gow and Page (1965: II, 114‐118, on Hedylus Ath. 11.473a); Fraser (1972: I,
557‐61). Schol. in Theoc. consider it a patronymic.
45 Philitas was particularly famous for his elegies, in particular Bittis (cf. Call. fr. 1 Pf., Hermesianax, fr.
7 Powell, Posidippus 63 AB).
157
poetry may well have reached “the throne of Zeus” (93), which is probably a reference to
Ptolemy Philadelphus himself. 46
It is inherently unlikely that a poet belonging to the courtly and poetic elite would
give any importance to a poetic competition with someone he appears to consider a “rural
nobody” like Lycidas. Clearly, Simichidas’ boasts are intended to awe this “simple”
goatherd; they should not be taken at face value. Moreover, the fact that Simichidas speaks of
his own poetic ability (even in a depreciatory sense) in the same breath as that of Philitas and
Asclepiades betrays his belief that he will be rightly called their equal sooner rather than
later. His faux modesty is a deliberate way of associating himself with their successful
poetics. It works on the principle that claims of allegiance implicitly suggest similarity to the
praised poet, as demonstrated in section 5.2.
Lycidas’ reply that Simichidas is “a sapling all fashioned for truth by Zeus” (πᾶν ἐπ’
ἀλαθείᾳ πεπλασμένον ἐκ Διὸς ἔρνος, 44) gains ironic weight in this light. 47 It addresses the
fact that Simichidas, despite (or perhaps because of) his feigned humility, unwittingly
reveals his real motives and opinion of himself to Lycidas. In his naivety, he raises the stakes
for comparison much too high, somewhat like a just‐published novelist saying that the Nobel
Prize will probably not come his way this year yet.
The true subtlety of Idyll 7, however, lies in the fact that with hindsight the poem as a
whole could be read as a tribute to Lycidas, “the simple goatherd,” and his extraordinarily
refined poetry. The poem thus creates an ironic distance between what is explicitly said by
Simichidas in praise of Philitas and Asclepiades and the qualities of the mysterious goatherd
poet Lycidas that are implicitly communicated by the Idyll as a whole. 48 With this fine piece
of irony, Theocritus demonstrates that he knows how the workings of praise, specifically
claiming allegiance to an admired poetics and comparison to admired poets, operate. A
46 Cf. Gow (1952: II, ad loc.), cf. Hunter (1999: 179). Ptolemy is also likened to Zeus in Id. 17.131‐4.
Another sign of Simichidas’ pretension is his bragging about the wealth and talent of his alleged
friends. At 31‐4 he emphasizes the riches of his hosts, who have been introduced elaborately earlier on
(4‐6). Lines 99‐102 contain exuberant praise of his friend Aristis, a lyre‐player.
47 Gow (1952: II, 143) detects no irony here, nor does Dover (1971: 154), however Hunter (1999: 163):
“Lycidas ironically takes him at his word.” For a meta‐poetic interpretation , see e.g. Goldhill (1991:
232‐3) and Ch. 7.4.
48 Although this is hard to prove, Lycidas’ song is generally considered aesthetically much superior to
that of Simichidas.
158
Hellenistic poet who proclaimed what he admired, thereby revealed who he hoped to be, or,
as in Simichidas’ case, to become.
5.5 Eliciting Praise
In the context of praise and admiration, some brief remarks are also due on the compliments
poets paid to the literary judgment of their patrons or other addressees. By implying that his
literary taste is impeccable, a poet implicitly obliges the intended recipient to like his poem.
A similar principle underlies the flattering opposition Callimachus creates in his Aetia‐
prologue between the ideal (or implied) readers of his text and his ignorant detractors, the
Telchines. 49 Phrases like the following illustrate this intention:
(...) ἐνὶ τοῖς γὰρ ἀείδομεν οἳ λιγὺν ἦχον
τέττιγος, θ]όρυβον δ’ οὐκ ἐφίλησαν ὄνων. (fr. 1.29‐30 Pf.)
For we sing for those who love the delicate sound of the cicada, and not the braying
of asses.
In this poem, the image of a negative reception of poetry (as exemplified by the Telchines’
complaints) serves as a foil to its desired reception by the addressee (Cf. Chapter 4.5). This
principle also informs the structure of Theocritus’16th Idyll for Hiero II of Syracuse (cf.
Chapter 2.3). By ridiculing the point of view of miserly and stingy patrons, Theocritus
implies that he expects Hiero to be generous and aristocratic in his approach to poets.
Ptolemy Philadelphus, on the other hand, whose generous patronage of the arts apparently
inspires more confidence, is not flattered by Theocritus with such indirect means but praised
explicitly as a connoisseur and generous patron: 50
οὐδὲ Διωνύσου τις ἀνὴρ ἱεροὺς κατ’ ἀγῶνας
ἵκετ’ ἐπιστάμενος λιγυρὰν ἀναμέλψαι ἀοιδάν,
ᾧ οὐ δωτίναν ἀντάξιον ὤπασε τέχνας.
Μουσάων δ’ ὑποφῆται ἀείδοντι Πτολεμαῖον
ἀντ’ εὐεργεσίης. (17.112‐115)
And there never comes a man skilled to raise his clear‐voiced song to the sacred
contest of Dionysus who does not receive the gift his art deserves, and those prophets
of the Muses sing of Ptolemy for his benefactions. (transl. Gow, adapted)
49 Cf. Schmitz (1999: 151‐178), see also Ch. 4.5.1.
50 Ptolemy is called φιλόμουσος by Thyonichus in Theoc. Id. 14.61.
159
The passage enacts the ideal of patronage: the principle of do ut des through which poetry
may thrive and procure κλέος for its patrons. It was of course extremely appropriate to
flatter this particular king in such a way, since his support of the Alexandrian Museum
showed that he wished to present himself as a lover of literature. 51 In the encomium,
Theocritus characterizes himself as one of the many “prophets of the Muses” who sing
Ptolemy’s praises: all singers are envisaged as peacefully hymning the king in unison
(17.115); an interesting contrast with the tactic employed in Callimachus’ Aetia prologue. It
would of course not do to suggest that Theocritus was the only poet interested in hymning
the King. As Chapter 8 will illustrate however, he does emphasize the fact that he is a poet
who is in possession of exclusive qualities which Ptolemy will need.
A similar consensus of praising voices is also predicted in the prophetic ending of Id.
16, where the peaceful future of a bountiful Sicily under the benign reign of Hiero is
envisaged:
εἷς μὲν ἐγώ, πολλοὺς δὲ Διὸς φιλέοντι καὶ ἄλλους
θυγατέρες, τοῖς πᾶσι μέλοι Σικελὴν Ἀρέθοισαν
ὑμνεῖν σὺν λαοῖσι καὶ αἰχμητὴν Ἱέρωνα. (16.101‐103)
I am but one, and the daughters of Zeus love many another beside; and may they all
be fain to sing of Sicilian Arethusa with her warriors and the spearman Hiero. (transl.
Gow)
The question whether this is a natural wish in a poet who seems to be desperately seeking a
patron in the rest of Idyll 16 is beside the point. What is important is the mollifying of the
mood of the prospective patron towards this single proposing poet. A little flattery, implying
that everyone must want to sing his praises, might accomplish this, or so Theocritus appears
to think. 52
The compliments Theocritus pays to his ξένος (guest‐friend) the Milesian doctor
Nicias (Id. 11, 13, 28) may also be addressed in this context. Theocritus is very flattering in his
appreciation of Nicias’ poetic sensibilities; he praises him extravagantly as exceedingly loved
by the nine Muses (ταῖς ἐννέα δὴ πεφιλημένον ἔξοχα Μοίσαις) and a holy shoot of the
sweet‐voiced Graces (Χαρίτων ἰμεροφώνων ἴερον φύτον). Some epigrams that Nicias
composed survive in the Palatine Anthology, which shows that Meleager deemed them
51 Weber reads the expression Μουσάων δ’ ὑποφῆται as an indirect reference to the Museum (1993:
322). However, on this expression, see Ch. 8.
52 Cf. Goldhill (1991: 279‐280).
160
worthy of his Garland. 53 Nicias must therefore have been a poet of some repute, even if the
epigrams are not of extraordinary quality. But this is beside the point, because in reality,
Theocritus is not primarily concerned with asserting that Nicias was an extraordinary poet.
In Idyll 11, the praise for Nicias’ poetic qualities is mainly part of the humorous explanation
of why he will be an expert in judging the wisdom of the Cyclops, who found the perfect
remedy for lovesickness in poetry: he is both a doctor and a poet. Perhaps Idyll 11’s
presupposed situation is that Nicias is unhappily in love and writing love‐poetry, like the
Cyclops Polyphemus, who was not known foremost for his inspired poetry. If so, the
“compliment” amounts to the following: “Nicias, you will be able to appreciate this poem
like no other, for, just like Polyphemus, you have become a poet now that you’re in love.” The
scholiast relates that Nicias replied to this humorous taunt:
ἦν ἄρ’ ἀληθὲς τοῦτο, Θεόκριτε∙ οἱ γὰρ Ἔρωτες
ποιητὰς πολλοὺς ἐδίδαξαν τοὺς πρὶν ἀμούσους. (fr. 566 SH)
That was very true, Theocritus. For the Erotes teach many, who were not musical
before, to be poets.
This ties in with the proposed explanation: Nicias seems to admit he has written poetry only
because he was unhappily in love. 54 Clearly, Theocritus’ compliments of Nicias have an
tongue in cheek or humorous edge and form an ironic parody of the conventional praise
usually lavished upon a recipient of poetry. As has been demonstrated, he is not above
paying such compliments on his own patrons, Hiero II and Ptolemy Philadelphus and, in the
context of his more familiar relationship with Nicias, the principles of the captatio
benevolentiae were perhaps gently parodied.
5.6 Conclusion
The drive underlying the wish to praise contemporaries have turned out to be not so
different from that fueling criticism and blame, so often regarded as typical for the
53 AP 6.122; AP 6.127; AP 6.270; AP 7.200; AP 9.315; AP 9.564; APl. 188; APl. 189, most of these are
dedications, some with a hint of bucolicism (AP 7.200; AP 9.564; APl. 189). As Gow and Page (1965: II,
429) remark: “they are of reasonable competence rather than of distinction (...) unless Nicias’ surviving
works are unfair to him, we must allow for the obligations of friendship and courtesy [in Theocritus’
praise of him].”
54 Alternatively, he might be turning the gibe on Theocritus, perhaps. Due to the lack of context, the
full implications of the epigram remain ambiguous.
161
atmosphere among the bickering scribblers in the Birdcage of the Muses. In both cases, it can
be defined as a wish for distinction, the creation of a position in the field of cultural
production.
A recurrent feature of praise is the wish to be aligned with the distinctive and refined
Leonidas). This is done by subtly incorporating the admired parameters of the praised
poetics in the poetry of praise itself. A double connection between the poetics of the two
poets at the giving and the receiving ends of the praise is thus forged, explicitly (by the mere
expression of praise) and implicitly (by incorporating the admired principles in the
expression of praise). By making an object of admiration the subject of poetry, the poet
adopts, so to say, the admired poetics of the other poet and moreover implicitly
demonstrates his authoritative judgment.
At times, praising a less successful poet may be worthwhile as well, because it
displays an exclusivity of judgment and a taste that will only be shared in times to come (as
in Callimachus’ epigram on Theaetetus). By proclaiming the immortality of the praised in his
poetry, the poet implies that his own poetry will also be immortal, as it will accompany and
testify to the immortality of the other.
Striving to attain a certain similarity to the object of praise is clearly the principal
factor underlying the praise of contemporary poets, then. In a slightly different form, this
principle is also evidenced by an author’s pleas for benevolent judgment on the part of the
reader (cf. Theocritus Id. 16, 17). Through praise of the addressee’s poetic sensibilities, the
poet hopes to secure a generous reception of the poem. Theocritus was clearly aware that
this principle was of fundamental importance to giving praise, claiming allegiance to the
poetics of successful contemporaries, and flattering patrons. He parodies these practices in
his humorous description of Simichidas, the naive poet comparing himself with the great
names of the age (7). Moreover, his extravagant compliments of Nicias’ poetic qualities,
deliberately placed in a comic context, also point to ironic awareness of the conventions of
the captatio benevolentiae, which he himself practices seriously in Idylls 16 and 17.
All in all, the subject of praise of contemporaries and the awareness of its principles
emerge as integral and vital parts of the Hellenistic discourse on poetics in the birdcage of
162
the Muses. Poets distinguished themselves not only with the divisive weapon of blame but
also by forming (occasionally eternal) alliances.
163
164
CHAPTER 6:
POETIC IDENTITIES: SPHRAGIS‐EPIGRAMS VERSUS ROLE‐PLAYING
6.1 Introduction
After analyzing the Hellenistic poets’ attitude towards their mythical, historical and
contemporary colleagues, the moment has now come to move on to their self‐representation
as poets. The first part of this chapter (6.1‐6.7) focuses on first‐person statements that are
crafted as self‐representations, instances where poets create a characteristic image of
themselves. 1 They belong to the category of sphragis, 2 the term that indicates signature
passages that either explicitly name an author or implicitly identify him or her by a list of
characteristics. 3 Although such passages are absent from the Homeric epics, 4 they can be
found as early as Hesiod (Th. 21‐36), the Homeric Hymn to Apollo (165‐172) and, most
famously perhaps, Theognis: 5
1 By “persona,” I mean the (to some extent possibly fictional) personality of the author as projected in
his first‐person utterances. The recognition of the concept “persona” is relatively recent; in the 19th
century, biographical readings of ancient Greek poetry that hardly distinguished between the
historical poet and his or her constructed persona were common, cf. de Jong (2002: 387‐399). This is
similar to ancient biographical practice; cf. Leo (1901), Momigliano (1971), Lefkowitz (1981).
Theoretical distinction between persona and poeta is not found in ancient literary criticism, cf.
Halliwell (1987: 172) on Arist. Po. 1460a5‐11, Clay (1998: 9‐40). New Historicism provides some useful
insights on the creation of personae as well; it advocates a return to the analysis of the connection
between an artist’s cultural context and his works, yet recognizes an element of deliberate “self‐
fashioning” that complicates the relationship between historical author and persona, cf. e.g. Greenblatt
(1980), Greenblatt and Gallagher (2000). Greenblatt’s theories have been applied to Pliny (Winsor
Leach, 1990), Horace (Mc Neill, 2001) and Cicero (Dugan, 2005).
2 The term is taken from Theogn. 18‐22. What kind of sphragis he envisaged (e.g. inclusion of his own
name, an actual seal to mark the scroll, deposition of the scroll in a temple, insertion of the name of
Cyrnus, the fact that his work was written down, not merely orally delivered) is disputed, cf. e.g.
Courtney (1990: 8‐9), Pratt (1995: 171‐184), Gerber (1997: 117‐129).
3 Kranz (1967: 27‐79) names the following characteristics of sphragis: invocation of the gods of poetic
inspiration, mention of the γένος (ethnicity and family) and τρόπος (character) of the poet, and (in
hymns) the αὔταρ ἐγώ‐formula indicating the next song the poet will embark upon.
4 This leaves out the Muse‐invocations or the representation of the blind bard Demodocus, who was
seen in antiquity as a reflection of Homer; they do not belong to the same category as Hesiod’s
sphragis.
5 On Hesiod’s sphragis cf. West (1966: ad 22‐34), Dornseiff (1966: 37‐8; 76), West (1978: 24), Griffith
(1983: 40). On HH Apoll., cf. Càssola (1999: ad loc.) and West (1999: 364‐382). On Theognis, see
Courtney (1990: 8‐9), Pratt (1995: 171‐184), Gerber (1997: 117‐129).
165
Κύρνε, σοφιζομένωι μὲν ἐμοὶ σφρηγὶς ἐπικείσθω
τοῖσδ’ ἔπεσιν, λήσει δ’ οὔποτε κλεπτόμενα,
οὐδέ τις ἀλλάξει κάκιον τοὐσθλοῦ παρεόντος∙
ὧδε δὲ πᾶς τις ἐρεῖ∙ “Θεύγνιδός ἐστιν ἔπη
τοῦ Μεγαρέως∙ πάντας δὲ κατ’ ἀνθρώπους ὀνομαστός.” (Theogn. 18‐22)
Cyrnus, let a seal be set by me, capable poet as I am, upon these words and they shall
never be stolen unnoticed and no one shall put a worse verse where the better one is
present. Thus will everyone speak: “these are the words of Theognis of Megara, and
he is famous among all people.”
Their raison d’être can be defined as follows:
In a time of mainly oral transmission, a poet who wished to retain the title to his
poetry, needed to stamp it with some mark of ownership; the ease with which poems
could pass from one collection to another, a hazard to which gnomic poetry in
particular was subject, is vividly shown by the well‐known overlaps between the
texts of Theognis on the one hand and on the other of Solon, Tyrtaeus and
Mimnermus. (Courtney, 1990: 7‐8)
This kind of sphragis gains importance when a poet is no longer naturally present at the
occasion of performance (i.e., when a version of a poem starts to circulate independently of
its author). Although the separation of author and work first occurred whenever a song was
performed in the absence of its composer, the sense of disconnection inevitably became more
evident as the oral‐aural transmission of poetry was replaced by writing and reading, a
development that found its culmination in the era of the book, as Rudolf Pfeiffer called the
Hellenistic era. 6
Apart from raising the problem of authorship, the physical separation of author and
work entailed the problem of identifying the speaker’s voice. At live performances, external
factors inherent to performance (e.g., number of speakers, gender, the presence of persons
and objects referred to in the song) allowed the audience to perceive to what degree the
speaker and the poetic “I” were identical. In the written and read versions of poetical works,
however, this was not always self‐evident; a speaking voice might remain unidentified when
6 On the importance of literacy to Hellenistic poetry, cf. Bing (1988). Unsurprisingly, this is also the
time when acrostics, which allowed authors to incorporate their name indelibly in their works, first
appeared. On (signature) acrostics in Greek and Latin poetry, cf. Courtney (1990: 3‐13). Examples of
acrostics serving as sphragis: Chaeremon, end of fifth century BCE: ΧΑΙΡΗΜ‐ (fr. 14b Snell); Nicander
of Colophon, second cent. BCE: Lobel (1928: 114‐115) ΝΙΚΑΝΔΡΟΣ: (Ther. 345‐353; Alex. 266–274.); the
iambic proem to Eudoxus’ (?) astronomical treatise, second cent. BCE: ΕΥΔΟΞΟΥ ΤΕΧΝΗ; the first 23
lines of the proem to the geographical work of a certain Dionysius, son of Calliphon, first cent. BCE:
ΔΙΟΝΥΣΙΟΥ ΤΟΥ ΚΑΛΛΙΦΩΝΤΟΣ.
166
it was removed from external identifiers provided by the original context of a performance. 7
Perhaps sphragis‐like poetic signatures are so common in Hellenistic poetry because they
help prevent this uncertainty by allowing the author to broadcast his authorship.
poet as historical person, which was remarked upon in Chapter 1. For by including sphragis‐
passages, the author identifies himself through the creation of a persona even when not
present at the reception of his work. The contents of these passages show that the work is
usually felt to be an expression of the poet’s character and creed. In the case of poetry
collections (e.g., of epigrams, the main topic of this chapter), readers would be inclined to
take all statements in the first person as expressions of the poet’s persona, such as it was
introduced in the sphragis, unless explicitly indicated otherwise (by name or gender
specifications).
The second part of this chapter will discuss instances of “role‐playing,” i.e., when a
poet creates a completely fictional personality, which differs from what we may assume is
his own historical personality or poetic persona (6.8). It may seem at first that these subjects
have little in common, or even that one is opposed to the other. This is partly true; yet, as I
will argue, both find their origin in the fact that (written) poem and poet were no longer
automatically coupled at the occasion of performance in the Hellenistic Age. On the one
hand, this stimulated poets to identify themselves vis à vis their readers in sphragis‐passages,
on the other, it also offered them the possibility to play hide and seek by manipulating their
readers’ expectations. Both of these ways of dealing with identity ultimately derive from the
awareness based on their own experience that hundreds of years after their deaths, readers
would wonder who the “I” expressing its opinions in the text on the scroll really was (cf.
Chapter 1). It could be important to make this clear unequivocally, to communicate with
future readers beyond the grave, as most of the sphragis‐epigrams would seem to do. But the
awareness that their texts, completely detached from their current contexts, would be all that
remained for the prospective reader, also offered Hellenistic poets the possibility of playing
with this reader, inviting him to guess at the identity of the speaker. In a way, this practice is
similar to what Peter Bing has observed in Callimachus’ epigrams, and which he calls
7 Cf. Bowie (1993: 1‐37).
167
“Ergänzungsspiel:” 8 the reader is invited to participate in the recreation of the presupposed
situation the poem describes.
6.2 Sphragis in Epigrams: Succinct Self‐portraits
As demonstrated in Chapter 1, the Hellenistic preoccupation with literary tradition
occasioned a vogue of literary epitaphs for dead poets. 9 Most of these can be read as
(playful) evaluations: in the compass of a few lines, they strive to convey the most essential
characteristics of the works and personality of these poets, items that were regarded as
reflections of each other. A remarkable echo of this practice is found in the sphragis poetry
that Hellenistic poets also started to write about themselves; these too often took the form of
literary epitaphs. They probably felt that they had an excellent opportunity to influence the
opinion of later audiences: they could now present themselves by the same tools they
employed to evaluate predecessors. Their outlook on the past steered their glance forward to
their own eventual fame and thus influenced the way they tried to enter the literary
tradition.
Apart from the fiction of being epitaphs, many of the sphragis epigrams create the
impression of being sung at symposia. 10 It was common practice to “joke over a cup of wine”
at these occasions (οἴνῳ καίρια συγγελάσαι, i.e., improvise or perform witty epigrams), 11 as
Callimachus phrases it in his own epitaph (AP 7.415). The preeminence of this theme
suggests that belonging to the social stratum that frequented symposia was an important
part of the projected identity of many third‐century poets. 12 There is of course a tension
between the ephemeral quality of symposiastic jokes and witticisms and the wish to leave
8 Bing (1995: 117‐123), cf. Meyer (2005).
9 Cf. e.g. AP 7.5 (Alc. of Messene on Homer); AP 7.11 (Asclep. on Erinna); AP 7.28 (Anon. on
Anacreon); 7.410 (Diosc. on Tellen); AP 7.709 (Alex. Aet. on Alcman).
10 Cf. Reitzenstein (1893). For recent reviews of his ideas, see e.g. Cameron (1995: 71‐103), Gutzwiller
(1998: 115‐122), Parsons (2002: 99‐137), Fantuzzi and Hunter (2004: 283‐349), Guichard (2004: 54‐55).
All these accounts stress the tension between fictional literacy and fictional orality characterizing
Hellenistic epigram.
11 Cf. Reitzenstein (1893: 87).
12 Of the poets discussed here, this applies to Asclepiades, Hedylus, Posidippus, and Callimachus. The
symposium is absent from the poetry of Leonidas. Nossis, as a woman, does not refer to it either. For
the importance of the symposium in Hellenistic elite culture, see e.g. Cameron (1995: 71‐104).
168
behind a poetic monument for future generations implied by the act of writing them down.
This indeed is the essential paradox of the Hellenistic epigram
6.3 Asclepiades, Hedylus, Posidippus: Eros, Bacchus and the Poet
The interaction of erotic and symposiastic themes with the representation of poetic personae
is a major theme in the poetry of Asclepiades, Posidippus and Hedylus. In antiquity, the
symposiastic epigrams of these poets were already perceived as so closely connected that
authorship of some of the poems was uncertain. 13 This led Reitzenstein to his famous thesis
of the Σωρός (Heap), a joint collection of epigrams by the three poets, where authorship was
not indicated. 14 Although this theory has not found wide acceptance, a close thematic as well
as historical connection between the three authors is undeniable. 15
Epigram AP 5.169 by Asclepiades 16 is generally regarded as the opening of a
collection of his erotic‐symposiastic poetry. 17 It lacks a signature in the sense of a name but
nevertheless qualifies as sphragis, because it expresses the preferences which characterize the
13 Asclepiades and Posidippus share six attributions and one is shared by Asclepiades and Hedylus, cf.
Gow and Page (1965: I, xxx; II, 117). They assume that these double attributions go back to Meleager
(first cent. BCE) because the doubt is not indicated by οἱ δὲ, like in all other attributions, but by ἤ. Mel.
AP 4.1.45‐46 also closely connects the three.
14 Reitzenstein (1970 [1893]: 101‐102). The collection was supposed to have functioned as a kind of
“written down symposium” of the three poets, in which one poem capped the other in the way this
happened at real symposia. Reitzenstein based this idea on the mention of the Σωρός in the scholia A
ad Il. 11.101. For a discussion of the problems in Reitzenstein’s thesis cf. e.g. Lloyd‐Jones (1963: 96‐7),
Gow and Page (1965: II, 116), Gutzwiller (1998: 152).
15 Asclepiades and Hedylus are both from Samos; Asclepiades features in an epigram of Hedylus (Ath.
11.473a/VI GP); Asclepiades and Posidippus are both named in an honorary decree at Delphi
(Homolle, 1909: III, 3 no. 192). Moreover, the latter two both describe Ptolemaic monuments in
Alexandria, which would suggest that they lived there as contemporaries, i.e., around the 270s BCE.
Gutzwiller (1998: 182) posits that Hedylus and Posidippus composed their collections to be read
against the background of the poems of the older Asclepiades.
16 Or “Sicelidas,” as he is called in Theoc. Id. 7.39 (cf. scholia ad loc.) and by Hedylus (Ath. 11.473a/IV
GP) and Meleager (AP 14.1,46). Testimonies suggest that he was born around 320 BCE (Gow and Page,
1965: II, 115), and thus “stands on threshold of the new age in which he was a powerful formative
influence.” He is also named by the Scholia Florentina on Call. fr. 1 Pf. as one of the Telchines, together
with Posidippus, cf. Ch. 4.6.
17 Cf. Gutzwiller (1998: 172); Guichard (2004: 139).
169
author’s persona by means of a priamel, a rhetorical form the Hellenistic epigrammatists
particularly favored in this context. 18
Ἡδὺ θέρους διψῶντι χιὼν ποτόν, ἡδὺ δὲ ναύταις
ἐκ χειμῶνος ἰδεῖν εἰαρινὸν Στέφανον∙
ἥδιον δ’, ὁπόταν κρύψῃ μία τοὺς φιλέοντας
χλαῖνα καὶ αἰνῆται Κύπρις ὑπ’ ἀμφοτέρων. (AP 5.169)
Sweet, in summer, for one who is thirsty is an icy drink; and sweet for sailors it is to
spot, when winter is ending, the constellation of Spring’s crown; but sweeter still
when one cover envelops lovers, and the Cyprian is praised by both of them.
The epigram expresses a specific outlook on life: of all of life’s pleasures, mutual erotic love
is the greatest. 19 This reads like an announcement of the (poetic) interests of the author.
Indeed, the great majority of Asclepiades’ poetry deals with love and its pleasures and
pains. 20 Yet, the praised sweetness arising from mutual love is exception rather than rule in
the collection. Asclepiades’ poetry on this topic may be “sweet;” 21 the torments he describes
hardly are. It is no surprise that the other signature poem, AP 12.50 (considered the closing
poem of the posited collection), offers a much more pessimistic outlook on love.
Πῖν’, Ἀσκληπιάδη. τί τὰ δάκρυα ταῦτα; τί πάσχεις;
οὐ σὲ μόνον χαλεπὴ Κύπρις ἐληίσατο,
οὐδ’ ἐπὶ σοὶ μούνῳ κατεθήξατο τόξα καὶ ἰοὺς
πικρὸς Ἔρως. τί ζῶν ἐν σποδιῇ τίθεσαι;
πίνωμεν Βάκχου ζωρὸν πόμα∙ δάκτυλος ἀώς.
ἦ πάλι κοιμιστὰν λύχνον ἰδεῖν μένομεν;
†πίνομεν∙ οὐ γὰρ ἔρως† μετά τοι χρόνον οὐκέτι πουλύν
σχέτλιε, τὴν μακρὰν νύκτ’ ἀναπαυσόμεθα. (AP 12.50) 22
18 A definition of priamel is given by Bundy (1962: I, 5): “The priamel is a focusing or selecting device
in which one or more terms serve as foil for the point of particular interest.” See further Race (1982).
On the programmatic use of the priamel in Hellenistic epigram, see Guichard (2004: 139‐141).
19 The poem stands in the tradition of general priamels, cf. e.g. Arist. Eth. Eud. 1214a6 (purportedly
inscribed on the Propylaea of the Letoön at Delos, but also found in Theogn. 255‐256): κάλλιστον τὸ
δικαιότατον, λῷστον δ’ ὑγιαίνειν∙ / πάντων ἥδιστον δ’ οὗ τις ἐρᾷ τὸ τυχεῖν. (Most beautiful is what
is most righteous; best is to be in good health; sweetest of all is to get that which one longs for).
20 Gutzwiller (1998: 123): “The identifying characteristic of this youthful Asclepiades is his entrapment
within an endless cycle of love, a cycle of desire and betrayal, symbolized by the dice game of the
Erotes, AP 12.46.” Cf. the depiction of Eros in Anacr. PMG 398 and A.R. Arg. 3.
21 The opening word Ἡδὺ should also be regarded as a poetic quality sought by Asclepiades, cf. the
frequent recurrence of this term in meta‐poetic contexts in other Hellenistic poets, e.g. Nossis AP
5.170, Theoc. Id. 1.1; 65; 145; 148, Call. Aet. 1.11.
22 Some notes on the text and interpretation: Gow and Page (1965, II: 127) remark that ἀώς (5) may
mean the same as ἡμέρα; Guichard (2004: ad loc.) thinks this is not the case. In line 6, the phrase πάλι
κοιμιστὰν λύχνον remains hard to understand, whatever reading is chosen. Line 7, despite many
conjectures also remains problematic. For a discussion see the commentary of Guichard (2004: ad loc.).
170
Drink, Asclepiades; why these tears? What is the matter with you? You are not the
only one that cruel Cypris has carried captive, and bitter Eros has not whetted his
bow and arrows on you alone. Why do you lie in ashes, a living corpse? Let’s drink
the unmixed drink of Bacchus; a finger of day is still showing. Should we wait again
to see the lantern to put us to bed? (?) We drink since Eros is not present. After a short
while, you fool, we will be made to rest the long night. 23
Whereas AP 5.169 expresses an ideal and a poetic program, AP 12.50 reflects the harsh reality
of Asclepiades’ experiences, which the reader has witnessed in the other poems in the
collection (cf. πικρὸς Ἔρως, bitter Eros, 4). The poem nuances the image of his persona and
of his poetic program offered in the first epigram: his view on love is played out between the
expectation that it is ἡδύ (sweet) and the experience that it is often πικρός (bitter). Hence, his
poetry comprises the two components of Sappho’s famous phrase “γλυκυπικρός Ἔρως”
(Eros, the bittersweet).
As Gow and Page note: “It is not quite plain whether A. is addressing himself or is
addressed by comrades at the symposium,” 24 but to my mind the first possibility seems more
probable. 25 If so, the epigram nicely illustrates the dichotomy of Asclepiades’ persona
(desperate lover and wryly commenting poet in one), which has been singled out as a
Perhaps a toast to love is lurking in the garbled syntax of the first half of the line. The idea expressed
might be something like “we drink to love anyway; for in a short while, not even bitter love will be
here.”
23 The poem owes a great deal to Alc. fr. 346 Voigt: πώνωμεν∙ τί τὰ λύχν’ ὀμμένομεν; δάκτυλος
ἀμέρα... etc. Guichard (2004: 267) claims that Asclepiades has deliberately reversed some of the
phrases. In Alcaeus evening has not arrived, yet, drinking can begin (1). In AP 12.50, day is about to
break, night is almost over; it is just as well to finish another drink and wait till daybreak (5, but see
previous note). Alcaeus calls for a heady mixture (one measure of water on two of wine, cf. e.g. Ath.
10.430a), to enable the drinkers to “forget troubles” (3). Asclepiades calls for unmixed wine (5), a drink
the Greeks thought only fitting for barbarians, in toasts (especially toasts to beloveds, cf. Theoc. Id.
2.150‐154 and 14.18), libations to the gods or in medical use (cf. Hippocr. Anaph. vii 56), cf. Page (1955:
ad loc.). Alc. frs. 335 and 38a Page also share some of the epigram’s thematic similarities, viz. the carpe
diem‐motif combined with drinking, cf. also Theogn. 877‐8; 973‐8.
24 Gow and Page (1965: II, 127). In favor of the second option: e.g. Wilamowitz (1906: 113): “So reden die
Genossen Asklepiades an, der trübselig aus Liebesgram an der Kneiptafel sitzt,” cf. Beckby (1958: IV, 545),
Hutchinson (1988: 275‐6), Gutzwiller (1998: 148).
25 So Knauer (1935: 13), Stella (1949: 56), cf. Guichard (2004: 60; 263): “La invitación a beber es un estilema
de la poesia simposiaca; la novedad de Asclepíades consiste en que se hace la invitación a sí mismo.” None of
the other epigrams by Asclepiades present a mimetic fiction in which the author is addressed,
whereas the author’s persona speaks on numerous occasions.
171
characteristic of his poetry. 26 Reason and emotion are split when it comes to the troubles of
love; 27 the only solution is to drink deeply and find oblivion.
The epigram lacks any reference to poetic immortality. This topic does however
interest Asclepiades elsewhere: it occurs in his epigrams on Erinna (AP 7.11) and
Antimachus (AP 9.63). Yet, in the setting of AP 12.50, poetic immortality is the last thing to
worry about for the speaker, caught up as he is in his unhappy affair and his cups of
unmixed wine. 28 The only thing that he expects will continue after his own death is that the
Erotes will go on playing their endless game of dice; the everlasting cycle of love, hope,
betrayal, and despair will continue. 29
Although Asclepiades does not explicitly connect them, it is well known that the
themes of drinking and love are often linked to the motif of poetic inspiration or
composition. 30 In Hellenistic poetry, the theme of the drunken poet is found, for example, in
the following epigram by Hedylus, which may have been a sphragis opening a collection of
his poetry. 31
πίνωμεν∙ καὶ γάρ τι νέον, καὶ γάρ τι παρ’ οἶνον
εὕροιμ’ ἂν λεπτὸν καί τι μελιχρὸν ἔπος.
ἀλλὰ κάδοις Χίου με κατάβρεχε καὶ λέγε “παῖζε,
Ἡδύλε.” μισῶ ζῆν ἐς κενόν, οὐ μεθύων. (Ath. 11.473a/GP V)
Let’s drink, for I would find a new, yes, in my cups, I would find a refined and sweet
verse. Come, drench me with gallons of Chian wine, and say, “Play, Hedylus.” I hate
to live to no purpose, without being drunk.
26 E.g. Gutzwiller (1998: 139), Guichard (2004: 57‐61). However, Gutzwiller does not read the present
epigram as an instance of this, but assumes the presence of an interlocutor.
27 Cf. below on Pos. AP 12.98 and AB 100 and Call. AP 12.43 and 12.73. Fantuzzi and Hunter (2004:
448‐462), cite many examples of the division between the intellect and the emotions in the man of
letters in love.
28 Cf. e.g AP 12.99,3‐4 (anon.): τηκέσθω Μουσέων ὁ πολὺς πόνος∙ ἐν πυρὶ γὰρ νοῦς / βέβληται
γλυκερῆς ἄχθος ἔχων ὀδύνης. (Let the laborious work of the Muses waste away, for my mind is prey
to the flames, with the pain of a sweet sickness). For the opposite idea, viz. that poetry can assuage
love’s disease, cf. Call. AP 12.150; Theoc. Id. 11.
29 AP 12.46,3‐4: ... δῆλον, Ἔρωτες, / ὡς τὸ πάρος παίξεσθ’ ἄφρονες ἀστραγάλοις. (It’s clear, Erotes,
you will continue playing dice, as before).
30 Wine as an inspiration, or rather a condition for the composition of poetry is attested as early as
Archilochus: ὡς Διωνύσου ἄνακτος καλὸν ἐξάρξαι μέλος / οἶδα διθύραμβον οἴνωι
συγκεραυνωθεὶς φρένας… (I know how to begin a beautiful dithyramb song for Lord Dionysus
when my mind is blitzed with wine... fr. 120 West). Cf. Call. fr. 544 Pf.: τοῦ […] μεθυπλῆγος φροίμιον
Ἀρχιλόχου (the winestruck mind of Archilochus).
31 Gutzwiller (1998: 179).
172
The opening word πίνωμεν (let us drink) recalls the sphragis of Asclepiades, but whereas
Asclepiades resorts to unmixed wine in desperation, looking for a remedy against his cares,
Hedylus drenches himself with wine because it inspires him. Life spent in sobriety,
according to this poet, is worthless (4). 32 He feels that his wine‐drenched poetry is something
adjectives λεπτός and μελιχρός. 34 However, unlike Callimachus, who uses them for instance
to compliment the poet Aratus on his polished poetry as the “work of sleepless nights” (AP
9.507), Hedylus presents his own epigrams as the irrational and spontaneous fruit of
uninhibited drinking, inspired by what he sees around him at the symposium. 35 Perhaps the
phrasing, suggestive of a repetitive drunken stutter (καὶ γάρ τι … καὶ γάρ τι … καί τι),
enacts this ideal on a stylistic level. Hedylus sees no contradiction in writing sweet and
refined verse and being drunk at the same time, as is confirmed by the last line of another
epigram of his, which pays a compliment to a colleague poet, a certain Socles: Ὤστε, φίλος,
καὶ γράφε καὶ μέθυε. (So, my friend, you should both write and be drunk). 36 Hedylus’
paradoxical poetic ideal, then, is the spontaneity of the wine‐drenched symposium, laid
down in polished verse.
Unlike Hedylus, Posidippus does explicitly address the opposition between irrational
conditions such as love and drink and the intellectual effort involved in the writing of verse.
This results in a number of sphragis‐poems that illustrate his view that wine should be
enjoyed in moderation, just enough to allow a bit of erotic desire to be kindled. This should
in turn be enough to allow the learned poet to write poetry about it and so combat the
32 For the interpretation of ἐς κενόν, cf. Gow and Page (1965: II, ad loc.).
33 On the unexpectedness of this claim, see Crowther (1979: 5).
34 Cf. e.g. Call. AP 9.507, on Arat. Phaen., with Gow and Page (1965: II, ad loc.), cf. Ch. 5.2. According to
the Et. M. 72.16, a certain Hedylus wrote (a commentary?) on the epigrams of Callimachus. Gow and
Page find it hard to believe this is the same man (1965: II, 289), Gutzwiller does accept it (1998: 171).
The striking use of literary terms in this epigram provides a reason to consider the possibility
seriously.
35 Cf. e.g. AP 5.199; AP 11.486; Ath. 11.473/GP VI; Ath. 8.344/GP VIII; Ath. 4.176/GP IX, and the
remarks of Gutzwiller (1998: 181): “While the epigrammatist sometimes takes a critical perspective on
those excessively indulging in the symposiastic pleasures of wine, food, and sex, the licentiousness
invited by unrestrained drinking is also used figuratively to set out the poetics governing the
collection.”
36 Ath. 11.473a/GP VI. This is the way in which most editors print the last line; the MS reading is: ὥστε
φίλει καὶ γράφε καὶ μέθυε. (So, make love, write and drink). At any rate, the idea that writing and
drinking can be combined remains unaffected.
173
disease he has allowed to assail him. 37 The following epigram possibly opened a collection of
Posidippus’ symposiastic epigrams:
Κεκροπί, ῥαῖνε, λάγυνε, πολύδροσον ἰκμάδα Βάκχου,
ῥαῖνε, δροσιζέσθω συμβολικὴ πρόποσις.
σιγάσθω Ζήνων ὁ σοφὸς κύκνος ἅ τε Κλεάνθους
μοῦσα∙ μέλοι δ’ ἡμῖν ὁ γλυκύπικρος Ἔρως. (AP 5.134)
Sprinkle, Cecropian jug, the dewy moisture of Bacchus, sprinkle it. Let the toast that I
contribute be bedewed. Let us be silent about Zeno, the wise swan, and the Muse of
Cleanthes, and let bittersweet Eros be our topic.
A toast to Eros, whom the toaster calls “bittersweet,” is proposed. Posidippus is aware that
the god of love may be unpleasant, yet, apparently seduced by wine and the sweetness that
may also be found in Eros, he wishes to sing of him. By using Sappho‘s expression, he
moreover implies that love is a venerable theme that has inspired great lyric poetry in the
past. The topic of Eros is introduced in opposition to the more solemn themes that belonging
to the wise swan Zeno and the Muse of Cleanthes, references to two eminent contemporary
philosophers and successive heads of the Stoic school in Athens. 38
Aslepiades’ desperate call for unmixed wine and Hedylus’ wish to be drenched with
gallons of Chian wine (κατάβρεχε, 3) find a restrained echo in the wish of a slight sprinkling
of wine‐dew in Posidippus’ sphragis (ῥαῖνε, δροσιζέσθω, 1‐2). This expression in fact alludes
to the idea that cicadas (symbols of poets and song) were traditionally believed to feed on
dew: so the symposiastic poet should feed on wine‐dew in order to sing. 39 The cicada as a
metaphor for the poet returns in another epigram, where it is subjected to the tortures of
love:
37 On the recurrent triangle love, drink and the learned poet in Hellenistic poetry, see Fantuzzi and
Hunter (2004: 342‐343).
38 Zeno did presumably not write poetry, but Cleanthes certainly did, e.g. the Hymn to Zeus, fr. 1
Powell. The adjective “Cecropian” presumably means that Athenian wine is drunk, or that the
symposium is imagined as taking place in Athens. Despite this fact (in the Hellenistic era, Athens was
of course more famous for philosophical schools than for anything else) the topic of this “Attic”
symposium is not to be philosophy, but love, a more Platonic subject (cf. Pl. Symp.). Gutzwiller (1998:
159): “Posidippus’ point here seems to be that wine is the proper accompaniment for song about Eros,
which he prefers to the more serious topics found in the philosophical writings of the stoics.” Of
course one of the main teachings of the Stoic philosophers was that to reach peace of mind, one had to
disregard passions (love, fear, anger and sadness) as much as possible.
39 Cf. Pl. Phaedr. 259c5‐259d8: cicadas had originally been human beings who got so caught up in their
song they forgot to eat and drink. The Muse decided to change them into the immortal insects freed of
bodily desire that live on dew. Call. Aet. fr. 1 Pf. also voices the poet’s wish to become a dew‐fed
cicada.
174
Τὸν Μουσῶν τέττιγα Πόθος δήσας ἐπ’ ἀκάνθαις
κοιμίζειν ἐθέλει πῦρ ὑπὸ πλευρὰ βαλών∙
ἡ δὲ πρὶν ἐν βύβλοις πεπονημένη ἄλλ’ ἀθερίζει
ψυχὴ ἀνιηρῷ δαίμονι μεμφομένη. (AP 12.98)
The meaning of the poem is ambiguous. The text could be read as expressing the claim that
the learned man is immune to love (cf. Gow and Page 1965: II, ad loc). 40 An acceptable
translation would then be:
Desire, having bound the Muses’ cicada upon a bed of thorns, wants to silence him
by kindling a fire under his flanks; but the soul that was previously trained in books,
does not care about other things, and scolds the obnoxious god.
To paraphrase: reading has steeled the soul of the learned man (3). 41 He scolds the obnoxious
god Pothos (Desire, 4) and does not care about anything but his reading.
Another reading separates the words in line 3 differently: ἄλλα θερίζει (he reaps a
different harvest), which results in the interpretation that the soul of the man who previously
labored in intellectual endeavors now sees itself forced to “reap a different harvest
altogether” (viz. that of love poetry, in which complaints are uttered against “bittersweet
love”). 42 Based on the Greek scriptio continua of the manuscripts (αλλαθεριζει), both
divisions are equally possible, and my tentative suggestion is that the ambiguity is
intentional. This would mean that the interpretation of the epigram is left to the inclination
could both escape the pains of love and give in to them: through love poetry.
6.4 The Seal or Testament of Posidippus
The so‐called “Seal of Posidippus” (SH 705/AB 118) is best treated separately, since it does
not appear to share any connection with the epigrammatic collections of Posidippus,
Asclepiades and Hedylus as discussed in the previous section. 43 This sphragis‐elegy may
40 This reading partly depends on taking δὲ as strongly adversative, cf. Denniston (1981 [1954]: 155).
41 One may wonder what kind of literature this refers to: philosophical (e.g. stoic) writings? Or
perhaps the idea is that through reading enough love‐poetry one becomes immune to love itself?
42 So e.g. Gutzwiller (1998: 160, n. 91). For the (implication of) a metaphor equating harvest with
poetry, cf. e.g. Theoc. Id. 7.155‐157.
43 For a history of the finding, publication and ascription of the poem, see Lloyd‐Jones (1963: 75‐77)
and the annotation in SH. Posidippus’ authorship had already been suggested by Trypanis (1952: 67‐8)
on the basis of an inscription at Delphi (dated 263 BCE), and another at Thermos fitting the details of
175
have headed or closed a collection of poetry by Posidippus that stands apart from his
symposiastic epigrams. 44
Regarding this poem, Gow and Page have stated that it does “not enhance
[Posidippus’] reputation… nor tell us much about him” (1965: II, 482). Although the reader
might be inclined to agree on the first point, the second calls for closer scrutiny. In the
following I will therefore follow in the footsteps of Lloyd‐Jones and undertake a close
reading that investigates the poem as a sphragis. The text is corrupt and often highly
problematic in many places; I will only touch upon the points that are relevant to my
argument.
εἴ τι καλόν, Μοῦσαι πολιήτιδες, ἢ παρὰ Φοίβου
χρυσολύρεω καθαροῖς οὔασιν ἐκλ[ύ]ετε
Παρνησοῦ νιφόεντος ἀνὰ πτύχ[α]ς ἢ παρ’ Ὀλύμπωι
Βάκχωι τὰς τριετεῖς ἀρχόμεναι θυμέλα[ς,]
νῦν δὲ Ποσε[ι]δίππωι στυγερὸν συναείσατε γῆρας (5)
γραψάμεναι δέλτων ἐν χρυσέαις σελίσιν.
λιμπάνετε σκοπιὰς Ἑλικωνίδας, εἰς δὲ τὰ Θήβης
τείχεα Πιπ[λ]ε̣ί̣ης βαίνετε, Κασταλίδες.
καὶ σὺ Ποσείδιππόν ποτ’ ἐφίλαο, Κύνθιε, Λητοῦς
υἵ’ ἑ̣κ̣ά̣ε[ργ]ε̣, β̣έ̣λ̣ο̣ς̣ (vacat) (10)
[..].[......]..ρ̣α̣ν̣[.]ν̣ω̣.............
τοῦ Παρίου φήμη τις νιφόεντ’ οἰκία.
τοίην ἐκχρήσαις τε καὶ ἐξ ἀδύτων καναχήσαι[ς]
φωνὴν ἀθανάτην, ὦ ἄνα, καὶ κατ’ ἐμοῦ,
ὄφρα με τιμήσωσι Μακηδόνες, οἵ τ’ ἐπὶ ν̣[ήσων] (15)
οἵ τ’ Ἀσίης πάσης γείτονες ἠϊόνος.
the poem, cf. AB test. 2 and 3. The texts read (2): Δελφοὶ ἔδωκαν ... Ποσειδίππωι ... Ασκληπιάδηι ...
αὐτοῖς καὶ ἐκγό[νοις προ] | ξενίαν. (The Delphians have given Posidippus and Asclepiades, them
personally and their descendants the right of proxeny; (3): αὐτοῖς καὶ ἐκγόνο[ις] το[ῖ]σδε
... ̣Π̣ο[̣ σ]ε̣ι̣δ̣ί̣π̣πωι τῶι ἐπιγραμματοποιῶι Πελλαίωι | ἔνγ̣υ̣ο̣ς̣ Κ̣(λ)ε̣οκράτης Ἡρακλεώτας.
44 Lloyd‐Jones defends an opening position (1963: 96), Barigazzi a closing one (1968: 195). Gutzwiller
keeps both possibilities open (1998: 152). Candidates for such collections are the so‐called Σωρός (i.e.,
in this case understood as a collection that only comprised Posidippus’ poetry), and the “epigrammata”
mentioned in the scholia A ad Il. 11.101, Lloyd‐Jones (1963: 96‐7), Gutzwiller (1998: 152). Lloyd‐Jones
moreover suggests that the poem constituted the opening to a collection of poetry concerning old age,
for which he suggest the title Γῆρας, cf. AB 118, 5. In the absence of attestations for such a collection,
this remains speculative. Gow and Page (1965: II, 484) list testimonies indicating that Posidippus also
wrote longer elegiac poetry. Recently the so‐called Milan Posidippus (P. Mil. Vogl. VIII 309, ed.
Galazzi, Austin and Bastianini; 2001 editio maior, 2002 editio minor) has aroused great interest. Its
attribution is based on the overlap of two poems formerly ascribed to Posidippus by Tzetzes and APl.,
viz. AB 15 and AB 65. Regrettably, the papyrus is not marked by any kind of sphragis. For the
controversy surrounding its authorship, see e.g. Gutzwiller (ed. 2005), esp. Johnson (2005: 70‐81) and
Krevans (2005: 81‐97). The debate is far from a conclusion (cf. Klooster 2007: 297‐301).
176
Πελλαῖον γένος ἀμόν∙ ἔοιμι δὲ βίβλον ἑλίσσων
†ἄμφω† λαοφόρωι κείμενος εἰν ἀγορῆι.
ἀλλ’ ἐπὶ μὲν Παρίηι ἀηδόνι λυγρὸν ἐφ[...]
νῆμα κατὰ γληνέων δάκρυα κε̣ι̣ν̣ὰ̣ χ̣έ̣ω̣[ν] (20)
καὶ στενάχων, δι’ ἐμὸν δὲ φίλον στόμα
α̣σ̣τ[̣ ...]..............
[..]...........
μηδέ τις οὖν χεύαι δάκρυον∙ αὐτὰρ ἐγὼ
γήραϊ μυστικὸν οἶμον ἐπὶ Ῥαδάμανθυν ἱκοίμην (25)
δήμωι καὶ λαῶι παντὶ ποθεινὸς ἐών,
ἀσκίπων ἐν ποσσὶ καὶ ὀρθοεπὴς ἀν’ ὅμιλον
καὶ λείπων τέκνοις δῶμα καὶ ὄλβον ἐμόν. (SH 705/AB 118)
If, Muses of my city, you have with pure ears heard anything beautiful, either from
Phoebus of the golden lyre, in the glens of snowy Parnassus, or near Olympus, as you
start for Bacchus his triennial ceremonies, now help Posidippus to sing of his hateful
old age, writing down the song on the golden columns of your tablets. Leave your
Heliconian peaks, and come to the walls of Piplean Thebes, Muses of Castalia. You
also loved Posidippus once, Cynthian god, of Leto the far‐shooting son … a dart … …
… an oracle to the snow‐white house of the man from Paros. May you send forth and
sound out from your holy shrine such an immortal voice, O Lord, even for me, so that
the Macedonians may honor me, both the islanders and the neighbors of all the
Asiatic shore. Pellaean is my family. May I find myself unrolling a book standing (all
at once?) in the crowded market‐place. For the Parian nightingale (grant?) … a
mournful thread, with (empty?) tears streaming down the eyelids, and groaning,
while through my own mouth ……… and let no one shed a tear. But for my part,
may I travel in old age the mystic path to Rhadamanthys, longed for by my people
and all the community, on my feet without a stick, sure of speech among the crowd,
and leaving to my children my house and my wealth. (transl. Austin, adapted) 45
The poem is addressed to the Muses and Apollo. The poet asks the Muses to help him sing of
his “hateful old age.” 46 Some lines later, they are invited to help him inscribe his song on
golden tablets; this presumably means it is supposed to become immortal 47 . At the moment
45 Some notes on the text and translation: in 5, AB read συναείρατε (help bear the burden). I prefer the
perfectly understandable original (συναείσατε), cf. Theoc. Id. 10.24. In 18, I fail to understand the
reason for the proposed ἄφνω; the original reads ἀμφω, which is however difficult as well. I prefer to
print daggers. In 20, I doubt the reading κε̣ι̣ν̣ὰ̣ “empty.” Regrettably, I was not able to see the original
tablet.
46 Cf. the sentiment voiced in Call. fr. 1.37‐8 Pf.: Μοῦσαι γὰρ ὅσους ἴδον ὄθματι παῖδας / μὴ λοξῷ,
πολιοὺς οὐκ ἀπέθεντο φίλους. (For upon who the Muses in childhood looked with no unfriendly
gaze, they won’t neglect them when they are grey).
47 Although it might also contain a reference to the Orphic practice of dedicating golden lamellae to
the gods of the underworld, cf. below for the Orphic connection.
177
of voicing this request the poet seems to be located at (“Pi(m)pleian) Thebes,” 48 for this is
where he asks the Muses to come to. Perhaps this geographical reference means to evoke
Orpheus (who was born in the vicinity) as a poetic model for Posidippus. The fact that
Posidippus claims (cf. 25) to be initiated in the mystic rites that allow men to pass into the
realm of the blessed after death might then furnish an additional link with Orpheus, who is
often connected with such rites. 49
Besides this indirect reference to Orpheus, there is another poet of the past who plays
an important role in the elegy, Archilochus. The god Apollo is asked to grant Posidippus an
oracle similar to the one he gave for the “man from Paros,” (τοῦ Παρίου 12, cf. 19 Παρίηι
ἀηδόνι). 50 It seems likely that the oracle referred to is the one Apollo gave to Archilochus’
father, saying his son would be “immortal and renowned in song among men.” 51 Posidippus
apparently feels his poetry ought to earn him honors similar to those Archilochus received
from the god.
It is clear that recognition of his poetic abilities is high on Posidippus’ agenda: he
wishes to be honored by all Macedonians and all inhabitants of the Asian shore. The
geographic precision of this wish may partly be explained by the fact that Posidippus
himself is of Macedonian stock, but it is even more relevant that practically all of the ruling
Hellenistic dynasties, in particular the Ptolemaic house, were. The Ptolemies moreover
dominated the eastern Mediterranean, that is to say, “the Asian shore.” Posidippus is
implying, therefore, that he confidently regards the social and cultural elite of the Greek‐
48 “Pi (m)pleian” may also be an epithet of the Muses rather than of Thebes; for the difficulty of
deciding on the spelling, see Lloyd–Jones (1963 ad loc.). He sees no way to interpret the adjective. Bing
(1988: 38) proposes that Pi(m)pleian Thebes may be understood as referring to a kind of literary
reality; it is anywhere Posidippus wishes it to be, if he only describes it on his tablets.
49 Pi(m)pleia is where Orpheus was borne by Calliope according to A.R. Arg. 1.25; it is near Pieria, the
traditional haunt of the Muses, cf. Rossi (1996: 63).
50 On the various oracles pertaining to Archilochus, see Gerber (1999, test. 3; 12‐18), Clay (2004: 9‐25).
Lloyd‐Jones thinks the oracle referred to is the third cent. BCE oracle of Mnesiepes, concerning the re‐
installing of the cult of Archilochus at Paros and the building of a sanctuary named the Archilocheion,
cf. SEG 15 (1958), 517. However, there appear to be no ancient references to this oracle. It may have
been of very local significance. Moreover, the wish for cultic honors is unparalleled in surviving
Hellenistic poetry. However, for the possibility that the older contemporary of Posidippus, Philitas,
was given such honors, see Hollis (1996: 56‐62).
51 “Ἀθάνατός σοι παῖς καὶ ἀοἱδιμος, ὦ Τελεσίκλεις, ἔσται ἐν ἀνθρώποισιν…” (Your son, Telesicles,
will be immortal and subject of song among men...). Cf. Gerber (1999: test. 3; 18). The other famous
oracle was pronounced to the killer of Archilochus: “You killed the servant of the Muses, depart from
the temple,” cf. test. 12‐18. In the present context, the former oracle seems more meaningful.
178
speaking world ruled by the Ptolemies as his primary audience. 52 This recognition on a
human scale (instigated by the wished‐for Delphic oracle?) should find its material
expression in an honorary statue, (cf. lines 17‐18, to the effect that Posidippus may “find
himself standing in the agora handling a scroll,” to celebrate his poetic achievements). 53
The following lines, owing to their fragmentary survival, cause serious
interpretational problems. A contrast seems to have been created between the tears that are
shed for the “Parian nightingale” Archilochus (19‐20) and the death of Posidippus, which he
apparently hopes will go unlamented (24). Lloyd‐Jones conjectures that this difference in
lamentation could be explained with reference to the fact that Archilochus died an early
death in battle 54 and wrote “bitter” (iambic) poetry, whereas Posidippus lived until old age
(25) and wrote poetry of a more pleasant character. 55 This wish thus serves to illustrate the
difference between Posidippus and Archilochus’ characters while underlining the fact that,
even though very different, Posidippus is as great a poet as Archilochus, although, as we
shall see, the fact that Posidippus wishes his death to remain unlamented is certainly also
connected to the fact that he is an initiate in some kind of mystic (possibly Orphic) rites.
The poem contains two kinds of wishes pertaining to Posidippus’ death and beyond.
As poet, he asks for divinely decreed honors similar to those of Archilochus and for a statue
in the agora, divine as well as human recognition for his poetic endeavors. Besides,
Posidippus also augured himself immortality of a different kind altogether through his
mystic initiation (25), which should ensure a life beyond death among the blessed in the
realm of Rhadamanthys for him. 56 As initiate of the mysteries, he asks for a healthy old age
52 On Posidippus’ connections with the Ptolemaic court, see Kosmetatou (2004: 225‐246), Stephens
(2005: 229‐248), Fantuzzi (2005: 249‐ 268), Thompson (2005: 269‐286).
53 See Lloyd‐Jones (1963: ad loc.) and Gutzwiller (1998: 152). Cf. the bronze statue of Philitas (Pos. AB
63), and the series of epigrams on the statues of the dead poets by Theocritus, discussed in Ch. 1. The
statue of a seated man holding a scroll in the Vatican collection (inv. no. 735) with the inscription
ΠΟΣΕΙΔΙΠΠΟΣ is believed by Dickie (1994: 373‐383) to portray the epigrammatist; others think it
depicts the homonymous contemporary comic poet.
54 On the (too) early death of Archilochus, and Apollo’s anger at the man who killed him, cf. Gerber
(1999: test. 12‐18).
55 Rossi (1996: 64) argues that ὀρθοεπής refers to the moral rightness of Posidippus’ poetry.
56 Cf. AB test. 1, a golden lamella (fourth cent. BCE from Pella) inscribed: Φερσεφόνηι | Ποσείδιππος
μύστης | εὐσεβής (To Persephone, from the pious initiate Posidippus). Considering its date, this may
refer to the grandfather of the present Posidippus, cf. Dickie (1995: 81‐86), (1996: 59‐65). Even so,
hereditary initiation in the family of Posidippus is possible. For the hereditary nature of proper
names, cf. Call. AP 7.525. The initiation is clearly of a religious kind; to read into the expression a
179
and for an unlamented death that may bring him among the righteous to the realm of
Rhadamanthys, longed for by his people. 57 Interestingly, it would seem that these wishes are
not so much expressed for the benefit of future readers, but rather aimed at impressing his
contemporaries.
Returning to the verdict of Gow and Page, I think that this elegy does in fact tell
much about Posidippus, his aspirations, and the way he saw himself. He confidently
presented himself to his contemporary readers as a successful poet beloved by the
Macedonians. Helpfully, he reminds them that he should be immortalized in statuary, since
in his own esteem he deserves universal fame on an equal footing with Archilochus. He
moreover claims to be immortal both because of his poetry and his initiation into the mystic
rites of Rhadamanthys. It is hard to find another sphragis as self‐satisfied in tone.
6.5 Leonidas: Dignified Poverty
Very different from Posidippus’ smug self‐congratulations are Leonidas’ sphragis‐epigrams.
Next to his great output of poems on humble lower‐class people and their toils, this
epigrammatist also wrote (epitaph‐) epigrams on Anacreon (2), Homer, Hipponax, Tellen,
Alcman and his contemporary Aratus, as we saw in Chapter 1 and 5. He was clearly aware,
then, of the lasting reputation poetry could procure its author. This awareness also finds
expression in the epitaph he wrote for himself.
Πολλὸν ἀπ’ Ἰταλίης κεῖμαι χθονὸς ἔκ τε Τάραντος
πάτρης∙ τοῦτο δέ μοι πικρότερον θανάτου.
τοιοῦτος πλανίων ἄβιος βίος∙ ἀλλά με Μοῦσαι
ἔστερξαν, λυγρῶν δ’ ἀντὶ μελιχρὸν ἔχω.
οὔνομα δ’ οὐκ ἤμυσε Λεωνίδου∙ αὐτά με δῶρα
κηρύσσει Μουσέων πάντας ἐπ’ ἠελίους. (AP 7.715) 58
I lie, far from the earth of Italy, and outside Tarentum, my fatherland; this fact is
bitterer than death to me. Such a life of wandering is no life—still, the Muses loved
meta‐poetical metaphor (Posidippus as initiate of the Muses vel sim., cf. Lloyd–Jones) is less attractive,
cf. Rossi (1996: 65).
57 Perhaps this is an allusion to Archil. fr. 133 West: οὔτις αἰδοῖος μετ’ ἀστῶν οὐδὲ περίφημος θανὼν
/ γίνεται∙ χάριν δὲ μᾶλλον τοῦ ζοοῦ διώκομεν <οἱ> ζοοί, κάκιστα δ’ αἰεὶ τῶι θανόντι γίνεται. (For
no‐one is respected or famous among his citizens after his death; we rather pursue the favour of the
living while we live; the dead are always treated in the worst way).
58 Gow and Page express doubts in attributing this epigram to Leonidas of Tarentum (1965: II, 391),
but it seems a reasonably safe bet to do so.
180
me, and I have sweetness in return for suffering. The name of Leonidas has not
perished: those selfsame gifts of the Muses proclaim me for all time.
Leonidas’ epigram takes the form of words spoken by him from the grave. The absence from
his fatherland (emphatically in enjambment), a result of his unhappy wandering life, is
worse to him than death. 59 Yet, both death and its concomitant oblivion and the distance
from his fatherland are remedied to some extent by the sweetness (once more, as in
Callimachus’ and Hedylus’ poetry the adjective μελιχρόν is used) of his poetry (5). It is
attractive to connect the expression in 3‐4 with Od. 8.63‐4, the description of Demodocus:
τὸν περὶ Μοῦσ’ ἐφίλησε, δίδου δ’ ἀγαθόν τε κακόν τε∙
ὀφθαλμῶν μὲν ἄμερσε, δίδου δ’ ἡδεῖαν ἀοιδήν. (Od. 8.63‐4)
For him the Muse loved exceedingly, and she gave him good and evil; she
robbed him of his eyes, but gave him sweet song.
Likewise the bitterness that accrues to Leonidas’ life of wandering poet is sweetened by his
talent. The implication may even be that his suffering somehow guarantees his talent, as in
Demodocus’ case. Leonidas moreover appears to hope that his roaming existence on earth
will be echoed by the roaming fame of his poems after his death; poetry making sweet in
death at last what was bitter in life (4). This poem itself, which found dispersion in book
form rather than being inscribed upon Leonidas’ tomb, is a pre‐emptive fulfillment of his
wishes. 60
As noted, the difference in tone with Posidippus’ sphragis is striking. The melancholy,
querulous tenor of the epigram, lamenting the bitterness of life on this earth, is typical of the
surviving poetry of Leonidas, who often wrote about wandering, hardship, and death,
especially of the poor, a social stratum to which he apparently felt affiliated. 61 In particular,
the epigram discussed seems connected with two other epigrams that contain the name
Leonidas and describe his poverty.
Λαθρίη, ἐκ πλάνιος ταύτην χάριν ἔκ τε πενέστεω
κἠξ ὀλιγησιπύου δέξο Λεωνίδεω,
59 On the hardships of wandering, cf. Leon. AP 7.736, which is often related to the present epigram. It
is unclear whether Leonidas was exiled or driven to a wandering life by his poverty, cf. AP 6.300 and
6.302.
60 Wilamowitz (1924: I, 140), Gabathuler (1937: 67‐8) and Gutzwiller (1998: 108) assume this epigram
closed a poetry book.
61 Cf. e.g. AP 7.726, AP 7.731, AP 7.736, AP 7.740, AP 7.472, AP 7.655. Gutzwiller (1998: 91) regards the
epigrams as “heavily influenced by Cynic tenets.”
181
ψαιστά τε πιήεντα καὶ εὐθήσαυρον ἐλαίην
καὶ τοῦτο χλωρὸν σῦκον ἀποκράδιον
κεὐοίνου σταφυλῆς ἔχ’ ἀποσπάδα πεντάρρωγον,
πότνια, καὶ σπονδὴν τήνδ’ ὑποπυθμίδιον.
ἢν δέ μ’ ἔθ’, ὡς ἐκ νούσου ἀνειρύσω, ὧδε καὶ ἐχθρῆς
ἐκ πενίης ῥύσῃ, δέξο χιμαιροθύτην. (AP 6.300)
Lathria, accept this gift from a wanderer, a peasant, from Leonidas who has few
resources. Take some rich cakes, olive oil saved for the purpose, this fresh fig just cut
from the branch, five grapes pulled from a tasty bunch, mistress, and this libation
poured from the bottom of the jar. And as you saved me from disease, so if you save
me from hateful poverty, you’ll have a goat as sacrifice. (transl. Gutzwiller)
Φεύγεθ’ ὑπὲκ καλύβης, σκότιοι μύες∙ οὔτι πενιχρὴ
μῦς σιπύη βόσκειν οἶδε Λεωνίδεω.
αὐτάρκης ὁ πρέσβυς ἔχειν ἅλα καὶ δύο κρῖμνα∙
ἐκ πατέρων ταύτην ᾐνέσαμεν βιοτήν.
τῷ τί μεταλλεύεις τοῦτον μυχόν, ὦ φιλόλιχνε,
οὐδ’ ἀποδειπνιδίου γευόμενος σκυβάλου;
σπεύδων εἰς ἄλλους οἴκους ἴθι (τἀμὰ δὲ λειτά),
ὧν ἄπο πλειοτέρην οἴσεαι ἁρμαλιήν. (AP 6.302)
Flee from my hut, furtive rodents; Leonidas’ poor canister cannot support mice. The
old man can survive on salt and a couple of crumbs; from my fathers I learned to like
this style of living. So why do you burrow into this hovel, nibblers, since you won’t
find a taste of any leftovers? Go run to some other house–my resources are few—
where you’ll get better rations. (transl. Gutzwiller)
That the first epigram (AP 6.300) is a votive offering asking for (public) success of this
collection of poetry seems suggested by Leonidas’ humble wish that the (enigmatic) goddess
Lathria 62 will save him from poverty. The simplicity of rustic offerings to the goddess could
be read as symbolic of Leonidas’ epigrams, representatives of a small and unassuming genre
in which he focuses on the humble existence of common people. 63 They are choice and
flavorsome items, albeit not sumptuous and rich; the complex and polished compounds
rhetorically heighten their value.
In AP 6.302, Leonidas even claims he is so poor he cannot support the mice invading
his hovel. All the same, he seems proud of his simple way of life (3‐4). The exhortation to the
62 Gutzwiller understands her to be Aphrodite, comparing epigrams by Gaetulicus (AP 6.190), and
Cornelius Longus (AP 6.191). Cazzaniga (1967: 63‐74) thinks the epithet refers to Artemis. If
Gutzwiller is correct, the disease referred to in 7 may be love.
63 Gutzwiller (1998: 110‐112). For the symbolism of offerings from a humble household store signifying
poetry, cf. Theoc. Id. 22.221‐223.
182
mice to find a place “where they’ll find better rations” may be a disguised message to critics:
Leonidas’ poetry is so unassuming it should escape being attacked by them. 64 Mice, crumbs
and a wandering life of hardship: Leonidas is clearly worlds apart from his pompous and
successful contemporary Posidippus.
6.6 Nossis: Positioning a Woman’s Poetic Perspective
A rare instance of sphragis epigrams by a female poet is provided by Nossis. Her elusive
identity and her almost exclusive interest in women have led to divergent theories about her
life, poetry, and conditions. 65 Eight of her eleven surviving poems describe dedications, 66
seven of them by women, the majority probably to Aphrodite. 67 Basing themselves on this
fact, some have posited that Nossis either was a hetaera (courtesan), 68 or, on the contrary, a
lady of aristocratic Locrian descent. 69 Current scholarship rather reads Nossis’ choice of
poetic themes, especially her interest in women, as an expression of female homosexuality
that was most famously exemplified in antiquity by Sappho, and thence as a sign of poetical
affiliation to this poetess. 70 Indeed, Nossis frequently refers both explicitly and implicitly to
her.
A well‐known problem is formed by the fact that Nossis is explicitly associated with
erotic poetry both by others (Meleager and Herondas) and by herself (AP 5.170), 71 whereas
64 Hopkinson (1988: ad loc.) notes that mice also appear in the hut of Molorchus (Call. fr. 59 Pf.).
Callimachus’ Hecale too lives in a rustic hut. Perhaps on a meta‐poetic level the humble, poor life
stands for λεπτότης.
65 Her floruit probably falls in the 280s or 270s BCE. She names Epizephyrian Locri in Southern Italy
(Magna Graecia) as her home. Her dates can be determined by taking into account her epitaph of
Rhinthon of Syracuse (AP 7.414), whom the Suda dates in the reign of Ptolemy Soter (who died in 283‐
2) and the reference to a Nossis in the poetry of Herondas (who belongs to the second quarter of the
third century).
66 There is one other epigram, which the ancient copyist already doubts, viz. AP 6.273.
67 See Gutzwiller (1998: 81).
68 Reitzenstein (1893: 142).
69 Polybius states that the hereditary aristocracy of Locri went by matrilineal descent (12.5.6). The fact
that Nossis concentrates mainly on women, combined with her emphasis on matrilineal descent (AP
6.252; 6.253; 6.265) fits with this statement. In addition, “Nossis” may have been an aristocratic name,
cf. Cazzaniga (1972: 173‐6).
70 Skinner (1989: 5‐18), Gutzwiller (1998: 74‐84). Gow and Page (1965: II, 434) moreover think Nossis
may have composed lyric poetry as well, like Sappho. This is suggested by the epithet μελοποιός
(AP).
71 Nossis states that nothing is sweeter than love (AP 5.170) and compliments a hetaera (AP 9.332).
Meleager described Nossis’ poetry as follows: μυρόπνουν εὐάνθεμον ἶριν / Νοσσίδος, ἧς δέλτοις
183
most of her extant epigrams are not explicitly concerned with love or sexuality. 72 This
other words, Nossis’ poetry may originally have even been more like Sappho’s.
Like her male colleagues, Nossis is clearly aware of literary tradition and the roles
that originality, emulation of literary models and fame play in it, as her references to earlier
poets and anticipation of becoming a precursor herself demonstrate. 74 The following
epigram, which looks simple and self‐contained, holds numerous intertextual allusions that
carefully position Nossis’ poetry in the Greek poetic tradition. It is usually considered the
sphragis of a collection: 75
Ἅδιον οὐδὲν ἔρωτος∙ ἃ δ’ ὄλβια δεύτερα πάντα
ἐστίν∙ ἀπὸ στόματος δ’ ἔπτυσα καὶ τὸ μέλι.
τοῦτο λέγει Νοσσίς∙ τίνα δ’ ἁ Κύπρις οὐκ ἐφίλησεν,
οὐκ οἶδεν †κήνα τ’†, ἄνθεα ποῖα ῥόδα. (AP 5.170) 76
Nothing is sweeter than love; all blessings are inferior to it. I even spat honey from
my mouth. This is what Nossis says; and whom the Cyprian has not kissed, she does
not know what sort of flowers roses are.
The first phrase, Ἅδιον οὐδὲν ἔρωτος, may be read as a reference to the sphragis of Nossis’
elder contemporary Asclepiades (AP 5.169, discussed above), presumably the first poet to
κηρὸν ἔτηξεν Ἔρως. (The myrrh‐breathing blossoming iris of Nossis, on whose tablets Eros himself
melted the wax, AP 4.1.9‐10). Herond. Mim. 6.20‐36 and 7.57‐8, name a Nossis (the poetess?) and an
Erinna (the other poetess?) as women interested in a βαυβών (dildo). Perhaps this is to ridicule their
(alleged or self‐professed) homosexuality?
72 The exception is AP 9.332,4 where there is a reference to a hetaera, who is praised for making a
golden dedication to Aphrodite, paid for by the money she has earned with her body. See also below
on AP 5.170, 4.
73 Gutzwiller (1998: 80) states that this perceived contradiction (i.e., ancient references to Nossis’ erotic
poetry, while her epigrams are not particularly erotic in tone) is based on the modern
“misunderstanding of female eroticism… [which in Nossis’ case arises] merely from the casting of her
gaze upon women as they go about the business of their private lives.” But see my remarks below on
AP 5.170, 4.
74 In an epitaph on the poet of tragic burlesques Rhinton of Syracuse (AP 7.414), Nossis also addresses
the question of fame for a poetic achievement. Gutzwiller (1998: 85) suggests: “The Rhinton epitaph
may have served to suggest that Nossis’ own poetry, though slight, was nonetheless innovative and
worthy of praise [emphasis added].”
75 Cf. Luck (1954: 170‐187).
76 A note on the text and translation: in the last line, the original reading κηνατ is hard to understand.
Stadtmüller reads τηνᾶς (fem. sing. gen.) referring to either Aphrodite (“she does not know what kind
of flowers Aphrodite’s roses are”) or to Nossis (“she does not know what kind of flowers Nossis’ roses
are”). It is probably best to suppose that κήνα equals ἐκείνη and refers back to τίνα δ’ ἁ Κύπρις οὐκ
ἐφίλησεν, in which case the solution κήνα γ’ (Reitzenstein) gives the best sense: “she does not know
what sort of flowers roses are.”
184
compose collections of erotic epigrams. 77 Asclepiades’ epigram names several pleasant
things, only to emphasize a greater pleasure: love. Nossis reduces his priamel to a short and
apodictic claim “nothing is sweeter than love,” contrasting the sweetness of love with all that
may metaphorically be considered sweet (ὄλβια, with a clear undertone of material
possessions, cf. LSJ s.v. I, Od.17.420), and with something literally sweet, honey (2). 78 By
agreeing with Asclepiades, she represents herself as adhering to his poetics. The fact
however that her assertion is made so confidently in her own name (3) also conjures up
echoes of the famous priamel in Sappho fr. 16. Sappho contrasts the opinions of οί μὲν ... οί
δὲ ... (some ... others) about what is beautiful (armies, fleet) with her own creed (emphatically
ἔγω δὲ, but I) that the most beautiful thing on this earth is “that which one desires” (fr. 16.1‐4
Voigt). 79
Another reference to Sappho may be discerned in the last phrase οὐκ οἶδεν † κήνα
τ’†, ἄνθεα ποῖα ῥόδα. In the first place, these words would seem to signify that whoever has
not tasted love knows not its delights; nor its pains, for of course, roses have thorns. Yet, this
complex metaphor would also appear to allude to the following Sapphic fragment:
κατθάνοισα δὲ κείσηι οὐδέ ποτα μναμοσύνα σέθεν
ἔσσετ’ οὐδὲ †ποκ’† ὔστερον∙ οὐ γὰρ πεδέχηις βρόδων
τὼν ἐκ Πιερίας∙ ἀλλ’ ἀφάνης κἀν Ἀίδα δόμωι
φοιτάσηις πεδ’ ἀμαύρων νεκύων ἐκπεποταμένα. (fr. 55 Voigt)
And you will lie dead, and there will be never be any remembrance of you in times to
come, for you do not partake of the roses from Pieria; no, in the house of Hades too
will you flit around unseen, amidst the shadows of the dead.
The fate of being completely erased from human memory is here prophesied to a woman
who does not “partake of the roses from Pieria” (i.e., who has no connection with the Pierian
Muses and their arts). Remembrance lives on exclusively in song; song provides subject and
singer with immortality. So when Nossis says, “whom the Cyprian has not kissed, she does
77 Cf. Gutzwiller (1998: 77).
78 The copyist of the AP already understood epigram 5.170 to contain an allusion to Asclepiades
(5.169), as witness the fact that he juxtaposed the two poems.
79 Fr. 16 Voigt: ο]ἰ μὲν ἰππήων στρότον οἰ δὲ πέσδων / οἰ δὲ νάων φαῖσ’ ἐπ[ὶ] γᾶν μέλαι[ν]αν /
ἔ]μμεναι κάλλιστον, ἔγω δὲ κῆν’ ὄττω τις ἔραται. (Some say that a parade of cavalry, some of foot
soldiers, others of ships, is the most beautiful thing on earth, but I say: it is that which one longs for).
Luck (1969: 102), Skinner (1989: 7‐11), (1991: 33‐4), Gutzwiller (1998: 76) all connect Nossis’ epigram
with Sappho’s priamel, but contrast Riedweg (1994: 141‐150).
185
not know what sort of flowers roses are,” 80 she is reacting to Sappho’s statement. She claims
that one has to taste of love in order to recognize “roses,” that is, to be able to partake
actively or passively of the Muses’ gift of erotic poetry. This interpretation is confirmed by
the fact that Meleager in his long opening poem to the Garland metaphorically calls Sappho’s
poetry “roses”: καὶ Σαπφοῦς βαιὰ μέν, ἀλλὰ ῥόδα. (And what little there is of Sappho, but
all of it roses, AP 4.1, 6). Lastly, it could be argued that the phrase contains a double entendre,
since ῥόδα could also metaphorically indicate the female pudenda (LSJ s.v. III, Pherecr.
108.29). If this should indeed be understood as the underlying pun, it sheds a somewhat
different light on the idea that Nossis does not refer to female homosexuality in her poetry at
all. 81
Nossis’ statement that she has “spat honey from her mouth” has a meta‐poetic ring to
it, considering the importance of metaphors of honey and bees referring to poetry and poets
in Greek literature. 82 Surprisingly, the phrase implies a somewhat negative attitude towards
“honey.” Nossis seems to claim that love itself is more important than the poetry concerning
it. It has attractively been suggested that Nossis rejects at least the poetry of a certain kind (of
poet). The phrase may in fact refer to the honey‐voiced poets of Hesiod Th. 96: ὁ δ’ ὄλβιος,
ὅντινα Μοῦσαι / φίλωνται∙ γλυκερή οἱ ἀπὸ στόματος ῥέει αὐδή. (Blest is he whom the
Muses love; sweetly the voice streams from his mouth). 83 Hence, it would allude to the
widespread popularity that Hesiod enjoyed as a model among such influential avant‐garde
poets as Callimachus and Aratus. 84 Nossis may be implying here that she does not position
herself in the tradition of such learned or ironic “poets’ poets”. Her poetry, by contrast, is
straight from the heart; Sappho is her model, not Hesiod. 85
80 It would seem she addresses women exclusively, if κήνα is read in 4.
81 The double entendre seems also hinted at e.g. in AP 5.81: Ἡ τὰ ῥόδα, ῥοδόεσσαν ἔχεις χάριν. ἀλλὰ τί
πωλεῖς; / σαυτὴν ἢ τὰ ῥόδα ἠὲ συναμφότερα; (You, rose‐girl, you’ve got a rosy charm, but what are
you selling? Yourself, or the roses, or both?).
82 Waszink (1974), Nünlist (1998: 60‐63).
83 Gutzwiller (1998: 76), cf. Hes. Th. 83‐4: τῷ μὲν ἐπὶ γλώσσῃ γλυκερὴν χείουσιν ἐέρσην / τοῦ δ’ ἔπε’
ἐκ στόματος ῥεῖ μείλιχα. (On his tongue the Muses drip sweet dew and his words flow sweetly from
his mouth).
84 Gutzwiller (1998: 76). For the connection Hesiod, Aratus, Callimachus, cf. Ch. 5.2.
85 Gutzwiller (1998: 76‐77) moreover suggests that Nossis refers to the poetry of Erinna, distancing
herself from it (Erinna, the maiden‐poet, who died before marriage; Nossis the woman who has tasted
love). This depends on references to Erinna in contemporary and later epigrams (7.13.1; AP 2.110; AP
7.121.1; AP 9.190) that call Erinna a bee‐like poet (a bee calls to mind honey, which Nossis, as she
phrases it, spits from her mouth). These references in the epigrams, Gutzwiller suggests, may have
186
Distinct allusions to Sappho are also found in another sphragis‐epigram, one that is
usually considered the closing poem of a collection. This repeated reference to Sappho may
in fact be an additional argument that both epigrams belong to the same collection.
Ὦ ξεῖν’, εἰ τύ γε πλεῖς ποτὶ καλλίχορον Μιτυλάναν
τᾶν Σαπφοῦς χαρίτων ἄνθος ἐναυσόμενος,
εἰπεῖν, ὡς Μούσαισι φίλαν τήνᾳ τε Λοκρὶς γᾶ
τίκτε μ’∙ ἴσαις δ´ ὅτι μοὶ τοὔνομα Νοσσίς, ἴθι. (AP 7.718)
Traveler, if you are sailing to Mitylene of the fair dancing grounds, to be inspired by
the blossom of Sappho’s charms, say that the land of Locri has borne me, dear to the
Muses and to her, and, knowing that my name is Nossis, depart. 86
The poem possesses thematic characteristics of an epitaph. The resemblance to Asclepiades
(AP 7.500), an epitaph for a man drowned at sea, who asks the passer‐by to bring to his
father the message of his death, is particularly suggestive. 87 Nossis varies this theme by
asking the passer‐by to tell of her birth on Locrian soil when arriving on Lesbos, where
Sappho, her poetic “mother,” was once born. Just as the dead man and his father
communicate through poetry over seas (of time) separating them, so do Nossis and her
predecessor Sappho. The epigram also seems to imply that, although other prospective poets
might travel to Lesbos to be inspired by Sappho (2), Nossis had no need for that. She could
write poetry in the vein of Sappho while staying at home. Such an interpretation invites a
comparison with the ending of Callimachus Iambus 13, which states that he has not felt the
need to travel to Ephesus to become skilled in the Ionic tradition of Iambic poetry of
Hipponax, as others have. 88
been due to characterization by Erinna of her own poetry as honey or to herself as a bee in her Distaff.
Although this idea has some points to recommend it, it remains hard to prove, lacking a substantial
text of the Distaff.
86 Some notes on the text and translation: I have chosen to adhere as closely as possible to the MS of
the AP. This means reading ἄνθος in 2, rather than αἶθος (Edmunds and Maas) and ἐναυσόμενος
rather than ἐπαυρομέναν (Reitzenstein) in the same line. Line 3 originally reads:
φιλατηναιτελοκρισσα. Here I accept Brunck’s emendation as given above. Line 4 reads:
τικτεμισαισδοτιμοιτουνομα, here I prefer Theiler’s emendation as given above to that of Brunck
(τίκτεν ἴσαν, ὅτι θ´ οἱ τοὔνομα).
87 Cf. Gutzwiller (1998: 86). AP 7.500: Ὦ παρ’ ἐμὸν στείχων κενὸν ἠρίον, εἶπον, ὁδῖτα, / εἰς Χίον εὖτ’
ἂν ἵκῃ, πατρὶ Μελησαγόρῃ, / ὡς ἐμὲ μὲν καὶ νῆα καὶ ἐμπορίην κακὸς Εὖρος / ὤλεσεν, Εὐίππου δ’
αὐτὸ λέλειπτ’ ὄνομα. (You, who pass by my empty grave, traveler, say to my father Melesagores, if
you visit Chios, that the evil Eastern wind wrecked my ship and my freight, and that of Euhippus just
this name is left.)
88 Fr. 203.14‐15 Pf.: ἀ̣είδω / οὔτ’ Ἔφεσον ἐλθὼν οὔτ̣’ Ἴωσι συμμείξας / Ἔφεσον, ὅθεν περ οἱ τὰ
μέτρα μέλλοντες / τὰ χωλὰ τίκτειν μὴ ἀμαθῶς ἐναύονται. (I sing, although I have not traveled to
187
In her poem, Nossis is carving out a distinct position in Greek literary tradition for
herself as a woman, by choosing a female model, Sappho. The passer‐by, who is addressed
and asked to spread the fame of Nossis’ poetic talents, should be understood as a prospective
poet of erotic poetry. Such poets 89 will name her as they travel to Lesbos to be inspired.
Nossis thus positions herself as a link in the chain of (female) love‐poets.
6.7 Callimachus: Ironic Self‐criticism
Of course Callimachus, the great master of third‐century epigram, cannot be absent from a
discussion of sphragis‐epigrams. Although the first epigram to be discussed here, like those
of Nossis employs an erotic theme to characterize his epigrammatic persona, Callimachus’
approach is more ironic and complicated. 90 As Fraser remarks, “[Callimachus] strikes … a
note of intellectual and still more emotional self‐criticism” throughout his epigrams (1972, I:
594); the following lines exquisitely illustrate this:
Ἐχθαίρω τὸ ποίημα τὸ κυκλικόν, οὐδὲ κελεύθῳ
χαίρω, τίς πολλοὺς ὧδε καὶ ὧδε φέρει∙
μισέω καὶ περίφοιτον ἐρώμενον, οὐδ’ ἀπὸ κρήνης
πίνω∙ σικχαίνω πάντα τὰ δημόσια.
Λυσανίη, σὺ δὲ ναίχι καλὸς καλός—ἀλλὰ πρὶν εἰπεῖν
τοῦτο σαφῶς, Ἠχώ φησί τις∙ “ἄλλος ἔχει.” (AP 12.43):
I hate the cyclic poem and I dislike the path that carries many hither and thither. I
also hate the roaming beloved, and I do not drink from the (common) well. All
vulgarity makes me sick. Lysanias, you are indeed fair, so fair–but before saying it
properly, some echo repeats “and some other’s affair.” 91
Since many of the themes in this poem echo meta‐poetic remarks found elsewhere in
Callimachus’ oeuvre, 92 the temptation is great to read it as another expression in this vein:
Callimachus loathes unrefined poetry and chooses to be an exclusive poet. However, the last,
erotic, couplet would not completely fit such an interpretation, and there have indeed been
Ephesus, nor mixed with the Ionians; Ephesus, whence those wishing to bring forth limping verse do
not unwisely kindle their flame).
89 Perhaps even poetesses, as Gutzwiller suggests, although the participles (2, 4) does not point
exclusively to a female addressee.
90 For two other sphragis epitaphs by Callimachus, see Ch. 7.3.
91 This may have been the opening of a section of erotic epigrams in a book, cf. Gutzwiller (1998: 218).
92 E.g. Aetia fr. 1 Pf.; Hymn II, 105‐113.
188
proposals to excise it. 93 The solution to this problem may be the recognition that the poem
takes the form of a negative priamel. 94 Callimachus does not privilege the opinion about
poetic matters he expresses first (I hate the cyclical poem) 95 over his other opinions (I hate the
well‐worn road, the roaming beloved and the common well). All these other statements
should therefore not be read as metaphors glossing the first, apparently meta‐poetic,
declaration, 96 but as exempla on the same level, leading up to the erotic conclusion. This
conclusion, if logic obtained, should be: “and you, Lysanias, are worst of all.” Yet, the
message is more complicated. First, the speaker declares his admiration for Lysanias
(Λυσανίη, σὺ δὲ ναίχι καλὸς καλός, 5), which gives the impression that Lysanias is not
vulgar. Eventually however, he realizes to his regret that Lysanias is another illustration of
his negative exempla (5‐6); he is not exclusive either, someone else “has him too.”
The persona Callimachus creates here is that of a poet who wishes to be a man of
good taste. Despite this, he suffers from a weakness for beautiful, yet regrettably vulgar
boys. The irresistible Lysanias embodies the vulgarity that the speaker at first claims to
resent so much. At the same time, the theme of “love for an unworthy beloved” is much
worn, even “common” in itself. 97 This illustrates the flaw in Callimachus’ alleged
fastidiousness and ironically criticizes and undermines his high‐minded claims. That the last
words (ἄλλος ἔχει, “another’s affair”) are spoken by an echo might be an implicit
beloved echoes through Greek elegy from the very beginning (e.g. in the poetry of
Theognis). 99 Callimachus demonstrates his consciousness of the fact that in love‐poetry he
93 E.g. Gow and Page (1965: II, 156‐7).
94 Henrichs (1979: 207‐212).
95 For the negative meaning of κυκλικόν, cf. Blumenthal (1978: 125‐127) and Pollianus AP 11.130,1‐2:
Τοὺς κυκλίους τούτους τοὺς “αὐτὰρ ἔπειτα” λέγοντας / μισῶ, λωποδύτας ἀλλοτρίων ἐπέων. (I
hate those cyclical poets, who say “And then, and then...”, filchers of other poets’ verses...), clearly a
sympathetic reference to Callimachean poetics, cf. Gow and Page (1965: II, 155).
96 Cf. the metaphors of water and the road Callimachus uses in fr. 1 Pf. and Hymn II, 105‐113.
female speaker rejects promiscuity. Henrichs (1979: 210) shows that all the metaphors (the worn road,
the common well) used in the epigram find their counterpart in erotic metaphors employed in
Theogn. 699‐602 and 959‐962. The irony is that they are worn and common expressions in themselves.
98 The echo has received a great amount of scholarly attention, focusing mainly on the question how
ναίχι καλὸς καλός can be supposed to be echoed by ἄλλος ἔχει. For a recent overview of scholarly
discussions on the topic, see Gutzwiller (1998: 221, n. 78). She reads the last couplet as an illustration
of “how refinement can inhibit fulfillment of desire.”(1998: 222).
99 Cf. Wilkinson (1967: 5‐6).
189
too involuntarily adopts a persona who is not entirely master of his own preferences, no
matter how refined a poet he may otherwise (wish to) be.
6.8
Role‐playing versus Self‐representation
As announced earlier, the exact opposite of a clearly identifiable persona, which helps the
reader recognize who the speaker in a poem is, can also be found in Hellenistic poetry, in
particular in some of Callimachus’ mimetic hymns. This section will argue that this can be
explained from the particular circumstances in which Hellenistic poets themselves read older
poetry as well as from the fact that their poetry was written and circulated in book‐form.
When reading a first person utterance without a context, a diligent reader will try to
identify the speaker from the text and, if necessary, mentally reconstruct the implied
occasion of performance or imagined situation of utterance. The reader must rely upon hints
in the text about the identity of the speaker (e.g., male or female qualifying adjectives,
participles, or pronouns) and references to the situation at the moment of speech (e.g., time
of day, location, and address to interlocutors). This process lends itself to experiment and
the openings of Hymns V and VI, an illusion of an actual occasion is created:
Ὅσσαι λωτροχόοι τᾶς Παλλάδος ἔξιτε πᾶσαι,
ἔξιτε∙ τᾶν ἵππων ἄρτι φρυασσομενᾶν
τᾶν ἱερᾶν ἐσάκουσα... (Hymn V, 1‐3)
All who pour water for the bath of Pallas, come out, come out! Just now I heard the
mares of the goddess whinny... (transl. Nisetich)
Τῶ καλάθω κατιόντος ἐπιφθέγξασθε, γυναῖκες∙
“Δάματερ, μέγα χαῖρε, πολυτρόφε πουλυμέδιμνε.”
τὸν κάλαθον κατιόντα χαμαὶ θασεῖσθε, βέβαλοι. (Hymn VI, 1‐3)
Sing, women, as the sacred basket returns, sing the refrain: Hail Demeter, Goddess of
nurture, Goddess of plenty! You uninitiated there! Gaze on the basket at street level
only. (transl. Nisetich)
100 The phrase is Hopkinson’s, with reference to the narrator in Call. Hymn VI.
101 On insubstantial voices in Callimachus, cf. Harder (1992: 384‐394; 2001: 399‐416; 2004: 63‐81).
190
In these two Hymns, the reader will eventually have to conclude that the speaker is female
and therefore cannot be identified with the author, Callimachus. However, this conclusion is
entirely dependent on the imagined occasion, a festival at the temple of a female deity,
where only women were welcome. Callimachus thus creates a riddle: how could he, as a
male author, possibly know what happened at such festivals? 102
It is generally agreed that these hymns were not meant for “real” cult practice. 103
They are therefore not to be read as “scripts” prescribing the actions that should be
performed on the (Hellenistic) occasion of actual rituals. Rather, Callimachus deliberately
wanted them to convey the illusion that they represented some cultic occasion that had taken
place in the (distant) past. This can be explained as follows. In the Hellenistic age, literary and
poetic texts of the Greek past that had originally been intended for oral performance were
preserved on scrolls and read privately and individually rather than performed publicly. 104
Parts of the context and code that would have helped original audiences to understand such
poems (in particular their deictic references) and identify their first‐person speakers were
thus lost to third‐century readers. This loss of context arguably also influenced the
Hellenistic poets’ way of looking at first‐person utterances in such texts. On the one hand,
reading texts out of their historical contexts fostered the biographical approach we have
already encountered in Chapter 1: character and life of an author were argued from or
reconstructed out of his/her oeuvre lacking independent information. When it came to the
creation of sphragis passages for their own works, this meant that Hellenistic authors tried to
identify themselves as unambiguously as possible, as the epigrams discussed in the first part
of this chapter illustrate.
On the other hand, Hellenistic poets, in their scholarly occupation must have noticed
that some first‐person passages had become obscure through loss of their original context.
This is most notably suggested by the scholia vetera to the Victory Odes and Paeans of Pindar,
102 In Hymn V there are no participles referring to the speaker to give the fact that she must be a
woman away. It is only made clear in lines 51‐54, which warn off all men. They form the prelude to
the story of how young Tiresias unwillingly saw Athena naked. Apart from all attendants addressed,
it seems even the goddesses horses are female. In Hymn VI, the situation is more or less the same: only
women are addressed, and it is clear that this is a festival where men are not wanted.
103 Cf. Legrand (1898: 281‐312), Wilamowitz (1924: I, 15), Harder (1992: 384), Depew (1993: 57‐77).
104 On how this affected the metrical choices of Hellenistic poets, see Hunter (1996: 4‐5): recitative
meters gradually replace lyrical ones. On the general loss of performance occasions and its effect on
Hellenistic poetics, see Hunter and Fantuzzi (2004: 1‐17).
191
which often struggle with the question of whether the poet or the chorus (or both) is
supposed to be speaking in a particular passage, or whether they are perhaps even “voicing
the sentiments of the victor.” References to ancestry or topography in particular were liable
Thus, for instance in P. 5.72‐80 for a victor from Cyrene, the question for the scholiast is
whether it was the poet or the chorus who was more justified in singing: 105
τὸ δ’ ἐμὸν γαρύει
ἀπὸ Σπάρτας ἐπήρατον κλέος,
ὅθεν γεγενναμένοι
ἵκοντο Θήρανδε φῶτες Αἰγεΐδαι,
ἐμοὶ πατέρες, οὐ θεῶν ἄτερ, ἀλλὰ Μοῖρά τις ἄγεν. (P. 5.72‐80)
And mine it is to proclaim the delightful glory that comes from Sparta, whence men
born as Aigeidai, my forefathers, came to Thera, not without divine favor, but some
Fate led them. (transl. Race)
Indeed, the scholiast remarks at this point: ὁ λόγος ἀπὸ τοῦ χοροῦ τῶν Λιβύων ἢ ἀπὸ τοῦ
ποιητοῦ. (The utterance is [made] either by the chorus of Libyans or by the poet.) 106 Such
remarks suggest that the passage of time could make the–presumably once‐familiar–
references in texts ambiguous and obscure to later readers. It is not unlikely that already the
Alexandrians, who, as we know, seriously occupied themselves with the study and critical
assessment of such texts (in particular Pindar’s), were aware of this problem.
Callimachus was one of the scholars who spent a great deal of his time in the Library,
studying and analyzing ancient scrolls. This must have formed his way of composing poetry.
I argue that he must have been well aware through his own reading of archaic texts like the
above passage from Pindar, that his own poems too would be read in the future rather than
performed. For this reason, he deliberately created in his Hymns various (fictitious) “lost
contexts”: the ritual bath of (the statue of) Pallas at Argos, and the festivals of Apollo at
Delos, and of Demeter (at an unspecified location). He pretends that the texts of these hymns
were originally pronounced in these particular settings. This effect is achieved, as we saw, by
“throwing the reader in the middle of proceedings” without any narratorial frame, and
subsequently using a great number of deictic references to the purported circumstances.
105 Cf. Lefkowitz (1991: 72‐88) who argues that the whole (mistaken) idea that the Victory Odes contain
changes of speaker can be retraced to these critics.
106 Even today the question remains disputed, as Race’s note (1997: ad loc.) demonstrates.
192
The unusualness of this practice may be demonstrated by contrasting it with the 18th
Idyll of Theocritus, the epithalamium of Helen sung by Spartan maidens, which is framed by
remarks of an external primary narrator, who sketches the background before giving the
floor, as it were, to a group of Spartan maidens. 107
Ἔν ποκ’ ἄρα Σπάρτᾳ ξανθότριχι πὰρ Μενελάῳ
παρθενικαὶ θάλλοντα κόμαις ὑάκινθον ἔχοισαι
πρόσθε νεογράπτω θαλάμω χορὸν ἐστάσαντο,
δώδεκα ταὶ πρᾶται πόλιος, μέγα χρῆμα Λακαινᾶν,
ἁνίκα Τυνδαρίδα κατεκλᾴξατο τὰν ἀγαπατάν
μναστεύσας Ἑλέναν ὁ νεώτερος Ἀτρέος υἱῶν.
ἄειδον δ’ ἅμα πᾶσαι ἐς ἓν μέλος ἐγκροτέοισαι
ποσσὶ περιπλέκτοις, ὑπὸ δ’ ἴαχε δῶμ’ ὑμεναίῳ∙
“Οὕτω δὴ πρωιζὰ κατέδραθες, ὦ φίλε γαμβρέ;”(Id.18, 1‐9)
Once then, in Sparta, at the palace of golden‐haired Menelaus, maidens, with blooms
of hyacinth in their hair arrayed the dance before the new‐painted bridal chamber‐
‒twelve in number were they, the foremost in the town, fair flower of Laconian
maidenhood‐‒when Atreus’ younger son had closed its doors on his loved Helen,
Tyndareus’ daughter, whom he had wooed and won. And all in unison they sang,
beating time with weaving feet to their song, while the house rang with the bridal
hymn. “Have you fallen asleep so early, dear bridegroom?” (transl. Gow; the song of
the girls continues for 50 lines; there is no return to the narratorial frame.)
We see here how Theocritus chose to provide the maidens with some background
information in a brief prologue, making it easier for his readers to understand the context,
and firmly creating a narratorial frame, which erases the impression of vivid directness that
Callimachus’ hymns so patently breathe.108
Despite their “dramatic” or mimetic appearance, the primary ancestor of
Callimachus’ Hymns is not in first instance drama, but rather the choral lyric celebration of
cultic festive happenings such as can be found in ancient performative texts (Pindar’s
epinicia, or the Partheneia of Alcman). These texts frequently contain references to affairs
contingent to the original performance, including names, topography, and deictic
Cf. Id. 6 and 11.
107
In other dramatic monologues and dialogues, Theocritus does use the dramatic technique that
108
throws the reader in the middle of a scene without a narrative introduction (e.g., 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 10, 14,
and 15); the same happens in the Mimiambs of Herondas. However, these poems are “mimes,” little
plays that may or may not have been intended for fully‐fledged dramatic performance or less
dramatic “recital” but that at least descend from a dramatic ancestry. They owe much to the mimes of
Sophron (fifth cent. BCE), who is indebted to, or represents a variant of, the Athenian dramatic form.
193
expressions. 109 To create a similar illusion of missing contexts, Callimachus makes the first–
person speaker in his mimetic hymns similarly address persons imagined to be present, and
use deictic references to imagined circumstances. 110 A comparison between a fragment of
Alcman’s Partheneion (6th century BCE) and the opening of the Callimachean Hymn to Apollo
(II) will illustrate the point:
ἦ οὐχ ὁρῆις; ὁ μὲν κέλης
Ἐνετικός∙ ἁ δὲ χαίτα
τᾶς ἐμᾶς ἀνεψιᾶς
Ἁγησιχόρας ἐπανθεῖ
χρυσὸς [ὡ]ς ἀκήρατος∙
τό τ’ ἀργύριον πρόσωπον,
διαφάδαν τί τοι λέγω;
Ἁγησιχόρα μὲν αὕτα∙ (Alcman fr.1 PMG 50‐57)
Can’t you see? The courser is a Venetian Horse, and the hair of my cousin
Hagesichora blooms like pure gold; her face is silver. Why must I tell you more
clearly? There is Hagesichora herself!
In this passage from Alcman’s famous Partheneion, the chorus of maidens is apparently
singing about one in their midst (perhaps, considering her name, their leader); this is made
explicit in 56/7. This utterance would presumably have been accompanied by some gesture
or choreographed move pointing out which of the girls was Hagesichora. The many other
mysterious references in the fragmentary poem (to unknown gods, rivaling choruses, girls in
the chorus, and festive activities on subsequent days) are also contingent to the original
context of the performance in early Spartan society and lead to contrary opinions in
109 Harder (1992: 385, n. 7) recognizes that there may be a relation between the mimetic elements in
Call. Hymns, the hints of mimesis in the HH and the conventions of choral lyric, but she leaves this
unexplored. For the difficulty of understanding Alcman’s Partheneia owing to their highly contingent
references, see Campbell (1982 [1967] ad loc.), Robbins (1997: 224‐225). In HH Apoll. 156‐175, the Delian
or Hyperborean Maidens are apostrophized as if present. See on the reception of this hymn in Call.
Hymn II, Bing (1993: 181‐198).
110 Harder (1992: 386‐387; 389) lists various means of creating the illusion of a (lost) occasion, such as
the address of a more or less well‐defined fictional audience; the indications that a speaker is fixed in
time and space (e.g. familiarizing articles indicating a location, to imply that events are seen from the
perspective of the speaker as “erlebendes Ich”); deictic words indicating time; use of present and future
tense referring to the actual situation and the speaker’s expectations.
194
scholarship about the details of this occasion. 111 It is easy to imagine how tantalizing such
texts appeared to Hellenistic scholars in later antiquity in their more complete forms. 112
As announced, the elusive references in Alcman’s Partheneion are comparable in
many ways to the opening of Callimachus’ Hymn to Apollo (II), where a scene of epiphany at
Apollo’s Delian shrine is mimetically re‐created in words. The echo of Alcman line 50 in οὐχ
ὁράᾳς (Call. Hymn II, 4) provides a clear pointer to Callimachus’ deliberate attempt to create
the illusion of a real occasion: 113
Οἷον ὁ τὠπόλλωνος ἐσείσατο δάφνινος ὅρπηξ,
οἷα δ’ ὅλον τὸ μέλαθρον∙ ἑκὰς ἑκὰς ὅστις ἀλιτρός.
καὶ δή που τὰ θύρετρα καλῷ ποδὶ Φοῖβος ἀράσσει∙
οὐχ ὁράᾳς; ἐπένευσεν ὁ Δήλιος ἡδύ τι φοῖνιξ
ἐξαπίνης, ὁ δὲ κύκνος ἐν ἠέρι καλὸν ἀείδει. (Hymn II, 1‐5)
How Apollo’s laurel sapling shook, how the whole temple shook with it! Back, back,
all who have sinned! The doors are rattling: it must be Apollo striking them with his
gleaming foot. Can’t you see? All of a sudden the Delian Palm nodded with joy, and
now the swan is singing high in the air, his lovely song. (transl. Nisetich)
By this technique, that is, by using an elusive voice to launch the reader into the middle of
proceedings without any introduction to create the illusion of a real performance,
Callimachus demonstrates his awareness of the complexities that accrue to reading and
interpreting ancient texts out of their context. He imitates and creates a similar situation for
his readers.
6.9 Conclusion
As the instances discussed in this chapter show, the Hellenistic poets’ awareness of their own
position as readers of texts of the past influenced their perception of their own task as
creators of texts that would become a decontextualized text of the past to future readers.
111 Cf. Campbell (1982 [1967] ad loc.), Robbins (1997:243‐253) Hutchinson (2001, ad loc.).
112 Robbins (1997: 224) remarks: “Probably because of the parochial nature of his poetry, [Alcman] was
considered a difficult poet, and this explains why he attracted considerable attention from scholars in
antiquity.” An example of creative reception of the Partheneia may be found in Theoc. Id. 18, cf. Hunter
(1996: 139‐166). As noted however, Theocritus places the song of the maidens in a historical context by
the brief frame.
113 In Call. Hymn II, there appears to be more than one speaker, cf. Bing (1993: 181‐198.
195
The absence of independent historical information caused Hellenistic poets to read
the poetry of their predecessors in a biographical way. This was commonly accepted as the
best way of gaining knowledge about their character, life, and morals, as literary epitaphs
demonstrate: Archilochus was violent, Anacreon drunk, and so on (cf. Ch. 1.5.3). This being
the case, the Hellenistic poets must have been doubly conscious that they could partly
determine how their own personalities would be reconstructed from their poetry.
The evident means to influence readers beyond the grave was found in the writing of
self‐epitaphs and other sphrageis. In these, writers characterize themselves and offered their
readers a key to their poetry. The voices created are those of dedicators at shrines, of the
dead speaking from their tombs, or of symposiasts in various degrees of inebriation who are
declaring their stance in life and their feelings about poetic creativity and fame.
Some Hellenistic poets revealed an awareness of the lasting quality of their own
memorials by alluding to the living fame that was the contemporary tribute to predecessors
like Archilochus and Sappho. At other times, this awareness seems absent, were it not for the
fact that the mere act of writing down one’s own name in poetry implies the expectation that
someday, somewhere, someone would read the descriptions of the unhappy love affairs or
drunken revels and care who the poet behind the creation was. This is what unites the
Hellenistic epigrammatists, however different their individual voices may be: they wished to
be read and interpreted and perhaps enter into the tradition to be anthologized or imitated
as predecessors in their own right.
Reading poetry of the past without a context could also swing the other way and lead
to ambiguity, interpretational problems, and the awareness that a first‐person statement
need not necessarily be identical to the voice of a poem’s author. This awareness also finds
expression in Hellenistic poetry, notably in Callimachus’ sophisticated mimetic Hymns,
which created the illusion of lost performances for readers. Callimachus crafted this illusion
by inserting deictic references to absent people and distant (or unreal?) locations, leaving his
readers to guess at the relation between the speaking voice and the author. Paradoxically,
this complicated practice also implies the wishes to be read and interpreted and to enter the
literary tradition.
196
CHAPTER 7:
ALLUSIVE NAMES, ELUSIVE POETS: ALIAS AND ALTER EGO IN SPHRAGIS‐
POETRY
7.1 Introduction
Just as a clear, unambiguous sphragis aims to offer the reader a key to the interpretation of
the work to which it is appended, so an enigmatic, ambiguous, or allusive one may relate to
a certain interpretational goal or advocate an interpretational strategy. The fact that the
reader is challenged to solve a riddle if he wishes to know more about the identity of the
author indicates that this work is aimed at the ξυνετοί, the careful, clever readers. 1 A similar
premise underlies the following fictitious Hellenistic epitaph, where form and significance of
the inscription (a rebus) collaborate to express the name and therein the character of the
deceased.
Δίζημαι κατὰ θυμόν, ὅτου χάριν ἁ παροδῖτις
δισσάκι φεῖ μοῦνον γράμμα λέλογχε πέτρος
λαοτύποις σμίλαις κεκολαμμένον. ἆρα γυναικὶ
τᾷ χθονὶ κευθομένᾳ Χιλιὰς ἦν ὄνομα;
τοῦτο γὰρ ἀγγέλλει κορυφούμενος εἰς ἓν ἀριθμός.
ἢ τὸ μὲν εἰς ὀρθὰν ἀτραπὸν οὐκ ἔμολεν,
ἁ δ’ οἰκτρὸν ναίουσα τόδ’ ἠρίον ἔπλετο Φειδίς;
νῦν Σφιγγὸς γρίφους Οἰδίπος ἐφρασάμαν.
αἰνετὸς οὑκ δισσοῖο καμὼν αἴνιγμα τύποιο,
φέγγος μὲν ξυνετοῖς, ἀξυνέτοις δ’ ἔρεβος. (AP 7.429, Alcaeus of Messene)
I search my brain to understand for what reason the roadside tombstone has received
as only inscription two phis engraved by the chisels of the stonecutters. Was the name
of the woman who is buried in the ground here perhaps Chilias (Thousand)? That is
what you get if you add the number up. Or did that go in the wrong direction, and
was the poor woman who inhabits this tomb called Pheidis? Now, like an Oedipus, I
have solved the riddle of the Sphinx! The one who elaborated the enigma of the
double letters must be commended: he sheds light for those who understand, but
leaves those who don’t in the dark.
There are only two characters inscribed on the tombstone: (Φ Φ). Since the character Φ had a
numerical value of 500, they would add up to 1000 (Chilias, 4); however, this is not the
1 Cf. DNP 10, 754‐755 s.v. Rätsel: “Wer das Rätsel stellt, ist im Wissen überlegen; so kann der Person bzw.
Instanz, die das R. stellt (z. B. dem Seher oder dem Orakel) von den Angesprochenen Autorität zugestanden
werden; andererseits strebt der Ratende, durch Lösung des R. seine Ebenbürtigkeit im Wissen zu erweisen.” Cf.
the epigrams of Callimachus and Leonidas on the Phaenomena in Ch. 5.2.
197
solution. Rather, the woman buried here was called Pheidis, which might be explained as
“Two times phi” (Φει δίς), but also as “Thrifty” (φείδομαι, to economize), a plausible name
for a Greek woman. At the same time, the sparseness of the inscription (only two letters)
excellently expresses the modest and frugal character of the deceased, who apparently did
not wish for a verbose and costly inscription on her tomb. 2
In some Hellenistic sphragis‐poetry, the name of the author likewise seems to be
expressed ambiguously or indirectly. The modern reader’s uncertainty about its meaning
may however arise from the loss of knowledge that was presumably still common among
contemporaries of the poets. In some cases, such as the alternation Asclepiades/Sicelidas, the
most likely assumption is that the alternative name was used as normally and frequently as
the name that is more familiar to the modern reader. 3 The case is more uncertain for
Callimachus/Battiades. Is the alternative name a patronymic or was it chosen by the poet in
connection with the colonist Battus, in reference to Callimachus’ ties to his mother city,
Cyrene and to Cyrenaic aristocracy? The status of ”Simichidas”, the alternative name that
Theocritus appears to use to refer to himself in Idyll 7, remains enigmatic and subject to
ongoing debate to this day. In other cases, the well known proper name of an author may be
used in such a way as to contain hidden puns that need to be decoded or even discovered. In
Chapter 5, the clever play on Aratus’ own name in the second line of the Phaenomena
(ἄρρητον) was for instance discussed; some more instances of this kind will be analyzed in
the present chapter. First the etymologizing background to such play with proper names will
be briefly set out.
7.2 Puns and Etymology
The Greeks felt that names and nouns (ὀνόματα κυρία) could reveal important facts about
the object or person they indicated to those who were perceptive to the “true meaning”
2 For the interpretation, cf. Gow and Page (1965: II, 20‐21): “No doubt the thriftiness implied in the
name is exemplified in the brevity with which it is expressed.” Hopkinson (1988: 254‐255) adds that
the brevity of the epitaph might point in the direction of Callimachean leptotes. Similar riddle epitaphs
are e.g. Leon. AP 7.422; Antip. Sid. AP 7.423; 7.424; 7.425; 7.426, 7.427, and Mel. AP 7.421.
3 The alternative name Sicelidas is found in Mel. AP 4.1.45; Hedyl. Ath. 1173A (VI GP) and Theoc. 7.39‐
41, cf. the scholia ad loc., who claim that it is a patronymic.
198
(ἔτυμος λόγος) they conveyed. 4 Some instances of this belief could be subsumed under the
category nomen est omen, literally, “the name is a sign or a token.” This resulted in
kledonomancy, divination from names, “a system which operates on the conviction that
language possesses an enigmatic oracular capacity to bear unexpected meaning not intended
or even understood by the speaker.” 5
The belief that proper names could contain hidden meanings is attested as early as
Homer. Words and names were explained in various ways that were later united under the
heading “etymology” (ἐτυμολογία), the science of the true explanation of a name or word. 6
From a modern linguist’s viewpoint, many examples of ancient etymology would be more
accurately classified as verbal or stylistic playfulness, puns that play on phonetic and formal
ambiguities or analogies (e.g. paronomasia, 7 figura etymologica). 8
In many cases, it is difficult to believe that the Greeks seriously considered the
derivations they proposed, and even harder to imagine that they thought such apparently
arbitrary similarities revealed a deeper meaning about the object or person indicated. Yet,
literary evidence certainly points in this direction. 9 Examples of “etymologies” on (proper)
names of individuals as well as peoples, cities and lands are extremely frequent in Greek
4 Since most Greek proper names originally possessed an easily distinguishable meaning, deriving
from a characteristic (physical, behavioral or otherwise, cf. DNP s.v. Onomastik), the origins of this
belief are easy to understand. With the passage of time it was especially names of which the
significance had become obsolete for which false etymologies could be established to provide a new
significance.
5 So Zeitlin (1982: 46) on Aeschylus, especially on his explanation of the name Helen (which he
connects to the root ἑλ‐, “to destroy,” Ag. 681‐90). On etymology in general, see also Woodhead (1928:
22‐23), O’Hara (1996: 13).
6 The first to use this word was presumably Philoxenus of Alexandria, a grammarian of the first
century BCE (see DNP s.v. Etymologie). However, the process of etymologizing had been current in
non‐systematical form long before. The first (ironical) reflection on quasi‐scientific attempts at
etymology can be found in Plato’s Cratylus. A treatise attributed to Augustine, but preserving material
from centuries earlier, explains the four principles governing ancient etymological derivations: 1)
κατὰ μίμησιν: by imitating sounds, or by using sounds whose smoothness, harshness and so on
mimicked that of the thing named; 2) κατ´ ὁμοιότητα: from the similarity of one thing to another; 3)
κατ’ ἀναλογίαν: by association, i.e., paronomasia and figura etymologica; 4) κατ´ ἀντίφρασιν: a name
indicates the opposite of a thing or some property it has, cf. O’Hara (1996: 20).
7 When there is a likeness in sound, but it is not (necessarily) intended that the words are
“etymologically” related, e.g. Il. 16.22: τοῖον γὰρ ἄχος βεβίηκεν Ἀχαιούς. (such woe befell the
Achaeans).
8 Where a derivation is clearly intended, e.g.: Odysseus from ὀδύσσομαι.
9 For some salutary caveats on the interpretation and “discovery” of etymologies and puns in ancient
texts (how can one be sure that the etymology is intended?), see Haslam (1992: 199‐204); O ‘Hara
(1996: 5).
199
literature. To name one of the more famous will have to suffice here. In the Odyssey, the most
notable example occurs in the passage in which Autolycus decides that his grandson is to be
called “Odysseus” since many are angry with Autolycus at the moment the boy is born
(ὀδύσσομαι, to hate, Od. 19.409). The connotations of this name, the epic implies, also apply
to Odysseus himself. 10 Names or sobriquets of poets are often explained in a similar way:
Στησίχορος means “He who sets up the chorus” 11 Μουσαῖος means “Belonging to the
Muse.” The alias Solon uses for Mimnermus (Λιγυαστάδη, fr. 20 W), is explained by the
Suda s.v. Μίμνερμος as deriving from the adjective λιγύς (ἐκαλεῖτο δὲ καὶ Λιγυαστάδης διὰ
τὸ ἐμμελὲς καὶ λιγύ: he was called Ligyastades because of his harmoniousness and his clear
[voice].) 12
The scholarly Hellenistic poets continued and intensified the interest in the
possibilities of etymologizing and wordplay as heuristic devices to explain origins of
customs, cities, and geographical landmarks, festivals, cletic titles of deities, proper names of
their characters, and so on. For instance, Callimachus’ Aetia and Hymns and Apollonius’
Argonautica reveal a distinct interest in the explication of names. 13 In this chapter I will argue
that it can indeed be found in the play upon proper names of the poets themselves.
10 Cf. Louden (1995: 27‐46) see also Soph. fr. 965 Radt: ὀρθῶς δ᾿ Ὀδυσσεύς εἰμ´ ἐπώνυμος κακῶν˙/
πολλοὶ γὰρ ὠδύσαντο δυσμενεῖς ἐμοί. (Rightly am I called Odysseus for my woes; for many enemies
hate me).
11 Whose original name was Teisias, according to the Suda s.v. Στησίχορος. Bowra (1936: 79) suggests
that the sobriquet may be based upon some passage of Stesichorus’ poetry now lost, in which he
spoke about his own name and origin.
12 A similar claim is made in the Suda about the alias of Simonides, Μελικέρτης (on a derivation from
μέλι or μελιχρός): ὃς ἐπεκλήθη Μελικέρτης διὰ τὸ ἡδύ. (who was also called Melicertes because of
his sweetness). Cf. the explanations of Plato’s name as provided e.g. in Diog. Laert. 3.4, linking it with
the adjective πλατύς (wide, broad). Whereas Plato’s original name would have been Aristocles, after
his grandfather (cf. AP 7.60), he would have received the sobriquet either because of his bulky stature,
the result of his wrestling lessons, or because of his broad forehead, or because of his broad style of
writing. Notopoulos (1939: 135‐145) argues that these explanations result from the (etymologically
influenced) guesses of later biographers.
13 Contemporary scientific prose treatises also provide abundant evidence for their interest in
etymology, as the titles of Callimachus’ lost scholarly works demonstrate: Ἐθνικαὶ Ὀνομασίαι (Local
Nomenclature), Περί Μετονομασίας Ἰχθύων (On Changes of Names in Fish), Μηνῶν Προσηγορίαι
κατὰ ἔθνος καὶ πόλεις (Local Month‐Names), Κτίσεις Νήσων καὶ πολέων καὶ μετονομασίαι
(Colonizations of Islands and Cities and their Changes of Names), cf. Suda s.v. Καλλίμαχος. For a
more playful approach to naming and names (anagrams) in the Hellenistic era, see Cameron (1995b:
477‐484).
200
7.3 Wordplay in Hellenistic Sphrageis
Some examples of play on the proper names of various Hellenistic poets have already been
discussed: the epigrammatist Crates (AP 11.218) pretended to blame Euphorion for his
literary tastes while playing on the obscene double entendres on the names of the authors he
mentions (Chapter 4.8). The epigram demonstrates the wide‐spread uses of punning and
quasi‐etymologising, which in all likelihood—apart from being sparked by scholarly
pursuits in etymology and aetiology—owe something to Old Comedy. 14 A more serious
instance of such play on an author’s name was found in the reference of Aratus to himself in
line 2 of the Phaenomena, and the allusions to this pun in the epigrams in praise of this work
(Chapter 5.2). In the light of these examples, it is opportune to cast a fresh glance at some
other well‐known passages in Hellenistic poetry.
It has been observed that the proems of the Argonautica of Apollonius and the
Phaenomena share some salient features, including a hymnic opening to a god that is central
to the poem, Zeus (Ἐκ Διὸς ἀρχώμεσθα, from Zeus let us begin...) 15 and Apollo (Ἀρχόμενος
σέο Φοῖβε, beginning from you, Phoebus...), respectively. Both also contain a belated and
remarkably phrased invocation of the Muses. 16 A punning allusion to the author’s name may
be a characteristic that should be added to this list of similarities. Aratus modestly placed the
pun on his own name in the second place, after Zeus (ἄρρητον, 2); it might be argued that
Apollonius was alluding to his own name in the beginning of the Argonautica through the
invocation of his eponymous god Apollo.
The pun at the opening of the Phaenomena is paradoxical. While appearing to name
Aratus, it implies at the same time that hemodestly wishes to remain unmentioned. How does
14 For examples of proper names in Comedy being abused to render obscene meanings, cf. e.g.
Henderson (1991 [1975]).
15 Although Theocritus Id. 17 also begins with this phrase, later writers explicitly attribute the phrase
to Aratus (Strato AP 12.1.1: Ἐκ Διὸς ἀρχώμεσθα, καθὼς εἴρηκεν Ἄρατος, “Let us begin from Zeus,”
as Aratus said). Cf. also Cic. Rep. 1.36; Quint. Inst. 10.1.46; Macr. Somn. 1.17.14; see also the lengthy
commentary in the Scholia (Martin) on the first line and Kidd (1997: 163).
16 Phaen. 16‐17: Χαίροιτε δὲ Μοῦσαι / μειλίχιαι μάλα πᾶσαι. Ἐμοί γε μὲν ἀστέρας εἰπεῖν / ᾗ θέμις
εὐχομένῳ τεκμήρατε πᾶσαν ἀοιδήν. (And hail, Muses, all most gracious! In answer to my prayer to
tell of the stars in so far as I may, guide all my singing. transl. Kidd); cf. Arg. 1.20‐22: Μοῦσαι δ’
ὑποφήτορες εἶεν ἀοιδῆς. (May the Muses be the “hypophetores” of the song.) On the structural
similarity between the openings, and the remarkable choice of verb in the address to the Muses, cf.
Kidd (1997: 162‐3; 174 respectively). See on the muse‐invocations of Aratus and Apollonius Ch. 8.3‐8.6.
The Aratus‐Scholia also mention the parallel of Apollonius ( Schol. Arat. Vat. 191). Conversely, the
Scholia on Arg. (1‐4a) mention the opening of the Phaen.
201
this relate to Apollonius’ choice to call on Apollo, while using the invocational title
“Phoebus” (1.1)? Perhaps a similarly paradoxical modesty is at play here. Robert Albis
suggests that Apollonius invokes Apollo as Phoebus perhaps to avoid making the play on
names too obvious:
Elsewhere however, Apollonius frequently refers to the god as Apollo, and when the
name appears in the genitive, it differs from the poet’s only by one iota (…) The
similarity of the names of the god and the poet suggests that Apollonius has a special
relationship with Phoebus. Apollonius means, after all “belonging to Apollo.” In the
context of poetic inspiration this relationship has a special resonance. A divinely
inspired poet is “entheos” [possessed by a god]. (Albis, 1996: 22)
Albis’ observations gain force when combined with the play on Aratus’ name, which, as we
saw, was remarked upon by his contemporaries. Both puns occur in the opening lines of the
poems, the perfect place for a sphragis. Both authors, Aratus and Apollonius, allude to their
name in their praise of their patron god, and both leave their name unmentioned. Their
signature is thus paradoxically hinted at and hidden simultaneously.
Two epigrams by Callimachus are of interest as well, since he appears to be
exploiting the connotations of his own name (Καλλίμαχος) and his patronymic, as it shall
provisionally be called, Battiades (AP 7.525). It seems that the two poems are related to each
other 17 and that both make a definitive statement about Callimachus’ poetics. Let us begin
with the epigram on Callimachus’ father.
Ὅστις ἐμὸν παρὰ σῆμα φέρεις πόδα, Καλλιμάχου με
ἴσθι Κυρηναίου παῖδά τε καὶ γενέτην.
εἰδείης δ’ ἄμφω κεν∙ ὁ μέν κοτε πατρίδος ὅπλων
ἦρξεν, ὁ δ’ ἤεισεν κρέσσονα βασκανίης. (AP 7.525)
You, who are passing by my grave, know that I am of Callimachus the Cyrenaic both
son and father. You would know both: one once was the chief of his fatherland’s
armed forces; the other’s song was stronger than envy.
The speaker in the poem is the father of Callimachus, who is, however, not named. 18 His
modesty is emphasized by this omission even while he is immortalized by his famous son’s
17 Scholars have regularly assumed that the two poems were companion pieces, e.g. Wilamowitz
(1924: I, 175, n. 2), Gabathuler (1937: 5), Fraser (1972: I, 576), Bing (1995: 126‐28), Gutzwiller (1998: 212).
18 It has been suggested e.g. by Gow and Page (1965: II, ad loc.) that, as often happens in non‐literary
epitaphs, the name may not have fitted the meter; the reader would have inferred that this was the
reason for its omission. Alternatively, as noted, AP 7.415 could be read in conjunction with this poem,
and so supply the name of the unnamed father of Callimachus, viz. Battus.
202
poetry. 19 The token by which this man wants to be known, or so the epigram claims, is the
paradoxical circumstance that he is both son and father of a Callimachus. This “riddle” is
solved by the explanation that there are two persons bearing the name Callimachus, one a
general (1‐2) and one a poet whose song was stronger than envy (4), an expression with
somewhat belligerent undertones.
This gives rise to a new riddle: how can these two namesakes be likened to each
other? How do they both live up to their name? The pointe of the epigram may be that the
two bearers of the same name, while having at first sight very different occupations, were in
some sense as alike as their name suggests. The grandfather of Callimachus was a
distinguished warrior. Callimachus the grandson was the vanquisher of envy through his
song; he was a “warrior with words.“ And so, both Callimachuses lived to gain fame for
their name, which might etymologically be explained to contain the elements κάλλος
(beauty) and μάχη (battle). At first sight, such a name might seem to befit a man at arms
better than a poet, yet Callimachus the poet certainly lived up to the name.20 The notoriously
belligerent persona of Callimachus, as known from works such as the prologue of the Aetia
(fr. 1 Pf.) and the Iambi (cf. Chapter 4), fits the meaning of his name surprisingly well.
The second epigram leaves out the name “Callimachus” and only refers to him by
what scholarship has predominantly accepted as a patronymic, Battiades: 21
Βαττιάδεω παρὰ σῆμα φέρεις πόδας εὖ μὲν ἀοιδήν
εἰδότος, εὖ δ’ οἴνῳ καίρια συγγελάσαι. (AP 7.415)
You are passing the grave of Battiades, who knew well how to sing and how to tell
jokes properly over wine.
The epigram has been read as an evaluation of Callimachus’ complete poetic output. The
phrase εὖ μὲν ἀοιδήν / εἰδότος, εὖ δ’ οἴνῳ καίρια συγγελάσαι could be said to cover the
whole range, from Callimachus’ longer poems (ἀοιδήν: the Hecale, the Aetia, the Hymns etc.)
to the poetry that is exemplified by the present poem, epigrams that were composed or
19 Wilamowitz (1924: I, 175, n. 2) suggested–surely somewhat naively–that Callimachus could not
write much about his father, because there just was not much to say about him.
20 Ferguson (1970: 66), without however referring to this epigram, remarks: “Certainly in general
Callimachus lived up to his name Glory in Battle.”
21 The reader would have known that Callimachus was meant anyway, as the epigram was
presumably found in a collection of Callimachus’ poetry, cf. Meyer (2005: 171).
203
performed at symposia (καίρια). 22 The first and last words (εἰδότος ... συγγελάσαι) of the
second line moreover aptly describe the whole field in which Callimachus’ poetry finds
itself: it is not only learned and scholarly, but also ironic and tongue in cheek. 23 The fact that
the epitaph should be so concise yet express all the essentials about its author and subject
reveals much about Callimachus’ poetic ideals as exemplified and expressed elsewhere. 24 His
preference is for short, subtle, and witty poetry, such as this epigram.
The fact that Callimachus here calls himself “Battiades” (i.e., the descendant of Battus,
the hero who founded Cyrene and first of a long list of eponymous kings) has usually been
linked to his connections with Cyrenaic aristocracy, or more broadly, to his patriotic feelings
for the colony of Cyrene as a whole. 25 Another interpretation simply explains ”Battus” as the
actual proper name of his father. 26 Whichever of these possibilities is correct, the literal
meaning of the name is of interest. In Greek, Βάττος means “Stammerer,” or “Lisper” (i.e.,
someone with a speech‐impediment). 27 In Herodotus’ account of the colonization of Cyrene,
the naming of Battus, later king of this settlement is explained thus (Hist. 4.155):
Χρόνου δὲ περιιόντος ἐξεγένετό οἱ παῖς ἰσχόφωνος καὶ τραυλός, τῷ οὔνομα ἐτέθη
Βάττος.
And as time went by he [i.e., Battus’ father] begot a child that had difficulty
speaking and stammered, to whom the name Battus [Stammerer] was given). 28
22 Cf. e.g. Reitzenstein (1893: 87), Parsons (2002: 104; 129): “Callimachus represents half his life as οἴνῳ
καίρια συγγελάσαι,” “[The epigram] ostensibly opens a divide between ἀοιδή and the opportunist
wit of the symposium.”
23 Cf. Reitzenstein (1893: 87).
24 E.g Aetia fr. 1 Pf., Hymn II, 105‐113, AP 9.566.
25 Cf. Cameron (1995: 8). White (1999: 168‐181) argues that antiquity would not have understood the
name as a direct patronymic, but as referring more broadly to ethnic ties and ancestry, Callimachus’
relation to the founder of his father city Cyrene, the heroic Battus (celebrated e.g. in Pi. P. 4 and 9). Cf.
e.g. Call. Hymn II, 96; Str. 17.3.21: λέγεται δὲ ἡ Κυρήνη κτίσμα Βάττου∙ πρόγονον δὲ τοῦτον ἑαυτοῦ
φάσκει Καλλίμαχος. (Cyrene is said to be a settlement by Battus; Callimachus claims to be a
descendant of his). Reitzenstein (1893: 233‐234) thought that the character Battus in Theoc. Id. 4
constituted a reference to Callimachus. This forms part of his bucolic masquerade‐thesis which has been
discarded, cf. e.g. Treu (1963: 273‐290). The occurrence of the name in Theocritus is however quite
striking; certainly considering the claim of White that Battus was an extremely unusual name.
Battiades is the name the Roman poets use to indicate Callimachus (Cat. 65.16; 116.2; Ov. Am. 1.15.13,
Ib. 55, Tr. 2.367, Stat. Silv. 5.3.157) As Gow and Page (1965: II, 152) suggest, this might indicate that he
called himself thus elsewhere besides.
26 Cf. Wilamowitz (1924: I, 175, n. 2), Gabathuler (1937: 5), Fraser (1972: I, 576), Bing (1995: 126‐28),
Gutzwiller (1998: 212).
27 Cf. LSJ s.v., quoting Hesych. and Suda. It is believed to be an onomatopoeic word. The verb
βαττολογεῖν/βατταρίζω means “to stammer,” or “to say the same word over and over again.”
28 According to Call. Hymn II, 76, Battus’ “original” name was Aristoteles.
204
Interestingly, Herodotus’ account of the colonization of Cyrene contains a significant
equivocation on the name of Battus; the name turns out to be a lucky omen. As Battus arrives
at the shrine of Delphic Apollo to ask the Pythia what to do about his voice, she replies:
“Βάττ’, ἐπὶ φωνὴν ἦλθες∙ ἄναξ δέ σε Φοῖβος Ἀπόλλων / ἐς Λιβύην πέμπει
μηλοτρόφον οἰκιστῆρα.”
“Battus, you have come to ask about your voice, but the Lord Apollo sends you
out to Libya rich in sheep as a colonist.”
Herodotus explains that this is as much as saying “Ὦ βασιλεῦ, ἐπὶ φωνὴν ἦλθες” (“King,
you have come to ask about your voice”), since in Libyan the word βάττος meant “king.”
And indeed, “King” was the title by which Battus was subsequently addressed as founder of
the colony Cyrene.
Callimachus was probably aware of this story, and he may have meant to hint at the
fact that Battus was a name of good omen, as history had proved. He may moreover have
wished to create a meaningful opposition between the connotations of the name “Son of the
Stammerer” and the fact that he was a succesful poet who suffered from no verbal
impediments at all. Indeed, Hesychius s.v. βαττολογία defines it as ἀργολογία,
ἀκαιρολογία (to prattle unseasonably). 29 This suggests that the reference to his patronymic
or alias should be understood as an instance of the explanation of a name κατ´ ἀντίφρασιν
(by expressing the contrary). 30 The name is a paradoxical token of Callimachus’ fluent yet
concise poetic speech, his specific ability of καίρια συγγελάσαι.
7.4 Theocritus, Simichidas and Lycidas
The question of the exact relation between Simichidas, Lycidas, and the poet Theocritus in
Idyll 7 is the last topic of this chapter. In this case, however, something different from and
perhaps more fundamental than the play on a name is involved. The issue is nevertheless
linked to the previous discussion, since it starts out from the difficult interpretation of what
is usually considered an alias, Simichidas. Considering the programmatic significance of
Cf. also Suda s.v. βαττολογία; cf. LSJ s.v. ἀκαιρία (4) “bad taste in writing” (D.H. Dem. 7).
29
Cf. lucus a non lucendo ([It is called] a grove because there is no light in it; Honoratus Maurus, fourth
30
cent. CE).
205
Theocritus’ seventh Idyll, 31 the characterization of Simichidas in the poem is of paramount
importance, since he is its internal narrator. 32 In order to get a better understanding of what
is at stake in the following discussion, a brief synopsis of the narrative contents of the poem
is necessary.
At the poem’s opening an internal narrator starts relating how, once upon a time, 33 he
was on his way to the celebration of the Harvest Festival (Thalysia) organized by some
aristocratic friends on the island of Cos. Together with his friends Eucritus and Amyntas, he
departed from the city towards the farm of the organizers of the Thalysia (1‐4). On the way, in
the noonday heat, they met a mysterious goatherd, named Lycidas (10‐14), whose looks and
smell are described in great detail (15‐20). This Lycidas addresses the previously nameless
narrator of the Idyll as “Simichidas” (21); there is no explanation of their knowledge of each
other’s names. The narrator proposes they exchange bucolic songs (36). After some
preliminary remarks on fame and poetic creeds (37‐41, 45‐48) and the promise of a guest gift,
a staff or stick (κορύναν/λαγωβόλον) on the part of Lycidas (43), they sing; the exchange
takes up a major part of the poem (51‐126). Afterwards, Lycidas hands Simichidas the guest
gift and suddenly disappears in another direction (129); the narrator and his friends reach
the farm, where a lush symposium in a locus amoenus, described in picturesque and sensuous
detail, is held (130‐157).
The significance of this “exchange of bucolic song” (which was first converted into a
poetic form by Theocritus, cf. Chapter 3.7) and of the particularly evocative description of the
rural symposium at the end depends on the appraisal of the status of the poem as a whole,
and of that of the protagonists in particular. Is everything what it looks like on the surface?
31 Cf. Gow (1952: II, introduction to the Idyll), Lawall (1967), Weingarth (1967), Goldhill (1991), Hunter
(1999). The numerous references to music, contemporary poets, the Muses, the Nymphs, poetic theory,
poetic fame, as well as the exchange of song that takes up the major part of the poem make clear that
this is a poem about poetry.
32 An internal narrator is a narrator who plays a role in his own story (also known as first‐person
narrator). On the narrators in Theocritus’ Idylls, see Hunter (2004: 83‐97).
33 Cf. Wilamowitz (1924: II, 142): “Theokrit hat durch das Anfangswort es war einmal das Erlebnis, von dem
er erzählt, in eine unbestimmte Ferne gerückt, alsob es ein Märchen ware.” Gow (1952: II, 131): “the Greek
implies only that the epoch referred to is closed, or the state of affairs no longer existing, not that it
belongs to the distant past… The opening suggests that T.’s circumstances have changed in some
way–for instance that he or his friends are no longer in Cos.” Clauss (2003: 289) remarks that the
parallels Gow adduces would seem to support both the interpretation of Wilamowitz and his own.
206
This point is related to the question of the identifications of Simichidas and Lycidas, which
have been variously evaluated. 34
The Scholia, in accordance with the practice of biographical readings of poetry in (late)
antiquity in general, mostly assume that Simichidas is an alias of the author and that the
whole poem should be read as an autobiographical record. They consequently interpret the
name Simichidas as either a patronymic, derived from a father who was named Simichos or
Simichidas, 35 or as a kind of sobriquet (ἐπώνυμον) referring to a certain physical feature of
the poet, namely his flat nose. 36 In any case, they mostly appear sure that he is to be equated
with the poet. 37
In the nineteenth century and well into the first half of the twentieth, a biographical
reading of the seventh Idyll remained the predominant approach. Attempts were also
repeatedly made to “unmask” Simichidas as well as Lycidas as participants in a masquerade
34 The scholarship on the seventh Idyll comprises ca. 220 publications, including numerous books. In
the compass of this chapter, I signal the most important trends in the scholarship concerning this
“enigmatic masterpiece” (Gow). In Weingarth (1967) a full discussion of the scholarship up to that
year can be found; Hunter (1999) provides a useful update.
35 Vita: πατρὸς Σιμίχου, ὡς αὐτός φησι (Whose father is Simichos, as he himself claims.); cf. Schol.
21a,b: ὁ Θεόκριτος Σιμιχίδα υἱος ὢν Σιμιχίδαν ἑαυτὸν ὀνομάζει πατρωνυμικῶς. (Theocritus, the
son of Simichidas, calls himself Simichidas with a patronymic). The Vita, Suda and the (Hellenistic?)
epigram that was presumably affixed to the Idylls also name an alternative father, namely Praxagoras
(3). This rings truer, since there is not, as in the case of “Simichos,” an obvious text‐internal reason for
calling Th.’s father thus.
36 Prol. 3: ἦν γὰρ τὴν ῥῖνα σιμός. (for he was snub‐nosed), cf. Schol. 21a. Although this too is
problematic, at least, if we believe, with Petroll (1965: 35) that the first person speaker of Id. 12 should
be identified with the poet, because there he mentions his ῥινὸς … ἀραιῆς (slender, straight nose). In
Id. 3, a goatherd complains that he has a σιμός nose. It seems to have been considered a typical
characteristic of goatherds.
37 Cf. Argumentum c (referring to Id. 7.1 ff): προλογίζει ὁ Θεόκριτος. (Theocritus speaks in the
prologue). The Suda also seems to consider it possible, cf. the explanation s.v. Θεόκριτος. So also the
epigram appended to the scholia after Id. 18, beginning Σιμιχίδα Θεόκριτε. There seems to have been
yet another school of thought: οἱ δὲ ἕτερόν τινα τῶν σὺν αὐτῷ καὶ οὐ Θεόκριτον διὰ τὸ “Σιμιχίδᾳ
μὲν Ἔρωτες ἐπέπταρον. (v. 96)” (Some think that [Simichidas refers] to one of the others in his
company, not to Theocritus, because of the phrase “the Loves have sneezed for Simichidas.”) They
differentiate between Theocritus and Simichidas without, however, explaining why the narrator is
addressed by Lycidas as “Simichidas.” The name Simichidas further occurs in an ingenious pun in the
pseudo‐Theocritean technopaegnion Syrinx (on its spuriousness, cf. Gow 1952: II, 553‐554), viz. in the
enigma/pun Πάρις Σιμιχίδας: Paris was the judge (κριτής) in the beauty‐contest of the goddesses
(θεῶν), hence Θεό‐κριτος. Nickau (2002: 389‐304) argues that the name Simichidas in Id. 7 indicates
that Theocritus was a follower of the contemporary poet of technopaegnia (such as the Syrinx) Simias;
his sobriquet would refer to this master.
207
bucolique with cultic or secular overtones. 38 This did not influence the biographical
approach, 39 so that a meta‐poetic interpretation of the poem in which the events should be
understood symbolically rather than literally was not undertaken.
Such a symbolic interpretation only became possible when scholars recognized that
the use of the name “Simichidas” rather than “Theocritus” might convey an essential
difference on some level between the internal narrator and the “author” Theocritus. This is,
for instance, hesitatingly expressed by Gow:
Simichidas describes in the first person an experience which evidently reflects, in part
at least, an experience of Theocritus himself. “I” in literature may stand for the author
himself (Id. 28) or for a character he has created (Id. 3); between these extremes an
author may identify himself not wholly but only in part with a character who uses the
first person. Hence, though the speaker in Id. 7 is plainly in part the poet, the two are
not necessarily identical (...) Still, it is most natural in this poem to assume the
identity, and with this caveat I shall assume it and suppose Simichidas to be neither
more nor less than an alias for Theocritus. (Gow, 1940: 47)
The way was now open to readings that recognized a certain symbolic, meta‐poetic quality
in the poem. Thus, Sanchez‐Wildberger (1955: 65ff) not only suggest that Simichidas is on a
meta‐poetic level part of the persona of Theocritus but also posits that Lycidas must be a part
of it. She regards the confrontation between the two poets in the Idyll as “eine
Doppelspiegelung des einen Theokrit” (68); in her view, the songs of both singers present
“dieselbe seltsame Mischung von städtischem Leben und Bukolik.” (67). There is, however, one
major problem with this interpretation: if it is correct, then why is Simichidas, not Lycidas,
the narrator? And why is the poem not composed in the form of a simple mimetic dialogue
38 This thesis proposed that all herdsmen in Theocritus’ poetry were really portraits of contemporary
poets in disguise, who convened on certain occasions to indulge in the simplicity of rural life. The idea
was propounded especially by Reitzenstein (1893), but several others participated in the “guessing
game” which resulted in manifold identifications, especially for Lycidas: Aratus (Bergk); Dosiadas
(Wilamowitz), Leonidas (Legrand), Callimachus (Gercke), Astakides (Ribbeck), Rhianus (Legrand) or
merely an “eccentric poet going about in herdsman’s outfit.” Wilamowitz later retracted his belief in
the masquerade bucolique (1906: II, 136), although he still maintained that Lycidas could well be the
Cretan poet Dosiadas.
39 Cf. e.g. the remarks of Wilamowitz (1924: II, 136): “Der Eindruck wird nicht tauschen dass er wirklich die
Erinnerung an das Erntefest wiedergibt, zu dem ihn Phrasidamos und Antigenes, die vornehmen Koer,
eingeladen hatten. Simichidas ist ja Deckname für Theokrit, ob für diese Gelegenheit erfunden, oder weiter
geltend, können wir ja nicht entscheiden. Versteck spielen wollte der Dichter doch nicht vor der Koische
Gesellschaft, für die er zunächst dichtete.” Similar views can be found as late as the 1960’s, e.g. Petroll
(1965: 32); Monteil (1968: 100).
208
(cf. Id. 4, 5)? 40 Simichidas’s role as the narrator undeniably gives him a greater claim to
identification with the author than Lycidas; he is in control of the narration of this poetic
encounter. This means Lycidas cannot be an alter ego on the same level as Simichidas. 41 This
problem is solved in Händel’s interpretation of the Idyll as an encounter between Theocritus
(Simichidas) and one of his own fictions, Lycidas, “einer jener idealisierten hochpoetischen
Hirten wie man sie auch sonst in den bukolischen Idyllen findet.” 42 Although this suggestion is
plausible, it does not explain why the author needed to be called “Simichidas” rather than
“Theocritus.”
Another strain in the history of interpretation continued to attempt to identify
Lycidas, while the Simichidas/Theocritus equation was simply accepted. 43 The first to make
the important observation that the seventh Idyll contained elements of the Dichterweihe, as
most famously found at the opening of Hesiod’s Theogony, was Van Groningen (1959). 44
Building on this idea, Puelma (1960) remarked upon the similarities between the meeting of
Simichidas and Lycidas and several meetings between gods and mortals in the Homeric
epics. 45 The idea that Lycidas represents a god in disguise was then propounded with force
by a number of critics. Yet, they could never agree which divinity hid behind the goatherd
who is so teasingly described as the quintessential goatherd. 46 This suggests that this
reading, like the masquerade bucolique, is not the best way to approach the figure of Lycidas. 47
40 Cf. Segal (1981: 125).
41 Cf. also Petroll (1965: 44).
42 Körte/Händel (1960 [1925]: 216). The reason he suggests for this fiction (viz. that Lycidas is
introduced to convince readers that such herdsmen could actually exist) seems strangely naïve.
43 Cf. e.g. Petroll (1965: 32): “Während die Identifikation Simichidas/Theokrit verhältnismässig einfach ist, hat
die Gestalt des Lykidas den Forschern viel Kopfzerbrechen bereitet und zahlreiche Deutungsversuche
hervorgerufen.”
44 These elements are: the mysterious meeting, the slightly abusive tone of the encounter, the reference
to the springs (Burina, Hippocrene). Most important, however, is the handing of the stick by Lycidas
to Simichidas as “a guest gift in the Muses,” cf. the handing of a laurel to Hesiod by the Muses.
45 Cf. also Cameron (1963: 291‐307) and Williams (1971: 137‐145). The latter proposed that Lycidas
should be identified with the god of poetry and song Apollo, which would make the ironies involved
in the condescending behavior of Simichidas towards Lycidas even greater.
46 Id. 7.13‐14: ἦς δ’ αἰπόλος, οὐδέ κέ τίς νιν / ἠγνοίησεν ἰδών, ἐπεὶ αἰπόλῳ ἔξοχ’ ἐῴκει. (His name
was Lycidas, and he was a goatherd. Nor could you fail to recognize him as such, since he looked
exceedingly like a goatherd).
47 Gods that have been proposed: a satyr (Lawall, 1967); Apollo (Williams, 1971); Pan (Brown, 1981;
recently defended anew by Clauss 2003). Segal’s remark (1981: 122) seems most convincing: “Lycidas’
divinity remains a hint only, a suggestion which the alert reader will keep in the back of his mind.”
Bowie (1985: 67‐97) interprets Lycidas as a character from the lost poetry of Philitas. Barring the find
209
Segal created a new range of possibilities by dispensing with exclusive identifications
when he called Lycidas “a symbol:”
A symbol cannot mean whatever the critic wants it to mean; but it is important to
recognize that a symbol may have several related and interconnected meanings.
Precisely because of the range of such interrelated meanings we can return to a
literary work again and again and never fully exhaust its significance. (…) Thus there
is no necessary contradiction in regarding [Lycidas] as a god, as an aspect of
Theocritus’ poetic personality, or (…) as a symbol of bucolic inspiration in general.
(Segal, 1981: 114)
Segal takes his cues from structuralism and regards the confrontation of Simichidas and
Lycidas as a series of binary oppositions between city (Simichidas) and wild countryside
(Lycidas), civilization and nature, Demeter (goddess of the Thalysia) and Pan (god of
herdsmen, flocks, and wild animals), reality and myth, irony and romance. He suggests that
it is exactly in the interplay between these dichotomies that bucolic poetry gets its form; the
encounter between Simichidas (the townsman) and Lycidas (the quintessential goatherd)
takes place on a country road, a no‐man’s land between city and rough mountainsides, and
leads to a celebration of the fruits of the tamed countryside, the Thalysia. 48 He regards the
Idyll as an attempt of Theocritus the poet to come to terms with the opposing constituent
elements of his new bucolic poetry.
He also appears to be one of the first to fully realize the significance of the fact that
“Simichidas” is an internal narrator who controls the narrative of the meeting, but that
Theocritus the poet has deliberately created Simichidas as his alter ego:
By enclosing the encounter within a frame and making it the subject of recollection by
a first‐person narrator, he forces us to see Lycidas from the point of view of
Simichidas’ I. This is not the device one would expect if the poem were merely trying
to contrast two sides of Theocritus’ poetry or personality, for then the two figures
ought to stand on the same level of reality and objectivity. (Segal, 1981: 125)
This resembles the observation that Gutzwiller builds upon in her perceptive study of
“pastoral analogy” as a determining constituent of bucolic poetry. She argues that the
essential significance of the bucolic Idylls is in the analogies constructed by the poet between
the herdsman characters in the main body of the poem, and the figures of narrator and
of a Philitas‐papyrus, this theory, though ingenious, is impossible to prove and therefore destined to
remain speculation.
48 Segal (1981: 137). For contrast as a creative force in bucolic poetry, cf. also Ott (1969).
210
narratee in the frame. In the purely mimetic poems there is only an implied frame formed by
the reader’s experience; the analogy remains implicit.
In the sixth Idyll, for instance, the narrator addresses a certain Aratus and presents the
dialogue of the two herdsmen Damoetas and Daphnis. The herdsmen in turn play the roles
of the Cyclops in love with Galatea and a praeceptor amoris. In this Idyll, the utterances made
at every level of the poem shed light upon the situation at another level. The situation of the
Cyclops and Galatea may in some way reflect the situation between the shepherds Damoetas
and Daphnis; the implication may be that they are lovers or friends who offer each other
advice upon matters of love. Their relation in turn illuminates the situation of the narrator
and his addressee (his friend or lover?) Aratus. 49
The situation in the seventh Idyll is fundamentally different because there is an
internal narrator, as Gutzwiller explains:
Simichidas and Lycidas do not correspond to characters in the frame, whose likeness
and difference define or mirror their own likeness and difference; the frame presents
only the narrator, who suggests his oneness with the poet himself by placing himself
in a recognizable time and place with companions and acquaintances who seem
historical personages. Because of this suggested identification, the poet himself is
implied in all the relationships of his autobiographical projection in the form of
Simichidas. And so, as Simichidas is an analogue of Lycidas, the poet may be viewed
as Lycidas’ analogue as well. (Gutzwiller, 1991: 160)
I would even go further and state that, whereas Simichidas is indeed an analogue or alter
ego of the poet, Lycidas is an alter ego once removed; an “alter alter ego.” To clarify that the
narrator is a fictional alter ego, not to be equated tout court with the poet, Theocritus, the
the character of the narrator, if “Simichidas” indeed derives from σιμός, snub‐nosed, as the
scholia assumed. This adjective came to mean “arch” or “pert,” because of the character that
was usually ascribed to people with flat noses. 50 Arch and pert would indeed appear to be
adjectives that quite accurately describe the narrator’s demeanor (e.g., 26‐30; 37‐4). 51
To develop the possibility that Simichidas is presented as a fiction in the poem, it may
be emphasized that the initially nameless internal narrator receives the name Simichidas
from Lycidas (21). This act indicates that he is, at some level, the creation of Lycidas. There is
49 Cf. also Bowie (1996: 91‐100).
50 Cf. LSJ, who cite Mel. AP 5.176; AP 5.178.
51 Cf. the remarks of Segal (1981: 167‐176).
211
no explanation why Lycidas calls the narrator “Simichidas.” 52 When the narrator eventually
starts singing his song, he accepts the name by which Lycidas has accosted him but appears
to keep it at a slight remove from himself (95‐98). The beginning of Simichidas’ song poses
some problems with regard to the question of its true authorship: 53
Σιμιχίδᾳ μὲν Ἔρωτες ἐπέπταρον∙ ἦ γὰρ ὁ δειλός
τόσσον ἐρᾷ Μυρτοῦς ὅσον εἴαρος αἶγες ἔρανται.
Ὥρατος δ’ ὁ τὰ πάντα φιλαίτατος ἀνέρι τήνῳ
παιδὸς ὑπὸ σπλάγχνοισιν ἔχει πόθον. οἶδεν Ἄριστις,
ἐσθλὸς ἀνήρ, μέγ’ ἄριστος, ὃν οὐδέ κεν αὐτὸς ἀείδειν
Φοῖβος σὺν φόρμιγγι παρὰ τριπόδεσσι μεγαίροι,
ὡς ἐκ παιδὸς Ἄρατος ὑπ’ ὀστίον αἴθετ’ ἔρωτι. (7.96‐102)
For Simichidas the Loves sneezed, for he, poor soul, loves Myrto as dearly as goats
love the spring. But Aratus, dearest friend in all to me, guards deep at heart a desire
of a boy. Aristis knows, a man of worth, the best of men, whom Phoebus himself
would not grudge to stand and sing, lyre in hand, by his own tripods—knows how to
the very marrow Aratus is aflame with love for the boy. (transl. Gow)
The oddness of this opening and the difficulty of deciding who the alleged speaker is have
been remarked upon:
The singer emphatically distances himself from the events he is describing. Whereas
the singer of Lykidas’ song unambiguously identifies himself as Lykidas (55), 54
Simichidas’ song could be performed by another singer: μοι in 103 and 118 are
inconclusive, and even τὸν ξεῖνον … μευ (119) does not necessarily pick up 98.
Simichidas’ song could be performed by others, whereas Lykidas’ performance is
wholly personal. (Hunter, 1999 ad 98)
I would like to suggest that the fact that the singer refers to himself so emphatically in the
third person might moreover indicate that he is not completely at one with the identity of
“Simichidas” as bestowed upon him by Lycidas. In other words, the internal narrator points
at the “fictional status” of Simichidas by his unwillingness to completely identify with him.
He appears to make Simichidas simultaneously the singer and the subject of his song; or at
least to create a (meaningful?) ambiguity as to the exact relation between Simichidas and the
52 Cf. Gow (1952: II, ad 11‐14) and Hunter (1999: ad 11‐14).
53 Cf. scholia at 21a: οἱ δὲ ἕτερόν τινα τῶν σὺν αὐτῷ καὶ οὐ Θεόκριτον διὰ τὸ “Σιμιχίδᾳ μὲν Ἔρωτες
ἐπέπταρον∙” (96). (Some think [“Simichidas”] refers to another in his company, not to Theocritus,
because of the phrase “The loves have sneezed for Simichidas”). However contrast scholia at 96‐97c:
περὶ ἑαυτοῦ ὁ ποιητὴς ᾄδων φησί∙ τῷ Σιμιχίδᾳ οἱ Ἔρωτες ἐπέπταρον. (Singing about himself, the
poet says: etc.).
54 Id. 7.55‐56: αἴ κα τὸν Λυκίδαν ὀπτεύμενον ἐξ Ἀφροδίτας / ῥύσηται∙ θερμὸς γὰρ ἔρως αὐτῶ με
καταίθει. (If he saves Lycidas, who is roasted by Aphrodite; for a hot love for him burns me up).
212
author of the song. Is it really the song of Simichidas? If so, what is the significance of the
reference to Aristis (99)? Perhaps the song that follows is really a song in the voice of Aristis,
just as Lycidas’ song gives voice to the song of Tityrus. 55 The way in which Aristis is praised
is remarkably similar to the way in which the narrator praises himself. 56 At any rate, what
comes across is that the voices are strangely mixed up, and it is difficult to ascertain the
ultimate authority behind the song.
The impression that Simichidas is in some way a “creation” of Lycidas seems to be
confirmed by Lycidas’ enigmatic remark to Simichidas that he is a πᾶν ἐπ’ ἀλαθείᾳ
πεπλασμένον ἐκ Διὸς ἔρνος (44, translated below). This expression, with its paradoxical
opposition of ἀλαθείᾳ (truth) and πεπλασμένον 57 (made up, fashioned, fictioned) has
“you are a sapling of Zeus all fictioned for truth,” meaning, “you are a convincing fiction, a
poetic creation that is true to life.” As Gutzwiller explains:
Understood so, the phrase has reference not simply to the truthfulness of
Simichidas’ preceding statement, but also to his truthfulness as a poet, his
ability to compose with verisimilitude, or even of his truthfulness as a poetic
fiction, his believability as the poetic creation of the narrator. (Gutzwiller, 1991: 166) 58
So, Simichidas may be considered a convincing creation of Theocritus. To complicate matters
further, it must be stressed again that he may in some sense also be a “creation” of Lycidas,
who of course ultimately is the creation of the narrator/Simichidas, too, as the narrator
controls the narrative of his meeting with Lycidas. There are other indications in the text that
55 Cf. the commentary of Gow (1952: II, ad loc.): “The most obvious inference from T.’s words would be
that Aratus’ love affair formed the subject of a poem by Aristis.” Heubeck (1984: 233‐43) proposed that
the song eventually sang by the first person narrator is indeed the song of Aristis. Cf. also Hunter
(1999: 180): “Like Lycidas, Simichidas’ song experiments with different voices: 103ff may be taken as a
recreation of the song of Aristis, or more probably as the voice of the poet [Aristis] himself.”
56 Praise of Aristis: ἐσθλὸς ἀνήρ, μέγ’ ἄριστος, ὃν οὐδέ κεν αὐτὸς ἀείδειν / Φοῖβος σὺν φόρμιγγι
παρὰ τριπόδεσσι μεγαίροι. (98‐99) resembles self‐praise of the narrator: καὶ γὰρ ἐγὼ Μοισᾶν
καπυρὸν στόμα, κἠμὲ λέγοντι / πάντες ἀοιδὸν ἄριστον. (Indeed, for I too am a clear voice of the
Muses and all call me the best singer, 37‐8); and of his art: ἐσθλά, τά που καὶ Ζηνὸς ἐπὶ θρόνον
ἄγαγε φάμα. (Wonderful things, that, I think, have brought my fame even to Zeus’ throne, 92).
57 Cf. LSJ s.v. πλάσσω: “a distinctly literary term, expressing a figment, or fiction of the imagination of
a poet,” cf. e.g. Xenophan. fr. 1.22‐23 DK: οὔτι μάχας διέπων Τιτήνων οὐδὲ Γιγάντων / οὐδέ <τε>
Κενταύρων, πλάσματα τῶν προτέρων. (Not recounting the battles of the Titans or the Giants or the
Centaurs, those fictions of earlier men.) and Pl. Tim. 264e4‐5.
58 Gow (1952: II, ad loc.): “the phrase has been suspected, and if taken at its face value is certainly odd.”
For a meta‐poetic interpretation, see e.g. Walsh (1985: 19), Segal (1981: 170‐1), Goldhill (1991: 232),
Hunter (1999 ad loc.).
213
Lycidas is Simichidas’ creation. This seems, for instance, to be suggested by the phrase
ἐσθλὸν σὺν Μοίσαισι Κυδωνικὸν εὕρομες ἄνδρα. (13: we found, with the Muses, a good
man of Cydonia). The ambiguous and remarkable expression σὺν Μοίσαισι … εὕρομες
might easily be construed as meaning, “we invented,” or “created with the help of the
Muses,” that is to say, “we composed a poem about this man, we invented him.” 59
In turn, this might explain the mysterious and much debated emphasis on Lycidas’
“extreme likeness” to a goatherd in one line although he is explicitly called an actual
goatherd in the following lines. 60 The underlying significance of the expression is perhaps
rather that Lycidas is an extremely realistic creation of poetry, the perfect quintessence of the
bucolic herdsman poet, a goatherd who “looks exceptionally like a goatherd.” Just as
Simichidas is “fictioned for truth,” Lycidas is a character that resembles greatly what he is;
he too is a convincing fiction.
The interpretation that either singer in the poem appears to be portrayed as the
creator and fiction of the other, or at least remarking upon the fictional status of the other, is
These singers, caught in a poetic fiction, are also themselves creators of singers in their songs.
All this ties very well into the tangled web of echoes, analogies, and allusions that
Theocritus spins in all of his bucolic Idylls, as argued in Chapter 3.12. As bucolic poetry is
poetry by singing herdsmen about singing herdsmen, it is only natural that the poet
Theocritus creates a poetic alter ego who simultaneously functions as the creator of his
antagonist (the singing herdsman Lycidas) and as the fiction of this singing herdsman
(“Simichidas”) in this poem. In a programmatic poem about the nature of bucolic poetry,
59 For εὑρίσκω meaning to “compose a song” cf. e.g. Hedyl. (Ath. 11.473a/GP V). It would usually
seem to carry a hint of “invention of a formerly non‐existent type of poetry”(cf. the expression protos
heuretes). None of the scholarship I have been able to see has this interpretation, the general trend
being merely to explain the phrase as meaning “we fell in by the good grace of the Muses” (i.e.,
pointing forward to the fact that the meeting would result in a musical exchange), cf. e.g. Gow (1952:
II, ad loc.), Goldhill (1991: 228), Hunter (1999 ad loc.).
60 Id. 7.14‐15: οὔνομα μὲν Λυκίδαν, ἦς δ’ αἰπόλος, οὐδέ κέ τίς νιν / ἠγνοίησεν ἰδών, ἐπεὶ αἰπόλῳ
ἔξοχ’ ἐῴκει. (His name was Lycidas, and he was a goatherd. Nor could you fail to recognize him as
such, since he looked exceedingly like a goatherd). This expression has been the starting point of the
whole debate on the identity of Lycidas. For a discussion of some of the older theories, cf. e.g. Gow
(1952: II, 128‐9): ἔξοχ’ ἐῴκει: “If pressed here, it would probably lend a little colour to the view that
Lycidas is not a goatherd at all.” The formula is very similar to the ones used to introduce gods in
human form in the Homeric epics, cf. Puelma (1960: 144‐164); Cameron (1963: 291‐307); Hunter (1999:
146‐150). On the remarkably opaque phrasing, see Goldhill (1991: 228‐229): “A doubt is introduced?
Yet precisely what is not provided is adequate, clear information to move beyond that doubt.”
214
such mise en abyme serves to illustrate the Chinese‐box‐like structure characteristic of
Theocritus’ bucolic poetry.
Lycidas’ song illustrates this. It tells of a symposium at which a herdsman‐singer,
Tityrus, will sing of the singing protoi heuretai of bucolic poetry: Daphnis and Comatas, the
cowherd and the goatherd who repeatedly feature in the poems of Theocritus and of his
herdsman‐characters. 61 The song of Lycidas typifies the way in which songs are embedded in
other songs, making different levels of song practically indistinguishable.
αὐλησεῦντι δέ μοι δύο ποιμένες, εἷς μὲν Ἀχαρνεύς,
εἷς δὲ Λυκωπίτας∙ ὁ δὲ Τίτυρος ἐγγύθεν ᾀσεῖ
ὥς ποκα τᾶς Ξενέας ἠράσσατο Δάφνις ὁ βούτας,
χὠς ὄρος ἀμφεπονεῖτο καὶ ὡς δρύες αὐτὸν ἐθρήνευν
Ἱμέρα αἵτε φύοντι παρ’ ὄχθαισιν ποταμοῖο,
εὖτε χιὼν ὥς τις κατετάκετο μακρὸν ὑφ’ Αἷμον
ἢ Ἄθω ἢ Ῥοδόπαν ἢ Καύκασον ἐσχατόωντα.
ᾀσεῖ δ’ ὥς ποκ’ ἔδεκτο τὸν αἰπόλον εὐρέα λάρναξ
ζωὸν ἐόντα κακαῖσιν ἀτασθαλίαισιν ἄνακτος,
ὥς τέ νιν αἱ σιμαὶ λειμωνόθε φέρβον ἰοῖσαι
κέδρον ἐς ἁδεῖαν μαλακοῖς ἄνθεσσι μέλισσαι,
οὕνεκά οἱ γλυκὺ Μοῖσα κατὰ στόματος χέε νέκταρ.
ὦ μακαριστὲ Κομᾶτα, τύ θην τάδε τερπνὰ πεπόνθεις∙
καὶ τὺ κατεκλᾴσθης ἐς λάρνακα, καὶ τὺ μελισσᾶν
κηρία φερβόμενος ἔτος ὥριον ἐξεπόνασας.
αἴθ’ ἐπ’ ἐμεῦ ζωοῖς ἐναρίθμιος ὤφελες ἦμεν,
ὥς τοι ἐγὼν ἐνόμευον ἀν’ ὤρεα τὰς καλὰς αἶγας
φωνᾶς εἰσαΐων, τὺ δ’ ὑπὸ δρυσὶν ἢ ὑπὸ πεύκαις
ἁδὺ μελισδόμενος κατεκέκλισο, θεῖε Κομᾶτα. (7.70‐89)
And two shepherds shall pipe to me, one from Acharnae, and from Lycope one, and
close at hand Tityrus shall sing how once Daphnis the neatherd loved Xenea, and
how the hill was sorrowful about him and the oaktrees which grow upon the river
Himeras’ banks sang his dirge, when he was wasting like any snow under high
Haemus or Athos or Rhodope or remotest Caucasus. And he shall sing how once a
wide coffer received the goatherd alive by the impious presumption of a king; and
how the blunt‐faced bees came from the meadows to the fragrant chest of cedar and
fed him on tender flowers because the Muse had poured sweet nectar on his lips. Ah,
blessed Comatas, yours is this sweet lot, you too were closed within the coffer; you
too, on honeycomb fed, did endure with toil the springtime of the year. Would that
you had been numbered among the living in my day, that I might have herded your
fair goats upon the hills, and listened to your voice, while you, divine Comatas, did
lie and made sweet music under the oaks or the pines. (transl. Gow, adapted)
Daphnis is the hero in the song of Thyrsis in Id. 1 (as he is here), and is mentioned in the mimetic Id.
61
5 (a short reference by Comatas). In the partly mimetic Id. 6, he is a speaking character introduced by
the narrator. A (different?) Comatas figures as a singer in Id. 5; cf. Ch. 3.11.
215
At the end of the song, the legendary goatherd poet Comatas, who was kept alive inside a
chest by the providence of the Muses, is suddenly addressed directly despite being long
dead and featuring here in a song embedded in a song. Ultimately, this means that the voices
of Theocritus (who gives a voice to his alter ego, “Simichidas”) and “Simichidas” (who
relates the song of Lycidas) and Lycidas (who sings of the song of Tityrus) and Tityrus (who
refers to the singing mythical goatherd poet Comatas) converge. 62
The passage is extremely convoluted in that the song of Lycidas is set in the future,
addresses a legendary and already ancient poet, and is recalled by Simichidas as something
he heard “once upon a time.” Through this conflation of voices and time, Comatas is
ultimately addressed by Theocritus himself, or by whoever is reciting the seventh Idyll. This
is the miracle of bucolic poetry: the legendary goatherd singer Comatas, who is apparently at
the heart of bucolic poetry, can be directly addressed and a song about his fate can resound
across the ages because it has been handed down in the bucolic tradition, in songs by singing
herdsmen about singing herdsmen; yet at the same time it seems invented at the moment of
recital.
The unisonous address to Comatas, achieved through this harmony and the dizzying
convergence of the voices of all the singers in all the layers of the poem makes clear that
there is a fundamental unity to bucolic poetry. Although they operate on different levels of
temporal and literary remoteness, and reality, myth, and fiction, they can be considered a
single entity. The voices easily cross these boundaries and thus symbolize both the
remoteness of the origins of bucolic poetry (Ἦς χρόνος ἁνίκ’, once upon a time, 1) and its
direct accessibility. Bucolic song simultaneously stresses the distance and elusiveness of its
past and brings that past, through performance, directly to life.
Up to a certain point, this also applies to the song of Simichidas. Simichidas sings
about his friend Aratus’ love for a certain Philinus. It seems likely that this Aratus is the
same Aratus addressed in the frame of Idyll 6. It is not certain that he is the author of the
Phaenomena; but if he were, the structural similarity of the songs of Simichidas and Lycidas
62 This is similar to Arg. 2. 705‐713, where the song of Orpheus, a hymn to Apollo narrated by the
narrator in reported speech, is suddenly interrupted by a direct apostrophe of the god. The question
who is speaking arises, Orpheus or the narrator. In last instance, it seems unanswerable, the implied
point presumably being that there is a convergence between the voices of Orpheus and the narrator,
cf. Ch. 3.5.
216
would be even greater. 63 Lycidas sings of Tityrus, who sings of Daphnis and Comatas, the
latter of whom is finally apostrophized. Just so “Simichidas” apparently sings of Aristis who
sings of (the poet) Aratus. Aratus is eventually apostrophized as well. Lycidas, a fiction of
“Simichidas” and Theocritus, sings of the fictional herdsmen in Theocritus’ poetry;
“Simichidas,” Theocritus’ fictional alter ego, addresses Aratus who is also addressed by the
poet Theocritus (Id. 6, 13). The internal narrator of the seventh Idyll is linked more closely to
the realistic frame of Theocritus’ poetry than Lycidas and is therefore able to refer to actual
contemporaries of Theocritus (Asclepiades and Philitas, Aratus, possibly Antigenes and
Phrasidamos). Nonetheless, he too is a fiction, as his name, given to him by the fictional
goatherd Lycidas, indicates.
7.5 Conclusion
As we have seen, a name might harbor unexpected but relevant meanings intended to be
decoded by the reader or interpreter of a work of poetry. To encourage such interpretations,
the name could be contextualized to suggest meaning and evoke significances and
similarities that would have otherwise gone unnoticed. Examples of this meaning‐laden
embedding include the scurrilous epigram by Crates (AP 11.218), the two epigrams of
Callimachus on himself and his father (AP 7.525; 7.415), and the signatures of Aratus and
Apollonius in the opening lines to their works.
The case of Theocritus/“Simichidas” is different in that it does not so much depend
on the correct interpretation of the connotations of the name per se, but rather on the
perception that “Simichidas” is a name given by Lycidas, a character in a poem, to the first‐
person narrator of that poem as an indication that this narrator is a poetic fiction. Once the
fictionality of the narrator/Simichidas is recognized, his fictional status becomes the key to
the interpretation of all that happens in the programmatic seventh Idyll. This fictional status
63 The scholia (Arg. ad Id. 6) suggest identifying him as the poet from Soloi: δύναται δὲ οὗτος εἶναι ὁ τὰ
Φαινόμενα γράψας∙ συγκεχρόνικε γὰρ τῷ Θεοκρίτῳ καὶ εἰκὸς <φίλους> ἀλλήλων γενέσθαι. (It is
possible that this is the one who wrote the Phaenomena, for he was a contemporary of Theocritus and it
is likely that they were friends). This identification was first questioned by Wilamowitz (1894: 182).
For arguments pro and contra the identification with the author of the Phaenomena, see Hubbard (1998:
27) (pro); Gow (1952: II, 118‐119) and Hunter (1999: 243) (contra). The structural similarity of the songs
could indeed argue in favor of identification with Aratus the poet.
217
points to the creative role of Lycidas, who paradoxically is himself a creation of the internal
narrator of the Idyll. Both are figments of the imagination of the other, and of the poet
Theocritus; and the latter reinforces this by pointing to the fictionality of his creations in
various ways (12; 44). The dual status of both Lycidas and Simichidas as poetic fictions and
poets is a comment upon the character of bucolic poetry, a poetry of (fictional) herdsmen
poets about herdsmen poets, singing of herdsmen poets, all created by Theocritus.
218
CHAPTER 8:
QUESTIONING THE MUSE: AUTHORITY AND INSPIRATION IN THE AGE OF THE
MUSEUM
8.1 Introduction
In an age that differed greatly from the times when Homer sang of the Trojan War and
Pindar praised the victors of athletic games, pervasive and undying topoi such as invocations
of the Muses and κλέος as poetry’s main raison d’être needed to be interpreted anew if they
were to remain relevant. 1 How was a poet to account for his knowledge of things past if the
Muse had, with the waning of orality, become a convention, perhaps even a figure of
speech? 2 Was the Muse still relevant? The inspiration she provided had been questioned in
Plato’s attacks on poetry, which denied any truth or educational value to the utterances of
poets, who, according to this philosopher, were in a state of irrational enthousiasmos when
composing their works. 3 Their poetry, then, could hardly contain anything that might
withstand the test of the intellect. To rethink the implications of the Muse and the inspiration
she provided therefore meant to question both the function of poetry as a receptacle of
collective memory, and the doctrine of divine inspiration.
In Homer’s Iliad, the Muses owed their omniscience to their eternal omnipresence,
which granted them knowledge of all that had happened in the past through eye‐sight as
opposed to hearsay (κλέος), the only source of knowledge available to humans:
ὑμεῖς γὰρ θεαί ἐστε πάρεστέ τε ἴστέ τε πάντα,
ἡμεῖς δὲ κλέος οἶον ἀκούομεν οὐδέ τι ἴδμεν… (Il. 2.485‐6)
For you are goddesses and are present and know everything, while we know nothing
but hear only rumors…
According to this belief, the cooperation of the Muses enabled a poet to convey an
impression of almost visual directness to his audience. 4 The listeners were made to feel as if
1 For an overview of the development of the concept of κλέος, see Steinkopf (1937), Greindl (1938).
2 For an analysis of the decline of the Muses’ importance, see Häussler (1973: 117‐145). For an
overview of Muse invocations in ancient literature in general, see Falter (1934).
3 On Plato’s opninions on poetry (especially in Ion and Resp.), see Murray (1981), Else (1986).
4 The root *ιδ‐ in ἴστε and ἴδμεν is related to eyesight, whereas κλέος is related to verbs of hearing
(κλύω). See on this passage De Jong (1987: 45‐52). Cf. Latacz (2000: ad Il. 2.485‐6): “Menschliches und
Göttliches Wissen unterscheiden sich nicht voneinander durch die Richtigkeit des Inhalts (…) unterschiedlich
ist lediglich die Grad der Genauigkeit und Zuverlässigkeit.”
219
they had been present, or at any rate the poet, at the events he was narrating. In a sense,
poetry thus made the past present through divine intervention. 5
By the Hellenistic age, when written literature, scholarly prose as well as poetry,
about people and things long gone was securely stored (but retrievable for those who knew
their way about the Museum), poetry about the past produced by fellows of the Museum
necessarily acquired a new character and function. A striking and well known example of
how the changed attitude vis à vis the past altered the perception of the Muses may be found
in Callimachus’ Aetia (fr. 75 Pf. Acontius and Cydippe). The narrator here states that the history
of the isle of Ceos, of which the love story of Acontius and Cydippe forms a part, derives
from the writings of Xenomedes, “an old man concerned with truth,” (πρέσβυς ἐτητυμίῃ
μεμελημένος) who “once stored the whole history of the isle in his mythological chronicles”
(ὅς ποτε πᾶσαν / νῆσον ἐνὶ μνήμῃ κάτθετο μυθολόγῳ). In itself, such a statement would
remind a reader rather of a historian than of a poet. However, the most surprising turn is yet
to come, for the narrator continues: “And from thence, the story of the boy swiftly made its
way to my Calliope” (ἔ̣ν̣θεν̣ ὁ π̣α̣[ι]δ̣ός / μῦθος ἐς ἡμετέρην ἔδραμε Καλλιόπην). 6 If the
story was set down in Xenomedes’ chronicles before it reached Calliope, this implies that she
is presented as a learned lady who does not gain her omniscience from omnipresence but
rather from the diligent study of ancient texts. Thus, the passage expresses that Callimachus
turns stories found in ancient documents into fiction (poetry). It is clear how far he has
wandered from the Homeric invocations of Iliad 2. Both poets make a claim to knowledge
about the past by relying on the Muse, but whereas Homer’s Muse is simply and
unquestionably omniscient on account of her divine nature, Callimachus’ Muse is reliable
because she chooses her sources well. Would Plato’s qualms as to the untrustworthiness of
irrational inspiration still apply to a Muse who gains her knowledge from a conscientious
chronicler?
5 Cf. Od. 8.487‐491, Odysseus’ compliment to Demodocus: Δημόδοκ’, ἔξοχα δή σε βροτῶν αἰνίζομ’
ἁπάντων. / ἢ σέ γε Μοῦσ’ ἐδίδαξε, Διὸς πάϊς, ἢ σέ γ’ Ἀπόλλων∙ / λίην γὰρ κατὰ κόσμον Ἀχαιῶν
οἶτον ἀείδεις, / ὅσσ’ ἕρξαν τ’ ἔπαθόν τε καὶ ὅσσ’ ἐμόγησαν Ἀχαιοί, / ὥς τέ που ἢ αὐτὸς παρεὼν ἢ
ἄλλου ἀκούσας. (Demodocus, I praise you above all men, whether it was the Muse, the daughter of
Zeus, that taught you, or Apollo; for well and truly do you sing of the fate of the Achaeans, all that
they did and suffered, and all the toils they endured, as though you had been present, or had heard
the tale from another).
6 On Callimachus’ unusual relation with the Muses in Aetia books 1 and 2, see Harder (1988: 1‐15).
220
Callimachus’ description of the way the Muse gathers her knowledge presumably
forms an accurate portrayal of the way many of the poetae docti of the Library or Museum in
reality proceeded: they found their material in prose treatises. The versification of such
learned prose works became popular in Hellenistic poetry, as can be seen from the vogue of
didactic poems: Aratus’ Phaenomena, largely a poetic adaptation of Eudoxus’ treatise of this
title, Eratosthenes’ Hermes, with its many geographical excursus, and the Alexipharmaca and
Theriaca of Nicander, which probably draw heavily on the works of the Alexandrian iologist
Numenius. 7 A final example of a somewhat different nature may be found in the epic
Argonautica of Apollonius. Throughout this narrative, learned excursions on recondite
aetiological and geographical facts breathe the atmosphere of the library, as is confirmed by
the many references to Apollonius’ possible sources in the scholia to his epic. 8 On the level of
vocabulary, the learned and “unspontaneous” content of Hellenistic poetry was matched by
a recherché employment of rare and archaic words, as shall presently be explored in more
detail.
In the field of encomiastic poetry, problems—albeit of a different nature—also arose.
Poets saw themselves in the entirely new position of having to praise kings like the
Ptolemies who had reserved the prerogatives of (semi‐)divinity for themselves and their
dynasties. 9 What was more, panegyric poetry had to compete with epideictic prose orations,
royal pageants, 10 and even temples and sacrifice in honor of the monarch. Could a poet in
such surroundings still capitalize on his privileged role, his own particular brand of divinity,
and claim to be a mouthpiece of the Muse? At any rate, caution was needed in this new
situation, and the two kinds of divinity, poetic and royal, had to sound in unison. 11
7 Nicander, who is probably later than Callimachus and Aratus, cf. Gow and Scholfield (1997 [1953]: 5‐
8), does not even bother to invoke the Muses; for him the fact that poetry draws on prose or other
written sources has apparently become completely acceptable.
8 On Apollonius’ sources see e.g. Stössl (1941).
9 Weber (1993) treats the relation of court and poets extensively, but pays little attention to this
potential problem. Hunter (2003) discusses the panegyric and the implications of divine rulership in
Theoc. Id. 17 in detail.
10 E.g. the impressive and lavish parade organized by Ptolemy Philadelphus described by Callixeinus
(Ath. 5= FHG3), on which see Rice (1983).
11 This is suggested by the alleged fate of the satirical poet Sotades who attacked the holy brother‐
sister marriage of the Ptolemies with obscene verse addressed to Ptolemy Philadelphus: Εἰς οὐχ ὁσίην
τρυμαλιὴν τὸ κέντρον ὠθεῖς (you are shoving your prick into an unholy hole, fr. 1 Powell). Anecdote
has it that this caused the latter to have Sotades shut into a leaden chest and thrown into the sea to
drown.
221
In coming to terms with such issues, Hellenistic poets looked, once more, to the
poetry of the past. They found ways to reinterpret what they encountered in the literary
heritage. The ensuing aims to illustrate this by discussing an example of a philological
approach to the past in poetry. I examine how the Hellenistic glossographical and
interpretative‐critical interest in Homer gave rise to a creative re‐fashioning of the figure of
the poet by Apollonius and Theocritus.
8.2 Homeric Scholarship and Hellenistic Poetry
With regard to Hellenistic scholarship on Homer, Antonios Rengakos states, “the rise of
Homeric scholarship as an academic discipline coincides with the heyday of Hellenistic
poetry. (…) This is no pure accident, but an essential relationship” (2001: 193). 12 This applies
to most major Hellenistic poets; in the case of Apollonius, one scholar even stated, “The
Argonautica itself is a work of scholarship on Homer,” 13 and another claimed it was “a kind of
comments on the alleged meaning of rare Homeric words, demonstrating through their
context how Apollonius (dis)agreed with the interpretations offered by previous and
contemporary scholars. 16 He was also concerned with verb‐ and noun‐formation on the basis
of incomplete Homeric paradigms. This is not coincidental: Apollonius himself wrote a
scholarly work on Homer, entitled πρὸς Ζηνόδοτον, in which he apparently attacked the
critical recension of Homer by Zenodotus, his predecessor as head librarian of the
Alexandrian Library. 17 Clearly, his scholarly interests impinged on his poetry, although this
does not mean that his poetry was subsidiary to them. Theocritus, the other poet to be
12 Cf. Pfeiffer (1968: 89), Fantuzzi and Hunter (2004: 23‐6).
13 Knight (1995: 39).
14 Rengakos (2001: 194). On the nature of Hellenistic critical scholarship on Homer, see further Pfeiffer
(1968), Porter (1992: 67‐114), Schmidt (1997: 1‐12) and Van Thiel (1997: 13‐37).
15 See Rengakos (1993); (1994); (2001: 193‐217). Fantuzzi (1988) has calculated that Apollonius uses 102
Homeric hapax legomena not attested since Homer. Of these, he uses 65 in the same metrical position as
Homer. For an idea of the extent of Apollonius’ occupation with Homeric vocabulary, one can also
look at the overwhelming amount of Apollonian Homerisms gathered by Campbell (1981).
16 Cf. Kyriakou (1995: 3‐4); Rengakos (1993 and 2001: 193‐216) provides many examples.
17 Rengakos (2001: 206‐209).
222
discussed here, was not a scholar connected to the Museum, yet his works too demonstrate
“an unrelenting and often learned engagement with (…) in particular the Homeric epics ...” 18
It is not surprising, then, to find that Apollonius and Theocritus both seized on a
Homeric hapax legomenon to express a crucial notion about their poetry. 19 The word in
question is ὑποφήτης (Il. 16.235), 20 which is varied by Apollonius in the Argonautica in the
form ὑποφήτωρ. 21 The significance and connotations of these rare words, which qualify
poets (in Theocritus Id. 16.29; 17.115; 22.116) and inspirational deities (in Apollonius Arg.
1.22), 22 will be analyzed, demonstrating how these poets view revealed knowledge or divine
inspiration. The preoccupation with Homer, Homeric scholarship, and Homeric vocabulary
makes it likely that hapax legomena would stand out for learned readers and convey a
message best understood against the backdrop of the original passage from which it was
taken and the scholarly debate about its interpretation. My discussion of Apollonius’ use of
the word will find itself substantially in agreement with the findings of José González’s
(2000: 270‐292) although his argument will be furthered in Apollonius’ case and expanded in
that of Theocritus, whom he only mentions in passing.
8.3 Overview of other Passages featuring ὑποφήτης
To provide a background against which to interpret the passages in Apollonius and
Theocritus, this section discusses the Homeric passage from which the hapax derives and lists
and analyzes all Hellenistic passages in which the word ὑποφήτης subsequently occurs. It
18 Thus e.g. Sens (1997: 36). Theocritus’ familiarity with Homer is widely agreed upon by scholars from
Gow (1952) to Hunter (1999).
19 On the importance of hapax legomena for the development of Homeric scholarship in general, see
Keil (1998).
20 The only other instances of variants of ὑποφήτης or ὑποφητεία between Homer and the Hellenistic
age are: Pi. P. 2.76: ἄμαχον κακὸν ἀμφοτέροις διαβολιᾶν ύποφάτιες. (a irremedial evil is the mutual
transmission of slander); Hyp. fr. 178.7: τὴν ὑποφῆτιν καὶ ζάκορον Ἀφροδίτης (the prophet and
attendant of Aphrodite).
21 Other attestations of this noun (probably all later): Eus. P. E. 5.8.7.6 (fourth cent. CE) quoting Porph.
De philosophia ex oraculis haurienda 158.7 (third cent. CE); Nonn. Paraphrasis Sancti Evangelii Iohannis
5.157 (fifth cent. CE); AP 14.1 (hard to date, but in all likelihood Hellenistic or later); Ps. Man.
Apotelesmatica 2.295 and 3.326 (third‐fourth cent. CE); P. Oxy 7.1015 (Encomium Theonis Gymnasiarchi,
third cent. CE); P. Berol. 10559A et B (fourth cent. CE); a quotation of Arg. 1.20‐22 in the Scholia ad
Dionysii Periegetae Orbis Descriptionem. Cf. Clauss (1993: 17, n. 13), González (2000: 270).
22 Although the word has a different significance in A.R. Arg. 1.1311, as will be discussed below.
223
must be noted that the word also occurs in Apollonius, in a passage (1.1310‐1320) that will
help to shed light on his use of a variant of the word (ὑποφήτωρ, 1.22) in his proem.
Homer, Iliad 16.233‐238
Il. 16.233‐238 contains Achilles’ prayer to Zeus before Patroclus goes into battle wearing his
friend’s armor. Achilles introduces his prayer with the following hymn‐like invocation:
Ζεῦ ἄνα Δωδωναῖε Πελασγικὲ τηλόθι ναίων
Δωδώνης μεδέων δυσχειμέρου, ἀμφὶ δὲ Σελλοὶ
σοὶ ναίουσ’ ὑποφῆται ἀνιπτόποδες χαμαιεῦναι,
ἠμὲν δή ποτ’ ἐμὸν ἔπος ἔκλυες εὐξαμένοιο,
τίμησας μὲν ἐμέ, μέγα δ’ ἴψαο λαὸν Ἀχαιῶν,
ἠδ’ ἔτι καὶ νῦν μοι τόδ’ ἐπικρήηνον ἐέλδωρ∙ (16.233‐238)
Lord Zeus, Dodonian, Pelasgian, you who live far away, ruler of stormy Dodona,
around you live the Selloi, your ὑποφῆται with feet unwashed, who sleep on the
ground; you have once heard my words in prayer–when you honored me and greatly
harmed the army of the Achaeans–so now also grant this wish of mine…
Achilles prays that Patroclus may avert battle from the Greeks ships and return alive and
well from the fray. As the narrator remarks, Zeus hears (ἔκλυε, 249) Achilles, which initially
creates the impression that the prayer will be granted. 23 But Zeus grants only the first part of
it, saving the Greek ships; he denies Patroclus a safe return:
Ὣς ἔφατ’ εὐχόμενος, τοῦ δ’ ἔκλυε μητίετα Ζεύς.
τῷ δ’ ἕτερον μὲν ἔδωκε πατήρ, ἕτερον δ’ ἀνένευσε… (16.249‐250)
So he spoke, in prayer, and Zeus of wise counsel heard him. And to him the father
granted one thing, but the other he denied...
The passage illustrates how unfathomable the designs and motivations of the gods may be
for humans and how futile human wishes in relation to divine power. The reference to the
Selloi, priests of the oracle of Dodona and intermediaries who explain the will of Zeus from
the sounds of speaking oaks, serves to emphasize this distance between humans and gods:
the word ὑποφῆται may here be translated as “interpreters/revelators/transmitters (of an
23 Cf. Janko (1985: ad loc.).
224
oracle or divine will/plan).” 24 The word is practically synonymous with προφήτης, 25 as the
explanation of the D‐scholia ad loc. confirms: 26
they are interpreters and expounders of the oracle after the priests have received it from the
gods (cf. ὑπομάντεις). This implies a hierarchy: Zeus (speaking through the oak)—priests
(ἱερεῖς, who produce the oracular response)—ὑποφῆται (who publish and interpret this
response)—public. This would seem to echo the practice as it was at Delphi, where the
hierarchy (at least in the classical age) was Apollo—Pythia—προφῆται—public. 27
Aratus, Phaenomena 163‐4
There were many stories about the birth of Zeus and his subsequent upbringing, either by a
goat or nymph called Amalthea or by both. 28 Aratus claims here that Zeus was brought up
by a goat that was catasterized as the star Capella. This is endorsed by his assertion that the
name “Olenian Goat” was given by the ὑποφῆται of Zeus:
Αἲξ ἱερή, τὴν μέν τε λόγος Διὶ μαζὸν ἐπισχεῖν∙
Ὠλενίην δέ μιν Αἶγα Διὸς καλέους’ ὑποφῆται. (163‐4)
The sacred Goat, who is said to have tendered her breast to Zeus: the ὑποφῆται of
Zeus call her the Olenian Goat. (transl. Kidd)
24 On the oracle at Dodona, see in general DNP s.v. Dodona and Parke (1967a and b). The consultation
of the oak was no longer in use in the Hellenistic age.
25 DNP s.v. prophetes: “wörtlich: Sprecher(in) (einer Gottheit). Er/sie deutet oder verkündet den Willen der
Götter (...) Prophetai sind dann (…) Menschen, die durch Audition, Vision, Traum o.ä. Offenbarungen einer
Gottheit empfangen und von ihr beauftragt werden, diese Kunde anderen mitzuteilen.“
26 Cf. González (2000: 277).
27 Cf. McLeod (1961: 317‐325), Parke (1965), Fontenrose (1978), although terminology expressing the
functions could vary. It may be that the scholia’s explanation is based on analogy with Delphic practice
as known from the classical era.
28 The story that Zeus was nursed by a goat was perhaps taken from the Cretan poet‐philosopher‐
historian Epimenides (sixth cent. BCE), cf. Kidd (1997: 242) and DK fr. 21; Str. 8.7.5 claims that there
was a nymph named Amalthea who possessed a goat which nurtured Zeus, cf. Hyg. 2.13.14. Call.
Hymn I, 48‐9 names the goat Amalthea.
225
In Aratus’ view of the cosmos, there is a divinely given name that describes which
catasterism the constellation symbolizes and hence provides significance to each
constellation. 29 Inquiry into the names of these cosmic phenomena constitutes an
interpretative effort as to the divine plan directing the cosmos. This explains why ὑποφῆται
are brought in to endorse the name “Olenian Goat.” They are privy to knowledge of how the
universe works through Zeus’ plan and able to explain this to humankind.
Apollonius, Argonautica 1.1310‐1320
In Arg. 1.1280‐1283, the Argonauts find that, after a stop at Mysia, they have set sail again
without bringing Heracles and Polyphemus. A dispute breaks out among them: should they
return or continue without their shipmates? In the middle of discord, Glaucus, the son of the
seagod Nereus, suddenly rises up out of the water and stops them from turning back:
τοῖσιν δὲ Γλαῦκος βρυχίης ἁλὸς ἐξεφαάνθη,
Νηρῆος θείοιο πολυφράδμων ὑποφήτης∙
(...) καὶ ἴαχεν ἐσσυμένοισιν∙
“Τίπτε παρὲκ μεγάλοιο Διὸς μενεαίνετε βουλήν
Αἰήτεω πτολίεθρον ἄγειν θρασὺν Ἡρακλῆα;
Ἄργεΐ οἱ μοῖρ’ ἐστὶν ἀτασθάλῳ Εὐρυσθῆι
ἐκπλῆσαι μογέοντα δυώδεκα πάντας ἀέθλους,
ναίειν δ’ ἀθανάτοισι συνέστιον, εἴ κ’ ἔτι παύρους
ἐξανύσῃ∙ τῶ μή τι ποθὴ κείνοιο πελέσθω.” (1.1310‐1320)
But to them appeared Glaucus from the depths of the sea, the wise interpreter of
divine Nereus (...) and he cried to the eager crew: ʺWhy against the counsel of mighty
Zeus do you intend to lead bold Heracles to the city of Aeetes? At Argos it is his fate
to labor for insolent Eurystheus and to accomplish full twelve toils and dwell with
the immortals, if so be that he bring to fulfilment a few more yet; so let there be no
vain regret for him.” (transl. Seaton, adapted)
Here too a ὑποφήτης clearly possesses privileged knowledge regarding the will of Zeus
(1.1315). 30 Unlike in the two previous passages, however, the mediator between humans and
29 There seem to be Stoic overtones to this belief, cf. Martin (1967) on Phaen. 1‐18. One could compare
the openly Stoic Zeus of Aratus’ contemporary Cleanthes in his Hymn to Zeus, line 2: Ζεῦ φύσεως
ἀρχηγέ, νόμου μετὰ πάντα κυβερνῶν… (Zeus, ruler of nature, you who steer all with your law…).
On the Stoic influences on Aratus’ view of the cosmos, see further Erren (1967), Effe (1977). Their view
has been nuanced by Kenney (1979). It is still a debated issue.
30 Cf. Feeney (1991: 71).
226
Zeus is a divinity himself. Moreover, Glaucus is not directly a ὑποφήτης of Zeus, but rather
of Nereus, the marine deity. 31 The information concerning the fate of Heracles comes to the
Argonauts from Zeus, via Nereus and Glaucus. 32 This complex way of relaying knowledge
about the divine plan is typical for the difficult communication between humans and gods in
the Argonautica. 33 At the same time, the hierarchical structure implied here is reminiscent of
the hierarchy in the D‐scholia glossing the word ὑποφήτης.
To recapitulate, a ὑποφήτης appears to be a revelatory prophet subordinate to a
divine authority in all of the discussed passages. He may be human (Il. 16.235; Phaen. 164) or
divine (Arg. 1.1311).
8.4 The Μοῦσαι ὑποφήτορες of Apollonius
I am now ready to return to one of the passages which formed the main focus of this chapter,
namely the passage at the end of the proem of Apollonius’ Argonautica 1:
Νῆα μὲν οὖν οἱ πρόσθεν ἔτι κλείουσιν ἀοιδοί
Ἄργον Ἀθηναίης καμέειν ὑποθημοσύνῃσι∙
νῦν δ’ ἂν ἐγὼ γενεήν τε καὶ οὔνομα μυθησαίμην
ἡρώων, δολιχῆς τε πόρους ἁλός, ὅσσα τ’ ἔρεξαν
πλαζόμενοι∙ Μοῦσαι δ’ ὑποφήτορες εἶεν ἀοιδῆς. (Arg. 1.18‐22)
The ship, as former bards relate, Argus wrought by the guidance of Athena. But now
I will tell the lineage and the names of the heroes, and of the long sea‐paths and the
deeds they wrought in their wanderings; may the Muses be the ὑποφήτορες of my
song. (transl. Seaton, adapted)
Because of the occurrence of the hapax ὑποφήτορες, this passage has long been a scholarly
conundrum defying convincing interpretation. 34 The word is not attested before Apollonius
31 Nereus was traditionally known, though not explicitly so in the Argonautica, for his prophetic
powers. The fact that Hesiod calls him ἀψευδέα καὶ ἀληθέα and νημερτής τε καὶ ἤπιος (Theog. 233‐
264) may reflect this belief. In general, all sea‐ and river divinities were believed to possess prophetic
powers.
32 At Soph. Trach. 1166, Heracles relates how he has received a prophecy very similar to the one in Arg.
1.1317‐20 at Dodona, in the wood of the Selloi. This would appear to be a relevant subtext connecting
the passage in Apollonius to the one in Il. 16.235.
33 On the gods in the Argonautica, see e.g. Klein (1931: 18‐51; 215‐257), Faerber (1932: 81‐82), Feeney
(1991: 69‐95), Hunter (1993: 77‐92), Knight (1995: 267‐287). The ignorance and ἀμηχανίη of humans
regarding the will of the gods pervade the epic.
34 E.g. TLG Stephanus (1829) s.v., Gercke (1889: 127‐150), Mooney (1912: ad loc.), Seaton (1912: ad loc.),
Fränkel (1968: ad loc.), Ardizzoni (1969: ad loc.), Paduano‐Faedo (1970: 377‐386), Vian (1971: ad loc.),
227
and only very rarely afterwards. It would seem, therefore, that he has coined it himself as a
variant of ὑποφήτης. 35 Starting out from LSJ’s explanation of the word, “suggester,
interpreter, expounder esp. of divine will or judgment,” the term has been interpreted in
either one of two ways: “suggester” (i.e., de facto: inspirer) or “interpreter.” In the context of
the Apollonian passage, this leads to the respective interpretations “inspirers of my song,” 36
which sounds very traditional, or “interpreters of my song,” 37 which sounds very unusual,
since it is usually held to imply that Apollonius puts himself above the Muse: Apollonius
sings the song while the Muses interpret it for the audience. This second translation would
imply a revolutionary, unique way of presenting the relationship between poet and Muse.
The passage has therefore been interpreted as a triumphant expression of the typically
Hellenistic “anthropocentric” worldview, a rebellion against the traditional subordination to
the gods. 38
It is necessary to study these apparently mutually exclusive meanings (interpreter
and suggester) in closer detail. To begin with, according to the laws of the formation of
nomina agentis in ancient Greek, ὑποφήτωρ should mean the same as ὑποφήτης:
‐tēr and ‐tōr occurs in nouns of relationship and in agent nouns. The agent nouns in ‐
tēr and ‐tōr are numerous despite their extensive displacement by ‐tēs and ‐tas. (…) As
a productive type of agent nouns this [i.e., the type of agent nouns ending in ‐tēr and
‐tōr] was displaced in Attic‐Ionic prose, and partly elsewhere by that in ‐tēs and –tas.
(…) But the older type [i.e., in ‐tēr and ‐tōr] still continued in use in poetry, including
Attic tragedy, and was even to some extent productive, since the later poets came to
feel that ‐tēr and ‐tōr was a stylistic device that might be freely substituted for ‐tēs. 39
This means ὑποφήτης and ὑποφήτωρ have practically the same meaning, which makes the
Muses in Apollonius “interpreters.” This has however frequently been challenged by
Fusillo (1985: 365‐6), Feeney (1991: 90‐1), Goldhill (1991: 290‐1), Clauss (1993: 17‐18), Hunter (1993:
125), Albis (1996: 20‐1), González (2000: 270‐290), Hunter (2001: 99); Cuypers (2004: 47‐8).
35 Apollonius was not averse to supplementing incomplete Homeric verbal paradigms; analogously,
he may have tampered with prefixes and suffixes of nouns and adjectives to coin new formations.
Rengakos (1994) does not discuss the word, because it is not strictly Homeric in its own right, but
merely derivative.
36 E.g. Seaton (1888: 84‐85), Mooney (1912: ad loc.), Fränkel (1968: ad loc.), Ardizzoni (1969: ad loc.), Vian
(1974: ad loc.), Green (1997: ad loc.). For a more complete bibliography: Fusillo (1985: 357 n. 16).
37 Gercke (1889: 127‐150), Paduano Faedo (1970: 377‐386), Vian (1974: ad loc.), Fusillo (1985: 365‐7),
Feeney (1991: 90‐1), Goldhill (1991: 290‐1), Clauss (1993: 17‐18), Hunter (1993: 125).
38 Paduano Faedo (1970: 377‐386).
39 Buck and Petersen (1984: 544‐546), cf. Risch (1974: 28). Benveniste (1948: 56) notes that there may be
a difference in nuance: ‐tēs and ‐tēr express “l’agent d’une fonction”; ‐tōr expresses “l’acteur d’une acte.” It
is hard to establish whether this nuance was still felt in Apollonius’ time.
228
critics, 40 who refuse to accept that the Muses could have been represented in ancient
literature as anything but “inspirers.” 41 Should we then accept the idea that the Muses are
called “interpreters of my song” by Apollonius? 42 But why should the Muses be presented in
1.22 as interpreters of Apollonius’ song to the audience when Apollonius’ attitude towards
them in the other invocations is so much more traditional? 43 This has been explained as
follows: Apollonius starts out boldly, but gradually pretends to lose confidence in his poetic
abilities as he tells his story. Eventually, he feels forced to return to the traditional model
where the Muse is hierarchically placed above him. 44 However, in reality, there are no cogent
reasons to assume that Apollonius does anything as extraordinary as placing the Muses
below him. The solution to the problem of the meaning “interpreter” may be found in a
comparison of the passage at 1.20‐22 with the use of the words ὑποφήτης and ὑποφήτωρ in
other passages (within and outside of the Argonautica) and in the correct interpretation of the
context of the Argonautica’s proem, as was first recognized by González. 45
As we saw in all passages discussed above, a ὑποφήτης is an individual
revealing/interpreting the will of a higher (divine) entity. This parallels the use of the word
ὑποφήτωρ in post‐Apollonian practice. 46 Instead of understanding the Muses as the
interpreters of Apollonius’ song for the benefit of the audience, therefore, a higher entity
whose will the Muses reveal or interpret should be sought. Turning to the context of the
invocation, that is to say, the proem of the Argonautica, it is obvious who this higher
authority must be: “Starting from you Phoebus, I will recall the fame of men born long ago,”
(Ἀρχόμενος σέο Φοῖβε παλαιγενέων κλέα φωτῶν / μνήσομαι, Arg. 1.1‐2).
From this passage, it transpires that the god Phoebus Apollo, traditionally the
“Mousagetes,” the leader of the Muses 47 as well as the god of prophecy and of song, must be
40 Seaton (1888: 84‐85), Mooney (1912: ad loc.), Fränkel (1968: ad loc.), Ardizzoni (1969: ad loc.), Vian
(1974: ad loc.), Green (1997 ad loc.) and Fusillo (1985: 357 n. 16).
41 Yet, one could argue that the dialogue of Callimachus and the Muses in Aetia 1‐2 is another example
of an untraditional way of representing this relationship.
42 A notion supported first by Gercke (1889: 135‐136).
43 Most notably at Arg. 3.1‐5; 4, 1‐4; 4.1381‐1382, on which see below.
44 E.g. Hunter (1987: 134), (1993: 105); Feeney (1991: 90‐91).
45 González (2000: 270‐292).
46 González (2000: 285‐290) demonstrates this by an elaborate syntactic analysis of the post‐Hellenistic
occurrences of the word ὑποφήτωρ.
47 Pi. fr. 94c Snell‐Maehler.
229
understood as the provider of the Muses’ knowledge. 48 Apollo is specifically invoked as the
god of oracles here, since the name “Phoebus” indicates him particularly in his Delphic or
Pythian incarnation. 49 To reinforce this emphasis, his associates the Muses are indicated with
the word ὑποφήτορες. This term, with its Homeric reminiscences, reminds the reader of the
oracle of Dodona, where the prophetic Selloi resided. Moreover, the oaks of Dodona
provided the prophetically speaking timber that built the Argo. 50 The oracular connection is
thus emphasized from the outset of the epic, 51 determining its theme, the Argo’s journey,
and its poetics, which will be discussed below.
As has already been noted, Apollo plays an important role throughout the narrative
of the Argonautica (cf. Chapter 3.6). The hymnic invocation to him indicates that he is
connected to its theme and its poet, his near namesake (cf. Chapter 7.3). However, this does
not mean, as Albis suggests, that ἀοιδή (1.22) should be equated with the oracle Apollo gave
to Pelias, referred to in lines 5 and 8. 52 A more convincing interpretation is that the Muses are
proleptically asked to reveal/transmit the “material for the song” (i.e., ἀοιδή), to Apollonius,
who turns it into a song. 53 In this set‐up, the Muses act as Pythia‐like priestesses of Apollo,
relaying his oracular utterances about the past to Apollonius. The resulting epic is a
translation of Apollo’s inspiration (an oracle relating to the past conveyed to the poet by the
Muses) into hexameter verse. 54 Apollo thus combines his qualities of inspirational god of
poetry (20) and god of prophecy (5, 8) at the beginning of this epic. 55
48 Albis (1996: 19‐21) had already suggested this interpretation but with different conclusions. To him
the Muses become suggesters or inspirers after all. González (2000: 270‐292) was the first to come up
with the correct interpretation of the translation interpreters.
49 Cf. the explanation of the name Phoebus in Aesch. Eum. 1‐8 and in HH Apollo. See on this latter text
Càssola (1997: ad loc.), Strauss‐Clay (2006).
50 Arg. 1.527; 4.580‐3, cf. Parke (1967: 17).
51 Among the Argonauts Mopsus is a prophet (or should we say hypophet?) of the oracle at Dodona,
while the prophet Idmon is a son of Apollo.
52 Albis (1996: 19).
53 González (2000: 281‐2) does not see it this way and consequently hesitates to whom the song should
be attributed, Apollo or Apollonius.
54 Cf. e.g. McLeod (1961: 317‐325) as to the existence of oral bards at the sanctuary at Delphi, who
formed the Pythia’s incomprehensible and unconnected shouts into hexameters. McLeod conjectures
that they are to be identified with the προφῆται officiating at Delphi. The idea that Apollonius
analogously translated the Muses’ oracles into poetry has also been explored by Albis (1996: 20).
González regards it as a “facile equation.”
55 The fact that Apollo is invoked earlier on and much more prominently than the Muses confirms that
the Muses are his subordinates, González (2000: 283).
230
Such “mantic” investigation of the far past, hidden by intervening eras, is an activity
that, like the search for truth about future events, was recognized by the Greeks as prophecy,
the interpretation of divine revelation. 56 Indeed, many oracles did not predict the future so
much as indicate which event in the past had occasioned a god’s wrath that needed to be
appeased. 57 The activity of the epic poet who traditionally told of events that took place long
before was in many ways similar to that of the prophet. 58 As West writes:
In the absence of written records the ability to see into the distant past is no less
miraculous than the ability to see into the future, and there is no room for a sharp
distinction between the two. Neither is possible without divine revelation, for only
gods have the necessary first‐hand knowledge. (West, 1966 ad Theog. 32)
This relates to the function argued for Apollonius’ Apollo and his servants, the Muses. Not
only does he give the oracles about future events to the Argonauts at the time of their
expedition through various seers, he also provides the poet Apollonius with inspiration and
knowledge relating to the same events, now long past, via his interpreters, the Muses. From
Apollo both the poet and the Argonauts receive information about the events that make up
the Argonautica: he is its fountainhead and this is why Apollonius begins his epic with an
invocation of him.
56 Cuypers (2004: 47) remarks that the Muses seem to be “the opposite of prophets” who “provide
insight into the past in the manner divinely inspired prophets provide insight into the future:
uncertainty remains.” However, “normal” prophets often provide insight into the past as well.
Moreover, in Arg. 1.1311ff, the hypophetes Glaucus refers to the future fate of Heracles.
57 Cf. e.g. Il. 1.59‐67, where Achilles proposes to ask a prophet to find out what has angered Apollo,
and what can be done to appease his anger; Calchas (1.69‐70 ff) does exactly that.
58 Hes. Theog. 31‐3: ἐνέπνευσαν δέ μοι αὐδὴν / θέσπιν, ἵνα κλείοιμι τά τ’ ἐσσόμενα πρό τ’ ἐόντα, /
καί μ’ ἐκέλονθ’ ὑμνεῖν μακάρων γένος αἰὲν ἐόντων. (They breathed into me a divine voice, so that I
might be able to celebrate the future and the past and they ordered me to hymn the race of the blessed
who live forever). Apollo appears to play a certain part in this investiture, through the laurel (Th. 30).
On the difficulty of ascertaining what future prediction Hesiod is referring to, cf. West (1966: 166),
Tigerstedt (1970: 172‐3). Cf. further Il. 1.69‐70: Κάλχας Θεστορίδης οἰωνοπόλων ὄχ’ ἄριστος, / ὃς ᾔδη
τά τ’ ἐόντα τά τ’ ἐσσόμενα πρό τ’ ἐόντα. (Calchas, the son of Thestor, the best of augurs, who knew
the present, the future and the past). Cf. further Epimenides, who chose only to prophesy about the far
past (fr. B4 DK). An epic poem is attributed to him about the building of the Argo and the voyage of
Jason to Colchis in 6500 lines (Diog. Laert. 1.111). It is hard to establish the truth of this claim, and the
relevance of it to Apollonius’ epic (cf. Huxley, 1969: 60), but the coincidence is striking.
231
8.5 Apollonius’ View on Poetic Inspiration
The word ὑποφήτωρ has now been interpreted in its context, but what further consequences
does this representation of the Muses have for Apollonius’ view of poetic inspiration? If
Apollonius’ knowledge derives from oracles, it is important to remember that “uncertainty
this hiddenness of divine purposes is subtly alluded to by Achilles’ mention of the Selloi,
priests necessary to interpret the will of Zeus. 60 Inscrutability of divine motives is also a
major theme of the Argonautica, as scholars agree. It is attractive to consider the relevance of
this theme for the presentation of the relationship between narrator and Muses. Apollonius’
representation of divine inspiration differs from the previous tradition mainly in the fact that
he questions how the Muses get their knowledge. The locus classicus with regard to this issue,
as noted above, is Il. 2.484‐286, where the Muses are presented as omnipresent and
omniscient. 61 According to Apollonius, however, the Muses themselves are not omniscient
per se but dependent on information they receive from Apollo, who is hierarchically above
them. Apollonius apparently felt that there was a hint of subordination in the word
ὑποφήτης (and by implication ὑποφήτωρ), which he exploited in this passage. The
presentation of Glaucus also illustrates this (Arg. 1.1311). He is called the ὑποφήτης of
Nereus, who has charged him with conveying the will of Zeus (1.1315) to the Argonauts. The
fact that a divinity may be called a ὑποφήτης confirms that some gods are subordinate to
others. They do not possess omniscience merely by virtue of their divinity. The hierarchy
Muses in 1.20‐22. The oracles of Apollo (Arg. 1.5; 8) may have set events in motion, but they
are not the ultimate cause of the expedition; they are in turn an expression of the inscrutable
plan of Zeus, as appears at other instances in the epic. 62 So the hierarchy is: Zeus—Apollo—
Muses—Apollonius—audience. 63
59 Formulation Cuypers (2004: 47); for the idea, cf. González (2000: 269) and Feeney (1991: 57‐98,
passim).
60 González (2000: 275‐278).
61 Cf. e.g. Murray (1981: 90‐91), de Jong (1987: 51).
62 Cf. the passage discussed earlier, Arg. 1.1310‐1320. On the inscrutability of the will of Zeus in the
Argonautica and its connection with the oracles of Apollo, cf. Feeney (1991: 59‐67).
63 Cf. Pl. Ion 533d‐e where poetic inspiration is compared to magnetism: like a magnet infuses its
power into an iron ring, which in turn attracts other iron rings, so the Muse inspires poets, who in
232
The passage at 1.20‐22, standing as it does at the opening of the epic, must be
considered programmatic for Apollonius’ treatment of revealed knowledge and inspiration
in general. Particularly in combination with the varied representation of the Muses in the rest
of the epic, it is significant for the point Apollonius tries to make: poetic inspiration is not a
straightforward or simple process, but a problematic, equivocal, and complex one consisting
appears to doubt their information 66 or reluctantly relates it, 67 and sometimes even speaks
against the will of the Muses, 68 this should be interpreted as illustrating various facets of
Apollonius’ knowledge about the past.
Some remarks may illustrate this. Apart from his remarkably varied invocations of
the Muses, the narrator occasionally emphasizes his qualms about the truth of his narrative
by his use of the particle που (I suppose), which normally marks statements as assumptions,
not as the certainties of an omniscient narrator. 69 This kind of usage is never found in
utterances of the omniscient narrator of the Homeric epics and is more congenial to a
narrator of a work of historiography wishing to express his reservations when his sources
are in conflict. 70 Clearly, then, Apollonius does not represent himself as an omniscient
narrator receiving unequivocal or directly comprehensible information from the Muses; it is
turn infuse their “enthusiasm” into their audience. In Apollonius’ case, the hierarchy is extended
upwardly, to include Apollo and Zeus.
64 Contrast González (2000: 270‐292), who tries to homogenize the invocations.
65 As he clearly does at 3.1‐4: Εἰ δ’ ἄγε νῦν ᾿Ερατώ, παρ’ ἔμ’ ἵστασο καί μοι ἔνισπε… (Come now,
Erato, stand by me and tell me...); 4.1‐5: Αὐτὴ νῦν κάματόν γε θεὰ καὶ δήνεα κούρης / Κολχίδος
ἔννεπε Μοῦσα, Διὸς τέκος. (You must tell me yourself now, goddess, the suffering and wiles of the
Colchian girl, Muse, daughter of Zeus...); 4. 552‐7: Αλλὰ θεαί, πῶς... (But goddesses, how...?); 4.1381‐
8: Μουσάων ὅδε μῦθος, ἐγὼ δ’ ὑπακουὸς ἀείδω / Πιερίδων, καὶ τήνδε πανατρεκὲς ἔκλυον ὀμφήν.
(This is the tale of the Muses and I sing obediently to the Pierides, and this report did I hear quite
clearly.).
66 Cf. e.g. at Arg. 1.24, where the verb φατίζεται (it is told) clashes strangely with the invocation of the
Muses two lines earlier, cf. Cuypers (2004: 50).
67 Arg. 2.844‐5: εἰ δέ με καὶ τό / χρειὼ ἀπηλεγέως Μουσέων ὕπο γηρύσασθαι... (If at the bidding of
the Muses I must tell this tale outright...).
68 Arg. 4.984‐5: ἵλατε Μοῦσαι, / οὐκ ἐθέλων ἐνέπω προτέρων ἔπος... (Be gracious, Muses, unwillingly
do I tell this tale of olden days...).
69 Cuypers (2005: 41‐45). Examples: 1.636; 1.972‐975; 1.996‐7; 1.1023; 1.1037; 1.1140; 1.1222; 2.607; 2.1028;
3.926; 3.1457, 3.1397; 4.557‐8. Knight (1995: 269) mentions “Apollonius’ concern with partial
knowledge, mistaken belief and incomplete revelation.” Cf. Feeney (1991: 88‐90).
70 Cuypers (2004: 46) remarks upon “Apollonius’ negotiation of the seemingly incompatible rhetorical
strategies of the epic storyteller who knows and states, inspired by the Muses, and the historian who
argues from evidence.” On the difference between the narrative voices of the Argonautica and the
Homeric epics, see Hunter (1993: 101‐119).
233
not something the Muses always may or will provide. This acknowledgement of the
problematic character of information relating to the past may be read as a metaphor for
Apollonius’ own negotiation of sources and informed invention about that past. 71 That
practically all information relating to the Greek past was stored in the Mouseion (lit. “shrine
of the Muses”), an institution with cultic associations of which Apollonius was the director,
may well be relevant to this particular conception of poetic inspiration. 72 The Muses would
not always provide unambiguous information; likewise, the documents in the Museum
might not provide clarity on all aspects of the distant past. They might contradict each other,
evoke doubts, relate incredible stories, or simply be silent on certain matters.
8.6 Parallels to Apollonius’ Representation of the Muses
In the Odyssey, Odysseus compliments Demodocus on his singing skills by saying “the
Muses must have taught you, or Apollo.” In this conception, Apollo and the Muses are both
related to the art of the bard, but there is no sign of a hierarchy between them. The poetry of
Apollonius’ contemporaries, however, does provide parallels of such hierarchies in which
the Muses function as transmitters subordinate to a higher authority. Aratus is one such
author. He begins his didactic poem as follows:
Ἐκ Διὸς ἀρχώμεσθα, τὸν οὐδέποτ’ ἄνδρες ἐῶμεν
ἄρρητον∙ μεσταὶ δὲ Διὸς πᾶσαι μὲν ἀγυιαί,
πᾶσαι δ’ ἀνθρώπων ἀγοραί, μεστὴ δὲ θάλασσα
καὶ λιμένες∙ πάντη δὲ Διὸς κεχρήμεθα πάντες.
Τοῦ γὰρ καὶ γένος εἰμέν. Ὁ δ’ ἤπιος ἀνθρώποισι
δεξιὰ σημαίνει ... (Ph. 1‐6)
71 Cuypers (2004: 47) thinks that some Muse‐invocations (e.g. 4.984‐85) resist such a reading. But the
fact that Apollonius here pretends to be telling a story the Muses dislike constitutes a reference to Pl.
Resp. 377e, where it is said that the tale of Cronus’ castration (referred to in Arg. 4.985‐6) is better not
told. In addition, it points to the fact that Apollonius here disagrees with Call. Aet. fr. 43.69‐71 Pf.
about the island at which the sickle that castrated Cronus was kept, cf. Livrea (1973: ad loc.). This
invocation addresses the conflicting traditions surrounding this story, and at the discussion of what is
fitting (prepon) in epic.
72 On the religious overtones of the Mouseion and its employees, see Fraser (1972: I, 324), Weber (1993:
353), Too (1998: 119). Diod. Sic. (1.49.3) calls the Alexandrian library “sacred.” For a remarkable
parallel, cf. Ath. 634c‐d on the famous scholar Aristarchus: Ἀρίσταρχος ὁ γραμματικός, ὃν μάντιν
ἐκάλει Παναίτιος ὁ Ῥόδιος φιλόσοφος διὰ τὸ ῥᾳδίως καταμαντεύεσθαι τῆς τῶν ποιημάτων
διανοίας. (Aristarchus the grammarian, whom Panaetius of Rhodes the philosopher called a seer,
through his great ability to interpret the deeper meaning of poems).
234
Let us begin with Zeus, whom we men never leave unspoken. Filled with Zeus are all
highways and all meetingplaces of people, filled are the sea and the harbors; in all
circumstances we are all dependent on Zeus. (transl. Kidd)
In this proem, Aratus presents his poetic venture as a way of translating the omnipresent
signs of Zeus (especially the heavenly bodies) into humanly comprehensible language, in
this case didactic poetry. For this undertaking, as he later states, he also needs the Muses,
who will point out to him (τεκμήρατε, 18) how he is to name the stars (ἀστέρας εἰπεῖν, 17)
and interpret them so that they will become a song. It may be assumed that the Muses
receive this information from Zeus, who initially designed and ordered the heavens: 73
Χαῖρε, πάτερ, μέγα θαῦμα, μέγ’ ἀνθρώποισιν ὄνειαρ,
αὐτὸς καὶ προτέρη γενεή. Χαίροιτε δὲ Μοῦσαι
μειλίχιαι μάλα πᾶσαι. Ἐμοί γε μὲν ἀστέρας εἰπεῖν
ᾗ θέμις εὐχομένῳ τεκμήρατε πᾶσαν ἀοιδήν. (Phaen. 15‐18)
Hail, Father, great wonder, great boon to men, yourself and the earlier race! And hail,
Muses, all most gracious! In answer to my prayer to tell of the stars in so far as I may,
guide all my singing. (transl. Kidd)
In this passage, then, the poet is presented as receiving information about the plan of the
uppermost divinity Zeus through the intercession of the Muses. 74 In reality, Aratus’ source of
inspiration and knowledge about the heavenly bodies was the prose treatise of the fourth‐
century astronomer Eudoxus. 75 In a similar way, Apollonius plunders the works of earlier
historians and geographers to describe the Argonautic journey as if relying on “revealed
knowledge” reaching him from Apollo through the Muses.
Another parallel, albeit of a slightly different nature, for Apollonius’ representation of
divine inspiration and the difficulty of shaping it into poetry may be found in Lycophron’s
Alexandra. 76 In this poem, Apollo inspires the Trojan prophetess Cassandra about the fate of
Troy and all that will happen afterwards; her enigmatic prophecy is relayed by a messenger
to her father, King Priam, as a narratological analysis of this poem shows:
73 Cf. the implication of the title of the Diosèmeia, a lost didactic work of Aratus.
74 Another less elaborate parallel may perhaps be found in the opening of Posidipp. AB 118. εἴ τι
καλόν, Μοῦσαι πολιήτιδες, ἢ παρὰ Φοίβου / χρυσολύρεω καθαροῖς οὔασιν ἐκλ[ύ]ετε... (If ever,
Muses of my city, you have with pure ears heard anything beautiful, either from Phoebus of the
golden lyre...), cf. Ch. 6.4.
75 Cf. Ch. 5.2.
76 On the dating of this enigmatic poem, cf. Kosmetatou (2000: 32‐53). It is possibly much later than the
works discussed here.
235
The key thing about Apollo as a narrator [in the Alexandra] is that he does not, strictly
speaking, narrate; rather he instills narrative content directly into the consciousness
of its recipient [i.e., Cassandra]. In effect, this is narrative unmediated by any form of
actual narration, and part of Cassandra’s problem is that the fabula instilled in her—
the whole of human history—has no intrinsic or pre‐formed narrative shape; it is up
to her to give it one… (Lowe, 2004: 309)
Apollo’s inspiration in this poem is once more an expression of the plan of Zeus, so the
Apollo—Muses–Apollonius—audience). The Argonautica illustrates the problems accrued by
the hierarchically relayed oracular information about the past through emphasizing the
unepic insecurity of the narrator. In the Alexandra, on the other hand, the difficulty of
interpreting oracles about the future and shaping them into a narrative is dramatically
embodied in the deliberately enigmatic language that made Lycophron notorious. This could
be read as Lycophron’s way of expressing the difficulties of the task of representing facts his
audience knew as myth and history as an oracle about future events.
8.7 The Theocritean Passages
I now turn to the passages in Theocritus’ Idylls where poets are named ὑποφῆται. To
determine whether any connection exists between them, a look at the broader context of the
poems in which they occur is necessary. In the first place, all three poems play with the
format of hymn poetry. 78 A unifying theme underlies them, namely the procuring of κλέος
(fame in song) by the poet for the dedicatees. In each of the poems, this process is somehow
problematic.
8.7.1 Idyll 16: κλέος and Prophecy
Idyll 16 has been named an “Enkomium der Zukunft” (Vahlen 1883: 211) because it
predominantly expresses wishes for the future instead of enumerating laudable past
77 Although in the Alexandra, where there is no external narrator, these last two categories remain
implicit.
78 Forms of ὕμνος / ὑμνεῖν in 16.2 (twice); 50; 103; 17.8 (twice) 22.1; 4; 10; 26; 135; 214; 219. On the
remarkable popularity of hymnic poetry in the Ptolemaic age, see Hunter (1996: 46‐48). On the close
parallels between the opening of 16 and 17 and the HH, see Fantuzzi (2001: 232‐233, n. 1).
236
accomplishments. This has been explained by the fact that Hiero II of Syracuse, the laudandus
of the poem, had not done anything by the time Theocritus wrote his encomium. 79 In the
poem, the word ὑποφῆται occurs (16.22‐31) in an offer of advice about the best way to spend
money:
Δαιμόνιοι, τί δὲ κέρδος ὁ μυρίος ἔνδοθι χρυσός
κείμενος; οὐχ ἅδε πλούτου φρονέουσιν ὄνασις,
ἀλλὰ τὸ μὲν ψυχᾷ, τὸ δέ πού τινι δοῦναι ἀοιδῶν∙
πολλοὺς δ´εὖ ἔρξαι πηῶν, πολλοὺς δὲ καὶ ἄλλων
ἀνθρώπων, αἰεὶ δὲ θεοῖς ἐπιβώμια ῥέζειν,
μηδὲ ξεινοδόκον κακὸν ἔμμεναι ἀλλὰ τραπέζῃ
μειλίξαντ’ ἀποπέμψαι ἐπὴν ἐθέλωντι νέεσθαι,
Μοισάων δὲ μάλιστα τίειν ἱεροὺς ὑποφήτας.
ὄφρα καὶ εἰν Ἀίδαο κεκρυμμένος ἐσθλὸς ἀκούσῃς,
μηδ’ ἀκλεὴς μύρηαι ἐπὶ ψυχροῦ Ἀχέροντος... (16.22‐31)
Fools, what gain is it, the gold that lies uncounted in your coffers? Herein is not, to
thinking men, the profit of wealth, but rather to be generous to one’s own desires,
and to some poet too, maybe; to do kindness to many of one’s kin, and to many too of
other folk; and ever to sacrifice to the altars of the gods, nor play the churlish host,
but to treat the stranger kindly at one’s board and speed him when he would be
gone; but most of all to honor the holy ὑποφῆται of the Muses, that even when you
are hidden in Hades you may be well spoken of and not mourn unhonored on the
chill shore of Acheron... (transl. Gow, adapted)
In this passage, ὑποφήτας (29) looks like a doublure of the more usual term for poets, ἀοιδοί
(24). 80 It seems unsubtle on the part of Theocritus to advise Hiero twice in the compass of
five lines to spend his money on poets, so it is attractive to assume that the two words
indicate two different types of singers. This may be explained as follows (cf. Chapter 2.3): in
5‐21, Theocritus complains that people are not prepared anymore to spend money on living
poets who may earn them κλέος. They think the poets of the past are enough. This is a
serious misunderstanding, as Theocritus, with an eye on his own profit, duly attempts to
point out. To procure fame, one needs the inspiration of the Muses and must sing of a
contemporary human subject. 81 This inspiration is not the same as the ability to perform the
79 So already Schol. ad 16 (Wendel 1914: 325), Gow (1952: II, 305‐307), Griffiths (1979: 12‐6); contrast
Hunter (1996: 77‐8), who thinks this is merely a topical fiction.
80 Wifstrand (1963: 309) reads 16.29 as a recapitulation, and stresses the connection between μάλιστα
and ὄφρα.
81 Cf. 16.58: Ἐκ Μοισᾶν ἀγαθὸν κλέος ἔρχεται ἀνθρώποισι. (From the Muses comes noble fame for
men); 69‐70: χαλεπαὶ γὰρ ὁδοὶ τελέθουσιν ἀοιδοῖς / κουράων ἀπάνευθε Διὸς μέγα βουλεύοντος.
237
songs of dead poets about the gods or the heroes of the past. Hence, Theocritus distinguishes
between the ἀοιδοί of line 24 (rhapsodes) and the ὑποφῆται Μοισάων of 29 (creative poets),
who are able to provide the living with κλέος. 82
The claim that it is the specific privilege of ὑποφῆται to glorify the living sits very
well with what Maehler remarks about the analogous expression “prophet of the Muses” in
Pindar: 83
Das erinnert an die alte Vorstellung die hinter dem Homerischen ἄνδρα μοι ἔννεπε
Μοῦσα steht, aber schon bei Homer war das zum bloßen Klischee geworden, und während die
homerischen Sänger einfach berichten wollen‚ was sich zugetragen hat, und sich nur darum
bemühen müssen es κατὰ κόσμον d.h. möglichst genau und vollständig zu tun, ist das was
Pindar zu verkünden hat viel prinzipieller verborgen; er will nicht das Geschehen berichten,
sondern das edle rühmen, aber eben das sieht er in Frage gestellt und von dem „blinden Sinn“
der Leute verkannt. (Maehler, 1963: 98)
Like Pindar, Theocritus identifies the specific power of the Muse‐inspired poet in this context
particularly as the ability to provide ἀγαθὸν κλέος to the living. To do so, he does not need
to make the Muse subordinate to another god, but presents her in her traditional guise of
purveyor of divine knowledge and wisdom, a goddess in her own right. The poet is her
priest and interpreter; Apollo has no place in this concept.
Nevertheless, the emphatic return to the concept of “prophet of the Muses” is
remarkable, since it shows that Theocritus, like Apollonius, seeks to return to the ancient
(mantic/vatic) origins of poetry in his self‐representation: poet and prophet apparently have
to be reunited if poetry is to be successful in this new age. This is confirmed by the
emphatically oracular prediction of the triumphant emergence of the dedicatee, a heroic
Hiero who will scare away the Carthaginians (71‐81). 84 In this poem, revealed knowledge
coming from the Muses clearly is not enigmatic and does not relate to the past. It is,
however, the exclusive possession of the (inspired) poet.
(For the roads are difficult for singers without the help of the daughters of Zeus of the mighty
counsel).
82 He is not consistent in this distinction; in the rest of the poem both poets and rhapsodes are referred
to by the word ἀοιδός. At 16.103 it seems there is a complete merging of rhapsodes, Muse‐inspired
singers and creative poets, all striving to sing the praises of Hiero and Syracuse. It is of course Hiero
who enables this profusion (and fusion) of poetry.
83 Pi. fr. 150 Snell‐Maehler and Paean fr. 52F6 Snell‐Maehler.
84 E.g. 16.73: ἔσσεται οὗτος ἀνὴρ ὃς ἐμεῦ κεχρήσετ’ ἀοιδοῦ... Cf. Gow (1952: II, 320): “emphatic
prophecy,” Dover (1971: ad loc.): “His language is a shade oracular.” For the tone, cf. e.g. Il. 4.164:
ἔσσεται ἧμαρ.
238
8.7.2 Idyll 17: Immortal Fame for an Immortal King
In Idyll 17 Theocritus, wishing to provide the king of Egypt with fame, encounters another
kind of problem. 85 At first sight, Ptolemy Philadelphus appears eminently fit for celebration
in song because of his achievements (77‐105). Unlike Hiero, he is moreover willing to pay
poets for this favor (106‐117). Clearly, then, he should be able to gain as much κλέος as he
wants:
οὐδὲ Διωνύσου τις ἀνὴρ ἱεροὺς κατ’ ἀγῶνας
ἵκετ’ ἐπιστάμενος λιγυρὰν ἀναμέλψαι ἀοιδάν,
ᾧ οὐ δωτίναν ἀντάξιον ὤπασε τέχνας
Μουσάων δ’ ὑποφῆται ἀείδοντι Πτολεμαῖον
ἀντ’ εὐεργεσίης. τί δὲ κάλλιον ἀνδρί κεν εἴη
ὀλβίῳ ἢ κλέος ἐσθλὸν ἐν ἀνθρώποισιν ἀρέσθαι;
τοῦτο καὶ Ἀτρεΐδαισι μένει∙ τὰ δὲ μυρία τῆνα
ὅσσα μέγαν Πριάμοιο δόμον κτεάτισσαν ἑλόντες
ἀέρι πᾳ κέκρυπται, ὅθεν πάλιν οὐκέτι νόστος. (17.112‐120)
And never comes there for the sacred contests of Dionysus one skilled to raise his
clear‐voiced song but he receives the gift his art deserves and those ὑποφῆται of the
Muses sing of Ptolemy for his benefactions. And for a prosperous man what finer aim
is there than to win him goodly fame on earth? That is abiding even for the House of
Atreus, while the countless treasure won when they took the great halls of Priam lies
hidden somewhere in that darkness whence there is no return. (transl. Gow, adapted)
Traditional though the thought expressed here may be, there is something remarkably odd
about this passage, since, considering whom he is addressing it seems as if Theocritus “flirts
with disaster,” because “such a memento mori seems like a fatal misjudgement at the
christening of a new and, by its own insistence, immortal dynasty” (Griffiths, 1979: 81).
Indeed, this is Theocritus’ problem: Ptolemy is no mere mortal: 86
Μοῦνος ὅδε προτέρων τε καὶ ὧν ἔτι θερμὰ κονία
στειβομένα καθύπερθε ποδῶν ἐκμάσσεται ἴχνη,
ματρὶ φίλᾳ καὶ πατρὶ θυώδεας εἵσατο ναούς∙ (17.121‐123)
Of men of old and of those the imprint of whose steps still warm the trodden dust
holds beneath the foot, Ptolemy alone has founded fragrant shrines for his dear
mother and his father... (transl. Gow)
85 Cf. Goldhill (1991: 277) who remarks upon “the difficulty of discovering a strategy of celebration
which is adequate to the new circumstances of the Ptolemaic dynastic rule, but which is not
diminished in contrast with the great tradition of Greek encomiastic verse.”
86 Cf. Goldhill (1991: 279‐280). Hunter (2003: 149) merely remarks: “Gods may have higher rewards,
but ὀλβίωι (120) reminds Ptolemy of his privileged position (sc. among mankind).”
239
Would such a king still need a poet to gain him κλέος and save him from oblivion after
death? The immortality of his parents seems to imply at least that, once Philadelphus himself
departs from this world, he will be among the gods on Olympus; he will certainly never be
“nameless and forgotten, wailing on the banks of cold Acheron.” 87 How does Theocritus
approach this problem in the rest of the poem? Is there a way out?
Lines 17.16‐33 have already sketched the immortal existence on Olympus of Ptolemy
Soter, Philadelphus’ father. The tone of the passage is strikingly similar to that of for instance
the Homeric Hymns to (Olympic) divinities, in its use of a quasi omni‐temporal present tense
to describe the actions of the divine Ptolemy Soter. 88 In setting the scene on Olympus, it
moreover provides an insight that is normally inaccessible to ordinary mortals. The
implication of the passage is therefore that only a vessel of the revealed knowledge of the
Muses is able to envisage this scene. 89 This is of course where the Μουσάων ὑποφῆται (119)
necessarily come in, among whom Theocritus may once more be reckoned. 90 Although
Ptolemy clearly does not need to fear oblivion in Hades like his mortal contemporaries, even
he, immortal as he is, needs a poet. This had in fact already been acknowledged in the phrase
ὕμνοι δὲ καὶ ἀθανάτων γέρας αὐτῶν (hymns are the gift of honor even for the gods, 8). 91 If
Ptolemy is a god, he will need hymns; hymns are the province of the Μουσάων ὑποφῆται.
Having more or less solved the problem thus, Theocritus ends his encomiastic hymn on a
prophetic note once more: 92
Χαῖρε, ἄναξ Πτολεμαῖε∙ σέθεν δ’ ἐγὼ ἶσα καὶ ἄλλων
μνάσομαι ἡμιθέων, δοκέω δ’ ἔπος οὐκ ἀπόβλητον
φθέγξομαι ἐσσομένοις· ἀρετήν γε μὲν ἐκ Διὸς αἰτεῦ. (135‐137)
87 Id. 16.30‐1, this is the fate that awaits Hiero should he not employ a poet.
88 E.g. Id. 17.19: ἑδριάει; 22: θαλίας ἔχει; 25: ἀθάνατοι δὲ καλεῦνται; 30: ἐδῶκεν (gnomic aorist).
89 Cf. Call. Ektheosis Arsinoes (fr. 228Pf.), which is located on Olympus as well. The opening phrase of
the fragment (Ἀγέτω θεός, οὐ γὰρ ἐγὼ δίχα τῶνδ’ ἀείδειν, let a goddess lead, for I am not competent
to sing of these things) suggests the referring of the song to a higher (divine) authority.
90 Hunter (2003: 148) connects the word with the Hes. Theog. 80‐93. Weber (1993: 322) thinks the phrase
points to the fellows of the Alexandrian Museum; however, as noted, the word also occurs in the
Sicilian Id. 16.
91 Cf. Pi. fr. 121 Snell‐Maehler: πρέπει δ’ ἐσλοῖσιν ὑμνεῖσθαι ... καλλίσταις ἀοιδαῖς. / τοῦτο γὰρ
ἀθανάτοις τιμαῖς ποτιψαύει μόνον, / θνᾴσκει δὲ σιγαθὲν καλὸν ἔργον. (It is proper for good men
to be hymned… with the noblest songs, for that alone touches upon immortal honors, but a noble
deed dies when left in silence). What makes the phrase in 17.8 even more piquant is the fact that it
alludes to the Homeric subtext ὅ γὰρ γέρας ἐστὶ θανόντων (for that is the honor for the dead). For
the thought that song is the best gift because it is immortal, cf. Call. Iamb. 12 (fr. 202 Pf.).
92 Cf. Hunter (2003: 197): “φθέγξομαι suggests the prophetic voice of archaic lyric (cf. Pi. O. 2.92).”
240
Farewell Prince Ptolemy, and of you no less than of other demigods will I make
mention, and I will utter, methinks, a word which men hereafter shall not reject; but
for excellence you must pray to Zeus. (transl. Gow, adapted)
Yet, prophecy apart, the passage is somewhat problematic: in the last half line, it almost
seems as if Theocritus is saying that Ptolemy has not yet achieved any ἀρετή (excellence); a
somewhat improper claim at the end of an encomium. 93 The Hesiodic subtext of the Kings
and Singers passage, which informs much of the rest of the poem, 94 may be relevant here too:
ὅντινα τιμήσουσι Διὸς κοῦραι μεγάλοιο
γεινόμενόν τε ἴδωσι διοτρεφέων βασιλήων,
τῷ μὲν ἐπὶ γλώσσῃ γλυκερὴν χείουσιν ἐέρσην,
τοῦ δ’ ἔπε’ ἐκ στόματος ῥεῖ μείλιχα∙ (...)
(...)
ἐρχόμενον δ’ ἀν’ ἀγῶνα θεὸν ὣς ἱλάσκονται
αἰδοῖ μειλιχίῃ, μετὰ δὲ πρέπει ἀγρομένοισι.
τοίη Μουσάων ἱερὴ δόσις ἀνθρώποισιν.
ἐκ γάρ τοι Μουσέων καὶ ἑκηβόλου Ἀπόλλωνος
ἄνδρες ἀοιδοὶ ἔασιν ἐπὶ χθόνα καὶ κιθαρισταί
ἐκ δὲ Διὸς βασιλῆες∙ ὁ δ’ ὄλβιος, ὅντινα Μοῦσαι
φίλωνται∙γλυκερή οἱ ἀπὸ στόματος ῥέει αὐδή. (Theog. 81‐98)
Whomever among zeus‐nourished kings the daughters of great Zeus honor and
behold when he is born, they pour sweet dew upon his tongue, and his words flow
soothingly from his mouth. (...) and as he goes up to the gathering they seek his favor
like a god with soothing reverence, and he is conspicuous among the assembled
people. Such is the holy gift of the Muses to human beings. For it is from the Muses
and far‐shooting Apollo that men are poets upon the earth and lyre‐players, but it is
from Zeus that they are kings; and that man is blessed, whomever the Muses love, for
the speech flows sweet from his mouth. (transl. Most)
King Ptolemy has already received the gifts of the Muses, thanks to Theocritus (who is their
servant and Apollo’s), but he must look to his own patron god Zeus for the specifically
“kingly” gift of ἀρετή, which will make people treat him like the god he is. Judging by the
rest of the poem this should not prove to be a problem, since through the intercession of his
father Ptolemy Soter and his forefather Heracles, Zeus’ own son, Ptolemy Philadelphus may
assume to be in Zeus’ good books. Through the allusion to Hesiod, the gifts of Zeus and that
93 Gow (1952: II, ad loc.) glosses ἀρετή as “glory, victorious achievement.” He believes the passage
indicates that the Syrian war was not yet brought to a successful end.
94 Cf. Hunter (2003: ad loc.). On the Kings and Singers passage and its programmatic message in Hesiod,
see Stoddard (2003: 80‐103).
241
of the prophet of the Muses are moreover implicitly coupled like they are in the Theogony;
together they determine the immortality of Ptolemy Philadelphus.
8.7.3 Idyll 22: Rewriting the Poetic Past
The final instance of the word ὑποφήτης is found in the complex Idyll 22. In this poem, the
poet sets out to hymn both the Dioscuri together (1‐26) and then Polydeuces (27‐136) and
Castor (137‐211) separately. A striking characteristic of the poem is that its second half,
narrating the fight of the Dioscuri with the Apharetids (22.134‐211), does not recount the fate
of its heroes in the traditional, well known, way (cf. Chapter 3.9). Considering the protean
quality of Greek myth, this may appear unsurprising, but it must be noted that Theocritus’
twenty‐second Idyll actually underlines the fact that the poet presents a revisionary version
of the tale. 95
The best known tale about this fight is as follows. According to Pindar Nemean 10, the
Tyndarids or Dioscuri once got into a fight with the sons of Aphareus, Idas and Lynceus “for
some reason to do with cattle” (N. 10.60). Castor, the mortal twin, son of Tyndareus, was
killed by the Apharetids. Polydeuces, son of Zeus, was so shattered with grief at the death of
his brother that he wished to die as well. Zeus offered him the following choice:
εἰ μὲν θάνατόν τε φυγὼν καὶ
γῆρας ἀπεχθόμενον
αὐτὸς Οὔλυμπον θέλεις <ναίειν ἐμοὶ>
σύν τ’ Ἀθαναίᾳ κελαινεγχεῖ τ’ Ἄρει,
ἔστι σοι τούτων λάχος∙ εἰ δὲ κασιγνήτου πέρι
μάρνασαι, πάντων δὲ νοεῖς ἀποδάσσασθαι ἴσον,
ἥμισυ μέν κε πνέοις γαίας ὑπένερθεν ἐών,
ἥμισυ δ’ οὐρανοῦ ἐν χρυσ<έοι>ς δόμοισιν. (N. 10.82‐88)
If you wish to escape death and hated old age and to dwell in Olympus yourself with
me and with Athena and Ares of the dark spear, you can have this lot. But if you
strive to save your brother and intend to share everything equally with him, then you
may breathe for half the time below the earth and for half the time in the golden
homes of heaven. (transl. Race)
95 Cf. Hutchinson (1988: 163: n. 33), Sens (1997: 216‐220). For a discussion of the differences in
treatment of the Amycus‐myth between Theocritus (22.27‐133) and Apollonius (Arg. 2.1‐97), see
Köhnken (2001: 86). He claims that in this case Theocritus presents the more traditional account of the
myth (in Apollonius’ version Amycus dies, in that of Theocritus he lives).
242
Polydeuces chooses to share death as well as immortality with his brother; hence the
Dioscuri reside part of the time on Olympus and part in Hades. 96
In Homer, the story appears to be different still. At Il. 3, the teichoscopia, Helen
speculates about the reason for the absence of her brothers; she fears they may have declined
coming to Troy for fear of being shamed on her account. The narrator remarks that in reality
they were already dead and buried in their native Lacedaemon. 97 This passage constitutes
the single mention in the Iliad of the Dioscuri. Their irrevocable death (no part‐time
immortality on Olympus here) implies that they share the status of the other mortal Homeric
heroes; they are no divinities.
Theocritus presents a remarkably different ending to the story of the Dioscuri.
Instead of dying or becoming partly mortal and partly immortal, they emerge victoriously
from the battles they wage, illustrating the narrator’s remark: “No light thing it is to war
with the sons of Tyndareus. They are mighty, and sons of a mighty sire.” (Οὕτω
Τυνδαρίδαις πολεμιζέμεν οὐκ ἐν ἐλαφρῷ∙ / αὐτοί τε κρατέουσι καὶ ἐκ κρατέοντος
ἔφυσαν, 22.211‐212).” 98 Once this rather remarkable difference between the tradition,
particularly the Iliad, and Idyll 22 is acknowledged, certain aspects of the hymnic envoi start
to look enigmatic:
χαίρετε, Λήδας τέκνα, καὶ ἡμετέροις κλέος ὕμνοις
ἐσθλὸν ἀεὶ πέμποιτε. φίλοι δέ τε πάντες ἀοιδοί
Τυνδαρίδαις Ἑλένῃ τε καὶ ἄλλοις ἡρώεσσιν,
Ἴλιον οἳ διέπερσαν ἀρήγοντες Μενελάῳ.
ὑμῖν κῦδος, ἄνακτες, ἐμήσατο Χῖος ἀοιδός,
ὑμνήσας Πριάμοιο πόλιν καὶ νῆας Ἀχαιῶν
Ἰλιάδας τε μάχας Ἀχιλῆά τε πύργον ἀυτῆς∙
ὑμῖν αὖ καὶ ἐγὼ λιγεῶν μειλίγματα Μουσέων,
οἷ’ αὐταὶ παρέχουσι καὶ ὡς ἐμὸς οἶκος ὑπάρχει,
τοῖα φέρω. γεράων δὲ θεοῖς κάλλιστον ἀοιδαί. (22.213‐222)
Farewell, sons of Leda, and send ever noble renown upon our hymns. All bards are
dear to the sons of Tyndareus, to Helen and to the other heroes that aided Menelaus
96 For a mortal Castor and immortal Polydeuces, cf. Cypria (Bernabé fr. 8): Κάστωρ μὲν θνητός,
θανάτου δέ οἱ αἶσα πέπρωται, / αὐτὰρ ὅ γ’ ἀθάνατος Πολυδεύκης, ὄζος Ἄρηος. (Castor is mortal,
and his fatal day is set; but the other one, Polydeuces, is immortal, that shoot of Ares).
97 Il. 3.236‐244: Ὣς φάτο, τοὺς δ’ ἤδη κάτεχεν φυσίζοος αἶα / ἐν Λακεδαίμονι αὖθι φίλῃ ἐν πατρίδι
γαίῃ. (Thus she spoke, but the lifegiving earth already held them, right in Lacedaemon, their own
fatherland).
98 Cf. Pi. N. 10.72: χαλεπὰ δ’ ἔρις ἀνθρώποις ὁμιλεῖν κρεσσόνων. (It is hard for mortals to wage
battle with their betters) and Call. Hymn. II, 25, with the remarks of Williams (1978: ad loc.).
243
to sack Ilium. Glory for you, princes, the bard of Chios fashioned when he hymned
the town of Priam and the ships of the Achaeans, the battles round Ilium, and
Achilles, that tower of strength in fight. And to you I too bear the soothing strains of
the clearvoiced Muses such as they give me and my own store provides; and for gods
songs are the fairest meed. (transl. Gow, adapted)
This passage seems to proclaim that Theocritus thinks that Homer has provided the Dioscuri
with renown, in the Iliad. 99 This is a problem, for, as noted, the Iliad mentions them only in
passing, and what is more, as already dead. As Gow puts it: “However we seek to evade this
difficulty, the objection remains that, in a hymn which celebrates the Dioscuri as gods, any
reference to the Iliad is unfortunate, since, according to that authority, they were of the same
clay as the other heroes.”
Considering Theocritus’ expert knowledge of Homeric poetry, it is hard to believe
this was some slip of the pen 100 . It seems more attractive to conjecture that Theocritus
deliberately invites his readers to contrast his own poetic treatment of the Dioscuri with the
the Dioscuri are referred to at all in the Iliad gains them immortal fame. 102 Yet, Theocritus
strives to procure them a different kind of immortality, or immortal fame. His poem actually
brings the Dioscuri back to life: if neither of them died in the battle with the Apharetids, they
would have been alive to wage war in the Iliad, and could have gained undying renown.
Theocritus restores this possibility like the true divine prophet of the Muses he claims to be:
this explains his statement that he brings to the Dioscuri both the gifts of the Muses (here the
99 That this is the poem Theocritus is thinking of is strongly suggested by the synoptic description in
22.218‐219. Gow (1952: II, 406) remarks that it is natural to take ἐμήσατο (22.217) and ὑμνήσας
(22.218) as referring to the same action, cf. Sens (1997: 218‐219).
100 Gow (1952: II, 406‐407) considers the possibility that Theocritus is referring to the Cypria (cf.
Cameron 1995: 436) but concludes (on the basis of Id. 16.49) that Theocritus did not ascribe this poem
to Homer. At any rate, according to the Cypria, the Dioscuri were not wholly immortal either. Dover
(1971: 250) and Hunter (1996: 76) interpret ὑμῖν (22.218) as referring to another group of heroes than
ὑμῖν (22.221). Yet, even if 22.218 refers to a wider group of heroes, it should still include the Dioscuri,
who are certainly addressed in 22.223 as θεοί, cf. Sens (1997: 210). Griffiths (1976: 363‐7) argues that
the narrative voice in Id. 22 must be understood as a parody of a narrator who does not know what he
is claiming; Laursen (1992: 92) sees the passage as an indication of Theocritus’ ethical views about the
Iliad: the fact that the Dioscuri did not participate in the war around Troy counts as laudable. This
oddly neglects to take account of the bloody and unjust battles Id. 22 describes.
101 Hutchinson (1988: 163, n. 33), cf. Ch. 3.9.
102 Even though they are dead and therefore hardly able to gain κῦδος, with its particular meaning of
“glory won in battle” (cf. LSJ s.v.).
244
Muses would seem to stand for the poetic tradition as symbolized amongst others by
Homer) and items from his own store.
This demonstration of poetic prowess may have been given for the benefit of the
Ptolemies, who accorded an important status to the Dioscuri in royal cult. They may even
have perceived a kind of “typological” similarity between their own status and that of the
proves to be of the essence for the gaining of κλέος. This is what is expressed, slightly
varying the adage of 17.8, near the end of Idyll 22: hymns are the most beautiful of honors for
the gods (γεράων δὲ θεοῖς κάλλιστον ἀοιδαί, 22.223). Hymns are “better than shrines,
sacrifices, processions and other honors” (Sens, 1997 ad loc.), because they immortalize by
revealing what usually remains hidden from the sight of men (as in 17), or by setting right
what has become (wrongly) established by tradition (as in 22). 104 In Theocritus’ hymn, the
Dioscuri have become immortals, as the Argonauts in Apollonius’ epic “hymn” (cf. Chapter
3.6), and Ptolemy in the seventeenth hymnic Idyll.
8.8 Conclusion
By representing the Muses as the “interpreters” of Apollo for the benefit of his epic about the
legendary past, Apollonius has done something interestingly innovative. He has not changed
the hierarchy of poet and inspirational deity, as scholars have claimed, but found a new way
of addressing the problematic aspects of revealed knowledge in a subtle envisioning of
divine inspiration. A particularly striking feature is the hierarchical structure he expresses by
his use of the phrase “may the Muses be the ὑποφήτορες of my song,” which implies that
the Muses are subordinate to Apollo and that therefore their information is not direct, with
all problems this entails. This hierarchical representation seems triggered by the
contingencies of an age in which most readers would have been aware that, in reality, poets
obtained a large part of their information about the past from the accounts of predecessors
103 Note the alternation between “sons of Zeus and “sons of Tyndareus.” Cf. the double paternity of
Heracles (Amphitryo and Zeus, cf. Id. 24); Alexander (Zeus‐Ammon and Philip); the same seems
implied of Ptolemy Soter (Lagos and Zeus?) at Id. 17.16, cf. Hunter (2003: 111).
104 Cf. the way Pindar changes traditional myth to fit his own conception of the divine (e.g. O. 1.35‐41;
O. 9.35‐40; N. 7.22‐27; 8.32‐37), on which see Sperduti (1950: 235), Pfeijffer (2004: 222‐223).
245
(who, in turn, doubtless had their own sources) stored in the shrine of the Muses, the
Mouseion. In Apollonius’ work, the Muses may be read as personified references to the
different ways in which an epic poet with scholarly inclinations establishes, negotiates,
chooses, and incorporates truth, tradition, and invention in his narrative. Their first
invocation (1.20‐22) questions the concept of revealed knowledge by implicitly asking how
they obtain their information. The passage thus points to the interpretational difficulties
adhering to the establishment of cause and effect, the decision about which version of legend
or history is true, and who is ultimately responsible for it.
By connecting prophecy and poetry in this way, Apollonius also, on another level,
links two disciplines that had long before his times become separate. This process is
reminiscent of the insertion of a hymnic opening and ending in his epic, as analyzed in
Chapter 3. In both instances, Apollonius is innovating and creates something new by
poets (prophets revealing the truth about the past and about the divine purposes that
structure the world and history). Meanwhile, he is able to turn this into a subtle trope of the
way in which a learned poet in an age of scholarship deals with the traditional concept of
inspiration coming from the Muse.
Theocritus’ use of the hapax is altogether different. 105 He uses the Homeric word in
pindarically influenced contexts of praise in order to emphasize the significance of his status
as κλέος‐providing singer for rulers with heroic or semi‐divine aspirations. He thus stresses
the importance and exclusivity of revealed knowledge about the present and future. Only
the poet in possession of such knowledge is able to provide humans but also immortal
beings with glamor and status. κλέος is the best gift for men; hymns are the best gifts for the
gods; hence both categories need a Muse‐inspired prophet to compose for them.
Styling himself thus as a ὑποφήτης Μουσάων, Theocritus not only points backwards
to the great poets of the epinician tradition, most notably Pindar, but may also be said to
foreshadow the Augustan poets:
When the Romans for the first time were becoming aware of Greek literature, and …
were turning to the Greeks for their literary types and their metre, it is fair to
conjecture that they simply borrowed the term poietes because they felt it carried
It could be asked who was the first to use the hapax; however, questions of priority in Hellenistic
105
poetry are notoriously difficult to answer, cf. Köhnken (2001: 73‐92).
246
greater prestige and dignity than their own word vates, in that it connoted a greater
degree of skill and polish. It was not until later that the term vates flowered anew and
was endowed with deeper brilliance by the Augustan poets who revived the word
deliberately, conscious of its more ancient religious connotation, and by so doing
renewed the ancient alliance between poetry and prophecy. (Sperduti, 1950: 221)
It seems Hellenistic poets too looked to the prophetic connotations of poetry to infuse their
works with a deeper brilliance. And so, although both poets arguably took the same subtext
as their basis for their new conceptions of the process of poetic inspiration, the ideas of
Apollonius emerge as directly opposite to those of Theocritus. Whereas Theocritus
emphasizes his closeness to the Muses and their omniscience and his similarity to such great
prophets of the Muses of the lyric, hymnic, and epic tradition as Pindar, Homer, and Hesiod,
Apollonius distances himself from the easy acceptance of the belief in revealed knowledge
and uses the concept to illustrate the novel difficulties facing a contemporary poet working
in a poetic tradition so full of opposing poetic, historical, mythical, and philosophical
traditions.
247
248
SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION
My argument throughout this study has been that it is necessary to consider two interrelated
factors to understand the way Hellenistic poets represented poets and poetry: their position
in Greek (literary) history and their socio‐cultural surroundings. To modern readers,
Hellenistic poets are relatively late in Greek literary history; they are the “Nachwuchs” of the
great Greek tradition, which ends with the classical era, the literature of fifth‐century Athens.
Hellenistic poetry is also different in nature from earlier poetry both in its formal aspects and
its choice of subject matter. It may be asked how Hellenistic poets themselves appreciated
their position vis à vis Greek literary history. Were they aware of this lateness and of the
different nature of their works? Did they feel continuity with the past or a break?
To understand the Hellenistic preoccupation with the literary past, it is helpful to
refer to Assmann’s concept of cultural memory. If ever there was a time in Greek antiquity in
which this cultural memory was deliberately formed, it must have been Hellenism, the
period that saw the introduction of great royal libraries as symbols of Hellenic culture. These
were the sites of the beginnings of systematic philology and eventually the formation of
canons of literary masterpieces and they instigated the debate about how these masterpieces
should be interpreted and why. Storing and studying literature in this way implies a feeling
of both of admiration for it and distance from it.
So Hellenistic poets did not regard older Greek poetry in the same way as
contemporary poetry, which, for as far as we can tell, formed indeed no part of the libraries’
collections. Yet, they clearly sought continuity with the literary past: they admired and
mined it for their own poetry to a greater extent than earlier poets had done. Yet their poetry
also differed more from the tradition than that of their predecessors; they must have sought
to authorize these new aspects of their poetry by their constant reference to tradition, real or
invented. Perhaps their position is best summed up by saying that most of them were
innovative poets and conscientious scholars of Greek literature at the same time, conscious of
their position as critical and creative readers reflecting on tradition without feeling
completely cut off from it. The past must have seemed to them like a “window and mirror:”
they sought to recognize their reflection, even if the world behind the looking glass was
different than their own.
249
What part did their socio‐cultural surroundings play in the molding of this attitude
towards the past? Many Hellenistic poets worked at or for royal courts that competed in
splendor and prestige. The most renowned was that of Ptolemy Philadelphus at Alexandria,
which promoted both the study and production of Greek literature on a grand scale to
establish the monarch’s claim on the cultural and political legacy of Alexander the Great. The
poets of the age were stimulated to look at and, to some extent, imitate the poetry of the past
to enhance the king’s prestige. Against this background, which must have represented a
powerful influence even beyond the walls of the Alexandrian Museum and Library, the
poets’ preoccupation with their response to the literary past becomes clear, as is duly
recognized in scholarship.
What has not received a similar amount of scholarly attention is that encouragement
by the court also was an important influence on social interaction between contemporaries
affiliated to these royal institutions. The material dependence would have led to rivalry for
the king’s favor and thereby fueled a strong drive to claim a position of distinction with
regard to one’s colleagues. Thus the courtly surrounding influenced the Hellenistic poets’
identity in two ways: it directed their glance towards the past encouraging them to ground
their new poetry in hallowed tradition, and it made them consider their position among
contemporary colleagues competing for the favor of the monarch.
1. The Past
Addressing the preoccupation with the past, the first part of my study focused on two
categories of predecessors, legendary poets and historical ones. Hellenistic poets attributed a
different status to figures such as Orpheus and the mythical herdsman‐poet Daphnis than to
their historical counterparts Homer, Archilochus, and Pindar. This was mainly due to the
fact that the legendary poets had left behind no indisputable literary legacy. To the
Hellenistic Greeks, Orpheus was an ambiguous figure, part mythical hero, part mystic
teacher, and part cultural forerunner of the Greek poets. The cowherd Daphnis’ legacy was,
even in antiquity, still vaguer.
being made into forebears for poetic practice. The fact that they had not left behind a clear‐
cut literary legacy was welcome: it gave Hellenistic poets the freedom to turn them into their
250
own predecessors by forming them after their own image. This need to ground their poetry
in the tradition may be explained using Hobsbawm’s concept of invented tradition. This can
be observed in the Argonautica of Apollonius, where Orpheus is made into a fictional
foreshadowing of the narrator’s persona. Theocritus employs the characters Daphnis and
Comatas in a similar way to provide what is now known to be his new poetic invention,
bucolic poetry, with a venerable and credible ancestry. The intricate design of his bucolic
Idylls give his readers the feeling that they are witnessing tales set in a fully rounded bucolic
world full of traditions; they can perceive the gist while remaining unaware of the full story.
So one way these poets used the work of poets of the past was to mold them as
desired in whatever way best reflected their own characteristics. However, this was not so
easy when the poets concerned were clearly circumscribed by a literary legacy that survived
to be studied. Historical poets had expressed their own tenets in poetry: this prevented their
being cast in entirely new roles. Yet, like legendary poets, they too were used as models
whose authority might be invoked in matters of innovative poetic practice.
The Hellenistic treatment of historical predecessors took on two forms. They were
evaluated, mostly in the literary epitaphs and other forms of epigram that flourished in this
era. I have chosen to focus on three aspects of the characterization of historical poets in
epigram: poetic practice (singing versus written composition); the reflection of character and
biography in poetic works, and the survival of the poetic legacy through the medium of
written texts. The topics are interrelated. Whereas earlier Greek poetry rarely stressed the
fact that poetry (or song) could be written down, it becomes the default expectation in the
Hellenistic era, the “age of the Book,” in Rudolf Pfeiffer’s words. That the works of
predecessors were securely preserved on scrolls is the reason Hellenistic poets were able to
judge them. Poetic works served as the inalienable monument to former poets’ existences.
The difference between an indisputable literary legacy (such as that of Sophocles) and a
legendary, ambiguous one (such as that of Orpheus) was recognized, as can be shown from
comparison of epitaphs written on these respective poets. This fact, that the foremost
testimony that remained of a poet after his death was his work, made characterization on the
basis of his works very attractive. Ancient biography was mainly an extrapolation of facts
from a poet’s works; this practice is clearly echoed by the epigrams. This also proves
important in the analysis of Hellenistic poets’ self‐representation in epigram. Their insight in
251
the way predecessors were perceived influenced the way in which they chose to present
themselves to future generations of readers.
Unsurprisingly, the biographical mode of reading occasionally led to caricatures,
such as Anacreon the lovelorn symposiast and Archilochus the venomous aggressor of
young maidens. It seems, however, that some poets were aware that such a reading of
literature ignored the creation of personae and roles. In my opinion, this was because
Hellenistic poets like Theocritus and Callimachus consciously experimented with such
different roles and personae in their own works: they were aware that the speaking “I” in
poetry does not have to be identical with the historical author. Theocritus’ epigrams that
ironically comment upon the traditional appraisal of poets such as Anacreon and
Archilochus alert the reader to this, but the creation of insubstantial voices in Callimachus’
Hymns may also be connected to it.
Besides numerous epigrams featuring predecessors, there are some examples of
incorporation of predecessors as models or authorities in other poetic texts. While Hellenistic
poets invoked their authority because they felt obliged to Greek poetic tradition, they were
unable fully to continue its practices. Not only their mode of composing (with constant
intertextual reference to the great tradition) but also the function of their poetry in society
(more than ever before, it was defined by reading rather than singing and became an
increasingly private art) differed from that of their predecessors. Yet, they did not want to
distance themselves completely from what had been produced before their own time; they
needed the past both to create and to validate the present. There were various ways of
invoking the authority of predecessors and hence justifying novel poetic practices.
Predecessors could be cast as models, protoi heuretai and inspirers; in such cases it was either
opportune to highlight certain traditionally acknowledged characteristics of their poetry or
to manipulate data about their life and works so as to make them fit the proposed aim.
Two examples of this practice have been discussed. Theocritus’ sixteenth Idyll uses
Homer, Simonides, and (implicitly) Pindar as examples of the thesis that praise in
(commissioned) poetry is the only way for a mortal to obtain immortal fame. Theocritus
needed to do this because, in his time, as he argues, “poetry” has come to be regarded by
miserly patrons preferably as “poetry by dead poets of the past.” He had to demonstrate that
poetry is a living, present thing that has to be nurtured in order to perform its natural task:
252
the providing of kleos. Paradoxically, the sixteenth Idyll does so by adducing the examples of
“dead poets of the past.” Hermesianax’ elegiac Leontion, on the other hand, playfully aims to
prove the thesis that all literature is the result of love affairs by “allegorically” interpreting
the works of Homer and Hesiod and others. On the one hand, this presentation of literary
history is a programmatic choice: Hermesianax supposedly refers to the long tradition in
which his erotic elegy stands. On the other, through reductio ad absurdum, this procedure
seems to reveal an awareness of how the appropriation of models works.
Merely naming poets as models or examples differs from the choice to allow them to
speak for themselves in poetry, as the difference between the abovementioned examples and
the poems of Timon (Silloi), Callimachus (Iambus 1), and Herondas (Mimiambus 8) illustrates.
These latter examples all incorporate poetic authorities as speaking characters. Interestingly,
in all cases this results in tensions between the message that is being propounded and the
medium through which it is expressed. In Timon of Phlius’ Silloi, the choice to introduce the
detractor of Homeric theology Xenophanes as the author’s guide through Hades to lead him
to his philosophical master, the sceptic Pyrrho, clashes strangely with the Homeric setting
and vocabulary. Moreover, it seems odd that Timon declared that he visited the underworld;
the afterlife was a thing sceptics claimed no knowledge about. This strategy illustrates the
awkwardness of appropriating a predecessor as an authority for a poet’s own assertions. By
choosing to formulate his narrative as an ironic fantasy, he alerted the reader to his
awareness of this.
Callimachus and Herondas both introduce an aggressive Hipponax in their iambic
poetry. While Callimachus pretends Hipponax is an independent personage who scolds the
scholars of the Museum about their quarrels, the latter is in fact his own creation. The poet is
partially hiding behind the mask of Hipponax, winking mischievously. In this way, he
demonstrates his awareness of the iambic practice of choosing a mask to voice unwelcome
opinions. Moreover, he creates a paradox by not abiding by Hipponax’ advice in the poem
and indulging in iambic quarrelsomeness in the rest of the collection. Herondas makes his
Hipponax teach him a lesson: by behaving towards his slaves in the same way as Hipponax
behaved towards him in his dream, he shows that he has truly captured the Hipponactic
iambic spirit of aggression. In both cases, Hipponax’ aggressive behaviour also makes the
253
reader wonder what the dead poet really would have thought of this new use of his literary
inheritance.
2. The Present
The second part focused on the poets’ portrayal of contemporaries, mainly from the point of
view of the social interaction of the Museum and Library and comparable institutions at
other royal courts. I have chosen to consider statements about other poets and their poetics
in the theoretical frame of Pierre Bourdieu, whose field of cultural production‐theory
elaborates the insight that art is not divorced from society or from the drives determining
social interactions. In other words, it would be wrong to view any kind of poetry, even
Hellenistic poetry, which has traditionally often been considered “l‘art pour l’art,” as a purely
aesthetic category. Bourdieu’s recognition of the workings of the striving for “distinction”
provided some useful starting points for a consideration of various subjects in Hellenistic
poetry. Thus I analyzed the much debated quarrel between Callimachus and Apollonius, as
well as the Aetia‐prologue of Callimachus and the related question of the identity of the
Telchines. My analysis of the ancient testimonies about the quarrel supports the growing
consensus that there is little evidence to assume that it took place. And even if it did, it seems
unlikely that its subject could be deduced. I suggest that the assumption that Callimachus
and Apollonius quarreled is probably due to the observation by later readers that they were
similar in stylistic aims. For an observer at some temporal distance, this in itself could
suggest that a quarrel between the two was likely; Callimachus’ polemical persona
presumably did the rest.
The ensuing analysis of this persona in the Aetia‐prologue, building on the findings of
Cameron, Asper, and Schmitz, shows that Callimachus’ main aim in this text was the
creation of a position of distinction and exclusivity for himself, regardless of whether the
Telchines were a historical reality. By claiming that he is envied and misunderstood, he
implies he is an exceptional and successful poet, who, however, only manages to please true
connoisseurs. So a text that has traditionally been interpreted as a purely aesthetically
motivated harangue reveals itself as the statement of a strategic position. The discussion of
254
some epigrams attacking contemporaries, finally, confirms that what poses as an aesthetic
judgement may often conceal very different and personal opinions.
The reverse of negative aesthetic judgments, praise, is a neglected subject in
Hellenistic poetry. Praise for contemporaries aims to make an assertion about the poetics of
the praising voice itself. It may thus serve as a means of obtaining distinction: with their
praise of certain elitist and esoteric characteristics of Aratus’ Phaenomena, Callimachus and
Leonidas showed that they belonged to the same category of refined (and esteemed) poets as
Aratus. Claiming immortality for a contemporary in a poem implies the expectation that the
praise itself will also be immortal. Theocritus’ Idyll 7 subtly parodies these principles by
making Simichidas claim allegiance to Asclepiades and Philitas. Despite his faux humility,
this characterization reveals how the young poet sees himself. Eliciting praise from an
addressee or patron works on a comparable principle: by praising the recipient’s literary
sensibilities, the poet obliges him to like the poem addressed to him, as happens in
Theocritus’ Idylls 16, 17; it is mocked in Idyll 11.
What has emerged up to this point is that the representation of other poets generally
reflects the poet who represents them, whether by inventing or manipulating the past to
serve as a poetic mirror, underscoring differences with contemporaries to create a distinct
position, or claiming allegiance to (successful or exclusive) contemporaries in order to draw
attention to a poet’s own artistic tenets. It could be claimed that all these appraisals and
representations of other poets contain implicit self‐portraits.
3. Selfrepresentation
In the third and final part, the overt self‐representation of poets was addressed. To begin
with, there are several noteworthy aspects to Hellenistic sphragis‐epigrams. They are the
poets’ evident wish to identify themselves explicitly and unambiguously as the author of
their poetry (for instance, by means of sphragis‐epigrams in poetry books) is due to the
circumstance that Hellenistic poetry is, in the first place, poetry for readers rather than for
aural audiences. Whereas oral performance necessarily clarifies the speaking voice in a
poem, written and read poetry does not succeed in this without using auxiliary means such
as explicit speaker identification in the text.
255
This process of facilitating author identification can also be deliberately reversed,
forcing the reader to work out who the speaker is on the basis of hints, as in the mimetic
Hymns of Callimachus. Both of these practices are ultimately grounded in the fact that
Hellenistic poetry was poetry by reader‐poets for a reading audience. Reading texts out of
their original contexts made the Hellenistic scholars acutely aware of the problems
encountered when visually reading a text that had originally been produced for oral
presentation: contingent references, ambiguous speaker changes and the like made
interpretation of such texts a challenging and sometimes daunting task.
As the discussion of the epigrams in praise of Aratus’ Phaenomena showed, sphragis‐
passages could also contain enigmatic elements, often related to etymological explanations
or puns on the name of the author (Ἄρατος/ἀρρητός). This observation was elaborated in
Chapter 7, where instances of such enigmatic self‐representation were analyzed. They invite
the reader to interpret clues and thus gain additional information about the way the author
wished himself to be perceived. Thus Apollonius stresses his connection with the god of
poetic inspiration and oracles Apollo in the opening of the Argonautica, while Callimachus
underscores his poetic ability to find the right word at the right time in his epigrammatic
self‐epitaph by implying a kat’antiphrasin explanation of the name Battiades (“son of the
stammerer”).
Theocritus poses a more complicated enigma to his readers when he calls the young
poet who is the narrator of his meta‐poetic seventh Idyll “Simichidas.” Scholarship is divided
about the degree to which Simichidas should be interpreted as an alter ego of the poet. This
question is complicated by the problem of the identification of Simichidas’ dialogue partner
in the poem, Lycidas. Simichidas has a stronger claim to identification with the author than
Lycidas because he is the internal narrator of the poem. On the basis of the meta‐poetic
interpretation of two intriguing expressions (ἐσθλὸν σὺν Μοίσαισι Κυδωνικὸν εὕρομες
ἄνδρα, 7.13; πᾶν ἐπ’ ἀλαθείᾳ πεπλασμένον ἐκ Διὸς ἔρνος, 7.44) as well as a structural
analysis of the Idyll, I have argued that both Simichidas and Lycidas are represented on a
meta‐poetic level as mutual fictions of each other. This means that the poem as a whole
presents a reflection upon the role of fictional herdsmen‐poets in Theocritus’ bucolic poetry.
It is an implicit recognition of the fact that he is the originator of the genre and has invented
its characters as well as its forebears: bucolic poetry originates in itself.
256
The final problem I addressed is that of the representation of poetic authority, in
particular the status of the Muse as a guarantor of revealed knowledge. By focusing on the
use of the Homeric hapax legomenon ὑποφήτης (Il. 16.235) and its variant ὑποφήτωρ, I
analyzed the concept of divine inspiration in Apollonius and Theocritus. The passages in
Hellenistic poetry in which these words appear are linked by a specific emphasis on the role
of the poet as a recipient and passer on of revealed knowledge (cf. González). For Theocritus,
this role is of particular importance in his problematic position of court‐poet glorifying
(divine) rulers or their favorite semi‐deities. By calling himself a ὑποφήτης, he arrogates a
particular panegyric authority to himself. Apollonius, on the other hand, emphasizes the
problems inherent to revealed knowledge about the past. By casting the Muses as a link in a
hierarchical chain, dependent on the ambiguous oracular wisdom of Apollo, he figuratively
addresses the problems of a poet working in the Museum, searching for information in
contradictory, obscure, or untrustworthy sources about the past. In last instance, the analysis
shows that both poets look back to the earliest origins of poetry for their self‐fashioning,
combining poetry and prophecy.
In conclusion, Hellenistic poets represent other poets to reflect on their interpretation
of these poets as well as on their own poetic tenets. They are simultaneously readers and
writers; both aspects form part of their identity as poets; they see themselves as innovative
reflectors on the tradition. Their explicit self‐representations appear to target a prospective
readership of erudite interpreters who will study this poetry and perhaps even look for their
own reflection in it. Thus their works become what they had made the works of their
predecessors and colleagues: both window and mirror.
257
258
APPENDIX : LIST OF HELLENISTIC EPIGRAMS ON POETS
Corpus
The corpus consists of early Hellenistic epigrams dealing with poets, i.e. epigrams produced
in the third Century BCE. I have chosen to exclude later Hellenistic authors such as Antipater
Sidonius and Thessalonicensis as well as Meleager, because they produced their poetry in a
different setting. Problematic are the epigrams attributed to Plato on Aristophanes (14 Diehl),
Sappho (AP 9.506) and Pindar (AP 7.35). I follow Gow and Page (1965) in excluding the first
two from the Hellenistic age, and attributing the last to Leonidas (20).
Poets of the Past
(Poems marked with an asterisk are discussed in the text.)
Orpheus
AP 7.9 Damagetus*
AP 7.10 Anonymous
Arion
AB 37 Posidippus*
Homer
AP 7.2 Anonymous
AP 9.2 Leonidas
AP 7.1 Alcaeus of Messene
AP 7.5 Alcaeus of Messene
AP 7.80 Callimachus (Homer and Creophylus)*
Hesiod
AP 7.55 Alcaeus of Messene
AP 7.54 Mnasalces
Pisander
AP 9.598 Theocritus
Antimachus
AP 9.63 Asclepiades*
Mimnermus, Antimachus, Hesiod, Homer
AP 12.168 Posidippus
On the nine lyric poets
AP 9.184 Anonymous
AP 9.571 Anonymous
Archilochus
AP 9.185 Anonymous
AP 7.664 Theocritus*
AP 7.351 Dioscorides*
259
Hipponax
AP 7.408 Leonidas*
AP 7.536 Alcaeus of Messene
AP 13.3 Theocritus*
Alcman
AP 7.709 Alexander Aetolus
Sappho
AP 9.189 Anonymous
Ath.13.696 Posidippus*
AP 7.407 Dioscorides
Pindar
AP 7.35 Leonidas
Anacreon
AP 7.28 Anonymous
AP 7.24 Pseudo‐Simonides
AP 7.25 Pseudo‐Simonides
AP 7.31 Dioscorides
APl. 306 Leonidas*
APl. 307 Leonidas*
AP 9.599 Theocritus*
Erinna
AP 9.190 Anonymous
AP 7.12 Anonymous*
AP 7.11 Asclepiades
AP 7.13 Leonidas
Philitas
AB 63 Posidippus
Thespis
AP 7.410 Dioscorides
Aeschylus
AP 7.411 Dioscorides
Sophocles
AP 7.37 Dioscorides
AP 7.21 Simmias*
AP 7.22 Simmias
Euripides
AP 7.46 Anonymous
Tellen
AP 7.719 Leonidas
Epicharmus
AP 9.600 Theocritus
AP 7.125 Anonymous
Cratinus
AP 13.29 Nicaenetus of Samos
Heracleitus
AP 7.479 Theodoridas of Samos
260
Poets of the Present (Including Self‐epitaphs)
Aratus
AP 9.507 Callimachus*
AP 9.25 Leonidas*
SH 712 = Vit. Arat. 1 (King Ptolemy “Physkon”)
Asclepiades
AP 12.50 Asclepiades*
Callimachus
AP 7.415 Callimachus*
AP 7.525 Callimachus*
AP 9.566 Callimachus*
AP 11.362 Callimachus*
AP 12.43 Callimachus*
AP 11.275 “Apollonius”*
Euphorion
AP 11.218 Crates*
AP 7.406 Theodoridas*
Hedylus
Ath. 11.473a, GP V Hedylus*
Heracleitus
AP 7.80 Callimachus*
Leonidas
AP 7.715 Leonidas*
AP 6.300 Leonidas*
AP 6.302 Leonidas*
Machon
AP 7.708 Dioscorides
Mnasalces
AP 13.21 Theodoridas of Samos*
Nossis
AP 5.170 Nossis*
AP 7.718 Nossis*
Posidippus
SH 705 = AB 118*
Rhinthon
AP 7.414 Nossis
Sositheus
AP 7.707 Dioscorides
Theaetetus
(AP 9.565) Callimachus*
261
Singing versus Writing in the Epigrams
A. Poets of the Past.
In these epigrams, the profession of the poet is expressed with the following words: ποιητής
(AP 7.2, 7.5 Homer; 7.664 Archilochus); ἀοιδός (AP 7.10 Orpheus; 7.1, 7.80 Homer; 7.13
Erinna; 13.29 Cratinus). Apart from these designations, there is a range of words forming a
continuum between the two: εὐφώνων Πιερίδων πρόπολος (AP 7.35 Pindar); μουσοποιός
(AP 9.598 Pisander; 13.3 Hipponax); ὑμνητήρ (AP 7.19 Alcman); ὑμνοπόλος (AP 9.24
Homer; 7.25 Anacreon; 7.13 Erinna); ωἰδοποιός (AP 9.599 Anacreon).
The expressions for the process/activity itself and its final product also range between
these terms. Singing/reciting is expressed by (compounds of) the verbs: ἀείδω (AP 7.664
Archilochus; 9.63 Antimachus; 7.5 Homer); κλάγγω (AP 9.571 Pindar); μελίζεσθαι (APl. 307
Anacreon); μέλπεσθαι (ΑP 7.21 Sophocles; APl. 306 Anacreon; AP 7.19 Alcman); πνείω (AP
7.55 Hesiod; 7.24, 7.25 Anacreon; 7.407 Sappho; 9.571 Simonides); or the nouns ἀοιδή (AP
7.410 Thespis; Ath. 13.696 Sappho); αὐδά (AP 9.571 Alcaeus; μέλη (AP 7.25 Anacreon);
μoλπή (AP 7.25 Anacreon); ὕμνος (AP 9.189 Sappho); στόμα (AP 7.411 Aeschylus; 9.571
Simonides; 9.184 Pindar); φθέγγω (Ath. 13.696 Sappho; AP 9.571 Bacchylides); φθόγγος (AP
9.571 Simonides).
References to the lyre and hence to singing can be found in (APl. 306, 307, AP 7.24,
7.25 Anacreon; 9.189 Sappho; 7.664 Archilochus; 7.10 Orpheus; AB 37 Arion).
It is further noteworthy that Sappho’s poems are called her “daughters” (AP 7.407);
Erinna too is pictured as “giving birth” to her poetry (AP 7.12). Cratinus (AP 13.29) also uses
the verb τέκω to describe the production of poetry.
Writing and its products are expressed by: γράμμα (AP 7.80 Homer; 9.63
Antimachus; 9.184 Anacreon; 7.411 Aeschylus); σέλις (AP 9.184 Simonides; Ath. 13.696
Sappho; AP 7.21 Sophocles); συγγράφω (AP 9.598 Pisander).
This leaves verbs and nouns that could both denote writing or the spoken word:
ἔπη (AP 7.12 Erinna; 7.2, 7.5 Homer; referring to hexametric poetry); διδασκαλία (AP 7.37
Sophocles); κυδαίνω (AP 7.1 Homer); ῥήματα (AP 9.600 Epicharmus; AP 7.408 Hipponax).
There is also a number of references to (specific) meters or genres (iambi, elegiac
distich, melic and epic meter, stichoi, comedy etc.) and to the “300 verses of Erinna, which
262
conquer Homer’s poetry” (AP 9.190). In general, lyric poets tend to be associated with song,
epic poets and dramatists with writing and singing/reciting.
B. Poets of the Present
In these epigrams a similar alternation between ποιέω, ἀείδω, γράφω and more opaque
metaphors for the poetic process is found: ποιέω (AP 11.218; AP 7.406, Euphorion); ποίημα
(AP 12.43, Callimachus AP 11.218 Euphorion); ποιητής (AP 9.566 Callimachus).
Singing/reciting is expressed by the following words and metaphors: ἀείδω and
compound verbs (AB 118 Posidippus; AP 7.525 Callimachus); ἀήδονις (AP 7.414 Rhinthon);
ἀήδων (AP 7.80 Heraclitus, referring to his works; AB 118 Archilochus, referring to the man);
ἀοιδή/ἄεισμα (AP 9.507, Hesiod/Aratus AP 7.415, Callimachus); ἀοιδός (AP 9.507 Hesiod);
κύκνος (AP 5.135 Zeno); τέττιξ (AP 12.98 Posidippus).
The following expressions seem to indicate improvisation: καίρια συγγελάσαι AP
7.415 (apparently used in opposition to ἀοιδή); παίζω (Ath 11.473a GPV Hedylus).
Writing is expressed by the words βίβλος (AB 118 Posidippus); γράμμα (AP 9.20
Aratus, note that in AP9.507 the same work is referred to by ἄεισμα); γράφω (ΑP 11.275
Callimachus; AB 118 Posidippus); δέλτον/σέλις (AB 118 Posidippus); ἐν βύβλοις
πεπονημένη ... ψύχη (AP 12.98 Posidippus); κωμῳδογράφος (AP 7.708 Machon).
This leaves words that would seem to indicate speaking rather than writing: ἔπος
(AP 9.507 Aratus/Hesiod Ath. 11.473a GPV Hedylus); ὀρθοεπὴς (AB 118 Posidippus); ῥήσιες
(AP 9.507 Aratus).
In some epigrams metaphors for poetry are used that leave unexpressed whether
written words are imagined or songs; the humble gifts Leonidas offers to the goddess Lathria
in AP 6.300 are usually understood metapoetically; since they suggest material objects,
written poems might be intended. A similar claim could be made about AP 6.302, where
Leonidas refers to his household stores, which mice try to raid. The “roses” of Nossis (AP
5.170) are more ambiguous, as is her expression for receiving inspiration in AP 7.718 (τᾶν
Σαπφοῦς χαρίτων ἄνθος ἐναυσόμενος). A similar metaphor is found in AP 7.708
(Dioscorides on Machon) ἐν Μούσαις δριμὺ πέφυκε θύμον, referring to the wit of Attic
comedy, transferred by Machon from Attica to Alexandria.
263
Sometimes (expressions containing) Μοῦσα indicate either the poetic
talent/inspiration of a given author (AP 5.134 Cleanthes), or his works (AP 7.715 Leonidas),
or a genre (AP 7.707 Sositheus).
264
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Achillea Stella, L. (1949) Cinque Poeti dellʹ Antologia Palatina, Bologna
Acosta‐Hughes, B. (2002) Polyeideia: The ʺIambiʺ of Callimachus and the Archaic Iambic Tradition,
Berkeley etc.
‐‐‐ (2004) ʹAlexandrian Posidippus: On Rereading the GP Epigrams in the Light of P. Mil.
Vogl. VIII 309ʹ In: Labored in Papyrus Leaves: Perspectives on an Epigram Collection attributed to
Posidippus (P. Mil. Vogl. VIII 309) (eds. Acosta‐Hughes, B., Kosmetatou, E., Baumbach, M.),
Washington D.C. and Cambridge, Mass., 42‐56
Acosta‐Hughes, B., Kosmetatou, E., Baumbach, M. (eds.) (2004) Labored in Papyrus Leaves:
Perspectives on an Epigram Collection Attributed to Posidippus (P. Mil. Vogl. VIII 309),
Washington D.C. and Cambridge Mass.
Adler, A. (1967; 1971) [1928; 1931; 1933; 1935] Suidae Lexicon, 4 vols., Leipzig
Albis, R. V. (1996) Poet and Audience in the Argonautica of Apollonius, Lanham MD etc.
Allen, T. W. (1931) Homeri Ilias, vols. 2‐3, Oxford
Ardizzoni, A. (1967) Le Argonautiche Libro 1, Roma
Asper, M. (1997) Onomata Allotria: Zur Genese, Struktur und Funktion poetologischer Metaphern
bei Kallimachos, Stuttgart
Assmann, J. (1997) Das Kulturelle Gedächtnis: Schrift, Erinnerung und politische Identität in
frühen Hochkulturen, München
Austin, C., Bastianini, G. (2002) Posidippi Pellaei quae supersunt omnia, Milano
Austin, N. (1967) ʹIdyll 16: Theocritus and Simonidesʹ TAPA 98: 1‐12
Barbantani, S. (1993) ʹI poeti lirici del canone Alessandrino nellʹ epigrammatisticaʹ Aevum
Antiquum 6: 5‐97
Barigazzi, A. (1968) ʹIl testamento di Posidippo di Pellaʹ Hermes 96: 190‐216
Beckby, H. (1957‐1958) Anthologia Graeca: griechisch‐deutsch, München
Bell, J. M. (1978) ʹκίμβιξ και σοφός: Simonides in the Anecdotal Traditionʹ QUCC 28: 29‐86
Benedetto, G. (1993) Il sogno e lʹinvettiva: Momenti di storia dellʹ esegesi Callimachea, Firenze
Benveniste, E. (1948) Noms dʹagents et noms dʹaction en indo‐européen, Paris
Bergk, T. (1886) Kleine philologische Schriften: Bd. 2: Zur griechischen Litteratur, Halle
Bernabé Pajares, A. (2007) Poetarum epicorum Graecorum testimonia et fragmenta. Pars II:
Orphicorum et orphicis similium testimonia et fragmenta, Berlin etc.
Bernabé Pajares, A., Olmos, O. (eds.) (1996) Poetarum epicorum Graecorum testimonia et
fragmenta, Leipzig
Bernsdorff, H. (1994) ʹPolyphem und Daphnis: Zu Theokrits sechstem Idyllʹ Philologus 138:
38‐51
‐‐‐ (2001) Hirten in der nicht‐bukolischen Dichtung des Hellenismus, Stuttgart
Bing, P. (1988) The Well‐read Muse: Present and Past in Callimachus and the Hellenistic Poets,
Göttingen
‐‐‐ (1988b) ʹTheocritusʹ Epigrams on the Statues of Ancient Poetsʹ A&A 34: 117‐123
‐‐‐ (1990) ʹA Pun on Aratusʹ Name in Verse 2 of the Phainomena?ʹ HSCPh 93: 281‐5
‐‐‐ (1993) ʹThe Bios‐tradition and Poetsʹ Lives in Hellenistic Poetryʹ In: Nomodeiktes. Greek
Studies in Honor of Martin Ostwald (eds. Rosen, R. M., Farrell, J.), Ann Arbor, 619‐31
‐‐‐ (1993b) ʹImpersonation of Voice in Callimachusʹ Hymn to Apolloʹ TAPA 123: 181‐198
‐‐‐ (1995) ʹErgänzungsspiel in the Epigrams of Callimachusʹ A&A 41: 117‐23
265
‐‐‐ (2002) ʹThe Un‐read Muse? Inscribed Epigram and its Readers in Antiquityʹ In: Hellenistic
Epigrams (eds. Harder, M. A., Regtuit, R. F., Wakker, G. C.), Leuven, 38‐66
Blomqvist, J. (1998) ʹThe Development of the Satirical Epigram in the Hellenistic Periodʹ In:
Genre in Hellenistic Poetry (eds. Harder, M. A., Regtuit, R. F., Wakker, G. C.), Groningen, 45‐60
Blum, R. (1991) Kallimachos: The Alexandrian Library and the Origins of Bibliography, Madison,
Wisc.
Blumenthal, H. J. (1978) ʹCallimachus, Epigram 28, Numenius Fr. 20, and the Meaning of
κυκλικόςʹ CQ 28: 125‐127
Bourdieu, P. F. (1989) Opstellen over Smaak, Habitus en het Veldbegrip, gekozen door Dick Pels,
vertaald door Rokus Hofstede et. al. Amsterdam
‐‐‐ (1993) The Field of Cultural Production: Essays on Art and Literature (ed. Johnson, R.)
Cambridge
Bowie, E. L. (1985) ʹTheocritusʹ Seventh Idyll, Philetas and Longusʹ CQ 35: 67‐91
‐‐‐ (1986) ʹEarly Greek Elegy, Symposium and Public Festivalʹ JHS 106: 13‐35
‐‐‐ (1993) ʹLies, Fiction and Slander in Early Greek Poetryʹ In: Lies and Fiction in the Ancient
World (eds. Gill, C., Wiseman, T. P.) Exeter, 1‐37
‐‐‐ (1996) ʹFrame and Framed in Theocritusʹ Poems 6 and 7ʹ In: Theocritus (eds. Harder, M. A.,
Regtuit, R. F., Wakker, G. C.), Groningen, 91‐100
Bowra, C. M. (1936) Greek Lyric Poetry from Alcman to Simonides, Oxford
Bremer, J. M. (1993) ʹAristophanes on his Own Poetryʹ In: Aristophane: sept exposés suivis de
discussions (eds. Degani, E., Bremer, J. M.), Vandoeuvres‐Genève, 125‐165
Brink, K. O. (1946) ʹCallimachus and Aristotle: An Inquiry into Callimachusʹ πρὸς
Πραξιφάνηνʹ CQ 40: 11‐26
Brown, E. L. (1981) ʹThe Lycidas of Theocritusʹ Idyll 7ʹ HSCPh 86: 59‐100
Bruns, I. (1896) Das literarische Porträt der Griechen im Fünften Jahrhundert vor Christi Geburt,
Hildesheim
Buck, C. D., Petersen, W. (1984) [1945] A Reverse Index of Greek Nouns and Adjectives: Arranged
by Terminations, with Brief Historical Introductions, Chicago
Bulloch, A. W. (1985) Callimachus: The Fifth Hymn, Oxford
‐‐‐ (1989) ʹHellenistic Poetryʹ In: The Cambridge History of Classical Literature: Vol. 1: Greek
Literature (eds. Easterling, P. E., Knox, B. M. W.), Cambridge, 541‐621
Bulloch, A. W., Gruen, E. S., Long, A. A., Stewart, A. (1993) Images and Ideologies: Self‐
definition in the Hellenistic World, Berkeley etc.
Bundy, E. L. (1962) [1896] Studia Pindarica, Berkeley etc.
Burkert, W. (1985) Greek Religion ‐ Archaic and Classical, Oxford
Burnet, J., (1967) [1907] Platonis opera, vol. 5. Oxford
Busch, S. (1993) ʹOrpheus in die Argonautika des Apollonios Rhodiosʹ Hermes 121: 301‐324
Cairns, F. (1984) ʹTheocritusʹ First Idyll: The Literary Programmeʹ Wiener Studien 97: 89‐113
Cameron, A. (1963) ʹThe Form of the Thalysiaʹ In: Miscellanea di studi alessandrini in memoria di
A. Rostagni (eds. anonymous), Torino, 291‐307
Cameron, A. D. E. (1972) ʹCallimachus on Aratusʹ Sleepless Nightsʹ CR 22: 169‐70
‐‐‐ (1992) ʹGenre and Style in Callimachusʹ TAPA 122: 305‐312
‐‐‐ (1995) Callimachus and his Critics, Princeton
‐‐‐ (1995b) ʹAncient Anagramsʹ AJPh 116: 477‐484
Campbell, D. A. (1982) [1967] Greek Lyric Poetry: A Selection of Early Greek Lyric, Elegiac and
Iambic Poetry, Bristol
Campbell, M. (1981) Echoes and Imitations of Early Epic in Apollonius Rhodius, Leiden
266
Canfora, L. A. (1989) The Vanished Library: A Wonder of the Ancient World, Berkeley etc.
Caspers, C. L. (2006) ʹThe Loves of the Poets: Allusions in Hermesianax fr. 7 Powellʹ In:
Beyond the Canon (eds. Harder, M. A., Regtuit, R. F., Wakker, G. C.), Leuven, 21‐42
Cassola, F. (1999) Inni Omerici, Milano
Cazzaniga, I. (1972) ʹNosside, nome aristocratico per la poetessa di Locriʹ ASNP 2: 173‐6
Clapp, E. B. (1913) ʹTwo Pindaric Poems of Theocritusʹ CPh 8: 310‐316
Clare, R. J. (2002) The Path of the Argo: Language, Imagery and Narrative in the Argonautica of
Apollonius Rhodius, Cambridge
Clauss, J. J. (1993) The Best of the Argonauts: The Redefinition of the Epic Hero in Book 1 of
Apolloniusʹs ʺArgonauticaʺ, Berkeley etc.
‐‐‐ (2003) ʹOnce upon a time on Cos: A Banquet with Pan on the Side in Theocritusʹ Idyll 7ʹ
HSCPh 101: 289‐302
Clay, D. (1998) ʹThe Theory of Literary Persona in Antiquityʹ MD 40: 9‐40
‐‐‐ (2004) Archilochos Heros: The Cult of Poets in the Greek Polis, Washington D.C.
Clayman, D. L. (1980) Callimachusʹ Iambi, Leiden
Couat, A. (1885) La poésie alexandrine, Paris
Courtney, E. (1990) ʹGreek and Latin Acrostichsʹ Philologus 134: 3‐13
Crowther, N. B. (1979) ʹWater and Wine as Symbols of Inspirationʹ Mnemosyne 32: 1‐11
Cunningham, I. C. (1971) Mimiambi / Herodas, Oxford
Cuypers, M. P. (1997) A Commentary on Apollonius Rhodius Argonautica 2.1‐310, Leiden
‐‐‐ (2004) ʹApollonius of Rhodesʹ In: Narrators, Narratees and Narratives in Ancient Greek
Literture (eds. De Jong, I. J. F., Nünlist, R., Bowie, A.), Leiden, 43‐63
‐‐‐ (2005) ʹInteractive Particles and Narrative Voices in Homer and Apollonius Rhodiusʹ
Caeculus 6: 35‐69
DʹAlessio, G. B. (1996) Callimaco, Inni, Epigrammi, Frammenti, vol. 1, Milano
‐‐‐ (1996) Callimaco: Aitia, Giambi e altri frammenti, vol. 2, Milan
Danielewicz, J. (2005) ʹFurther Hellenistic Acrostics: Aratus and Othersʹ Mnemosyne 58: 321‐
334
Davies, G. A. (1925) ʹCallimachus, Epig. XXIʹ CR 39: 176
De Jong, I. J. F. (1987) Narrators and Focalizers: The Presentation of the Story in the Iliad,
Amsterdam
‐‐‐ (2002) ʹVan poeta tot persona in de vroegste Griekse literatuurʹ Lampas 35: 387‐399
‐‐‐ (2004) ʹGeen held zonder dichterʹ Lampas 37: 179‐186
De Marco, V. (1963) ʹApollonio Rodio I 1‐22ʹ In: Miscellanea di studi alessandrini in memoria di
A. Rostagni (eds. anonymous), Torino, 350‐355
Degani, E. (1973) ʹNote sulla fortuna di Archiloco e di Ipponatte in epoca ellenisticaʹ QUCC
16: 79‐104
‐‐‐ (1991) Hipponax: Testimonia et Fragmenta, Stuttgart
Denniston, J. D. (1981 [1954]) The Greek Particles, Oxford
Depew, M. J. (1992) ʹΙαμβεῖον καλείται νῦν: Genre, Occasion, and Imitation in Callimachus,
fr. 191 and 203 Pf.ʹ TAPA 122: 313‐330
‐‐‐ (1993) ʹMimesis and Aetiology in Callimachus’ Hymnsʹ In: Callimachus (eds. Harder, M. A.,
Regtuit, R. F., Wakker, G. C.), Groningen, 57‐77
‐‐‐ (2000) ʹEnacted and Represented Dedications: Genre and Greek Hymnʹ In: Matrices of
Genre. Authors, Canons, and Society (eds. Depew, M., Obbink, D.), Cambridge Mass., 59‐80
Dickie, M. W. (1994) ʹWhich Posidippus?ʹ GRBS 35: 373‐383
‐‐‐ (1996) ʹThe Dionysiac Rituals at Pellaʹ ZPE 109: 81‐6
267
Diels, H., Kranz, W. (1966) [1951] Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, vol. 1, Berlin
‐‐‐ (1966) [1952] Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, vol. 2, Berlin
Dornseiff, F. (1966) ʹHesiods Werke und Tage und das alte Morgenlandʹ Philologus 110: 397‐415
Dover, K. J. (1971) Theocritus: Select Poems, Oxford
‐‐‐ (1993) Aristophanes: Frogs, Oxford
Drachmann, A. B. (1: 1903; 2: 1910; 3: 1927) Scholia vetera in Pindari carmina 3 vols., Leipzig
Dräger, P. (2001) Die Argonautika des Apollonios: Das zweite Zorn‐epos der griechischen
Literatur, München
Dugan, J. R. (2005) Making a New Man: Ciceronian Self‐fashioning in the Rhetorical Works,
Oxford
Eagleton, T. (1985) Literary Theory: An Introduction, Oxford
Effe, B. (1977) Dichtung und Lehre: Untersuchungen zur Typologie des antiken Lehrgedichts,
München
‐‐‐ (1988) ʹDas poetologische Programm des Simichidas: Theokrit Id. 7,37‐41ʹ Würzb. Jbb. 14:
87‐91.
‐‐‐ (1995) ʹAlexandrinisches Herrscherlob: Ambivalenzen literarischer Panegyrikʹ In:
Affirmation und Kritik, zur Politischen Funktion von Kunst und Literatur in Altertum (eds. Effe, B.,
Binder, G.), Trier, 107‐123
Eichgrün, E. (1961) Kallimachos und Apollonios Rhodios, Berlin
Else, G. F. (1986) Plato and Aristotle on Poetry, Chapel Hill
Enenkel, K. A. E., Peijffer, I. L. (eds.) (2004) The Manipulative Mode, Political Propaganda in
Antiquity: A Collection of Case studies, Leiden
Erbse, H. (1975) Scholia Graeca in Homeri Iliadem: (Scholia vetera) Vol. 4 Scholia ad libros O‐T
continens, Berlin
Erren, M. (1967) Die Phainomena des Aratos von Soloi: Untersuchungen zum Sach‐ und
Sinnverständnis, Wiesbaden
Erskine, A. (1995) ʹCulture and Power in Ptolemaic Egypt: The Museum and Library of
Alexandriaʹ Greece and Rome 42: 38‐48
Faerber, H. (1932) Zur Dichterischen Kunst in Apollonios Rhodiosʹ Argonautika: Die Gleichnisse,
Berlin
Falter, O. (1934) Der Dichter und sein Gott bei den Griechen Und Römern, Würzburg
Fantuzzi, M. (1988) Ricerche su Apollonio Rodio: diacronie della dizione epica, Roma
‐‐‐ (2001) ʹHeroes, Descendants of Hemitheoi: The Proemium of Theocritus 17 and Simonides
11 W2ʹ In: The New Simonides: Contexts of Praise and Desire (eds. Boedeker, D., Sider, D.),
Oxford, 232‐242
‐‐‐ (2005) ʹPosidippus at Court: The Contribution of the Hippika of P. Mil. Vogl. VIII 309 to the
Ideology of Ptolemaic Kingshipʹ In: The New Posidippus: A Hellenistic Poetry Book (ed.
Gutzwiller, K. J.), Oxford, 249‐268
Fantuzzi, M., Hunter, R. L. (2002) Muse e Modelli: La poesia ellenistica da Alessandro Magno ad
Augusto, Roma‐Bari
‐‐‐ (2004) Tradition and Innovation in Hellenistic Poetry, Cambridge
Feeney, D. C. (1991) The Gods in Epic: Poets and Critics of the Classical Tradition, Oxford
Ferguson, J. (1970) ʹThe Epigrams of Callimachusʹ Greece and Rome 17: 64‐80
Fontenrose, J. E. (1978) The Delphic Oracle: Its Responses and Operations, with a Catalogue of
Responses, Berkeley etc.
Ford, A. L. (1981) A Study of Early Greek Terms for Poetry: ἀοιδή, ἔπος and ποίησις, Ann Arbor
268
‐‐‐ (2002) The Origins of Criticism: Literary Culture and Poetic Theory in Classical Greece,
Princeton
Fränkel, H. F. (1968) Noten zu den Argonautika des Apollonios von Rhodos, München
Fraser, P. M. (1972) Ptolemaic Alexandria, vols. I (text), II (notes), III (indexes), Oxford
Freese, J. H. (1926) Aristotle: The Art of Rhetoric, London
Furley, W., Bremer, J. M. (2001) Greek Hymns vol. 1: The Texts in Translation, Tübingen
Fusillo, M. (1985) Il Tempo delle Argonautiche: Un analisi del racconto in Apollonio Rodio, Roma
Gabathuler, M. (1937) Hellenistische Epigramme auf Dichter, St Gallen
Gerber, D. E. (ed.) (1997) A Companion to the Greek Lyric Poets, Leiden
‐‐‐ (1999) Greek Iambic Poetry from the Seventh to the Fifth Centuries BC, Cambridge Mass. etc.
Gercke, A. (1889) ʹAlexandrinische Studienʹ RM 44: 127‐150
Giangrande, G. (1968) ʹThéocrite, Simichidas et les Thalysiesʹ AC 37: 491‐533
‐‐‐ (1980) Scripta Minora Alexandrina 1, Amsterdam
Goldhill, S. (1991) The Poetʹs Voice: Essays on Poetics and Greek Literature, Cambridge
Gonzalez, J. M. (2000) ʹMusai Hypophetores: Apollonius of Rhodes on Inspiration and
Interpretationʹ HSCPh 100: 270‐292
Gow, A. S. F. (1940) ʹThe Seventh Idyll of Theocritusʹ CQ 34: 47‐55
‐‐‐ (1952) Theocritus vols. I :Text and II :Commentary, Oxford
Gow, A. S. F., Page, D. L. (1965) The Hellenistic Epigrams, vols. I: Text and II: Commentary,
Oxford
Gow, A. S. F., Scholfield, A. F. (1997) [1953] Nicander: The Poems and Poetical Fragments, Bristol
Green, P. M. (1997) The Argonautika by Apollonios Rhodios, Berkeley etc.
Greenblatt, S. J. (1980) Renaissance Self‐fashioning: From More to Shakespeare, Chicago etc.
Greenblatt, S. J., Gallagher, C. (2000) Practicing New Historicism, Chicago etc.
Greindl, M. (1938) κλέος, κῦδος, τίμη, εὔχη, φάτις, δόξα: Eine bedeutungsgeschichtliche
Untersuchung des epischen und lyrischen Sprachgebrauchs, München
Gresseth, G. K. (1970) ʹThe Homeric Sirensʹ TAPA 101: 203‐218
Griffith, M. (1983) ʹPersonality in Hesiodʹ CA 2: 37‐65
Griffiths, F. T. (1976) ʹTheocritusʹ Silent Dioscuriʹ GRBS 17: 353‐367
‐‐‐ (1979) Theocritus at Court, Leiden
Guichard, L. A. (2004) Asclepíades de Samos: Epigramas y fragmentos, Bern etc.
Gundert, H. (1978) [1935] Pindar und sein Dichterberuf, Utrecht
Guthrie, W. K. C. (1952) [1935] Orpheus and Greek Religion: a Study of the Orphic Movement,
London
Gutzwiller, K. J. (1983) ʹCharites or Hiero: Theocritusʹ Idyll 16ʹ RM 126: 212‐38
‐‐‐ (1991) Theocritusʹ Pastoral Analogies: The Formation of a Genre, Madison Wisc. etc.
‐‐‐ (1996) ʹThe Evidence for Theocritean Poetry Booksʹ In: Theocritus (eds. Harder, M. A.,
Regtuit, R. F., Wakker, G. C.), Groningen, 119‐148
‐‐‐ (1998) Poetic Garlands: Hellenistic Epigrams in Context, Berkeley & Los Angeles
‐‐‐ (ed.) (2005) The New Posidippus: A Hellenistic Poetry Book, Oxford
Häussler, R. (1973) ʹDer Tod der Musenʹ A&A 19: 117‐145
Halperin, D. M. (1983) Before Pastoral: Theocritus and the Ancient Tradition of Bucolic Poetry,
New Haven
Harder, M. A. (1988) ʹCallimachus and the Muses: Some Aspects of Narrative Technique in
Aetia 1‐2ʹ Prometheus 14: 1‐15
‐‐‐ (1990) ʹUntrodden Paths: Where do they lead?ʹ HSCPh 93: 287‐309
269
‐‐‐ (1992) ʹInsubstantial Voices: Some Observations on the Hymns of Callimachusʹ CQ 42: 384‐
394
‐‐‐ (1998) ʹʹGeneric Gamesʹ in Callimachusʹ Aetiaʹ In: Genre in Hellenistic Poetry (eds. Harder,
M. A., Regtuit, R. F., Wakker, G. C.), Groningen, 95‐113
‐‐‐ (2001) ʹWie ben ik? Rol en masker in Callimachusʹ Aetia en Iambiʹ Lampas 35: 399‐416
‐‐‐ (2004) ʹCallimachusʹ In: Narrators, Narratees, and Narratives in Ancient Greek Literature (eds.
De Jong, I. J. F., Nünlist, R., Bowie, A.), Leiden, 63‐81
Harriott, R. M. (1969) Poetry and Criticism before Plato, London
Harvey, A. E. (1955) ʹThe Classification of Greek Lyric Poetryʹ CQ 5: 157‐175
Haslam, M. (1992) ʹHidden Signs: Aratus Diosemeiai 46ff. Vergil Georgics 1.424ffʹ HSCPh 94:
199‐204
Havelock, E. A. (1963) Preface to Plato, Cambridge, Mass.
‐‐‐ (1986) The Muse Learns to Write: Reflections on Orality and Literacy from Antiquity to the
Present, New Haven etc.
Henderson, J. (1976) ʹThe Cologne Epode and the Convention of Early Greek Erotic Poetryʹ
Arethusa 9: 159‐79
‐‐‐ (1991 [1975]) The Maculate Muse: Obscene Language in Attic Comedy, Oxford
Henrichs, A. (1979) ʹCallimachus Epigram 28: A Fastidious Priamelʹ HSCPh 83: 207‐212
Herington, J. (1985) Poetry into Drama: Early Tragedy and the Greek Poetic Tradition, Berkeley
Heubeck, A. (1984 [1973]) ʹEinige Überlegungen zu Theokrits Thalysienʹ Ziva Antika 23: 5‐15
Hobsbawm, E. J. E., Ranger, T. O. (eds.) (1984) The Invention of Tradition, Cambridge
Hofstetter, E. (1990) Sirenen im Archaischen und Klassischen Griechenland, Würzburg
Hollis, A. S. (1990) Callimachus: Hecale, Oxford
‐‐‐ (1996) ʹHeroic honours for Philetas?ʹ ZPE 110: 56‐62
Homolle, M. T. (1909) Fouilles de Delphes, Paris
Hopkinson, N. (1984) Callimachus: Hymn to Demeter, Cambridge
‐‐‐ (1988) A Hellenistic Anthology, Cambridge
Hose, M. (1994) ʹSyntonos agrypnie (Kallimachos Epigramm 27 Pf.),ʹ Glotta 72: 196‐199
Housman, A. E. (1921) ʹRostagniʹs Ibisʹ CR 35: 67‐8
Hubbard, K. T. (1998) The Pipes of Pan: Intertextual and Literary Filiation in the Pastoral Tradition
from Theocritus to Milton, Ann Arbor
Hunter, R. L. (1987) ʹMedeaʹs Flight: The Fourth Book of the Argonauticaʹ CQ 37: 129‐139
‐‐‐ (1992) ʹCallimachus and Heraclitusʹ MD 28: 113‐123
‐‐‐ (1993) Apollonius Rhodius: The Argonautica, Literary Studies, Cambridge
‐‐‐ (1996) Theocritus and the Archaeology of Greek Poetry, Cambridge
‐‐‐ (1999) Theocritus: A Selection, Cambridge
‐‐‐ (2001) ʹThe Poetics of Narrative in the Argonauticaʹ In: A Companion to Apollonius Rhodius
(eds. Papanghelis, T., Rengakos, A.), Leiden, 93‐126
‐‐‐ (2003) The Encomium of Ptolemy Philadephus, Berkeley etc.
‐‐‐ (2004) ʹTheocritus and Moschusʹ In: Narrators, Narratees, and Narratives in Ancient Greek
Literature (eds. De Jong, I. J. F., Nünlist, R., Bowie, A.), Leiden, 83‐97
‐‐‐ (2007) Review of Brian W. Breed, Pastoral Inscriptions: Reading and Writing Virgilʹs Eclogues.
BMCR 2007.03.39
Hutchinson, G. O. (1988) Hellenistic Poetry, Oxford
‐‐‐ (2001) Greek Lyric Poetry: A Commentary on Selected Larger Pieces : Alcman, Stesichorus,
Sappho, Alcaeus, Ibycus, Anacreon, Simonides, Bacchylides, Pindar, Sophocles, Euripides, Oxford
Huxley, G. L. (1969) Greek Epic Poetry from Eumelos to Panyassis, Cambridge, Mass.
270
Huys, M. (1991) Le poème élégiaque hellénistique P. Brux. Inv. E. 8934 et P. Sorb. Inv. 2254,
Bruxelles
Iacobacci, G. (1993) ʹOrfeo Argonauta: Apollonio Rodio 1.496‐511ʹ In: Orfeo e lʹOrfismo (ed.
Masaracchia, A.), Roma, 77‐92
Iles Johnston, S. (2005) ʹIntroduction: Divining Divinationʹ In: Mantikê: Studies in Ancient
Divination (eds. Struck, P. T., Iles Johnston, S.), Leiden,
Jacques, J.‐M. (1960) ʹSur un acrostich dʹAratos (Phén., 783‐787)ʹ REA 62: 48‐61
Janko, R. (1992) ʹThe Iliad: A Commentary (vol. IV, books 13‐16)ʹ (ed. Kirk, G. S.), Cambridge,
‐‐‐ (2003) [2000] Philodemus: On Poems, Book One, Oxford
Johnson, R. (1993) ʹPierre Bourdieu on Art, Literature and Cultureʹ In: The Field of Cultural
Production: Essays on Art and Literature (ed. Johnson, R.), Cambridge,
Jung, F. (1929) Hipponax Redividus, Bonn
Kahane, A. (1994) ʹCallimachus, Apollonius, and the Poetics of Mudʹ TAPA 124: 121‐133
Kaibel, G. (1894) ʹGriechische Friedhofspoesieʹ Deutsche Revue über das gesamte nationale Leben
der Gegenwart 19: 367‐80
‐‐‐ (1965;1966) [1887;1890] Athenaei Naucratitae Deipnosophistarum libri xv, 3 vols. 1‐2; 3, Leipzig
Kambylis, A. (1965) Die Dichterweihe und ihre Symbolik: Untersuchungen zu Hesiodos,
Kallimachos, Properz und Ennius, Heidelberg
Kassel, R. (1968) [1965] Aristotelis de arte poetica liber, Oxford
Keil, D. (1998) Lexikalische Raritäten in Homer: Ihre Bedeutung für den Prozess der Literarisierung
des griechischen Epos, Trier
Kennedy, G. A. (ed.) (1989) The Cambridge History of Literary Criticism: Vol. 1, Classical
Criticism, Cambridge
Kenney, E. J. (1979) ʹThe Typology of Didacticʹ CR 29: 71‐73
Kerkhecker, A. (1999) Callimachusʹ Book of Iambi, Oxford
Kern, O. F. G. (1972) [1922] Orphicorum fragmenta, Zürich
Kidd, D. A. (1997) Aratus Phaenomena, Cambridge
Klein, L. (1931) ʹDie Göttertechnik in den Argonautika des Apollonios Rhodiosʹ Philologus 86:
18‐51; 215‐257
Kleingünther, A. (1933) Πρῶτος εὑρέτης: Untersuchungen zur Geschichte einer Fragestellung,
Klooster, J. J. H. (2007) ʹDe Onsterfelijke Inspiratie van Kennis en Leugens: Sirenen bij
Homerus en Apollonius Rhodiusʹ Tetradio 15: 185‐200
‐‐‐ (2007) ʹReview of Gutzwiller 2005 ʹThe new Posidippus: A Hellenistic Poetry Bookʹʹ
Mnemosyne 60: 297‐301
‐‐‐ (2007) ʹTheocritusʹ In: Time in Ancient Greek Narrative (eds. De Jong, I. J. F., Nünlist, R.),
Leiden, 63‐80
Knauer, O. (1935) Die Epigramme des Asklepiades von Samos, Würzburg
Knight, V. H. (1995) The Renewal of Epic: Responses to Homer in the Argonautica of Apollonius,
Leiden
Knox, P. E. (1985) ʹWine, Water and Callimachean Polemicsʹ HSCPh 89: 107‐119
Köhnken, A. (1981) ʹApolloʹs Retort to Envyʹs Criticism: Two Questions of Relevance in
Callimachusʹ Hymn 2, 105ff.ʹ AJPh 102: 411‐422
‐‐‐ (2001) ʹHellenistic Chronology: Theocritus, Callimachus and Apollonius Rhodiusʹ In: A
Companion to Apollonius Rhodius (eds. Papanghelis, T., Rengakos, A.), Leiden, 73‐92
Körte, A., Händel, P. (1960) Die Hellenistische Dichtung, Stuttgart
Kosmetatou, E. (2000) ʹLycophron’s Alexandra Reconsidered: The Attalid Connectionʹ Hermes
128: 32‐53
271
‐‐‐ (2004) ʹConstructing Legitimacy: The Ptolemaic Familiengruppe as a Means for Self‐
Definition in Posidippusʹ Hippikaʹ In: Labored in Papyrus Leaves: Perspectives on an Epigram
Collection Attributed to Posidippus (P. Mil. Vogl. VIII 309) (eds. Acosta‐Hughes, B., Kosmetatou,
E., Baumbach, M.), Washington D.C. and Cambridge Mass. etc., 225‐246
‐‐‐ (2004) ʹVision and Visibility: Art Historical Theory paints a portrait of New Leaderschip in
Posidippusʹ Andriantopoiikaʹ In: Labored in Papyrus Leaves. Perspectives on an Epigram Collection
Attributed to Posidippus (P. Mil. Vogl. VIII 309) (eds. Acosta‐Hughes, B., Kosmetatou, E.,
Baumbach, M.), Washington D.C. and Cambridge Mass. etc., 187‐211
Kranz, W. (1967) ʹDas Verhältnis des Schöpfers zu seinem Werk in der althellenischen
Literaturʹ In: Studien zur Antiken Literatur und ihrem Fortwirken (ed. Vogt, E.), Heidelberg, 7‐26
‐‐‐ (1967) ʹSphragis: Ichform und Namensiegel als Eingangs‐ und Schlussmotiv antiker
Dichtungʹ In: Studien zur antiken Literatur und ihrem Fortwirken (ed. Vogt, E.), Heidelberg, 27‐
79
Krevans, N. (1993) ʹFighting against Antimachus: The Lyde and the Aetia reconsideredʹ In:
Callimachus (eds. Harder, M. A., Regtuit, R. F., Wakker, G. C.), Groningen, 149‐161
‐‐‐ (2005) ʹThe Editorʹs Toolbox: Strategies for Selection and Presentation in the Milan
Epigram Papyrusʹ In: The New Posidippus, A Hellenistic Poetry Book (ed. Gutzwiller, K.),
Oxford, 81‐96
Kroll, W. (1924) Studien zum Verständnis der römischen Literatur, Stuttgart
Kyriakou, P. (1995) Homeric hapax legomena in the Argonautica of Apollonius Rhodius,
Stuttgart
La Penna, A. (1957) P. Ovidi Nasonis Ibis, Firenze
Lai, A. (1995) ʹIl χλοέρον σισύμβρον di Nicia, medico poeta Milesioʹ QUCC 16: 125‐131
Lanata, G. (1963) Poetica Preplatonica: Testimonianze e frammenti, Firenze
Latacz, J., Stövesandt, M. (2000) Homers Ilias: Gesammtkommentar auf der Grundlage der
Ausgabe von Ameis‐Hentze‐Cauer, München etc.
Latte, K. (1957) ʹΑΣΚΟΛΙΑΣΜΟΣʹ Hermes 85: 25‐391
Laursen, S. (1992) ʹTheocritusʹ Hymn to the Dioscuri: Unity and Intentionʹ C&M 43: 71‐95
Lawall, G. (1966) ʹApolloniusʹ Argonautica: Jason as Anti‐Heroʹ HSCPh 19: 121‐169
‐‐‐ (1967) Theocritusʹ Coan Pastorals: A Poetry Book, Cambridge, Mass.
Lefkowitz, M. R. (1980) ʹThe Quarrel between Callimachus and Apolloniusʹ ZPE 40: 1‐19
‐‐‐ (1981) The Lives of the Greek Poets, Baltimore
‐‐‐ (1991) First‐person Fictions: Pindarʹs Poetic ʹIʹ, Oxford
Legrand, P.‐E. (1898) Etude sur Théocrite, Paris
‐‐‐ (1960) Hérodote. Histoires, vol. 4, Paris
Lehnus, L. (1989) Bibliografia Callimachea, 1489‐1988, Genova
Lelli, E. (2004) Critica e polemiche letterarie nei ʹGiambiʹ di Callimaco, Alessandria
Lembach, K. (1970) Die Pflanzen bei Theokrit, Heidelberg
Leo, F. (1901) Die griechisch‐römische Biographie nach ihrer literarischen Form, Hildesheim
Lesky, A. (1971) Geschichte der griechischen Literatur, Bern
Levin, D. N. (1971) Apolloniusʹ Argonautica Re‐examined: The Neglected First and Second Books,
Leiden
Levitan, W. (1979) ʹPlexed Artistry: Aratean Acrosticsʹ Glyph 5: 55‐68
Lindsell, A. (1937) ʹWas Theocritus a Botanist?ʹ Greece & Rome 6: 78‐93
Livrea, E. (1973) Apollonii Rhodii Argonauticon Liber iv, Firenze
Lloyd‐Jones, H. (1963) ʹThe Seal of Posidippusʹ JHS 83: 75‐99
Lloyd‐Jones, H., Parsons, P. J. (eds.) (1983) Supplementum Hellenisticum, Berlin, New York
272
Lobel, E. (1928) ʹNicanderʹs Signatureʹ CQ 22: 114‐115
Lohse, G. (1966) ʹDie Kunstauffassung in VII. Idyll Theokrits und das Programm des
Kallimachosʹ Hermes 94: 413‐425
‐‐‐ (1967) σύντονος ἀγρυπνίη (zu Kallimachos Epigr. 27,4)ʹ Hermes 95: 379‐381
‐‐‐ (1973) ʹDer Aitienprolog des Kallimachos als Reproduktion von Wirklichkeitʹ A&A 19: 20‐
43
Long, A. A. (1978) ʹTimon of Phlius, Pyrrhonist and Satiristʹ Proceedings of the Cambridge
Philological Society 204: 68‐91
Long, H. S. (1966) [1964] Diogenis Laertii vitae philosophorum, 2 vols., Oxford
Lord, A. B. (1960) The Singer of Tales, Cambridge Mass. etc.
Louden, B. (1995) ʹCategories of Homeric Wordplayʹ TAPA 125: 27‐46
Lowe, N. J. (2004) ʹLycophronʹ In: Narrators, Narratees, and Narratives in Ancient Greek
Literature (eds. De Jong, I. J. F., Nünlist, R., Bowie, A.), Leiden, 307‐314
Luck, G. (1954) ʹDie Dichterinnen der griechischen Anthologieʹ MH 11: 170‐187
Maehler, H. (1963) Die Auffassung des Dichterberufs im frühen Griechentum bis zur Zeit Pindars,
Göttingen
‐‐‐ (2003) Bacchylides: Carmina cum fragmentis, München
Maehler, H., Snell, B. (1971) Pindari carmina cum fragmentis, pt. 1, 5th edn, Leipzig
‐‐‐ (1975) Pindari carmina cum fragmentis, pt. 2, 4th edn, Leipzig
Margolies deForest, M. (1994) Apolloniusʹ Argonautica: A Callimachean Epic, Leiden
Martin, J. (1965) Arati Phaenomena, Firenze
‐‐‐ (1974) Scholia in Aratum vetera, Stuttgart
Masaracchia, A. (1993) ʹOrfeo e gli ʹOrficiʹ in Platoneʹ In: Orfeo e lʹOrfismo (ed. Masaracchia,
A.), Roma, 172‐195
‐‐‐ (ed.) (1993) Orfeo e lʹOrfismo, Roma
Matthews, V. J. (1996) Antimachus of Colophon: Text and Commentary, Leiden
McLeod, R. (ed.) (2004) The Library of Alexandria: Center of Learning in the Ancient World,
London
McLeod, W. E. (1961) ʹOral Bards at Delphiʹ TAPA 92: 317‐325
Merkelbach, R. (1952) ʹBettelgedichte, Theokrit, Simonides und Walther von der Vogelweideʹ
RM 95: 312‐327
Meyer, D. (2005) Inszeniertes Lesevergnügen: Das inschriftliche Epigramm und seine Rezeption bei
Kallimachos, Stuttgart
Mineur, W. H. (1985) ʹFrom Book‐worms to Reed‐warblersʹ Mnemosyne 38: 383‐285
Momigliano, A. (1971) The Development of Greek Biography: Four Lectures, Cambridge, Mass.
Monteil, P. (1968) Théocrite, Idylles (II, V, VII, XI, XV), Paris
Mooney, G. W. (1912) The Argonautica of Apollonius Rhodius, London
Morrison, A. D. (2007) The Narrator in Ancient Greek and Hellenistic Poetry, Cambridge
Most, G. W. (2003) ʹEpinician Enviesʹ In: Envy, Spite and Jealousy; The Rivalrous Emotions in
Ancient Greece (eds. Konstan, D., Rutter, K.), Edinburgh, 123‐143
‐‐‐ (2006) Hesiod: Theogony, Works and Days, Testimonia, Cambridge Mass.
‐‐‐ (2007) Hesiod: The Shield, Catalogue of Women, Other Fragments, Cambridge Mass.
Murray, P. (1981) Plato on Poetry: Ion; Republic 376e‐398b9; Republic 595‐608b10, Cambridge
‐‐‐ (1981b) ʹPoetic Inspiration in Early Greeceʹ JHS 101: 87‐100
Musti, D. (1999) I Telchini, le Sirene: Immaginario mediterraneo e letteratura da Omero e Callimaco
al romanticismo europeo, Pisa
273
Nagy, G. (1979) The Best of the Achaeans: Concepts of the Hero in Archaic Greek Poetry, Baltimore
etc.
Nauta, R. R. (1990) ʹGattungsgeschichte als Rezeptionsgeschichte am Beispiel der Entstehung
der Bukolikʹ A&A 36: 117‐137
‐‐‐ (2002) Poetry for Patrons: Literary Communication in the Age of Domitian, Leiden
Nelis, D. P. (1992) ʹDemodocus and the Song of Orpheusʹ MH 49: 153‐70
Nickau, K. (2002) ʹDer Name >Simichidas< bei Theokritʹ Hermes 130: 389‐403
Nisetich, F. J. (2001) The Poems of Callimachus, Oxford
Nünlist, R. (1998) Poetologische Bildersprache in der Frühgriechischen Dichtung, Stuttgart
Ogilvie, R. M. (1962) ʹThe Song of Thyrsisʹ JHS 82: 106‐10
OʹHara, J. J. (1996) True Names: Vergil and the Alexandrian Tradition of Wordplay, Ann Arbor
Ott, U. (1969) Die Kunst des Gegensatzes in Theokrits Hirtengedichten, Hildesheim
Pack, R. A. (1952) The Greek and Latin Literary Texts from Greco‐Roman Egypt, Ann Arbor
Paduano Faedo, L. (1970) ʹLʹinversione del rapporto poeta‐musa nella cultura ellenisticaʹ
ASNP: 377‐386
Page, D. L. (1955) Sappho and Alcaeus: An Introduction to the Study of Ancient Lesbian Poetry,
Oxford
‐‐‐ (1967) [1962] Poetae melici Graeci, Oxford
Page, D. L., Dawe, R. D. (1981) Further Greek Epigrams, Cambridge
Parke, H. W. (1967) The Oracles of Zeus, Oxford
‐‐‐ (1967b) The Greek Oracles, London
Parke, H. W., Wormell, D. E. W. (1956) The Delphic Oracle, Oxford
Parsons, E. A. (1967) The Alexandrian Library: Glory of the Hellenic World: Its Rise, Antiquities
and Destructions, New York
Parsons, P. J. (2002) ʹCallimachus and the Hellenistic Epigramʹ In: Callimaque: sept exposés
suivis de discussions (eds. Montanari, F., Lehnus, L.), Vandoeuvres‐Genève, 99‐136
Pertusi, A. (1955) Scholia vetera in Hesiodi Opera et Dies, Milano
Petroll, R. (1965) Die Äusserungen Theokrits über seine Person und seine Dichtung (Diss.),
Hamburg
Pfeiffer, R. C. F. O. (1934) Die neuen Diegeseis zu Kallimachos‐gedichten, München
‐‐‐ (1949) Callimachus vol. 1 fragmenta, Oxford
‐‐‐ (1953) Callimachus vol. 2: Hymni et Epigrammata, Oxford
‐‐‐ (1968) History of Classical Scholarship: Vol 1: From the Beginnings to the End of the Hellenistic
Age, Oxford
Pfeijffer, I. L. (2004) ʹPindar and Bacchylidesʹ In: Narrators, Narratees and Narrative in Ancient
Greek Literature (eds. De Jong, I. J. F., Nünlist, R., Bowie, A.), Leiden, 213‐235
Platthy, J. (1968) Sources on the Earliest Greek Libraries: with the Testimonia, Amsterdam
Porter, J. I. (1992) ʹ Hermeneutic Lines and Circles: Aristarchus and Crates on the Exegesis of
Homerʹ In: Homerʹs Ancient Readers: The Hermeneutics of Greek Epicʹs Earliest Exegetes (eds.
Lamberton, R., Keaney, J. J.), Princeton, 67‐115
Possanza, D. M. (2004) Translating the Heavens: Aratus, Germanicus and the Poetics of Latin
Translation, New York etc.
Powell, J. U. (1981) [1925] Collectanea Alexandrina, Oxford
Pratt, L. H. (1995) ʹThe Seal of Theognis, Writing, and Oral Poetryʹ AJPh 116: 171‐184
Prescott, H. W. (1899) ʹA Study of the Daphnis Mythʹ HSCPh 10: 121‐40
Pucci, P. (1979) ʹThe Song of the Sirensʹ Arethusa 12: 121‐132
Puelma, M. (1960) ʹDie Dichterbegegnung in Theokrits Thalysienʹ MH 17: 144‐164
274
Race, W. H. (1982) The Classical Priamel from Homer to Boethius, Leiden
‐‐‐ (1997) Pindar: Nemean Odes; Isthmian Odes; Fragments, Cambridge Mass.
‐‐‐ (1997) Pindar: Olympian Odes; Pythian Odes, Cambridge Mass.
Radke, G. (2007) Die Kindheit des Mythos: Die Erfindung der Literaturgeschichte in der Antike,
München
Radt, S. L. (1971) ʹTheocriteaʹ Mnemosyne 24: 251‐9
Reitzenstein, E. (1931) ʹZur Stiltheorie des Kallimachosʹ In: Festschrift Richard Reitzenstein
(eds. Fränkel, E., Fränkel, H.), Leipzig,
Reitzenstein, R. (1970) [1893] Epigramm und Skolion: Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte alexandrinischen
Dichtung, Hildesheim
Rengakos, A. (1993) Der Homertext und die hellenistischen Dichter, Stuttgart
‐‐‐ (1994) Apollonios Rhodios und die antike Homererklärung, München
‐‐‐ (2001) ʹApollonius Rhodius as a Homeric Scholarʹ In: A Companion to Apollonius Rhodius
(eds. Papanghelis, T. D., Rengakos, A.), Leiden, 193‐216
Rice, E. E. (1983) The Grand Procession of Ptolemy Philadelphus, Oxford
Risch, E. (1974) Wortbildung der homerischen Sprache, Berlin
Robbins, E. (1982) ʹFamous Orpheusʹ In: Orpheus, the Metamorphoses of a Myth (ed. Warden,
J.), Toronto, 3‐23
‐‐‐ (1997) ʹSimonidesʹ In: A Companion to the Greek Lyric Poets (ed. Gerber, D. E.), Leiden, 243‐
253
Rosen, R. M. (1992) ʹMixing of Genres and Literary program in Herondas Mimiamb 8ʹ HSCPh
94: 205‐216
Rosenmeyer, P. A. (1997) ʹHer Masterʹs Voice: Sapphoʹs dialogue with Homerʹ MD 39: 123‐
149
Rosenmeyer, T. G. (1969) The Green Cabinet: Theocritus and the European Pastoral Lyric,
Berkeley etc.
Ross, W. D. (1964) [1959] Aristotelis ars rhetorica, Oxford
Rossi, L. (1996) ʹIl testamento di Posidippo e le lamelle auree di Pellaʹ ZPE 112: 59‐65
‐‐‐ (2001) The Epigrams ascribed to Theocritus: A Method of Approach, Leuven
Rossi, L. E. (1971) ʹI generi letterari e le loro leggi scritte en non scritte nelle letterature
classicheʹ BICS 18: 69‐94
Ruijgh, C. J. (1984) ʹLe Dorien de Théocrite: Dialecte Cyrénien dʹAlexandrie et dʹEgypteʹ
Mnemosyne 37: 56‐88
Rumpel, J. (1879) Lexicon Theocriteum, Leipzig
Russell, D. A. (1981) Criticism in Antiquity, London
Rusten, J. S. (1982) Dionysius Scytobrachion, Opladen
Sale, W. (1965) ʹThe Popularity of Aratusʹ CJ 61: 160‐164
Schefold, K. F. (1965) Griechische Dichterbildnisse, Zürich
Schenkeveld, D. M. (1964) Studies in Demetriusʹ On Style, Amsterdam
Scherer, B. (2002) Mythos, Katalog und Prophezeiung: Studien zu den Argonautika des Apollonios
Rhodios, Groningen
Schmidt, E. A. (1987) Bukolische Leidenschaft,oder, über antike Hirtenpoesie, Frankfurt ‐ Bern ‐
New York
Schmidt, M. (1997) ʹVariae Lectiones oder Parallelstellen: Was notierten Zenodot und Aristarch
zu Homer?ʹ ZPE 115: 1‐12
Schmitz, T. A. (1999) ʹʹI hate all common thingsʹ: The Readerʹs Role in Callimachusʹ Aetia
Prologueʹ HSCPh 99: 151‐178
275
Schwinge, E. R. (1986) Künstlichkeit von Kunst: Zur Geschichtlichkeit der alexandrinischen Poesie,
München
Scodel, R. S. (1987) ʹHorace, Lucilius and Callimachean Polemicʹ HSCPh 91: 199‐215
Seaton, R. C. (1888) ʹNotes on Ap. Rhod. with Reference to Liddell and Scottʹ CR 2: 83‐84
‐‐‐ (1912) Apollonius Rhodius: Argonautica, Cambridge, Mass.
Seeck, G. A. (1975) ʹDichterische Technik in Theokrits Thalysien und die Theorie der
Hirtendichtungʹ In: ΔΩΡΗΜΑ Hans Diller zum 70. Geburtstag. Dauer und Überleben des Antiken
Geistes (eds. Vourveris, K., Skiadas, A.), Athens, 195‐211
Segal, C. P. (1974) ʹSimichidasʹ Modesty: Theocritus Idyll 7.44ʹ AJPh 95: 128‐136
‐‐‐ (1981) Poetry and Myth in Ancient Pastoral: Essays on Theocritus and Virgil, Princeton
‐‐‐ (1989) Orpheus: The Myth of the Poet, Baltimore
‐‐‐ (1998) Aglaia: The Poetry of Alcman, Sappho, Pindar, Bacchylides, and Corinna, Lanham MD
etc.
Sens, A. (1992) ʹTheocritus, Homer and the Dioscuri: Id. 22.137‐223ʹ TAPA 122: 335‐350
‐‐‐ (1997) Theocritus: Dioscuri (Idyll 22), Göttingen
‐‐‐ (2005) ʹThe Art of Poetry and the Poetry of Art: The Unity and Poetics of Posidippusʹ
Statue Poemsʹ In: The New Posidippus, A Hellenistic Poetry Book (ed. Gutzwiller, K. J.), Oxford,
206‐228
Skiadas, A. (1965) Homer im griechischen Epigramm, Athens
Skinner, M. B. (1989) ʹSapphic Nossisʹ Arethusa 22: 1‐11
‐‐‐ (1991) ʹNossis Thelyglossos: The Private Text and the Public Bookʹ In: Womenʹs History and
Ancient History (ed. Pomeroy, S. B.), Chapel Hill, 20‐48
Slings, S. R. (1987) ʹArchilochus: First Cologne Epodeʹ In: Some Recently Found Greek Poems (eds.
Bremer, J. M., van Erp Taalman Kip, A. M., Slings, S. R.), Leiden, 24‐51
‐‐‐ (1990) ʹThe I in Personal Archaic Lyricʹ In: The Poetʹs I in Archaic Greek Lyric (ed. Slings, S.
R.) Amsterdam, 1‐30
Snell, B. (1938) Leben und Meinungen der sieben Weisen: griechische und lateinische Quellen aus
2000 Jahren mit der deutschen Übertragung, München
‐‐‐ (1975) [1946] Die Entdeckung des Geistes: Studien zur Entstehung des europäischen Denkens bei
der Griechen (4., neubearb. Aufl.), Göttingen
Spanoudakis, K. (2001) Philitas of Cos, Leiden
Sperduti, A. (1950) ʹThe Divine Nature of Poetry in Antiquityʹ TAPA 81: 209‐240
Stanzel, K. H. (1995) Liebende Hirten: Theokrits Bukolik und die alexandrinische Poesie, Stuttgart
und Leipzig
Steinkopf, G. (1937) Untersuchungen zur Geschichte des Ruhmes bei den Griechen, Halle
Stephanus, H. (1831‐1865) Thesaurus Graecae Linguae, Paris
Stephens, S. A. (2002) ʹEgyptian Callimachusʹ In: Callimaque: sept exposés suivis de discussions
(eds. Montanari, F., Lehnus, L.), Vandoeuvres‐Genève, 235‐263
‐‐‐ (2003) Seeing Double: Intercultural Poetics in Ptolemaic Alexandria, Berkeley etc.
‐‐‐ (2004) ʹFor You, Arsinoeʹ In: Labored in Papyrus Leaves, Perspectives on an Epigram Collection
attributed to Posidippus (P. Mil. Vogl. VIII 309) (eds. Acosta‐Hughes, B., Kosmetatou, E.,
Baumbach, M.), Washington D.C. and Cambridge Mass. etc., 161‐176
‐‐‐ (2005) ʹBattle of the Booksʹ In: The New Posidippus, a Hellenistic Poetry Book (ed. Gutzwiller,
K. J.), Oxford, 229‐249
Stoddard, K. B. (2003) ʹThe Programmatic Message of the ʺKings and Singersʺ Passage:
Hesiod Theogony 80‐103ʹ TAPA 133: 1‐16
276
Stössl, F. (1941) Apollonios Rhodios: Interpretationen zur Erzählungskunst und Quellenverwertung,
Bern
Strootman, R. (2007) The Hellenistic Royal Court: Court Culture, Ceremonial and Ideology in
Greece, Egypt and the Near East, Utrecht
‐‐‐ (forthcoming [2009?]) ʹLiterature and the Kingsʹ In: A Companion to Hellenistic Literature
(eds. Clauss, J. J., Cuypers, M. P.), Malden
Struck, P. T. (2005) The Birth of the Symbol: Ancient Readers at the Limits of their Texts, Princeton
‐‐‐ (2005b) ʹDivination and Literary Criticism?ʹ In: Mantikê: Studies in Ancient Divination (eds.
Iles Johnston, S., Struck, P. T.), Leiden, 147‐166
Tanner, R.G. (2004) Aristotle’s Works: The Possible Origins of the Alexandria Collection In: The
Library of Alexandria: Center of Learning of the Ancient World (ed. McLeod, R.), London, 79‐95
Thompson, D. J. (2005) ʹPosidippus, Poet of the Ptolemiesʹ In: The New Posidippus, A
Hellenistic Poetry Book (ed. Gutzwiller, K. J.), Oxford, 269‐286
Tigerstedt, E. N. (1970) ʹFuror Poeticus: Poetic Inspiration in Greek Literature before
Democritusʹ Journal of the History of Ideas 31: 163‐178
Too, Y. L. (1998) The Idea of Ancient Literary Criticism, Oxford
Traill, D. (1998) ʹCallimachusʹ Singing Seaʹ CPh 93: 215‐222
Treu, M. (1963) ʹSelbstzeugnisse alexandrinischer Dichter (Kallimachos, 13. Iambos; Theokrit
XVI)ʹ In: Miscellanea di studi alessandrini in memoria di Augusto Rostagni (eds. anonymous),
Torino, 273‐90
Trypanis, C. A. (1952) ʹPosidippus and Delphiʹ CR 2:
Vahlen, J. (1884) ʹÜber Theokrits Hieroʹ Berliner Sitzungsberichte: 823‐842
Van Erp Taalman Kip, A. M. (1987) ʹAnd Daphnis went to the Stream: The Meaning of
Theocritusʹ 1.140‐141ʹ Hermes 115: 149‐151
Van Groningen, B. A. (1959) ʹQuelques problèmes de la poésie bucolique grecqueʹ Mnemosyne
12: 24‐53
Van Sickle, J. B. (1975) ʹThe New Erotic Fragment of Archilochusʹ QUCC 20: 125‐56
Van Thiel, H. (1997) ʹDer Homertext in Alexandriaʹ ZPE 115: 13‐36
Verdenius, W. J. (1983) Principles of Greek Literary Criticism,
Vian, F. (1974) Apollonios de Rhodes. Argonautiques, Tome 1 Chant 1‐2. Texte établi et commenté
par F. Vian et traduit par E. Delage., Paris
‐‐‐ (1980) Apollonios de Rhodes. Argonautiques Tome 2 Chant 3. Texte établi et commenté par F.
Vian et traduit par E. Delage, Paris
‐‐‐ (1981) Apollonios de Rhodes. Argonautiques Tome 3 chant 4. Texte établi et commenté par F.
Vian et traduit par E. Delage et F. Vian, Paris
Voigt, E. M. (1971) [1963] Sappho et Alcaeus, fragmenta, Amsterdam
Von der Mühll, P. (1962) Homeri Odyssea, Basel
Von Reden, S. (1995) ʹDeceptive Readings: Poetry and its Value Reconsideredʹ CQ 45: 30‐50
Walcot, P. (1978) Envy and the Greeks ‐ A study of Human Behaviour, Warminster
Walsh, G. B. (1984) The Varieties of Enchantment: Early Greek Views of the Nature and Function of
Poetry, Chapel Hill
‐‐‐ (1990) ʹSurprised by Self: Audible Thought in Hellenistic Poetryʹ CPh 85: 1‐21
‐‐‐ (1985) ʹSeeing and Feeling: Representation in Two Poems of Theocritusʹ Classical Philology
80: 1‐19
Waszink, J. H. (1974) Biene und Honig als Symbol des Dichters und der Dichtung in der griechisch‐
römischen Antike, Opladen
277
Weber, G. (1993) Dichtung und Höfische Gesellschaft: die Rezeption von Zeitgeschichte am Hof der
erste drei Ptolemäer, Stuttgart
Wehrli, F. (1941) ʹApollonios von Rhodos und Kallimachosʹ Hermes 76: 14‐21
Weingarth, G. (1967) Zu Theokrits 7. Idyll (diss.), Freiburg
Wendel, K. (1967) [1914] Scholia in Theocritum vetera, Leipzig
‐‐‐ (1974) [1935] Scholia in Apollonium Rhodium vetera, Berlin
West, M. L. (1966) Hesiod: Theogony, Oxford
‐‐‐ (1972) Iambi et elegi Graeci, vol. 2. (Simonides, Archilochus, Hipponax), Oxford
‐‐‐ (1973) The Orphic Poems, Oxford
‐‐‐ (1974) Studies in Greek Elegy and Iambus, Oxford
‐‐‐ (1978) Hesiod: Works & Days, Oxford
West, S. R. (2000) ʹLycophron’s Alexandra: “Hindsight as Foresight Makes No Sense?”ʹ In:
Matrices of Genre. Authors, Canons, and Society (eds. Depew, M., Obbink, D.) Cambridge Mass.,
153‐166
White, S. A. (1999) ʹCallimachus Battiades (epigr. 35)ʹ CPh 94: 168‐181
Wifstrand, A. (1963) ʹZu Theokrits Charitesʹ In: Miscellanea di studi alessandrini in memoria di
Augusto Rostagni (eds. anonymous) Torino, 308‐310
Wilamowitz‐Möllendorff, U. v. (1894) ʹAratos von Kosʹ Gött. Nachr. 182
‐‐‐ (1906) ʹDie Textgeschichte der griechischen Bukolikerʹ Philologische Untersuchungen 18:
‐‐‐ (1924) Hellenistische Dichtung in der Zeit des Kallimachos. 2 vols., Berlin
Wilkinson, L. P. (1967) ʹCallimachus, A.P. xii.43ʹ CR 17: 5‐6
Williams, F. J. (1971) ʹA Theophany in Theocritusʹ CQ 21: 137‐145
‐‐‐ (1978) Callimachus: Hymn to Apollo, Oxford
Woodhead, W. D. (1928) Etymologizing in Greek Literature from Homer to Philo Judaeus, Toronto
Wyss, B. (1936) Antimachi Colophonii reliquiae, Berlin
Young, D., Diehl, E. (1971) Theognis, Leipzig
Youtie, H. C. (1973) ʹCallimachus in the Tax Rollsʹ In: Scriptiunculae II (ed. Youtie, H. C.)
Amsterdam, 1035‐41
Zanker, G. (1987) Realism in Alexandrian Poetry: A Literature and its Audience, London
‐‐‐ (1998) ʹThe Concept and Use of Genre‐marking in Hellenistic Epic and Fine Artʹ In: Genre
in Hellenistic Poetry (eds. Harder, M. A., Regtuit, R. F., Wakker, G. C.), Leuven, 225‐238
‐‐‐ (2004) Modes of Viewing in Hellenistic Poetry and Art, Madison Wisc.
Zanker, P. (1995) The Mask of Socrates: The Image of the Intellectual in Antiquity, Berkeley etc.
Zeitlin, F. I. (1982) Under the Sign of the Shield: Semiotics and Aeschylus Seven against Thebes,
Roma
Ziegler, K. J. F. (1934) Das hellenistische Epos: Ein vergessenes Kapittel griechischer Dichtung,
Leipzig
Zimmerman, C. (1994) The Pastoral Narcissus: A study of the first Idyll of Theocritus, Lanham,
MD etc.
278
SAMENVATTING
Om te begrijpen hoe en waarom Hellenistische dichters andere dichters en dichtkunst
verbeelden in hun eigen werken zijn twee met elkaar samenhangende factoren van belang:
hun positie in de Griekse literaire geschiedenis en hun sociaal‐culturele achtergrond. Om
met het eerste te beginnen, voor de moderne lezer komen de Hellenistische dichters
betrekkelijk laat in de Griekse literaire traditie die (voor velen) eindigt met de klassieke
periode, of de literatuur van het Athene van de vijfde eeuw. Bovendien verschilt
Hellenistische poëzie van eerdere poëzie in zowel formeel opzicht als onderwerpskeuze.
Men kan zich dus afvragen hoe Hellenistische dichters zelf hun positie zagen. Waren zij zich
bewust van hun “laatheid”? Aangezien zij zich in hun poëzie intensief bezighielden met het
verleden rijst de vraag of zij continuïteit voelden met dit verleden, of juist een breuk.
Om de belangstelling voor het verleden te begrijpen, is het zinvol om gebruik te
maken van Jan Assmann’s concept “Das Kulturelle Gedächtnis” (cultural memory). Als er ooit
een periode in de Griekse Oudheid geweest is die een bewuste vorming van een dergelijke
cultural memory stimuleerde, dan wel het Hellenisme, de tijd waarin de stichting valt van de
eerste grote koninklijk bibliotheken, dragers en symbolen van de Helleense cultuur. Hier
werd voor het eerst systematisch filologie bedreven en werden de literaire canons
samengesteld; hier ook vond het debat plaats over de interpretatie van de grote literaire
meesterwerken. Dit bewaren en bestuderen van literatuur impliceert een gevoel van zowel
afstand als bewondering.
Aan literatuur van het verleden werd door Hellenistische dichters dus niet dezelfde
status toegekend als aan contemporaine poëzie, die dan ook niet tot de collecties van de
bibliotheken behoorde. Toch zocht men duidelijk aansluiting met het literaire verleden: het
werd in grotere mate bewonderd en gebruikt voor het schrijven van nieuwe poëzie dan ooit
tevoren. Tegelijkertijd verschilt Hellenistische poëzie meer van de traditie dan eerdere
poëzie. Hellenistische dichters trachtten daarom bepaalde aspecten van hun poëzie te
legitimeren door steeds aan de traditie te blijven refereren, of zelf tradities te creëren.
Misschien kunnen we hun positie het beste typeren door te zeggen ze zowel innovatieve
dichters als consciëntieuze geleerden waren: bewust van hun positie als kritische en
creatieve lezers reflecterend op een gekoesterde traditie zonder daarbij het gevoel te hebben
279
dat deze traditie geheel afgesloten was. Het verleden moet hen tegelijkertijd een “window and
mirror” (venster en spiegel) hebben toegeschenen: ze trachtten hun eigen spiegelbeeld in de
poëzie van het verleden te herkennen, al was de wereld achter het glas voor hen afgesloten.
Wat was de invloed van de sociaal‐culturele achtergrond op hun kijk op het
verleden? Veel Hellenistische dichters werkten aan of voor koninklijke hoven die onderling
wedijverden in prestige. Het meest succesvol was ongetwijfeld het hof van Ptolemaeus
Philadelphus in Alexandrië. Hier werd de bestudering en productie van Griekse literatuur
op grote schaal ondersteund om de claim op de culturele en politieke erfenis van Alexander
de Grote waar te maken. Dichters werden gestimuleerd om de poëzie van het verleden te
bestuderen en tot op zekere hoogte te imiteren om het prestige van de koning te
vermeerderen. Tegen deze achtergrond, die ook zal hebben doorgewerkt buiten de muren
van het Alexandrijnse Museum en de Bibliotheek, valt de preoccupatie van dichters met het
verleden, en de manier waarop dit verleden moest worden voortgezet goed te begrijpen,
zoals overigens in moderne wetenschappelijke literatuur wordt erkend.
Dat de koninklijke interesse ook invloed uitoefende op de onderlinge verhoudingen
tussen dichters heeft minder wetenschappelijke belangstelling gewekt. Waarschijnlijk leidde
de materiele afhankelijkheid tot rivaliteit om de gunst van de koning en daardoor tot het
claimen van een exclusieve positie in vergelijking met collega‐dichters. Zo beïnvloedde het
hof de identiteit van Hellenistische dichters dus op twee manieren: enerzijds richtte het hun
blikken op het verleden en stimuleerde hen aan te knopen bij de gerespecteerde traditie,
anderzijds confronteerde het hen met collega‐dichters die dongen om de gunst van de vorst.
1. Het Verleden
Het eerste deel van mijn studie richt zich op de preoccupatie met het verleden, en wel in de
vorm van twee soorten voorgangers, namelijk de mythische en de historische dichters. De
Hellenistische dichters kenden een andere status toe aan dichters als Orpheus en de
mythische herder/dichter Daphnis dan aan historische dichters Homerus, Hipponax en
Pindarus. Dit lag vooral aan het feit dat de mythische dichters geen onbetwiste literaire
erfenis hadden nagelaten. Voor de Hellenistische Grieken is Orpheus een dubbelzinnig
280
figuur: mythische held, mystieke leraar en wegbereider van de Griekse dichtkunst. De
herder Daphnis en zijn nalatenschap waren, zelfs in de oudheid al, nog vager.
Het feit dat deze dichters geen duidelijke literaire nalatenschap hadden, vormde geen
belemmering voor hun functioneren als voorbeelden van poëtische praktijken. Integendeel,
dit was eerder een voordeel: het gaf Hellenistische dichters de vrijheid ze om te vormen tot
hun voorgangers en zelfs tot hun evenbeeld. Het verlangen om nieuwe poëzie in een traditie
te plaatsen kan verbonden worden met Hobsbawm’s theorie over “Invented Tradition.” In
Apollonius’ Argonautica wordt Orpheus zo tot een fictieve voorafschaduwing van de persona
van de verteller. Theocritus gebruikt op een vergelijkbare manier de figuren Daphnis en
Comatas om zijn eigen poëtische uitvinding, de bucolische poëzie, te voorzien van een
geloofwaardige en eerbiedwaardige afstamming. De doorwrochte opzet van zijn bucolische
Idyllen geeft zijn lezers het gevoel toeschouwers te zijn van een complete bucolische wereld
vol tradities; ze raden naar de strekking van de verhalen die verteld worden zonder ooit de
volledige versie te horen.
Hellenistische dichters gebruikten hun voorgangers dus om ze te vormen tot een
beeld dat het best hun eigen eigenschappen weerspiegelde. Dit was echter niet zo eenvoudig
als de dichters waar het om ging duidelijker contouren hadden door een overgeleverde
rollen worden gedwongen. Toch werden ook zij gebruikt als voorbeelden op wier autoriteit
een beroep kon worden gedaan als het ging om innovatieve poëzie.
Er zijn twee manieren waarop de Hellenistische dichters hun historische voorgangers
benaderen. In de eerste plaats vinden we evaluaties, meestal in literaire epitafen en andere
epigrammen. Er zijn drie aspecten van de karakterisering van historische dichters in
epigrammen behandeld: de poëtische praktijk (zingen versus schriftelijke compositie); de
reflectie van karakter en biografie in poëzie, en de overlevering van de poëtische erfenis door
middel van geschreven teksten. Deze drie onderwerpen zijn gerelateerd. Terwijl eerdere
Griekse poëzie nauwelijks aandacht schonk aan het feit dat poëzie kon worden
Hellenistische dichters konden werken van voorgangers bestuderen en beoordelen juist
doordat ze bewaard waren op papyri. Poëtische werken werden zo tot het onvervreemdbare
monument van een dichter. Het verschil tussen een historische dichter als Sophocles, wiens
281
erfenis geboekstaafd was, en een mythische als Orpheus, werd erkend, zoals duidelijk blijkt
uit de epitafen die op beiden gedicht werden.
Het feit dat wat er van een dichter overbleef alleen terug te vinden was in poëzie,
maakte reconstructie van zijn persoonlijkheid op basis van zijn werken aantrekkelijk.
Antieke biografie was dan ook vooral gebaseerd op het abstraheren van feiten uit poëzie; dit
is tevens terug te vinden in het epigram. Dit blijkt ook van belang voor de zelfpresentatie
van Hellenistische dichters. Hun inzicht in de manier waarop hun voorgangers beoordeeld
werden, beïnvloedde de wijze waarop zij zichzelf presenteerden aan toekomstige generaties
lezers. Natuurlijk leidde de biografische manier van lezen ook tot karikaturen, zoals
Anacreon de verliefde drinker en Archilochus de venijnige belager van jonge meisjes.
Sommige Hellenistische dichters lijken zich ervan bewust dat een dergelijke wijze van lezen
geen rekening hield met het feit dat dichters personae en rollen konden creëren. Dit
bewustzijn komt voort uit hun eigen praktijk: ook in hun eigen poëzie vertegenwoordigt het
sprekend “ik” niet altijd het standpunt van de auteur. Theocritus geeft hier blijk van in zijn
ironische epigrammen op Anacreon en Archilochus, maar ook de creatie van zogenaamde
“insubstantial voices” in de hymnen van Callimachus is hierop terug te voeren.
Naast epigrammen die getuigen van de belangstelling van Hellenistische dichters
voor hun voorgangers, zijn er ook enkele andere teksten waarin deze voorgangers als
personages worden opgevoerd. Hellenistische dichters deden een beroep op de autoriteit
van deze voorgangers, maar waren niet in staat om hun praktijk in elk detail te imiteren.
Niet alleen hun manier om poëzie te componeren met behulp van talrijke intertextuele
referenties aan de grote traditie verschilde van die van hun voorgangers, maar ook de functie
van hun poëzie, die steeds meer geschreven werd om gelezen te worden door het individu in
plaats van beluisterd door de gemeenschap. Toch wilden ze zich niet distantiëren van het
literaire verleden; ze hadden het nodig voor het creëren en legitimeren van het heden.
Er bestonden verschillende manieren om de autoriteit van voorgangers in te roepen
en zo nieuwe poëtische praktijken te verantwoorden. De voorgangers in kwestie konden
worden ingezet als voorbeelden, protoi heuretai en inspirators; in dergelijke gevallen was het
gunstig om algemeen erkende eigenschappen van hun poëzie selectief te benadrukken, of
om gegevens over hun leven en werken te manipuleren zodat ze geschikt werden voor het
vooropgezette doel. Hiervan zijn twee voorbeelden geanalyseerd. Theocritus (Id. 16)
282
gebruikt Homerus, Simonides en (impliciet) Pindarus als bewijzen voor de stelling dat
poëtische loftuitingen de enige garantie voor onsterfelijkheid bieden. Hij doet dit omdat,
naar hij beweert, “poëzie” in zijn tijd door het gierige publiek slechts wordt begrepen als
“poëzie van dode dichters van het verleden.” Hij moet daarom aantonen dat poëzie leeft en
onderhouden moet worden als zij haar natuurlijke taak wil volbrengen, het verschaffen van
kleos (roem). Paradoxaal genoeg doet hij dit juist door de “dode dichters van het verleden”
aan te voeren als voorbeelden voor de stelling dat levende dichters betaald moeten worden.
De Leontion van Hermesianax daarentegen tracht op speelse wijze aan te tonen dat alle
poëzie uiteindelijk het resultaat is van liefdesrelaties door op “allegorische” wijze de werken
van onder andere Homerus en Hesiodus te duiden. Enerzijds is dit een programmatische
keuze: Hermesianax verwijst zogenaamd naar een lange traditie waarin zijn erotische elegie
staat. Anderzijds lijkt deze procedure door een reductio ad absurdum ook te erkennen hoe het
claimen van literaire voorbeelden werkt.
Het noemen van dichters is niet hetzelfde als hen toestaan zelf te spreken, zoals het
verschil tussen bovengenoemde gedichten en die van Timon van Phlius (Silloi), Callimachus
(Iambus I) en Herondas (Mimiambe 8) duidelijk maakt. Deze laatste voorbeelden voeren
poëtische autoriteiten op als sprekende personages. Dit resulteert telkens in spanningen
tussen de boodschap die de tekst wil overbrengen en de wijze waarop dit gebeurt. In de Silloi
van Timon botst de keuze voor Xenophanes (bekend om zijn kritiek op de homerische
goden) als gids die de auteur door Hades moet leiden naar diens filosofisch voorbeeld
Pyrrho op eigenaardige wijze met de Homerische setting en taal. Het is al merkwaardig dat
Timon beweerde de onderwereld bezocht te hebben; het hiernamaals was iets waar een
sceptische filosoof geen kennis over claimde. Deze ironische fantasie illustreert zo hoe lastig
het is om een voorganger te claimen als autoriteit.
Callimachus en Herondas presenteren beiden een agressieve Hipponax in hun
iambische poëzie. Callimachus voert Hipponax op als een zelfstandig personage dat de
geleerden van het Museum berispt vanwege hun geruzie; in werkelijkheid is deze Hipponax
natuurlijk zijn eigen creatie; Callimachus verbergt zich achter Hipponax’ masker. Zo
refereert hij aan het iambische gebruik om onwelkome meningen “gemaskerd” uit te dragen.
Hij creëert bovendien een paradox door zich in de rest van de collectie Iambi niet aan
Hipponax’ waarschuwingen tegen onderling geruzie te houden. In Herondas’ Mimiambe 8
283
leert Hipponax de auteur een les: Herondas bejegent in dit gedicht zijn slaven precies zo als
Hipponax hem bejegent in zijn droom. Zo toont hij dat hij de echte iambische toon te pakken
heeft. In beide gevallen zorgt de agressie van Hipponax ervoor dat de lezer zich afvraagt wat
hij werkelijk van deze bewerking van zijn literaire erfgoed zou hebben gevonden.
2. Het Heden
Het tweede deel concentreert zich op de verbeelding van contemporaine dichters, vanuit het
oogpunt van sociale interactie in het Museum en de Bibliotheek van Alexandrië en
vergelijkbare instellingen aan andere hoven. Ik heb uitingen van dichters over hun collega’s
in het theoretische kader van Pierre Bourdieu geplaatst, wiens Veld‐theorie (the field of cultural
production) het inzicht uitwerkt dat kunst nooit los kan worden gezien van de samenleving,
of van de drijfveren van sociale interactie. Het zou verkeerd zijn om welke poëzie dan ook,
ook Hellenistische poëzie, die traditioneel vaak beschouwd wordt als “l’art pour l’art,” te
benaderen als een puur esthetische categorie. Bourdieu’s nadruk op het streven naar een
positie van exclusiviteit (distinction) werpt een nieuw licht op bepaalde aspecten van
Hellenistische poëzie.
Ik heb hiervan gebruik gemaakt voor mijn analyse van de beroemde strijd tussen
Callimachus en Apollonius, de Aetia‐proloog van Callimachus en de gerelateerde kwestie
van de identiteit van de Telchinen. Hieruit kwam naar voren dat de antieke testimonia, zoals
tegenwoordig vrij algemeen wordt aangenomen, weinig bewijs leveren dat er inderdaad een
dergelijke strijd zou zijn geweest. Maar zelfs als zij er wel zou zijn geweest is het
onwaarschijnlijk dat het onderwerp ervan achterhaald kan worden. Mijn suggestie is dat het
idee van de strijd te wijten is aan het feit dat latere lezers zagen dat Callimachus en
Apollonius beiden actief waren aan het hof van Ptolemaeus Philadelphus en poëzie
produceerden die in stilistisch opzicht verwant is. Dit moet hen op de gedachte gebracht
hebben dat ruzie onvermijdelijk was; de polemische persona van Callimachus droeg hier nog
aan bij.
De analyse van deze persona in de Aetia‐proloog, gebaseerd op de studies van
Cameron, Asper en Schmitz, toont dat Callimachus zichzelf met deze tekst een positie van
exclusiviteit wilde verwerven, ongeacht het feit of de Telchinen een historische realiteit
284
vertegenwoordigen of niet. Door te beweren dat hij onbemind en onbegrepen is, impliceert
hij in werkelijkheid een excellent en succesvol dichter te zijn, die alleen kenners weten te
waarderen. De traditionele lezing dat het hier om een puur esthetische kwestie gaat wordt zo
bestudering ook eerder op persoonlijke vetes dan op esthetische waardeoordelen te berusten.
Het tegendeel van negatieve oordelen, lof, is een onderbelicht onderwerp in
Hellenistische poëzie. Veel lofprijzingen voor collega’s zeggen evenveel over degene die
prijst als over de geprezene. Het prijzen van een tijdgenoot kan het verkrijgen van een positie
van exclusiviteit ten doel hebben: door bepaalde esoterische kenmerken van Aratus’ poëzie
te prijzen, tonen Callimachus en Leonidas dat zijzelf tot dezelfde categorie verfijnde (en
gewaardeerde) dichters behoren als Aratus. De bewering dat een tijdgenoot onsterfelijke
werken heeft geproduceerd impliceert tevens dat deze loftuiting zelf onsterfelijk zal zijn.
Theocritus’ 7 e Idylle parodieert de principes die hieraan ten grondslag liggen op subtiele
wijze door de onervaren Simichidas te laten zeggen dat hij de grote dichters Asclepiades en
Philitas bewondert; dit toont ondanks zijn zogenaamde bescheidenheid hoe de jonge dichter
zichzelf ziet. Volgens hetzelfde principe kan een patroon worden uitgenodigd om een
poëtisch werk te prijzen: door te suggereren dat hij verstand heeft van poëzie wordt hij
verplicht het gedicht in kwestie dat dit beweert mooi te vinden, zoals gebeurt in Idylle 16 en
17; het wordt geparodieerd in 11.
De verbeelding van andere dichters werpt zo licht op de dichter die hen verbeeldt;
ofwel door het verleden tot spiegel van de dichter zelf te maken, of door verschillen of
overeenkomsten met tijdgenoten te benadrukken om zo een positie te bepalen in het artistiek
culturele veld. Al deze oordelen over andere dichters zijn feitelijk impliciete zelfportretten.
3. Zelfrepresentatie
In het derde en laatste deel wordt de openlijke zelfrepresentatie van dichters behandeld. De
sphragis‐epigrammen vormen het complement van de biografisch beïnvloede epitafen op
dode dichters. Bovendien is de evidente wens van deze dichters om zichzelf expliciet te
identificeren als auteurs van hun eigen werken terug te voeren op het feit dat Hellenistische
poëzie in de eerste plaats leespoëzie en geen luisterpoëzie is. Mondelinge voordracht maakt
285
dingen duidelijk over de spreker waar leespoëzie alleen met behulp van uitgesproken
identificatie in slaagt. De identificatie van de auteur kan natuurlijk ook in haar tegendeel
verkeren, waarbij de lezer gedwongen wordt zelf uit te vinden wie de spreker is, zoals in
Callimachus’ Hymnen. Deze beide praktijken zijn terug te voeren op het feit dat
Hellenistische poëzie werd geschreven door lezer‐dichters voor een lezend publiek. Het
lezen van contextloze teksten had de Hellenistische geleerde dichters ervan doordrongen
wat voor problemen er kleefden aan ambigue sprekers en referenties aan relevante situaties.
Sphrageis konden op een andere wijze enigmatisch zijn, door etymologieën of
woordspelingen op de naam van de auteur. Zij nodigen de lezer zo uit door oplossing van
het raadsel extra informatie te bemachtigen over de wijze waarop de auteur zichzelf wenste
te zien. Zo benadrukt Apollonius in de openingsverzen van de Argonautica zijn connectie
met de god van orakels en poëzie Apollo en lijkt Callimachus zijn vermogen tot het vinden
van het juiste woord op het juiste moment te onderstrepen door een kat’antiphrasin uitleg van
zijn alias Battiades (“zoon van de stotteraar”). Ook deze manier van zelfrepresentatie houdt
verband met de leescultuur in het Hellenisme.
Theocritus geeft de lezer door zijn creatie van de onervaren spreker “Simichidas” in
de metapoëticale 7e Idylle een nog gecompliceerder raadsel op. Is Simichidas een alter ego
van de dichter? De vraag wordt bemoeilijkt door de raadselachtige status van de tegenspeler
van Simichidas in de Idylle, Lycidas. Simichidas maakt onmiskenbaar meer aanspraak op
identificatie met de auteur, doordat hij de spreker is in het gedicht. Op basis van de
Κυδωνικὸν εὕρομες ἄνδρα, 7.13; πᾶν ἐπ’ ἀλαθείᾳ πεπλασμένον ἐκ Διὸς ἔρνος, 7.44) en
een structurele analyse van de Idylle heb ik beargumenteerd dat Simichidas en Lycidas op
een metapoëticaal niveau worden voorgesteld als wederzijdse creaties. Het gedicht als
geheel vormt een reflectie op de rol van fictionele dichter‐herders in Theocritus’ bucolische
poëzie. Zo is het een impliciete erkenning van het feit dat Theocritus zelf de schepper van
genre is en dat hij ook de personages en stichters ervan heeft geschapen: bucolische poëzie
vindt zijn oorsprong in zichzelf.
Tot slot kwam de verbeelding van poëtische autoriteit aan bod, in het bijzonder de
status van de Muze als de schenkster van geopenbaarde kennis. Dit kreeg de vorm van een
analyse van het Homerische hapax legomenon ὑποφήτης (Il. 16.235) en de variant ὑποφήτωρ
286
zoals door Apollonius en Theocritus gebruikt om hun concept van poëtische inspiratie uit te
drukken. De passages waarin dit woord voorkomt, zijn verbonden door een nadruk op de
rol van de dichter als recipiënt en doorgever van geopenbaarde kennis (cf. González). Voor
Theocritus is deze rol vooral van belang voor zijn problematische positie als dichter aan een
hof van een zelfverklaard goddelijke koning. Door zichzelf ὑποφήτης te noemen meet hij
zich een specifieke autoriteit als panegyricus aan. Apollonius daarentegen benadrukt de
problemen die kleven aan geopenbaarde kennis met betrekking tot het verleden. Door de
muzen voor te stellen als schakel in een hiërarchische ketting, afhankelijk van de orakels van
Apollo, stelt hij metaforisch de problemen van een dichter als hijzelf aan de orde, werkend in
het Museum, zoekend naar informatie in tegenstrijdige, obscure of onbetrouwbare bronnen
over het verleden. In laatste instantie illustreert deze analyse dat beide dichters teruggrijpen
op de vroegste oorsprong van de poëzie, de combinatie van poëzie met profetie.
verbeelden om te reflecteren op de poëticale opvattingen van zowel de ander als van henzelf.
Ze zijn tegelijkertijd lezers en schrijvers; beide aspecten vormen deel van hun identiteit als
dichters; ze zien zichzelf als vernieuwers die terugblikken op de traditie. Hun expliciete
zelfrepresentaties lijken bedoeld voor een toekomstig lezerspubliek van erudiete interpreten
die deze poëzie zullen analyseren en misschien zelf ook weer op zoek zullen gaan naar hun
eigen reflectie erin. Zo is hun poëzie geworden tot dat waartoe ze de werken van hun
voorgangers hadden gemaakt: een venster en een spiegel.
287