0% found this document useful (0 votes)
49 views

Introduction To Uncertainty: Jes Us Fern Andez-Villaverde Duke University

This document introduces some basic concepts of uncertainty in modern macroeconomics. It discusses discrete time, events that can occur in each period, and assigning probabilities to those events. It also covers household preferences using expected discounted utility, with a focus on time separability, time discounting, and common utility functions like CRRA that exhibit constant relative risk aversion. It then presents a stochastic process for consumption and calculates the welfare cost of business cycle fluctuations, finding it to be extremely small under standard assumptions. Some alternatives are noted that could potentially increase this cost, such as moving away from a representative agent model.

Uploaded by

thakur08
Copyright
© Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
49 views

Introduction To Uncertainty: Jes Us Fern Andez-Villaverde Duke University

This document introduces some basic concepts of uncertainty in modern macroeconomics. It discusses discrete time, events that can occur in each period, and assigning probabilities to those events. It also covers household preferences using expected discounted utility, with a focus on time separability, time discounting, and common utility functions like CRRA that exhibit constant relative risk aversion. It then presents a stochastic process for consumption and calculates the welfare cost of business cycle fluctuations, finding it to be extremely small under standard assumptions. Some alternatives are noted that could potentially increase this cost, such as moving away from a representative agent model.

Uploaded by

thakur08
Copyright
© Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 30

Introduction to Uncertainty

Jesús Fernández-Villaverde
Duke University

1
Introduction to Uncertainty

• Modern macro studies stochastic processes of observed variables.

• Two elements:

1. Dynamics.

2. Uncertainty.

• We will introduce some basic concepts by presenting a pure exchange


economy with stochastic endowments.

• In this lecture, we will present the expected discounted utility and we


will use it to assess the welfare cost of the business cycle.
2
Time

• Discrete time t ∈ {0, 1, 2, ...} .

• Why discrete time?


1. Economic data is discrete.
2. Easier math.

• Comparison with continuous time:


1. Discretize observables.
2. More involved math (stochastic calculus) but often we have ex-
tremely powerful results.

• Calendar versus planning time.


3
Events

• One event st happens in each period.

• st ∈ S = {1, 2, ..., N} .

• Note:

1. S is a finite set. We will later talk about measure theory.

2. S does not depend on time.

• Event history st = (s0, s1, ..., st) ∈ S × ... × S = S t+1.


4
Probabilities

• Probability of st is π(st).

³ ´
t
• Conditional probability of st+1 is π st+1| s .

• At this moment, we are not imposing any transition probability among


states across time.

• Our notation allows the particular cases:


³ ´
π st+1 | st = π (st+1)
³ ´
π st+1 | st = π (st+1| st)

5
Commodity Space

• One good in the economy.

• However, good indexed by event history over infinite time. Hence our
commodity space is slightly more complicated (see chapter 15 in SLP).

• Commodity space: (C, k·k) .

• We pick l∞, i.e., the space of sequences c = (c0, c1, ...) , cn ∈ R that
are bounded in the norm:
kck∞ = sup |ci|
i

6
Household Preferences

• Preferences admit a representation:


∞ X
X
U (c) = β tπ(st)u(ct(st))
t=0 st∈S t

• This is known as the von Neumann-Morgenstern expected utility func-


tion.

• Remember:

1. Key assumptions: continuity and independence axioms.

2. Linear in probabilities.

3. Cardinal utility: unique only up to an affine transformation.


7
Facts about Utility Function I: Time Separability

• Total utility c equals the expected discounted sum of period (or in-
stantaneous) utility u(ct(st)).

• The period utility at time t only depends on consumption in period t


and not on consumption in other periods.

• This formulation rules out, among other things, habit persistence.

• However, it is easy to relax: recursive utility functions.

8
Facts about Utility Function II: Time Discounting

• β < 1 indicates that agents are impatient.

• β is called the (subjective) time discount factor.

1 .
• The subjective time discount rate ρ is defined by β = 1+ρ

• Assumption: constant over time→exponential discounting.

• Alternatives: hyperbolic discounting.

9
Facts about Utility Function III: Risk Aversion

• Arrow-Pratt Absolute Risk Aversion:


u00 (c)
ARA = − 0
u (c)
Why do we divide by u0 (c)?

• Arrow-Pratt Relative Risk Aversion:


u00 (c)
RRA = − 0 c
u (c)

Interpretation.

10
Common Utility Functions

• Constant Absolute Risk Aversion (CARA):

−e−ac

• Constant Relative Risk Aversion (CRRA):


c1−γ − 1
for γ =
6 1
1−γ
log c for γ = 1

(you need to take limits and apply L’Hôpital’s rule).

11
CRRA Utility Functions

• γ plays a dual role controlling risk-aversion and intertemporal substi-


tution.

• Coefficient of Relative Risk-aversion:


u00(c)
− 0 c=γ
u (c)

• Elasticity of Intertemporal Substitution:


u(c2)/u(c1) d (c2/c1) 1
− =
c2/c1 d (u(c2)/u(c1)) γ

• Advantages and disadvantages.


12
Why CRRA Utility Functions?

• Market price of risk has been roughly constant over the last two cen-
turies.

• This observation suggests that risk aversion should be relatively con-


stant over the wealth levels.

13
Cost of Business Cycles

• Simple CRRA utility function already answers many questions.

• Lucas (1987), Models of Business Cycles: What is the welfare cost of


business cycles?

• Importance of question:

1. Limits of stabilization policy.

2. Macroeconomic priorities.

14
A Process for Consumption

• Assume that consumption evolves over time as:


t − 12 σ 2z
ct = μ (1 + λ) e ztc
³ ´
where log zt ∼ N 0, σ 2z .

• The moment generating function of a lognormal distribution implies:


m σz 2 2
m
E (zt ) = e 2

• Then:
µ ¶
− 12 σ 2z
E e zt =1
³ ´ 1 (1−γ)2 σ 2
E zt1−σ = e2 z

15
A Compensating Differential

• We want to find the value of λ such that:


³ ´1−γ
1−γ t
μc −1
ct −1
E =
1−γ 1−γ

• If these is true period by period and event by event, it should also be


true when we sum up.

• Moreover, the converse is also true: λ is the smallest number that


makes total utilities over time to be equal. Why? Because of the
CRRA and the i.i.d. structure of zt.

• Interpretation: λ is the welfare cost of uncertainty, i.e., by how much


we need to raise consumption in every period and state.
16
Finding λ

• Dropping irrelevant constants, λ solves:


µ ¶1−γ
− 12 σ 2z
E (1 + λ) e zt =1⇒
− 12 σ 2z (1−γ)
(1 + λ) e Ezt1−γ = 1 ⇒
− 12 σ 2z (1−γ)+ 12 (1−γ)2σ 2z
(1 + λ) e =1⇒
1 2
(1 + λ) e− 2 γσz = 1

• Taking logs: λ ≈ 12 γσ 2z .

• Let us put some numbers here. Using quarterly U.S. data 1947-2006,
σ 2z = (0.033)2 . What is γ?
17
Size of γ

• Most evidence suggests that γ is low, between 1 and 3. At most 10.

• Types of evidence:
1. Questionnaires.
2. Experiments.
3. Econometric estimates from observed behavior.

• Two powerful arguments from growth theory international compar-


isons. We will revisit these points when we talk about asset pricing.

• Rabin’s (2000): “Risk Aversion and Expected-Utility Theory: A Cali-


bration Theorem.”, Econometrica.
18
An Estimate of the Cost of the Business Cycle

• Let us take γ = 1 as a benchmark number. Then, we have:


1 1
λ ≈ γσ 2z = ∗ 1 ∗ (0.033)2 = 0.0005
2 2

• Even if we take γ = 10 as an upper bound:


1 1
λ ≈ γσ 2z = ∗ 10 ∗ (0.033)2 = 0.005
2 2

• These are extremely small numbers.

• Later we will see how this finding is intimately linked with the Equity
premium puzzle.

• How could we turn around this result?


19
Alternatives Routes

• We assumed:

1. Representative agent.

2. Exogenous lognormal consumption.

3. Expected utility.

• How important are each of these three assumptions?

20
Representative Agent

• Representative agent: fluctuations are at the margin.

• Lucas is very explicit about the possible costs of inequality.

• We will see in the next lecture that with complete markets we will
have perfect risk sharing.

• But the interesting question is the effects of business cycles with in-
complete markets and heterogeneity.

• Krusell and Smith (2002), loss of 0.001 of average consumption, 65%


of households lose when business cycles are removed.
21
Exogenous Lognormal Consumption

• A combined hypothesis: exogenous consumption+lognormal consump-


tion.

• Exogenous consumption⇒Cho and Cooley (2001), business cycles may


increase welfare: mean versus spread effect.

• Lognormal consumption⇒great depressions? Chaterjee and Corbae


(2005): welfare cost of 0.0187. They calibrate a great depression
every 87 years.

• A nonparametric approach by Álvarez and Jermann (2004) suggests


costs between 0.0008 and 0.0049.
22
Problems of Expected Utility

• We have representation:
∞ X
X
U (c) = β tπ(st)u(ct(st))
t=0 st∈S t

• Three strong assumptions:

1. Intertemporal elasticity of substitution and risk aversion are deter-


mined by just one parameter.

2. Temporal separability.

3. Expected utility.

• All are problematic and they may affect our calculations.


23
Recursive Utility

• Espstein-Zin preferences (1989):


∙ ³ ´ ρ ¸ ρ1
ρ α α
Ut = (1 − β) ct + β EtUt+1

separates elasticity of substitution:


1
γ=
1−ρ
from risk-aversion α.

• Applied to evaluate cost of business cycles by Tallirini (2000).

24
Risk in the Long Run

• Bansal and Yaron (2004): difficult to distinguish a long run component


from a random walk.

• Implications for the equity premium.

• Croce (2006): cost of business cycle.

25
Temporal Anomalies

• Present-bias. Frederich, Lowenstein, and O’Donoghue (2002), “Time


Discounting and Time Preference: A Critical Review”. Journal of
Economic Literature.

• Explanations:

1. Hyperbolic discounting (Phelps and Pollack, 1968, Laibson, 1996):



X
δβ tu(ct)
t=0

2. Temptation: Gul and Pesendorfer (2003).


26
Uncertainty Anomalies

1. Framing effects (Kahneman and Tversky).

2. Allais paradox. Three prizes in a lottery: {0, 1, 10}

Problem 1: L1 = (0, 1, 0) versus L2 = (0.01, 0.89, 0.1) .

Problem 2: L3 = (0.89, 0.11, 0) versus L4 = (0.9, 0, 0.1) .

3. Ellsberg paradox.

27
Ambiguity Aversion

• Knight (1921) risk versus uncertainty.

• Gilboa and Schmidler (1989):

min EQu (c)


Q∈P

• Two possible extensions:

1. Choice over time.

2. General class of ambiguity aversion.


28
Choice over Time

• Epstein and Schneider (2003):



X
min EQ β tu(ct)
Q∈P
t=0

• Difficult technical assumption⇒rectangularity.

29
Ambiguity and the Variational Representation of Preferences

• Maccheroni, Marinacci, and Rustichini (2006):


n o
min EQu(c) + φ (Q)
Q∈P

• The function u represents risk attitudes while the index c captures


ambiguities attitudes.

• They extend it to the intertemporal case.

• One particular example:


n o
min EQu(c) + θR (Qk P )
Q∈P

• Hansen and Sargent’s (2006) research program on robust control.


30

You might also like