Does Husserl Have A Philosophy of History in The Crisis of European Sciences?
Does Husserl Have A Philosophy of History in The Crisis of European Sciences?
Does Husserl Have A Philosophy of History in The Crisis of European Sciences?
Doug Mann
To cite this article: Doug Mann (1992) Does Husserl have a Philosophy of History in the Crisis
of European Sciences?, Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 23:2, 156-166, DOI:
10.1080/00071773.1992.11006984
Article views: 1
157
end product of a collection of individual human acts, the view towards which
Husser) leans). It is within the confines of this motif that the question of
whether the Crisis propounds a philosophy of history must be decided.
After even the most cursory reading of the Crisis, one is struck by
Husserl's situating of phenomenology within the general historical framework
of European philosophy, notably within the empiricist tradition that culminates
and is overturned in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. Quite uncharacteristically
(when comparing this work with his earlier views), Husser) castigates those who
artificially separate historical and epistemological elucidation in his fragment
'The Origin of Geometry' (Husser), 370). Contrary to this view, Husser) sees the
"essence" of history as a dialectical struggle between competing ways of
thinking, following the Hegelian motif previously introduced:
The true struggles of our time, the only ones which are significant, are struggles between
humanity which has already collapsed and humanity which still has roots but is struggling
to keep them or find new ones. The genuine spiritual struggles of European humanity as
such take the form of struggles between the philosophies, that is, between the sceptical
philosophies - or non-philosophies, which retain the word but not the task - and the
actual and still vital philosophies (Husserl, 15).
On the one side Husser) arrays the forces of a decaying empiricism and
its ally psychology (understood as a natural science); on the other,
phenomenology. Naturally, it is the latter that Husser) sees as that which is
truly vital in European thought.
Some commentators have interpreted the Crisis in a radically historicist
vein: thus James Morrison attributes to the later Husser) the view that all self-
reflection is, of necessity, historical reflection (Morrison, 315). In a less
extreme fashion, but representing no less of a break with Husser)' s earlier
view of philosophy, Ricouer interprets the Crisis thus: "The idea of
philosophy, this is the teleology of history. This is why the philosophy of
history in the end is the history of philosophy, itself indistinguishable from
philosophy's coming to self-awareness" (Ricouer, 153). That Husser)
believed that philosophy develops historically, that it moves in a zig-zag
fashion towards a true understanding of consciousness and the world, is
difficult to deny after reading Part II of the Crisis. It remains to consider
some of the concrete content of this analysis, and to see whether a philosophy
of history is as evident as the commentators quoted above suggest.
The First Crisis in the Dialectic: Galileo and the Mathematisation of Nature
158
world which is pregiven, taken for granted though experience, seeks the 'objective truth' of
this world, seeks what, in this world, is unconditionally valid for every rational being, what
it is in itself. It is the task of episteme, ratio, or philosophy to carry this out universally ....
Transcendentalism, on the other hand, says: the ontic meaning of the pregiven life-world is a
subjective structure, it is the achievement of experiencing, pre-scientific life (Husser!, 68-9).
The new scientific theories of the Renaissance, freeing themselves from
the traditions of a dogmatic religion, sought to "measure the life-world .... for
a well-fitting garb of ideas, that of the so-called objectively scientific truths"
(Husser!, 51). Galileo resurrected Euclidean geometry, and by arithmetising it
and applying this new tool to nature, made the latter a "mathematical
manifold" (Husser!, 23). The ideal shapes of geometry became the "limit-
shapes" of nature, of an idealised nature, of a nature forced into an
objectivistic strait-jacket. Lastly, the world is transformed from a totality to a
whole by means of the presumption of universal causal regulation:
everything in the world is related through a causal nexus to everything else,
in strictly physical terms (Husser!, 31 ). Of course, this included human
subjectivity, or, as it was then termed, the soul, although it was not until the
seventeenth century that the idea of this relation of the soul to the physical
world was given its first intellectually honest and radical exposition.
The significance of Galileo's achievement does not escape Husserl's
attention. The Italian philosopher of nature acts as the symbolic starting point
of the modem dialectic of objectivism and transcendentalism, a dialectic that
had yet to play itself out in Husserl' s own time. The new way of thinking
which he inaugurated objectified the world: the totality of phenomena
become an enclosed cosmos of facts. Insofar as Galileo's achievement took
place at a discrete historical moment, and insofar as the legacy he left behind
developed temporally (i.e. its fullest implications were not encountered until
Hume's scepticism came to light), the mathematisation of nature with which
Husser! credits him can be seen as the first stage in the proto-dialectic of
objectivism and subjectivism, or transcendentalism.
The Second Crisis in the Dialectic: Descartes, Hume, and the Radicalisation
of Doubt
162
Does the Life-World Change? The Possibility of a Purely Doxie Science
163
possible from within the phenomenological movement. However, Husser) does
not make any great effort to work out such a science within the confines of the
Crisis, and maintains a deep ambivalence towards the temporal and the
changing throughout this work. To accord Husserl a sense of historicity, we
must go beyond his concept of the life-world, which remains ambiguous to the
end.
164
But in yet another sense, the notion of crisis can fit within the general
structure of a philosophy of history without assuming any sort of
determinism. For both philosophers of progress like Condorcet and Saint-
Simon, and for philosophers of the decline of civilisation like Spengler and
Toynbee, the determinism in their thought is linked to a call to action. If we
really have no choice as to the immediate (or distant) future of our culture or
civilisation, then the arrival of a crisis must be seen by and large as a matter
of inconvenience. However, if the possibility of change effected by acts of
human will exists, then the notion of crisis can be contained within a non-
deterministic philosophy of history.
Bibliography
Brand, Gerd. "Intentionality, Reduction and Intentional Analysis." In Phenomenology. Ed.
Joseph Kockelmans. Garden City: Anchor Books, 1967.
Blumenburg, Hans. "The Life-World and the Concept of Reality." In Life-World and
165
Consciousness: Essays or A ron Gurwitsch. Ed. Lester E Embree. Evanston: Northwestern
University Press, 1972.
Carr, David. "Husserl's Problematic Concept of the Life-World." American Philosophical
Quarterly 7 (1970), 331-9.
Husser!, Edmund. The Crisis of the European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology.
Trans., intr. David Carr. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1970.
Kockelmans, Joseph. Edmund Husser/'s Phenomenological Psychology. A Historico-Critico
Study. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1967.
Makreel, Rudolph A. "Husser!, Dilthey and the Relation of the Life-World to History." In
Husser/ and Contemporary Thought. Ed. John Sallis. Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press,
1983.
Moneta, Guiseppina C. "The Order of Time and Self-Responsibility." In Husser/ and
Contemporary Thought. Ed. John Sallis. Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1983.
Morrison, James C. "Husserl's Crisis: Reflections on the Relationship of Philosophy and
History." Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 37 (1976-7), 312-30.
Paci, Enzo. "Life-World, Time, and Liberty in Husser!." In Life-World and Consciousness:
Essays for Aron Gurwitsch. Ed. Lester E Embree. Evanston: Northwestern University Press,
1972.
Ricouer, Paul. Husser/: An Analysis of his Phenomenology. Trans., ed. G Ballard and Lester E
Embree. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1967.
Schmidt, Richard. 'Edmund Husser!." Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. New York: Macmillan,
1967.
Sinha, Debabrata. Phenomenology and Existentialism: An Introduction. Calcutta: Progressive
Publishers, 1974.
Spiegelberg, Herbert. The Phenomenological Movement. 3rd edn. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff,
1982.
Thevenaz, Paul. What is Phenomenology? Ed., intr. James M Edie. Trans. J Edie, Charles
Courtney, Paul Brocke1man. Chicago: Quadrangle Books, 1962.
166