What Is Freedom If It Is Not Power PDF
What Is Freedom If It Is Not Power PDF
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Berghahn Books is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
What Is Freedom if It Is Not Power?
Peter Morriss
Introduction
The underlying idea behind this article is that it might help us to understand
the concept of freedom by considering it alongside the concept of power. I
shall say little here about what 'power' is, for the simple reason that I have
already written a book on this concept, and I still stand by most of what I said
in it.1 Instead, I shall try to say something about freedom that is compatible
with what I have already said about power.
I shall, then, start with two assumptions. The first is that there is a concept
of power that can be called 'power-to', or an ability concept of power; it can
often be replaced by the much simpler word 'can'. It is the concept that we
use when we say that America had the power to overthrow the government of
Saddam Hussein. In my book, I argued that this is the main (and most impor-
tant) concept of power, by contrast with its main rival, which is usually called
'power over'. I still stand by that claim, but in this article I only need the much
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2 Peter Morriss
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
What Is Freedom if It Is Not Power? 3
A common idea is that freedom is a subset of power, or, more usually, that
lack of freedom is a subset of lack of power. That is the idea that I will explore
in this section. The recent writer who has given this idea most attention is
Matthew Kramer (in Kramer, 2003). On his account, having the ability to do
X is a necessary condition to be either free or unfree to do X. One is unfree to
do X if one is able to do it, but is prevented from doing it by an appropriate
constraint; one is free to do X if one is able to do it and is not prevented from
doing it by any appropriate constraint. But if one is unable to do X, then one
is neither free nor unfree - one is merely unable. As Isaiah Berlin said, we
cannot fly like an eagle or swim like a whale,10 but that does not make us
unfree to do those things. And, having made this distinction, advocates of neg-
ative liberty then usually go on to advance the Primacy of Freedom Thesis ,
which is that it is far more significant if you are unfree to do something than
if you are merely unable to do it.1 1
I will not go into any detail yet about what might make a constraint an
'appropriate' constraint; instead, I will stick with the key idea, which is that a
constraint that is introduced intentionally and purposefully by another human
being is a freedom-reducing constraint; a constraint that is entirely natural is
not a freedom-reducing constraint. A standard example of this is to consider
two similar unfortunate cases: in both you are exploring a cave, and, whilst
you are inside, a large boulder rolls over the only entrance, completely block-
ing it, and trapping you so that you cannot get out. In the first version (Sce-
nario I), the boulder was placed there deliberately by your enemy, who wanted
to trap you; in the second version (Scenario II), the boulder was dislodged by
an earthquake, rolled down the hillside, and, by bad luck, happened to end up
blocking the entrance to the cave. In both cases the same boulder is in the
same place, making you unable to leave. But Kramer, along with most theo-
rists of negative liberty, say that you are made unfree to leave only in Scenario
I, and not in Scenario II.12
This is standard stuff, but I want to continue this story somewhat. I want
you to imagine that you are trapped in this cave. You have just spent an
unhappy few hours convincing yourself that the boulder is far too heavy for
you to move, and that it is blocking the entrance so completely that you cannot
possibly squeeze past it. You also do not have your mobile phone with you (or
maybe it does not work in the cave), and you have established that there is no
other possible way out. You are therefore contemplating slowly starving to
death, trapped in this cave. And then - and what a great relief! - you hear a
voice outside; and it turns out that a local farmer is passing by, with a tractor,
and he hears your cries for help. Upon ascertaining your predicament, he then
surprises you by asking how the boulder got there. You reply, surely not unrea-
sonably: 'But it doesn't matter how it got there; could you please let me out?'.
But then this farmer says, 'Ah, but it does matter, you see. I've just been read-
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
4 Peter Morriss
ing Kramer, a
that would be
who values fr
there naturally
and that would
and discovers
you are not un
to die in peac
It is not clear
any sense at a
meet is to give
and act like th
Kramer hims
thought that t
important is t
get out. If the
reason to rescu
dom. In other
than lack of f
ual story: wh
what matters
selves). So it s
more importa
negative freed
matter at all ,
Perhaps befor
couple of coun
have over-sim
freedom, a rat
one is free and
version of the
you if doing s
a ratio cannot
the boulder h
increase this
trapped, releas
dix for the cal
increased, the
you. I do not t
The second co
have suggeste
infringement
farmer refuse
what happens
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
What Is Freedom if It Is Not Power? 5
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
6 Peter Morriss
scanned and i
which means n
the use of tha
surprised to f
words; and it
'whiteness' wa
from gloomin
dom from pa
although 'fre
one of the me
piler did not s
Thinking of f
want to start
cific to suit w
concerns to s
seem to be a c
This is relative
account of fre
dyadic: it is si
this the third
mark the abs
clearly a larg
have this powe
the person can
to have power,
is considered p
I now want to
lum's account
outline, there
convention of
complicated.
dyadic concept
then there mu
We should on
one, when th
America was
had the power
an absence of
mind that the
can hegemony
absence of con
the actor can o
If we are draw
that absence h
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
What Is Freedom if It Is Not Power? 7
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
8 Peter Morriss
would be on th
they are not in
and nobody els
come, freedom
What I have b
Carter's sense
are unwelcome,
used a slightly
said that we co
ate.23 The poin
Concepts of Lib
'The nature of
about 'ill will'
and (merely) un
And this allow
Kramerian farm
response to you
suffering cause
all other concer
relatively mino
how the inabil
cave example.
the one that is
the other exit
whether you w
might well mat
the second exit
to you that at
Some people p
imagine someo
Kramerian far
about the ill w
abilities, and n
freedom would
So my attempt
in different w
think that this
of freedom: th
been put as we
his autobiograp
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
What Is Freedom if It Is Not Power? 9
The second sense of freedom which I would like to consider is being a free
person , which is exemplified by not being a slave. For whilst the prisoner is
the exemplar of the person who has little or no freedom of action , the slave is
the exemplar of the unfree person.21
Prisoners are unfree, I have suggested, because there are few things that they
are free to do ; that is not the case with slaves. Some slaves were free to do a
great deal, and a great deal more than many non-slaves. Slaves, in many slave-
owning cultures, could become very rich, could gain considerable political
power, could themselves own slaves, and could hold respected positions in soci-
ety.28 We do not discover that a person is a slave by looking at what they are
able or free to do , and deciding on that basis whether they are a slave or not.
Rather, to be a slave is to have a certain legal status. For that reason, slave-
hood does not admit of degrees: one cannot be more or less of a slave; one
either is a slave or one is not.29 Neither is slavehood a threshold concept, such
that those who score below a certain level on some dimension are slaves,
whilst those who score above are riot; there is no such dimension. The distinc-
tion between being a slave and being free is an absolute one.
Certain facts follows from the fact that one is a slave, one of which is that
one is subject to the more-or-less arbitrary power of one's master.30 But the
logic does not go the other way around: one is not considered a slave because
one is subject to arbitrary power; one is subject to arbitrary power because one
is a slave. Even that is misleading. In many slave societies, the lowest status of
all was to be free; for one then had no protector, and was therefore subject to
the arbitrary power of everyone.31 The slave, on the other hand, was subject
only to the arbitrary power of his master. Hence the slave could be subject to
rather little arbitrary power.
In order to understand what it meant to be a free man,32 as opposed to
being a slave, we have to take seriously the importance of status , and that is
not easy given the ideologies that most of us hold. Arguments about status in
modern political philosophy tend to occur at the periphery: there is a consid-
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
10 Peter Morriss
erable literature
tend to take it f
status matters:
dominance of lib
status, and has l
does is to make
believe deeply i
probably think
againstnon-liber
heads round the
owning society.
a slave should be considered so valuable.
If to be unfree is to be of a lower status, this is unfreedom of a different sort
from the unfreedom of the prisoner. A prisoner does not necessarily lose status
by being imprisoned.35 A king who is thrown into a dungeon might still be a
king: indeed, he would not be incarcerated in that way if he was not seen as a
king.36 And one of the standard theories of punishment (retributivism) claims
that to punish is exactly to respect the status of the punished, as a rational
human being.37
Isaiah Berlin noted that advocacy of liberty 'is comparatively modern. There
seems to be scarcely any discussion of individual liberty as a conscious polit-
ical ideal ... in the ancient world' (Berlin, 1958: 176). He then proceeded to
give a sketch of how liberty had developed as an ideal, which was tailored to
his own purposes. I want also to give a very quick excursion into how the con-
cept of freedom entered our language (that is, English - but I think that much
the same is true of other European languages).38 It was not directly from the
Latin contrast with slavery.
Initially, 'free' was used to refer to states that were independent; and this
principle of national liberation was once again dominant when Isaiah Berlin
was writing on freedom, and he was highly sceptical of it, since such move-
ments for national liberation were motivated by a desire to produce free states ,
not necessarily free persons?9 This call for national liberation is really an
inheritance of a medieval world-view, in which the idea of freedom could only
be applied to collective entities, not to an individual person.40 By extension,
its usage was extended from states to those corporate entities, within a state,
which were free of royal or baronial interference. Thus one of the earliest Eng-
lish usages of the word 'liberty' was to describe an area in which the standard
rights of rulers did not apply. This sense of Liberty, as a distinct form of local
government, was not abolished until the Local Government Act of 1888, and
there is still a part of Dublin which is called 'The Liberties': it is an amalga-
mation of a number of smaller areas, each of which was a Liberty.41 Entities
such as guilds and cities were also called 'free' when they possessed, or were
granted, immunities from obligations that existed elsewhere. Thus the Treaty
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
What Is Freedom if It Is Not Power? 1 1
Part of the reason that freedom has become so important to us is that we have
adopted a Romantic vision of the human condition. This contains an ideal of
man as a creator, ; someone who imposes his will on the world, and moulds it
to his purposes.43 Importantly, each of us is the creator of our own life (if of
nothing else).44 And, as significantly, each of us has to be recognised by others
as the sort of person who is the creator of his own life. It is only with this addi-
tional factor that it becomes demeaning in itself to be a slave, and demeaning
to be treated as a slave by others; it is in this world- view that to be demarcated
as a slave is intrinsically hurtful, and not just instrumentally undesirable.
This idea has been expressed as well as I know by Berlin - not in his 'Two
Concepts', but in a lecture he gave on Rousseau at much the same time. I can-
not do better than quote him at some length:
For him [Rousseau], liberty is identical with the human individual himself. To say
that a man is a man, and to say that he is free, are almost the same.
What is a man for Rousseau? A man is somebody responsible for his acts - capa-
ble of . . . following the path either of right or of wrong. ... If a man is not free, if a
man is not responsible for what he does, if a man does not do what he does because
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
12 Peter Morriss
he wants to do it
achieves somethi
he does not do th
If a man is coerc
circumstances, t
a thing, a chatt
selection betwee
native goals becau
if he is determin
because he is bu
somebody else w
ulated like a pup
(Berlin 1952: 3 1
Such a person i
Berlin on Rous
For a man to wi
degrading. ... 'T
man ...'. (Berlin
The conclusion
sense in which f
person you are -
a cow or a chattel. This is the sort of consideration that allows us to talk about
people being able to 'hold their head high', however little they are able to do.
And it connects with my previous idea that having freedom of action is to be
not subject to insulting constraints.46 Something along these lines has, I think,
motivated those who have actually fought for freedom in societies in which it
could not be taken for granted.
Republican Freedom
In this section I want to consider briefly some aspects of Philip Pettit's 'repub-
lican' theory of freedom.47 1 shall suggest that there are problems with Pettit's
account, but that these problems can be solved and the political parts of the
theory rescued and put on a firmer basis. During the course of this section, I
shall draw attention to a couple of oddities and historical anachronisms in Pet-
tit's account, and suggest that we can draw important conclusions from them.
The first is the following. At the core of Pettit's theory is the claim that
what republicans hated most was slavery: 48 Yet, on the face of it, this is a
strange claim. Two of the major republican periods best known to Anglo-
phones are republican Rome and the early republic in the U.S.A. Not only
were both slave societies, but the republicans themselves were usually slave-
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
What Is Freedom if It Is Not Power? 1 3
Pettit's second historical anachronism sheds doubt on his central claim about
the nature of republican freedom. Pettit draws a distinction between 'republi-
can' (un)freedom and (what he calls) 'liberal' (un)freedom. On a liberal
account of freedom, Pettit says, you are only unfree to do some X if you are
actually prevented from doing X; for the republican, however, you are unfree
if you could be prevented from doing it. Putting this in the language of power:
for a republican you are unfree in so far as you are subject to the power of
another; for the liberal, you are only unfree in so far as the power-holder exer-
cises their power, so as to interfere with your actions.
Matthew Kramer has drawn attention to an undesirable implication of Pet-
tit's theory, by introducing what he calls 'a rather far-fetched example' of a
Gentle Giant. Kramer introduces the example as follows:
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
14 Peter Morriss
Suppose that, in
From adolescenc
gent than any of
cratic sway ove
coercing some of
one would dare
becoming a tyra
his community.
the nearby hills
he spends his tim
On the republic
the community
dom at all. Kram
a significant ad
I would agree -
Virtually all th
U.S.A. and Brit
believe that the
nity; they calle
us mortals as to
that this power
wise enough to
blasphemy to
phemy must be
ceptual confusio
our freedom. In
destroys freedo
This indicates t
argues Pettit, i
that power is
nasty way);53 so
tyrant.54 As Kr
licans think of
republican unde
of absolute pow
they thought o
and not the rep
However, that i
of the story. F
(for some that
welcomed; He w
same, however,
quite explicit. M
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
What Is Freedom if It Is Not Power? 1 5
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
16 Peter Morriss
on the other. Ro
a res publica is
under which the
. . . ' (Wirszubski
despots in that t
part of what was
There is here so
under it, the ma
answer (or a sk
not have the fre
they can resist
power: what peo
Pettit in an earl
cal programme
gross disparitie
distinctive conce
not need) a conc
And rightly so.
Conclusion
In this article I have argued for the following claims. First, that power is far
more important than most contemporary political philosophers have recog-
nised. Second, that the difference between lacking the power to act and lacking
the freedom to act is (very roughly) that lack of power injures (for you cannot
do things) whilst lack of freedom insults (you cannot do things because of a
constraint which demeans you). Third, that therefore the Primacy of Freedom
Thesis implies that insult should be given priority over injury, and so it is only
plausible when that priority is plausible. Fourth, that we do well to contrast
three different exemplars of an unfree actor: the prisoner, the slave, and the
subject of tyranny. Fifth, that being a free person rather than a slave matters
because (and in so far as) our status as a (certain sort of) person matters. Sixth,
that the republican approach is best seen as a combination of a concern (even
an obsession) with such status, and also an opposition to tyranny - and this
latter itself is best thought of as a concern with well-being rather than freedom,
and the recognition that power is needed in order to resist and curb tyranny.
If I am even half-way right, then we need to change much of our attitude to
political philosophy. We need to distinguish far more carefully between (con-
ceptual) political philosophy and (empirical) political theory; and restore the
validity of the latter. And we need to reinvestigate nearly obsolete concepts,
such as status and tyranny. After all, freedom became a dominant value in
opposition to the ruling ideologies within very status-conscious and hierarchi-
cal societies: it was a revolutionary value. It may be that we cannot detach this
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
What Is Freedom if It Is Not Power? 1 7
Acknowledgements
Much of the work on this article was done whilst I was a Visiting Fellow in the
School of Politics and International Relations, Research School of Social Sci-
ences, Australian National University. I am grateful to Keith Dowding for
arranging this visit, and for the National University of Ireland, Galway (my
then employer) for awarding me the sabbatical leave that allowed me to go to
ANU. Whilst there I benefitted particularly from frequent conversations with
Keith Dowding and Pamela Pansardi.
Earlier, preliminary, versions of this article were presented to the ANU
School of Politics and International Relations' Seminar series in Canberra,
Australia (March 2010); to the Symposium on Power, Freedom and Democ-
racy, University of Birmingham, England (September 2010); and to the Work-
shop on Power and Freedom, University of Pavia, Italy (June 201 1). I am most
grateful to the organisers of these events for their kindness in inviting me (and
looking after me when I was there). I also benefitted greatly from the com-
ments made in the discussions after my presentations, which forced me into
significantly altering the direction of my arguments. I have also gained a lot
from further comments from Geoff Cupit, Cecile Hatier and anonymous
reviewers for this journal.
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1 8 Peter Morriss
Appendix
(1) F2 f 2
(F + U) (f+u)
We can, for simplicity, assume that F > f > 0. (f is greater than zero since it is
certainly the case that there are some things which you are free to do in your
cave, though there are not very many. It is true that there are some things you
are free to do in the cave that you are not free to do if released: think in peace,
perhaps. But it is fair to assume that these are trivial compared to the things
you would be free to do if released and not free to do if not released - which
is, presumably, why you want to be released. Hence F is bigger than f.)
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
What Is Freedom if It Is Not Power? 1 9
(2) F2 f.
(F + U)
I can see no reason why inequality (2) must, necessarily, hold. It is true that
we are assuming that F is greater than f, but we know nothing about the relative
values of F and U. If U is very large relative to F - that is, if our measure of the
actions you are unfree to do if released is much larger than the measure of the
actions you are free to do - then (2) will not be true.
It might appear that you would indeed be better off in the cave, if the range
of unfreedoms you suffer outside is so large. But note that this follows solely
from Kramer's different treatments of the two Scenarios: if the boulder was
placed there by your enemy, you should be released even when U is huge rel-
ative to F. It is only because Kramer treats the two scenarios so differently that
we get these different results.
Hence the Kramerian farmer in my example, when responding to your pleas
to be released, has to obtain two sorts of information. The first is the one men-
tioned in the text: how the boulder got lodged in the mouth of the cave. The
second, which is required only when the boulder got there naturally, is enough
information about your various freedoms and unfreedoms to establish whether
inequality (2) holds. If he decided that your U was too high relative to your F,
he would then have to tell you that you would not be sufficiently free to war-
rant releasing. (But, to repeat, he would release you if the boulder was put
there through human agency, however little freedom and much unfreedom you
might have outside.) That response seems even less warranted than the one
given in the main text.
Notes
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
20 Peter Morriss
5. Dworkin (2011
imposed by other
your ability to do
should perhaps ad
6. More recently,
2007, and Carter,
have a slightly m
7. Carter (1999: 2
8. Carter (1999: 17
provided by his u
dom (pp. 97, 250);
dom' is omnipote
allowing us to gai
money and power
9. Like most writ
are not complete
corresponding to
ferences in the w
10. Berlin (1958: 16
1 1 . Kramer seem
tionship between
between an unfre
12. For this to be
impact at all on th
that the boulder to
discussed in somew
(2009: 58-62).
13. This counter-ar
14. See Kramer (2
15. Morriss (2009
1 6. This counter-a
Power, Freedom,
17. It might instea
that your predica
But then, when (a
(because you are no
ing theory either.
18. The definition
unrestraint; ease o
19. The OED gives
speech or behavio
the third [online]
20. The OED gives
this as obsolete. A
generous, magnan
coexist because the
ignored was desir
2 1 . That was the
. . . ' the only two
itions of whitene
because Walker as
of colour as unde
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
What Is Freedom if It Is Not Power? 2 1
3 1 . Thus, to quote one passage from Orlando Patterson ( 1 99 1 : 23) from many:
[I]n nearly all traditional societies [p]ersonal freedom had no place .... Indeed, such a
condition amounted to social suicide and, very likely, physical death. In many respects it
was a condition worse than slavery ....
See also Tarling (2007: 143):
How far the possible advantages of hierarchy might apply to slaves perhaps depends on
the nature of the slavery involved. ... At least in respect of some of its forms in South-
east Asia, my own area of expertise, it [being a slave] was seen as an advantage.
32. I am afraid that it really is impossible to avoid sexist language in this context: in many
slave-owning societies there was no such thing as a free woman.
33. This is, I think, not quite true. Much of the argument about gay marriage is about status: the
status of being married. Those who advocate gay marriage do indeed do so in part to obtain
a range of benefits for long-term gay couples that previously only heterosexual couples
could enjoy. But when the argument is that some sort of Civil Partnership, bringing all those
benefits, is not enough, and that only marriage will do, it is about status and nothing else.
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
22 Peter Morriss
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
What Is Freedom if It Is Not Power? 23
References
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
24 Peter Morriss
Dworkin, R. 201
Press.
Fourquin, G. 1976. Lordship and Feudalism in the Middle Ages. London: George
Allen & Unwin.
Grice, H. P. 1989. 'Logic and Conversation', in H. P. Grice, Studies in the Way of
Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hampsher-Monk, I. 2012. 'Political Liberty and the Concept of Citizenship in Early
Modern Discourse', Paper delivered to the 2012 Oxford Political Thought
Conference, January 2012.
Harding, A. 1980. 'Political Liberty in the Middle Ages', Speculum 55 (July): 423-43.
IgnatiefF, M. 1998. Isaiah Berlin: A Life. London: Chatto and Windus.
Ishiguro, K. 1989. The Remains of the Day. London: Faber.
Jászi, O. and J. D. Lewis. 1957. Against the Tyrant. Glencoe: Free Press.
Kalyvas, A. 2007. 'The Tyranny of Dictatorship: When the Greek Tyrant Met the
Roman Dictator', Political Theory 35: 412-42.
Kramer, M. H. 2003. The Quality of Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kramer, M. H. 2008. 'Liberty and Domination', in C. Laborde and J. Maynor (eds),
Republicanism and Political Theory. Oxford: Blackwell.
Kristjánsson, K. 1996. Social Freedom: The Responsibility View. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Lewis, C. S. 1954. 'The Humanitarian Theory of Punishment', reprinted in R. J.
Gerber and P. D. McAnany (eds), Contemporary Punishment: Views ,
Explanations, and Justifications. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press,
1972.
Locke, J. 1689. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding [many editions].
Locke, J. 1690. The Second Treatise of Government [many editions].
MacCallum, G. C. 1967. 'Negative and Positive Freedom', Philosophical Review 76:
312-34.
Mandela, N. 1994. Long Walk to Freedom: The Autobiography of Nelson Mandela.
London: Little, Brown.
Milne, K. 2009. The Dublin Liberties, 1600-1850. Dublin: Four Courts Press.
Milton, J. 1642. Commonplace Book , in J. Milton, Complete Prose Works vol. I. New
Haven: Yale University Press, 1953.
Milton, J. 1651. A Defence of the People of England , in J. Milton, Complete Prose
Works vol. IV New Haven: Yale University Press, 1966.
Morriss, P. 1987. Power: A Philosophical Analysis. Manchester: Manchester
University Press.
Morriss, P. 2009. 'Power and Liberalism', in S. R. Clegg and M. Haugaard (eds), The
Sage Handbook of Power. London: Sage.
Patterson, O. 1982. Slavery and Social Death. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Patterson, O. 1991. Freedom Vol. 1: Freedom in the Making of Western Culture, n.p.:
BasicBooks.
Pettit, P. 1996. 'Freedom as Antipower', Ethics 106: 576-604.
Pettit, P. 1997. Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Pitkin, H. 1988. 'Are Freedom and Liberty Twins?', Political Theory, 16: 523-52.
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
What Is Freedom if It Is Not Power? 25
This content downloaded from 132.174.250.76 on Sun, 29 Mar 2020 12:48:06 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms