Confucian Cosmopolitanism 2014
Confucian Cosmopolitanism 2014
Confucian Cosmopolitanism 2014
Philip J. Ivanhoe
ABSTRACT
Scholars in the humanities and social sciences are keenly aware of and
often deeply engaged with more global or cosmopolitan approaches to their
respective fields; nevertheless, theories of cosmopolitanism remain exceed-
ingly controversial and arise exclusively from Western philosophical sources.
Recently, Martha Nussbaum presented a contemporary Western liberal
cosmopolitan theory and sought to integrate it with a call for multicultural
education. In this essay, I describe, analyze, and criticize Nussbaum’s
conception of cosmopolitanism and argue that it does not sit comfortably
with her laudable advocacy of multicultural education. I then draw upon
resources within the Confucian tradition to sketch two alternative concep-
tions of cosmopolitanism, which I argue are both more powerful than what
Nussbaum proposes and better support the kind of multicultural education
she so eloquently advocates.
KEY WORDS: Confucian, cosmopolitan, cultural diversity, ideal guest, Kant,
multicultural education
1. Introduction
In this essay, I use Martha Nussbaum’s views on cosmopolitanism and
the responses of a number of her critics to trace the main currents within
Philip J. Ivanhoe is Chair Professor of East Asian and Comparative Philosophy and Religion
in the Department of Public Policy at City University of Hong Kong. He specializes in
East Asian philosophy and religion and their potential for contemporary ethical and social
theory. Philip J. Ivanhoe, Department of Public Policy, City University of Hong Kong,
Kowloon Tong, Hong Kong, [email protected].
1
This work was supported by a grant from The Academy of Korean Studies funded by the
Korean Government (MEST) (AKS-2011-AAA-2102).
2 This poem by Alexander Pope was greatly admired by Kant, who is said to have recited
responses I discuss, along with several others, can be found in Cohen 1996. Her essay and
versions of several of the responses I will explore here first appeared in Boston Review: A
Political and Literary Forum (Nussbaum 1994). As noted, my concern is with a number of
influential philosophical conceptions of cosmopolitanism, but sophisticated and influential
views about and conceptions of cosmopolitanism are being explored by a wide range of social
and political theorists. For a splendid introduction to some of these, see Vertovec and Cohen
2002. Thanks to Ray Forrest for bringing this literature to my attention.
4 Nussbaum goes into much greater detail about the nature and function of such an
education in Nussbaum 1998. While I fully endorse almost all of what she says in advocating
such an ideal, I see the same tension between competing conceptions of cosmopolitanism in
this work.
5 In her response to Nussbaum’s essay “Patriotism and Cosmopolitanism,” Sissela Bok
(1996) cites the passage from Pope which appears as the epigraph of this essay and goes
on to argue that Rabindranath Tagore, whose work Nussbaum cites to support her first
conception of cosmopolitanism, actually followed a more gradualist theory of moral educa-
tion, beginning with a child’s home tradition and then extending outward to embrace others,
which, as we shall see, is what Confucian cosmopolitanism recommends.
24 Journal of Religious Ethics
Kant and his followers, advocating things like the principle of respect for persons as rational
agents (Moralität), and Hegelians, who champion the critical importance of particular
cultural backgrounds and practices (Sittlichkeit).
Confucian Cosmopolitanism 25
2. Nussbaum on Cosmopolitanism
Nussbaum begins her presentation of cosmopolitanism by quoting clas-
sical sources and most prominently Diogenes Laertius who claimed to
be “a citizen of the world.” It repays us to pause to consider what it might
mean to be “a citizen of the world.” Nussbaum offers several different,
potentially incompatible possibilities. For example, she claims that the
cosmopolitan is a “person whose allegiance is to the worldwide community
of human beings” (1996, 4) and someone who gives “reason and moral
capacity, our first allegiance and respect” (1996, 7). Depending on how we
understand the first view, it could describe an ideal that a wide range of
figures, religious as well as secular, embrace. For example, the Christian
ideal of agapē seems like an example of this view. If, though, we take it
in light of the second claim, which is what Nussbaum clearly intends, then
it describes a much more specific, Kantian, conception of cosmopolitan-
ism.7 On such a view, the primary and overriding concern of each person
is the rational moral capacities of others. I am to regard each and every
person as an equal member of what Kant called the “kingdom of ends.” My
first obligations and fidelity are not to my family, community, tradition,
or state—such things are “morally irrelevant” (1996, 5)—but to the “moral
community made up by the humanity of all human beings” (1996, 7).
What makes persons worthy of respect and moral regard, what makes
them human, is their status as rational agents; this is what they essen-
tially are.
There are a number of challenges, both practical and theoretical, for
such a view of cosmopolitanism. These may not be fatal, but they are
formidable. I will mention only two, before turning to the criticisms raised
by others. The first is one of many practical problems. As a matter of fact,
people live in states which require them to do things like pay taxes. The
taxes they pay are used by the state primarily to defend and support
the citizens of the state. Someone who really tried to live as a citizen of
the world should refuse to pay taxes to any “mere state.” At least in the
world we live in, this simply is not possible. Nussbaum herself pays taxes
in the United States, and this leaves her recommending an ideal that she
does not and cannot follow. One might respond by saying that such an
objection does not challenge the philosophical cogency of her position, but
the practical problem identified here points to a more basic philosophical
issue. Kant himself insisted that ought implies can; so if states and other
kinds of social institutions are necessary in order for individuals to work
out and practice any adequate kind of moral life, this presents a profound
challenge to Nussbaum’s view. From a purely conceptual point of view, in
the absence of any kind of institutional structure it is difficult to under-
stand how one could be a citizen at all. The very notion of being a citizen
implies allegiance to some particular social group; this is what distin-
guishes citizens from aliens. If taken literally, being “a citizen of the
world” either implies the establishment of a single world government or
inclines toward incoherence.8 If we try to qualify our way out of this
criticism by saying that “citizen of the world” means only that one feels
some allegiance to the other nations, cultures, and people of the world,
then the notion of cosmopolitanism becomes more plausible but much less
dramatic and radical. All it then means is that one shows some level of
concern for the other people of the world.
Another ambiguity in Nussbaum’s conception of cosmopolitanism is
found in her notion of allegiance toward all of humanity. She draws a
contrast with “patriot” views, which entail showing preference for the
fellow citizens of one’s state, and recommends that we treat everyone in
the world equally. What, though, such equal treatment amounts to is far
from clear. Take for example her use of the metaphor of “concentric
circles” to illustrate her position (1996, 9). On such a view, we are to see
ourselves as existing in an innermost circle around which are larger and
larger circles representing close family, friends, neighbors, fellow citizens,
and ultimately everyone in the world. This is a common way people
describe the Confucian view (though one does not find this particular
image in traditional Confucian writings). Nevertheless, Confucians insist
that our first and primary duties always remain focused on families. We
extend our feelings beyond our families and out to those in the outermost
circle, but our love for them (our allegiance to them) is much less direct
or intense. Nussbaum seems to agree with this general approach when
she says the goal is to make “all human beings more like our fellow
city-dwellers” (1996, 9, emphasis added). Her view, though, is only asking
8
Establishing a single world government makes sense conceptually, but there are serious
problems with such a view. First and foremost, it undermines the celebration of diversity,
which is a key feature of Nussbaum’s view. Second, it requires that the various existing
states in the world will somehow agree to dissolve and merge into one, an aspiration that
shows no sign of being realized. Third, it eliminates the important role that a diversity of
states offers. A single world government would lack any alternative perspective or break
upon its power and easily invite tyranny. I argue that such diversity of perspective is one of
the reasons we should embrace the fact of ethical pluralism as a good thing. See Ivanhoe
2009a. Of course, the United Nations remains both appealing and plausible, but it is not a
world government; it is a formal association of states affording the governments of the world
an institution and set of procedures for meeting to discuss and adjudicate their differences.
Confucian Cosmopolitanism 27
Analects 12.5 teaches that “all within the four seas are brothers” (四海之内皆兄弟也) (Kongzi
1972). The ideal for early Confucians is thus like that expressed in Friedrich Schiller’s
immortal lines in To Joy: “Alle Menschen werden Brüder, wo dein sanfter Flügel weilt.”
10 One might be hostile, disappointed, or simply indifferent to the fact of ethical plural-
ism, but Nussbaum’s advocacy of cosmopolitan education seems clearly aimed at a moral
ideal that celebrates such diversity. For more on different responses to ethical pluralism, see
Ivanhoe 2009a.
28 Journal of Religious Ethics
11 I explore this set of issues, concerning what it might mean to respect a variety of
12
As we will see below, when we discuss Hilary Putnam’s response to Nussbaum’s view,
a similar argument could be made by comparing the study of other cultures with the study
of different traditions of music (Putnam 1996).
13 It is important to distinguish the view I am describing here from the notion of a moral
connoisseur. The latter is someone whose appreciation and ability to distinguish flavors is
based not upon a grasp of theoretical principles but upon broad reflective experience of
different tastes. For a splendid analysis of this kind of view, see Hutton 2002, 167–86.
14 In his response to Nussbaum’s essay, which I will not discuss in detail here, Robert
Pinsky likens her view of cosmopolitanism to cultural Esperanto. See Pinsky 1996, 85–90.
30 Journal of Religious Ethics
one’s sense of oneself as an ethical being and the ways in which one
perceives and thinks about moral problems reflect the culture or tradi-
tion of which one is a part. This is why such institutions are inherently
valuable. It is also why a true cosmopolitan celebrates diversity in culture.
On this view, there is no single privileged culture or tradition for working
out how people should live. Nussbaum belongs to the Western Enlight-
enment tradition, and this is one among many ways to understand oneself
and work to improve one’s society. It is a tradition that has contributed to
other modern cultures as well. Nevertheless, it is only one among equals
in the eyes of rooted cosmopolitans.
Gertrude Himmelfarb presents even stronger criticisms of Nussbaum’s
view, arguing that the cosmopolitanism Nussbaum describes is not only
an illusion but dangerous. She expresses at least three different kinds
of concerns about Nussbaum’s analysis. Her first objection hinges on
Nussbaum’s attempt to describe a form of cosmopolitanism that rests
primarily on abstract moral principle and she notes that while such
principles can describe a universal morality they cannot support a state-
less community (polis) (1996, 74). The idea here is that people do not live
in a world defined by abstract moral principles but in one ordered by
actual political institutions. Only the latter offer us the mechanisms by
which to order and enforce a way of life. States are not constituted or
sustained by moral principles alone; they have particular histories and
command the allegiance of people who live in these concrete, ongoing
communities.
Himmelfarb’s second objection is that Nussbaum’s description of
cosmopolitanism is idealist both in how it describes the world and what
it hopes for (1996, 74–75). In regard to the first, Nussbaum repeatedly
appeals to things like the “world community of justice and reason” (1996,
8) and the “common aims, aspirations, and values of humanity” (1996, 9).
She further claims that one of the basic imperatives of cosmopolitanism is
the “vivid imagining of the different” (1996, 9–10). This seems to present
a tension: on the one hand we are told that people in the world already
agree about the most important parts of life; on the other hand, we are
told to imagine and appreciate differences. Himmelfarb makes a separate
but related point: there is no world community of justice, reason, and
common values. Different cultures embrace profoundly different and irrec-
oncilable ideas about morality.16 Nussbaum is not reporting how the world
is; she is projecting her own liberal values onto the world and seeking to
reform it in this image. This hardly seems like an exercise in imagining
16 Himmelfarb’s descriptive claim does not rule out the possibility of much greater moral
consensus, and there are good reasons to be a bit more optimistic than she seems to suggest
on this score. Nevertheless, her description of the current state of the world strikes me as
accurate and sobering. Others are much more sanguine about the degree and future of moral
32 Journal of Religious Ethics
disagreement in the world. For example, see Moody-Adams 1997. In my view, this particular
work takes the principle of charity to excess and relies too heavily on arguments about what
one can imagine being so.
Confucian Cosmopolitanism 33
17 Putnam’s remark here recapitulates Hegel’s famous criticism of Kant’s moral philoso-
phy in paragraph 135 of the Philosophy of Right as an “empty formalism” (Hegel 1996).
34 Journal of Religious Ethics
3. Confucian Cosmopolitanism
As noted above, Hilary Putnam argues for the necessity of both the
particular, historically embedded perspective of tradition and the general,
abstract, complement of universal reason in order to think both critically
and substantially about ethical issues. Kongzi made a similar point when
in Analects 2.15 he said, “Study without reflection is a waste; Reflection
without study is a peril” (學而不思則罔;思而不學則殆) (Kongzi 1972). We
cannot either simply chant and defend the classics or seek some abstract
Archimedean point for ethical leverage; any such point is purely imagi-
nary; it hangs in mid-air; it offers no real fulcrum. Such a view means
that any viable form of cosmopolitanism must see value in both these
perspectives.
As we saw in reviewing the criticisms of Nussbaum’s Kantian-inspired
conception of cosmopolitanism, such a view fails to provide any solid
grounding in the actual world of value; this leads to serious problems
both theoretical and practical. No such difficulties plague Nussbaum’s
discussion of cosmopolitan education, but, as argued above, this latter
conception of cosmopolitanism seems to assume that ongoing traditions
of belief and practice are critically important not just to the people who
hold them but to a plausible account of a cosmopolitan point of view.
This suggests an alternative conception: a cosmopolitan is not a citizen
of nowhere but an interested guest or visitor18 of various cultures and
ways of life who is comfortable around the world. A cosmopolitan is not
the cultural equivalent of a speaker of Esperanto but rather a fluent,
multilingual traveler who knows and appreciates the special character-
istics and tenor of different natural languages and how each offers
distinctive insights into our common humanity. This is the kind of ideal
I would like to construct by drawing upon different aspects of the
Confucian tradition. To be precise, I will describe two different versions
of cosmopolitanism each developed around a core metaphor taken from
traditional Confucian writings. These share the common quality of rec-
ognizing and appreciating the irreducible pluralism that one finds
among the traditions of the world; the two conceptions differ, if at all,
in the degree of intimacy they envisage between different cultures. I will
not argue for the superiority of either but instead offer them together
as pointing toward the possibility of Confucian-inspired conceptions and
theories of cosmopolitanism.
Our first conception of Confucian cosmopolitanism is inspired by
Analects 3.15, which says,
When the master entered the ancestral temple,19 he asked about each and
every thing done there. Someone remarked, “Who says this son of the man
from Zou20 understands the rituals? When he entered the ancestral temple,
he asked about each and every thing done there!” When the master heard of
this remark, he said, “This is just what ritual requires.” (Kongzi 1972)21
This passage has been interpreted in different ways, but a point shared
by many traditional commentators and most contemporary translators is
the idea that in asking about the affairs of the ancestral temple Kongzi
was displaying considerable humility. As an expert in the Zhou rituals,
he would of course know about every little thing done in the ancestral
temple, but because he genuinely does not think of himself as some kind
of absolute authority, he humbly inquires about each and every thing done
in the temple.22 A further point, not inconsistent with this reading but
going beyond it and changing the focus, is that such a practice recognizes
and engages the people in the ancestral temple in an agreeable and
humane way. By asking about each and every thing in the ancestral
temple, Kongzi shows an interest in these people and what they hold dear,
and he brings them into the common cause of Zhou tradition. Such an
interpretation seems to make better sense of why such a practice would
itself be considered a ritual; it does much more than display humility, it
joins people together in an important, shared social activity.
I would like to suggest that we make something like Kongzi’s behavior
our practice and use this as a basis for our first conception of cosmopoli-
tanism. The idea is that we should sincerely inquire about the cultural
treasures of other people when we visit their countries, the religious
symbols and rituals of those we meet when we encounter them in the
course of our lives, the possessions people put on display when we enter
their homes, and the customs, beliefs, and norms they follow when we
visit and move among them. Such a practice can help us to understand
these people and the lives they live; more importantly, the very act of
asking—the ritual of inquiry—about such things will help develop as well
as express and convey our respect for and interest in them.
The guiding image behind this conception of cosmopolitanism is that
of an ideal visitor or guest: someone who comes to another’s country,
temple, home, or life with an attitude of open curiosity, a characteristically
Confucian “love of learning” (好學), and a desire for and anticipation of
19 A number of commentators believe, quite plausibly, that this refers to the ancestral
temple in Lu, which would make it the temple dedicated to the ancestors of the Zhou
dynasty’s ruling line.
20
Kongzi’s father had been an official in this town and hence is referred to here as “the
man from Zou.”
21 A short passage in Book Ten also tells us that Kongzi asked about each and every thing
experiences that will deepen not only their knowledge about but appre-
ciation of what it is to be human. Such an attitude does not see the value
of other people primarily, much less exclusively, in terms of their moral
agency; it is much more focused on the particular products of human
feeling, imagination, and reason that constitute the ongoing tradition and
culture one is visiting. It seeks to understand the complex expressions of
value and meaning instantiated in actual traditions and cultures and how
they hang together to constitute particular forms of life.
As good guests, we defer judgment, at least in most cases, about the
things we are seeking to understand until we are confident that we can
see their true significance within the larger frame of this particular form
of life. We are willing to try on, in sympathetic imagination, different
beliefs, attitudes, and practices in order to plumb more fully the depths
of our shared humanity. Such a visitor or guest does not immediately
measure every new event or experience against the norms of her home
tradition—as if this offers some absolute and universal standard. There is
nothing worse than a visitor who is always rushing to compare every new
experience with what is familiar, behaving like a child who refuses to
taste or sincerely attempt to appreciate a new dish because it does not
look like or remind them of what they eat at home.
The openness and spirit of adventure and curiosity of a cosmopolitan
does not prevent her from evaluating another culture or its practices.
Such judgments are part of what it is to respectfully consider another
point of view and way of life. Perhaps just as often, such cosmopolitans
will come to see considerable value in a particular foreign practice that
was not at all apparent on first consideration. The effect is not unlike how
we gain a different appreciation of a small patch of color when we step
back and see it playing a part within a larger and more complex tapestry,
mosaic, or canvas. The cosmopolitan as ideal visitor or guest will also
often be led to see her home culture and its various practices in new and
different lights. While one can of course question the beliefs, attitudes,
and practices of one’s home tradition without comparing them to others,
it is much more difficult to gain the imaginative traction one needs to do
so in the absence of clearly articulated alternatives. In any event, what
one cannot do without such comparison is to consider one’s home beliefs
in light of the actual existing traditions around one, many of which have
successfully served as the basis for ways of life for millennia, as is the case
with Confucianism. Since one of the aims of ethical practice and reflection
is to responsibly engage and respond to the people around us—and not
merely hypothetical or notional people—this kind of sympathetic com-
parative study seems to be a moral imperative of the first order. Without
such study and everyday practice, claims about respecting other human
beings become vanishingly thin and one risks leading a narrow, cramped,
and provincial life. This last set of points is very important and leads back
Confucian Cosmopolitanism 37
Sima Niu, feeling distressed said, “Others all have brothers; only I have
none!” Zixia replied, “I have heard the saying: Life and death are matters of
fate; Wealth and honor depend upon Heaven. Cultivated people are rever-
ently attentive and do nothing amiss; they are respectful and practice the
rites, regarding all within the four seas as brothers. How could cultivated
people ever worry about having no brothers?” (Kongzi 1972)23
23 Compare footnote 9.
38 Journal of Religious Ethics
the other hand, the appeal to our fellow-feelings for those in the same city
is rather weak, and this is brought out when compared to the Confucian
alternative.
If we try to think about and feel for other people on the analogy of
how we feel about our own siblings, we are called on to have much greater
sympathy for those we do not know. We are asked to take a more active
interest in their welfare, to be more accommodating regarding their
differences with us, and more forgiving of their faults. These features of
the Confucian perspective actually are quite familiar to most people, for
almost all of us regularly invoke Confucian-style arguments when we
deliberate or seek to persuade others to adopt our views about a range
of ethical issues. For example, if someone physically harms, mocks,
harshly criticizes, or shows inadequate understanding for or patience with
another, we often ask them to imagine how they would feel if someone
acted in the same way toward their brother or sister. It is not uncommon
for people who harbor deep and repugnant prejudices about things like
sexual orientation or race to find a way through them when they find their
own sister or daughter is a lesbian or marries someone from the race they
despise. Such appeals lose almost all of their force if we ask others to
imagine how they would feel if someone mistreated someone from their
city rather than their own brother or sister. Of course, not everyone
presented with such arguments is able to think and feel their way to
decency even with the right comparisons, but the fact is such connections
often do provide a way to reach a fair and proper appreciation of others.
In successful cases, when people come to see such prejudices for what they
are and succeed in appreciating “alien” others for the fellow human beings
they are, they achieve these ends by the welling-up and extension of moral
feelings and not the descent from on high of abstract moral principles to
straighten out the affairs of daily life.24 Confucians ask us to extend the
love, generosity, patience, and understanding we naturally tend to have
for our siblings to everyone in the world. This is a much better aim and
method than seeking to extend a sense of city fellow-feeling, for the latter
is not deep or committed enough to carry us through the difficulties that
extension entails.25
24 Mengzi was the first to develop an explicit Confucian view about the extension of
moral feelings. His view has been explored by David S. Nivison, Kwongloi Shun, Bryan W.
Van Norden, David B. Wong, and Craig Ihara. I have summarized their accounts and offered
my own interpretation in Ivanhoe 2002, 221–41.
25 It is important to recognize the amount of work required to pursue the ideal of
cosmopolitanism, and Confucian discussions of the need for and difficulties of self cultivation
are important in this regard. As noted in section 2 of this essay, the kind of cosmopolitan
education Nussbaum advocates is more challenging than it might at first seem; it requires
a serious commitment to learning about other cultures and the sympathetic cultivation of
understanding and appreciation.
Confucian Cosmopolitanism 39
4. Conclusion
We have presented Martha Nussbaum’s analysis and defense of
cosmopolitanism, arguing that she actually offers two accounts of cosmo-
politanism: the first describes cosmopolitanism in terms of a particular
Kantian-style moral principle concerning the value of persons; the second
describes cosmopolitanism in terms of a particular moral response to the
fact of cultural diversity, what she refers to as cosmopolitan education.
Her first version of cosmopolitanism is close to the classical statement by
Diogenes Laertius, who claimed to be “a citizen of the world.” We have
argued that this view risks developing into various forms of totalitarian-
ism or lapses into incoherence, since the very notion of being a citizen
implies membership in a particular polity. Human beings do not and
cannot live in the thin air of some abstract conception of “the world”; they
do and must live in actual communities and through ongoing traditions;
they work out the forms their lives might take within such familiar
environments. We have explored a range of different criticisms that all
support, in different ways, this general objection to Nussbaum’s first
description of cosmopolitanism as a way to fill out and strengthen the
general perspective we seek to defend.
We then went on to describe two forms of cosmopolitanism inspired by
parts of the Confucian tradition. The first describes cosmopolitanism in
terms of an ideal visitor or guest, while the second is inspired by the idea
that we should regard all people in the world as our brothers and sisters.
Both these forms of cosmopolitanism avoid the kinds of problems that
were discussed in regard to Nussbaum’s liberal expression of cosmopoli-
tanism. Neither asks us to abandon our actual, historically embedded
27
Another implication of the first form of Confucian cosmopolitanism is that there is a
corresponding set of virtues appropriate to those who serve as hosts. Among other virtues,
a cultural host will need to have patience, forbearance, enthusiasm, and creativity in order
to welcome, educate, and edify guests. A teacher of a multi-cultural curriculum will also need
to cultivate and manifest similar virtues when entertaining her student “guests.”
Confucian Cosmopolitanism 41
as best as they can the values, ideals, and practices of their siblings. They
put their shared relationship before their personal perspectives and
preferences. Even when they disagree, they will do everything possible to
avoid being disagreeable and work to ensure that they never lose sight of
the bond between them.
The Confucian conceptions of cosmopolitanism sketched in this essay
not only avoid the problems we have explored in regard to Nussbaum’s
liberal conception but also offer the outlines of an appealing model
for what cosmopolitanism might be as a moral attitude and practice.
I have not here argued to replace the Kantian moral principle behind
Nussbaum’s conception of cosmopolitanism with an alternative Confucian
moral principle; instead, I have described the Confucian view as a moral
response, not a moral theory.28 Nevertheless, almost all forms of Confu-
cianism are best understood as expressions of virtue ethics, which points
the way to a better view of the underlying theoretical foundations of
Confucian cosmopolitanism.29 Moreover, we can see the outlines of this
foundation in Nussbaum’s views about education and in the very notion of
cosmopolitanism itself. The intuitive appeal of a cosmopolitan education
lies primarily in the ways it expresses an ideal for being a respectful,
curious, well-informed, and open-minded person. In other words, the
justification for such a life lies in the appreciation of certain virtuous
dispositions or a certain kind of character. A large part of what attracts us
about cosmopolitanism is that it offers a clear sense of what it is to be a
wise and worldly person: the cosmopolitan, like Kongzi’s “cultivated
person” (君子), presents an appealing picture of a good way to be.
The two forms of cosmopolitanism I have presented here by no means
exhaust the resources to be found in the Confucian tradition. For example,
the “Evolution of the Rites” (禮運) chapter of the Book of Rites (禮記)
describes an ideal age in which, “The world is for everyone” (天下為公); in
the same work, this is called the period of “Great Unity” (大同). These
ideas served as inspirations for cosmopolitans like Kang Youwei (康有為)
(1858–1927)30 and might serve as important sources for crafting alterna-
tive Confucian conceptions of cosmopolitanism. The Ming dynasty Confu-
cian Wang Yangming (王陽明) (1492–1529) taught that in some deep sense
all the people, creatures, and things of the world are united and form “one
body.”31 He insisted that seeing the world as one body is the proper ideal
28 I earlier noted the potential value of the Kantian approach to cultivating a cosmopoli-
tan point of view (see footnote 7) and of course this is not the only way in which Kant’s moral
theory remains valuable to human beings today.
29
For my understanding of the Confucian tradition as a form of virtue ethics, see Ivanhoe
2013a.
30 For an introduction to Kang and his thought, see Hsiao 1975.
31 For an introduction to Wang and his writings, see Ivanhoe 2009b. Nussbaum briefly
REFERENCES
Appiah, Kwame Anthony
1996 “Cosmopolitan Patriots.” In For Love of Country: Debating the Limits
of Patriotism, edited by Joshua Cohen, 21–29. Boston: Beacon Press.
2006 Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in A World of Strangers. New York: W. W.
Norton and Company.
Bok, Sissela
1996 “From Part to Whole.” In For Love of Country: Debating the Limits of
Patriotism, edited by Joshua Cohen, 38–44. Boston: Beacon Press.
Chai, Shaojin
2011 Wang Yangming’s Cosmopolitanism of Oneness: Graded Care and
Integral Pluralism. PhD diss., University of Notre Dame.
Cohen, Joshua
1996 For Love of Country: Debating the Limits of Patriotism. Boston:
Beacon Press.
Hegel, G.W.F.
1996 Philosophy of Right. Translated by S. W. Dyde. Amherst, N.Y.:
Prometheus Books.
Himmelfarb, Gertrude
1996 “The Illusions of Cosmopolitanism.” In For Love of Country: Debating
the Limits of Patriotism, edited by Joshua Cohen, 72–77. Boston:
Beacon Press.
32
I dedicate this essay to Bridget Dorothy Slater to welcome her into our marvelous,
challenging, and if all goes well increasingly cosmopolitan world. Thanks to Shaojin Chai,
Erin M. Cline, Michael R. Slater, Aaron Stalnaker, Justin Tiwald, and two anonymous
readers for the JRE for very helpful corrections, comments, and suggestions on earlier
drafts.
Confucian Cosmopolitanism 43
Hsiao, Kung-chuan
1975 A Modern China and a New World: K’ang Yu-wei, Reformer and
Utopian, 1858–1927. Seattle, Wash.: University of Washington Press.
Hutton, Eric L.
2002 “Moral Connoisseurship in Mengzi.” In Essays on the Moral Philoso-
phy of Mengzi, edited by Xiusheng Liu and Philip J. Ivanhoe, 163–86.
Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett Publishing Company.
Ivanhoe, Philip J.
2002 “Confucian Self-Cultivation and Mengzi’s Notion of Extension.”
In Essays on the Moral Philosophy of Mengzi, edited by Xiusheng
Liu and Philip J. Ivanhoe, 221–41. Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett
Publishing.
2009a “Pluralism, Toleration, and Ethical Promiscuity.” Journal of Religious
Ethics 37.2 (June): 311–29.
2009b Readings from the Lu-Wang School. Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett
Publishing Company.
2010 “Moral Tradition Respect.” In Ethics in Early China, edited by Chris
Fraser, Dan Robins, and Timothy O’Leary, 161–73. Hong Kong:
University of Hong Kong Press.
2013a “Virtue Ethics and the Confucian Tradition.” In Cambridge Compan-
ion to Virtue Ethics, edited by Daniel Russell, 49–69. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
2013b “Senses and Values of Oneness.” In The Philosophical Challenge from
China, edited by Brian Bruya, forthcoming. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press.
Kongzi
1972 A Concordance to the Analects of Confucius. Taipei: Ch’eng-wen
Publishing Company.
Lasch, Christopher
1995 The Revolt of the Elites and the Betrayal of Democracy. New York:
W. W. Norton.
Micklethwait, John and Adrian Wooldridge
2003 A Future Perfect: The Challenge and Hidden Promise of
Globalization. New York: Random House.
Moody-Adams, Michele M.
1997 Fieldwork in Familiar Places: Morality, Culture, and Philosophy.
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Nussbaum, Martha C.
1994 “Patriotism and Cosmopolitanism.” In Boston Review: A Political
and Literary Forum 19.5 (October/November). Available at: http://
new.bostonreview.net/BR19.5/nussbaum.html (accessed September
16, 2013).
1996 “Patriotism and Cosmopolitanism.” In For Love of Country: Debating
the Limits of Patriotism, edited by Joshua Cohen, 3–20. Boston:
Beacon Press.
44 Journal of Religious Ethics