Between Holism and Reductionism
Between Holism and Reductionism
Between Holism and Reductionism
Received 14 December 2012; revised 17 January 2013; accepted for publication 17 January 2013
Ever since Darwin a great deal of the conceptual history of biology may be read as a struggle between two
philosophical positions: reductionism and holism. On the one hand, we have the reductionist claim that evolution
has to be understood in terms of changes at the fundamental causal level of the gene. As Richard Dawkins famously
put it, organisms are just ‘lumbering robots’ in the service of their genetic masters. On the other hand, there is a
long holistic tradition that focuses on the complexity of developmental systems, on the non-linearity of gene–
environment interactions, and on multi-level selective processes to argue that the full story of biology is a bit more
complicated than that. Reductionism can marshal on its behalf the spectacular successes of genetics and molecular
biology throughout the 20th and 21st centuries. Holism has built on the development of entirely new disciplines
and conceptual frameworks over the past few decades, including evo-devo and phenotypic plasticity. Yet, a number
of biologists are still actively looking for a way out of the reductionism–holism counterposition, often mentioning
the word ‘emergence’ as a way to deal with the conundrum. This paper briefly examines the philosophical history
of the concept of emergence, distinguishes between epistemic and ontological accounts of it, and comments on
conceptions of emergence that can actually be useful for practising evolutionary biologists. © 2013 The Linnean
Society of London, Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, 2014, 112, 261–267.
‘Emergence’ is a controversial concept with a convo- and similar ideas as obscurantist and leading only to
luted history, in both science and philosophy. It is never ending and fruitless debates – think, say, of
therefore not surprising that it has been misused and Richard Dawkins’ (1976) dismissal of anything smell-
vilified, as well as more often than not misunderstood. ing like group selection, or his famous quip that living
Typically, the idea of emergence is brought up by organisms are nothing but ‘lumbering robots’ control-
researchers who are – for one reason or another – led by their selfish genes.
unhappy with an ultra-reductionist scientific pro- It is undoubtedly the case that methodological
gramme, preferring instead some kind of holism or reductionism has an enviable track record both in
interactionism in the way they approach their biology specifically and in science more generally. By
research questions (think of the always current the onset of the 20th century chemistry had already
debates on gene–environment interactions: Lewontin, for all effective purposes been reduced to physics (Le
1974a). Just as surely, biologists who are embedded in Poidevin, 2005; although this is by no means an
reductionist programmes are skeptical of emergence accepted conclusion in philosophy of chemistry:
Hendry & Needham, 2007), and hopes were high
that biology would soon follow suit. Indeed, the
*E-mail: [email protected] demise of vitalism and the contemporary surge of
© 2013 The Linnean Society of London, Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, 2014, 112, 261–267 261
262 M. PIGLIUCCI
model-based genetics at the beginning of the 20th One of the earliest articulations of the concept of
century seemed to nail the argument in favour of emergence in biology is due, perhaps surprisingly, to
reductionists. In 1931 J. B. S. Haldane could confi- John Stuart Mill (1843: III(6)1): ‘To whatever degree
dently declare that ‘Biologists have almost unani- we might imagine our knowledge of the properties of
mously abandoned vitalism as an acknowledged the several ingredients of a living body to be extended
belief ’, although he was at the same time uncon- and perfected, it is certain that no mere summing up
vinced by exclusively mechanistic explanations of of the separate actions of those elements will ever
biological phenomena: ‘We must find a different theo- amount to the action of the living body itself.’ The
retical basis of biology, based on the observation that idea being expressed here is familiar in both biology
all the phenomena concerned tend towards being so and statistics nowadays: we know of plenty of exam-
© 2013 The Linnean Society of London, Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, 2014, 112, 261–267
PRIMER ON EMERGENCE 263
the sciences are fundamentally dis-unified, which can think of emergent properties from either an onto-
means that any talk of a ‘theory of everything’ is logical or an epistemological stance, although the two
nonsense (and, in his view, even socially dangerous, are not mutually exclusive. Ontology, of course, has to
because it gives priority to a particular, mechanistic, do with the nature of things, while epistemology has
view of science and knowledge). Dupré’s argument to do with how we (think we) come to have knowledge
begins with the (uncontroversial, among philoso- of the nature of things. Ontological claims are inher-
phers) observation that science itself depends on ently metaphysical, while epistemological claims are
metaphysical assumptions that are not justifiable not (they can be purely pragmatic, or derived from
empirically, and proceeds to question three related principles of logic). To complicate things further,
theses underlying the project of unification: determin- several philosophers (though by no means all!) from
© 2013 The Linnean Society of London, Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, 2014, 112, 261–267
264 M. PIGLIUCCI
metaphysics? All in all, I think the most reasonable actual complex genetic networks in living organisms.
course of action is actually to take a neutral, agnostic, Robustness measures the tendency of genetic net-
stance on the matter and to proceed to where we are works to withstand internal disruptions (e.g. muta-
going next: epistemological emergence. tions) while maintaining functionality, and is related
O’Connor (2006) helpfully describes two types of the to the broader concept of evolvability (Pigliucci, 2008).
latter, which he labels predictive and irreducible- While the mathematics of Romero & Zertuche
pattern. Predictive emergence is the idea that in (2007) is not for the faint of heart, their results are
practice it is not possible to predict the features of a relatively straightforward: robustness emerges from
complex system in terms of its constituent parts, even the statistical properties of a genotype–phenotype
if one were to know all the laws governing the behav- map modelled as an NK Kauffman-type network,
© 2013 The Linnean Society of London, Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, 2014, 112, 261–267
PRIMER ON EMERGENCE 265
of environments. As Lewontin (1974b) elegantly house-building metaphor, another one is to cash out
showed in reference to the specific case of the herit- on the promise of evo-devo in order to understand the
ability of human IQ, grasping the concept of a reac- emergence of phenotypes in biological organisms.
tion norm allows one to understand seemingly Regardless, the point remains that this – as well as
paradoxical ideas such as, for example, that a change the previous case of robustness – seems to represent
in environmental variance may affect estimates of a genuine case of emergence, at least at the epistemic
heritability (as it has been empirically demonstrated level (as I mentioned above, ontological emergence is
several times since: Pigliucci, 2001: ch. 4), even a metaphysical notion that is likely not to be settled
though the ‘genetic’ component of phenotypic variance empirically, and about which the best course of action
remains unaltered. is to maintain philosophical neutrality).
© 2013 The Linnean Society of London, Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, 2014, 112, 261–267
266 M. PIGLIUCCI
numbers, first on a single row – which is easy to do – Dobzhansky T. 1981. Dobzhansky’s genetics of natural popu-
then on multiple rows, which becomes immediately lations I-XLIII. Lewontin RC, Moore JA, Provine WB,
overwhelming.) Wallace B. New York: Columbia University Press.
Interestingly, Johnson’s example of an emergent Dupré J. 1995. The disorder of things: metaphysical founda-
property that is not mysterious, and yet that we tions of the disunity of science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
cannot cognitively deal with, is cellular automata (for University Press.
a similar take, also using cellular automata, see Elgin M. 2006. There may be strict empirical laws in biology,
after all. Biology and Philosophy 21: 119–134.
various works by Mark Bedau, e.g. Bedau, 2002).
Fodor J. 1974. Special sciences (or: the disunity of science as
Johnson’s (2010) figure 2 presents a standard cellular
a working hypothesis). Synthese 28: 97–115.
automaton, and argues that we cannot predict the
© 2013 The Linnean Society of London, Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, 2014, 112, 261–267
PRIMER ON EMERGENCE 267
and nurture. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Schmalhausen II. 1949. Factors of evolution. The theory of
Press. stabilizing selection. Philadelphia, PA: Blakiston.
Pigliucci M. 2008. Is evolvability evolvable? Nature Reviews Vidal M, Cusick ME, Barabási AL. 2011. Interactome
Genetics 9: 75–82. networks and human disease. Cell 144: 986–998.
Romero D, Zertuche F. 2007. Number of different binary Waddington CH. 1942. Canalization of development and the
functions generated by NK-Kauffman networks and the inheritance of acquired characters. Nature 150: 563–565.
emergence of genetic robustness. Journal of Mathematical Weinberg S. 1992. Dreams of a final theory. New York:
Physics 48: 083506. [11 pages]. Pantheon.
© 2013 The Linnean Society of London, Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, 2014, 112, 261–267