1992 Postexistentialism in The Neo Gothic Mode of Anne Rice
1992 Postexistentialism in The Neo Gothic Mode of Anne Rice
1992 Postexistentialism in The Neo Gothic Mode of Anne Rice
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
University of Manitoba is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
Mosaic: An Interdisciplinary Critical Journal
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Postexistentialism in the
Neo-Gothic Mode: Anne Rice's
Interview with the Vampire
Mosaic 25/3
0027-1276-92/010079-19$01,50©Mosaic
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
80 Barbara Frey Waxman
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vampires and Ethics 81
Pilate, 'What is truth?' but the oracle that was so eloquent one moment, is
dumb the next, or if it answers, it is with that ambiguity that makes us dread
we have to consult again—again—and for ever—in vain" (64).
Despite Melmoth's blasting of humankind for its "malignity and hostil
ity" (236), Maturin's narrator hopes to establish a moral framework for the
world: "Such, perhaps, will be the development of the moral world. We
shall be told why we suffered, and for what; but a bright and blessed lustre
shall follow the storm, and all shall yet be light" (248). Although this
passage sounds optimistic, light and certitude do not prevail in Maturin's
novel. As Elizabeth R. Napier has observed, in works like Melmoth the
Wanderer we experience the existentialist quester's "exhaustion at being
tantalized by meaning and finally being denied it" (52, 149).
The prefiguring of existentialism in Melmoth is apparent not only in the
novel's quest motif, but also in its emphasis on issues of entrapment, escape
and individual moral agency. Such issues, within a Christian framework,
are raised in Moncada's tale of his imprisonment in the monastery and his
escape with the aid of his brother and a man who had committed parricide.
Moncada describes the pressure of moral responsibility and our occasional
desire to relinquish it: "I was like a clock whose hands are pushed forward,
and I struck the hours I was impelled to strike. When a powerful agency is
thus exercised on us,—when another undertakes to think, feel, and act for
us, we are delighted to transfer to him, not only our physical, but our moral
responsibility. We say, with selfish cowardice, and self-flattering passive
ness, 'Be it so—you have decided for me,'—without reflecting that at the
bar of God there is no bail" (141).
The will to freedom and Immalee's choice to wed Melmoth are also
analyzed existentially by the narrator of Immalee's tale: "When a mind
strong by nature, but weakened by fettering circumstances, is driven to
make one strong spring to free itself, it has no leisure to calculate the weight
of its hindrances, or the width of its leap,—it sits with its chains heaped
about it, thinking only of the bound that is to be its liberation—" (295).
Maturin ponders the individual's capacity for moral choices while being
hampered by vices that can turn her/him into Satan's agent: he concludes
bleakly that we are our own worst enemies (334).
Victor Frankenstein, protagonist of Mary Shelley's classic Gothic novel,
is another Romantic quester, the personification of the scientific researcher
hero who seeks knowledge about human existence, answers to ontological
questions and understanding of our moral nature. Although he thinks that by
creating human life he has found one answer, the result is that he is left with
more problems, with "pain, No Exit, and damnation." Even family ties as
a source of meaningful existence, the spiritual satisfactions of nature, ro
mantic love and domestic happiness are interrogated by Shelley: none offer
Victor permanent solace or refuge in his morally ambiguous, post-creature
world. The frozen wastelands of the North are a fit emblem of the existen
tial void surrounding Victor at the end of his life.
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
82 Barbara Frey Waxman
Concern with moral choice and speculation about the nature and origins
of evil are also evident in Bram Stoker's vampiric Gothic novel Dracula.
Through the character of Professor Van Heising, who has analyzed the
facets of evil, Stoker suggests that evil is not an isolatable force, but is
inextricably linked to good. The two moral absolutes, as bipolar opposites,
define each other, according to Van Heising: "For it is not the least of its
terrors that this evil thing [Dracula] is rooted deep in all good; in soil barren
of holy memories it cannot rest" (247). Van Heising postulates that evil
originates in good, that it develops as a radical rebellion against goodness.
Stoker implies that Dracula could not have seduced the virtuous Lucy were
it not for the lustful impulses growing in the soil of her virtuous soul.
Conversely, Dracula himself might have had some "training" in good that
led to his rebellious alienation or satanic leap into the realm of evil.
Dracula moves beyond Maturin's and Shelley's existential concerns by
blending "modern" scientific thinking with theology in the moral project of
Van Heising. By focusing on the seductive nature of evil and the human
psyche's vulnerability to it, Dracula offers a quasi-Freudian investigation
of the way that the amoral human unconscious and its pleasure-seeking
impulses conflict with societal taboos and moral codes. With its interweav
ing of good and evil, and in its illustration of the amoral nature of human
sexuality in a world no longer supported by a framework of faith, Stoker's
novel heralds the perspective of a twentieth-century existentialist.
Like Stoker, Shelley, Maturin and other Romantic writers, Anne Rice
embraces the Gothic, and in particular the vampire, as a vehicle for philo
sophic speculation. While vampires have historically been considered an
image "of anthropomorphized evil" (Thompson 6), Rice's vampires become
what Susan Ferraro calls "loquacious philosophers who spend much of
eternity debating the nature of good and evil" (67). They are also vehicles
to explore the tabula rasa condition of twentieth-century human existence,
as well as the quest for truths, moral rules and a purposeful existence.
Interview with the Vampire is structured in four parts, beginning and
ending as an interview between a young journalist and the vampire Louis,
set in New Orleans in the present (1970s). In the middle sections, Louis
mostly narrates his past, with questions and reactions occasionally inter
jected by the journalist. The interview is being recorded on a cassette
player, as Louis describes how he became a vampire in 1791 at the age of
25 and how he developed relationships with other vampires, particularly
Lestat, his maker, and Claudia, the child-vampire whom he and Lestat have
created. The plot offers traditional Gothic love triangles and power struggles,
as in Louis's alliance with Claudia to "kill" Lestat and rid themselves of his
domination, and in Claudia's withdrawal from Louis to be with Madeleine,
the vampire that Louis had created for her. After the "death" of Lestat, the
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vampires and Ethics 83
scene shifts to Paris, home of an old "coven" of vampires, the Théâtre des
Vampires.
In the Théâtre lives an ancient vampire, Armand, to whom Louis is
attracted mentally and physically: as is typical of Gothic fiction, incest and
homoeroticism are prominent in the book. Armand acts as his teacher,
warning Louis against killing the other vampires. Despite his wisdom,
Armand's world-weariness pushes Louis toward desperate action, a war
with the Theatre des Vampires in which Louis is imprisoned (the conven
tional entrapment imagery). He is rescued by Armand. Claudia is burnt to
ashes in these wars, Louis torches the Théâtre, and Lestat returns from the
"undead," seeking reunion. Finally, Louis and Armand, now outcasts from
vampiric society, return to New Orleans. At the end of the novel, despite
having learned of Louis's ordeals as a vampire, the young interviewer asks
to be turned into a vampire and to join the search for Lestat.
In many respects Interview—despite or by way of its popular Gothic plot
of power struggles—contains Rice's most complete existentialist and
postexistentialist philosophizing. Ferraro captures its philosophical spirit
when she calls it "a brooding meditation on good and evil, immortality and
death" (28). According to Ferraro, the novel's comparison of mortal death
to versions of immortality implies that sometimes mortal death is preferable
(74). This may be because of Rice's view of the prevalence of human evil
in her godless world. Her parallelling of evil vampirism with immoral
human behavior is suggested when one of the Parisian vampires declares
that "men [are] capable of far greater evil than vampires," but that vampires
"strive to rival men in kills of all kinds" (245). In the aftermath of the Nazi
Holocaust, which has greatly expanded philosophy's and literature's con
ceptualizing of human evil, this statement is acceptable to many thoughtful
readers. With evil a given, then, Rice offers existentialist paths to meaning
ful action. She also posits some postexistentialist conditions and ideas
about moral choice.
In his study of Melmoth the Wanderer, Hennelly has observed that
existentialism comes in many varieties, but in all of them there is a "revolt
against any authority—Church, State, Society—that places a synthetic,
abstract system between the individual and real life experience" (669). In
other words, he sees the existentialist, isolated from all institutions, as
confronting a universe devoid of moral absolutes, where the individual
must construct his/her own system of authority. The existentialist's "onto
logical insecurity" is an angst about the universe's "relativism, meaning
lessness, and even nihilism" (671).
There is, however, a component of existentialism that pulls the indi
vidual back from the edge of suicidal despair: the freedom of choice and the
ethic of responsibility. These empower one to choose actions, to shape a
meaningful moral life, to judge oneself, and to take responsibility for the
consequences of one's actions. The difference between existentialism and
postexistentialism, as I use the terms, is that the postexistentialist cynically
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
84 Barbara Frey Waxman
notes the relativity not only of morality, but also of freedom and choice.
Postexistentialism recognizes that there are internal and external constraints
on the individual's ability to build a good life. The vampire Louis is like
that still-hopeful existentialist who must confront the compelling
postexistentialist outlook which fears that freedom itself may be a chimera.
Rice's novel places Louis in a life which Kierkegaard would identify as
pure existence. Helmut Kuhn describes this rarified existence as "that
passionately intensified form of human life which makes the mind suscep
tible to experiencing a crisis, and through crisis, existence" (409). Rice
explores the complexities of human nature by analyzing Louis's life-crisis
and by highlighting his differences from humans. As Elizabeth MacAndrew
has noted, Rice's novel "uses the supernatural, as the Gothic tradition has
always done, to present new views of human nature ambiguously, so we are
forced to ask questions about it" (250).
Rice's novel is unique, however, because in it the vampire's conduct is
self-condemned. Even after rejecting God's law, Louis accepts responsibil
ity for the consequences of his evil acts, includ' ig his killings. He sees his
evil conduct as resembling Sartre's acts of "bad faith," behaviors whereby
the existentialist "lapses" and temporarily rejects both responsibility for
acts and freedom of choice. In other words, when he kills, Louis tempo
rarily believes that his vampiric nature forces him to kill; after the kill, he
struggles against any notion of having a fixed nature that dictates his
conduct and thus reaffirms his moral responsibility. In addition, Louis is
repelled by his objectification of each victim as Other and by his efforts to
make his victims' surrender of their freedom the means by which he fulfills
his own goals.
Persistent in spite of his compulsion to kill, then, is Louis's urge to
embrace ethical behavior, which according to philosopher Hazel E. Barnes
involves "recognition of the need to justify one's life" (9), as well as
acceptance of "responsibility for others and for one's own past and future"
(25). Louis's ethical stance provokes the derision of Lestat and Claudia,
who revel in their killings. His alienation from them by these moral promptings
suggests the existentialist's condition; "an isolated individual," he "is not
compelled to acknowledge his involvement with others unless he cares to
do so" (Barnes 51). Suffering from this loneliness, Louis parries his ethics
and does seek reunion with them, despite their egocentrism and amorality.
Through Louis, Rice's novel displays a twentieth-century ethical relativ
ism more complex than Stoker's. Presenting the vampire as a metaphor for
the ambiguities of human nature and of our moral energies, Rice extends
Stoker's notion that evil is rooted in good; as she presents it, evil encom
passes a profound knowledge of and longing for good. Interview thus
explores what Judith Wilt describes as the "tempting proposition that the
killer obtains special knowledge and special sensitivity to life, and the
vampire, whose life is death, has supreme comprehension and sensitivity"
(90). Rice gives this proposition an existentialist framework by positing
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vampires and Ethics 85
that the morally sensitive Louis lacks supreme comprehension of the mean
ing of his life, even as he struggles to obtain gnosis or to create an expla
nation for his existence. Rice's postexistentialist addendum is to emphasize
the naivete of the existentialist assumption that one can obtain supreme
comprehension and shape his/her own fate.
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
86 Barbara Frey Waxman
Christian belief remaining in him, then, Louis feels guilty about his ego
tism. In turn, as his existential outlook develops, he views with alarm
Lestat's ego-crushing impact on him, the existentialist equivalent of a
cardinal sin: Lestat objectifies Louis (the Other) and makes of Louis's
freedom "the instrument of [his] own project" (Barnes 87-88). Lestat's
egocentric project is to turn Louis into a vampire, even if he does not freely
choose to become one, in order to secure Louis's plantation for his ailing
father.
Looking back on his transformation from man into vampire, Louis can
not say how or whether he decided on this fateful step in his life. The
ambiguity of his language reflects his crushed ego, his repressed self
consciousness, his confusion about the determining factors behind this
choice, all of which traits are uncharacteristic of the existentialist:
Katherine R
pursued by
not consciou
Thus, while
ties for exi
nism for a
freedom.
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vampires and Ethics 87
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
88 Barbara Frey Waxman
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vampires and Ethics 89
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
90 Barbara Frey Waxman
phers like Rorty point out the parasitical nature of human life and its
incapacity to be independently willed: "one may say that there can be no
fully Nietzschean lives, lives which are pure action rather than reaction, no
lives which are not largely parasitical on an un-redescribed past and depen
dent on the charity of unborn generations" (42). Confused in his definition
of human nature, yet yearning to be human, Louis experiences an identity
crisis which puts him in what Karl Jaspers calls a "boundary situation," an
intense, unchangeable situation—such as endurance of suffering or guilt—
that we "cannot see through as a whole" and that we can avoid "only by
closing our eyes to [it]"; boundary situations are "like a wall we run into,
a wall on which we founder. We cannot modify them; all that we can do is
to make them lucid" (178-80). In his boundary situation, Louis accepts
responsibility for being a flawed vampire because he thinks and feels too
much; he is too human (254).
His human longings draw Louis to human culture and specifically to the
arts because they promise him "a deeper understanding of the human heart"
(321). Like Sartre, who in his earlier years was drawn to a literature yoked
to ethics (Barnes 39-40), Louis turns to the young journalist to help him
shape his life's story and extrapolate its moral significance. According to
Paul Jude Beauvais, Sartre sees the writer as "a unique volitional agent"
who dwells in a particular historical context and who desires to observe and
record his or her life and times; Sartre's writer is also shaped by member
ship in a social class (19, 20). Thus the writer embodies both existential
possibility and the prison of circumstances, a combination that reflects
Louis's existential/postexistential conflict and explains his attraction to the
journalist. As he speaks to the young writer, the otherness of Louis is
dispelled. MacAndrew has observed that this narrative arrangement encour
ages readers to give "imaginative assent" to the vampire's tale "of passions
that we can recognize" (249-50), to identify with Louis as if he were a
human being.
Louis also turns to other human arts, especially drama, when he visits the
Théâtre des Vampires in Paris. It is fitting that Rice brings Louis on a
pilgrimage to Paris, a major center both of art and of existentialist thought,
to seek justification of his existence. Although Louis kills, one of the few
acts that even Sartre would see as irredeemably evil, he still maintains this
human cultural framework, which encourages him to hope in his future
goodness. Surely goodness can grow in this rich soil, even though it has
been sown with the vampire's evil. Rice, until near the end of the novel,
leads readers to believe, with Louis, in such a possibility.
This possibility seems especially viable when readers consider the third
aspect of Rice's novel: the concepts of community and love, vampiric and
human, that Louis affirms and seeks. As MacAndrew points out, Rice
"explores the forms of human love and the nature of its relationships"
through Louis and the others (249). Ramsland also notes that through Louis
she depicts "the impetus in the human heart to seek others" (172). In
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vampires and Ethics 91
contrast to Stoker's Dracula, whom Wilt calls an isolato (87), Louis actively
seeks to end his painful isolation, the given condition of the existentialist.
He forges relationships, although ultimately unsatisfactory ones, first with
the woman Babette, then with Claudia, and finally with Armand. He also
experiences community both when he and Lestat live with Claudia, a curi
ously incestuous triangle, and when Madeleine forms a new triangle with
Claudia and Louis. Finally, he visits the vampire "commune" in Paris,
which enacts the negative traits of the extended nuclear family: unified by
kinship and conformity, it is also ravaged by jealousy, mistrust and power
struggles.
As Hennelly notes in his study of Melmoth, alienation and the failure of
love are common existential themes in Gothic literature: "Love does not
usually provide the needed release from the universal Angst-, rather it frus
tratingly highlights the failure of real communication" (674). His words
would also apply to the love life of Louis, on which he had hoped to build
a life of goodness. The frustration and disillusionment about love which
Hennelly describes become Louis's postexistential condition.
Louis's loneliness is most alleviated by Armand, for whom he feels a
deepening love: "it was as if the great feminine longing of my mind were
being awakened again to be satisfied" (237). Later he says, "I felt a longing
for him so strong that it took all my strength to contain it" (256). While Rice
uses sexual language to describe this love, sexual passion may also be a
metaphor for Louis's impassioned philosophical and intellectual searching:
he feels the deep love and admiration of an apprentice-philosopher for a
wise master and his stores of knowledge. For this love, however, Claudia
and Madeleine must eventually be sacrificed. This love between vam
pires—a reflection of love between human beings—can destroy those who
experience it. So-called humanizing love becomes the impetus for inhuman
ity, for acts of existential bad faith, for murder. All that the wise Armand
can, ultimately, teach Louis is the complexity of evil, just as Rice leads us
to realize that no good can emerge from the vampire.
Despite his initial hopes and longings, then, Louis finally confronts the
nothingness of the universe. When his relationship with Armand fails,
Louis understands that he is alone. His intention of creating a valuable
pattern for his life, which had included loving relationships, has not been
fulfilled; so, as Barnes would conclude, his existence has not been "worth
while" (107). He recognizes that he will never "grow warm again and filled
with love" (339). There comes a Kierkegaardian moment of "generalized
dread...of nothing in particular...[of] this nothing, this void we confront"
(Maclntyre 149). Then he takes up the vampire's stoic detachment, reject
ing the option of reaching out to others in love. He acknowledges his
postexistential condition, letting his vampirism now dictate his actions.
Louis's last hope is in reaching out, not in love but in despair, to the
journalist who might be able to make meaning out of his life's story for
other human beings. By speaking to the journalist, Louis hopes to warn
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
92 Barbara Frey Waxman
humans not to seek the eternal life of the vampire and to dispel the illusion
that they are free to shape their own destinies and to eschew evil. This
reaching out to the young writer also fails, it may be argued, since the
journalist's response to the story is to ask to be turned into a vampire too.
He would not have made this request if he had really understood Louis's
portrayal of the vampire's enslavement to his own nature.
Love and community have actually been Louis's downfall, not his salva
tion. Formerly Louis had mirrored the Victorian age in which he was born,
an age, Walter Houghton has observed, that replaced God with love as the
source of salvation. Louis had looked to love with great hope. Now, how
ever, having seen into the essence of love, he experiences a crushing fall
from "grace and faith [that] is the fall of a century" (288). This fall propels
him, philosophically speaking, into the postmodern world, where Rice
destabilizes Louis's and readers' usual categories of good and evil by
aligning love with eternal damnation.
Just before her death, Claudia is clear-eyed about the love between
vampires—love among the ruins of a moral structure. She teaches Louis
about vampiric love's quintessential evil, and he gives it a philosophical
dimension: "that is the crowning evil, that we can even go so far as to love
each other...and who else would show us a particle of love, a particle of
compassion or mercy? Who else, knowing us as we know each other, could
do anything but destroy us?" (319). As one vampire peers into the soul of
another, he sees absolute evil and, if ethically motivated like Louis, he must
judge that soul as harshly as he judges himself. Barnes says of the existentialist's
vision, "my own judgments cannot move outward without an accompanying
inward movement. Consequently, I am always before the Bench. The eye of
Judgment is ever there" (78). Louis has, nevertheless, loved two vampires,
thereby denying his ability to judge himself or others and surrendering his
power to choose what is good over what is evil. Such postexistentialist
moral tolerance, needed for vampires' love, is defined by Claudia and Louis
as the vampires' permanently damning evil: it seems inhuman, a tolerance
of which humans would be incapable.
Or would they? Readers of Rice's novel have been drawn into this
postmodern world of the vampire so powerfully and have had their simplis
tic moral sensibilities so thoroughly "drained" that in their disorientation
they might be receptive to new objects of love and compassion, open to
more complex categorizings of good and evil and to new ways of explaining
the universe. Through the interview format, Rice has swayed us to suspend
our aversion toward the vampire, and in so doing leads us to question
assumptions about human nature and to re-envision the repositories of good
and evil in the world. Moreover, because Rice morally energizes the vam
pire Louis, we are inclined to reject the traditional compartmentalizing of
good and evil. Louis emerges as an appealing, remorseful, though obses
sive, killer: his obsessive need to kill makes him a victim of his nature, but
he struggles against this restriction of his freedom.
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vampires and Ethics 93
Rice's later vampiric fiction reveals the consistency of her interest in the
major philosophical questions of modern and postmodern times. In The
Vampire Lestat, especially, the protagonist from the beginning is a vampire
with a conscience, repelled by "the stories of the ugly nihilistic men of the
twentieth-century" (509) and seeking guidelines for moral choices, even in
selecting for his kills only remorseless evildoers. As Lestat's mentor the
ancient vampire Marius says, even seventeen hundred years ago vampires
were "questing...rejecting the answers given us"; but Lestat is unique
among mortals and immortals in his commitment to the quest for knowl
edge: "To really ask is to open the door to the whirlwind....But you have
been truly asking" (380). Lestat, decrying the placelessness of the vampire's
evil nature and actions in the world, moves beyond the despairing conclu
sion of Rice's earlier novel. He finds a function for his evil condition,
which is to create "the art that repudiates evil," the music of rock stars that
"dramatize[s] the battles against evil that each mortal fights within himself'
(10). Louis had had hopes for the efficacy of art, but his hopes had been
dashed by the failure of his relationship with Armand.
Through art and beauty Lestat in Rice's second novel takes up where
Louis leaves off. The work begins with his despairing observation that on
their deathbed people "probably don't find out the answer as to why [they]
were ever alive... .We pass into nonexistence without ever knowing a thing"
(55). Then, however, he turns to the beauty that humankind creates, culti
vating an amoral wilderness that he calls the Savage Garden, " an uncharted
land where one could make a thousand fatal errors, a wild and indifferent
paradise without signposts of evil or good" (131). He suggests that mean
ings and guiding laws, derived from the esthetic, do exist (143). The Master
painter-vampire Marius becomes his role model, because Marius "found a
way to imitate mortal life....He created good things...he believed more in
the vistas of heaven that he painted than in himself' (310). Both Lestat and
Marius believe in the beauty and goodness of the world, and Lestat admires
Marius's efforts to stem the chaos that threatens to destroy the world: as he
sees it, this is a way for a vampire to achieve some good—to become a little
more lovable (335).
Lestat's amoral esthetic framework has a drawback, however: it encour
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
94 Barbara Frey Waxman
ages the Théâtre of the Vampires in Paris to "make a mockery of all things
sacred" (265) and it sanctions Lestat's plan to wage war against mortals as
the novel ends. Lestat uses his "Satanic powers to simulate the actions of
a good man!" In other words, Lestat has the moral conscience of an exis
tentialist, but he redefines the conscience as something that prompts the
individual to do whatever he or she wants. Since art has limited redemptive
force, Lestat also considers the salvational powers of love. Like some of
Rice's other vampires, he believes in and longs for love, even while declar
ing that "it's a concept born out of moral idiocy, this idea of love!" (231).
A vampire seeks companionship and love because he cannot stand being
alone as a killer (425), because he cannot accommodate death easily or
name a place for evil in the world (446). Yet even with his impulse for love
and goodness fighting his evil instincts, he emerges at the end of the novel
without a system of ethics and, like Louis, with a postexistentialist sense
that his freedom to choose is circumscribed by his thirst for blood and the
vagaries of history. In her second novel Rice is more optimistic about the
value of art and love than in the first novel, but she still does not fully trust
that they will offer a meaningful life.
Lestat, nevertheless, continues his existential quest and asserts his free
dom to break the rules of vampires; as Ferraro has observed, "in Lestat's
search for the meaning of existence, he gleefully breaks them all" (28).
There is a comedic quality to his outlook that is missing from Louis's view.
Even though Lestat knows that vampires, like mortals, are "prisoners of
circumstance" (Ferraro 67), he is not as burdened by such knowledge as
Louis had been. With a satirist's humor, he describes his mission to create
new evil in rock music, with its "images of evil, not evil...[its] image of
death, not death": "So let us take on a new meaning...I crave the divine
visibility. I crave war [with mortals]...the new evil...the twentieth-century
evil" (531). In seeing evil as shaped by the historical moment that makes
rock music its fit vehicle, Lestat mirrors Sartre's post-World War II blend
of Marxism and existentialism which, as Beauvais has observed, leaves "a
margin of freedom...for individuals to act in ways that contradict their
social conditioning"; Beauvais suggests that for Sartre, "self and society are
mutually determining: history makes man, but man makes history" (13, 14).
More than Louis, Lestat in Rice's second novel persists in his existentialist
quest, despite his postexistentialist recognition of constraints.
Whatever tentative conclusions Lestat reaches at the end of his tale about
the conditions of individual freedom, purposes of evil, and influences of
history on existence, the vampiric quest for meaning and philosophical
questioning continues in the ensuing Vampire Chronicles. In Rice's 1988
novel, The Queen of the Damned, which revisits the power struggles of the
vampires and depicts Queen Akasha's efforts to defeat Lestat, Ramsland
observes the existentialist concern with "'paradox, free will, personal choice'"
(qtd. in Ferraro 67). Moreover, Rice's metaphysical speculations are even
present in her nonvampiric erotic novels, such as Exit to Eden (1985) and
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vampires and Ethics 95
Belinda (1986), written under the pen name of Anne Rampling, and The
Claiming of Sleeping Beauty (1983), written under the name A.N. Roquelaure.
In these works Rice uses a less supernatural but still fantastical medium and
continues to explore issues of freedom and moral choice. Indeed, in these
works, she suggests that intimate sexual relations and vampirism have many
things in common.
In Exit to Eden, for example, instead of describing vampires who create
and possess mortals through the Dark Trick, Rice depicts mortals who
possess one another by fuelling sexual fantasies and desires and who obtain
sexual fulfillment through pain and pleasure. A sadomasochistic fantasy
island of the Club-Med variety is the site of the elaborate slave/master sex
games that transform patrons and employees of the Club into uncivilized,
almost supernatural, creatures. Like the vampires who feel their victims'
hearts beating as they suck their blood, the participants in the Club's
sadomasochistic rituals experience an intimacy in which "you reached out
and touched the beating heart of the person" (13).
This context prompts the "head sex-manager" Lisa to question her own
morality and the objectives of the other island "professionals," as well as to
explore philosophical alienation and the degree of freedom available to the
individual. Lisa confesses to having felt like a freak, a sexual outlaw, as a
younger woman because of her sexual feelings and fantasies. Every bit as
lost and marginalized as Rice's vampires, Lisa suggests that perhaps "we are
all outsiders, we are all making our own unusual way through a wilderness
of normality that is just a myth" (6). Questioning her mentor Martin about
her creation of an "Outsider Heaven" on the island, she echoes the questions
about identity and earthly purpose raised by vampires and existentialists: "Is
what we do right, Martin? Or is it evil? Are we the good thing that we tell
ourselves we are, are we the healthy thing we say we are to others? Or are
we some evil, twisted thing that never should come to be?" (278). The
tentative conclusion she reaches before the book's romantic, love-affirming
ending is that by channeling aggressive, violent feelings into harmless sexual
fantasizing and game-playing, the Club people may save the world from war.
Lisa's quest leading to this conclusion begins with an episode that sug
gests the existentialist's sensation of exile, fear of the borders of freedom,
and interrogation of the meaning of work and life. Returning from a vaca
tion, Lisa's plane has to circle for a long time before landing; that is, she
has psychic and literal difficulty re-entering the island—"no entry" instead
of "no exit"—and feels as if she is experiencing "an existentialist play.
There is my world down there but I cannot get into it. Maybe it is all
something I've imagined" (12). As the narrative progresses, however, the
nightmare recedes. The search for love by Lisa and her lover Elliott recalls
the yearning for companionship of Louis, Lestat and Armand; their explo
ration of freedom is similar to the rebellious paths that were taken by Louis
(as autobiographer) and Lestat (as rock star). Whereas the vampires failed
in their quest, however, Lisa and Elliott ultimately succeed.
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
96 Barbara Frey Waxman
WORKS CITED
Ferraro, Susan. "Novels You Can Sink Your Teeth Into." New York Times Magazine (14 Oct.
1990): 27-28.
Hennelly, Mark M., Jr. "Melmoth the Wanderer and Gothic Existentialism." Studies in
English Literature 21.4 (1981): 665-79.
Houghton, Walter E. The Victorian Frame of Mind. New Haven: Yale UP, 1957.
Hume, Robert D. "Exuberant Gloom, Existential Agony, and Heroic Despair: Three Variet
ies of Negative Romanticism." Thompson 109-27.
Jaspers, Karl. Philosophy. Vol. 2. 1932. Trans. E.B. Ashton. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1970.
Kuhn, Helmut. "Existentialism." A History of Philosophical Systems. Ed. Vergilius Ferm.
New York: The Philosophical Library, 1950. 405-17.
MacAndrew, Elizabeth. The Gothic Tradition in Fiction. New York: Columbia UP, 1979.
Maturin, Charles. Melmoth the Wanderer. 1820. Intro, by William F. Axton. Lincoln: U
Nebraska P, 1961.
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. Adventures of the Dialectic. Trans. Joseph Bien. Evanston, IL:
Northwestern UP, 1973.
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Vampires and Ethics 97
Ramsland, Katherine. Prism of the Night: A Biography of Anne Rice. New York: Dutton,
1991.
Rice, Anne [Anne Rampling], Exit to Eden. New York: Dell, 1986.
Interview with the Vampire. New York: Ballantine, 1976.
"A Talk with Anne Rice." Interview by Charles Winecoff. Book of the Month
Club News (Dec. 1990): 11.
The Vampire Lestat. New York: Ballantine, 1986.
Rorty, Richard. Contingency, Irony and Solidarity. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1989.
Shelley, Mary. Frankenstein. 1816. New York: Signet, 1965.
Stoker, Bram. Dracula. 1897. New York: New American Library, 1965.
Thompson, G.R. "Introduction: Romanticism and the Gothic Tradition." The Gothic Imagi
nation: Essays in Dark Romanticism. Pullman: Washington State UP, 1974.
Wilt, Judith. Ghosts of the Gothic. Princeton: Princeton UP, 1980.
This content downloaded from 75.110.234.29 on Thu, 16 Apr 2020 03:43:18 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms