Vollenhoven Reader
Vollenhoven Reader
Vollenhoven Reader
CHAPTERI
WHAT IS CALVINISM?
(33a22]
CHAPTERII
ee
‘A
! understand by scriptural philosophy a philosophic basic conception orp
that continually reckons with Holy Scripture.
This is not to say that advocates of scriptural philosophy may content
themselves with studying the Bible. They too will have to depend on much
more than just Scripture. For example, those who want to devote them-
selves to christian political activity ought to know the contemporary political
situation, nationally and internationally. This knowledge cannot be derived
exclusively from Holy Scripture. And even those who want to know what
the situation is as far as the church is concerned, neglect the study of books,
magazines, and newspapers only to their own detriment. The term “scrip-
tural" only means to say that the philosophy that values this predicate con-
tinually reckons seriously with Holy Scripture, yes, does this to such an ex-
tent that it relies on Scripture, in other words, is in line with Scripture.
Whensetting forth its basic themes, then, this philosophy can also duly
link up with the calvinian answer to the question as to the main content of
Holy Scripture.
However, in order to exclude any misunderstanding—ambiguous ter-
minclogy should above all be avoided—I will include a few comments still
on the chosen formulation. Generally speaking they can be brief, except for
the first remarks which require some more depth. [/33a23]
A.
Scripturalphilosophy teaches the direct sovereignty of God, who has
revealed himself in his word, over all things, no matter in what area and in
what connection, and, in like manner, clearlydistinguishes between Godas
Sovereign and that which he has created.
1. The qualification who has revealed himself in his word is far from
superfluous. There is no word that philosophy has tossed about and played
with more than the word "god." Sometimes it's been used to indicate a cer-
tain primeval unity, at other times, God was said to be identical with pure
form. Especially in the Middle Ages, when many Christians set themselves
to the task of combining heathen and scriptural thought, sin abounded on
Draft ® JHK Translation Page 31
Calvinism and the Reformation of Philosophy
this score. That is why I state with emphasis: if people think they have to
endorse a conception about God in their philosophy, other than what Scrip-
ture teaches us, then this “god” is not the God of Scripture, and their philos-
ophy is not calvinian.
2. On the basis of this word revelation scriptural philosophy accepts
that God created heaven and earth and since then bears them by the word of
his power. Hence, following Scripture, it honors only him as the jinn basis
of everything and sharply distinguishes him from the things invisible and
visible in heaven and on earth that rest uponthis “basis.”
3. In the third place: What is sovereignty? The answerto this ques-
tion can be clarified by referring to the [/33a24) relationship of an absolute
monarch to his subjects. This relationship is to be rejected when it occurs
among men; rooted as it is in a conception that deifies the monarch, either
because he is looked upon as the creator of the state or as the son of the na-
tional deity. Such a human sovereign formulates a law and considers him-
self to be elevated above the law, But God indeed created the entire cosmos
and indeed placed it under his commands.
This is also why we can indicate the [grens] demarcation or line be-
tween God and cosmos.
It could very well be that the word “line” at first does not seem very
appropriate. This term can call to mind something spatial: e.g. in the sense
that a circle divides a plane into two parts, its circumference being the
boundary between thepart that is enclosed and that which is not. In the pre-
sent context, the words "limit" or “line” when used in this spatial sense are
obviously contraband. For the line between God and cosmos cannot, of
course, be spatial. That which is spatial itself belongs to that which is cre-
ated and a spatial boundary can therefore only mark off something in the
cosmos from somethingelse in the same cosmos, such that thelatter lies our-
side the former. But whoever thinks that God stood outside the cosmos
could notdo justice to the confession of his immanence.
Yet the term “grens" can most certainly be used here. This word has
another meaning as well. Used in that sense, it denotes the "x" that makes a
clear distinction possible, without suggesting anything spatial. We can
speak ofa line or limit in this second sense when,of the two wedistinguish,
the one lies entirely on this side and the other entirely on that side of the
said limit. The only thing to watch out for is this: that when determining
the line we reckon with the nature of the two that we want to distinguish.
Well, that happens also when we say: “The line between God and cosmosis
the law." For everything that stands above the law for the cosmos is
Sovereign over the cosmos, and this honor is due only to the God of
Draft D JHK Translaion Page 32
Calvinism and the Reformation of Philosophy
rooted in ordinances of God, but in each case these ordinances hold for a
specified area, and in so doingalso limitthe competence ofthis authority.
Nothing undermines the esteem for sanctioned authority, also in christian
circles, more than when those who bear this responsibility presume duties
and rights they don't have. That's why wesee little merit in any kind of re-
action againstKuyper’swork. Rather, his basic point deserves resolute af-
firmation.
But even this is not sufficient. In addition, it will need to be thought
through more thoroughly and applied where that hasn't happened yet.
First, as far as thinking through sphere sovereignty again, difficulties
have arisen, and continue to do so, {/33a28) because the term “sphere” has a
double meaning,* The first meaning has more to do with the difference be-
tween “the one” and "the other." The extent [grenzen] of this kind of sphere
can for the most part be defined spatially, in the sense that different munici-
palities, local churches, and the like, are found next to each other. This
criterion sometimes presented problems when people focused on the
[physical] extent or reach of the operation, but these problems usually can be
resolved by asking, "Where's the center?” Different departments of a mu-
nicipality ail work the same territory. But their headquarters differ. Even
though close cooperation will save a good deal of time and effort, people
also understand that, in cities of any size, the one workman will only obey
the instructions of this bureau and another only the work orders coming
from thatoffice.
When we're looking at the demarcation between different functions,
each of which is tied to different laws and hence lies in different law
spheres, things are completely different. The line between the two functions
of a man whois both father and foreman is not marked by the threshold
between his house and the firm. He's still husband and father when he takes V
his wife and children to see the company's new line of products. And when
the brief case is open on the dining room table and he's bent over his books,
he is obviously busy as foreman.
Those who remember the difficulties that arose around the discussion
of the “bakers' law" will readily agree that the answer to the question "What
is a sphere?" does become clearer when people keep this difference between
kinds of spheres in mind. It's a distinction that can have very practical con-
sequences.
What can we say about applying this thought to relatively new terri-
tory? People don't have to go to college to know the things I've been dis-
cussing. Abraham Kuyper often found listening ear for the distinctions he
3H. Driesch, Wissen und Denken, ein Prolegomenon zu aller Philosophie (Leipzig:
E. Reinicke, 1919) 16-18.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 36
Calvinism and the Reformation of Philosophy
was not going to work? And even when people have te acknowledge some
kind of functional diversity, that old audacity keeps coming back. They do
not expect any more surprises. Should they happen upon a set of distinct
functions, they right away try to arrange this diversity within the categories
they already have. In Babylon we find the astrologer distinguishing the spa-
tial field and movement; a vitalist swears by the difference between the me-
chanical and the organic; others see only that emotional life is totaliy differ-
ent from organic life, which is a difference the Marburgers in turn misun-
derstand, such that they just as emphatically point to the fact that analysis
cannot be reduced to the emotions. This attitude naturally brings with it the |
problem that functions wrongly grouped under one of the two functions peo-
ple had correctly discerned were not distinguished clearly, the one from the
other. I have already referred to compressing the arithmetic with the spatial.
But it is also common knowledge that the Greek conception of logos was a
conflation of analysis and the lingual function, of thought and the statement,
from which analytics (“logic”) and linguistics are still reeling.
What must we think of this struggle? These tactics are sound to the
extent they have indeed discerned a difference in function. Movement can-
noi be subsumed under space nor can the organic be included under move-
ment. Emotional life is truly something other than organic life, just as the
analytic differs from the emotional. The creation is like a book written by
God, and all such domains are distinguished as so many chapters in this
book. But precisely because each of these thinkers is correct to the extent
each of them found difference that can't be denied, all are also wrong the
moment[/33a31] each of them wants to force the wealth of diversity in its en-
lirety into the scheme of the one difference that, after falling into oblivion
during an earlier period, they fortunately found again, but at the same time
quite wrongly overestimate.
This is why, with an eye to the history of science, we claim for now to
be able to distinguish the following functions: the arithmetic, the spatial,
the physical (= energetic, this includes kinetic energy, to which classical
mechanics had limited itself}, the organic, the emotional or psychic, the an-
alytic or logical, the historic, the linguistic, the social, the economic, the
aesthetic, the juridic, the ethical, and the pistic function, All of these func-
tions, in the order given, are, as functions of things very closely connected
to one another, subjected to the laws of God that hold for them.
From the above we see that we have to distinguish law and order.
There is an order fo laws, just as there is an order to the functions. If we
equate order and law, we raise the possibility on all kinds of confusion.
Somewill conclude from the fact that onlyone order exists, that there is also
no more than one functional Jaw and that there is therefore no good reason
to distinguish the laws for the different functions. Others, proceeding from
Draft D JHK Translation Page 37
Calvinism and the Reformation of Philosophy
the diversity of functional laws, will conclude that there is a diversity of or-
dinances and will easily lose sight of the order of these laws. Still others
will equate one of the many laws with the one order and then cometo the
conclusion that outside the domain for which this law holds there is no or-
der.
Now that we have distinguished these functions, morelight falls on the
functional difference between things from different realms. Numbers, for
example, have only one subject function, the arithmetic; circles have two,
the arithmetic and the spatial; physical things are subject to three of these
laws, the arithmetic, the spatial, and the physical. A plant has one subject
function more than physical things, namely, the organic; an animal, one
more than a plant, namely the psychic; a human being, many more than an
animal, namely, the analytic, historic, linguistic, social, [/33a32] economic,
juridic, ethical, and pistic. Given their highest actual function, we can call a
stone a physical thing, a plant an organic thing or organism, and an animal a
psychic thing. I will talk about human beings in a moment.
6. The connections in the cosmos are no less important than the do-
mains that we haveto distinguish.
There are connections in one and the same thing (intra-individual) as
well as between different things (inter-individual}, These two kinds of con-
nection need to be clearly distinguished. That is why I will first deal with
them separately and then show how a thing can move from the one to the
other.
a, J] will take the intraindividual connection first and distinguish two
sorts: a connection between the successive states of one and the same thing
and a connection between a thing'sdifferent functionsinoneandthe same
State.
Let's begin with the second kind ofintraindividual connection. That a
connection exists between the functions of a thing in one and the same mo-
ment is news to no one. Just think of the connection between an organic in-
flammation and the pain that accompanies it in the emotional, or, reversing
things, the psychic pressures that coincide with economic instability. As
long as people know they are dealing here with one and the same thing, no
one is struck by these connections.
Difficulties first arise when people buy into the tendency of current
philosophy and consider the one thing to be the result of two pseudo-things.
I am obviously not criticizing the technical analysis of the chemist, for ex-
ample, who is able to resolve things composed of two or more other things
into their factors. The elements the chemist ends up with in this manner are
quite rightly called "things." They are both chemical elements and hence
belong to the same realm. They likewise have similar functions, namely, an
arithmetic, a spatial, and a physical function. Thesituation is completely
Draft © JHK Translation Page aT
Calvinism and the Reformation ofPhi geAT 3S"
for example, neces organs, but lack the sense organs, which they also
don’t need because they have no senses. In other words, we see in the
sense organs that the organic functioning of humans and animals is
adapted to their supra-organic existence, with this lower “anticipating”
the higher. On the otherside, the more complicated functions not only
rest on the less complex functions, but also always point back to these
as well, displaying what wecall “retrocipations."
Anticipations and retrocipations exist then by virtue of the verti-
cal connection of different functions in the same thing. This connection
must be clearly distinguishedfrom the horizontal interrelation be-
tween similar functions of different things. Butthen [giventhis verti-
cal connection] it is not permissible to split the plant into a stone and
an organic function, or the animal into an organism and a psychic
function, nor a human beingirintoananimalandasupra-animal part.
Draft © JHK Translation PapeAz
Calvinism and the Reformation of Philosophy
37
For functions are function”of things andpeople may not present a
group¢of these thing functions as though it were a thing. This is not to
deny the difference between body and soul, to which 1 will return’ op
Ao
ht
When people use the words "body" and "soul" scripturally, they are re-
ferring to a difference laid in human life by God. But this has nothing
to do with groups of functions that humansarbitrarily elevate into so-
called things, with the result that they then are stumpedto find the an-
swerto the obviously unsolvable puzzle of how it can be that two of
these pseudo-things nevertheless seem to be one! [/33a34]
Besides the connection we havejust discussed between the func-
tions of one thing, thereisanother connection that is also in-
traindividual: a thing, in allits functions, foes trough‘different states.
stand isolated from each other. If we from the present look back to-
ward the past, we discern that what comeslater lay,‘enclosed in what be lies/?
was earlier and came/from that. And yet the present couldn't have M2 comia/ 7
been predicted from the past,just as the future can't be predicted given
the present. This points to a unique connection between what's earlier
and what'slater. What'searlier apparently includes a myriad ofpossi-
People often deal with the interrelation between subject and ob-
ject only in their theory about knowledge. Butthat's not right. Even if
they avoid the mistake positivism makes and don't conceive the exis-
lence of objects as depending upon investigation, more than likely,
when objects have a place only in their theory of knowledge, they are
not distinguishing clearly enough between object and field of investig-
ation. That itself has dire consequences for science. The most impor- |
tant place in the field of investigation does not go to objects, but to the
subjects! Hence, people making this mistake run the risk of missing
what is most important in what they wantto investigate.
Whatis even worse, if that's possible, is what this mistake does to
objects. Nothing can become field of investigation without someone
to do the investigating, but whether something is an object does not
“ =
depend on whether or notit is being investigated.” It celebrates its of-
tenglorious existence as object completely independent of the question
of whether anyoneattends to it or not. For there are objects every-
~
where where[/3336] a lower function repeats itself in a higher one.
For example, points in space are the repetition of the discontinuous
nature of numbersin the spatial, which is itself continuous; there are
paths in the physical that thernselves do not move,but are “traced” by
moving things; so too, space, which is itself not euclidean, takes its cue
in the physical as perceptual space, which is euclidean; and the biotic
prickling of light repeats itself in the psychic as color. More examples:
a rose is an organic thing that neither thinks, enjoys, nor worries—as
Scripture says so tellingly of the lilies of the field, "they do not labor or
spin"—andit is distinguishable, andit can be appreciated aesthetically
and “priced" economically by a human being, also when there is no
one there to distinguish it from others, to enjoy its play of colors, or to
estimate its value.
c. Finally still, something regarding the transition of a thing from
an interindividual into an intraindividual connection and its converse.
Wefind thefirst transition both within the samerealm,e.g., when
connecting two chemicals into one, and between things from different
realms, e.g., the nourishment of plants with minerals, also of animals
with plants, and of human beings with all of these.
* (compare with Kalsbeek, p. 121 “None of these aspects can exist apart from
man who sees, analyzes, forms, appreciates, and causes justice to be done....
for when a thing is considered apart from the horizon of human experience
with its divesity of aspects, nothingis left of that thing.”]
Draft © JHK Translation Page 45 Y2a
Calvinism and the Reformation of Philosophy
There are, at the same time,also transitions that go in the reverse
direction. These we find, for example, in genetic connections, by
which J mean the evolving of the one thing out of one or more pre-ex-
isting things in the same realm.It should be obviousthat this evolving
is totally other than what the followers of the functionalistic evolution
theory taught, according to whom things with more functions could
arise outof things with fewer functions. The studyof the evolvingthat
actually takes place, stays far away from these speculations and only
examines whatit finds in the cosmos. Andthatis, as we said, only the
rise of one thing from another within the same realm. 1 will try to
clarify this evolving with a simple example: an electron that is emitted
from an atom [/33a37] to which it belonged earlier. We see that this
electron, which earlier stood in an intraindividual interrelation with
the other constituents of that atom, is now only connected interindi-
vidually. Things get a bit more complicated when the thing emitted
takes on an intraindividual interrelation with another thing with which
it previously was connected interindividually. This happens, for ex-
ample, with sexual reproduction in plants, animals, and human beings.
Only when people actually study the evolving that goes on, and
that's fortunately happening again, will it be possible to build up a de-
cent conceptof "kind." What goes by that nametodayis little more
than recorded similarities in the "form" [or morphology] of things.
This leaves peoplestill to argue over whether such a universal "form"
actually exists and can be used as a standard to decide when things
participate more or less in this form, or whether this universal form is 0
simply a product of the abstracting activity of our thinking. When
people apply thefirst option to the human race, they elevate their own
idealto the level of norm for others and then look down on those who
don't meet that norm. With the second option they end up with cos-
mopolitanism. How very different the conception of Holy Scripture,
which knows no “ideas"? and does not point in the direction of cos-
mopolitanism. Scripture teaches that all human beings are “of one
blood" (Acts 17:26) and, when it talks about the souls of the descen-
mopolitanism. Scripture teaches that all human beings are “of one blood”
(Acts 17:26) and, when it talks about the souls of the descendents who are
"in the loins” or "in the hip” of the forefathers," understands evolving very
concretely. This is why Scripture values all those genealogies and, whenit
follows this line back to the beginning, ends with Adam, whois the only
human being, except Jesus, not born from an intimate union. Thefirst hu-
man came into being through creation. It was a special act of creation,
through which God revealed his love in this, that he wanted to be his Father
in heaven; which is also why Adam is called "son of God" (Luke 3:38), a
child that was to be the image of his God and reflect the glory of his Fa-
ther.!! [/33a38]
B.
Scriptural philosophy views religion as a covenant (unio foederalis)
. Made known to humankind, also before the fall, by means of word revela-
tion.
1. With this proposition calvinian philosophy directs itself first of all
against the suggestion that religion is a matter of people being "taken up,”
whether substantially or functionally, "into God." That's also why we are
discussing religion separately. There would be no reason to do so if we
could somehow agree with the conceptions that are current. Religion would
then have been included in the previous section.
Why must we be so insistent that religion not be confused with any
human subject functions, also not with their pistic functioning?
~The answerwill become clear as we take a look at what the pistic func-
tion is.
As function, that is, as believing, it is nothing more than the ac-
ceptance of God's word revelation or the acceptance of what one takes to be
word revelation. That last part is important because nonchristians have a
pistic function too."? If we keep this in mind and, at the same time, despite
“appearance.” As far as idea is concerned, the word does not once appear in
Holy Scripture.
Genesis 35:11, 46:26; Exodus 1:5; Judges 8:30; 1 Kings 8:19; 2 Chronicles 6:9;
Acts 2:30; Hebrews 7:5 and 10. Note that except for where reference is made to
the Mediator (Acts 2:30) this evolving is limited to the flesh, that is, to that which
is created.
2 Corinthians 3:18. The original text does not have "beholding” (King James,
e.g.], but “reflecting” (NIV, e.g.]. See also, Exodus 34:35.
2 Dr A. Kuyper, E Voto Dordraceno (Amsterdam; Hoveker en Wormser, 1905)
Til, pg. 536: “...alsof zulk een man nu duiten alle peloof stond. Neen, elke
moderne en elk dusgenaamd ongelovige is tegel¥k een afgodendienaar en heefi
een vals geloof,..."
Draft D JHK Translation Page 43
Calvinism and the Reformation of Philosophy
mt
that, equate living in covenant with God with any of the human functions,
then the inevitable result, whether intended or not, is universalism. Faith,
spiritual life, conscience, or whatever they call it today, become rays of the
divine being, crystallizations of the Logos, or some such. But with every-
one exhibiting all these functions, the universalist is no longer able to see
"9 Canons of Dordt, I-IV, 12. As such there is no objection if people in this re-
gard want to call this making alive “unconscious,” as long as they intend to say
with this term that this act of God precedes our knowing it. Assuming also that
this “preceding” is not understood functionally, that is, that it is not used in the
sense of “sub-conscious." Compare my “Tweeérlei wetenschap: Haitjema's
critiek op Kuyper's conceptie getoetst en afgewezen” in De Standaard
(November 9, 1931}. Nor ought people to take regeneration to be a seed that de-
velops itself. It is an act of God to which being born again corresponds and
which reveals itself as the years pass in the need for reinforcement in the strife
from the word of God. Some object to this view by pointing out that Scripture
says that faith is “a gift of God.“ But takenin its context the place they appealto
(Ephesians 2:8) refers not only to faith, but certainly also to being made alive
(5,6). Besides, don't forget that an Apostle, writing to Christians about faith, is
not holding forth about a function without direction, but about the christian faith,
' Genesis 5:22 and 24; Exodus 19:5; Deuteronomy 33:9; Psalm 25:10, 103:18,
132:12; Isaiah 56:4 and 6; Daniel 9:4,
=<
Draft D JHK Translation Page 45
Calvinism and the Reformation of Philosophy
C. r
Conceming the situation after the fall, scriptural philosophy accepts:
1. the total depravity of man,
2. death as punishmentfor sin, and
3. the revelation of the grace of the sovereign God in the Mediator.
1. Those who followed the above understand that scriptural phi-
losophy also accepts God's word when it communicates hard truths. All
told, much more will be gained by doing that than by refusing to look reality
in the face. Here, too, philosophy cannot change anything. It has simply to
try to grasp God's word clearly.
Draft p JHK Translation Page 46
Calvinismand the Reformation of Philosophy
In the first place there is the message of Holy Scripture that the human
race is corrupted by sin. Death, then, affects not only Adam, but also all
who were included in him (1 Corinthians 15:21). And those who know
what they are saying can't say this without their words crying out like Paul's
did: “For all have sinned and fall short of the glory of God" (Romans
3:23). This holds, then, for every individual member of the human race and
does not touch just a partof their lives, buttheir entire being. Fortheir
hearts are untrustworthy(Proverbs28:26) and (/33a43] from their heart, out
of which are the springs of life, come evil thoughts and all kinds of abomi-
nations that defile them (Matthew 15:18-19).
Hence, when God's grace comes between both, a struggle ensues in
that heart between callous and compliance, between the old hate and the new
love, between “flesh” in its bad sense and “spirit.” This opposition, clearly,
does not correspond with the distinction of “intent and actuality" [geest en
leven] derived by recent philosophy from the age-old one that occurs not
only in the lives of Christians, but in the lives of everyone.”
2. In light of the preceding, what scriptural thinking understands by
“death” also becomesclear.
We know that Holy Scripture distinguishes here between the first and
the second death (see 2 Corinthians 5:3-8). A hasty comparison seems to
suggest the same distinction among the ancients. But a closer look proves
that what here seemed to be "the same" is really totally different. Ancient
philosophy tookits starting point and goal in man, and more specifically, at
least to the extent they wanted to bereligious, in his functions. That's why
they saw death at the functional level as a desirable division. They took the
first death to be a division between the body that was moved and the soul,
its mover. The second death was when the highest part of the soul that had
escaped the prison of the body left the lower part of the soul behind on the
moon, in order to completeits return to the sun.'®
Obviously, the basic thought of Holy Scripture is completely different.
It is not man that is trustworthy, but God. And the very best that can hap-
pen to people is to walk in covenant with God; to enjoy the wonderful sweet
life as only children of the heavenly Father can. To die then, according to
Scripture, is in no way something to be [/33a44] desired. On the contrary,
death comes to man from God as punishment for serious transgression.”
That holds for the first death as well as the second. The difference between
these two is primarily that the first death comes to all who were included in
* [The Germantranslation (35454) has here: “und auch gar nicht antithetisch ist."]
~ 18 Revelation 20:14,21 compared to Revelation 2:11 and 20:6.
~ 17 Yeberweg-Pracchier, Die Philosophie des Altertums (Berlin: S. Mittler & Sohn,
1926) 538.
Draft D JHK Transtation Page 47
Catvinism and the Reformation of Philosophy
Spirit, will be raised as a "spiritual body."*° We see that the words "body"
and “spiritual” are used here in such a way that there is nothing con-
tradictory in their connection as long as we understand the terms as Scripture
uses them and do not, living in a world of thought completely foreign to it,
read that world into these words.
3. I could not help but mention grace already in the previous points.
But it would still be good to focus on it for a moment.
a. First a few terminological questions.
What is grace? Whatis its relationship to "nature" and to “sin”? Is it
good toconnect this word with "realm" and talk about “realm(s) of grace"?
Here too, let's bepin with the positive elaboration. “Grace” means first
of all "mark of favor”; in the relationship of God to sinners, “forfeited mark
of favor." Grace,inthisrelation, always proceeds from God. Its opposite
is neither nature nor sin, but "God's wrath."
The answerto the question about the relationship of grace to nature, or
the natural state, depends of course on the sense in which the word "nature"
The life of language with respect to “sin” is less complicated than that
of “nature.” Originally in Scripture, it meant "missing the mark” by trans-
gressing God's commandments, whilestil! remaining under the law. Grace
in relation to sin, then, means “forgiveness.” And just as on God's side
grace is the contrary of wrath, sc also, on the side of man, forgiven sin
stands over against the sins that still cling to us, that is, the sins that remain
imputed to us.
Finally, the question whether the meaning of "grace" allows us to talk
about “realms of grace." As such, there is no objection against doing so, as
long as people remember that this realm, if not further defined, is always the
Same as that of creation and is only called “the realm of grace” because and
to the extent that God looks in pleasure upon it. This realm is much broader
than the Church as body of Christ and, all the more, greater than the life of
this Church as ecclesiastical institution. Even in the remotest regions God
still today often grants rich gifts to particular people to rule the lives of folk
and family. Calvinists have always seen this, and express it in their talk of
“common grace." The realm of special grace, then, stands to that of com-
21-1 Corinthians 2:14. This text [about “the natural man”) should not be used to
support the claim that someone in physics cannot prove the existence of God.
Such a proof is impossible, but the text is not about the natural sciences, but
about a dead sinner. See the note on page 47.
2 1 Corinthians 15:46. See the notes on pages 47 and 48; also K. Schilder, War is
de hei? Kampen: J.H. Kok, 1932) 54ff. and 89ff,
Draft D JHK Translation Page 50
Calvinism and the Reformation of Philosophy
mongrace—to the extent Godin his favor looks down uponhis creature—as
the life in the cosmos that is reconciled to God stands to that which is not so
reconciled. [/33a47] We can conclude that the distinction between "common"
and “special” grace, and their respective realms, is completely legitimate.
People are looking for trouble, however, when they divide a person's life in
two somehow andthen lay this distinction on top of that division. The trou-
ble being that they then return to” the Roman Catholic view of nature and
grace, while depriving themselves of the possibility to realize this by using
calvinian terms that mean totally something else. Because this peril is so
conceivable, it isprobably better, in the spirit of Scripture, to speak of
"objects"ofgrace rather than "realms."
b. Obviously more important than the matter of terms is the question
of how grace comes to man.
We could answer, “through the Word." But the question is then, what
we understand this to mean. If we equate it with the word that is preached,
we end up equating life making grace with a kind of ministerial magic. So
we haveto distinguish, on the one side, the creating and hence divine Word,
who preached, sent his prophets, finally appeared himself, and also now lets
his word be preached and, on the other side, the preached gospel word
which, being meant for people, spoke and speaks of him in human lan-
guage. In other words, behind the word as communicated knowledge
—
stands’ the Word that, in a completely unique manner, covenanted with him
who, received of the Holy Spirit and born of the virgin Mary, is the second
Adam. In spite of his ties to fallen human nature, and through his unbreak-
able connection with God and anointment by the Holy Spirit, he leads every-
[/33a49]
CHAPTERIII
INTRODUCTION
If this is to change in the future, we mustfirst of all realize that we
lack _a classification, befitting our view, of the “basic themes"of non-
scriptural philosophy. How often don't peoplepresentdeism andpantheism,
for example, as sharp contrasts, only to label their own Standpoint as
"theism"! Now in the first place, even when we see that this way of doing
things brings us no further, we need to remain fair. There was a time when
Calvinists had to defend themselves on these two fronts, and we can only be
thankful that it happened. In the second place, we need to remember that
the terminology often had to be devised in haste; in fact, it usually relied
upon that of others, for the simple reason that it was the issues that were
primary. I too originallyspoke of Calvinism in the sphere of philosophy as
being "theistic"; until a passage in Kuyper's E Vote, where he explicitly
discusses the use of this word—which he uses elsewhere without
question-and senses something wrong in its use, *4lso made me skeptical
aboutits suitability.
Meanwhile, skepticism itself yields little. What we need are positive
results.
Which method oughtto be followed in order to obtain these? [/33250)
METHOD
It is not surprising that people who attempt such a survey initially think
they have to proceed on the basis of how the various authors characterized
themselves. But it doesn’t take long before they find out that this approach
leads nowhere. First of all, many of these brilliant thinkers left behind very
little in the way of decent terminological characterizations of their system.
Besides, to the extent others did do so, it really doesn't help much. The one
uses terminology that the next one contests. And combining the collected
results would, even on the main points—just think of what people associate
with the word “god"—lead to the strangest contradictions. This would ob-
viously hinder insight sooner than sharpen it, as is abundantly clear from
many survey texts.
Consequently, there is no other way than to classify the different sys-
temsaccording to the answers they give to precisely formulatedandwell ar-
ranged questions.
People might very well object that the results to which this method
leads will bear all to much the stampof the person posing the questions.
However, two things can be said in response. First of all, this ob-
jection is not as large as one thinks: a clear survey from a specific attitude is
better than an enumeration of problems and solutions without perspective.
And secondly, one should keep in mind that not every position is of equal,
be it more or less, value, as the relativists claim: when the classificatory
questionsare fruits of a scriptural thinking,the classification obtained on the
basis of answers given to these questions also offers the needed guarantee of
being objectively grounded. Hence, I indulge the hope that the result to je
which I came may also prove useful to others than those who are my part- |
ners in principle..... {33a50//]
Draft D JHK Transtation Page 55
Calvinism and the Reformation of Philosophy
* In the apriori line of thought, whatis "higher" is considered secure, with what is
"lower" depending on what is higher. Emanation, as in tight or logos from
above, is a preferred analogy. An emphasis on being and absolutes are typical,
Epiphenomenalism presumes that what is “higher” rests on “the lower.” There is
a sirong preference for “growth” metaphors (and becoming, relativiry) that em-
phasize physis, e.g., the fruitfulness of the land, stream, and mother-earth.
@ Subjectivism and objectivism have an incorrect view of object functions and sub-
ject functions, respectively.
* Nominalism denies the existence of logical object functions: once the sense per-
ceptions are in, it's all mental from there on in; “truth” is found within the indi-
vidual. Realism overestimates the significance of logical object functions for
thinking; “truth” is not only within, but primarily outside the individual,
Y Yay S4 is en
Prerwadic of pase 26
Draft D JHK Translation Page 56
Calvinism and the Reformation of Philosophy
tions. Functions are the channels through which the issues of the human
heart come to expression. But what holds for all the functions, holds like-
wise for the pistic function (of faith): what people believe, ultimately de-
pends on the heart they have. Faith is a function all people have; there are
no nonbelievers. But while the believing of Christians respects the word of
God, the believing of nonchristians directs itself to a surrogate, and is called
“unbelief.” Vollenhoven describes the individual human heart, which is ei-
ther open or closed to God's word, as “pre-functional" and, as such, not ac-
cessible to another person's analysis or judgment. Rather, the obedience or
disobedience that lives in another person's heart only comes within our
purview through the various modesof earthly existence, in human activities
and their results, all of which, in one way or another, can be object for hu-
man analysis. In other words, faith so conceived is a behavioral aspect of
our lives, while it is from out of the heart that religion radically and totally
determines and dominates human living.
Vollenhoven’s claims with respect to the pervasive influenceof reli-
gious direction are prescriptive. He would bethelast to deny that a lack of
integrity prevails, also among Christians, between peoples’ religion and
their lives. As we'll see in this essay, obedient and disobedient living in one
person'slife are not like water and oil (74).
Bavinck had made a different but somewhatrelated distinction between
faith as a personal attitude and view of life and dogmatics as a formulated
system of religious belief statements or theology. This distinction was im-
portant for Bavinck for a number of reasons. On the one hand,it left room
for empirica} psychology as a science distinct from theology. Waterink, in
contrast, who denied the distinction, preferred to order psychology under
christian dogmatics. He made dogmatic theology the leading principle from
which the basic framework for psychology should be derived. This implied
that the better articulated one's theology was, the more christian was one's
perspective on psychology. For Bavinck, a vibrant christian faith life did
not take away the need for psychology. As heput it: Just because people
believe Christ doesn't mean that they have arrived theoretically; so also be-
ing an unbeliever does not make you demented ora liar.
Although they differed on the relationship of faith and learning and,
hence, theology and psychology, Waterink and Bavinck had a very similar
anthropology. A human beingis a unity of body, soul and spirit, whereby a
person's soul and spirit, the personality, are two sides of a single
incorporeal substance. The spirit side, which is the core of man,ties him to
whatis invisible and divine, while the soul side is tied to the body and what
is visible. In his psychology, Waterink assumed that someone's inherited
traits could be explained with reference to human ature, namely, to soul
and body, but that the immortal, “spirit” part of everyone, the ] or ego, was
Draft D JHK Translation Page 69
Faith:
Its Nature, Structure,
and Significance for Science
Mr. Chairman, ladies and gentlemen: I was eager to comply with the
invitation to contribute to this conference. That comes not only because of
my pleasant memories of the Utrecht study conference in 1946, but also, and
especially, because it is important to improve our contact. AsI see it, Ro-
man Catholics and Calvinists in The Netherlands are becoming alienated
from each other, to the detriment of our country. If this situation is going to
change, then wearefirst of all going to have to understand each other well.
Conferences tike these are a most appropriate meansto that end.
The themeof the conference is “Faith and Science," and today we are
to approach it from the angle of faith. With that in mind, I asked myself:
Whatis the nature of faith? What part does knowing play when it comes to
faith? And, what value does faith knowledge havefor science?
The Nature
of Faith
evil, i.e., in obedience to the law of love or not. In other words, the whole
man is religious, and his life is a walk before the face of God in obedience
or disobedience.
But in the framework of functional existence faith also occupies the
most important place. This function is the highest, which implies that all
the others [e.g. the aesthetic, economic, social, lingual, and analytic] are
lower [functions] and together form the substrate of faith. Because ofthis,
faith refers back to all those other functions and these, in turn, point forward
to (anticipate) faith. Faith, then, is part of the functional “cloak” and, as
such, is part of the structure of man. it is not something that was Jost and
that was returned later as a donum superadditum, a super-added gift (of
grace).
B. So far I have considered faith in individual existence. But a person
never lives this way: he comes out of community and into many com-
munities. There are many such societal relationships. Think, for instance,
of clubs, associations, business enterprises, the state, and the family. These
societal relationships all have cultural-historical formation as their basis; in
addition, they ali imply the use of language, the observation of social cour-
tesy and interaction, while their highest function indicates the purpose.
The community of faith is also a societal structure. It, too, is inherent
to human life. A community of faith is not something only Christians
know; pagans knowit as well. In christian circles people call this commu-
nity "church."
Hence, the church, like the societal relationships we just noted, bears a
functional character. One should distinguish "church" from the “corpus
christianum,” the people of the Lord, whichis the prefunctional community,
rooted in Christ.
Ecclesiastic offices, therefore, are also functional and should be distin-
guished from the prefunctional office in which the representative of hu-
mankind acts in matters that are to be done for humanity before God. [/50473)
C. With this, we come to the genetic. Human life is not simply some-
thing of today. It also has a past.
This past plays a role in the nurturing that prepares the individual per-
son to stand at a later age within the societal relationships in the community.
But the past is also important for communities. They have their history as
well. Here too the direction of that which is functional is determined by the
heart and, as such, byreligion, i.e., by the relation to God. That is why the
history of religion is dominated by the falt of the first Adam. Adam did not
lose [the capacity for] faith, but directed it differently. He no longer be-
lieved God, but Satan. But he did lose his prefunctional office, that there-
after was entrusted to Christ as the second Adam.
Draft ® JHK Translation Page 74
Faith: Nature, Structure, and Significance
The Structure
of Faith
B. Faith also stands in connection with its substrate [i.e., with the
other, less complex functions]. Not only does faith rest on it; it forms a
whole with it. Faith refers to this substrate through traits that are inherent
to faith. The joy and sorrow of faith refer to the sensitive [mode of being].
Its thinking and knowledge to the analytic [mode of being]. The offering
refers to the economic [mode of being) and trust [as brothers and sisters in
Christ] to the ethical. These retrocipations are not elements in the sense that
one could say that faith consists of joy plus sacrifice plus trust. Faith is
something unique, sui generis. One cannot define it other than by saying
that it is the highest function. These traits are implicit to faith, but they do
not qualify faith. The debate over whether faith is emotional, cognitive, or
volitional is therefore meaningless.
C. Consequently, the knowing implicit in faith is no more important
than, for instance, trust, But in connection with our topicof the significance
of faith for sciencethis trait does merit special attention here.
Wenote in the first place that this thinking and knowing bears a non-
scientific character. It may definitely not be confused with the science about
faith which is part of theology. Taken Scripturally, faith (believing) is
knowing Godin the face of Jesus Christ. [/50d75}
ated knowing found in the special sciences: and subsequently turns back, on
this detour, deepened and enriched, in philosophy to the knowledge of the
whole,
C. In all this the nontheoretic knowledge peculiar to faith occupies a
special place. For, while faith as a function remains a human function,
nevertheless, when one hears and listens to the Word revelation, which is
reliable in itself, and therefore needs no witness to back it up, he not only
learms something about the cosmos, but also about God andhis relation to
the cosmos. Whoever believes Genesis 1:1, for example, knows something
about God, namely, that he created the world, and something about the cos-
mos, namely, that all the world is created by God. And this knowledge has
to do with the main issues; if you will, with the circumscriptive concepts.
Once I have this knowledge, on the negative side, it leaves no room for
idolizing anything that is created, while on the positive side, it helps in ar-
riving at the common [/50d76) denominatorofall creation—namely, thatit is
subjected to the law of God and, by that, to God Himself.
The same holds with respect to faith knowledge concerning history.
Those who accept the fall into sin understand that in the fall humankind,
though unchangedin structure, radically changed in direction, As long as
no new turn-around (conversic) occurs, we live no longer to the right but to
the left.
Nontheoretic knowledge also includes what we know about the wrath
and grace of God. Both revelations are the disposition of God towards sin
and the sinner. That is why grace never, in any way, stands in opposition to
nature, but always over against wrath. As far as the relationship of grace to
(fallen) nature is concerned: the effect of grace can best be seen as a calling
to life and as healing. For grace brings forth gifts of grace, and the greatest
of these is the conversion, the regeneration of the heart. So this is no extra
dimension received as donum superadditum, but the influence of grace
through which we again begin, out of love, to live in obedience, not only in
a “religious sphere,” but as men and womenin integral wholeness.
The concepts of nontheoretic faith knowledge are accordingly all total-
ity concepts. They cannot replace the concepts of scientific investigation,
but they circumscribe them. WhateverI find by way ofscientific investiga-
tion is there before the investigation begins and sooner orlater fits within
that framework,
Faith, whether Christian or pagan, may not be considered “beyond” in-
vestigation. But such theoretic work is always a special science about faith,
that as field of investigation is there before that investigation can begin, and
therefore is not constructed or founded by science.
Conclusion
Draft D JHK Translation Page 77
Faith: Nature, Structure, and Significance
If we see the relationships in this way two things are understood. (a) A
theoretic basis for christian faith is impossible. (b) But, in contrast, a chris-
tian foundation for science is certainly possible. It is indeed a primary re-
quirement. For a science that does not have this foundation lacks the
framework in which also scientific knowledge ought to be placed.
These things are also of great importance for the investigator during his
work. They embed his efforis in the great struggle for truth and nurture a
sense of responsibility [/50d77): Theoretic work is part of our life, which in
its totality stands in service of God. Thus science becomes part of our
walking before his face. Further, they sharpen our insight, not only for that
which is present in what we investigate, but also into whatis lacking by rea-
son of sin. Forinstance, a historian will not only describe what he finds in
a pagan author such as Plato, but he will also see what Plato could not have
known.
In other words, being a Christian is infinitely more than being a stu-
dent. Being a student is being allowed to study; thus it is more than not be-
ing a student.
And being a student is infinitely more than to study as a nonchristian.
For the christian studentall of life, including also its theoretic side, includ-
ing activity and results, is safe with Christ in God. (50¢77/]
3.
SOCIAL SPHERES
AND LAW SPHERES
the very ways of being that are intrinsic to all earthly {i.e., nonangelic)
creatures. Where did this theory about law spheres come from?
Vollenhoven mentions in this essay two factors that contributed to the
rise of the theory ofrelatively distinct modal law spheres: (a) Kuyper'sin-
sight that the methods used in the various sciences differ because of a differ-
ence in what they investigate and (b) the realization that what a science in-
vestigates, its “field of investigation,” is (just) an aspect of things, some of
which are objects and others are subjects, and both of which are subject to
the same law. These two factors, concerning what determines a science's
method and what a field of investigation includes, can actually be docu-
mented from his early publications. What follows is a sketch of the incep-
tion of the theory of modally qualified law spheres based (only) on refer-
ences to these two points as found in Vollenhoven's writings. !
Whendiscussing the nature of science in his 1894 encyclopedic study,
Principles of Sacred Theology, Kuyper made the claim that just as the object
of the different sciences varied, so also should their methods. Atthetime,
though acknowledging many sub-disciplines within each faculty, Kuyper
was defending the existence of five faculties or departments at the university
level: theology, law, humanities, medicine, and natural science. By locat-
ing "a principle group of the object of science [which includes al! existing
things,} in a realm of its own” (195), Kuyper was also hoping to vindicate
and secure a place for theology amongthe other disciplines. He apportioned
the realms these sciences study by using "antithetical" divisions between
God (theology) and man; man among men (law); within man, between soul
(humanities) and body (medicine); and between man and nature (natural sci-
ence). In each case, Man (understood as the universal human conscious-
ness), what Kuyper called "the subject of science," functions as, what he
called, "the principle of division" for making distinctions within "the object
of science" (190).
As Kuyper realized, the crucial question then becomes: which ob-
jects/things actually exist and what is the nature of the object in question
such that the method used to study it should differ? "Faith in the existence
of the object to be investigated is the conditio sine qua nonof all scientific
investigation” (48). One reason Vollenhoven became interested in
Meinong's theory of objects (Gegenstinde) was thatits classification of the
sciences was based on the object studied (18a173), but even more so because
it helped Vollenhoven define what he in 1918 understood concerning the
existence and nature of the object that mathematics studies, namely, number.
In fact, one of his objectives in his doctoral dissertation was "to provide
proof for the thesis that the three schools of thought in mathematics
(empiricism, formalism, and intuitionism, all of whom disagreed on the na-
ture of number] are direct offshoots of the three schools of metaphysics
Draft D JHK Translation Page 81
worlds [on the other]. In this way the soul remains a unit. The whole human
soul, as unique new project of the Divine Artist, is immortal; psychology con-
tinues to have one Gegenstand and one method, namely inner perception.
Physiological psychology is not psychology, but physiology; which can inform
us at most aboutthe relation of soul and body, probably only about the latter
and its reactions and so forth, that accompany psychic acts, And we have
nothing born again that must be conceived as a donum superadditum.
There is too muchin this letter to comment on here, but his remark about
psychology illustrates the program of advocating a “pluralism of methods"
(30d90): a science's object should define its method.
Vollenhoven was advocating “obedience to the lawful authority of
these Gegenstande": “the object of physics is distinct from that of
mathematics [and that of psychology}.... Objectification is not a creating, as
the Marburgers think, but an apprehending, such that you cannot follow the
whim of your method, even if you do so systematically, because the method
is dictated by the metaphysical Gegenstand" (22d143}. In 1920(a12)
Vollenhoven had pursued a similar line of thinking in meticulously
following Hans Driesch's use of the phenomenological method ("Husserl's
objective logic, against which there are no objections as long as it remains
purely descriptive") “to arrange the sciences logically according to their
object: you know you are entering a new field of investigation every time
you have to introduce a new hypothesis or related group of hypotheses.
[For example,] the epistemological distinctiveness of biology is maintained
if you can nof work things out using just the hypotheses of physics.”
Volienhoven began to advocate the same approach: “The orderofthefields
can be derived from the logical arrangement [erdening] of the methods,"?
with the understanding that a difference in method is correlate to the differ-
ence in the field being researched (26242). As Vollenhoven reiterated years
later: for each science this means "that from the start a method has to
conform continually to the material being investigated” (61c2).
So, Vollenhoven consistently advocated this rule about scientific meth-
ods. All the same, because his understanding of “the object of science"
changed significantly between 1922 and 1925 caution should be taken lest
this continuity be misconstrued. The story of this changeis too longtotell
here, but a few "snapshots" from this period will shed some light and bring
us to the second factor that Vollenhoven mentions about "fields of investi-
gation" as contributing to the theory of modal law spheres.
Although he at no time denied God's sovereignty over all of life or
questioned the validity of a heteronomous worldview, before 1925 Vollen-
hoven embraced "self-consciousness" as his philosophic starting point. Un-
til 1927 his research and writing were primarily in the area of the theory of
knowledge and the sciences. He realized that "being is always richer than
thinking” (184437) and in 1919 “pointed to the need for pressing on, behind
Draft D JHK Translation Page 83
What did change was his understanding around 1924 of what this meant for
his theorizing about human knowledge and the sciences. One indication of
this changeis that after 1920 he no longer will talk about theself subjecting
itself to some law or norm or logical principle. No longer does a person
have a (knowing or sensing) subject; everyone, and everything creaturely, is
subject. In other words, after 1924, Vollenhoven's sense of "subject" is
different: "subject" means, in the first place, "subject to God [Gode
subjéct)" (25ms3); all subjects are “subjected to the laws of God” (26ms9);
and there is nothing besides Godthat is not subject to him. (This should not
be taken to mean that everyone obeys God and his laws; that some people
break the speed limit does not mean they are above or beyond these laws.)
The difference this makes in Vollenhoven's sense of philosophic orientation
might be compared to the change ofattitude a spouse would experience by
moving from the conviction "I also have a wife and am going home soon to
be faithful to her” to the sense "] am married and seek to be faithful to my
spouse in all things and at all times.” With a passing reference to Alberdi,
Vollenhoven in 1925(ms7) also describes the change as a move from
Aristotle's Greek upokeimenon {that which lies under) to the Latin's "more
passive form" subjectus (that which is placed under).4 People do not subject
themselves to the norms for right thinking because they want to come to
knowledge, but find themselves subject to those norms per definition,
because thinking and knowingare functions of the God-given office of being
human subjects (26b382).
One obvious conclusion that follows from this renewed sense of sub-
jectivity is that all "objects" are, with respect to God, “subjects” in this
sense. For example, things being sensed (perceived objects) as well as those
who are sensing those things (perceiving subjects) are both “subjects” in the
sense of subjected to God's law, and in this case to God's laws for sense
perception (26d177). However confusing terminologically this claim may
be, what Vollenhoven is now convinced of is a common field of shared
cross-sections, actually many qualitatively different cosmic connections, laid
in creation that no longer place subject over against object(ion) such that the
one must act upon the other (interaction), but that these two, at least in some
important respect, fit together, are interrelated, share common ground and,
to that extent, belong to the same field (25c392). For psychology this
means the psychologist studies the psychic law sphere, which includes the
entire domain of "that which is psychic [het psychische],"5 namely, the set of
ali things in so far as they are subject to God's laws for instinct, sensation,
perception, feeling, and emotion. The same holds for physics; its field of
investigation, the physical Jaw sphere, is different in character
(quality/modality) but includes theset of all things in so far as they are sub-
Ject to God's laws for energy. So too every science works within
Draft D JHK Translation Page 86
intestines, but the capacity to form these in relation to [samenhang met] the
food, displays a pure, form defining, and hence, qualitative character"
(20a4-5). Driesch's "pink slip" comes because he calls what is a concept,
namely, “organic form,” real,
— In 1922 Volienhoven not only criticized the positivistic reduction of ev-
erything to numbers and formulas, but also pointed out how importantit is
not to impose what people see or imagine (or not) on what is going on
physically. Although he disagrees with what Einstein has to say about ether,
he praises his theory of general relativity for its reminder that "to define the
concept ‘physical object’ with respect to ‘mathematical object' and
‘biological object,’ it is not necessary that euclidean space be presupposed”
(22d141). Einstein was highlighted again in 1926(d172): “he taught us to
reflect on the difference between perception and physical measurement.”
Movements have to be compared with other movements; motion is always
measured with respect to a moving or resting system. “Einstein came with
the sober remark that even though the standpointof the perceiver is very im-
portant for perception, the person busy with kinematics only has to take the
Kinetic side of things into account, to which, of course, the perceptual posi-
tion of every researcher is tied" (29d61).
— In 1927(ms81} Vollenhoven mentions Einstein again. He is leveling a
critique against frameworks in which an active creative subject stands over
against a passive created object, against views of the world and of knowl-
edge in which self stands marked off against non-self, and he concludes with
the remark that “you end up with as many lines of division as there are
selves and what for one is called the 'seif* belongs in the 'view' of the mil-
lion others to the 'non-self.'. The question, ‘Which point of view has prefer-
ence?’ is impossible to answer (Einstein)."
By 1927 Vollenhoven's discovery of how “being-subject" could func-
tion as his point of orientation completed his break with a dualistic frame-
work of interaction and the cosmos was embraced as philosophy's (limited
by law) field of investigation.
Vollenhoven’s publications document his indebtedness to Henri Berg-
son, Alexius Meinong, Bertrand Russell, Heinrich Rickert, Hans Driesch,
and others, as well as to Groen, Kuyper, Bavinck, Geesink, and Woltjer.
Vollenhoven was obviously more akin to the latter group. In neither case
was his acquiescence complete or uncritical; his indebtedness never simply a
matter of adoption, Vollenhoven had an antithetic attitude towards unscrip-
tural philosophy, but he also acknowledged that it is at least a catalyst for
scriptural philosophizing (29d63). This also proves to be the casein the de-
velopment ofthe theory of modal law spheres.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 88
End notes
' For Herman Dooyeweerd’s contribtion to this process, see Roger Henderson's /-
luninating Law: The construction af Herman Dooyeweerd's philosophy (diss.
Free University, 1994} 136ff.
2 (26a36); “Biology and physics stand on a par next to each other as sciences, al-
though, as is evident from the biological method, the biotic field rests on the
physical field. And these fields are cross-sections of the cosmos, such thal a
cosmic unit... is present in a variety of fields" (26a13).
3 In 1926 he mentions the fields: (logical) relation, number, space, time, move-
ment, energy, biotic, psychic... economic, juridical, and ethics..., although late in
1926 the logical aspect, as the first law sphere subject to a norm, was relocated,
possibly on Dooyeweerd's urging, to follow the psychic. In 1928(c27) the modal
order was almost as complete as it would stay: arithmetic, spatial, mechanical
{energy, chemical), organic, psychic, logical (analytic/synthetic), social, historic,
linguistic, economic, juridic, ethical, pistical (with a place for the aesthetic ac-
knowledged but left unspecified). In 1930(d22) they run: arithmetic, spatial, me-
chanical, physical (energy), organic, psychic (emotional), analytic (“logical”),
historic, linguistic, social, economic, aesthetic, juridic, ethical, pistic." See also
pages 36 and 192,
* He continues to use the term “substance” sporadically into 1927, with “subject
unit [subjectseenheid}” coming on strong, and explicitly urges people to stop us-
ing it after 1929 (see e.g. 3068, 32d398).
5 (25ms9). Vollenhoven was aware ofhis use of substantives and one time warned
against their possible danger: "Thereis in this contextlittle to say concerning the
term ‘that which is created’ [het geschapene, which could also be translated as
“creation"]. Grammatically it is a substantive referring to the result of God's cre-
ating activity as distinct from the creator. Referring to it in this way does not
make it independent or divided from him, Language and thinking make use of
the substantive to isolate, with an eye to looking at, that to which it refers. But
that is no grounds for assuming that all substantives are references to detached
Dingen an sich, And certainly not in this case: the grammatical substantive,first
ofall becauseit is logically speaking a relational concept, indicates in which con-
nection it stands to the Creator, namely, as product of his labor.”
[/50n4)
Sphere Sovereignty
for Kuyper and for Us
social movement, art, government, ethical life, and faith, saw no chance to
include these fields under "science" and therefore assigned them to the do-
main of practical reason. Positivism, though it shared the breadth of the
Enlightenment’s scope, rejected that solution. If the supra-analytic aspects
do not fit the seventeenth century's notion of science, then the bounds of
science have to be expanded. The thoughtitself was a good one. The mis-
take was that, in spite of broadening the scope of science, they continued to
understand it mathematically, equating the latter with precision thinking. As
a result, people were forced to reduce the diversity in method, required by
the diversity of the research, to a difference in men's minds. Instead of ac-
knowledging a manifold of areas open for investigation, they proposed a di-
versity of points of view from which the human mind would viewreality.
To expand the range of the sciences was not a problem for Kuyper.
Nor was recognizing a diversity of methods. What he strongly protested
against was the positivistic derivation of this diversity. The many different
methods of the sciences are not rooted in the activity of the human mind, but
in the richness of God's work ofcreation,
How Kuyper worked out this thought can indeed, after the fact, be
criticized on more than one point. By latching on to the usual number of
departments within the university at the time he distinguished only five ar-
eas; and on top of that he equated "area" and “object.” On both points the
founders of calvinian philosophy have had to correct their mentor.
But, here too, pointing out this shortcoming was accompanied with a
thankful tribute to the validity of the basic thought. In this way, deeper re-
flection on Kuyper's results was simply a matter of course.
Kuyper's calvinian sense of reality twice led him to argue for the
recognition of diversity in God's works. But while he spoke of "sphere
sovereignty" in the case of societal connections, he did not do so with refer-
ence to the diversity that the sciences investigate.
Thedifference in Kuyper's stance here was no coincidence. According
to him, the connections of everyday life have to do with subjects, while re-
search deals with objecis. In addition, when he spoke of "sovereignty" he
thought not only of God's sovereignty, but, influenced by Romanticism,
also of the authority of office bearers in the various sectors ofsociety.
Here, too, further reflection brought light.
In the first place, equating "field of investigation" with "object" didn't
seem to work. I will use the example of psychology to make that clear. Its
field of investigation is the psychic or sensitive aspect of things. Is that the
same thing as “sensed object"? In no way! The sensitive aspect ofreality
does include sensed objects, like colors, but also much much more, namely,
the entire emotive, sensitive life of man and animal. In other words, it also
includes what wecall “psychic subjects.". Hence, psychology's field of in-
Draft D JHK Translation Page 93
Sphere Sovereignty for Kuyper and for Us
vestigation includes objects, but also subjects. Indeed, the latter are even
more important than the former. On the other hand, the higher, more com-
plex areas one finds with societal connections, may not be equated with
subject functions. The economic arena includes more than just economic
activity. Without objects—goods in this case—economic activity would
even be unthinkable. And so we see that “lower” arenas include more than
objects and that "higher" ones comprise more than subjects!
In like manner, the sovereignty of God had to be distinguished from
the authority of office bearers. Their authority does come from God and in
fulfilling their task to positivize God's law for a particular arena they do, in
their office, stand on the side of the law. But as office bearers they are also
human and remain subject to the law of God, even within the arena for
which they hold office, just like those over whom they are entrusted with
authority,
Both changes were conscious deviations from Kuyper. On the other
hand, they lay completely in line with what he had done. As Kuyper did
more than once, anyone who makes a case for recognizing the riches in
God's creation work cannotfail in the long mun to see the diversity of object
and subject. As far as the second point is concerned, things are even more
simple. To the extent that people, with Kuyper, bow before the majesty of
God, they will also outgrow their romantic perception of office bearers
whichis still evident here and there in Kuyper.
When both changes are accepted, however, all of it, whether it's what
Kuyper spoke of using “sphere sovereignty” or those arenas where he
couldn't dothis, all of it is subject to the law of God. This, of course, is
not to deny the diversity of these areas. But this diversity, however exten-
sive it may be, proves to be a diversity all of which is subject to the law and
therefore to God, whetherit functions as a subject or as an object.
That being the case, Kuyper's pupils are entirely justified in using
“sphere sovereignty” even when nottalking about societal connections.
The difference between “sphere sovereignty" for Kuyper and for us
rests, then, on a few corrections, by means of which greater justice is done
to Kuyper's deepest intention: respect for the diversity in God's work.
Thatis whythis difference should sooner be praised than censured.
These corrections were inescapable. Without them Kuyper's view
would have becomeinflexible and his work be erased in the future, That is
why I just had to continue to distinguish field of investigation and object,
even when a numberof theologians asked that I follow the principles of sa-
cred theology found in Kuyper's Encyclopedia. That the contact between
the special sciences and philosophy is beginning to bear somefruit in more
than one department can be ascribed to distinctions unfortunately dismissed
by some of Kuyper's students around 1930.
Draft B JHK Translation Page 94
Sphere Sovereignty for Kuyper and for Us
But let's be fair. That the theologians in particular were at the time
extra careful is understandable. Innovations in 1920 and 1926 had yielded
nothing but disappointment. On the other hand, they knew us. Andit isn't
difficult for a healthy intuition to figure out whether the critique by fellow
disciples of their common mentor comes from a range of ideas that [/50n7] is
totally foreign to his view and arbitrarily expressing scorn and jeers, or
whether it is moved by the desire to preserve the valuable stem even though
that might require some powerful pruning.
But enough of that. The purpose of this article and the next one is not
to dig up sad stories from the past, but just the opposite: to make a contri-
bution toward healing the unity in the camp of Kuyper's students. The point
now is simply this: when Kuyperianism first began to unfold on a limited
scale many opponents were initially interested and convinced; as time passed
it had difficulty recruiting continued support and hence needed correction on
a number of points; when calvinian philosophy introduced these necessary
revisions, it did not revolutionize things, but continued on in the spirit of
Kuyper.
4.
DISCERNING
LAWS AND PITFALLS
essay from 1951, “Norm and Law of Nature,” he leaves a good deal
concerning laws and norms unsaid. And so, we will want to place this
discussion of norm and law of nature in the broader context of
Vollenhoven's understanding of law. This will not only contextualize this
essay, but also prepare us for a discussion of law-related traces of the Trinity
that boldly resurface in 1955.
The question the present essay addresses: "Is it correct to place law of
nature and norm under the heading ‘law'?"” seems innocent enough. We
will see that Vollenhoven, using an adroit variation on "it depends on what
you mean by nature," nonetheless answers just one third of the way into the
essay with clarity and poise: for both senses that the word "nature" could
have for a Kuyperian, the answer is "Yes." That most people mean some-
thing else by "nature" is given no more than a mention. The remaining two-
thirds of the essay is devoted to a different question that Vollenhoven raises
himself and then addresses, One that is much closer to home, namely: what
is the direction of the question posed? What is the connection such that
placing “law of nature" and “norm” under the same heading would be a
problem? In doing so, he also provides us an excellent glimpse of his
"problem-historic" approach. The end result will be a balanced critique of
Kuyper: s/s is good and thar is late-Aristotle behind a christian facade.
Although there is obviously more nuance to Vollenhoven's philo-
sophica} starting point than can be captured in one sentence, that sentence
would have to read: the beginning and end of Vollenhoven's philosophizing
is the relation of that which is creature to the Creator and, more specifically,
the relation of human beings to the covenanting God of Scripture. In order
te incorporate a deeper historical base regarding this key issue and how it
relates to Vollenhoven's understanding of law, the next few pages will
summarize his thoughts on the topic for the period 1930-1932. In the previ-
ous chapter we saw that 1925 marks a significant development regarding his
understanding of subjectivity (to God and his law), and extensive lecture
notes document how those thoughts developed during the rest of the decade;
in the first chapter we looked, among other things, at his notion of law as
demarcation, which remains crucial to his thinking over the years; and in his
1955 essay "The Unity of Life,” coming up in Chapter Seven, we will find a
striking continuity with what he was writing 25 years earlier. Again, what
follows in the next three pages is basically a weave of quotations drawing
only on texts from 1930 to 1932 that focuses on what Vollenhoven wrote
about the relation of that-which-is-subject to He-who-is-sovereign. The
primary text proves to be his introductory syllabus in philosophy dated
1930; the final edition of which we will come to in Chapter Eight.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 97
ity. The Spirit is active, leading all creatures, even at the level of atoms that
are splitting: "here too there are different possibilities, which leaves room
for the sovereign leading of the Spirit" (30d50). The Spirit “displays the
same character of Leader in his work among those particular creatures to
whom the Logos directs himself in a way other than through a word that
called them into being. For he sovereignly leads them in their relationship
with respect to the word of God. Correlate with the leading of the Spirit is
the result it achieves: the setting of the direction in that which he leads
[which is ‘something other than the existential course of that which is led'
(31f43)]" (30d50). The Spirit's leading ties in with the word: “The word
reveals the law and indicates the direction, while the leading sets the direc-
tion" (31£43).
(b} The relation of creaturely subjects to the divine sovereign involves
the place and purpose of people in particular and everything else in general.
As for the unique place, character, and constitution of human beings,
Vollenhoven notes that they (1) have more functions than do the other crea-
tures, such that (2) the subject functions, like the spatial or physical, that
they have “in common" with nonhuman things are nonetheless different by
having more “anticipations," and finally (3):
In the third place, by virtue of their highest function, which depends onall of
the lower ones, people are open to God's claim on them and to the Spirit's
leading in determining their attitude regarding the commandmentgiven by the
Logos. Asa result, their cohabitation as well, based on the difference in sex,
is completely different in character from nonhuman things: pollinating and
copulating here make room for sexual intercourse, whereby the attitude re-
garding word revelation is of fundamental importance (Genesis 2:25 and 3:7).
(30d51)
These last three points are tied directly to being created in the image of God:
"Created as he is, with all of his functions, by the living God out of the
earth, and spoken to and led by Him, man,in this triune structure of cre-
ated, spoken to, and led, is as servant on the side of that which is created the
correlate of the triune God" (30d51). What is unique about being human
can also be summarized in terms of "what's religious in our life, the heart,
which, corrupted after the fall, lives again when it is made alive by the grace
of God"; in that context the functions can be appreciated “as mutually irre-
ducible channels for the issues of life” (32d402). In other words, being a
born-again Christian makes all the difference in the world, "precisely be-
cause it changes the direction of our activities in all of the functions"
(30b17).
As for the place and purposeof these irreducible functions, as well as
for every other creaturely thing in general, the focus with respect to the re-
Draft D JHK Translation Page 99
lation of subject to sovereign falls primarily on the sovereign law. The en-
tire cosmos is created by God and there is a "limit that marks the creature
off from the Creator": "Everything on that side of this line is God and
everything on this side is created. This limit is the Jaw. Because the law
divides law-giver and subjects” (30d14); which is not to say that this line
sets God “outside what lies on the other side of the law, but only above it"
(31fl1). Every thing and all the functions of every thing are rocted in a
creative act of God and are subject to him and under his Jaws. The functions
of individually different things—referred to abstractly as “this's and
that's"—differ modally. The peculiar character of each mode exists "by
virtue of a unique law of God” (30b26), such that the modality of each of
the 15 functions is correlate with a similarly qualified law. Likewise, the
modality of interrelations is the same as the law sphere in which they are
found: “All the this's and that's for which the same law holds together
make up the domain or sphere ofthis law, its law sphere" (30d24). Thereis
a natural sequence (order) to these law spheres.
The laws for these spheres belong to those precepts of God [de wil des
bevels] that have been revealed, in the sense that they “can be knownin that
whichis subject to them"; but should not be equated with our formulation of
them (30b10). Some of these laws are norms. When that is the case
"direction" (towards or away from God) plays 2 primary role. The analytic
function is “the first normative subject function, in the sense that the logical
law is the first in the cosmic order that displays the character of norm"
(30d52). Direction also plays a role in the sub-analytic spheres (evil desires,
bad memories, mental health, sick bodies, pangs of guilt), but the possibility
of choice is not an option there. In other words, supra-psychic law spheres
“also have to display obedience to commands" (30b13):
Correlate with the norm on the side of the law is the choice on the side of the
subject: it has, namely, the choice between ‘listen to' and ‘be disobedient.’
While remaining subject to the normative law,it can be obedient and disobedi-
ent to the norm-dependent commandment. For example, a logical action can
be (correctly) logical or illogical, a historical action (correctly) historical or
unhistorical, a social action (correctly) social or unsocial, a pistical action cor-
rectly (=Christ) believing or unbelieving. (30d52)
"[NJothing can go against these laws of creation,” which is not to say that
commandments cannot be disobeyed (30d78).
Vollenhoven makes only passing reference to sphere sovereignty, men-
tioning the "competenceof office-bearers in societal connections to formu-
late for these connections the laws that hold for them” (30d77). In looking
for an analogy to get at the inspiration of Scripture, though, he is both frank
and enigmatic as to how tentative, but also trustworthy, this formulation is:
“The clearest way to get at what inspiration is like is to note the relationship
of a law holding for people and the formulation of such a law by those com-
Draft D JHK Translation Page 100
is a tradition that he not only can trace historically back (to Aristotle’s later
“monarchian" views on a universal or supra-individual mind) and forth (via
Galen, Sabellius and Marcellus, to Kuyper's view of the subject of science,
namely, universal consciousness), but will also critique negatively in a man-
ner that illustrates "Kuyper's intuition that heresy is the bastard of the con-
nection of Christendom and pagan philosophy." The crux of the issue in
this context proves to be twofold: how therelation between whatis univer-
sal and what is individual can best be understood and whether sin has af-
fected what logic studies.
Onthis last point, Kuyper had claimed in his Principies of Sacred The-
ology: "The formal process of thought has nor been attacked by sin, and for
this reason palingenesis (regeneration} works no change in this mental task.
There is but one logic, and not two" (159). Vollenhoven disagreed, calling
in 1932 for a christian logic: “Since the fall you can't just assume that ana-
lytic activity squares with the norm thatholdsfor it. There's simply no ba-
sis for the claim that the effects of sin, which misdirected all the activity of
human existence, left analytic activity untouched. Naturally, someone can
say that the fall did not change the structure of that which analytic, but that
is nothing special. Sin never undoes the structure, but everywhere reverses
the direction. Which is precisely the point here" (48f44). One of the most
basic bones of contention on this score is the foundational question: What
does and does notfall under the norms for right thinking? How universal,
how inclusive,is the analytic law sphere? Vollenhoven was convinced that a
logic that includes the mind of God in the domain ofthethis's and that's for
which the same law holds will be different from one that respects the laws
for analysis as the limit between creature and Creator.
The broader question of universality and individuality surfaces in this
essay as well. Vollenhoven's views on this topic are almost confusingly
simple. Herejects the primacy of one over the other (universalism and indi-
vidualism) as well as solutions that place the one (macro) nex fo the other
(micro) or the one above the other. As he sees things, everything under
God's sovereignty is always and at the same time both universal and indi-
vidual in the sense that being-human and being-this-human are always found
together (40a76; 56b3). Human nature is present in human beings. So,
when a science focuses on a defined law sphere, both the universal trait,
which characterizes the entire sphere, and the individual trait, which char-
acterizes the successive moments, simultaneous constituents, and the inter-
relations between these, are always both present. Within such a field, the
scientific (and philosophic) attitude usually focuses on the universal char-
acter of things, the "structure" of a thing or a connection. This universality,
as structure—not to be equated with the universality of the law as the demar-
cation between God and cosmos—can be found out through an abstraction
Draft D JHK Translation Page 102
Norm and
Law of Nature
Even though the law's diversity may not be as large as that of the cos-
mos, there is nonetheless diversity to be found here. Straightaway, and
analogousto the difference with human beings between soul and body, taken
in the scriptural sense of heart and cloak of functions, a difference can be
noted between summation and differentiation. The former summarizes the
core ofthe law to be a requirement of love for God and for the fellowman he
has placed next to us. This one law, however, is differentiated in a manifold
of laws for functional life.
The diversity in the law between law for that which is prefunctional
and Jaw for that which is functional is different from the diversity between
the various functional laws. Thefirst diversity is a binary distinction, while
the diversity of functions is not a duality but a plurality,
In cases like this plurality we are allowed no more than a bifurcation
with the help of a negation. In like manner wecan distinguish in the cosmos
between vegetal and nonvegetal creatures. But this does not give us the
right to consider plant and nonplant as two components from which the
world has been constructed. Distinguishing constituents that can be found
within the cosmos is one thing, a division of components the connection of
which would give rise to the world as a secondary unit is something totally
different!
There is an analogous case concerning the law. Somelaws are nomns,
while others do not display a norming character. But this diversity does not
negate that both groups of ordinances are laws set by God for that which is
created.
In general, this should all be fairly clear. But because the diversity of
Jaws that are norms and of laws that are not norms is especially important
for answering the question as to the relationship of law and norm,I deliber-
ately wantto take a closer lookat this diversity.
What is the root of this difference between laws that are correctly
called norms and those that do not have a normative character? I have dis-
cussed this question extensively elsewhere.’ In brief, the answer can be
summarized as follows.
For every law there is something correlate that is subjected to it. So
also, for every diversity of law that which is subjected to it also differs.
This rule applies as well for the functional laws. However, as a result, the
relation between the law and that which is subject to it in the one law sphere
is not the same as that relation in the others. This is so becausethis relation
is dominated by the character of the respective law sphere. When examining
the law spheres one by one wenote the peculiarity that in the analytic or
iogical law sphere the function is busy distinguishing. Which is to say that
' See my Hoofdlijnen der logica (Kampen: J.H. Kok, 1948) 27, 28.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 105
Norm and Law ofNature
ils task is to take note of the diversity in God's works. That is why the an-
alytic law sphere is typified by the fact that that which is subjected to the
Jaw not only differs from this law, but that given its own nature it can as-
certain this diversity. That is the reason why logical thinking can also dis-
tinguish itself from the law that holds for it. The past preserves more than
one attempt oflogical thinking to formulate the law that holdsforit.
Those efforts result in what are called "principles." They may well
have been formulated by men of science, but principles are in no way scien-
tific in character, Actually, they are nothing other than the very law for that
which is logical, to the extent human thinking was successful in putting
these laws into words. Also, they hold for nonscientific thinking as much as
they do for scientific thinking. Nonscientific thinking benefits from know-
ing these principles too. That is why the principles play an importantrole in
life; [/51n4] the principles people accept as holding for their thinking matter
indeed.
Something similar is also present in the supra-analytic law spheres.
There too people are looking for principles, for somewhere to begin. We do
well always to distinguish these kinds of principles from the law. At best, a
human formula includes no more than what someone has grasped of God's
law. That is why principles can sometimes be altogether false and, even
when they appear to be sound, are never unchanging, as are God's laws, but
must be revised repeatedly.
In contrast, in the law spheres less complex than the analytic we do not
find a search for principles in this sense, Not that law and function coincide
in these law spheres. Here too, they remain two. This is also evident given
that we speak of normal and abnormal in the psychic and biotic as well. But
the biotic and psychic are as such not in a position to take note of the differ-
ence between law and function. Self-distinction is first present in analytic
life.
So, whereverlife distinguishes itself from the law that holds for it and,
to the extent it proceeds to formulate the law in terms ofprinciples, takes
them into account, we speak of "norms." Consequently, there is no room to
object to the distinction of laws that do norm life and those that do not.
Actually, it proves to be an excellent way to distinguish supra-psychic life
from sub-analytic life. But this distinction does imply that the norm is a
specimen of law; a view that is in line with the vocabulary of Scripture as
well as of everyday life.
That being said I also hope my view of the relationship of norm and
law will be clear. The question as it is posed, however, refers not just to
"law" but to "law of nature.” So let me add to the exposition of my point of
view a few words about this special topic.
Draft ® JHK Translation Page 106
Norm and Law of Nature
2 The “laws” of Newton and Boyle are revisable formulations of established regu-
larities that focus primarily on relationships within that which is subject in a
physical way. The extent to which these Jaws are in line with the actual law jor
that which is physical is a question that can't be dealt with here. Neveris it the
case, even after revision, that they are identical. "Laws" in this sense are not
even principles in the sense discussed above,
Draft D JHK Translation Page 107
Norm and Law ofNature
ered by a “mathematical physics” that has stepped far beyond its bounds,
while for norms, often downgraded subjectivistically to values, lithe more
remains than the direction or subjective sense of what is going on in this
field,
The opposition of law of nature and norm in this sense need not hold
me up here. However important it may be for understanding modem phi-
losophy in general, these problematics are not a factor for the person asking
the question, coming as he does from a Kuyperian perspective. For those
who might be tempted to question this, remember that according to his En-
cyclopedia Kuyper's theory of science leaves no room for accepting, let
alone over-estimating mathematical physics.
However, when we look in a less modern direction, the issue of
“norm/law of nature" understood as an antithesis proves to be far less perva-
sive. Even among dualistic conceptions, which see no reason to object to
teaching that a human being is constructed from a transcendent and a non-
transcendent component, only one of them attributes both supposed compo-
nents to human nature. The numberofdualistic viewsthat limit "nature" to
the lower [realm] are likewise few in number. The only place I have found
this used is amongspiritualists and a few aristotelian conceptions.
Spiritualism is undoubtedly, historically speaking, a rather strong
movement that was repeatedly influential also in christian circles. This
danger is no less today. Remember, for example, how back in the 1920s
more than one member of the younger generation, also among Calvinists,
was infatuated by Wilhem Windelband and Heinrich Rickert and that even
today Emil Brunnerfascinates many. But this tendency is more Anabaptist
than Kuyperian. I would certainly be misinterpreting the question if I un-
derstood it in this way. Consequently, I can also pass spiritualism by,
which some, it seems to me, wrongly accuse Kuyperof.
A few aristotelian type conceptions remain. This term here refers not
to one or another of Aristotle's own views defended during the course ofhis
development, but to systems of thinkers that aligned themselves with him
only in part. History includes a rather large numberof such conceptions.
All of these systems are oriented moreorless to Aristotle's final view
of things. This is evident in their preference for the theme of form and
matter coupled with the opposition of active and passive intellect.
Not all of these conceptions are important for us right now. This is
related to the fact that within this group scores of differences arose. The
most significant of these divergences had to do with the question whether or
not the active intellect was [/51h5] universal. Towards the end ofhis life
{d. 322 B.C.] Aristotle himself definitely had opted forits universality. It is
clear that he was teaching at the time that there existed a supra-individual
mind (nous) that descended as transcendent mental energy upon the mental
Draft D JHK Translation Page 108
Norm and Law ofNature
faculty of individual human souls (psychai) and activated it. But already
during the Roman Empire Porphyry [d. 303] and others, who via Boethius
(d. ca, 324] and others would come to influence Thomas Aquinas [1225-
1274) and others, disagreed with the master on this point. Others, in turn,
continued to maintain the universality of the active intellect.
in the present context we have only to do with this last group. Butit,
too, was not univocal in every respect. The primary difference among them
had to do with the relationship of the universal godhead to the likewise uni-
versal intellect. On this point Aristotle himself had taught that universal
thinking was not divine. This position was stilt held by Alexander of
Aphrodisias [ } and others during the Roman Empire. But already a century
earlier the famous aristotelian doctor Galen [d. ca. 200] had presented an
other view regarding this point. As far as he was concerned the universal
inteliect was divine as well, In the history of philosophy both conceptions
get hidden behind those of Porphyry and others. But they becomesignifi-
cant in the further courseofaffairs.
This can be attributed to the fact that the early christian thinkers dis-
played notonly a platonic leaning, but more than one of them tended toward
Aristotle. The conceptions of Alexander and Galen also gained a following
in these circles. Indeed, not much was needed to drift into a synthesis here.
They had "simply" to equate the Father with the godhead and the Word of
God, the Logos, with the universal intellect found in the final conception of
Aristotle. That some actually took this step, in part because of an incorrect
interpretation of texts, John !:9 among others, is evident from the history of
early christian philosophy. Arius [d. ca. 336], for example, worked
Alexander of Aphrodisias in in this way and Sabellivs (ca. 312) did the same
with Galen.
As a result neither could do justice to the trinity of Persons in God and
both ended up with a monarchian conception. In spite ofthis the difference
between them was quite large. Arius was forced to conclude that the Logos
was not divine, while Sabellius had to consider that the Logos was divine.
That is why the church, even thoughit resolutely rejected the subordination
of Son and Spirit in Sabellius's conception, had grounds for considering the
Sabellians less serious enemies than Arius and others.
This difference became much more prominent when with time both
groups, in part becauseof the critique they endured, became more moderate.
Neo-arianism, for example, despite its concessions, both whenit first arose
as well as later when it, owing to the permission of sympathetic caesars, was
preached to the Ostrogoths as a result of large migrations in Italy, Spain,
and northwest Africa and rose in prominence, was recognized immediately
by the church and rejected out of hand. In contrast, Marcellus [bishop] of
Ancyra [d. ca. 374], whose conception sought more orless to reconcile that
Draft D JHK Translation Page 109
Norm and Law ofNature
of Sabellius with the confession of the Church before it was definitely con-
demned in 381, initially presented orthodoxy with more than one puzzle to
solve.
This is not the place to follow Marcellus into all the details. It is suffi-
cient to note that while he more or less agreed with Sabeliius concerning the
Trinity, he clearly distantiated himself from him in other regards. For ex-
ample, he distinguished two kinds of universal Logos, namely, a divine Lo-
gos, which was initially at rest and with creation began to move, and a cre-
ated Logos. The latter was the thinking activity that descended upon the
thought function of human souls. That faculty, too, is a form, but an indi-
vidualized form due to its attachment to matter. The line [grens] between
universal and individual temporarily lies between the intellect and mental
faculty, but in the future, at least for those who are saved, once again be-
tween form and matter.
I need hardly note that this conception, too, contained litle that was
new. Kuyper's intuition that heresy is the bastard of the connection of
Christendom and pagan philosophy proves to be true here as well. The pa-
ganistic prototype of Marcellus was an aristotelian author who wrongly at-
tributed his work to Galen and hence is referred to in the history of philoso-
phy as pseudo-Galen. The difference between Galen and (this) pseudo-
Galen runs parallel in pagan circles with the difference between Sabellius
and Marcellus, At the same time, modal monarchianism can be traced back
in its entirety to aristotelian thinkers and not to Heraclitus.
This conclusion, that I recently found, is also important for under-
standing modern philosophy. Schleiermacher, who, as is known, was very
much influenced by Sabellius, was, though also an idealist philosophically, a
declared opponent of Hegel's penchant for Heraclitus. But more light now
falls on Kuyper as well. In the first place, the accusation of Hegelianism
leveled against him proves untenable. The universal consciousness in his
Encyclopedia is not Hege!'s Geist, but the supra-individual intellect of the
late Aristotle. And there is not even an ounce of similarity between
Kuyper's distribution of the sciences into those of mind for spirit] and mat-
ter, as far as its foundation is concerned, and Dilthey's similar sounding
distinctions. The accusation of Sabellianism should not be leveled too
quickly either. Kuyper's own critique of Schleiermacher is reason for cav-
tion on this point. In addition, we saw above that Sabellius and Marcellus
need to be distinguished. On the samescore, the influence of Marcellus on
Kuyper cannot be questioned. Already in 1903 S. Greijdanus pointed in that
direction. Because his critique has to do with Kuyper's teaching about the
Mediator I will leave that for the moment; it will probably come up again
Draft D JHK Translation Page 110
Nerm and Law ofNature
when discussing a following point.” What does have to do with our topic
specifically is a hesitation I had already as a student with Kuyper's view of
the logical [realm], long before I ever heard of Greijdanus's objections.
This objection did not affect the core of his Encyclopedia, the view of two
kinds of science, which in contrast I found engaging from the start. It had
to do with Kuyper’s claim that the analytic [realm] was constructed from
two components, namely, individual function and universal force, that were
supposed to complement each other as nontranscendent “faculty” and
transcendent “activity.” This dualism ties logic to the hylemorphism and
faculty psychologyofthe late Aristotle. But not only that. It does nottally
with our unmistakable personal responsibility for our own thoughts.
Anyone who takes this last point seriously has to acknowledge that even
though the structure of that which is created, and hence also our analytic
life, remained untouched by sin, our logical function, seen as one of the
modes in which the direction of the human heart manifests itself, must have
been tainted bythefall.
The point in question is far from unimportant. Theissue hereis cer-
tainly not about attributing mistakes to a lack of natural ability or to sloppi-
ness and temporary fatigue. The entire history of current philosophy stands
as proof of how paganism dominates the problems it engages as well as its
solutions and basic concepts. Hence my plea for The Necessity of a Chris-
tian Logic (1932) and my attempt to carry through on that project in my
Contours ofLogic (1948). [/51h6]
The content of both of these publications is positive. Pointing out de-
ficiencies of others, let alone of Kuyper, was simply not their primary in-
tent. The first work lacks even an attempt at a historical analysis of his
standpoint. And the secondalso includes nothing more than a few short ref-
erences understandable only to the honed reader’ concerning the connection
between Kuyper's view and the system of the late Aristotle. At the time, it
was still not clear to me precisely how this relationship ran historically, I
began to understandthis a little better only after studying philosophy during
the Roman Empire further. Only when drafting my answerto the question
regarding the meaning of the opposition of norm and law of nature among
some of Kuyper's followers did things becomeclearer to me.
So, I am indebted to my esteemed opponentfor this gain. I hopethat
he in turn has been served by my analysis of the historical background to his
question; not to mention many others who, though followers of Kuyper,
may have questioned the validity of his view on this point.
Mayit be that the above helped them all to understand why on this
point calvinian philosophy must resolutely find its own way. All the same,
here too it can appeal again to Kuyper. His early writings do not presume
an untainted logical function and in his magisterial address "Sphere
Sovereignty,” with which he opened the Free University in 1880, he distin-
guishes on page 11 among other things "a realm of thinking over which no
other law than that of logic may rule."
That these two views are incompatible with each other goes without
saying: sphere sovereignty implies that what is universal and whatis indi-
vidual are both present in every law sphere. The former characterizes the
whole, the latter the parts. The speculative construction of the Logos the-
ory, in contrast, sees the logical [realm] as universal and the sub-logical
[realms] as individual. In practice that dovetails more easily with the
Roman Catholic subsidiarity principle than with the calvinian recognition of
diversity in life's reaches.
Kuyper himself was apparently not aware of this contradiction. In ad-
dition, because the founder of the Anti-Revolutionary Party staunchly held
sphere sovereignty high, it initially made little or no practical difference.
But nowthat three decades after the master's death more than oneofhis stu-
dents prefer to gyrate around speculative elements in his view, the question
ought to be raised as to whether the slackness that we see around us here and
there,also politically, is not in part a consequenceof this internal contradic-
tion.
Last time my contribution ended with an appeal to develop further,
where possible, Kuyper's principle of sphere sovereignty and not to be satis-
fied with just what hesaid.
This discussion of the second question went somewhatdeeper. It led to
distinguishing on a specific point in the work of our common mentor two
ways of understanding things that contradict each other, the oldest of which
proved to be more in line with Scripture.
That is why I want to formulate my intention somewhat differently
here. Whendisparate lines are visible in Kuyper's work, it is our responsi-
bility to embrace the one that is most scriptural and consistently to follow
through onit in the light of the Word revelation.
But that holds then for aif students of Kuyper.
An attempt undertaken to that end hence appeals to everyone who
thankfully links up with Kuyper.
>:
USING AND ABUSING
SCRIPTURE
the framework within which Christians live and move and understand their
being here.
The essay that follows talks about these issues, particularly as they re-
late to philosophizing: about the relationship of worldview to life and of
philosophy to the sciences. Whether Scripture informs both of these rela-
tionships, and if so how, provesto be the pivotal issue.
Vollenhoven never really focused much on worldview as such. As a
result how he saw the relationship between worldview and academic disci-
plines, including philosophy, is not always as transparent as a generation
trying to play catch-up on this point might like. His remarks on the topic
are often made in passing. One reason he did not deliberate the issue was
because it was not a "problem" for him. His worldview and thefact thatit
was supposed to influence his philosophizing was simply pre-supposed, a
second nature assumption picked up from Kuyper & Co.
Vollenhoven, however, was explicit concerning what he meant philo-
sophically by "presuppose." In his lecture notes from 1927(ms37)there is a
short but noteworthy statement, that probably also sheds somelight on his
problem-historic method:
The “subject [onderwerp]” of philosophy is not a word, but what is presup-
posed [het onderstelde] in a problem, Its “subject” is that which is “given,”
what is placed-under [onder-steld] the question posed so as to solve it. A
philosophic “predicate” is likewise not a word, but that which, in the answer,
fills in what was still uncertain in the problem as to what needed to fill that
place when the question was posed. It is the momentof certainty in the propo-
sition that replaces the momentof uncertainty in the question.
Vollenhoven just assumed—it was a given—that everything must be directed
to the glory of God in love-filled obedience, from his Christian walk and
worship to his philosophizing (which was, of course, part of his walk).
Whathe said of his mentor Prof. Geesink (in 27290) also holds for himself:
He "was convinced about the possibility of a science that would not continu-
ally break down his reformed christian life of faith, but could live in full
harmony with it. This conviction may have moved him in his work, butit
could not supplantthe labor of thinking andreflecting."
Literally, the Dutch word "Jevens- en wereld-beschouwing" would be
translated "view of life and view of the world." We will use both "world
and life view" as well as the more common "worldview." Although Vol-
lenhoven never makesa pointofit again, he did record an interesting dis-
tinction when still a student. In a piece about Abelard published in
1914(a120), he writes that when there's a conflict between one's view of the
Trinity and of redemption, between dogmatics and ethics, the cause usually
will be found “in the life of one's own soul." Two presuppositions in this
context are, first, "the view you have of the Trinity dominates your concep-
tion of the world, as does your understanding of redemption your outlook on
Draft D JHK Translation Page 115
man efforts it is bound by the limits for that which is created. As a general
science it has to reflect on the structure of creatures and their ontic genesis,
on the place of the law and the structure of and mutual relationships among
man, animal, plant, and nonliving things. It is also supposed to be in line
with [stroken] the established knowledge (both the everyday knowing and
Special scientific knowledge) of the philosopher. The task Vollenhoven
gives the philosopher is to build on and be in agreement with both; with this
stipulation, at least through 1939, that the philosopher build on theseto the
extent that she "does not catch either making mistakes" (30d10/39h9),
Asfor the relationship of philosophy to other ways of human knowing,
Vollenhoven always gives clear priority to the nonscientific knowing of ey-
eryday. Anyone's philosophy, be they Buddhist or Baptist, remains depen-
dent on their worldview, even more so than the special sciences are. With
its glimpse of the whole, which, as we will see, any philosopher needs,
philosophy actually stands closer to the practical wisdom of everyday than
does any other science (36hh163; 41011; 35e1). But what kind of depen-
dence does philosophy have on worldview? Vollenhoven seems to give two
different but compatible answers to this question. The one answeris a con-
ceptual one, namely, of nonscientific basis and theoretic superstructure.
Philosophy is seen as the scientific formulation or theoretic assimilation of
the world and life view (56b1), in such a way that the scientific concepts,
“negatively, may not be incompatible with and, positively, should be in
agreement with [the nonscientific concepts]" (48f64; see below, 182). Phi-
losophy formulates what the worldview circumscribes. The advantage being
“that the entire process is summarized and can be conveyed in unambiguous
terms” (35438). The second answeris quite different in character. Here
philosophy is described as translating the deepest yearning of the human
heart: "the philosophic endeavor, if it is going to be done well, must
be
dominated by the longing ofthe ‘love, poured out in our hearts by the
Holy
Spirit'” (37d7; 45e27). These two answers are evidence of the fact that
Vollenhoven's systematics was the result of an inner connection between
an
inspired faith commitment and the intensive work of theoretic reflection.?
Vollenhoven knew full well that many before him had been
moved by
faith and in their thinking had reckoned with Scripture. But
he was also
convinced that in so doing many had compromised and warped some
basic
biblical themes. Butin this regard, for all his instructions about
avoiding
negative descriptions, Vollenhoven, all told, breaks his own rule
that one
can best concentrate on the positive formulation. When it comes to
the use
of Scripture in relation to philosophizing, he has more to say about
how
things have gone wrong onthis score than about how best to proceed.
In
this essay, as elsewhere, he distinguishes three typical ways in
which using
Scripture and doing philosophyyield less than desirable results.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 118
(1) By far the most pervasive way in which biblical themes are mixed
with philosophy is the method of eisegesis-exegesis. The words "eisegesis"
and “exegesis” are derived from Greek compounds meaning “to bring into"
and "to lead out of." This procedure usually involves a “high view of
Scripture" that unconsciously ends up reading into the text, as in "reading
between the lines," what is not there, sometimes even interjecting what is in
conflict with Scripture. Then, when these foreign elements have been, so to
speak, read into the text, they are, when “just reading what the text says,"
taken out again, through unsound exegesis. Questionable beliefs and pagan
thought pattems are unwittingly carried into the text, in such a way that it
seems that the Bible sanctions them! Often it happened in the early church
that Christians in their debate with the pagans would say: "We believeit,
not because you say so, but because we know it from the Bible.” In such
cases they were trying not only to reckon with what Scripture reveals, but to
extract from the text a complete philosophy-in a chapter and verse, biblicis-
tic fashion. But what happens in these cases is that people are simply mak-
ing explicit what was implicit to their understanding already before going to
Scripture. This type of synthesis continues to cause endless grief within the
Church: Christians running the race under the umbrella of God's grace
nonetheless read different theories into Scripture and consequently run into
serious conflict with each other.
(2) A second kind of synthesis avails itself of a paradox. This
“method” is hard to comprehend because it implies a contradiction in one’s
thinking: a point of view is accepted that is at the same time realized to be
contrary to Scripture. In other words, paradox synthesis believes Scripture,
because it is the word of God, but also current philosophy—philosophy after
all is philosophy!—all the while recognizing that "here and there" they are
in conflict with each other. Hence the paradox: both Scripture and the ar-
guments of philosophy are true. Something similar is going on when a
christian school says on the one hand to do everything to the glory of God
and, on the other hand, advocates a behavioristic vision of culture that,
along with B. F. Skinner, is optimistically convinced that we have as yetto
see what man can make of man. Clearly, this is an untenable position. Yet
it constitutes an improvement on the method of eisegesis-exegesis, for it re-
alizes that logical argument cannot simply, withoutcritique, be incorporated
into what we know onthebasis of Scripture.
(3) The third kind of accommodation to unredeemed thought Vollen-
hoven calls nature/grace synthesis. This disposition surfaced in the sixth
century, prepared the way for medieval Scholasticism, and produced condi-
tions for a process of secularization that ultimately resulted in the triumph of
humanism. Even today the christian community is plagued by the effects of
Draft D JHK Translation Page 119
a nature/grace mentality. Any sacred /secular dualism heard of today has its
roots here.
Vollenhoventraces this approach back to the Council of Orange which
when dealing with the state of man before and after the Fall, used terms that
distinguished and seemed to accept a difference between “natural grace” and
“supernatural grace." This set the stage for the notion that the Fall caused
man to lose something “super-natural." It was merely a matter of time be-
fore it was agreed which attributes could be assigned to “supernature," and
which ones to "nature." In effect, the anthropology implied by the Council
of Orange presents man as follows: before the Fall "natural" man possessed
a special measure of "supernature." When hefell, the “supernature” was
lost, while his "nature" remained essentially in tact. This common “nature”
—weakened by the Fall, but nonetheless present in everyone—still func-
tioned normally under the guidance of the "natural light of reason.” For as
Aristotle(!!) had said long ago: “reason” is the determining characteristic of
"natural man,”
This view of man became the basis for Scholasticism. According to
scholastic PhDs and ThDs, there are only those twoareas in life, namely,
the area of “nature,” which includes among other things the state, society,
philosophy, “reason,” law, and the sciences; then there is the area of "super-
nature," which includes grace, the Church, theology, faith, and "religion,"
The nature-grace framework sends theologians to divinity school, but re-
gards philosophy as “natural,” an expression of the “natural” man and there-
fore acceptable (to the extent it does not contradict what we know of and
from the “higher" realm of grace). Likewise, astronomy is astronomy and
zoology zoology. Consequently, there is no perceived need for a christian
philosophy on the one hand and, on the other, usually a receptive attitude to
whatis called "natural theology."
Medieval scholastics became very adept in their use of natural theol-
ogy. Can we know and describe God by means of "reason," by means of
tational arguments without using "the means of grace," like faith or Scrip-
ture? Vollenhoven cites proofs for the existence of God and repeated at-
tempts at logically explaining and describing the podhead, or how God
knows what he knows, as examples of misdirected projects of "unaided rea-
son” in service of the Creator. Along with John Calvin
(cf. institutes, 1,5,9), Vollenhoven was out to provide a more biblical alter-
native to natural theology. He celebrated the fact that God can be known
and worshipped, but also warned against reasoning and philosophizing about
God beyond what he has revealed about himself through Scripture and cre-
ation.
As we noted in Chapter One, synthesis philosophy, whatever its
method, is always an attempted combination, like irying to connect iron and
Draft D JHK Translation Page 120
End notes
foolishness. So also indirectly, and not always intended as such: knowledge and
error, So ‘believing in’ and ‘studying about,’ though different, are in no way at
odds. On the basis of this difference the Calvinist will not first of all measure his
neighbor according to logical and intellectual standards. At the same time, he
will also resolutely expect that those with the articulate arguments and a clear in-
tuition see this all as the outcomeof the primary (special) and secondary (general)
action of God's Spirit, and practice obedience, also in things logical, out of love
for him.”
3 “Advice to Christian Philosophers," 1984.....
SCRIPTURE USE
AND PHILOSOPHY
[/5316]
[INTRODUCTION]
The topic mentioned in the title may not be equated with that of "Scrip-
ture and philosophy." Naturally, Scripture and philosophy are presupposed
here, but (/5317) our use of Holy Scripture is something different from
Scripture itself. Scripture after all is divine. In contrast, our use of Scrip-
ture remains human. And while Scripture is holy, our use of Scripture, ev-
ery lime again, proves to be tainted with sin. Hence,its use lies at the level
of sinful human life, tied to Holy Scripture.
If we are going to talk then about Scripture use and philosophy, the
question is really: “How ought we be using Scripture when we are busy
philosophically?"
This question is going to be broached, of course, only among Chris-
tians. When people take no account of God and his word, this question nat-
urally is not a factor.
But even thoughthis question is asked only in christian circles does not
mean that the intent with which it is being posed is also always correct. The
very word “use” calls for caution here. This term need not, but can reflect a
misdirected intent. That is the case when westart with ourself and ask,
"What can I gain now from Scripture?" But, as | said, such a conception,
which must be labeled a misconception, is not inherent, so that, having
made the point, we can also move on.
What is more important is that we are not busy with Scripturefirst of
all philosophically. We do not go to Scripture in the first place as philo-
sophic people, but as people without anytitle, without any pretensions.
Holy Scripture directs itself first of all to the life of everyday. For
teaching, rebuking, but at the same time for consolation, so that we shall
have hope; so that our prospect as Christians will be toward things above; so
that we know there is a doorin life through which God comes in order to
speak to his people; a door through which we too with our response to that
divine Word may direct ourselves to God.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 123
Scripture Use and Philosophy
In the second place, that Word allows us to see the whole world as it is
created by God. It tells us that this world is created by God and that we
may never hold anything in this world for divine. This, too, is meant
primarily in a practical sense: idolize nothing, neither things nor people!
Furthermore, God has placed this world under his law: love-filled
obedienceis the first thing that is asked of every one.
In that regard, in the beginning there was no talk ofspecial sciences
and philosophy. Everyday life concurs with that: there are millions who
recognize Holy Scripture as God's Word and have learned to take God at his
Word. And ofthose millions more than 95 percent do not busy themselves
with special science or philosophy.
Nevertheless, Holy Scripture does have something to do with philoso-
phy. What can we say aboutthis relation?
The past teaches that people in christian circles usually laid the connec-
tion [between Scripture and philosophy] incorrectly. They proceeded from
what was originally a pagan conception and then turned to Holy Scripture.
The result was naturally a connection of pagan concepts with scriptural
themes. In other words, synthesis.
Survey texts are often in the habit of shortchangingthe history of syn-
thesis philosophy. This is understandable. When the relationship of Scrip-
ture and philosophy is not important then synthesis thinking and its results
will not be of interest either. But that standpoint cannot be the right one.
Synthesis philosophy introduced a large number of new themes. Besides
that, it dominated the thinking in western and southern Europe for about 15
centuries. These are two good reasons for not takingit lightly.
Further study shows that this epoch comprises three periods. The first
of these is the period of early christian thinking, the second that of the Mid-
dle Ages, and finally the period of the prereformation and “christian” Hu-
manism.
The first synthesis was the most original. Its results were assimilated
during the Middle ages into a learned scholasticism. The third period tried
in an antischolastic and reactionary turn to bring early christian thinking
backto life; only to find out to their disappointment that this did not work.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 124
Scripture Use and Philosopity
natural, Adam, in the state of innocence, had received the supernatural, but
forfeited it through the fall. The supernatural was said to have been restored
to the Christian by grace. The philosophy adopted from pagan thought be-
longed in turn to the realm of nature. But that philosophy also had thought
about God and had its own image of him. This was (/5318) an image other
than the church's, which subscribed in part to Holy Scripture and in part to
the tradition of eisegesis-exegesis. As a result, they ended up with a duality;
as had the paradoxical connection. Which is not to say they somehow
agreed with them. The reciprocal relationship of the pagan view and that of
the church was not paradoxical, but was referred to as that of portal and
culmination.
So these are the three connective frameworks of synthesis philosophy.
They managed to hold sway for some time. For example, they can be rec-
ognized in the three-cornered debates waged in scholastic style during the
early Middle Ages between thinkers like [Willem van Champeaux, Petnis
van Damiani and Lanfranc]. What did slowly change with the course of
history was the recruiting power of these three. The nature-prace approach,
which at the time of the church fathers had relatively few advocates, really
came into its own during the hey-day of the scholastics. But the other two
continued to hold people's interest as well. Still today biblical humanists
follow the reading in, reading out method; the followers of Kierkegaardlive
the paradox; and Roman Catholic thinkers, but Protestant ones as well, hold
to the nature-prace theme.
Those who notice this understand that the campaign we have to wage
toward a scriptural philosophy that is free of any kind of synthesis is partic-
ularly demanding.
[B. Scriptural philosophy]
What do we intend with the term "scriptural philosophy"?
First of all, we should not go to Scripture with our own conception in
place, looking for Scripture to sanction it, but, from our youth on,to let
Scripture have the last word in ourlives.
No one is born a philosopher. Everyone comes into the world as a
baby. Everyone begins their knowing lives with the nonscientific knowl-
edge of everyday experience. Infants already learn something about mom.
That infant is a littke human being. But don't read too much ofthe adult
into that young soul. On the other hand, don't walk around with the idea
that young children are actually little animals with nothing more to go on
than sense perceptions, and know their mother only for the food and warmth
she provides. Because they are young human beings, children also know
love and trust. That's also the way Holy Scripture sees them. David knew
aboutthat, that he trusted the Lord already as an infant; not that he could
Draft ® JHK Translation Page 126
Scripture Use and Philosophy
have translated that faith, at the time, into words. What we do find is a
dedication to God in the faith commitment of the parents. Sometimes there
is already then also a direct bond in trust with God, a being secure in his
love.
Then we grow up and get to know our parents, our brothers and sis-
ters, our surroundings. First the crib, then the room, after that the back-
yard, the street, acquaintances and friends, school.
This is all nonscientific knowledge. And what's so nice aboutthis is
that it is not a stage that passes. There are many things that do pass during
the years of childhood, but nonscientific knowing stays. We know each
other as man and woman with nonscientific knowledge. As parents we
know our children with nonscientific knowledge. Most of ouractivities ev-
ery day we carry out with nonscientific knowledge.
Over a period of time a view develops, a unified look, that is not sci-
entific, Jet alone philosophic. It's a worldview on life. Like: Humanism,
Catholicism, Lutheranism, Calvinism.
Calvinism, too, is nonscientific knowledge. But it is more than a vari-
ety of knowledge based on a gradually widening horizon as we continue to
come into contact with other people and extend our perception's purview.
Wetake a view of things along from home or work hard at appropriating
another one. It's not a scientific conception, but a view of God, of the
world, of life, of being human, of our neighbors, also of ourself.
This kind of view of things marks a person. The humanism of some
humanists, like the catholicism of some Roman Catholics, is written all over
them. There are even those who look like they're Calvinists. But the view
we are talking about is not scientific. There are stalwart Calvinists, men and
women, who have no more than a high school education, who couldn't go to
college or didn't want to, but who nonetheless support and encourage
calvinian activities in their prayer, involvement, and gifts.
With that I come to scientific knowledge. Scientific knowledge con-
tains special scientific knowledge, which limits itself to one field. But there
is also philosophic knowledge. These two are very closely connected with
each other, but do not coincide. Philosophy is the science that wants Lo
learn from all the special sciences, because it's interested in it all, but then
queries further, It is very much interested in the mutual connection of the
fields of investigation to which each special science is assigned one, butalso
in the method applied by each of these sciences as they proceed. Philosophy
is, therefore, the general science. Butit is not a big repository. What one's
view oflife is for nonscientific knowledge, that's what philosophyis for sci-
entific knowledge,
Draft D JHK Translation Page 127
Scripture Use and Philosophy
the opposition of good and evil, love and hate, obedience and disobedience
to the love commandis lost, but that the opposition of regularity and irreg-
ularity runs and cuts right through it.
The mutual relationship of these two laws is not a matter of higher and
lower functions. The love command claims the whole person and thestatis-
tical calculations of regularity and irregularity make sense for the knowledge
of the higher functions as well as of the lower functions. Nor can this rela-
tionship be reduced to a duality in sources of knowledge, as though the love
command could only be found with Scripture while regularity could be
found without it. The meaning of the love command becomes clear to us
only when we investigate the history of the cosmos; and the history of the
cosmos, which continues to play a major role in the sought after regularity,
cannot be understood unless we reckon with the broad lines of that history as
indicated in Holy Scripture.
It follows from a number of these things that even though incorrect
conceptions conceming the mutual relation of these laws are to be rejected,
both are definitely connected with each other.
This connection lies first of all in God. For behind both laws stands
his will. Think, for example, of the old distinction of the will of God's de-
cree and the will of his precept.
This distinction should not be equated with that of revealed and secret
wili. The first distinction touches on God's willing irrespective of its
knowability, the second one has to do with the relation of this willing to our
knowledge. In addition, the will of God's decree is not always completely
clear to us, while, on the other hand, the will of God's precept can also be
investigated by us to the extent that the precept has already been realized.
In this manner, finally, the meaning of positive law is also under-
standable. This law is certainly not the formulation of a discerned reg-
ularity. It does not record, describe, or explain anything, but aims to lead
life in a specific direction. Nor is it identical to the love command. Itis
actually because of this command that legislation has to be criticized repeat-
edly and, when that battle remains fruitless, rules that have been elevated to
positive jaws need to be replaced as quickly as possible with better ones.
But given the fact that positive law is identical to neither law as regularity
nor the love command, it can connect the two of them. That is why the au-
thorized office bearer has to take both of these into account when drafting
positive law. The sense of positive law is precisely this: that it positivize
God's love command in its specification for a [modally] qualified societal
connection, for one specific societal connection, during a specific time pe-
Tiod. Hence, a positive law binds only those who belong to the connection
in question, during the time it is valid. But it does so as the command of
God, all be it indirect. Think here of the motivation for this kind of respect
Draft B JHK Translation Page 130
Scripture Use and Philosophy
found in the Heidelberg Catechism [Q&A 104]: “for through them God
chooses to rule us."
Obviously, here too, many questions remain, The above is nothing
more than an endeavor that seeks to contribute to showing how calvinian
philosophy, also in its analysis of the concept of law, has its eyes open to
the demands of the special sciences as well as of everyday life, while
remaining trueto its religious basis. [ 5319//]
6.
DIFFERING WITH
DOOYEWEERD
lies in the fact that Vollenhoven directly addresses differences between him-
self and Dooyeweerd; something he did not do in the context of the class-
room until 1963 and not in a public forum until 1968.*
After a very gentle apology for why there are differences among like-
minded people and what can be done aboutit, Vollenhoven highlights three
points of divergence: (1) Dooyeweerd's talk of the law-side and subject-side
of the cosmos and his own distinction within the law between love com-
mand, lawful regularity, and positive law; (2) how time relates to the differ-
ence between heart and functions; and, only very briefly, (3) the difference
between faith as function and faith as heartfelt commitment. His 1953 essay
"Religie en geloof" begins to address the last question more extensively, but
is not included in this volume. The threefold law is the mainstay in Chapter
Seven, so we will leave that topic until then. Which leaves us with the
question of time: with Vollenhoven's understanding of time as past, pre-
sent, and future of creaturely change and with Dooyeweerd's claim that
modal order is an order of time and, more importantly, that the religious
center of a human being is the supratemporal root, a transcendent con-
centration point, of the modally qualified temporal aspects of that person's
functioning and that Jesus Christ is the true supra-individual concentration
point of the entire temporal cosmos.
One way to get at this difference between Vollenhoven and Dooye-
weerd is to focus on their understanding of how philosophy positions itself
with respect to the whole ortotality of the cosmos. Both agree that the cos-
mos in genera] and people in particular have a religious root and a divine
origin.? They also agree that philosophizing is a human activity directed to
the totality of the cosmos and is, as al] human activity, rooted in the human
heart (soul, self) which itself falls beyond the limits of theoretic analysis.
For Dooyeweerd, "Meaning is the being of all that has been created
and the nature even of our selfhood.” This implies that philosophy is
“theoretical thought directed towards the totality of meaning." In order to
glimpse or grasp this whole, I must “choose nry standpoint [not over against
or above or beyond, but] in this totality of meaning,” lest this totality, the
meaning of our temporal cosmos, “remain strange to me": “In my central
selfhood I mustparticipate in the totality of meaning [—in the Archimedean
point of philosophy)... if [ am not to lose myself in the modal speciality of
meaning...." This time-transcending Archimedean point “must truly be the
concentration-point for philosophic thought and as such it must transcend the
modal diversity even in its coherence." On the other hand, in transcending
temporal diversity, the philosopher is equipped for the task: "The intent of
philosophy is to give us a theoretical insight into the coherence of our tem-
poral world as an inter-modal coherence of meaning.” A person's selfhood
is a “radical religious unity,” the concentration-point of one's individual ex-
Draft x JHK Translation Page 133
istence, but not of the entire temporal cosmos. Forthat, the self must come
to share in the new root of humanity, in the Second Adam. Thecentral and
radical unity of our existence is "at the same time individual and supra-indi-
vidual; that is to say, in the individual I-ness it points beyond the individual
ego toward that which makes the whole of mankind spiritually one in root,"
namely today, toward Jesus Christ, "the religious root of existence." The
fulness of meaning, as totality and radical unity, in which we participate in
Christ, “is not actually given and cannot be actually given in time, though
all meaning refers beyond itself to its supra-temporal fulfillment.” "[This]
deeper totality necessarily transcends the mutual coherence of all modal as-
pects of temporal reality, just as our selfhood transcends the coherenceofits
functions in these aspects.”
This introduction is just a draft and is not complete.
Draft x JHK Translation Page 134
' See A. Tol and K.A. Bril, eds., Vollenhoven ais wijsgeer: Inleidingen en teksten
(Amsterdam: Buijten en Schipperheijn, 1992) 108-111. Tol’s primary indicators
for dating the piece are threefold: a faculty meeting on 5-7 April 1952 during
which Vollenhoven raised five of the three points elaborated on in this piece; the
threefoid distinction in the law, which was presented in a public context for the
first time at a conference on 6 January 1953 (being the Scripture use piece from
the previous chapter), is presumed in this report; and the apparent revision on
Vollenhoven's part concerning the expression of time in the arithmetic and spatial
modes of earthly being. This last point is somewhat technical, but is probably not
as new a revision as Tol suggests. Two examples easily documentthat the arith-
metic and spatial modes with respect to time were different for Vollenhoven from
the start. In 1926(a55), the order of the modes ran: logic, number, space, time,
movement, energy.... By 1927 the analytic mode followed the psychic and time
was no longer modal: “time is neither an individual or a modal difference. But
we do find it in all the modalities of an individuality” (31124). In 1930 and 1931,
the difference between these two modes and the others is said to lie in the fact
that the arithmetic and spatial are “non-active” (30d37; 31f33). So, Vol-
lenhoven's struggle with these two modes was not something peculiar to the early
1950s. Secondly, given what we have seen of Vollenhoven's long standing dis-
tinction between law and command (97) and that the place ofpositive law is ac-
knowledged from early on, points we will return to in the next chapter, the three-
fold distinction of the law is likewise not as unique to 1952 or 1953 as Tol sug-
Bests.
2 See in A. Tol and K.A. Bril, eds., "Problemen rondom de tijd” (1963) 160-198:
and “Problemen van detijd in onze kring” (1968) 199-211.
3 For Dooyeweerd neither the speciality (= diversity) of meaning nor the totality of
meaning exist by itself, but suppose "an archté, an origin which creates meaning”:
"All meaning is from, through, and to an origin, which cannotitself be related to
a higher arché.” Dooyeweerd refers to this dependence of meaning on the origin
as the “genetic relativity of meaning" and describes philosophic thought directed
to the origin as its “basic genetic tendency,” rooted in the “restlessness of our
ego... towards the arché of our selfhood and ofthe totality of meaning."
DIVERGENCES:
REPORTI
[/53mst11)
INTRODUCTION
Among the instructors of calvinian philosophy, not all of whom are
connected with the Foundation as professors, there exist a number of diver-
gences. They cameto the attention of Professor H.J. Van der Maas already
in the summer of 1949 and since then have surfaced repeatedly during the
study conferences of the Association [for Calvinian Philosophy].
It should come as no surprise that differences like these occur in this
group too. It can easy happen that not everyone sees a specific difficulty, or
possibility, at the same time. Even when they do, they will very likely,
given the different path each has covered to date and the different task with
which each is entrusted, not always follow the same method in resolving the
issue. Besides, these divergences can only produce objections when people
lose sight of the [/53ms112} tentative character of, or individual stamp on, the
results booked so far.
In positive protestant circles there is a dual corrective for these kind of
lapses. It is preserved in the saying [of Groen van Prinsterer): "It is written
and it has happened." In our circles this amounts to: work continually by
the light of Holy Scripture and reflect on the history of philosophy in gen-
eral and on that of our own groupin particular.
Whencarrying out this twofold requirement, however, intensive delib-
erations among those concerned may not be lacking. That is why thankful
use is made of the Coetus Docentium [Meeting of Faculty] that was set up
by the foundation's board.
BACKGROUND
Taking stock of the prehistory of calvinian philosophy, we see that its
fathers were influenced by the Marburpers and Husserl. Since that time, of
course, the work of these schools has also been subjected to a foundational
critique within our circles. But the course ofaffairs just mentioned has left
its marks here and there. In the theory about being, too muchattention is
focussed now and then on the functions and in the theory of knowledge, the
interest shown in special scientific knowledge is often too one-sided. One
result is that the rest of that which is created is easily referred to as thoughit
had something "mystical" about it. But we cannot forget that this “rest” in-
cludes the heart, the Church, the human nature of the Mediator, and the
world of angels, among other things, and demands that we make many more
distinctions and, of course, are also very careful when deciding on the ter-
minology.
OVERVIEW
Ordered systematically, the most significant difficulties concern the
following [/53ms113) points: (a.) law and subject, (b.) the structure of that
which is subject and time, and (c.) the prefunctional.
A. Lawand subject
For a long time Dooyeweerd and Vollenhoven stood some distance
from each other on this point. Dooyeweerd placed both law and subject in
the cosmos; using the term "cosmos" to refer to the part of that which is cre-
ated that finds its centrum in man. That is why hedistinguishes within the
cosmos law-side and subject-side, which he takes to be related as that which
is universal to that which is individual. In contrast, Vollenhoven spoke of
the triad God-law-cosmos, in the sense that God exists independent of law
and cosmos andis not their correlate, but sets the law for the cosmoshe cre-
ated such that law and cosmos (cosmos taken as a whole) are each other's
correlate. That is why he could not talk about the "law-side” and "subject-
Draft D JHK Translation Page 137
Divergences
side" of the cosmos. He understood the law to always stand above the cos-
mos, such that what was subject to this law was identical to the cosmos and
not one ofits sides.
With time both standpoints have approached each other in part.
Dooyeweerd wants to distinguish the ius divinum (divine law) in its temporal
refraction of meaning from the ius Aumanum (human law). Vollenhoven
also wants, in addition, to talk about law in the sense of regularity in the
cosmos,
Yet differences remain. Even leaving the “temporal refraction of
meaning” and the rather juridical connotations of "ius" stand for the mo-
ment, Vollenhoven considers the distinction of ius divinum and ius hu-
manuto be inadequate. He feels that a three-part distinction is called for:
(1) the Jaw of God that stands as norm above the cosmos, that on earth
touches only man directly, and that holds for the other creatures only indi-
rectly, in other words, only via man; (2) the cosmos, including man; and (3)
the positive law, through which office bearers, given their office in their
modally qualified and regionally defined societal connection, positivize
God's law, correctly or not, primarily for human life.
Re |: "Norm" here refers to “the Jaw of the Lord,” summarized by
Christ in the double love command. This law holds primarily only for hu-
man life. It makes no senseto talk about christian animals, plants, or physi-
cal things. But human life, too, can only be more or less in line with this
law. Even when human beings in their living obey this law (for example,
earlier in Paradise and presently in the human nature of the Mediator), they
in no way coincide with it. [/53ms11¢) Besides, the norm stands as holy over
against what is subject to it, which, except in the human nature of the Medi-
ator, since the fall is always, at least in part, not holy but sinful. That's
why Scripture can talk about the “curse of the Law" for those subjects who
transgress it and why cosmos (“world'), according to Scripture's religious
dialectic, in different places means "God's awesome creation,” "what's
warped by evil,” and "what's being saved.”
Re 2: In contrast, the rules or, if one prefers, laws in the cosmos have
to do with the regularity both of what does and of what does notline up with
the law in the sense of norm. Statistics can be assembled conceming dips
and rises in the number of murders committed as well as about frequencies
in the numberof live births. This area obviously is not disassociated from
the good-evil opposition. What Scripture is speaking about in terms ofthe
guilt or iniquity of sins are likewise facts that go into defining the subse-
quent course of affairs. But the difference remains. Therelation of guilt to
the norm is something other than rules and exceptions in the structure.
That's why when scientists examining the structure in the cosmos find an
Draft D JHK Translation Page 138
Divergences
exceplion to what they thought was a rule, they look for a more en-
compassing rule that includes this deviation as well.
This insight sheds light on the mutual difference of normative and non-
normative laws. This difference does not correspond with that of higher and
lower modalities, For example, health stands over against sickness also in
the psychic and biotic modalities as the correlate of conforming to the norm
or not; so also with physical things, we read that they obey the Mediator.
Nor [does it correspond] with that of summary and temporal refraction of
meaning. For apart from the question of temporality, to which wewill re-
turn, the difference between the unity in the core and the diversity in the
elaboration is present in the norm as well as in what is subject to it. In ad-
dition, the diversity among the commandmentsof the second table of the law
is in no way correlate with the diversity of modalities in the outer cloak of
human functions.
Re 3: The difference between the law of God as norm and thepositive
law does not require as broad a discussion. The one thing that should be
noted is that the office bearers themselves are also subject to the norm in the
various societal connections. Scripture refers to them, on the one hand, as
“gods,” but also as "normal people.” Their work, too, always remains ac-
countable to the norm to which they and their countryman are bound in their
consciences, also when their task of positivizing implies that they have to
take their fellow citizen's hardness of heart [/53ms115] into account.
C. The prefunctional
Finally, we want to draw your attention to difficulties in connection
with the prefunctional [heart], apart from the question of time. Up until
now the anthropology of calvinian philosophy distinguished the heart and
the cloak of functions, taking faith to be the highest function.
From different sides a number of cbjections have been raised against
this view. They have to do in part with the place of faith taken in the sense
of allegiance, which cannot be functional, and also in part with the view of
the church as institute, especially its diaconate and discipline, to the extent
this also has validity for the kingdom of heaven.
To the extent these objections have not arisen from within our ranks,
they come to us from reformed Christians who should be taken seriously.
Meeting their objections would further our work immensely. On the other
hand, we have to maintain this distinction, lest we end up with the position
that the [/53ms117] instituted church either ought to dominatetheentire life of
the Christian oris really not a distinct societal connection. Neither of these
seem right to us. In the near future serious attention will also be given to
this point.
7.
TRACES OF THE
TRINITY
Commemoration lecture for the Utrecht chapter of the $.S.R. held on Octo-
ber 13, 1955° by Prof. dr. D.H.Th. Vollenhoven
Ourlife can be and ought to be of one piece. In this sense the unity of
life stands over against the brokenness oflife.
Of late, people speak almost exclusively about life's brokenness. If
this happened in a christian spirit, that would be one thing. Then we would
simply have to caution against being one-sided; even though that emphasis is
understandable to the extent we need to be reminded that since the fall we
will find unity of life only within life's brokenness. But the mind-set that
wants to discuss the topic "brokenness oflife" is a completely different one.
Orientating themselves to the recent past, people point out that reason with
its apriori concepts has fallen hopelessly short not only in the area of sci-
ence, but in practical things as well. That is why they disqualify reason. It
is not banned from the choir, but it will no longer carry the melody. Rising
above the voices assigned to theoretical and practical reason one hears the
shrill cry of the existentialist who, after dismissing history among other
things, only allows for reasonless decisions in concrete situations, and in so
doing tries to be "historical."
In many ways, this brokenness can be understood. Likewise, many
who have experienced this brokenness deeply deserve our pity. It is no
small matter if someone like Kierkegaard [1813-1855] collapses on a street
in Copenhagen at the age of 52 as a result of the seriousness with which he
sought to implement this existential attitude toward life. Yet his pursuit suf-
fered from a fatal misunderstanding that, given the fact that manystill today
are attempting to combine Christianity and existentialism, should certainly
be acknowledged. For the brokenness existentialism is getting at differs
fundamentally from the brokenness that Christianity recognizes. When Paul
moans “All fall short of the glory of God," that is something different from
being riddled in the cross-fire of rationalism and irrationalism. Paul's words
go much, much deeper. Pau! does not have the recalcitrance that ultimately
brings people, failing to free themselves from the rationalistic view of law
and at their wits end, to proclaim lawlessness. In contrast, Paul's words rest
on the weight of the fact that we do not measure up to God's norm: we
don't make the grade, and those who went before us were nobetter.
Given with the created-being of that which is created is also its struc-
ture. For that which is created does not exist as a loose collection of sepa-
rate things. Within creation we discern kinds. Not in a morphological sense
that things are similar to each other, but in a genealogical sense. Creatures
are individual, but nevertheless capable of splitting, of reproducing, of
mating, of having intercourse. These kinds, in other words, know an earlier
and later. In addition, to the extent we are dealing with real kinds, which
naturally have variations, they are all created according to their own nature.
The higher kind does not come forth out of a lower one, but in the same
realm the later generation does come forth out of an earlier one. There is
evolving, but no evolution. This is not a process of constructing in the
mechanical sense of the word. The following kingdom does not originate
because an extra level is added to the things of the former, In each kingdom
the things are fully structured [doorgestructureerd|. They form an inner
unity. A plant is not a collection of atoms held together by a biotic ent-
elechy, nor is an animal a collection of plants to which an emotive life is
added from above.
Let me give an exampleofthis integral unity, of being fully structured.
Animals and human beings perceive things and in doing so use their senses.
These senses are organs. As organs they can be impaired as well as healthy.
When medically examined, they are treated as organs. When J] go to the
optometrist he doesn't ask me to read the letter charts straightaway, but first
has melook at a little red light while he uses a bright focused light to inves-
tigate if there is possibly 2 problem inside my eyes that he can't correct.
Only when they prove to be healthy does he check whether my eyes’ lenses
display any deficiencies.
But now this is what is unique: although the eye is an organ, we look
in vain for something like an eye in organisms. Plants have nothing analo-
gous to it. Sense organs are organs, but they are absent in organisms, in
other words, in things that are typified by the organic function, as the high-
est function they have. Organic things like eyes are only found in animals
and human beings, pointing forward to their activity in higher functions.
Human life, as well, is structured in this integral way.
It is not so that we are made up of a body, a group of sub-psychic
functions, on the outside, to which is added a soul that contains therest.
Even less so are we constituted by a body, soul, and intellect. All of these
are present in that unity, be it only on the out-side. For the unity of man
mustfirst of all be distinguished in an inner and outerlife.
Thus we see a lawfulness in the work of the Father. But there is more,
We speak of the Father and our creation, of the Son and our deliverance. In
the Catechism, as a book for general instruction,that is fine. But tonight we
must not be too hasty in this regard. We can only speak of redemption after
Draft ® JHK Translation Page 149
The Unity ofLife
misery has made its appearance. But the Son was busy long before that. As
Logos he is God in his speaking to the people, God revealing his Word.
This is a second [law]. It is not a command that creates nor is it a
structuring activity. Creation in all of its diversity is already presupposed
when the Word revelation begins. Man is there as well. But then something
new happens to man. Humankind was not separated from the rest of cre-
ation, but put in an exceptional position. And the Logos, God in his speak-
ing, then addresses man, revealing to him the thoughts ofhis heart.
This happened in paradise already, before the fall and completely inde-
pendent of it. At the time there is yet no talk of deliverance nor of the
knowledge of misery mediated by this Word revelation. It's the glory of the
Creator that is revealed. God speaks about his work to the man and also
shares with him something of his vision for humankind, and of the task that
awaits him. In speaking to the man in this way, God is showing his interest
in him, When God instructs Adam to take note of the animals and to give
them names on the basis of his findings, then God looks on, interested in the
results. For whatever Adam would call the animals, that would be their
name.
It is similar to that of a father who carefully observes what his child
can do already, It is early evidence of God's favor. Human beings are pre-
sented here as friends of the Lord and as co-workers.
There is actually more here than just the norm, The norm within this
Word revelation is simply that God wants something, that God gives the
commission to work the garden and to take care ofit: to workit, so that the
garden becomes fruitful; and to take care of [shamar, to guard] it, so that it
remains protected against the enemy man had yet to meet.
And in this way that Word revelation, including the norm, becomes a
source of blessing. When Adam sees the animals and observes them in the
congeniality of their nest life, he draws the analogy with himself, and he
misses something.
That first human being is special; for soon, out of him, another human
will be created. He is special in still another respect, for he is the first
Adam, the office bearer. But, on the other hand, he is also just a normal
human being. He has a need for companionship and, more specifically, for
the companionship of a woman. That is why God's providing him with Eve
is the solution to a problem he posed himself and the fulfillment of a wish.
We find here a relationship of Word revelation, of God speaking to
man, and the waiting for an answer. Only later, once the fall has set in and
the office is forfeited, does the norm in the Word revelation becomea source
for knowing misery. But by then also much has happened with the nature of
man. Notthat it has been lost. Not even partially: that nature has remained
Draft B JHK Translation Page 150
The Unity ofLife
exactly the same; and yet it is completely changed, because its direction
turned around.
Humankind went, as it were, from right to left. God's co-worker
turned to one who flees before the face of the Lord. Consequences followed
straightway. God in his wrath came to man saying: You should not have
done this. You believed the wrong one.
There are also repercussions for human life. Adam and Eve wereini-
tially alienated not only from God, but also from each other. And later Cain
slays his brother.
There are consequences for the relationship between humankind and the
rest of creation as well. The earth is cursed "because of you." Man's labor
will be made difficult. The land will bring forth thorns and thistles. And
soon the earth will rear up against human life when it is forced to drink the
first human blood.
That will live on later as well. Then that norm will indeed become a
source for knowing misery. People in Sumer, centurieslater, will still know
that immortality was snitched from man by a snake. Still later, in Greece,
when Socrates, the idol of so many humanisis, claims that nobody intention-
ally does what they know is wrong, Euripides contests that position. He
registers his protest when he has a heroine say: We know whatis right, but
we don't do what is right; some because of sloth or because of some other
vice that they prefer to what is noble. This is what Holy Scripture calls con-
sciences accusing and excusing each other.
The law can also be known through tradition. This has nothing to do
with the Stoics’ construct of natural law, but it is something upheld by God.
And even thoughit is a source for knowing our misery, the law that is found
thereis still a blessing.
Word revelation continues. It also speaks of grace.
Law and Gospel do not oppose each other. Because when the law ac-
cuses, then the Gospel comes proclaiming the deliverance that God has de-
vised. The law and the Gospel are opposites only for those who negate the
law's charge; for the Pharisee who still thinks he can fulfill the law. But
they conflict so little that both law and Gospel are heard from the mouth of
the same Logos, from the same Person in the Divine Being.
And also later, rather than doing away with the law when he comes
down to earth to bear its curse for us, he discloses its deep meaning. He
shows that the law requires love, not only for the compatriot, but also for
the enemy. Shortly thereafter, he asks for mutual love in a new command,
in a new community to be founded by his blood. With that heis pointing
toward the work of the Spirit, who pours the love out in us, in our hearts.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 151
The Uniry ofLife
Finally, there is a third law as well: the law of the Spirit. There is
talk of it already at creation. It is the law of the culmination. The Spirit of
God moves over the waters, and then things begin to happen with that work
of the Father.
That Spirit is also present in paradise. For a moment there, the ques-
tion was: will humanity, undivided and unswerving through the course of
time, allow God's Spirit to lead it to the finish or was something going to
intervene? Would humanity be divided, split up, and were those who would
once again follow the Spirit's leading only going to reach the goal after a
long detour?
The answer proved to be the negative one: notall will follow. For
them, the law of death revealed itself in the course of their lives, But on the
other side, there are likewise also many in whose lives the law of the Spirit
of life reveals itself, even though they had to reach their life's goal via a
detour.
In this way the fall intersects the work of the Spirit. But the Spirit's
leading proceeds uninterrupted. He maintains the structure of human nature
and through his work there are men and women who not only hear the norm,
but also listen to it. These are ones who accept and embrace the promises of
the Gospel still, however unbelievable they may sound, and who keep on
trusting the Logos.
Among these are the very first human beings. Adam in faith, in spite
of the misery in which they found themselves, soon calls Eve the mother of
all the diving.
TheSpirit's leading occurs in part through the offices: also via the par-
tial offices.{+)
The Holy Spirit does not recognize any geniuses. It does recognize
people who receive special protection from the Spirit, people who are given
special gifts by the Spirit. These include the builders of the temple as well
as rulers. The Spirit of the Lord even comes to Saul, in spite of his unre-
pentant heart. Through officials like these, the Spirit wants to uphold the
nation. He causes them to contend for authority and against revolution, to
shelter, in compliance with the sixth commandment, life against death, to
protect marriage from divorce, property from theft, good repute from libel,
and the love there is in life from the hate.
Butit is the same Spirit that withdraws grieving when Saul, after he's
become king in Israel, raises up a pillar for himself, desiring to deprive her
of its view of the future and of the Messiah. The Spirit also guards against
smaller sins. For example, when David misuses his authority to pursue his
private lusts and sendsa letter along with Uriah that contains a signed war-
Draft D JHK Translation Page 152
The Unity ofLife
rant for his death. It is also the same Spirit that strikes David when his
pride brings him to order a census of the people.
The same Spirit is also involved with the consummate office, with the
Man Jesus Christ, because he receives the Spirit, the Spirit of the office,
without measure.
The Spirit also works outside Israel in the same way. There is not only
a hardness of hearts in human nature, but also a working for the good. Tne
government that does the task it ought need not describe the situation it en-
counters. It can leave that to science. The governmentis not there to study,
but to govern, even though it will have to make use of the results of all
kinds of research. What's the government to do then?
The government builds bridges between those other two laws for our
benefit. \t applies the norm of Godto the situation as it presents itself in
that jurisdiction and at that time.
In that way government can be a blessing to life.
It preaches as well, but not the law of God as such. It does not de-
scribe life, but applies God's law to the situation that's there.
Paul does the very same thing as apostle. He is confronted by bigamy.
It was quite common in those days. Paul determined that office bearers
could only have one wife. He is not introducing a double standard here, but
giving pedagogical leadership. Those whoare called to lead must also set an
example. Pretty soon the entire congregation will follow suit. And that is
what happened too. Even in circles long alienated from the Word, bigamy
is spoken aboutin horror and disgust.
And so we have found three types of law: in creation, in the Word
revelation, and in the Spirit's leading.
But these laws are not just loosely associated each other. Neither are
the Father and the Son and the Holy Spirit. These three are one. The
church with its confession of the Trinity has turned itself against separating
God's being one and being three. Monarchianism, for example, taught that
separation: it sought to preserve unity as highest final cause, the thinking of
thought, and placed the threefold distinction in a universal intellect that ac-
tualizes the thought of human beings. No, said the church, the same Godis
simultaneously one and three.
There is also a certain sequence. The Son most definitely does not
come to confound the work of the Father, but that of the devil. The Holy
Spirit presupposes the work of the Son, proclaiming that, in tum, to the
people. This threesome, however, is not the principle for the periods of
world history nor doesit give us grounds for speculating aboutthe relation-
ship of universality and individuality.
Likewise, the law is threefold and yet a unity. It is, as it were, parallel
with the Trinity of the God who gives us that law. This gives rise to the
Draft D JHK Translation Page 153
The Unity ofLife
supposition that real unity of life can only be had where we hold to the tri-
une law of the Triune God.
Ii.
That is why we not only have to know that law. We must also ac-
knowledge it and submit ourselves to it. But watch your step with these
trinitarian traces (vestigia Trinitatis). There has always been a good deal of
speculation. Caution is required.
The gravest dangers are avoided by remembering that such a threefold
unity in our human lives is possible only under the law, precisely in connec-
tion with the threefold character of the law. God sets the law. The worldis
not God's correlate nor an emission of his being. It is created by him and
put under the law he gave. The worldis not correlate with God but with the
law.
How are weto listen to these Jaws then? To take them seriously and to
submit to them?
Wedoso first of all in the wisdom that knows God and oneself; that
knows God as King, Lawgiver, Judge: and that trusts him as the one who
will save us.
But we must do so then in practical, everyday knowledge as well as in
the sciences.
Practical knowledge comes first.
The mistake of contemporary existentialism is precisely the priority
given to science. After recognizing that that doesn't work, they put the do-
main of practical reason in its stead, only to embrace irrationalism when
practical reason falls short as well.
The order should be reversed. How we sequence these things should
be dictated not by the course ofaffairs in a failed Europe, but by the struc-
ture of life as God has made it. What is primary then is the knowledge of
God and ofourselves. {t is on this basis that we move into everyday life.
Nonscientific knowledge is not only prescientific. It is there prior to sci-
ence, but it also remains. We enjoy this kind of knowing so much, even
when a person's life is by and large devoted to science.
50, practical knowledge comesfirst.
Then we have to think about the structures and natures [of things] as
they are created. We needto distinguish different fields. It is hardly sur-
prising thatthis insight is acknowledged so seldom, but people always relied
on the philosophy that took the intellect to be the highest and could not ac-
cept it when the intellect distinguished all kinds of other activities in man.
That led them to talk about epiphenomena,or to think they were dealing
here with arbitrary creations of the human mind.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 154
The Unity ofLife
under the preaching of the Son who wants to save the understanding too and
to sanctify it for his service through his Spirit.
Yet finally, in that practical knowledge of everyday there is also the
law of the Spirit's leading. It is there that we see the value of positive law
which tries as government to apply God's will, his law, to a specific situa-
tion that in no way meets that law. That does not happen by decreeing: The
Netherlands is christian! But it can happen by giving leadership, proceeding
deliberately, moving things in a specific direction.
Wecan be very thankful when things work this way. And even if peo-
ple work differently than this we will continue to see in government some-
thing that in spite of itself still contributes to protecting authority from rev-
olution, sheltering life from death, safeguarding marriage, and so forth. We
will also still ask a blessing for those through whom Godsees fit to rule us.
We do that because we know they have not only the might but also the au-
thority and that authority, following a mediated path, comes from God.
Finally, we have to take this threefold law into account also when it
comes to scientific knowledge.
Talk about an endless task!
Butlife's unity is not supposed to begin with the unity in science.
Even when it comes to knowledge, we are to begin with wisdom, with the
wisdom that takes stock of the relationship of God and man, and of hu-
mankind to God.
Oncethis unity is grasped in principle, we will do that in everydaylife,
in the knowledge of everyday, and ultimately also in science. Life does not
demand that everyone goes to college. But the unity of life does require that
those who do go on to study and whoseek life's unity through faith in
Christ Jesus will also strive for unity in science.
And that unity is within the realm of possibilities.
That is also true if the task is to immerse oneself in the details of re-
searching just one aspect of that life. Just think again, for an analogy, about
everyday life. We all have many experiences, we are always meeting new
people. Someofus stay in the same locale, but every day brings something
new. Others God calls to relocate and they move into totally new sur-
roundings. Or some may make a long trip, multiplying their experiences
time and again. But poor is the person whoselife's knowledge is nothing
more than the added sum of all those experiences. That's tiring enough to
kill you!
We have a view of life and the world within which we can place all
those experiences. We have circumscriptive concepts. They too were given
to us. Not in the sense of apriori concepts. We received them through nur-
Draft JHK Translation Page 156
The Unity ofLife
ture and upbringing, in the light of God's Word or not. If we have a world
and life view informed by the light of that Word, we can situate all those
daily experiences, We won't get hoodwinked by the first faction that comes
our way dreaming of a new society, because we suspect every human being
who wants to work by their own power. On the other hand, we do notdis-
trust from moment to momentthe area where the Spirit of Christ is working.
We know from Holy Scripture, from his promise, and see confirmed in ex-
perience that despite all the frailty and indifference, much more comes of
things again and again than we could have ever hoped.
Just as a view of life and the world sets the practical knowledgeofall
experiencesin the right context, we have something similar when it comes to
science. The unity of those many fields of investigation rests in God's cre-
ation. Moreover, the unity of the many special sciences rests in the general
science [we call philosophy] that reflects on the mutual connection of those
fields and disciplines and also ponders the nature of such a discipline and the
method needed to study it. Philosophy can assist us in a way similar to how
a world and life view helps us. It precedes the many experiences of every-
day life. Not in an apriori sense, but as circumscriptive whole. I am not
talking here about some perk we could add to the rest and that is extremely
difficult. On the contrary, philosophy's aid can lend us support and bring us
further because, in the midst of the multitude of details, it keeps in view the
unity.
In this way, it is possible to seek the unity of life, not only through the
wisdom that comes with living, but also in practical and scientific knowing.
This unity is, of course, always a unity in brokenness. Butit is also a unity
of life that is founded in the unity a threefold law that itself goes back to the
Trinity of God confessed by the christian churchofail ages.
8.
INTRODUCING
PHILOSOPHY
PREFACE
First a few words concerning the name, purpose, and method ofthis
course and concerning the division of this syllabus,
1. Name
The name ofthis course consists of two parts: Thefirst is “isagoge";
to which is added as specification “philosophiae." We deal briefly with the
meaning of each of these words (a. and b.) and then with the meaning of
their combination (c.).
a, /sagoge is the transcription (rendering of a foreign word in the char-
acters of another language) of the Greek word “eisagoge." This word is a
compound of “eis-" "into" and “agoge" (from “agein") "a leading." Hence,
isagoge means introduction.
b. Philosophiae is an inflected form of “philosophia." This word is
also a compound. The constituent parts are “philos"—friendly and
“sophia"—wisdom. Hence, philosophy meanslove of wisdom.
Nowthis circumscription is very old; if we can believe tradition, it
stems from Pythagoras, a Greek philosopher from the sixth century B.C.
However, he combined it with a serious misconception. Pythagoras is re-
puted to have said that he, being a man, did not possess wisdom as did the
gods, but strove toward wisdom. He assumed that human thinking can as-
pire to the possession of divine wisdom. In orderto eradicate this miscon-
ception it is good to note at the outset that in the circumscription of
"philosophy" as “love of wisdom" we are concerned exclusively with what
human beings can attain, hence, with human wisdom.
As for the relationship of the term "philosophy" to this human wisdom,
note that though it first of all denotes this human striving, it also means
something else, namely, the complex of statements that express the knowl-
edge men obtained through this striving. Philosophy, therefore, signifies
both a deed and result.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 173
Tsagoogé Philosophiae
have an eye for difficulties that we ourselves did discern, and we thereupon
ignore them as well. Therefore, after reading a scientific work, the question
should always be asked, at least by those who want to work scientifically:
“Is what the author asserts correct, that is to say, does it comport well with
the state of affairs?" And only if one is of the opinion that this question may
be answered in the affirmative, can he uninhibitedly tum to writing, even
though this affirmative answer will be far from acceptable to many. In like
manner J.G. Walch gave an introduction to philosophy (1727}—1 mentionit
here because it is the oldest under that name in the time of the Renais-
sance—from a purely rationalistic standpoint. He maintained that what he
and those who thoughtlike him, the rationalists, had to say, was built on the
state of affairs.
A third group of introductions is prompted by the thought that the
problems with which philosophy was concerned hitherto were posed incor-
rectly, be it completely or in part. Such authors often begin with negations,
i.e, with the rejection of other theories, or at least integrate the same in their
exposition of what they claim to have found. J.G. Fichte (1797 and 1801)
and J.F. Herbert (1813) are examples of older writers, the Frenchman
Charles Renouvier (1895), the Dutchman J.P.N. Land (1889, 21900) and
J.G. Wattjes (1926), the Germans F. Paulsen (1892, 91924), O. Kiilpe
(1895, 121929), Erich Becher (1926), Wilhelm Wundt (1901, 81920) and W.
Windelband (1914, 31923),the Englishman G.S. Fullerton (1906) and B.
Russell (1912, 31918), and the Belgian L. Raeymaker (1938, 71944) are
more recent examples. Their works, which are to be used with the greatest
of caution given the fact that none stand on the scriptural standpoint, not
only acquaint us with what these writers positively claim, but also with what
they challenge.
Comment; The fact that some of these books were reprinted so often demon-
strates how great the need is for introduction, A need also recently expressed
in the cry for a “unity in style" in academic forming.
To the extent that their standpoint allows, these authors also deal with
the matters at issue. And everyone who does that can help us; everyone,
that is, to the extent they keep the limits of philosophy in mind and therefore
to the extent they philosophize well.
3. Method
A. The method of this course must in the first place be thetical. For the
point is to learn to approach the difficulties faced by thinking from one's
own point of view.
Comment: This thetical approach can never be replaced by historical ex-
positions: after all, the history of philosophy is something else than phi-
Draft D JHK Translation Page 175
Isagoogé Philosophiae
losophy. For that reason, science about this history (“historica”) is something
else than introduction.
A combination of these two methods such as has recently (1929) been at-
tempted by F. Heinemann does not foster clarity and is therefore not to be rec-
ommended.
only thing that a person does, it leads to nothing else but philosophic nihilism.
Usually a person stops before that. But even then, they do not always take
sufficient account of their own standpoint. This has the further consequence
that the formulation of a particular problem is accepted as correct but both the
negative and the positive answer to it are considered unsatisfactory. Hence
they combine the two: warning others for the one-sidedness of each of the two
parties separately, This kind of combination, if the question is indeed one that
can be answered by a clear cut yes or no, must be rejected, however. Forif
both parties are right-if this is not the case there would be no question of
combination—then the formulation of the problem is incorrect and must be re-
placed by another one and must not be cloaked by a combination,
A phenomenonthatis even less desirable is eclecticism. It usually does
not even penetrate as far as the problem, correctly formulated or not, but
simply supports a number of thoughts come across here or there, without
even bothering to inquire whether they are compatible,
It is by maintaining that which is tenable in one's own position, by
critically examining not only the result acquired by others but also the result
of one’s own thinking at an earlier time, and by having the courage to accept
the implications of one’s position, that one can make progress through
struggle and attain a double profit: a reinforced position and a more definite
rejection of whatever is inconsistent with it.
4, Division
The division of the material is correlate with the distinction within the
provisional result, that is to say, the distinction between positive and nega-
tive,
The positive must have precedence. If this is not the case, the anything
but imaginary danger looms that a person will never be done with his nega-
tion. Also the advocate of an opinion that is rejected has the right to know
what is behind the criticism that led to this rejection.
One way of proceeding is to take one particular question and deal with
it in a positive and then negative manner and consequently to turn to another
problem, etc. This procedure, however, meets with the following objection:
in order to clarify the diversity in the formulations of the question and an-
swers, it would be necessary in the case of every problem to outline the
schools of thought that have concerned themselves with this question and
would therefore necessarily lead to repetition. Hence preference must be
given, if only for reasons of economyoftime, to the procedure whereby the
positive result is given in a coherent whole.
This is, of course, not to say that whatever has implicitly been rejected
may also be ignored. Onthe contrary, it must be precisely presented in or-
der that people may also know and understand the conceptions and terminol-
ogy of others. This, however, should not be done in thepresent context, but
in the survey of the history of philosophy; forit is there that the different
Draft D JHK Translation Page 177
fsagoogé Philosephiae
schools of thought are outlined within the framework oftheir basic thoughts
and in the context of their historic period.
For these same reasons, the Isagoge gives an account of my ownposi-
tive result. In the few instances where a negative comment has been made,
the only purpose has been to clarify the implications of the position spelled
out in the text.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 178
fsagoogé Phitosophiae
INTRODUCTION
In order to not deal with entirely different matters at the same time, I
am not at this point going to consider the second part of this proposition.
Nor do I want to raise the question at this point of whether the whole
thought experiment upon which this assertion is said to rest, namely, the at-
tempt to isolate thought from its foundation and its past, is even possible,
The only question I] want to raise here is whether, supposing the reasoning
of Descartes werecorrect, the term "thinking" [cogitare] is the right term for
Draft Db JHK Translation Page 179
lsagoogé Philasophiae
the same thing by the term "knowing" (or by the term for the correlate of
knowing, namely, "knowledge").
The insight with which a businessman serveshis firm is to be sure the
result of more than just thinking. It is the result of knowing. But experi-
ence teaches that this knowledge can and often is present in cases where the
person concerned has no scientific knowledge. We must therefore in the
first place distinguish between scientific and nonscientific knowing. Philo-
sophic knowing does not fall underthelatter.
Therefore, the question must now be discussed whether language cor-
rectly distinguishes scientific and philosophic knowing. First of all, the
question arises: are both identical? In other words, can we say "All scien-
tific knowing is of a philosophic character"? That is certainly not the case:
many men and women are engaged in the special sciences with great compe-
tence without evincing much interest in philosophic questions. This byitself
is sufficient to distinguish within science between special science and philos-
ophy.
In summary, I cometo the following conclusion: philosophic knowing
is not identical with scientific knowing but is subsumed as nonspecial-scien-
tific knowing, together with the knowing of the special sciences, under sci-
entific knowing.
Put more briefly, philosophic knowing is scientific, but not special sci-
entific knowing.
10. The relationship ofphilosophic knowing and nonphilosophic knowing
In every case where two things are different, we can ask aboutthe rela-
tionship between the two, That is why we now come to the relationship
between philosophic and nonphilosophic knowing.
This relationship too cannot yet be extensively discussed. Nev-
ertheless, a few things can be said aboutit at this point; not only negatively,
but also in a positive sense.
On the negative side, we must hold fast to the insight that philosophic
knowing, althoughit itself is of a different nature, may not ignore nonscien-
tific and special scientific knowing.
Onthe positive side, the relationship between the two is a double one:
I. Philosophy presupposes both kinds of knowing and builds on both.
2. Philosophy must reflect also on the place and the task of both kinds
of knowing and must treat these points at greater length in the theory of
knowledge.
11. Philosophic knowing and the knowing in (sacred) believing
Among what is included in nonscientific knowing, we find also the
knowing that is included in (sacred) believing. First a word to clarify both
members of this term.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 181
Isagoogée Phitosophiae
that stands under the law or anything that is created that stands above the
law.
Comment 4: This means that we reject the following:
a. Realism (in the classical sense) with its doctrine that the law also holds for
God: Godis not subjected to the law, although he is bound by virtue of his
faithfulness to maintain his law once put to the creature. We find the combi-
nation of these thoughts already in Calvin: "Deus legibus solufas est” and
"Deus non ex lex est.” *
b. The attempt to understand the basic relation between God and cosmos as
that between whole and part. This viewpoint allows for a numberof different
elaborations.
1, When consistently applied, there are two conceptions possible;
- God is the whole, the cosmos a part—for example, that part of him thatis
manifest: pantheism.
- The cosmos is the whole, God a part of the cosmos—-for example, the re-
sultant of the operation of many cosmic forces or else the result of pistic repre-
sentation: pancosmism.
2. When inconsistently applied, we also find two views:
- A part of the world is divine; partial theism.
- A part of God is cosmic: partial cosmism.
Comment 5: To speak of law as the line between God and cosmos does not
purport to indicate completely the difference between God and cosmos;
“difference,” as is denoted by word pairs like Creator and creature, infinite
and finite, is something other than “line” or “limit.”
Comment 6: The law's mode of being is that of “holding for." The law,
therefore, always stands above and outside that for which it holds—a comment
directed against objectivism and subjectivism. Law is therefore not
"regularity" etc.: processes subjected to the law are regular orirregular.
Comment 7: The law of God holds for everything and therefore brooks no
exceptions at all. This also holds for the normative laws: the fact that these
can be transgressed does not mean atal! that they are thereby also abolished.
To acknowledge law as the line between God and cosmos is a re-
quirement of the fear of the Lord, which is of significance for much more
than exclusively for science, but which also may not belackinginit either if
science is not to lead to putative or pseudo-knowledge, that is to say, to er-
ror rather than to genuine knowledge.
14, The significance of these answers for the determination of the place of
philosophy
Now these answers are of great importance, also for philosophy. As
we have seen, it is human striving and a result thereby obtained. Both be-
long to the created. They are not elevated above the law of God, but sub-
jected to it, to the word revelation and to the guidance of the sovereign God.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 185
fsagoogé Philosophiae
15. The significance of these answers for the conception of the task of
philosophy
These answers imply however also a distinctive conception of the task
of philosophy.
A. In the first place they limit this task. Philosophy may never deny or
seek to push aside that which exists, not even to the smallest degree: to do
so would be to deny either God orall or part of his work, or fail to do jus-
tice to its nature.
1. That is why, in the first place, it cannot take the place of belief in
the word revelation of God; for all of our knowledge about God rests di-
rectly or indirectly on that belief, and what a philosopher who rejects the
word of God claims to know about him tums out upon closer investigation
to be pure speculation.
2, Moreover, secondly, philosophy can not annex other parts of the
nonscientific life either: philosophers may at times have governed state
wisely, but they did not do that exclusively by virtue of their philosophic
competence. For philosophy remains science, And although the man ofsci-
ence also received other gifts, the extension of his work is so demanding that
at least a part, also of his rapport, usually does not have the opportunity of
developing itself. That may be the case with another part—but even then,
whenthere is a harmony between the various branches of his work, the dif-
ference remains.
3. Finally: philosophy may also not push the special sciences to the
side. If it does this anyway, then an ignominious defeat, as it suffered e.g.
after Hegel, is well deserved.
B. But even thoughits task is limited, the philosophythat keeps the line
between God and cosmosin mind truly need not be in want of work. For he
whobelieves that God created the cosmos, proceeds every time again from
the presupposition that the wealth in that which is created will be much
greater than we ascertained up to that time. For that reason such a philoso-
pher can never say: "I am ready, look here, a closed system.” On the con-
trary: his result, though acquired systematically, is always a provisional
Draft D JHK Translation Page 186
isagoogé Phitosophiae
one, for he remains filled with expectation, attuned to new surprises that
will no doubt complement the main conception that agrees with belief, yet
will time and again supplement and usually alter earlier findings.
16. Thefield ofinvestigation for philosophy
The question remains as to what philosophy can investigate. This
question can be completely answered only after a definition of "science,"
which is here inappropriate. Yet the preceding does offer sufficient basis in
orderto initially survey the field of investigation. It is the entire domain of|
the cosmos.
17. The point of orientation and the route ofphilosophy
A. Because the whole cosmos is subjected to God's law and therefore to
God, this being-subject is our point of orientation. Thatis to say, all further
determinants and differences are oriented to this being-subject.
B. This is also decisive for the route that we follow. Beginning with
subjectivity in this sense of the word, we look for the further determinants
of this being-subject and discern in them a great variety.
18. Division
Following the route mentioned above we find first of all a twofold
specification: for that which is subject to God is either heavenly (Part I) or
earthly (Part II). Both contain what is initially a completely unsurveyable
concrete wealth, of which that of the earth is best known to us. After the
analysis of the diversity in these two, we discuss the connection between the
two (Part IIT).
An Appendix presents the result of applying what is found to several
more complicated questions.
As was said, completeness is not to be had. The intention of the fol-
lowing is accordingly only to denote in words as clearly as possible the most
important determinants and distinctions that I have discerned in the cosmos
in order that others may see them as well.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 187
fsagoogé Philosaphiae
PART I
THE DIVERSITY
AND CONNECTION OF THE DETERMINANTS
OF THE HEAVENLY-SUBJECT
however they may differ from earthly creatures, have that mere-being-crea-
ture in common with us.
B. This conception consequently forbids us to equate earthly-being with
created-being; it is only a part of that which is created.
21. The antithesis and the worid ofthe angels
The difference in the world of angels between good and evil angels is a
difference different from those mentioned above.
Holy Scripture informs us that it arose through the fact that one of the
most important angels did not remain standing in the truth, that is to say, in
the constancy, safety, and faithfulness of God. In this irreparable fall he
was followed by many other angels and he with them cameto stand over
against the good angels.
In correlation with this difference there arose the difference between
heaven and hell. Also this difference therefore does not exist by virtue of
creation but by virtue of the judgment of God on account of the sin of the
angels. It is important to make a clear distinction between those two lest we
end up in an antithetic dualism (Parsiism or Zoroastrianism)orelse in a con-
ception that views the lowest as demonic, the highest as heavenly, and the
earth as the result of their combination (Babylonian world picture, astrol-
ogy).
Draft D JHK Translation Page 189
fsagoogé Philosophiae
PART Il
THE DIVERSITY
AND CONNECTION OF THE DETERMINANTS
OF THE EARTHLY-SUBJECT
Introduction
22. The many determinants of earthly-being
The word “earth” only implicitly refers to the wealth created in it by
God. Holy Scripture denotes the relationship of "earth" to this variegated
multiplicity as a relationship of that which was initially encompassing to that
which was initially encompassed (Genesis 1:2), and the evolving of the latter
out of the former as the work of the Spirit of God, who guides all ofthis,
reciprocally connected, to development.
Comment I: This evolving has reference exclusively to earth, not to heaven
and (certainly) not to God himself.
Comment 2: This evolving is not to be identified with evolution. The latter
presupposes the derivability of that which is higher out of that which is lower,
whereas evolving presupposes the derivability of that which is later from that
which is earlier.
Now the diversity that manifests itself thus is much too great to be able
to survey without further analysis.
In the first place, there is that unique relation between that which is
created and God, which we call “the covenant"; a relation in which
mankind, as is evident from its religion, occupies the most important place.
With this, the difference between mankind and that which is subject to
it is given; apart from this however, there exists a great diversity of Aing-
doms and kinds.
Within the kinds we finally come upon things. These are not present
separate and next to each other, but are connected with one another in all
kinds of ways and accordingly demonstrate a clear similarity in the structure
and diversity of their analytically irreducible determinants.
23. The needfor a double investigation
The sequence in which we just mentioned the many determinants of
earthly being was arrived at through resolution. Analyzing that which is
concrete, further and further, we finally arrive at diversities that cannot be
further analyzed.
Having arrived at these, it is also possible to follow the reverse route.
Draft D JHK Transtation Page 190
isagoogé Phitosophiae
In this case we begin where analysis ended, that is to say, with the an-
alytically irreducible diversities and then proceed in the direction of ever
preater complexity,
Comment: The analytically irreducible diversities are therefore not elemental
in nature: to analyze is not the same as finding componentparts.
As it stands we could simply confine ourselves to the inquiry men-
lioned first, for it indeed has a greater advantage over the second. This ad-
vantage cannot lie in its being "creative," for that it is not. All human
knowing is a part of that which is created and this investigation is no excep-
tion to this rule. The advantage I have in mind has to do simply with the
fact that the "whole" comes to the foreground.
Butprecisely because this glimpse of the whole may notbe lacking, we
cannot confine ourselves to the second inquiry apart from the first. For a
clear view of the determinants, which are discerned later, can only be had if
their connection with that of which they are determinants is kept in mind:
the earth, after all, is not a collection of kingdoms, a kingdom is not a col-
lection of kinds, a kind is not a collection of things, and a thing is not a
collection of analytically irreducible determinants.
There are, however, great advantages to be had when the second inves-
ligation followsthefirst. In the first place, we eliminate the danger of never
getting beyond vague generalities and e.g. speaking of “wholes” without
ever seeing the wealth that they contain. Secondly, in this manner we
clearly see that the "whole" we saw first cannot be built out of the "parts"
obtained through resolution: what is lacking is precisely the connection that
was kept in mind when followingthefirst route.
24. Nevertheless a preference is necessary
Meanwhile the scope ofthis Isagoge does not permit us to devote an
equal amountoftime to both routes of this twofold investigation.
So as not to let the advantages of the second elude us andafter the brief
treatment of the first route above, we now turn our full attention to the sec-
ond,
25. Initially not discussing something does not imply its elimination
Hence we continuethe investigation in a moment by beginning with the
analytically irreducible determinants of a thing, so as to then proceed ever
further in the direction of that which is concrete.
In doing so it is unavoidable that much that is of primary importanceis
not discussed initially. At the same time one should keep in mind that we do
not for a momentexclude any ofthis in our knowing activity. For example,
the fact that along this route religion is discussed last, does not mean that we
eliminate it in our investigating. On the contrary: it is religion that also
distinguishes our knowing from that on nonchristian thinkers, Our concep-
Draft ® JHK Translation Page 191
Isagoogé Phitosophiae
tion concerning the arché and limit, our expectation in which we do ourin-
vestigation, always attuned to new surprises, and the determination both of
the field that we can explore and of the point of orientation that dominates
the entire route, all rely on the word revelation of God, accepted through
faith. Butthat is not all. We also owe to the word of God the insight that
what we, as a result of this postponement, examinefirst is not the full con-
crete life of everyday, whose wealth we will, precisely because of this de-
tour, be better able to appreciate.
Comment: The elimination of this knowledge and ofthe religion that obtained
this knowledgeis therefore not possible, and hence the question as to the de-
sirabitity of the same cannot even come up for discussion.
The same aiso holds, however, with respect to everything else that is
not discussed right away: it is tabled because it is simply not possible to
deal with everything at once.
26. Subdivision
The subdivision of this second part follows from the above. Wewill
discuss in:
Division I The structure of thing and man;and in
Division I] The structure of the kingdoms and of humankind
Division I
The Structure of Thing and Man
27. Subdivision
In the treatment of the structure of thing and man wediscuss the fol-
lowing:
Chapter 1 The two most simple determinants and their basic con-
nections;
Chapter 2 The third determinant and its combination with the others.
CHAPTER 1
THE Two Most SIMPLE DETERMINANTS
AND THEIR BASIC RELATIONS
28. Subdivision
In this chapter we will discuss the following:
Section 1 The two most simple determinants, the diversity within
both, and their combined occurrence.
Section 2. The two basic connections within these determinants, the di-
versity in both, and their combined occurrence.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 192
lsagoogé Philosophiae
Section 1
The Two Most Simple Determinants,
The Diversity in Them,
and Their Combined Occurrence
29. Subdivision
Two of the most simple determinants are found in things. It is immate-
rial in what order we deal with them since they never occur separately.
They must both be discussed, however, before treating their combined oc-
currence.
From this follows the subdivision:
A. The first most simple determinant and its diversity;
B. The second most simple determinantandits diversity;
C. The combined occurrence of both most simple determinants.
b. Negatively: First of all, "belief (faith)" is not the same as “religion,” which
can only be dealt with later [see §115ff]. Secondly, as we have already ob-
served, “belief (faith)" is not identical with faith in Christ; all people believe,
but not everyone believes in the Christ of God [see §11).
It is plain that there is a rich diversity in this first determinant and this
rich abundance is perhaps even greater than we have seen so far.
32. Terminology
For the sake of brevity we call the diversity discussed above the "thus-
so-difference."
33. The mutual irreducibility ofthe thus-so determination
Within one and the same se, further determination of se can occur, as
we shall see below [§§37 and 60-63].
However, none of the thus-so determinations can be reduced to an-
other. If we attempt to do so, we become involved in antinomies. Anti-
nomies, however, by virtue of the being-subject of everything to a law that
is correlate to it, cannot occur in the cosmos in a primary sense, that is to
say, apart from human error. They are the result of a confusion we will dis-
cuss later [§§201 and 202).
That which is denoted by the words “this number"can be, for example,
the number ihree. The numberthree is a number. Thatis to say, it is sub-
ject to the arithmetic Jaw. But we do not find this property only in the case
of the number three, but in the case of everything that is number. The de-
terminant denoted by the word "this" is not in conflict with the similarity
between the number three and all other numbers. Nor does it do away with
this similarity: it presupposes it. It is simply an other determinant.
37. The nature ofthis determinant
This determinant too belongs to the analytically irreducible de-
terminants. That is why it is difficult to circumscribeit.
However, to avoid confusion,it is good to show briefly that it does not
coincide with the two other determinants that we already discerned in the
earthly subject [§33], namely, the thus-so determinant [A] and its further
specification [B].
A. To this end | ask myself in the first place the question: is this further
determinant something other than a diversity in thus-so determination? Let
us try to clarify the import of this question by a specific case. Thus ] can
put it, for example, in the following way: Is the relationship between mum-
ber and this the same as that between arithmetic and spatial, or not?
To ask the question is to answerit in the negative, for it is plain that
what causes the number to be “the number three" is something other than
Spatiality, which is entirely lacking here.
B. Is it then perhaps the case, someone might ask, that the determinant
“this” is a further specification of "thus"?
This question also must be answered in the negative. To support this
negation it is sufficient to juxtapose the term "this number" and the term
“rational number.” In the latter case, we have the designation of a further
specification of number as number; however, there are many rational num-
bers, but there is only one number three. Consequently, the determinant
being-individual does not further specify the numerality of three, but is a
determination that retains its significance even whenall further specifications
of its numerality have been added up.
38. The diversity in this-derermination
If no other numberexisted besides three, then it would be impossible to
speak of diversity in the this-determination of numbers. But since there in
fact are more numbers than this one alone, we must also deal with this diver-
sity.
As this number, three is different from all other numbers. The word
"other" here denotes that al! numbers that are subsumed underit lack the
determination being-three. Nevertheless they do most certainly have a qual-
Draft D JHK Transtation Page 196
lsagoogé Philosophiae
italive determination of their own thatis entirely parallel to that of this num-
ber. This can be indicated by means of the terms “this,” "that," etc.
39. Terminology
In connection with what is noted above we can typify this determinant
briefly as shis-that-difference.
40. The law sphere
Therefore the this-that difference is not incompatible with the possibil-
ity that this and that are alike in that the same law holds for both.
All this's and that's for which the same law holds together constitute
the domainor the sphere ofthis law; they are its law sphere. Since there are
manylaws, there also exist therefore many of such law spheres.
Consequently, we may not deduce from the fact that weillustrated the
existence of the this-that-difference only in the case of the arithmetic law
sphere that this difference occurs only here. It occurs in all law spheres.
Forit is also true that the onespatial figure is not the other and that a dis-
tinction can be made between this and that energetic activiry, this and that
analytic activity, this and that ethical act, etc.
Comment 2: The reason why the vertical lines are chosen for the formerdif-
ference rather than for the later can best be indicated tater [§55].
adverbs of time and the tense of a verb, in the social in the giving ofpriority
[for example, “ladies first"], in the economic in the giving and receiving of
interest, in the aesthetic as aesthetic (not pure) duration, in the juridic as
length of validity (think of the retroactive force of a positive iaw), in the
ethical in the choice of the “right” time, in the pistic in the alternation of
liturgically festive and ordinary games. Has
Comment 1: Time is therefore not a mode ofintuition: it exists independently
of our mental activity.
Comment 2: Time is not a modality: therefore the juxtaposition of space and
time is incorrect.
49. The different modalities of ithe subject unit in time—the term subject
Junction
Since we are now also taking time into account, it becomes evident in
retrospect that we have so far conceived of the different modalities of an in-
dividual subject unit as though they were timeless. We can now dispense
with this abstraction: the modalities of an individual subject unit never exist
outside of time.
Once this insight has been gained, it is also possible to introduce a
shorter term for this being-subject of the individual subject unit to laws of
differing modality, namely "the functioning of the subject unit." Conse-
quently, we can say concisely: “a subject unit has more than one subject
function.”
The (subject) functions of a subject unit differ from each other, of
course, modally.
Section 2
The Two Fundamental Connections
in Both Distinctions
and Their Occurrence in Combination
50. Introduction and subdivision
We met with connection both between that which differs individually
and between the subject-modalities. These connections too always occur in
combination. Consequently, we make the following subdivision:
A. The connection between that which differs individually;
B. The connection between the subject functions:
C, The combined occurrence of both connections.
Draft pb JHK Translation Page 201
lsagoogé Phitosophiae
A. THE CONNECTION
BETWEEN ENTITIES THAT DIFFER INDIVIDUALLY
54, Introduction
The fact that two entities that differ individually belong to a single law
sphere was not enough to establish the existence of a connection between
them (see §51). Noris sufficient reason given for the use of the term con-
Draft D JHK Transiation Page 202
Isagoogé Philosophiae
nection between subject functions if we simply refer to the fact that they of-
ten occur together (see §46). For surely it is one thing to observe thata cir-
cle is subject to both the law for the arithmetic and to that for the spatial, but
another thing if f am able to give an answer to the questions: Is the spatial-
being of the circle connected with its (modal) property or function of being-
arithmetic? And, if so, what evidence is there of a connection between the
arithmetic and the spatial subject function?
However, if we attempt to answer these questions, then it appears in
both cases that there is something presupposed, namely a natural order of
subject functions.
Consequently, we must take a lookat this first.
55. The order of the subjectfunctions
Let us examine whether there exists any order between the arithmetic
and the spatial and if so, what it is. A polyhedron, for example, is subject
both to spatial and to arithmetic laws. It has a stereometric form and its
planes can be counted. But at the same time, there is more here than a
“both-and.” The fact is that spatial properties presuppose arithmetic ones
and not vice versa. For it is possible to express the magnitude of a line with
the help of numbers, but not possible to clarify the relationship of numbers
simply with the help of the relationship between radius and circumference,
Therefore, when | calculate the length of a line, I do have interrelations be-
tween numbers at hand, but [ have no use for the interrelations between lines
when I am busy with numbers.
This indicates a certain order between the two. There is number ev-
erywhere where there are lines, But it is quite possible for spatiality to be
absent when I speak exclusively about numbers. Numbers are therefore pre-
supposed in the case of lines, but lines are not presupposed in the case of
numbers. In the order of the subject functions, therefore, the arithmetic pre-
cedes the spatial.
Similarly, every movement presupposes spatiality. Every organic ac-
tivity presupposes the conversion of energy. A psychic state presupposes
organic life. Analytic discernment presupposes a sensitive attention
(sometimes only a very weak one) with reference to something. Historic life
presupposes the presence of some analytic judgment. Speech, whether it
comes 10 expression or not, presupposes historic activity. Social intercourse
presupposes language, etc. Conversely, it is not true that a line's being tan-
gential to another presupposes conversion of energy: 1 can no more explain
a tangential line in terms of the latter than I can explain the relationship of
numbers in terms of lines.
Comment [: In the foregoing, I have only indicated for the sake of brevity
that every function presupposes that which is next lower to it. However, this
implies of course thatit also rests upon all the other lower functions. This be-
Draft D JHK Translation Page 203
lsagoogé Philosophiae
comes evident, for example, from the fact that when there is something wrong
in those lower functions, the higher functions do not function well either.
Similarly, an inflammation in the organic is accompanied with pain in the psy-
chic. And certain kinds of brain damage disturb the function of thinking.
Thus, there appears to exist a natural order of subject functions in
which that which is more complicated always presupposes the less compli-
cated, but in which the lower does not presuppose the occurrence of the
higher functions.
Morespecifically, it turns out that the subject functions occur in the
order in which they were enumerated already in §31. Moreover, it will be
plain on the basis of this "being-presupposed" why I earlier [§46] chose
horizontal lines for the denotation of thus-so differences.
Comment 2: In the first place, we can not incorporate this order of sequence
in the diagram given in §46. To that end, one should begin with the listing of
the functions from the bottom, that is, with the arithmetic. It also turns out
that the differences between subject units, listed in §46A, can be represented
by the differences in length in the vertical lines of the diagram on the next
page.
pistic
ethical
juridic
aesthetic
economic
social
lingual
historic
analytic
psychic
organic
physical
Spatial
arithmetic
man animal plant chemical mathematical number
element figure
60. The analogy of the subject function with its substrate; retrocipation
The more complicated subject function presupposes one or more less
complicated subject function(s). This means not only thatthe latter precedes
(or succeeds as the case may be) the function involved, in the order of sub-
ject functions as (a part of) its superstrate. But also that the more compli-
cated subject function in its turn refers back to its substrate. Thus a
“dimension” for example is definitely spatial in character. Nevertheless,
space refers back, in the multiplicity of dimensions (which can always be
multiplied), to number.
Comment 1: The number ofspatial dimensions can always be multiplied. Our
preference for three dimensional space can not be explained until later (see
§65).
This reference back of higher to lower functions can be given the per-
spicuous name retrocipation.
The examples of this connection—which does not occur in the arith-
metic because it lacks a substrate—can be found everywhere in the cosmos.
Thus all the supra-arithmetic functions retrocipate on the arithmetic: all
these functions possess a multiplicity that is inherent to them—a multiplicity
of dimensions but also of forces, of organs, etc. We discover something
similar in the supraspatial sphere: they retrocipate on the spatial; their oc-
currence transverses a course on the basis of whichit is possible to describe
this occurrence, as far as this analogy is concerned, with a curve. Further-
more, all the supraphysical retrocipates on the physical substrate: all these
functions bear a dynamic character—think only of growth in the organic,
emotion in the psychic, mobility in thinking, etc. Further examples of
retrocipation are: development in the supra-organic; the "feel" of things in
the suprapsychic; the (nonscientific) cognitive element (of both thinking and
knowing) in everything above the analytic; the role played by the scheme
means-ends in the supra-historic; the language of social intercourse, of
commerce, of poetry etc. in the supra-lingual; commerce in the supra-so-
cial; the thrift principle in the supra-economic; the harmonization of
interests in the supra-juridic and the assuranceofbelief in the pistic.
It follows from the above that the higher a functionis situated in the
order of functions the more retrocipations it possesses: whereas the spatial
has only one retrocipation, we find no fewer than thirteen retrocipations in
the pistic.
Comment 2: Ofthe retrocipations in the pistic, two have been prominent in
history: the retrocipation on the analytic (knowing) and that on the ethical
(trusting). However, these two are not the only retrocipations: another exam-
ple is sacrifice, in which the pistic retrocipates on the economic. It is of
course completely incorrect to conceive of the first two retrocipations as the
Draft D JHK Translation Page 206
fsagoogé Phitosophiae
component factors of faith: they are only traits present in all faith alongside
other features.
The numberof retrocipations is therefore one (in the second function) plus
two (in the third function) + .. . 13 (in the 14th function), to make a total
of 91,
Comment 3: A retrocipation can be
represented schematically with the help
of an arrow pointing downward in the
following manner.
Comment 4: Since the retrocipation(s) to (all) its substrate function(s) is (are)
always inherent in a higher function it is possible to briefly denote which func-
tions are present in this way in an individual subject unit in terms ofits highest
function. Thus a circle is a spatial subject unit. A river is a physical one and
a plant an organic one. While the total of man's functions can for the time
being be called a pistic subject unit.
looking back, seeing more, we can summarize the old with the new. Since
no subject unit exists without such a connection between its functions, there
is no reason to introduce a new term at this point. As long as I still need
this term I understand by it now: an individual this with two or more func-
tions that stand in vertical, mutual connection.
65. Evidences of the mutual connection of object functions on the object
side: Therepetition ofthe substrate in the superstrate
It is not uncommon nowadays to meet with the opinion that the differ-
ence of subject and object is nothing more than a distinction: that is, the
product of human thinking. Orelse, if this is not considered to be correct,
then in any case, that this difference occurs for the first time in that which is
analytic. However, this opinion is not consonant with the structure of the
cosmos.
If the existence of objects is recognized, however, then it must be seen
in its connection with the cosmos as a whole, so as to prevent an exappera-
tion of its importance.
If we do this, it turns out that the object is the repetition of the sub-
strate in the superstrate.
The simplest example of this can be found in the spatial law sphere. A
straight line as long as it is not intersected by another straight line is ex-
tended endlessly in a single direction or dimension. In the multiplicity ofits
dimensions, space retrocipates to the arithmetic law sphere. However, this
multiplicity of dimensions has as an implication that as soon as a straight
line is intersected by another one drawnin anotherdirection a point arises.
We are here met with something that up until now we have only
touched on in passing. For points do have spatial character, but unlike
lines, they are discontinuous.
Let ustake a closer look at these matters.
The discontinuity of points reminds us of that of numbers. We might
therefore be inclined to speak here of a retrocipation. Butthis is precisely
whatis forbidden us by the discontinuity of points, since the character of the
subject functions remains the samealso in retrocipation, and the spatial sub-
ject, also in its retrocipation, always shows continuity.
Wetherefore come upon something here that has to do with a connec-
tion with the arithmetic and yet does not coincide with the retrocipation.
Nevertheless, it is not isolated from retrocipation either: without the
multiplicity of dimensions, there are no points.
If we are to give account of what we have found, then we can say that
the discontinuity of number is here repeated within space, and thatthis Tepe-
tition is rooted in the fact that space retrocipates to the arithmetic.
Thecase that we have just dealt with is only one of many. This is al-
ready apparent in the case of that which is arithmetic. For this function is
Draft D JHK Translation Page 211
fsagoogé Philosophiae
repeated not only in the spatial, but also in all its remaining superstrate
functions. As an example, we might adduce here the phenomenonofvirtual
movement. That is to say, that movement by which the proper movement of
a physical thing or system is canceled out by motions that impinge upon it
and yet remains virtually present—as is apparent as soon as the forces
working in from without become weaker or stronger.
But there are also other functions besides the arithmetic that possess
such object functions in their superstrate spheres. For example, space is re-
peated in the physical as rectilinear movement. That is to say, as the kind of
movement in which the impinging forces cancel each other out. Other ex-
amples of a repetition of space are life space, perceptual space, analytic and
imaginative space—in other words, space in an organic, psychic, analytic,
and technical sense.
Comment 1: Technical space is Euclidean space. In this way it will be clear
why space in itself is not Euclidean. Similarly, it becomes clear why every
attempt to approach the existence of non-Euclidean space with the aid of
imagination is doomed to failure.
The supraspatial is also repeated in its superstrate. For example, physical
movement is repeated in the organic as stimulus, in the psychic as sensibly
perceptible (roughness, color, sound, taste, smell), in the analytic as the
knowable, in the technical as formable, in the lingual as nameable,etc.
The same holds for the leading function in plants and animals. In this
way, an organism that possesses subject functions in none of the supra-or-
ganic spheres does possess an cbject function in all these spheres. A flower,
for example, has no feeling, yet it is psychically perceptible. It does not
think, but it is analyzable. It is not technically busy, but in a nursery does
prove to formable. Moreover, it can be given a namelingually. It has so-
cial usefulness (for example, for highlighting a canal or dike) and although it
is not itself economically busy(lilies of the field do not toil, neither do they
spin), it does have an economic value; it is also aesthetically beautiful or
ugly; it can be juridically a possession or a corpus delicti, It is an ethical
symbol of troth in friendship and marriage ("Say it with flowers!") and it is
a pistic object of belief and unbelief.
Comment 2: This also casts some light on the sacraments: as far as their
leading function is concerned, they are nothing but water or bread and wine.
In other words, physical and organic subject units (and not the body of the
Lord as Luther believed, influenced as he was by the incorrect theory accord-
ing to which every statement is a statement ofidentity), But they lend them-
selves as pistic object to be the sign and seal of something.
In summary, every subject function possesses an object function in every su-
perstrate sphere.
Draft B JHK Translation Page 212
fsagooge Philosophiae
Comment 3: Objects can be modally classified, just as retrocipations can be
within the subject—that is, they can be grouped as spatial objects, physical
objects, etc. Within every modal group, it again makes a difference as to
which substrate function is repeated in a given case. The numberof classes
within the different groups is therefore not equal: the spatial law sphere has
only one class of objects, namely points. The physical already possesses two,
the organic three, and so forth. The pistic law sphere has the greatest number
of classes of object functions, namely 13. The total number of these classes
therefore amounts to 91, and is therefore as great as that of the retrocipations.
Comment 4: Objects do not only play an important role in the cosmos, and in
our practical lives, but also in the history of philosophy and the special sci-
ences; we need only think of the debate about “secondary” qualities between
subjectivism and objectivism.
If we do not proceed from the subject functions, but from the subject
units, then it is correct to say that ali subject units, including those that do
not possess all the subject functions that occur in the cosmos, do have func-
tions in all spheres.
Conversely, in any given law sphere, every subject unit occurs, if not
as subject, then as object. This is sometimes also called the universality of
the law sphere.
Comment 5: It is under objects that we mustclassify a good number ofthese
so-called “secondary qualities."
Comment 1; This is the mistake made, for example, by someone who wants
to construct a line out of its points and to this end begins by conceiving of
points as spatial subjects. That is, looks upon them as very small lines. This
mistake is often masked by saying that points are small lines (smaller than any
measure that can be laid next to them) andthat it is therefore possible to build
up the larger line only if one has an infinitely increasing number of such in-
finitely diminishing lines at his disposal. But one must choose between one of
two alternatives: either these “little lines" really are lines, in which case they
are first of all continuous and secondly finite (that is, intersected by two lines
of another direction), so that no more than a finite numberofthese finite, little
lines are necessary for the construction of a large finite line. Or else, these
“little tines” are not tines at all, but points; and in that case even the infinite in-
crease of them will not provide us with the continuity we are looking for.
2. On the other hand, the derivation of object functions from subject
functions is excluded as well. The theory of “self-objectification" forgets
this, believing that the "secondary qualities” can be explained from the self-
disintegration of a world subject.
Comment 2: The same mistake is made indirectly by the person who avoids
speculations about the origin of objects but classifies the object under the sub-
ject. That is done, for example, by someone who considers the secondary
qualities of physical things as an interrelation of different subjects, or else
takes these qualities, being nonphysical, to be intramental.
Comment 3: The expression “next to each other" in our text does not imply
that subject and object always belong to different subject units. Next to sub-
Ject-object relations where this is indeed the case (for example, in the case of
the human cultivation of plants and animals), there are also subject-object rela-
tions in which subject and object belong to the same subject unit, as is the case
€.g. with lines and points of the same figure, or with someone's cultivating “a
slim figure," etc.
Comment 4: Let us attempt to also picture the object functions in a schematic
diagram. Proceeding from the diagram of subject units found in §55 we can
use dotted lines to indicate what has reference to objects in it, The horizontal
dotted lines group the subject functions modally. The vertical ones do this in
accordance with the substrate to which they belong. In this way, the classes of
objects are indicated schematically by the intersecting points of the horizontal
and vertical lines.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 214
Tsagoogeé Philosophiae
PIStiC peternceeeeee erates race acnereasies ee
ethical |. cbod
joridic .:.
aesthetic .:
economic
social
lingual
historic .3..:
analytic .:..1
psychic
organic
physical .:..:
Spatial .:
arithmetic | | | | | I | 1]
man I | ps dhanvoer
nrh patial figure
ig ysical element
m anism
a
that in scrapping an incorrect term for one of the two mutually irreducible
connections, this connection most definitely continues to exist. How we de-
termine our choice in such cases is a question that, from the point of view of
the clarity of philosophic terminology, is of secondary importance. However,
“secondary” does not mean “arbitrary.” Hence, I would recommend that, for
example, the term "cause" (in view of the usage in the special sciences) be re-
served for certain supraspatial interrelations which we will discuss below (see
§78A comment).
The large curves denote interindividual-relations; the small curves denote in-
traindividual-relations.
(subphysical) functions. Its sole place is in the interrelation and then only in
those that are supraspatial.
B. But here too it has a much more discrete place than is often assumed.
1. Active-passive does not always coincide with the difference in in-
dividuality. This correlation, therefore, is not inherent to the interin-
dividual-relation. When e.g. two things cooperate, both stand in inter-
individual-relation, but both subject functions are active.
2. Active-passive also does not coincide with the relationship between sub-
ject and object functions: the emotively perceptible object function cclor
e.g. is not necessarily also a perceived color. On the other hand, subject
functions can also be passive, e.g. in the case of remembered activity.
C. That is why the correlation active-passive ought to be explicitly men-
tioned as always something extra.
In the following paragraphs I discuss a few combinations in which this
schema occurs,
CHAPTER 2
THE THIRD DETERMINANT, [Ts DIVERSITY
AND THE COMBINED OCCURRENCEOFTHIS
DETERMINANT WITH BOTH OF THE OTHERS
85. The third determinant
Besides the two most simple determinants discussed above, namely,
that of individuality and modality, a third most simple determinant occurs in
the earthly subject. It is that of "good" and "evil."
As in the case of the heavenly subject, here too this determinant is not
an original determinant. That is to say, its appearance is not by virtue of
creation,
Meanwhile, since the fall it does play an extremely importantrole in
the earthly subject and especially in human existence.
86. The diversity in this determinant
A. It ts that of good and evil.
B. The character bomeby this diversity is not only a purely dual one;it is
also antithetic. Evil stands over against good as disobedience over against
obedience.
87. The relationship of this diversity in the case of man to that discussed
previously
As was the case regarding the relationship between the modal and the
individual differences, here too we must first attend to the mutual irre-
ducibility of the opposition good-evil and the diversities dealt with earlier,
so as to then look for an answer to the question, how they are connected.
88. The irreducibility of this diversity to both of the others and to their con-
nections
Wewill first discuss (I) the impossibility to reduce the antithetic dual-
ity to either of the other diversities as such and their combination; subse-
quently (II) the impossibility of such a reduction to the diversities that pre-
sent themselves both in their connections and in their combination. In both
parts of this paragraph wewill investigate first whether or not there is any
talk of duality; only when that is the case do we ask the question whether or
not this duality is also antithetical.
I. The impossibility to reduce the antithetic duality to either of the
other diversities as such (A} and in combination (B).
Draft D JHK Translation Page 221
Isagoagé Phitosophiae
93. The relationship, in the case ofman, ofheart (soul) andthe rest (body)
The above also throwsscriptural light on the relationship between soul
and body.
Both have in common with each other that they only occur with human
beings (as members ofthe cosmos created with time).
The difference between these two, at least to the extent that it can be
discussed here, lies in the fact that the soul is prefunctional, while the body,
in contrast, is functional.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 225
fsagooge Phiiosophiae
Division I
The Structure of the Kingdoms
and of Humankind
95. Introduction
In the previous division we dealt with the structure of things and man.
In so doing the concrete existence of that which is subject in an earthly way
was already approached in an important way. Yet in no way can it be said
that we have arrived. Thing and man are after all individual creatures but
both stand in genetic connection with other things and men and they also
take their own place in religion. Consequently these twotraits have to be
discussed in any case if we want to see that which is subject in an earthly
way in its concreteness,
CHAPTER I
THE STRUCTURE OF THE KINGDOMS
96. Survey
That which is subject in an earthly way, thing and man, does not stand
byitself, but is included genetically under one or another kingdom.
Consequently we have to discuss the variety of these kingdoms and
then their mutual connection.
Draft D JHK Transiation Page 226
Isagoogé Philosophiae
Section |
The Variety of the Kingdoms
97. Introduction
That which is subject in an earthly way displays a variety of genetic
connections or kingdoms: the kingdom of physical things, that of plants,
that of animals, and that of human beings.
To the extent these genetic connections are all "kingdoms" there is a
similarity; to the extent a variety exists there is also a diversity.
Let us first of all ask about what is clear concerning this similarity and
this difference on the basis of what we have found up until now. Naturally
the answerobtained in this way will not be sufficient: the kingdom connec-
tion includes more. Yet that more stands out more clearly when we first see
how far what we discussed above reaches.
98. Points of similarity and difference between the kingdoms to the extent
that both ofthese can be clarified
A. Wecan state:
1. Concerning the similarity: the things that belong to one kingdom all
have a leading function in the same modality.
2. Concerning the diversity: the things belonging to different kingdoms
differ in the modality of the leading function.
B. Thinking through both statements further, we find:
ad 1: similarity with the things of one kingdom in:
a. the numberof subject functions and object functions;
b. evidences in everything of vertical connection between these
functions;
c. the structure of each of these functions in connection with the
numberand the nature of the anticipations and retrocipations;
d. the modal determination of the intraindividual and in-
terindividual interrelations.
ad 2: difference with the things belonging to diverse kingdoms in the same
points.
99. Another point ofsimilarity and difference
Up until now we have not discussed the genetic connection in the case
of things and human beings. However, this connection is present among
both things and people. If we take that into account now as well, then we
find two points.
1. Ali things, except for the first ones, arose and arise from previous
things. In other words, the rule “nothing comes from nothing," which obvi-
ously does not hold for the creating of the first things—that being a work of
Draft D JHK Translation Page 227
isazgoogé Philosophiae
God—does hold without limit for later things. There is only one exception,
which we will get to below.
2. The genesis of these things takes place within the realm to which
that thing belongs. That is to say, the things of one realm, and this holds
for people too, agree in this that they are not genetically interrelated with the
things of the other realms.
Comment: This formulation is negative. That has to do with the fact that in
the nonhuman realms we do find a variety of genetic series or true
(genotypical, not phenotypical) species. While there is no compelling reason
to assume that these series were previously genetically interrelated, that is the
case for human blood groups.
case of the Mediator according to his human nature. On the other hand, this
occurrence does not contradict the rule. Rather it confirms it: Christ, in
contrastto us, had to parallel Adam.
Section 2
The Connection Between the Different Kingdoms
104, Introduction
Although there are no genetic connections between these kingdoms,
they are nevertheless tied to each other. That is obvious from the many re-
lations between things belonging to different realms.
These relations are primarily twofold. In the one case there is an
affinity among subjects from the various realms. In the other case the sub-
ject-object relation predominates.
105. This connection with respect to the affinity of subjects from different
kingdoms
There are many cases to distinguish here.
1. The connection is one of involuntary cooperation. The warmth gen-
erated by the sun, the ground loosened by the roots of lupines, and the col-
lection of honey by bees are al] examples. These fit in with certain expres-
sions of human activity and to that extent work together with it.
Comment: In these cases avoid an anthropomorphic interpretation of the ac-
tivity of the nonhuman things involved in this cooperation.
2. There is also a connection when the relation between subject func-
tions of things from various realms is coupled with the correlation active-
passive, as, for example, when growers and breeders intentionally promote
the growth ofplants and animals.
3. The affinity is even stronger when the interrelation between these
kinds of subject functions moves from interindividual to intraindividual.
These interrelations recently came to the forefront because of advances in
nutrition theory. Many inorganic salts proved to be vital for the healthy
functioning of organisms, animals, and human beings. So also, a number of
Draft D JHK Translation Page 230
Isagoogé Phitosophiae
vitamins are necessary for preserving the organic function, and therewith the
existence, of man and animal.
106. This connection in the subject-object relation
In by far the most cases the connection between the different realms
Tuns via the subject-object relation. Here, the activity of a member of a
higher realm—man, animal, or plant—directs itself to one or more things of
another realm in their object function. These kind of interrelations exist
between all realms. A plant will use a stone to support or protectitself and
animals use plants for food and nests. But this connection plays an even
more important part in the relationship of people to things in the nonhuman
realms.
107. The place of the subject-object relation in the relationship ofhuman life
to the things of the remaining kingdoms
In the organic law sphere people, animals, and plants are subjects,
while physical things are objects. In the psychic law sphere people and ani-
mais function as subjects, while plants in addition to physical things function
as objects. Qua subject [functions], there is a parallel between man, plant,
and animal in the organic, and likewise another parallel in the psychic be-
tween man and animal.
There are no parallels in the suprapsychic [spheres]. Human beings
alone are subject there. The things from all the other earthly realms are pre-
sent only as objects. In addition, the number of object functions in these
higher spheres is larger than in the lower ones. That explains the great sig-
nificance of the subject-object relation in and for human life.
Complete insight into what this relation encompasses here obviously is
not possible as long as the theory of objects is not yet elaborated. So I will
limit myself here to outlining it briefly just for the analytic and historic law
spheres, both of which are of particular importance for human societal con-
nections.
108. The subject-object relation specifically in the analytic and historic law
sphere
A. Human knowing, as will become clear when we deal with the theary
of knowledgelater, in no way depends entirely on the subject-object rela-
tion. Understanding neighbors and oneself are obvious counter-examples.
But nevertheless this relation plays an important part in human knowing. If
physical things, plants, and animals did not function as objects in the ana-
lytic law sphere, even nonscientific knowledge about these realms would be
out of the question. Not to mention that know-how would lack its immedi-
ate foundation.
Draft D JHK Translation Pape 231
Isagoogé Philosophiae
CHAPTER 2
THE STRUCTURE OF HUMANKIND
109. Introduction
The human race is not only connected with other kingdoms, but con-
structs in part upon this basis many societal connections, among which the
completion of his task is divided. Now, this task is given to humankind by
God. Hence, even more important than these connections is the relation in
which the human race religiously stands to God. Consequently, we have
now to deal with these connections and with religion.
Section 1
The Societal Connections
110. Survey
Wewill discuss respectively: the character of these connections, their
diversity, their mutual relationship, and their relation to religion.
111, The character
The connections to be discussed occur only in human life. They are
founded historically, contain in addition to this function also the lingual and
social, and intend cooperation in a supra-lingual sense.
In like manner, all these connections display the following traits. They
are connections of power by virtue of their historic basis. Their lingual
character comes out in the fact that consultation, conviction, and convincing
are everywhere present as constitutive factors. These connections derive the
Draft D JHK Translation Frage 232
Isagoogé Phitosophiae
however, that the social also relies on the analytic, both relations are in no
way irrational in nature.
112. The diversity
Here too, there are more than one of these connections. The founda-
tion is the same for all. In addition, often the same people are involved in
different connections. Consequently, the basis for this diversity can not lie
here, but must be sought elsewhere. Further investigation shows that this
diversity must be attributed to the difference in prevailing function.
For clubs and associations the prevailing function is the social; for
business and factory, the economic; for the artist's guild, the aesthetic; for
the state, the juridic; for the family, the ethical: and for the cultic connec-
tion, the pistic function.
Now each of these connections includes all of the human functions
between the historic and its destination function. Thus, most of these con-
nections also agree with each other in that they have morethan just the his-
toric, lingual, and social function in common. Factory, artist's guild, state,
family, and cultic connection all possess also an economicside; all of these
connections except the factory, also a juridic aspect; and both family and
cultic connection, an ethical function. Meanwhile, such communal areas, as
well as the historic and the lingual, certainly do differ from each other, due
to the fact that all of these functions are also determined differently on the
basis of the difference in destination function. That is why, for example,
justice for the cultic community is not the same as for the family and dif-
ferent again than that for the state.
Correlate with this double difference, namely, in destination function
and in the functions in between, is also the fact that the task of the office
bearers in each connection is unique. That is why a previous generation al-
ready, following Kuyper,rightly spoke of "sphere sovereignty.”
In practical life this adage soon got a strongly negative connotation.
But sphere sovereignty, also today, is truly not devoid of meaning. Yet,
here too, we oughtto see the position as the basis for the negation. This
principle means in the first place that those in authority in each institution
have to positivize the laws holding for that connection in consultation with
those who pay respect.
Comment 1; Kuyper's adage haslost nothing ofits power, even for ourtime.
Wecan soonersay thatits significance has increased. Think only ofthe re-
sponse that this conception received elsewhere: the rise of "the subsidiarity
principle” among Roman Catholics and the move for “functional decentraliza-
tion" in socialistic circles, Also, its significance was clarified in many ways
now that the younger generation of Kuyper's followers also took this thought
seriously in the theory of functions.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 234
lsagoogé Philosophiae
Comment 2: To avoid misunderstanding we ought more sirongly than did
Kuyper to distinguish sovereignty and autonomy. The first has to do with
modal differences, the second with individual differences. Family and factory
are both sovereign in their own realm; the first is ethically qualified, the sec-
ond is qualified economically. Within the circle of both connections, however,
exists a great diversity: there are many famities and many factories and busi-
nesses. Naturally, it makes no sense, in fact it is confusing, to also call the
freedom of the different families with respect to each other's internal rules
"sovereignty." In any case, there is a difference here and a distinction also in
terminology can only clarify things further. We find these differences else-
where as well. States have the same sovereignty, namely, juridic sovereignty.
However, with respect to each other they are not sovereign but autonomous,
as are the provinces within the territory of the samestate.
Comment 3: Autonomy should also be sharply distinguished from two other
matters.
(i) from Autonomyin the sense of the self-sufficiency declaration of men with
respect to God. This autonomy stands over against Heteronomy, that is to
say, the acknowledgment that the law is set by God and not by us, like auton-
omy tn the sense of being qualified to formulate rules for one’s ownterritory
stands over against heteronomy, standing under the laws of anotherterritory.
In this way we can understand that degenerate thought, basingitself on Auton-
omy, landed up time and again in Heteronomy. In contrast, Calvinism, pro-
ceeding from Heteronomy, was able to maintain both sphere sovereignty and
autonomy and in so doing, in a land as ours, whereit had great influence, be-
came and remained the “origin and security of our constitutional freedoms.”
(ii) from Autarky, that is to say, wanting to be self-sufficient. Included in
autonomy is the acknowledgment of being juxtaposed with other connections,
but autarky, temporarily or not, denies this juxtaposition.
answering the question whether this task is seen by both parents and whether
in so doing they have an eye for the uniqueness ofthe different institutions.
Comment 1: Nurturing is then the task of the family, primarily that of the par-
ents, in the second place, that of eventual brothers, sisters, and family helpers.
If the nurturing is endangered, by death, sickness, or also through neglect,
then other families, first of all among the relatives, have to lend a helping
hand. Only when this kind of help is not present does the cultic connection
have a task, and in its absence the state, because otherwise these connections,
too, as well as the others, eventually will suffer. This task is, however, an
extremely limited one. {t does not imply that these connections take the nur-
turing upon themselves, but only that they entrust the child to another family.
Comment 2: As children grow up, schools assist families with their children's
education. This assistance too, itself the result of the cooperation of many
parents if things are right, is not there to take the place of the family, but to
lighten and support the nurturing of the children by the family.
The principle of sphere sovereignty does have very special significance for
the school. It affects its relative independence with respect to sister institu-
tions, as is the case for the other life connections, butit also affects the goal of
its work, Education aims primarily at sharpening the ability to distinguish and
at conveying distinctions, But without distinguishing their destination, it is im-
possible to realize societal connections and, tied to that, the unfolding of hu-
manlife in the following generation, which the school, of course, is there to
heip educate. Consequently, in the near future the school plays only a sup-
portive, but importantpart in this realization.
B. Thestatic relationship can be defined positively as well as negatively.
1. Positively, this relationship ought to be one of genuine cooperation.
For all of these connections aim at developing different components of hu-
man life.
This cooperation includes two things:
(a) fulfilling one's own task. A state cannotflourish if economiclife, orga-
nized by trade and industry, does not grow. Family life, too, languishes
when thepistic connection falls short.
(b) acknowledging the unique task of the other connections. After all, they
owe neither their origin nor their continued existence to the goodwill of an-
other connection. Consequently, none of these connections have to seek
permission from any of the others to act or advance.
This double requirement does not only hold for the area of the prevail-
ing function, but also for the activity of different [societal] connections in
those law spheres that they have in common. Hence, cooperation does not
only imply that state, family, and cultic connection recognize each other's
unique nature, but also that they respect each others bylaws. That is why
particularly those who recognize both stipulations in all of these connections
have an important task. Loss is inevitable for those who do not acknowl-
edge them.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 236
isagoogé Philosophiae
Heretoo,it is the law of God that decides what is good and evil. More
specifically, the second table of the ten commandments, which, in contrast
to the first, does not address man in his relationship with God directly, but
in his relationship to his fellow man.
Hence, in the first place, we have to ask about the contentof this law.
It reads, in the summary given by Christ (Matt. 22:39) and in accordance
with the Old Testament (Lev. 19:18): "Love your neighbor as yourself."
Three points respectively draw our attention here: the concept "neighbor,"
the "as," and the requirement "to love."
The neighbor, as well as those addressed in this commandment, is the
whole person to the extent we are placed in his or her proximity during the
divinely directed course of our lives.
"As"—Greek hoos—is not talking about an amount, as if it were
pointing in the direction of the “correct mean" between egoism and altruism.
Scripture does not see the arithmetic [sphere] as !aw for the rest. This term
means something else, namely, "in the same way as." This presupposes that
we also ought to love ourselves—of course, in the same way as we love our
neighbor. As a result, this Aoos requires a criterion that lies beyond the one
love [of self] as well as the other love (of neighbor]. The intent is that we
are 10 love ourselves and our neighbor as image of God, that is, to the extent
we and they, as children, are like unto the Father in Heaven.
Love. Take note of two things: love's antithetical structure and its
prefunctional character.
Thestructure of this love is antithetical. That is, the commandthat re-
quires me to love my neighbor and myself to the extent that we display traits
of our Father, also requires that I hate my neighbor and myself to the extent
that we display the opposite.
The character of this love is prefunctional. It does not coincide with
our functional existence, because love [or hate] defines that existence. Nor
should we equate this love with a specific functional relationship, e.g., with
ethical relationships, and certainly not with a sexual-ethical relation-
ship—although this love permeates both of these. Scripture neverrefers to
the secondtable of the law—andcertainly not all of the ten commandments
together—as the “moral law."
if we summarize the above then it appears that the task of bringinglife
connections to realization ought to be carried out according to the second
table of the ten commandments. That is what the law requires. Which is
not to say that this law is always observed. For even in relationship to that
part of the law that has to do with the relationship to one's neighbor, obedi-
ence as well as disobedienceis present.
Ultimately, these two do not stand alone. The same is true for the cor-
relate part of the law. For just as the law, to the extent that it demands lov-
Draft D JHK Translation Page 238
fsagoogé Phitosophiae
Section 2
Religion
A. INTRODUCTION
116. Wharreligion is
Religion is the relationship of mankind to the first and great com-
mandment: "You shall love the Lord your God with all your heart, and with
all your soul, and with all your mind, and with all your might."
From this summary of the first table of the law, which was given by
Christ (Matt. 22:37}—following the Old Testament (Deut. 6:5)—it is plain
that God appears here as the God of the covenant. Therefore religion is the
relationship of mankind to the God ofthe covenant in obedience and disobe-
dienceto his fundamental law oflove.
Draft D JHK Translation Pape 239
Isagoogé Philosophiae
120. Introduction
A. Character
This covenant has two characteristics: with respect to Logos revelation
there is no reference to grace (in the sense of forgiveness) or to re-creation,
and as far as religion is concerned we maynote that the personinvested with
office was the first man, that his relationship to the word of God did not
Draft D JHK Translation Page 24]
lsagoogé Philosophiae
prove constant, and that all those who were represented by this office-bearer
in his office descended from him, or were to descend from him.
B. Division
Since this covenant was not kept by the office-bearer concerned, we
must distinguish here two phases; namely that before and thatafter the Fall.
121. The covenant of creation before the Fall
Two stages are to be distinguished in this period. The correlation of
Logos revelation and religion occurs in both.
A. The first stage: before the creation of Eve.
1. The Logos revelation to Adam .
When the Triune God has called Adam into being, as the initial execu-
tion of his plan to create men "in our image,after our likeness" (Gen. 1:26),
Adam speaks to him as "Lord" [Yahweh], that is, as God of the Covenant
and God mandates him to till and keep the Garden of Eden (Gen. 2:15).
The first part of this mandate, which among other things meantthat
Adam was to examine thelife of other earthly creatures, referred primarily
to the relationship of Adam to an (admittedly limited number of) his fellow-
creatures (in a field that was still very restricted).
As to the second part, matters were different. It evidently referred to a
danger that was threatening from elsewhere, and consisted in this, that a part
of the world of angels had not remained standing in the truth, i.e. constancy
(John 8:44), and were threatening earthly life in the garden. Forthis part of
the mandate is followed immediately by the probationary command (Gen.
2:16 and 17}, in which the region is indicated where the attack of the enemy
can be expected. The revelation of the death penalty in case of transgression
was an additional incentive to stand firm in the face of a possible temptation
and thus to gain the blessing—to live eternally in God's favor. This
"keeping," therefore, directly touched Adam's relationship to God and his
prefunctionat office, as prophet, priest, and king, to be faithful to him.
This mandate was in both parts a demonstration of God's favor.
Comment 1: Hence the covenant of creation can also be called "covenant of
favor," although in my opinion the former term is to be preferred, both be-
cause it is more comprehensive, and because the conception of "favor" in this
meaning, namely "grace," is sometimes used in a2 broader sense than that of
“favor forfeited by sin." Whichever term is chosen, however, the doing of
worksin this covenant was not (nor does the term “covenant of works,” it in
any case did not arise until later, mean what, judging from experience, it tends
to suggest, namely) an earning of God's favor, but the execution of a double
task that was assigned to Adam by virtue of that favor. For obedience there
was the promise of blessing (victory over the enemy and the inability any
longerto die); as punishment for disobedience, on the other hand, was fixed
Draft D JHK Translation Page 242
Isagoogé Philosophiae
the curse (succumbing in the struggle, perishing in the wrath of God in the
first death).
2. Religion
It consisted in the acceptance, in faith, of task and office.
Comment 2; Then, just as now, faith meant holding for truth all that God has
revealed in his word, and relying on his favor; on the other hand, of course,
there is not yet any question offaith in “grace” (in the sense of forgiveness).
When Adam names the animals, he also pays attention to the genetic
connection between the older and younger generation, and on that basis to
the cooperation of the sexes. He then notices that he lacks the possibility of
such cooperation (Gen.2:20).
Comment 3: Holy Scripture does not represent Adam as an asexual being
preceding the differentiation of the sexes or elevated above it (monogenic in
the speculative sense attached to it by Parmenides and others): Adam is a
male, who feels keenly the need of a woman as helper,
Consequently, after this lack has been noticed by Adam and God has
supplied him with what was missing, in accordance with his plan (Gen.
1:26), Adam immediately acknowledges this, joyfully as the fulfillment of
his desire (Gen.2:23),
Comment 4: The information that Eve was created out of Adam tells us that
God did not call the second human being into being separately, from the first,
but preserved the unity of mankind from the outset.
B. The second stage: after the creation of Eve.
1. The first Logos revelation to Adam and Eve,
This revelation comprised the command offruitfulness and an exten-
sion of the task.
a. The command: “Be fruitful and multiply" is issued by the Logos.
This is already a clear indication that the depreciation of marriage which is
endemic to many schools of current philosophy finds no support in Scrip-
ture. We can gain a sound perspective on marital life onlyif, preserving the
word of God, we look with wonder upon the genetic development of human
life as the result of the Spirit's action, which causes human life to flourish
(Ps. 127 and 128), both through the proliferation of mankind and through
the flourishing of the life of plants and animals which keeps pace with the
former (Deut. 7:13 and many other places).
b. Following immediately upon the command of fruitfulness is the
mandate: "subdue the earth and have dominion overthe fish of the sea,"
etc. If we comparethis task with the task Adam had been entrusted with be-
fore the creation of Eve, then it appears that it has been considerably en-
larged: the mandate is no longer confined to the garden, but also has refer-
Draft b JHK Translation Page 243
Isagoogé Phitosophiae
ence to the earth and the sea. This extension is no doubt related to the pos-
sibility of the development of the human race given with the creation of Eve.
2. Religion
a. It is no longer the religion of a single person, but of a married cou-
ple. This has two consequences. The first spiritual institution is rooted
from the outset in the prefunctional: wedlock is viewed here as a relation-
ship of two fellow humans both of whom arecreated in the image of God.
Comment 5: We must, of course, be careful not to identify “being-in-the-im-
age-of-God" with this interhuman institution: there is no trace in Scripture
(unlike the conceptions prevalent among many pagan peoples) of a sexual
bend in God.
On the other hand, it is only here that Adam's prefunctional office
finds its completion. For it was not until after the creation of Eve that
Adam could act before God also on behalf of another in the things that must
be performed before him on behalf of that other (those others), and thus
could become “a type of the one who was to come" (Rom. 5:14).
b. With respect to their knowledge of the antithesis of good and evil,
the following should be kept in mind. Before the Fall Adam and Eve had by
experience that which was “good,” namely, to live as children of God who
showed the love of their heart through obedience and through observing the
warnings of the Logos against the danger that threatened from the world of
the spirits. One of the ways in which they did this was that each, in their
relationship to their neighbor, did notlive for themselves, as a little world in
itself (microcosmos) or as an individual that shuts itself off from its envi-
ronment, but in mutual relationship with his or her neighbor. That neighbor
was equipped in a different way, but stood in the same relationship to God
and was subjected to the same law(s).
Nevertheless, in this period some knowledge of evil was not lacking.
To be sure, the first human beings did not possess this knowledge by experi-
ence, unlike their knowledge of the good. Yet an easily pictured act had
been forbidden them. They were aware of this prohibition, and of the fact
that death was threatened in case the act in question was performed.
Thus even before the Fall life was not without the threat of danger.
Nor was it without the royal battle in fulfilling the task in service to God,
the struggle that constitutes the meaning of history. For the future of
mankind, therefore, everything depended on the question whether Adam, the
Office-bearer, would stand in obedience on God's side in this battle against
the evil one, or would be disobedient to his Creator.
122. The covenant of creation after the Fall
A. Human life in and immediately after the Fall.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 244
Isagoogé Phitosophiae
Holy Scripture, the only source for our knowledge aboutthese things,
informs us that man was deceived by Satan. Morespecifically, he was de-
ceived with the help of cunning and delusion. For by the question: "Did
God say?" the covenant relationship was swept aside as well as the word of
God robbed of its character as law. With this the road was paved for the
proclamation of the ideal of Autonomy: eritis sicut Deus ("You will be like
God"].
The actual catastrophe took place when after Eve Adam also suc-
cumbed, For with that also the head ofthe covenant proved to be unfaithful
to God, willfully disobedient to his law, and the weaker one vis-a-vis the en-
emy.
As a result of the forbidden deed Adam and Eve now nolonger stand
in a relationship of trust to God: they now fear his wrath. But also the
reciprocal interrelation suffers the consequences: sincethey first imagine, in
their delusion of sovereignty, that they will become God, they are now
alienated from each other: he who denies that he is subjected to the laws
imposed by God will also fail to see the interrelationship, for this stands
subject to the laws.
Good and evil now no longer stand in their life in the relationship of
that which is present to that which is denoted, but in that of past to present.
Tainted by sin and moreover no longer able to do the good that the com-
mandment continued to require of them, and therefore also guilty in that in-
ability, they were now subjected to death. This was a penalty that also, on
the basis of Adam's position of office, spread to Eve and all her descendants
(Rom, 5:12).
The Fall of course did not elevate men above the law: the trans-
gression of the law occurs under the law. Nor did the changein the world's
State affect the structure of man and mankind: Adam and Eve will soon be-
comethe ancestors of their descendants.
The nature of man, however, was something that, though it was not
lost, did undergo a great change. As we have seen, being-in-the-image-of-
God and standing in original righteousness to his law was initially inherent
to man’s nature. Now both of thoserelational states turned into their oppo-
site at the Fall. As far as the former is concemed, the statement of Z. Ursi-
nus applies: "Man is transformed by the Fall from a glorious image of God
to an abominable image of Satan." And as to the second state: original
righteousness was now replaced by unrighteousness.
Comment 1: This twofold refusal can
be represented diagrammatically as
follows:
Draft p JHK Translation Page 245
isagoogé Phitosophiae
It goes without saying that a man with such a radically altered nature
could no longer occupy the prefunctional office, in other words, that Adam
had to be relieved of his office.
Comment 2: On the strength of the distinction between being-image and of-
fice, the Reformation here asserted against Roman Catholicism that man's na-
ture, though transformed in the bad sense, was not lost; whereas his office
was.
ft. Introduction
meant that the second Adam, unlike his predecessor, had to stand firm in
temptation. But since re-creation is not a second creation, he also had to
bear on behalf of his own the punishment that had been fixed for breaking
the first covenant, in order to satisfy God's justice and to propitiate his
wrath,
if we compare this task with that of the first Adam, then we observe
that it has become immensely more difficult. For the weight of God's wrath
against the sin of the entire human race could not be borne by any human
being: consequently the office-bearer of the second covenant had also to be
God. As man, as the seed of the woman, he had on the one hand to be
joined with Adam in the state of innocence, and on the other hand to be par-
allel with him, that is, to be free from his sin. Therefore we must distin-
guish in the Messiah (Greek: Christos) the unification of the Logos with a
concrete, individual human nature, and the conception ofthe paternal factor
of the latter from the Holy Spirit, although these two were not separate in
time. Furthermore, a distinction must be made between these two, which
made the execution ofthe task ofoffice possible, and the investiture with the
office.
Comment 3: The church here spoke of “nature,” and not of “person” (in dis-
tinction from Nestorius), in order to indicate that, supposing the concept of
person was serviceable in anthropology, the human constituent in the Mediator
never existed separately, that is as component, since its very origination was
subservientto the incarnation of the Word.
Consequently, the positive correlate of the rejection of the view advocated
by Nestorius is that the Person of the Son has united himself with the human
nature, and that the result of this unification (Henasis) is a unity (Henofes), not
a unit.
This formula is to be distinguished from a completely different one, ac-
cording to which the human nature of the Mediatoris said to be “impersonal”
(anhyposiatos). For this expression (which moreover has at least three senses
and thus can hardly be called univocal) means in essence that either something
of the nature in question is denied (either its individuality or its integrity) or
this nature is seen as a duality that requires a vinculum substantiale
[“sunstantial means of connection”), a role assumed in this case by the Son of
God. None of these constructions therefore agrees with Holy Scripture or
with dogma.
Comment 4: The virgin birth therefore does not imply a contempt for mar-
riage (as P. A. Kohnstamm and his followers believe) but on the contrary,
served the salvation ofall of humanlife, including marriage.
b. The relationship of the office-bearer to the word of God.
in contrast to the case of the first Adam, this relation is constant: in
life and death Christ according to his human nature placed his reliance on
the word of God, and does this still. Thus in the hour of temptation he
Draft D JHK Translation Pape 248
lsagoogé Phitosophiae
proved stronger than Satan, for which reason the angels came to serve him
(Matt. 4:1-11).
c. The relationship of the office-bearer to those comprehended in him.
This relation as well is different from formerly. Because while all
those comprehended in thefirst covenant were to descend from Adam, and
he did in fact become, through Eve, the ancestor of us all, one participates
in the Christ only by imputation. This imputation is two-sided: "God made
him who knew nosin to besin for us, so that in him we might become the
righteousness of God" (2 Cor. 5:21; [cf.] Rom 8:3; Gal. 3:13; 1 Peter 2:22-
24).
With respect to both sides (that is, also as far as the second part, being
declared righteous, is concerned) this imputation is anchored in election,
which is distinguished from predestination—the formeris only a decision for
good, the latter is a decision for both goodand ill.
Scripture tells us that both predestination and election exist. However,
it does not tell us by name who are included in election, except in a few
cases, and then only of persons who have died long ago (compare Gen.
26:23 with Mal. 1:2 and 3 and with Rom, 9:12 and 13). Yet we are not in
the dark in this regard. Predestination and election are worked out in time,
a process in which the God of the Covenant adheres to the structure ofhis
own work ofcreation.
125, The covenant worked out in time
In the process of working out the covenant, being declared righteous
becomes a being made righteous [justification].
Thelatter takes place first of all in the Mediator, specifically in the ac-
ceptance of his suffering and death at his resurrection from the dead
(Rom.4:25).
This fruit of his work is now conferred by the glorified Christ on all
who belong to him in their justification, which is comprised in that calling
by which he makes the spiritually dead alive. For this making alive or re-
generation is the turning around of the heart, which has the effect that the
renewed person, acquitted of guilt and punishment, and having a right to
eternal life, begins to walk accordingto all God's commandments.
Comment 1; This act of God takes place “immediately,” thatis, not by means
of the persuasion ofthe will (Remonstrants) or of the persuasion of predestina-
tion (school of Saumar), but directly by the word of God, in the sense of voca-
tio efficax: it is God who gives life to the dead and calls into existence the
things that do not exist [Rom. 4:17 RSV].
This turnabout can be diagrammed as
follows:
Draft D JHK Translation Page 249
Isageogé Phitosophiae
This act of God is not to be identified with the preaching of his word
by the envoys of the Christ: for regeneration precedes the opening of the
heart to the word of their preaching (Acts 16:14).
Comment 2: The revival of this insight since the end of the previous century
is especially due to the influence of A. Kuyper.
However, this given of the Scriptures is combined in Kuyper with two
other statements that can in any case be distinguished from it and therefore
ought to be considered separately.
The content of these statements was that regeneration was the embryonic
seed, and furthermore thal it was accompanied by a testimony ofthe Spirit to
the effect that Scripture is God's word. With reference to the first statementit
may be remarked that Scripture (Luke 8:11 ff.) compares the (open) heart with
the (prepared) earth, but relates the image of the seed to the preached word.
With respect to the second notion we observe the following: it was Kuyper's
intention to keep the testimony in question purely “formal,” in opposition to
the doctrine of the “inner light," of which he was a vigorous opponent, His
conception regarding the restimonium Spiritus Sancti speciale must not be con-
fused with the theory of a testimonium Spiritus Sancti generale. Nonetheless
the former was certainly not without content either, which is not surprising
since a “testimony” simply cannot be formal. Moreover, such a testimony is
superfluous: Scripture in itself is credible, and must be acknowledged by the
regenerate without such a testimony; whatit tells us about the testimony of the
Spirit does not comeuntil after christian faith, and therefore is not dealt with in
this study until Jater. For that reason both additions are to be rejected.
However, this criticism may not lead to a rejection of the basic statement:
in the struggle against the overestimation of ecclesiastic office on the remote
and recent past, the latter constitutes an important gain.
Regeneration also effects a turnabout in the pistic function (the fides
qua creditur, i.e. faith by which a person believes}. By virtue of this turn-
about, faith is now directed to the word of God that is preached (by the ec-
clesiastic office-bearer), especially to its essence, namely the Gospel. En this
way faith, now in the sense of that which is believed (fides quae creditur), is
awakened by the preached word,
This awakening is followed by strengthening. This takes place par-
tially by that same preached word, partially by the use (in faith) of the
sacraments.
The preached word, which is always unconditional, comprises partially
prediction, partially promise.
The prediction concerns the first or second coming of Christ, which
took place (will take place) despite unbelief among God's people (Gen.
18:12, Isaiah 7:12ff, Luke 1:18 and 18:8).
The promise, on the other hand, has a different character. As promise
it is directed not only to the believers, but also to their children and to those
who have been taken up together with them into the fellowship of the
church; and now,as the promise of God, whois the faithful One, it demands
Draft D JHK Translation Page 250
lsagoogé Phifosophiae
Within this period we must again distinguish two phases, namely the
one before and the one after the Flood.
129. Before the Flood
A. The Logos revelation
Since man had been seduced by Satan, the first rapprochement(if there
was to be any question of living-with-God-again) had to come from Gead's
side, something that was only possible through the love of God.
God did in fact come. Taking the new situation into account, his love
has the character of grace: already in Paradise he announces the Mediator of
the New Covenant. This Mediator, as the seed of the woman, will live in
enmity with the seed of the serpent, but will be victorious in that struggle.
B. Religion
1. Correlate with this change in revelation is a change in religion:
though saved from debasementit is not restored to the old situation, but be-
comes religion appropriate to the new situation, religion of grace. The re-
newed faith, likewise, no longer holds for truth only the word of God spo-
ken before, but also the promise of God concerning the deliverance ofall
who believe this promise (as the Heidelberg Catechism puts it [Q & A 21]:
“not only to others, but to me also").
2. Not all, however, participate in this faith: not a few arrogantly re-
ject the promises of God.
That difference can already be observed empirically in the life of the
first family: Eve accepts the promise and relies on the God of the Covenant
(Gen. 4:1). Cain, on the other hand, is arrogant: when God does not accept
his sacrifice he burns with anger, does not listen to the warning against a
new sin, and does not concern himself, even after his evil deed, about any-
thing but the preservation of his own life, now struck by a special curse
(Gen. 4:3-14),
Comment: The council of God also includes this difference. Predestination,
which has reference to all development, is of course double (gemina) with ref-
erence to the taking of these two ways; when it concerns a decision for good,
it is called election. Accordingly, election is not gemina, providedit is distin-
guished from predestination,
3. In connection with this difference in the human race, the antithesis
now revealsitself therein. This is of course also discernible in the working
out of the task that was assigned to mankind, andin the cultural results ofits
efforts.
130. After the Flood
A. The supplementation in Logosrevelation at the time of Noah,
1. Although faith in the promises of God remained (Gen. 5:24), sin
gained groundrapidly, and the earth was even filled with violence [cf. Gen.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 2.54
fsagoogé Philosophiae
6:11]. Therefore God repented that he had made the creatures. Yet he did
not destroy his work, but decided to mitigate the outbreak ofsin.
2, Simultaneously with this announcementofhis instruction to Noah,
God also makes known to him the term “covenant” (Gen. 6:18) in order to
give an indication of life after the Flood in reliance on this grace. In ad-
ministering the covenant with a severely chastised humankind, which was
preserved in that very chastisement, God does not only refrain from punish-
ing men with a second Flood, but also communicates this intention of his,
proclaiming the appearance of the rainbow as a reminder of his promise. He
also allows the consumption of animal meat for food, promises a regular al-
ternation of seasons, and bridles sin by including in governmental law the
blood revenge that had already been exercised before (Gen. 4:23).
B. Religion
1. By faith (which is not only found among the Semites!) in this en-
riched promise, the periodic cultivation of the land, and of the animals that
are required for it, becomes possible. Presupposed in this faith is trust in
the basic promise of deliverance.
2. At the same time unbelief (which is also found among the de-
scendants of Shem!) has the effect that people regard as divine certain inter-
relations (e.g. between sky and earth or between the two sexes), offices
(office-bearers), things (sun and moon, etc.), or functions (thinking, imagi-
nation). Unbelief also attaches itself to the periodicity of seasonal change by
dishonoring God in the worship of plant gods. As a result ofall of this the
assurance of faith is replaced by a sense of insecurity. Thus we understand
how animism could forget that the nonhuman earthly creatures stand in reli-
gious relation to God, only by way of man, and, proceeding from the correct
assumption that there is psychic life also in animals, explained this fact to be
a result of the transmigration of the soul. In this way animism led to the
prohibition of slaughtering, by which the benefits of the Noachian covenant
were largely nullified.
Comment 1: The confusion of soul and psychiclife is an ancient error.
Comment 2: The covenant with Noah is therefore a phase in the covenant of
grace-the second in the period of nondifferentiated Logos revelation. The de-
nial of this character is related to two misconceptions. According to the first
of these, life between Fall and Flood had brought the late flowering of the
covenant of creation; according to the second, the covenant of grace did not
begin until Abraham. Neither of these views is correct: the main incision of
history is found not at the Flood, but at the Fall, and the covenant of grace al-
ready begins in Paradise, when God, in the absence of a worthy office-bearer,
promises provision in the mother promise.
This also disposes of the possibility offitting the relationship between the
covenant with Noah and that with Abraham into the scheme nature-prace,
Draft D JHK Translation Page 255
Isagoogé Phitosophiae
Distinct from this law are the commandments for public life, which
now restrain blood revenge in family law, and the prescriptions concerning
ceremonial practices that certified promises or served to recall the mighty
acts of the God of the Covenant and to avert mingling with the pagansliving
in the area (for example, the command notto eat certain animals that played
a prominent part in many heathen religions precisely on the basis of their
connection with the grave and death).
Comment: In sharp contrast to a fascination with death found among some
nations in the vicinity who considered death to open the possibility for extraor-
dinary development, the word of God continued to see death as punishment.
ThatIsrael, in time, also came to know some things aboutthe difference in the
situation after death, between those who embraced and those who rejected
God’s promises, and especially with regard to the difference after the resur-
rection (Psalm 49), is obviously something completely different,
3. The prefunctional office of the Messiah is foreshadowedin the three
offices of prophet, priest, and king, which stand next to each other. The
Messiah, however, will fill all three together. He will be a prophetlike
Moses and a king like David. The priesthood proved to be more difficult,
for that was tied to a tribe other than Judah. Hencetheprediction about the
Messiah as priest and king talks of a future in which the differentiation of
the revelation to Abraham will be removed: the Messiah will be a priest in
the order of Melchizedek (Psalm 110). These prophesies are secure, even if
they are not believed, not even by those who, as membersofthe holy line,
will be most affected when they fulfilled (Isaiah 7:1-17).
B. Religion
1. The special promises to Israel also require a special faith. Unbelief
and the breach offaith on the part of membersof the national community are
soundly rebuked. If they do not take the warning to heart, then the curse
will come for breaking covenant. Differences still remain. The sin is more
serious as: the promises are repeated (Deuteronomy 29:21), the covenantis
renewed (Joshua 5:1-9), the command becomes morespecific (Joshua 6:18
and 7:1), the promise narrows to one family (2 Samuel 7 and Isaiah 7:17),
prophecy becomes less scarce (Isaiah 24:6), or the reformation among the
people was more robust (Zechariah 5:3) and with that the break more reso-
lute. The punishment, too, is correlated with the difference in guilt. Some-
limes the curse even affects the culture of those being punished (Joshua
7:24, Zechariah 5:4).
2. At the same time God remains a God of the nations who do not
know these rights (Psalm 147:20), live without the law, that is, this law
(Romans 2:12), but are then, without being judged by this law, also lost
simply by not believing the promises that were revealed to them. That does
not take away from the fact that God is good to individual aliens, outside Is-
Draft D JHK Translation Page 257
Isagoogé Philosophiae
rael's community and excluded from their paschal feast (Exodus 12:43 and
Deuteronomy 10:18), as well as to whole groups. For example, the heavy
punishmentthat strikes Egypt and Babylon stands over against God's good-
ness towards Nineveh when only the threat of judgment brings them to re-
pentance.
2. As believers they now know all things (1 John 2:20), that is to say,
with respect to the previously and for the most part hidden will of God con-
cerning salvation, and yield fruits of the spirit in thanksgiving.
3. Moreover, they live and die in the expectation of Christ's return.
For, now that they can distinguish the two comings of God's Son, a clearer
light also falls on their dying. Dying, still now, involves a being
disengaged from one’s context. People dread that (2 Corinthians 5:1-4).
People prefer that the Christ would return, so that the way to the grave
would be replaced with a sudden and, they will admit, necessary change.
But two prospects will comfort Christians who die young. Thefirst is this,
that the punishment that will also befall them, as children of Adam, comes
along with a blessing. For them too,life's unity will be broken. But at the
same time, the struggle between "spirit" and "flesh," that consumed their
life, is over. While on earth evil desires sprang from their hearts too, now
their soul, purified of these things, lives with the Lord (2 Corinthians 5:8).
And their body will soon follow suit. Though buried in corruption,
dishonor, and weakness, their body, like their soul, will not fall prey to
death. This seed, connected as it is to the Holy Spirit, will be raised as a
spiritual body (1 Corinthians 15:42-3). The believers who do experience the
return of the Christ will, up until that moment, likewise be mortal and have
to “put on" immortality.
Both groups of Christians, those raised and those changed, are then
freed from the power of the second death to which the remainder will be
subjected (Revelation 20:14 and 21:8, compared to 2:11 and 20:6).
Comment: “To be subjected to the second death" is not "to be annihilated,"
just as “continue to exist” is not the same as "be immortal." Both confusions
can be found among advocates of what they call "conditional immortality." To
refute them soundly one must not only avoid the first mistake, but the second
as well. Scripture teaches that all human beings continue to exist in soul and
body after death. But, departing from humanistic usage which attributes im-
mortality only to the higher [part], but then also to the higher [part] of al! hu-
man beings already on this side of the grave (!), Scripture also teaches that
only believers in Christ will put on immortality, just after the resutrection and
as whole persons,
God's restorative activity, our pistic function takes to be true and certain
what this revelation says to us, namely, that we have an eternal covenant
with God, and that what it says about the blessing and curse of that covenant
therefore also holds for us. As long as we keep this covenant, and put to
death our flesh, all things will work together for our good and, in spite of
our sins and as apparent from the chastisement, we will belong in life and
death to the Lord, irrespective of whether we know that or not (when sleep-
ing or unconscious). But if we turn away from the Christ, God will hide his
face from us as well and, if we do not return, we can expecta stiffer judg-
ment than those who have disregarded a narrower revelation. Accordingly,
the struggle rages precisely in the life of the Christian between "flesh" and
“spirit” (Romans 7), that is, between the old and the new man.
Comment: This struggle does not exclude that of one function against the hy-
pertrophy of another. That kind of difficulty, although an effect of the Fall, is
also evident among those who are entirely oblivious to the struggle of the
Christian. They consider the solution to this difficulty to be the most
important one and try with their own power to become its master. However,
this is what Paul refers to as “carnal.”
PART Ill
THE CONNECTION
BETWEEN HEAVEN AND EARTH
137. Introduction
Wehave now dealt with the most prominent structures known to us of
that which is created. In Part I we discussed the few givens about heaven
and in Part IJ, those concerning the earth.
It still remains for us to turn our attention for a momentto the connec-
tion between these two.
The connection between heaven and earth is often equated with the
connection between the higher and lower functions of man. The claim is
then that human beings are made up of a spiritual and a material substance,
with the spiritual substance displaying varying degrees of affinity with the
heavenly spirits,
Against that the following can be noted.
1. In our investigation of the cosmos we have come across many things, but
no substances.
Comment: "Hypostasis” in Holy Scripture is in its religious sense “firm foun-
dation."
In its use outside Scripture distinguish with respect to this word its nonsci-
entific and scientific usage, and within the latter, between special scientific and
philosophic usage.
Here, of course, we are dealing exclusively with its philosophic usage,
where the word always implies possessing a self-sufficient ground (self-suffi-
ciency notin the sense of disposition). Its use in this sense is, then, obviously
out of the question.
2. This standpoint does not distinguish the spirit of men from the higher
functions. In other words, it honors a functionalistic conception of the hu-
man heart.
3. This approach does not bring out that the individual human being, also
functionally, is an unbroken subject unit.
4. Religion, in this view, is linked either to a presumed goal built into things
or to asceticism,
5. The genetic connection in which the individual human being stands to
Adam is denied for the higher functions.
C. Trying to avoid functionalism, some equate the difference between
heaven and earth with the intraindividual connection between the human
heart (soul, spirit) and the cloak of human functions (body). What they do
keep, however, is the idea of a composition.
One should be warned aboutthis position on the following grounds.
1. Spirit in Holy Scripture means directional principle. That is why this
word can be used in the sense of the religious center of earthly as well as
heavenly creatures that are directed, obediently or not, to serve God. There
are simply no grounds(also not in Holy Scripture) for concluding on the
basis of this common designation of creatures, which in this usage are named
after one side only, while actually belonging to different worlds, that there
exists a much more comprehensive connection. When spiritualism, true to
its individualistic roots, negates the [reality of] office, it ought to realize that
the realists (in the medieval sense of the word) had as much (or as little)
tight, based on the nameofthe office "angel" (= messenger), to postulate
the connection between heavenly and earthly hierarchy.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 263
Isagoogé Philosophiae
APPENDIX
PART I
HUMAN KNOWING
imroduction
Division |
Nonscientific Knowing
149, Introduction
As for nonscientific knowing we can distinguish its structure andits
development. A chapter is devoted to the discussion of each of these two.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 267
Isagoogé Philosophiae
CHAPTERI
THE STRUCTURE OF NONSCIENTIFIC KNOWING
150. Whar knowing is
Knowing is having knowledge, hence living in a state of rest.
151. Knowing and coming to know
This state of rest follows on a state of greater or smaller effort, during
which one “comes to know."
1. We remember that the psychic belongs to the substrate ofall the higher
functions.
2. The mention of that which is analytic as well as that which is supra-ana-
lytic. People obstruct their own ability to discern the richness in nonscien-
tific knowing when they do not acknowledge these supra-analytic functions
or, as the apriorists, take them to be pre-analytic and, in so doing, have no
place for retrocipations to that which is analytic.
B. It is correct distinguishing.
If analytic functioning is poor due, for example, to exhaustion, then
mistakes are made andthe result is not knowledge buterror.
C. it is always a distinguishing of that which is different from the other
with which it is connected horizontally and vertically.
156. Division
In connection with the last point we must take note of the role of the
analytic interrelation (1) as well as of the vertical connection in the activity
of coming to know (2).
157. introduction
The diversity within the analytic interrelation is just as great as the di-
versity in the horizontal connections of any other modality. We distinguish
the synchronic (a) and the diachronic (b) interrelations.
2. The distribution of analytic perceptions into outer and inner does not
coincide with that of interindividual and intraindividual, which crosses it.
Hence, there are, when we take both distinctions into account, not two
groups, but four.
Comment: We have io be very careful with the use of the terms "inner" and
“outer” as adjectives of "perception,"
1, They may never be used to refer to a difference in the function of what is”
perceived; as in, for example, inner perception is perception of the psychic
and outer is of the physical.
2. In order to say exactly what is meant when using these terms, mention
should also always be made of whether the interrelation of perception is in-
traindividual or interindividual; in other words, whether you are perceiving
something of yourself or of someone or somethingelse.
member now that I looked as well as what I saw. Thefirst of these was an
activily on my part, the looking which I now recollect. Hence, that looking
stands in a successive intraindividual connection with my rememberingthis.
The second was what I perceived analytically at the time, namely,the prints
with which I then stood in an interindividual connection. The conclusion
would seem to be valid that there exist both interindividual and intraindivid-
ual interrelations of recollection,
However, further reflection brings to light that the cases are not the
same. It is possible that I recall that I saw something without knowing ex-
actly what I saw, in other words, what precisely that something was. For
example, when [ have to prove my alibi for the hour during which | was
busy with that looking, or am looking for a pencil that I think J have lost in
the mean time, then what I saw not only moves completely into the back-
ground, but recalling it is simply not included in the recollection of my ac-
tion. But now the other case. It can certainly happen that I remember very
well what I saw and barely that I saw it. That will happen often when what
I am looking at during the interindividual perception of my looking had my
complete attention. And yetit is not possible for me to recollect what I saw
as seen without having the other recollection, namely, the recollection of the
seeing, inherentto this recollection.
That is why an intraindividual action is primary when it comes to rec-
ollection.
E. Whatis recalled can be a subject as well as an object.
1. In the example just introduced, I remember my seeing of yesterday.
What is passive in this interrelation, then, is the functioning of a subjectin
the past.
2. In contrast, when I remember my biotic reaction to a previous
change in climate, what is being recalled is an intraindividual analytic ob-
ject.
F. In discussing perceptions, we noted that there are perceptions of per-
ceptions [see §§160D1 and 161E1]. Something similar is the case with rec-
ollection. I can remember that yesterday I was involved in a conversation
filled with recollections of my youth. In these cases, what is remembered is
always an action of the subject.
This irreducibility does not exclude the possibility that both can be
there al the same time (see §166) and occur together (see §167).
ceived by the one who was expecting it, the expectation later becomes rec-
ollectable. But however closely connected with each other, the act of recol-
lection never becomes expectation, nor the latter a recollection: they con-
linue to differ in time direction.
170. Introduction
Up until now I discussed only the horizontal connections in knowing.
Here too however, evidence of vertical connection is not absent. We find it
in thinking as well as in the knowable; for that which is analytic is far from
an isolated chamber of consciousness or categorial apparatus. | will only
discuss thinking here.
If there is to be talk of connection however, then there must also be
difference. That is why I first take up the difference and then the evidence
of connection.
171. The difference between the analytic and the otherfunctions
It is not necessary to work out the difference between the analytic
function and all of the others: an exposition of the difference between it and
a few of the others, mainly immediately adjacent functions is sufficient; but
also needed because of the prevailing confusion.
A. The difference between the analytic function and a few lower ones.
1. The analytic function is often identified with the mathematic func-
tion. This identification is rooted in different causes. Some call both the
analytic as well as the mathematic “abstract” (a}; on the other hand, others
view both as “apriori" (b).
a, The first way of speaking appeals to the fact that that which is math-
ematic is never present other than in nonmathematically qualified things and
thus must be separated out from these. But this process is entirely different
from that of abstracting, e.g. from individuality when thinking about math-
ematic figures and nonmathematic things.
b. He who calls the analytic and the mathematic both “apriori" is first
of all of the opinion that the analytic does not rest on the sub-analytic, but is
joined to the latter as a donum superadditum, and then connects this outlook
with the fact that that which is supra-mathematic presupposes that which is
mathematic. But against the first claim it can be remarked that nothing in
the cosmosis apricri, and against the second, that "being presupposed” sig-
nifies here “being substrate," thus implies the exact opposite of this sup-
posed apriority.
2. The still frequent confusion of the analytic with the psychic is usu-
ally rooted in the lack of clarity concerning that which is psychic; so that
Draft D JHK Translation Page 277
isagoogé Phitosophiae
B. The Knowable
173. What is knowable
Perceiving, recollecting, expecting: these all proved to be a directing
of oneself to what is knowable in the present, the past, and the future. For
us to give account of what knowledge is we must also ask what is knowable
in that towards which suprapsychic distinguishing is directed.
The following are knowable:
A. God to the extent he has revealed himself both through his word as
well as through his creatures, to the extent we can know these.
Comment I: God, therefore, can be known through two means. If one uses
the terms “Scripture and nature“ for these means, one ought to keep in mind:
a) that there was a time in which the word of God was not yet written; and b)
that nature should be understood to be all the work of God and especially not
only a part of earthly creatures. In this sense “nature” also includes all institu-
tions and the genetic course ofaffairs therein, for better and for worse.
Comment 2: Not all of the works of God are knowable for us, as will be seen
below,
B. His law governing the cosmos and knowable by the light of the word
of God from the cosmos.
C. The cosmos; more specifically:
1, Heaven, in the sense of the world ofspirits, to the extent we receive
communication about it from the word of God.
2. Earth, a) to the extent we receive communication about it from the
word of God, and b) to the extent we can investigate its past, present, and
future.
As for the latter, we oughtto distinguish further:
1} the primary state of affairs, that is to say, what in that which is
knowableis notitself knowledge or error, and
Draft D JHK Translation Page 279
Isagoogé Phitosophiae
174. The connection between the activity in coming to know and what is
knowable
The thinking subject belongs to the cosmos.
That is why, negatively, it cannot transcend the limits of the cosmos.
Onthe other hand, positively, it stands connected with all that is know-
able:
1. with God, who also calls coming to know into his service as expression of
love-filled obedience;
2, with God's law—the relationship to God's law is not simply con-
templative: this law is there neither exclusively nor even primarily to be
pondered, but to be obeyed;
3, also with the cosmos, to the extent it is knowable. That is why we turn
against skepticism, which still has ideals for knowing but despairs of their
realization, as well as against mysticism, which disqualifies coming to know
what lies outside of us as being "external" and considers the knowing pro-
cess to be introspective.
Comment: This connection is a direct one. In other words, it is not the case
that things or people first create impressions in me and that I then arrive at re-
sults by abstracting from the impressions present within me. No, the person
thinking focuses his attention on what is knowable, be it thing or person, and
analyzes it, abstractly or not, there where it is and in so doing arrives at re-
sults.
For that reason, contrary to what the copy theory claims, the connection
between what is knowable and the result is not direct. In between what is
knowable and the related result there is always the analysis of the person
thinking, who analyzes what is knowable correctly or not and, in turn, comes
to knowledge or error concerning what is knowable. Onthis score, Plato and
not Aristotle is right.
Meanwhile, keep in mind that this activity is analytic in character. Re-
jecting the copy theory given the aforementioned grounds in no way implies
Draft D JHK Translation Page 280
fsagoogé Philosophiae
that this activity is creative or even productive. We do not bring forth knowl-
edge or error from ourselves, but come to these two as though they were re-
sults, to be gained only through the analysis of something knowable.
C. The Result
175. Two kinds of result
Wedistinguish here concept and statement.
In the concept we know a state of affairs; in a statement, a state of af-
fairs in relation to something (namely, the subject of the statement).
176. Concept and statement, being determined by the norm, by that which is
known, and by the analytic activity
A, Concept
1. Being determined by the norm.
Not only the activity, but also the result is normed: That is why we
speak of contradictory and noncontradictory concepts.
2. Being determined from the side of that which is known. In this con-
nection we distinguish:
a. Primary concepts, that is to say, concepts aboutstates of affairs that
are themselves not knowledge or error and secondary concepts. Thelatter
are concepts about states of affairs that are conceptual.
b. Extensions of concepts: That the extension of the concept man is
broader than that of the concept woman is rooted in the relationship of the
number of women to the number of men.
3. Being determined from the side of the knower. Wedistinguish here:
a. Perceptual and abstracted concepts.
b. Simple and composite concepts.
B. The statement.
1. Being determined by the norm.
Distinguish contradictory and noncontradictory statements. Being
contradictory or not has to do neither with the statement's subject nor with
its predicate, but with their relation. A statement is contradictory only when
a predicate is and is not attributed to a subject at the same time. Of the fol-
lowing three statements, only the last one conflicts with the norm of prin-
cipium contradictionis [principle of contradiction]: "Truth and falsehood are
incompatible"; "This argument is contradictory"; and "This is true and not
true in the same respect."
2. Being determined by that which is known.
This determines the quality of the statement as well as its extension.
a. Quality here has to do with a statement's relation being positive or nega-
tive.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 281
Isagoogé Philosophiae
CHAPTER 2
THE DEVELOPMENT OF NONSCIENTIFIC KNOWING
177. introduction
Until now I have limited myself to discussing the structure of knowing
at one moment. What was said already then also stood in connection with
the past and the future. But so as to not confuse things, I] proceeded as
though the moment of now would not soon belong to the past and, so also,
as though the past did not increase and the present did not shift. This, natu-
rally, was an abstraction, only permissible for the sake of clarity and under
the condition that | abandon it as soon as possible. Now that I have reached
that goal, I will let go of that abstraction completely so as to concentrate
now on what was disregarded in what was knowable and in knowing,
namely, on what is genetic in both.
178. That which is genetic in the knowable
A. In the word of God.
We saw previously (§§121-134) that this did not remain stationary, but
increased and changed. We also noted (§173) that the word of God is writ-
ten in human language and hence is knowable for us. Combining both of
these givens, we find that in the Aistoria revelationis the word of God, and
hence what is knowable for people, increased.
B. Likewise, that which is accessible in the cosmos to human in-
vestigation does not remain the same, Atoms disintegrate and stars collapse
and melt together; plants, animals, and people, interbreed, evolve, and
vary. A second important element is the fact that we can know the pastbet-
ter than we can the future and hence, as the past grows, what can be known
better does as well. Finally, do not forget the changes and expansionof that
which is knowable that arises from human endeavor: we no longer speak of
the Zuiderzee (South Sea), but of the Lsselmeer (Lake Issel); and on the
polders of tomorrow there will be obviously much more to distinguish
geographically than there is today. Here too then, there is an increase and
change in what is knowable for nonscientific thinking.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 282
Isagoogé Phitosophiae
Comment: Tracing the evolving of humanity leads to a knowledgethat, in the
footsteps of Holy Scripture, people also often found in nonscientific circles
(family trees recorded on the front page ofthe old Bible).
knowledge about the sub-analytic is not safe: a tree is set as “living” over
against "dead" matter, and the like. These and similar distortions in concept
formation are especially dangerous for supra-historic life because the forming
of concepts belongs to its substrate. Misformed concepts will lead to a fault in
the foundation that will prove to be devastating for the edifice built upon it.
Owing to this, government, family, school, and church are continually under-
mined by an anthropology that places a part of man above God's law.
is going to watch C's behavior and will be able to verify whether the conclu-
sion A drew is correct.
194, Demonstration
Demonstrations are social in nature. They use proofs, among other
things, but also all the nonscientific knowledge available. By presenting an
argument onetries to convince one's neighbor squarely; sometimes, just to
persuade in a less objective manner. It is possible to convince someone on
sound grounds, but also on those that are less so. The means one uses to
achieve one's goal make up one of the factors that form a tradition. These
ways and means are of paramount importance for gaining insight into one
part of nonscientific knowledge.
Comment: There is so much more to social life than demonstrative proofs!
Leaders in this area fortunately also have other means at their disposal.
Maintaining invested authority does not stand or fall with the dexterity of the
office bearer in arguing what he considers to be right!
Division IT
Scientific Knowing
198. Introduction
A. Scientific knowing everywhere relies on nonscientific knowing.
B. For now, J can only indicate very briefly what oughtto be discussed in
a theory aboutscientific knowing.
199, Division
Wedistinguish special-scientific and nonspecial-scientific [scientific]
knowing. [ devote a chapterto the discussion of each.
CHAPTER 1
SPECIAL SCIENTIFIC KNOWING
200. The connection between nonspecial-scientific and special-scientific
knowing
Knowing in the special sciences distinguishes itself from nonspecial-
scientific knowing by its ongoingisolation of increasingly refined interrela-
tions in the several law spheres. We speak of a special science when no
more than one nonanalytic modality is investigated.
Comment: "Mathematics," “astronomy,” “zoology,” etc., are terms, formed
at a time prior to a sharp demarcation offields of investigation, that indicate
sciences in an earlier stage. Today, they are separating more and more into
true special sciences. For example, mathematics into arithmetic and geometry,
and theology into pistology and ethics; ethics in this context, then, is always
theological ethics, but notall theology is christian or holy.
201. Method
Being busy in a special scientific way implies then that the analysis of
the investigator is directed to a nonanalytic law sphere.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 291
Isagoogé Philosophiae
CHAPTER 2
NONSPECIAL-SCIENTIFIC SCIENTIFIC KNOWING
206. Summary
Whatfalls under this heading can only be done justice with a broader
discussion than is now possible. Pedagogy, among otherthings, fits in this
bracket. It is much more than a special science.
Draft D JHK Translation Page 293
fsagoogé Philosophiae
PART Il
THE THEORYABOUT
KNOW-HOW AND TECHNOLOGY
207. Introduction
The theory about expertise can only be dealt with much more briefly
than the theory about knowledge. Know-how belongs under the historic
[function] and, hence, presupposes the analytic {functicn].
Wewill first discuss know-how and thenits relationship to science.
Division 1
Know-How
208. Introduction.
We will discuss the following: the relationship between the historic
[function] and know-how, technical mastery, the basis of what is being
worked and the working ofit, and the combination of mastery and assimila-
lion in a higher interrelation.
209. The historic [function] and know-how
Thehistoric [function] includes more than expertise. Even the subject-
object relationship in the historic cannot adequately clarify what know-how
{techné] is. There is also a practical understanding of products of skill.
Know-how can itself only be circumscribed as a practical effort in the rela-
tionship of subject to object within in the historic sphere whose goal is to
satisfy practical-historic needs.
210. Technical mastery
The subject-object relation in the historic [sphere] stands in the fore-
ground here, connected with the schema active-passive. An example can
elucidate this.
From physical things, from pieces of metal, people make machines,
among other things. Before that happened the economic object function of
the metal was not lacking, then already it had an economic value. But it was
not yet a machine. Before it could become that two things were needed.
Here too,it is first the subject function that has something to say. If metal
was less resistant to fire it would not be used for machines. You can only
get out of it what's “in it.” On the other hand, a thing does not become a
machine without "extracting" what's in it, that is, without the often diligent
industry of people.
Draft JHK Translation Page 294
fsagoogé Phitasaphiae
Comment 1: This example also has the advamtagethat those who take the time
to investigate it carefully will be cured once and for all of the theory that
claims that all the sub-economic spheres function like machines. Neither the
organic nor the physical (and therewith, the mechanical) [spheres] are ma-
chine-like.
Here, too, we meet the active-passive correlation. In this case it is
connected to a state of affairs that is somewhat more involved than what we
have found previously. The “mastery” is here that human activity, taking
the make-up of the "material" to be mastered into consideration, changes a
thing's already present object function according to a more or less articulated
plan in compliance with an observed need that someone wants to satisfy.
Comment 2; “To master"—broader than "to form"—is not, on the side of the
subject, "to create," for it presumes the presence ofthe individual created ma-
terial and of the working person. Neither is it, on the side of the object, a
matter of connecting functions it does have with those it doesn't. It is only a
change within the context of the functions already present in the material,
Comment 3: The “material” need not always be a physical thing. Plants and
animals, limiting ourselves for the moment to nonhuman things, can also be
used. Think of the part played by flora and fauna in a botanical garden and in
a zoo.
Why can this mastery only occur through human beings? The grounds
for this are not found in the active-passive schema, which we find already in
the physical [sphere], particularly, in the relationship between corpuscles.
The answer to this question first becomes clear after investigating what
Mastery presupposes modally: not only a psychic desire, but also an analytic
distinguishing, particularly, of means and end as technical correlates. Take
is why mastery is first present in the historic law sphere, in which only hu-
man beings possess a subject function. The more complicated the sphere is
in which the complex change lies, the more mastery it also presupposes.
Art, for example, as aesthetic mastery of material, presupposes more than
just know-how.
211. The basis of know-how
Distinguish between the basis of the mastering and of what is mastered.
A. The basis of the mastering varies, but is never lower than the historic
[function].
B. The basis of what is mastered varies as well. It always lies in the
highest of the law spheres in which the object involved still possesses a sub-
ject function. For metal that is the physical, for plants and animals, respec-
tively, the biotic and psychic law spheres.
Draft B JHK Translation Page 295
lsagoogé Philosophiae
Division 2
Know-How and Science
213. introduction
Distinguish two things here: the relationship of know-how to special
science and to philosophy.
214. Relationship of know-how and special science
Know-how is present in every culture, but never without technical
thinking and knowing in the categories of means and end.
All the same, practical thinking and knowing is something other than
doing and having science. Likewise, know-how inits primitive forms is not
attached to the special sciences.
Therelationship is very different, however, in cultures with highly de-
veloped special sciences. There know-how banks on the special sciences.
Surgery builds on organology, chemistry on physics and organology, and
experiments on various special sciences.
That, however, is also the reason for the confusion in terminology be-
tween fechné (know-how) and technology. These should be distinguished.
Techné is the praxis, while technology is the science about this practical
know-how. Technology, then, is a subdiscipline of the science called his-
tory.
215. Know-how and philosophy
Philosophy, being science, also presupposes practical expertise as part
of nonscientific life.
On the other hand, philosophy has to reflect on the place, on thelimits,
and on the religious sense of practical know-how; something that happens
more and more nowadays.
Draft P JHK Translation Page 296
Isagoogée Philosophiae
PART If
THE THEORY ABOUTART AND AESTHETICS
216. Introduction
Art falls under the aesthetic (law sphere] and hence presupposes much
more than the analytic [function], namely, the historic [function] and know-
how.
Wehaveto discuss here first art and thenits relationship to science.
Division 1
Art
217. Introduction
Once again our attention turns te the relationship between aesthetics
and art, then to artistic mastery, to the basis of what is mastered and of the
mastering, and finally to the combination of mastery and appropriation in a
higherinterrelation.
218. The aesthetic and art
The aesthetic [law sphere] includes more than art. Here too, even the
subject-object relationship in the aesthetic is not sufficient to make clear
what art is. The subjective enjoyment of objective natural beauty is aesthetic
but notartistic. Art, then, can be circumscribed as being practically busy in
the relationship of subject to object in the aesthetic sphere, with an eye to
satisfying aesthetic needs.
Comment: It is best not to replace “needs” with “taste,” which is too rational
and hence one-sided.
Division 2
Art and Science
222. Introduction
Heretoo, given the differences in science, distinguish the relationship
between art and special science and the relationship between art and philoso-
phy.
223. Art and special science
Art presupposes the aesthetic [function], that is, practical knowledge,
not science.
In turn, the science about art presupposes artistic life. This science of
art is a subdiscipline of aesthetics, which is broader.