191571-Article Text-217179-1-10-20190326 PDF

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 24

Traces of Utopia:

Socialist Values and Soviet Urban Planning


J. C. Myers

Diagram of Group Distribution in the Urban Environment


© The Ideal Communist City by A. Gutnov et al.

Not long after the most recent turn of the century, but well past the point at which
a wide variety of commentators had signed and date-stamped socialism’s death
certificate, the publisher of a libertarian website made a disturbing discovery: the
criticisms of suburban sprawl articulated by planners advocating “smart growth” matched
almost exactly the vision put forward by Soviet urban planners in a book entitled The
Ideal Communist City. Mixed-use development would facilitate access to public
services. High-density housing would promote equality and community. Public
transportation would ease congestion by reducing the need for private automobiles. The
New Urbanism was nothing short of a communist plot and its outcome, the author of
Vanishing Automobile Update #53 warned, would be just as grim and foreboding as the
gray world once enclosed within the Iron Curtain.1 In one sense, of course, this was the
sort of hysterical slippery slope paranoia that would have made Colonel Jack Ripper
proud: If the communists tie their shoes with bows, we’d better use square knots!
Fallacious reasoning along these lines was certainly not new in American society, but in

1
“Smart Growth and the Ideal City” <http://ti.org/vaupdate53.html>.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 2

2005 it was strangely anachronistic. Yet, despite its rather feverish overtones, the
recognition of a connection between urban planning and the socialist tradition was not
altogether inaccurate. Socialist politics and urban planning do have something to do with
each other, and understanding their relationship to one another can help us to transcend
the ways in which both friends and enemies of the socialist tradition have often
misrepresented many of its most important elements.
Several of those elements are strongly present throughout the text of The Ideal
Communist City – a fact that is especially intriguing given their severe limitation or
outright denial in the policy agenda of the Soviet Union. This point alone is worthy of
some reflection. Despite the inability or unwillingness of Soviet leaders to pursue a
political strategy recognizable to Western socialists as analogous to their own, socialist
ideas and ideals seem to have remained present and legitimate in the world of Soviet
professionals. But this would represent only one possible reason for reexamining such an
obscure text as The Ideal Communist City and perhaps not even the most important one.
It is unquestionably true that our understanding of the Soviet Union remains clouded by
the ideological context in which so much scholarship about it was produced. More
immediately pressing, though, than the correction of Cold War errors regarding Soviet
socialism is the shoring-up of socialist political philosophy. It will be my contention here
that an analysis of The Ideal Communist City offers us two opportunities in this respect.
As a text directly concerned with the practical transformation of the world, The Ideal
Communist City offered readers an unusually clear presentation of its political agenda –
something ironically lacking in many works more immediately concerned with political
theory. First, then, an examination of some Soviet planners’ visions of a socialist future
will allow us an opportunity for reflection on the central elements of socialist political
philosophy. Some aspects of that vision are far-reaching – even utopian in their
aspirations. Others, however, are so seemingly pedestrian that we risk overlooking their
importance – and here lies the second opportunity that awaits us. The direct materiality
of the register of urban planning can help to reveal that even at its most utopian, socialist
political philosophy retains an immediately practical side whose presence is never far
from daily life.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 3

Urban Planning and the Socialist Tradition

The American edition of The Ideal Communist City found its way into print
through something of a circuitous path. In the late 1950s, a team of Moscow University
academics led by Alexei Gutnov produced the book originally titled Novye Elementy
Rasseleniia (New Elements of Settlement). An Italian translation was issued in 1968
under the title Idee per la Città Communista. This text was then translated into English
in 1971 by New York publisher George Braziller.2 The original date of the text’s
production is important, as it helps to explain its somewhat surprising tone. The bold
socialist utopianism driving the book’s vision seems to run counter to our typical
expectations of Soviet scholarship. But we sometimes forget that the late 1950s was a
time of relative intellectual openness and socialist renewal in the USSR, initiated by
Khrushchev’s 1956 condemnation of Stalin’s tyranny. It was in the climate of the
Khrushchev Thaw that Gutnov and his colleagues set about to create what architectural
critic James Mayo called “a concrete spatial agenda for Marxism.”3
Mayo’s description of the book is meant to indicate something beyond the use of
architecture simply to legitimize political authority. Rather, in The Ideal Communist City
we find an attempt by socialist architects and planners to “interpret physically what their
political ideals could achieve.”4 They begin their work, then, from the basic assumptions
of historical materialism – physical necessity and the social transformation of our
environment:

The premises in question concern human beings, each with a specific biological
make-up. They include their need for food, clothing, shelter, etc., the context into
which they are born (natural and social), and finally their own vital activity,
which takes two different forms: the natural – birth, growth, and reproduction –

2
Alexei Gutnov, et al., The Ideal Communist City, trans. Renee Neu Watkins (New York: George Braziller
1971). See also Boris S. Pushkarev, review of The Ideal Communist City in Russian Review, v. 31, n. 2
(1972), pp. 189-90, p. 190.
3
James M. Mayo, “The Manifestation of Politics in Architectural Practice,” Journal of Architectural
Education, v. 50, n. 2 (1996), pp. 76-88, p. 81.
4
Ibid.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 4

and the social – the collaboration of many individuals in a system of common


action to ensure survival.5

But to these basic premises, historical materialism adds the crucial observation that
human societies organize themselves into classes based on the control of surplus
production.6 Property relationships between direct producers and appropriators of
economic surpluses are understood as central to both social organization and class
conflict.7 Thus, Gutnov et al. recognize connections between class structure and the
spatial organization of urban environments.8 Turning a critical eye to the capitalist West,
they note a relative lack of planning, limiting the ability of architects to grapple with the
problems of mass construction. Worse yet, the architect in capitalist society “must adapt
his work to profound social inequalities.”9 On the one hand, Gutnov, et al. acknowledge
that a communist society must begin its development from within an inherited urban
environment. On the other hand, though, they also express a bold, forward-looking
ambition:

Unlike similar transitional stages in the past, however, the present does not call
on us simply to wait and see how the new communist environment will shape
itself and then to note its characteristics. It is the special and historical claim of
communism to be a work of conscious creation based on theory.10

We can hear in this a strong echo of what Donald Sassoon has described as socialism’s
moral agenda: a refusal to accept distress as the fated human condition.11
There is also here an indication of the affinity between urban planning and the
basic impulses of socialist politics. Historically, urbanization and industrialization have
led to the severe compression of human activities and thereby to discomfort and disease.
Yet, the beginnings of urban planning lie not with the onset of discomfort itself, but with
5
Gutnov, et al., p. 16.
6
Duncan Foley, “Recent Developments in the Labor Theory of Value,” Review of Radical Political
Economics, v. 32, n. 1 (2000), pp. 1-39, p. 6.
77
Ellen Meiksins Wood, The Origins of Capitalism (New York: Monthly Review Press 1999), p. 70
8
Gutnov, et al., p. 21.
9
Ibid., p. 150.
10
Ibid., p. 25-6.
11
Donald Sassoon, One Hundred Years of Socialism (New York: New Press 1996), p. xxiii.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 5

the rise of mobilized protest by those most grievously affected by it.12 It was in this
context that Robert Owen was led to produce what Leonardo Benevolo has identified as
the first fully elaborated urban plan.13 In the early part of the nineteenth century, fierce
riots broke out in several British mill towns. Owen, at the time a young industrialist, was
asked to produce a report on the causes of the unrest and solutions to whatever lay behind
it. He went well beyond his charge, arguing that the source of the riots lay in the squalid
conditions of working class neighborhoods and creating a detailed blueprint for the
complete transformation of urban settlement. Owen’s plan was summarily dismissed by
the government officials who had commissioned it and is now remembered only as an
artifact of nineteenth century utopianism. In it, however, we can recognize germinal
elements of the socialist agenda: a central concern with the lives of ordinary working
people and a desire to improve their lot through the political regulation of property.
Socialist planning is now more typically identified with centralized economic
coordination. Yet, the definition of socialism in such narrow terms has largely been
insisted on by its adversaries. Milton Friedman, for example, bases his critique of
socialism in Capitalism and Freedom on a strict binary choice between market and plan
as methods for economic organization.14 Marx, however, tells us little about economic
planning, and the broad range of social democratic, socialist, and communist
governments that have come to power since the beginning of the twentieth century have
employed varying mixes of market and non-market mechanisms. In truth, of course,
economic planning and the operation of markets have never been mutually exclusive
options. Every capitalist firm begins its production process with planning, and every
contemporary capitalist economy relies on state intervention for its continued operation.15
As much as the sometimes comically poor performance of the Soviet economy pointed
out the severe limitations of centralized economic planning, the impossibility of
unadulterated laissez-faire capitalism was demonstrated conclusively by the Great
Depression. Economic planning is, to be sure, an element of socialist political practice,
12
Leonardo Benevolo, The Origins of Modern Town Planning (Cambridge: MIT Press 1971), p. 32
13
Ibid., pp. 49-50.
14
Milton Friedman, Capitalism and Freedom (Chicago: University of Chicago Press 1962), p. 13.
15
David Schweikart, “Criticism of Ticktin” in Bertell Ollman (ed.), Market Socialism: The Debate Among
Socialists (London: Routledge 1998), pp. 126-7; Alec Nove, The Economics of Feasible Socialism
Revisited (New York: Harper Collins 1991), pp. 43-44; Gabriel Kolko, After Socialism (London: Routledge
2006), pp. 94-99.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 6

but it by no means excludes other economic management techniques, nor is it the


fundamental defining feature of socialist ideology.
In the broadest sense, wherever law is applied with the intention that social order
will result, planning is at work. We might say, for example, that behind the legal edifice
of contract and property law forming the foundation of a market economy lies a plan for
the enrichment and empowerment of those lucky or skillful enough to acquire sufficient
quantities of the right resources and put up for sale the right goods or services. The fact
that this plan does not announce in advance the names of those to whom social surpluses
will flow or the particular mix of goods and services that will appear on the market means
only that the plan – liberal capitalism’s plan – includes certain unplanned elements, as
any plan must. What, then, could we say is specific about planning in the socialist
tradition? The greatest emphasis on planning is surely to be found in the work of the
utopian socialists and their production of highly detailed imaginings of radically
reorganized human settlements. In More and Bellamy, these take the shape of literary
excursions into either the foreign or the future.16 Here, the fictional narrator’s position as
both outsider and amateur social scientist is used to reveal the intentional design behind
social order. Science fiction often depicts alien societies whose difference from our own
is due solely to the ontological difference of alien life itself.17 But More’s Utopians and
Bellamy’s future Americans are human beings like us. Their foreignness lies only in the
fact that they have designed for themselves new institutions and chosen to live according
to new rules. Owen and Fourier then proceed to the next step – moving from fictional
accounts of societies radically reorganized by planning to the production of such plans
themselves.
The New Unit of Settlement (NUS) described in The Ideal Communist City
resembles nothing so much as Owen’s Village of Cooperation or Fourier’s Phalanx. But
in this resemblance we encounter an intriguing contradiction. The NUS is a blueprinted
community, redesigned from the ground up as an intentional effort to produce socialist
values through urban design. Yet, the institutions in which Gutnov and his colleagues
trained and worked routinely declared themselves to be connected to a scientific socialist

16
Thomas More, Utopia (New York: Penguin Books 2003); Edward Bellamy, Looking Backward (New
York: Penguin Books 1986).
17
See Frederic Jameson, Archaeologies of the Future (London: Verso 2007).

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 7

tradition that had broken with utopianism. Though Marx suggests in the Critique of the
Gotha Program that certain elements of socialist society cannot be planned in advance, it
is Engels who draws a sharp line of demarcation between utopian and scientific roads to
socialism.18 The former he finds to be unscientific precisely in their striving for
unachievable levels of exactitude, saying of Owen and Fourier’s designs: “The more
completely they were worked out in detail, the more they could not avoid drifting off into
pure fantasy.”19 For Engels, the opportunities for socialist advance lay not in a complete
break with the present, but in the dialectical possibilities offered up by capitalism. Here,
he draws an analogy with Darwinian evolution, suggesting that every new development
must emerge from within the existing, as both the solution to a fatal limitation and the
chance to extend the usefulness of previous achievements.20 Socialism, in other words,
could not be the product of a lone genius, drafting in isolation the design for a perfect, yet
alien world. Instead, capitalism’s own successes and failures would make the outlines and
building blocks of socialism apparent. Interestingly, this is also the position taken by
Bellamy, who imagines the transition to socialism not as a revolutionary rupture, but as
the natural outcome of capitalism’s own evolution.21
The dialectical tension here – between organic emergence and planned
transformation – is worth examining, as it runs throughout both socialist political thought
and architectural theory. Socialists since Marx have debated the inevitability of
transformation. During much of the twentieth century, a radical version of Engels’
scientific socialism held that a socialist transformation would be brought about virtually
without intentional human intervention. Capitalism’s own drives and contradictions
would result in the necessary forms of change, meaning that no setback was ever really a
setback – everything happened for a reason and all roads led toward the socialist future.
Late twentieth century post-modernism arose as much-needed assault on this view of
history, but too often resulted in the equally hopeless and inaccurate conclusion that
political action led nowhere, except to identically totalitarian forms of closure. Both sides
in the debate could have benefited from one of the fundamental insights of architecture,

18
Karl Marx, Critique of the Gotha Program in Terrell Carver (ed. and trans.), Later Political Writings
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1996), pp. 214-15.
19
Frederick Engels, Socialism: Utopian and Scientific (New York: International Publishers 1998), p. 36.
20
Ibid., p. 48; 52.
21
Bellamy, p. 61.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 8

that within the existing lie multiple, though limited possibilities for change. A particular
site will support certain structures, but not others. Yet, the nature of a site is never such
that all of a structure’s design features are given in advance. Social formations encounter
limits and contradictions. They produce grievances on the part of those who live within
them. But no contradiction or grievance indicates in advance a single, discrete solution.
There is never only one way forward. Engels and Bellamy are entirely correct to suggest
that the ground cannot be cleared and a wholly new society built from scratch. Yet, the
practices of urban planning and architecture suggest their deepest affinities with the
socialist tradition in their ability to remind us that within the realm of the possible, we
remain responsible for an enormous range of very meaningful decisions.

Socialist Values in the New Unit of Settlement

Gutnov et al. identify four fundamental principles governing their design for the NUS:

(1) Equal mobility for all. Residential sectors are at equal walking
distance from the center and from the forests and parks surrounding
them.
(2) Distances are planned on a pedestrian scale. No home is so remote
from the center or from the park area that it cannot be reached by a
reasonably short walk.
(3) Elimination of danger from vehicular traffic. Rapid public
transportation operates outside the pedestrian area yet is linked
centrally with NUS. (Its circuits carry people from home to work and
from home to home.)
(4) Green belts. Every sector is surrounded on at least two sides by open
land.22

The planners’ central concern with social equality is immediately apparent in their
preference for pedestrian and public transportation over privately owned vehicles, as well

22
Gutnov, et al., p. 117.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 9

as in the related bias toward high-density apartment housing. Here, they clearly
acknowledge what is at stake in the planning of residential developments:

Ideal conditions for rest and privacy are offered by the individual house situated
in the midst of nature. But this is an expensive kind of well-being. . . . The villa
is the traditional retreat of the leisured minority at the top of the bourgeois
society. The attempt to make the villa available to the average consumer means
building a mass of little houses, each on a tiny piece of land. . . . The mass
construction of individual houses, however, destroys the basic character of this
type of residence.23

In their rejection of the American model of suburban sprawl, Gutnov’s team specifically
notes its unfeasibility in a society premised on equality.24
As Noberto Bobbio has suggested, the attitude toward equality can be taken as a
defining line of demarcation between the political valences of Left and Right.25 Within
the somewhat narrower range of specifically socialist proposals for the reorganization of
human communities, the emphasis on material equality has always been a defining
feature. More’s Utopians stake out the furthest boundary here, pursuing a radical
equality of personal possessions that extends to items of clothing and obviates the need
for locks on the doors of homes.26 Modern socialism retreats from the Utopians’ radical
fundamentalism, but retains a central concern with equality:

Equality is the expression of the equal value of all human beings and the
precondition for the free development of the human personality. Basic
economic, social and cultural equality is essential for individual diversity and
social progress. Freedom and equality are not contradictory. Equality is the
condition for the development of individual personality.27

23
Ibid., pp. 68-9.
24
Ibid., p. 69.
25
Noberto Bobbio, Left and Right (Cambridge: Polity Press 1996), p. 60.
26
More, p. 53; 55.
27
Socialist International, Declaration of Principles <http://www.socialistinternational.org/
viewArticle.cfm?ArticleID=31>.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 10

Yet, liberalism also claims equality as one of its defining values. What, then, can we say
is specific about the socialist understanding of what it means to be equal? Equality might
be had in any number of different realms: legal, political, economic, or cultural.28
Against the feudal order’s juridically recognized hierarchy of hereditary ranks, liberalism
demanded legal equality: the law’s perception only of abstract individuals, each with
identical packages of rights and responsibilities. Socialism’s origins, of course, lie in the
unveiling of a contradiction between liberalism’s promise and its performance. Marx’s
early writings remain the most eloquent and incisive discourse on the sterility of legal
equality for ordinary working people, who discover daily that liberalism’s abstract
individual is presumed to possess farms, factories, businesses of all kinds, and to be at all
times in the position of an employer of labor, rather than that of an employee. While
liberalism demands legal equality between individuals, it calls with equal vigor for the
protection of private property and, thereby, of economic inequality. Yet, the wealthy
individual’s accumulation of property can, in reality, easily be converted into legal,
political, and cultural forms of advantage.29 Further, within the bargaining regime of the
capitalist labor market, there can be no guarantee that the employer’s naturally
advantageous position (possessing a large stock of resources and being, therefore, able to
survive longer without the laborer than the laborer can survive without a wage30) will not
draw to him or her a disproportionate share of the enterprise’s rewards.31 Many hands
contribute to social production, but as profit is measured against wage in the liberal
capitalist world, some abstract individuals find themselves vastly more equal than others.
Surely the most famous statement of a socialist equality principle is that quoted
by Marx in the Critique of the Gotha Program: “From each according to their ability; to
each according to their need!”32 Here we find a complex vision of equality, far richer
than the leveled-down uniformity of More’s Utopia, as well as a more precise
understanding of the value placed on equality by socialists. Equality might be valued for
its own sake, in which case spartan homogeneity would serve not only adequately, but
28
See, for example, Stuart White, Equality (Cambridge: Polity Press 2007), pp. 4-11.
29
Karl Marx, Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844 in Robert C. Tucker (ed. and trans.), The
Marx-Engels Reader (New York: Norton 1972), pp. 71, 103.
30
Adam Smith, Wealth of Nations (Indianapolis: Hackett 1993), p. 32.
31
Robin Hahnel, “Exploitation: A Modern Approach,” Review of Radical Political Economics, v. 38, n. 2
(2006), pp. 180-1.
32
Marx, Critique of the Gotha Program, p. 215.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 11

efficiently. Yet, the emphasis on abilities and needs in Marx’s equality principle suggests
not homogeneity, but difference. What is meant to be equalized, according to this
principle is the distribution not of resources, but of opportunities for self-realization.33
As Amartya Sen has argued, equal resources put into the hands of people who are by
nature unequal (in terms of strength, disposition, innate skill, etc.) would result in a
skewed distribution of real possibilities for the development of human capabilities.34 Of
course, the search for all possible human capabilities and the matching of resources
necessary to equalize their distribution across a large population would immediately
exhaust the potential of even the most highly developed society. Perhaps as Stuart White
suggests, a more realistically achievable socialist equality principle might aim at the
equalization of a limited set of core capabilities.35 Even this more restricted version of
socialist equality, however, directs its ultimate attention not toward particular goods to be
allocated to all in equal amounts, but toward an equal sharing of the potential for human
freedom.
Yet, freedom is precisely what liberals charge socialists with violating in their
pursuit of greater material equality. Liberalism’s notion of freedom is famously
described by Isaiah Berlin as the absence of external forces steering or restricting
individual choice.36 Milton Friedman usefully illustrates this idea with his suggestion
that Robinson Crusoe, trapped on his island, lacks not freedom, but power.37 So long as
no government compels him to obey speed limits or pay his man Friday a minimum
wage, he remains free. This, for the libertarian anarchist, is paradise: the private island
on which law can never be anything more than the individual owner-ruler’s whim.
Lawless markets, though, can be savage affairs and capitalism has nowhere survived
without states to define and defend property rights, and ensure that transactors keep their
contracts. But even this small step toward political order requires the restriction of
negative freedom. Protecting the shop-owner’s goods from my thieving hands will mean

33
Norman Geras, “The Controversy About Marx and Justice” <http://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/
philosophy/works/us/geras.htm>.
34
Amartya Sen, Choice, Welfare, and Measurement (Cambridge: Harvard University Press 1997).
35
White, p. 87.
36
Isaiah Berlin, “Two Concepts of Liberty” in Robert E. Gooding and Philip Pettit (eds.), Contemporary
Political Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell 1997).
37
Milton Friedman, Capitalism and Freedom (Chicago: University of Chicago Press 1962), p. 12.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 12

denying me a range of choices I would otherwise remain free to make.38 One type of
socialist response to the liberal insistence that freedom is found only in the absence of
law, then, is to say that restricting some forms of action might result in a net gain of
freedom for all. Prohibiting murder, for example, meaningfully limits the range of
choices available to potential murderers. But it is also likely to result in a net gain of
freedom for all in society who might now be able to walk the streets without fear.39
In his consideration of freedom, Larry Preston identifies a fundamental
contradiction shaping our ability to explore the idea in meaningful terms. On the one
hand, we would want to define freedom as a condition in which an agent’s conscious
deliberation plays an essential role in the process of choosing between alternatives. On
the other hand, as observers, we remain unable to enter into the agent’s consciousness in
any unmediated fashion. Thus, any understanding of freedom requires an assessment of
the conditions under which choices are made.40 Liberal political thought, for example,
defines freedom in terms of the presence or absence of external coercion – most typically
in the form of law. As Preston notes, however, this way of understanding what it means
to be free crucially ignores the role played by material resources in the conditioning of
choice. The person who lacks musical training is not free to choose to play an
instrument. The musician who possesses ability but no instrument is similarly unfree.41
For those concerned with what Berlin called “positive freedom,” Robinson Crusoe indeed
lacks freedom of many kinds. Interestingly, after denying the importance of positive
freedom in the case of a stranded castaway, Friedman makes the case that in a socialist
society, advocates of capitalism would be denied freedom because they would lack the
necessary resources to press for their political cause.42
Positive freedom is crucial to Marx’s understanding of both human nature and the
nature of the good society. The human essence, for Marx, is found in our potential for
activity unconnected to the demands of physical necessity. The work that we do in order
to live is forced from us by bodies that grow hungry and thirsty, and a world that
38
G. A. Cohen, Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1995), p.
56.
39
Ibid., pp. 54-5; 237.
40
Larry M. Preston, “Freedom, Markets, and Voluntary Exchange,” American Political Science Review, v.
78, n. 4 (1984), p. 961.
41
Ibid., p. 961, 963.
42
Friedman, pp. 16-17.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 13

stubbornly refuses to provide sustenance without labor.43 Only when our physical needs
are met and we choose to remain active do we do so freely. The resources with which to
satisfy physical necessities represent the preconditions of that freedom. A form of
society compatible with human nature, then, would endeavor to provide its members with
real possibilities for free activity, to the greatest extent possible.44 It is in this sense that
we can best understand Marx and Engels’ description of communist society in the
Manifesto as, “an association in which the free development of each is the condition for
the free development of all.”45 We might note here the stress they place on both equality
and freedom. Equality is valued precisely to the extent that it means equal freedom to
develop human capabilities. We hear this idea echoed by a range of socialist theorists
and organizations:

Every socialist movement’s proud and beautiful goal is a society based on


freedom, mutual cooperation, and solidarity, where all exploitation is abolished
and each individual’s free and harmonious development is the condition of
everyone’s free development.46
Democratic socialism is an international movement for freedom, social
justice and solidarity. Its goal is to achieve a peaceful world where these basic
values can be enhanced and where each individual can live a meaningful life with
the full development of his or her personality and talents and with the guarantee
of human and civil rights in a democratic framework of society.47

The socialist understandings of equality and positive freedom now allow us to perceive
the importance for socialist political theory of public goods. All but the most radical
anarchists will admit the need for certain resources to be decommodified in cases where
free-riding would undermine the supply of a necessary social good. Friedman, for
example, admits that local law enforcement and national defense would be impossible
were consumers allowed to choose on an individual basis how much or how little they

43
Marx, Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts, pp. 74, 76.
44
Ibid., p. 84.
45
Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, The Communist Manifesto (London: Verso 1998), p. 62.
46
Swedish socialist leader Nils Karleby, quoted in Timothy Tilton, The Political Theory of Swedish Social
Democracy (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1990), p. 73.
47
Socialist International, Declaration of Principles.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 14

would like to purchase.48 Socialists, though, have always made the supply of public
goods – and the expansion of such supply – central to their political agenda. But here,
liberal political theory detects a contradiction between positive and negative freedom.
For every public good to be supplied in decommodified form by the state, private
resources must be seized from individuals. And in seizing private resources to be
redistributed as public goods, the state also usurps a range of choices that would
otherwise remain with the individual. Every form of positive freedom supplied
collectively by government comes at the cost of a quantity of negative freedom
individuals must surrender.
The best case that can be made for liberalism’s promotion of freedom lies here, in
the vision of individuals free to pursue their own good in their own way. Yet, both game
theoretic modeling and empirical reality readily demonstrate that lacking political
intervention, the presence of any significant inequality in the possession of productive
resources in a market economy will result in increasing levels of material inequality.49
Unless the scales are to be continually rebalanced by some sweeping form of confiscation
and redistribution, liberal capitalism will always fail to make all individuals equally free
to pursue their versions of the good. As we have already seen, though, any real-world
socialist government will also fail to fully equalize the distribution of all possible human
capacities and must necessarily settle for the goal of a more egalitarian apportioning of a
limited range of core capacities. This compromise will never satisfy the demands of
radical liberalism. Who is to say, the liberal will ask, that the portion of my income you
intend to seize in order to pay for universal public education is not better spent on my
own consumption of fine cigars? If we are forced to weigh goods one-for-one in this
fashion, there may be no adequate response to the charge that nothing more than
individual taste is responsible for valuing one over the other. What we might identify as
core capacities, however, have intriguing multiplier effects that alter their equation with
other goods. Physical necessities – food, clean water, shelter, sanitation – function not
simply as goods, but as the preconditions of our enjoyment of any good. Health care and
education act in even more dynamic ways as multipliers, extending and expanding the

48
Friedman, pp. 23-24.
49
See, for example, Hahnel, pp. 181-3.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 15

range of choices we might make and goods we might pursue. The provision, in other
words, of certain forms of positive freedom – those connected to core human capacities –
may cost us a quantity of negative freedom at the outset, but repay the investment in kind,
many times over.
The support of core capacities through the provision of public goods is, in fact,
the keystone of a broad tradition of social egalitarian political philosophy encompassing
socialism, communism, and social democracy.50 We find this in More’s Utopia and in
Owen’s New Lanark, where fully decommodified supplies of food, clothing, shelter,
education, and child care figure prominently.51 We find it also in the policy agendas of
the socialist and social democratic parties tracing their lineage to the formation of the
Second International.52 It became common during the 20th century to draw sharp
distinctions between the designs of the utopian socialists and the far more modest
achievements of the European parliamentary parties. But such sharp distinctions may
serve the purposes of political competition more adequately than those of political
philosophy. Though far more limited than the provision of public goods imagined by
More or Bellamy, the attempts by Second International parties to even partially
decommodify housing, health care, or education can be understood as sharing with the
utopian imagination an underlying desire to equalize the distribution of opportunities for
freedom.
What is perhaps most intriguing about the urban design described in The Ideal
Communist City is its strong connection to this element of the social egalitarian tradition.
As we have seen, the importance of positive freedom is found in the relationship between
human activities and material resources. Gutnov et al. begin their radical reimagining of
urban space from precisely this nexus, mapping a wide range of human relationships onto
spatial forms. Kinship and family, for example, are seen as linked to individual housing,
school communities, parks, and nature. Necessary productive work is mapped to schools,

50
It is worth recalling here that during the 19th century, no firm lines of demarcation had yet been drawn
between these three terms. Only after WWI and the emergence of strong sectarian divides between parties
did it become possible for political theorists to begin to distinguish the goals of social democracy from
those of socialism or communism.
51
More, pp. 53-55, 62-63, 67, 70, 110; Benevolo, pp. 40-41.
52
See, for example, Sheri Berman, The Primacy of Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
2006), pp. 28-30; Sassoon, p. 24; Tilton, p. 45, 268.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 16

public services, research centers, and industrial or agricultural complexes.53 Two


(related) aspects of the map are particularly intriguing. First, clashing with the Cold War
portrayal of Soviet thought as uniformly oriented toward a totalitarian insertion of rigid
state control into all areas of life, Gutnov’s team includes both freely chosen relationships
and solitude in their list of vital human activities. Their concern to provide for privacy
and solitude is reflected in the discussion of residential space:

Housing for the general population will be substantially altered, yet its
fundamental purpose will remain the same. The human being needs a private
place where he can separate himself from others, rest, sleep, and live his family
life. Housing must respond to these needs; it must create conditions suited to
restoring the physical and moral forces that a man expends in his productive and
social life.54

Second, consumer activity is recognized as representing one particular set of


relationships, rather than the means by which all types of relationships might be
established. The Soviet planners specifically contrast their vision of public parks,
recreational facilities, and club venues with the typical form taken by space devoted to
leisure activity in capitalist countries: the shopping center.55 On the one hand, in the
context of the Soviet Union’s centrally planned economy, it is presumed that spatial
goods will be connected to the system of public supply. On the other hand, though,
Gutnov’s team does not allow the presumption of a state-owned economy to cause them
to lose sight of the connection between the supply of public goods (as forms of positive
freedom) and the support of both core capacities and, ultimately, negative freedom:

Life structured by freely chosen relationships represents the fullest, most well-
rounded aspects of each human personality. These are developed through
choices made during the time free from work, on the basis of interests, desires,
and cultural options open to all. . . . Leisure activity creates numerous individual

53
Gutnov et al., p. 27.
54
Ibid., p. 65.
55
Ibid., pp. 95-96.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 17

and material needs. These mean that areas must be assigned to leisure activity,
areas that, of course, should be fully accessible to everyone.56

Rather than assuming that publicly provided forms of positive freedom will satisfy in and
of themselves the full range of human needs, Gutnov et al. echo Marx’s understanding of
positive freedom as the foundation from which individually chosen paths might be
pursued. As contrasted with the liberal version of the good society, however, the
provision of positive freedoms in the form of public goods is meant to ensure that the
ability to develop individual tastes, preferences, and capacities is not monopolized by a
wealthy elite.
But in addition to spatial and other material resources, an additional element is
required in order for negative freedom to be truly realizable: time must remain in the day,
unabsorbed by the range of necessary activities in the workplace and the household. The
recognition of time as a form of positive freedom was a central aspect of Marx’s work
that has too often been underappreciated. Marx’s early writings divide the field of human
experience into spheres of necessary and free activity, noting that both draw upon the
same pool of time in which any activity might be carried out.57 In Capital, Marx reflects
on the connection between capitalist class stratification and the distribution of time, and
points to a shortening of the working day as the fundamental premise for an expansion of
human freedom.58 Socialism, it is worth remembering, was for Marx and most of the
other 19th century social egalitarians a way of putting the gains of industrialism to best
use, not a method for the high-speed industrialization of underdeveloped countries. But
rapid industrialization was precisely what Soviet socialism became during the Stalin
years, Marx’s notion of freedom from necessary labor giving way to the Stakhanovist
glorification of work in the sphere of necessity.59 Here again, in The Ideal Communist

56
Ibid., p. 87.
57
Marx, Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts, p. 76.
58
Karl Marx, Capital v. 3, in Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Collected Works v. 37 (London: Lawrence
& Wishart 1998), pp. 806-8.
59
The dynamics of the Stalin-era cannot, of course, be separated from the personality of Josef Stalin
himself. Yet, the brutality of the period of Soviet industrialization compares in many ways with the
brutality of the Industrial Revolution in Britain, Western Europe, and North America. The fact that the
latter process was driven by the invisible hands of market forces should not obscure the fact that as a direct
result of the push for rapid industrialization, working hours increased dramatically, living and working
conditions deteriorated, and the lives of most ordinary working people were cut tragically short.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 18

City, we can feel the new mood of the Khrushchev Thaw and the attempt by Soviet
intellectuals to put the socialist project back on its rails. Their analysis of the economic
context in which the NUS will emerge specifically cites Marx’s goal of a reduction in the
working day:

The working day can be reduced through the extraordinary growth in labor
productivity, which in turn can be attributed to electrification, automation, and
efficient production procedures. As this change takes place, the proportion of
work time to free time changes radically. For the first time in the history of man,
leisure time will exceed work time. The problem becomes “how to reduce to the
minimum the time required for socially necessary work.” If we consider the
demands that are apt to be made in various kinds of labor, we can estimate that
an individual’s work time will tend to average approximately four hours per
day.60

Soviet socialism may never have achieved this goal, yet its statement as a goal remains
significant. While liberals and social egalitarians might both find virtue in the idea of
human freedom, no contemporary neoliberal would ever call for a reduction of the
working day as a goal to be achieved by the good society. In this respect, it could be said
that the distribution of time remains one of the key questions demarcating a now vacant
political space waiting to be filled by a new social egalitarian movement.

What’s Missing?

What is particularly intriguing about The Ideal Communist City as an artifact of


mid-century Soviet intellectualism is its connection to the broad social egalitarian
tradition, despite the multiple ways in which Soviet political leaders too often ignored,
deferred, or abandoned that tradition’s values. Two values central to the social
egalitarian tradition, however, are missing from the NUS design. The first is democracy.
As August Nimtz has argued, the modern movements for social egalitarianism and

60
Gutnov et al., p. 36.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 19

electoral democracy evolved in close connection with one another.61 Yet, radical liberals
such as Milton Friedman have long held socialism and democracy to be incompatible.
Without the freedom to own farms and factories, Friedman maintained, the freedom of
the ballot box would soon be lost.62 Curiously, though, an earlier generation of liberal
political thinkers feared not that socialism would curtail democracy, but that democracy
would result in socialism.63 In considering this dramatic reversal of liberal political
thought, we might reflect on the contrast between nascent bourgeois rule, struggling to
secure its foothold, and mature, robust capitalism, utterly confident in its hegemony. A
more pointedly material explanation for the turn in liberalism’s attitude toward
democracy is offered by Albert Einstein, who turns Friedman’s fear of a state controlled
media against him, reminding us that with the concentration of capital, it is capitalists
who control the means of information, and thus wield tremendous influence over the
electorate.64
Democracy, wherever it appears in political life, is premised on equality. To the
extent, then, that socialism is aimed at the pursuit of meaningful social equality,
democracy is a natural extension of its logic into the realm of politics. Just as with the
values of equality and positive freedom, we find the belief in democratic politics woven
throughout the broad social egalitarian tradition. More’s Utopians elect neighborhood
representatives who in turn elect town mayors (campaigning for office, though, is
prohibited).65 Marx and Engels made clear in both their written work and their political
activism a belief that democracy was a prerequisite of socialism.66 And while we cannot
minimize the importance of their debate over the proper form to be taken by democratic
institutions, both Lenin and the leaders of the Second International parties put forward
powerful claims for the legitimacy of democratic politics.67 Yet, whether because of the

61
August H. Nimtz, Jr., Marx and Engels: Their Contribution to the Democratic Breakthrough (Albany:
State University of New York Press 2000).
62
Friedman, p. 10.
63
Berman, p. 1; White, p. 46.
64
Albert Einstein, “Why Socialism?” in Leo Huberman and Paul M. Sweezy, Introduction to Socialism
(New York: Monthly Review Press 1968), p. 17.
65
More, pp. 54-55, 86. The Utopian electoral system bears an interesting resemblance to representative
institutions in contemporary Cuba. See Peter Roman, People’s Power: Cuba’s Experience with
Representative Government (Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield 2003).
66
Nimtz, pp. 286, 303-4.
67
V. I. Lenin, State and Revolution (New York: International Publishers 1983); Sassoon, pp. 10, 24;
Socialist International, pp. 1-2.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 20

tyrannical intentions of political elites, the material constraints of underdevelopment and


industrialization, or the external pressures imposed by hostile aggressors in the
international arena, the political institutions of the USSR failed to develop in a genuinely
democratic direction. Thus, Gutnov’s planning team is silent with respect to questions of
politics.
In considering the possible connections between urban planning and democracy,
at least two broad approaches present themselves. Planning itself might somehow be
democratized, bringing citizens and their concerns directly into the process of organizing
collective urban space. Yet, urban planning may represent one of the areas of life in a
highly developed mass society in which expertise must be allowed to correct the potential
shortsightedness of the layperson. A second approach, then, might emphasize planning
for democracy: the organization of collective urban space in such a way as to improve the
ability of citizens to engage meaningfully in political life. Thinking in this register, we
can recognize some ways in which the NUS design, while not speaking directly to the
needs of democratic politics, might nonetheless serve such needs. Pedestrian-scaled
communities might lend themselves to a higher degree of social interaction than the
highway-linked suburbs in American cities that today often lack sidewalks altogether.
Accessible neighborhood community centers could facilitate deliberative democracy in a
way utterly ruled out by privately owned shopping malls bearing “No Solicitation” signs
on their doors. Needless to say, the reduction of the working day called for by social
egalitarians and foreseen by Gutnov et al. would be a necessary prerequisite for the
practice of engaged democracy.
The second value central to the social egalitarian tradition, but missing from The
Ideal Communist City, also takes root in the basic notion of equality and extends its logic
outward. If citizens are to be equal with one another in the nation-state, not only legally
and politically, but socially as well, on what good grounds should our pursuit of equality
stop at the nation-state’s boundaries? Various forms of nationalism have sometimes
combined concepts of endogamous equality and exogenous inequality, but since the mid-
19th century, internationalism has been a vital component of the socialist, communist, and

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 21

social democratic movements. It has also, of course, been a key point of contention and
division between various sectarian elements within that broad tradition.68
The founding statement of modern internationalism remains both the boldest and
the most influential. In the Communist Manifesto, Marx and Engels asserted that their
vision of working class political practice could be distinguished from other contemporary
varieties solely by its insistence on the transcendence of the nation-state:

1. In the national struggles of the proletarians of the different countries,


[communists] point out and bring to the front the common interests of the entire
proletariat, independently of all nationality.
2. In the various stages of development which the struggle of the working class
against the bourgeoisie has to pass through, they always and everywhere
represent the interests of the movement as a whole.69

Yet, it was not the case (as too many interpretations have suggested) that the founders of
the First International simply found it implausible that the industrial proletariat might be
swayed by the siren songs of nationalism. Rather, as Marx’s comments on the failed
revolution in France make clear, the development of capitalism as a transnational form of
economy meant that any attempt at social revolution would be meaningless until it too
had transcended national boundaries:

Just as the workers thought they would be able to emancipate themselves side by
side with the bourgeoisie, so they thought they would be able to consummate a
proletarian revolution within the national walls of France, side by side with the
remaining bourgeois nations. But French relations of production are conditioned
by the foreign trade of France, by her position on the world market and the laws
thereof; how was France to break them without a European revolutionary war,
which would strike back at the despot of the world market, England?70

68
See J. C. Myers, “Politics Without Borders: Internationalist Political Thought,” New Political Science, v.
24, n. 3 (2002).
69
Marx and Engels, p. 51.
70
Karl Marx, The Class Struggles in France in Saul K. Padover (ed.), On Revolution (New York: McGraw-
Hill 1971), p. 162.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 22

Internationalism, in this sense, was less a giddy feeling of humanist universalism than a
gritty realization that if capitalism now operated globally, emancipation from it would be
possible on no smaller scale.
The belief in internationalism was carried into the mass social democratic parties
in Europe, but new debates and new conditions also significantly reshaped its meaning.
On the one hand, both the accelerating practice of colonialism and the looming threat of
national war suggested a renewed emphasis on Marx’s call for transnational political
action by and for the working class. On the other hand, as the new social democratic
parties increasingly found their way into the halls of European parliaments, some leaders
began to suggest that each national proletariat had a significant interest in its own
country’s power and well-being. Thus, as the Second International took shape, it did so
along the lines of a solidaristic alliance between organizationally distinct national parties.
The collapse of that alliance, as all but a handful of the European social democrats
followed their national governments into war, led thinkers such as Luxemburg, Lenin,
and Trotsky to argue for the creation of a new International, with binding power over its
members and a genuine capacity for transnational action. The founding of the USSR (as
Perry Anderson notes, the only state in history to make reference in its name neither to
nationality nor to territory71) made possible the realization of this new Third
International, but also tied their fortunes tightly together. For a time, party organizations,
propaganda organs, and political actions gained an unprecedented level of coherence and
coordination. But as Stalin steered the USSR toward his vision of “socialism in one
country,” the Third International was increasingly undermined and eventually eliminated
in a wartime concession to Churchill and Roosevelt. Thus, we can imagine that by the
late 1950s, Gutnov’s team of planners and architects would have carried out their work in
an atmosphere complimented by statements of internationalist sentiment, but lacking
material structures of international solidarity and action.
Here, too, we may find ourselves entering a sphere in which the urban planner qua
planner has little to say. It may be perfectly possible, for example, for contemporary
American architects and planners to carry out their work in the context of a world market
economy without allowing this fact to influence their designs apart from, perhaps, the

71
Perry Anderson, “Internationalism: A Breviary,” New Left Review, n. 14 (2002), p. 14.

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 23

availability of various building materials. We might imagine, though, at least two ways
in which the concerns of egalitarian internationalism could find their way into the work
of planners. First, to be sure, would be the question of global environmental
sustainability. While even the forces of the market economy can – with sufficient
political will – be restrained within nation-state boundaries, the forces and elements of
the Earth’s environment know no such limitations and it becomes increasingly clear that
all life we know of shares one world. Planning decisions of all types, then, must take into
account the sustainability of urban communities within the global environment. This
issue becomes even more pointed for social egalitarian planners, who cannot assume that
some will be rich enough to shield themselves from climatic change, while the rest will
be poor and powerless enough to ignore.
But Marx’s comment on the political limitations imposed by the world market
suggest a second way in which internationalism might impact upon the work of urban
planners. Just as the interconnected nature of the global environment makes it difficult –
if not impossible – for lone communities or even nation-states to ensure environmental
sustainability, the flow of capital within the world market severely limits the ability of
small or isolated political entities to pursue planning initiatives supportive of social
egalitarianism. This is not to say that local movements and administrations cannot drive
forward planning agendas rooted in egalitarian values, but that broader forms of change
will require broader and more powerful forms of political foundation. In this sense, we
might say that Gutnov et al.’s NUS design was never the basis for real urban
redevelopment precisely because the USSR remained an isolated socialist experiment
within a hostile capitalist world.
Here we touch upon the now hopelessly stale and unhelpful question that has
always riven the socialist, communist, and social democratic traditions, both internally
and from one another: can meaningful progress toward social egalitarian goals be made
only in the context of a sweeping revolutionary transformation or can such progress be
made incrementally, through small-scale efforts at reform? Tragically, what has always
been missing from this debate was a recognition of the dialectical tension between its
poles. The practice of politics is necessarily the pursuit of goals and values in the context
of unending change. Even the maintenance of a tradition means constant adjustment to

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087


J.C. Myers 24

circumstances that are forever in flux. Every revolution is made in the context of a world
that has not yet been transformed and, therefore, engages at each step in forms of
incremental transformation. Even those revolutionaries who inaugurate the most perfect
form of constitution will leave to future generations a continual struggle to defend and
renew their achievement. The image of socialism or communism as a final end-state,
then, has always been an illusion. Curiously, though, the European social democratic
parties that rejected the rhetoric and strategy of revolution also tended to fall into the trap
of perceiving the moderately reformed, controlled market society as an end-state. As a
result, they often failed to develop effective strategies with which to defend and deepen
their victories. In the 1980s and 1990s, when the forces of neoliberal capitalism pushed
back against social democracy, it became clear that “reform” could have more than one
political valence.72
The intellectuals whose ideas helped to drive the neoliberal resurgence felt no
need to invent elaborate plans for the total transformation of society in order to argue for
the values of capitalism. Despite the fact that, in their view, those values were unjustly
muted, blunted, and restrained, they existed and could be seen in every privately owned
farm, factory, and newspaper stand. In much the same way, we might recognize the
presence of socialist values in every public school, public park, and public sidewalk – the
very mundane, material elements given so much attention by Gutnov’s planning team. It
remains undeniably true that nothing resembling their NUS design is likely to emerge
from within a society that has not already undergone a dramatic political transformation
driven by a social egalitarian movement. Yet, it is equally true that no such movement is
likely to emerge outside of a political context in which ordinary citizens come to
recognize and to value the ways in which their lives are made better by the provision of
positive freedoms in the form of public goods. Gutnov’s planners, in other words, may
have set out to create a utopian vision of the future, but in the context of the future that
actually arrived, the importance of their work now lies in its ability to remind us of the
political values contained within the elements of everyday life.

72
See David Harvey, A Brief History of Neoliberalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press 2005).

Copyright © 2008 by J.C. Myers and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087

You might also like