Rowan Williams, On Being Creatures, 4th Esa Lecture 1989

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 12

The Fourth

ERIC SYMES ABBOTT


Memorial Lecture

delivered by

Professor Rowan Williams


Lady Margaret Professor of Divinity
and Canon of Christ Church, Oxford

at Westminster Abbey
on Monday the fifteenth of May, 1989
and subsequently at Lincoln Minster and Keble College, Oxford
The Eric Symes Abbott Memorial Lecture Trust was endowed by friends of Eric Abbott to provide
for an annual lecture or course of lectures on spirituality. The venue for the lecture will vary
between London, Oxford and Lincoln.

The Trustees are: the Dean of King's College London (Chairman); the Dean of Westminster; the
Warden of Lincoln Theological College; the Chaplain of Keble College, Oxford; the Very
Reverend Dr Tom Baker; the Reverend John Robson and the Reverend Canon Eric James.

©1989 Rowan Williams


On Being Creatures

I.

Christian reflection on creation has been a bit of a Cinderella in twentieth-century theology


– at least until the last few years, when a variety of pressures has brought it very much to the fore.
New developments in cosmology have aroused some – rather confused – theological interest, on the
one hand; and the daily increasing gravity of our environmental crisis has sharpened our concern to
relate human interests and needs to the balance of the entire system of the world, on the other – so
that we have begun to ask what it might mean to see the unity of our humanness with a material
world both ordered and limited. Both these developments have very naturally prompted the raising
of questions connected with the doctrine of creation. Less directly, pressure has come from certain
feminist quarters: has not a redemption-oriented Christian theology functioned as an expression of
the male urge to shake off the threatening and humiliating ties that bind spirit to body, to the earth,
the cycle of reproduction, woman imaged as the sign of fallenness, of unspiritual nature? Hence the
emergence of an interest in ‘creation-centred spirituality’, which “begins … with the theme of
original blessing rather than original sin”. 1 Its characteristic language is one of trust in the material
order of the world, the rejection of nature-spirit dualism and indeed of the creator-creature divide, in
a certain sense: the key term is ‘panentheism’, designating the way in which all beings have their
life in God, in a simple, ‘synchronous’, interwoven pattern, a timeless moment which breaks in on
our awareness as and when we see the transparency of beings to (God’s) Being. This perception of
the world becomes the foundation for a spirituality that is prophetically critical of our exploitative
distance from our world, and generative of a universal compassion working towards justice. It is
“the spiritual tradition that is the most Jewish, the most biblical, the most prophetic and the most
like the kind Jesus of Nazareth preached and lived”, 2 and it has, according to Matthew Fox, been
largely forgotten in Western Christendom in recent centuries.

However, despite this rather naïve appeal to the obvious superiority of a ‘biblical’
spirituality, it is clear that Fox is putting some very grave questions to the whole of the classical
Christian account of creation, biblical and post-biblical. It is not a simple matter of reclaiming one
bit of Christian tradition to set against another. The problems are forcefully set out in Rosemary
Ruether’s Sexism and God-Talk: Towards a Feminist Theology, 3 which contains an intriguing
discussion of the possible agenda underlying the Hebrew myth of creation in its distinctness from
Babylonian and Canaanite thought-forms. For the latter, ‘creation’ is a movement of self-regulation
within a single continuum, “the matrix of chaos-cosmos”; for the Hebrews, the creator is more like
an artisan working on material outside his own nature, by what appears as “a combination of male
seminal and cultural power (word-act) that shapes it ‘from above’”. 4 There is a correlation between
cosmic order and moral righteousness: submission to the ‘cultural’ power of God – the power of
God to name, define, locate things – will guarantee the world’s harmony. This is already a step
towards the more drastic hierarchicalism and alienation of the Greek model of the world’s making,
where human consciousness (implicitly male) is recognised as akin to the primary agency of God as
mind, and foreign to the realm of matter. For Ruether, a theology of the creative matrix must be
constructed; not in terms of the static immanence of Babylonian myth, but by understanding that
history is not the liberation of spirit from nature. “Feminist theology needs to affirm the God of
Exodus, of liberation and new being, but as rooted in the foundations of being rather than as its
antithesis.” 5 Instead of a view that privileges historical action as heroic rupture, breaking away
from the natural and timeless, a kind of imitation of the primordial rupture between nothing and
something which is the authoritative word of creation, we must develop a model of the divine as
what encompasses and pervades the system of the universe, the ultimate resourcefulness that
enables the system (including our historical action) constantly to recover balance and harmony. 6
This also has the effect 7 of challenging traditional accounts of eschatology: if there is no single,
‘linear’ story of God’s liberative action (a story bound to give unique power and definitional force
to the human group that appropriates it), there is no movement to a last end, a millennium – only a
confidence that, within the divine matrix, nothing is ultimately lost.

Many of these themes are echoed in the more recent work of Sallie McFague, Models of
God: Theology for an Ecological Nuclear Age. 8 Here again we find the suggestion that the
classical view of creation sees it as an exercise of ‘cultural’ power, the giving of form to the
(external) formless. This aesthetic view, God as artist, implies a certain detachment in God’s
judgment of the world: “An artist, upon completing a work, makes a judgment whether it is good or
bad; the judgment is an aesthetic one based on critical standards”. 9 These standards are, McFague
suggests, ‘neutral’, not intrinsic to the person of the artist, in sharp contrast to the standards by
which a parent judges a child; and it is this latter parental image of ‘production’ which we ought to
be developing as a theological tool, since it allows a far more central importance to the idea of
continuity between creator and creation, the bonds of kinship. Despite the problems of putting them
together in a logical unity, the images of God as bringing creation to birth and of the world as God’s
body 10 have a real affinity. God’s ‘interests’, if we can speak in such terms, are bound up with the
world’s; so that there can be no temptation to model one’s behaviour on a God utterly without any
investment in the life of creation, as if the best form of life were one which repudiated involvement
in or dependency upon the material world. 11 God as maker of what is decisively not God is a
dangerous notion, insofar as it generates and legitimates monarchical control over the world,
dualistic contempt for the world and the exaltation of abstract ‘spirit’ – all the pathologies which,
for McFague, afflict the culture of the present age, with its crises of international and environmental
security.

There are several points of strain, if not contradiction, in all this. It is not at all clear how far
for McFague ‘Hebrew’ thought (whatever exactly this is) escapes the charge of monarchical
distortion simply by having a robust doctrine of covenant; 12 Ruether’s critique cuts a good deal
deeper than McFague allows on the question of pervasive patriarchialism in Jewish scripture. And
the metaphor of the world as God’s body – rather more carefully and comprehensively handled by
Grace Jantzen – seems, paradoxically, to require a disturbingly stark dualism: we are not our bodes,
after all, especially when those bodes are “sick, maimed, ageing, enslaved, or dying”; 13 and if we
are in the long run somehow not identical with our bodies, it is theologically safe to think of the
world as God’s body. We are not committed to seeing God’s identity as dependent upon the
material world; 14 God is in some sense free of any particular body or even the sum total of bodes,
as we cannot wholly be. God could in principle form another ‘body’ to express the divine life, and
we do not have that sort of freedom. Yet there is an analogy in the kind of relation we have to our
bodies: “God relates sympathetically to the world, just as we relate sympathetically to our
bodies”. 15 This is baffling: ‘sympathy’ is surely the last thing I can feel for my body since it is my
body that feels. If sympathy is the capacity to recognise with moral concern the kinship between
another’s situation and my own, I could only ‘sympathise’ with my body if ‘I’ were a kind of
parallel being with a different history of sensations. The suspicion grows that the ‘God’s body’
image can only work by trading on precisely the residual dualism that is elsewhere under attack,
and by evading some plain and uncomfortable philosophical questions. The results, I think, are far
more morally and spiritually worrying than anything the artistic analogy can produce; and
McFague’s treatment of this latter is again rather puzzling. Does any artist judge her works by
these supposedly ‘neutral’ criteria? Isn’t it rather that an artist ‘judges’ (the wrong word, anyway)
the thing made by its own integrity and coherence, an integrity rooted in the artist’s own sense of
being-in-the-world? And it is perfectly possible to understand one’s artistic failure as a moral and
personal matter. Anyone disposed to think Sallie McFague right about artists might do worse than
read Geoffrey’s Hill’s essay on Poetry as ‘Menace’ and ‘Atonement’. 16
There is some fundamental muddle here about the kind of difference we can and should
speak of in relation to God and God’s world. Both McFague and Ruether, the latter with more
sharpness of focus, see the crises of the age as rooted, to a very significant extent, in the twin
problems of dualism and hierarch; and they are entirely right to point to elements in the rhetoric and
the narrative of much of traditional Christianity which display in strikingly clear form the disastrous
possibilities of a certain kind of God-world differentiation, especially when coupled with a parallel
spirit-nature disjunction. But neither writer spends long in trying to understand what exactly the
doctrine of creation out of nothing actually means in the hands of those who have most carefully
dealt with it, and what its implications might be for understanding or imagining ourselves as
creatures. The weight of modern objection to what is thought to be the classical doctrine is, at the
very least, a witness to the truth that no amount of theological refinement can, of itself, prevent the
slide into destructive and sterile patterns of thought that license diseased or oppressive patterns of
action and relation. But this means that the answer to the problem is not solely the generation of a
new idiom (especially one which is confessedly full of conceptual strains), but should involve a
hard look at what the original doctrine’s logic is meant to state and safeguard – whether or not we
finally decide to go on giving it the privilege it has had in the past. That is the task this lecture
attempts to begin.

II.

The belief that God created the world out of nothing was unquestionably a distinctive Jewish
and Christian view in the late antique world. Other accounts of creation may ascribe to God the
initiative in setting things in motion or imposing order on passive matter; but the notion of an
absolute origin is not to be found with anything like comparable clarity outside the Judaeo-Christian
environment. There is a growing trend, of course, towards the view finally expressed in the great
Plotinus’ work, the source of Neoplatonism, that the entire complex world of things that can be
known and talked about depends on or flows out of a simple, wholly unified primary reality, the
One; but it would be odd to describe this as an action in the way ‘creating’ seems to be an action.
Although it would take too long to discuss here the probable origins of the idea of creation from
nothing, it is significant that such language seems to have emerged into full prominence around the
time of Israel’s return from Babylonian exile (above all in the ‘Second Isaiah’, Is. 40-55). This
deliverance, decisive and unexpected, is like a second Exodus; and the Exodus in turn comes to be
seen as a sort of recapitulation of creation. Out of a situation where there is no identity, where there
are no names, only the anonymity of slavery or the powerlessness of the ghetto, God makes a
human community, calls it by name (a recurrent motif in Is. 40-55), gives it or restores to it a
territory. Nothing makes God do this except God’s own free promise; from human chaos God
makes human community. But this act is not a process by which shape is imposed on chaos: it is a
summons, a call which establishes the very possibility of an answer. It is a short step to the
conclusion that God’s relation to the whole world is like this; not a struggle with pre-existing
disorder that is then moulded into shape, but a pure summons. “My hand laid the foundation of the
earth, and my right hand spread out the heavens; when I call to them, they stand forth together” (Is.
48.13). In the Exodus, God can be said to fight against the ‘chaos’ of Pharaoh’s tyranny and to
bring Israel out of the sea as the Babylonian gods brought the world out of watery chaos; but no
literal battle is fought, and what exists after was simply not there before. More and more, creation
is seen as performed by the free utterance of God alone; the imagery of moulding something out of
something else recedes.

What is left is not even the ‘cultural’ activity described by Ruether: God does not impose a
definition but creates an identity. Prior to God’s word, there is nothing to impose on. This has
some interesting implications. It mans that creation is no sort of process; it is not a change.
Aquinas expressed with complete clarity what Isaiah’s words ultimately entail when he said that
‘creation’ simply points you to existing reality in relation to a creator. 17 It does not indicate some
enormous event which would explain everything that came later; as Aquinas realised, the doctrine is
equally compatible with thinking the universe had an identifiable beginning and thinking it exists
eternally. It simply tells you that the entire situation of the universe, at any given moment, exists as
a real situation because of God’s reality being, as it were, turned away from God to generate what is
not God. And this is not an explanation (because the existence of the world is not a puzzling fact,
as opposed to other, straightforward facts; it is all the facts there are), but a statement that
everything depends on the action of God. 18

The point for our purposes is that it makes perfect sense, in such a perspective, to say that
creation is not an exercise of divine power, odd though that certainly sounds. Power is exercised by
x over y; but creation is not power, because it is not exercised on anything. We might, of course,
want to say that creation presupposes a divine potentiality, or resourcefulness, or abundance of
active life; and ‘power’ can sometimes be used in those senses. But what creation emphatically
isn’t is any kind of imposition or manipulation: it is not God imposing on us divinely-willed roles
rather than the ones we ‘naturally’ might have, or defining us out of our own systems into God’s.
Creation affirms that to be here at all, to be a part of this natural order and to be the sort of thing
capable of being named – or of having a role – is ‘of God’; it is because God wants it so. And this
implies that the Promethean myth of humanity struggling against God for its welfare and interests
makes no sense: to be a creature cannot be to be a victim of an alien force (colonised by an alien
‘culture’). Conversely, the overcoming of ‘nature’ as a proper goal for spirituality is highly
problematic: we need a very careful theory of how nature is distorted or obscured before this
language is remotely possible; an account, in effect, of how we mistake the unnatural for the
natural.

Creation in the classical sense does not therefore involve some uncritical idea of God’s
‘monarchy’. The absolute freedom ascribed to God in creation means that God cannot make a
reality that then needs to be actively governed, subdued, bent to the divine purpose away from its
natural course. If God creates freely, God does not need the power of a sovereign; what is, is from
God. God’s sovereign purpose is what the world is becoming. This may throw some light on a
further cluster of controversial issues to do with creation’s absolute dependence on God – in the
terms of classical theology, the fact that there is no ‘real relation’ between the world and God. The
objection is quite often made that a relationship of unilateral dependence is incompatible with
anything we could mean by love. Relations that we call ‘loving’ are mutually constructive; they are
not all gift on one side and all receiving on the other. Such a pattern would mean that one party
could never ‘grow up’ to the status of a giver, but would always be looking to have her or his needs
met by the other – an infantile perspective; while the person who is defined as a ‘giver’ only is one
we look on with some suspicion, asking what is being blocked or denied by the refusal or inability
to receive. In short, if our relation to the creator is one of unconditional dependence, it looks as
though both God and (rational) creatures are locked into a pattern which in the human context we
should regard as diseased.

Dependence in human affairs is one of the most complex of subjects. We are afraid of it –
both because of the diseased relationships that go with unbalanced dependence and, more deeply,
because of the strong attraction of the human psyche towards the ‘illusion of omnipotence’, or at
least the illusion of being an individual, self-regulating system. We have, in other words, both good
and bad reasons for fearing dependence, and it is not always easy to distinguish between them.
Ernest Becker’s brilliant work, The Denial of Death, 19 speaks of our sense of ourselves as
individuals as a ‘vital lie’; to emerge as agents at all, so as to negotiate our position in a highly
dangerous environment, we must believe in the possibility of ‘equanimity’ – balance and control.
Yet to achieve the sense of this possibility, we require support from outside ourselves, from
resources of symbolic power. Our problem is thus the overcoming of dependence by dependence:
“We enter symbiotic relationships in order to get the security we need, in order to get relief from
our anxieties …; but these relationships also bind us, they enslave us even further because they
support the lie we have fashioned”. 20 To shore up our sense of independence, we intensify our
dependence on those external factors which assure us of worth or meaning, while denying more and
more stridently that we are involved in dependence at all. The necessary illusion of individuality
thus condemns us to tragic compulsion, a diet of spiritual salt water. Any kind of health in this
situation requires a twofold honesty: the recognition of the inevitability of dependence (since we are
not self-regulating systems) and the recognition of the fundamental need to imagine oneself,
nonetheless, as a true agent, not confined by dependence (in other words, a suspicion of whatever
looks like a path of limitless dependence). We are in the almost intolerable position of needing to
be educated to fear what we cannot but need.

However: if our fundamental need is for what enables us to stand over against our
environment as agents, it should be clear that to recognise honestly the character of that need is to
take a first step away from the compulsive search for ‘piecemeal’ securities, the shoring-up of
identity by exploiting specific facets of the very environment which threatens to swallow the self; it
might be possible, in the light of such a recognition, to distinguish the single underlying need for
the sense of being an agent from any and every object-specific need, so as to learn some freedom
from the pressure of object-specific needs. If I know that I cannot secure my sense of myself as
agent by an ever-expanding exploitation of limited object needs, I shall at least avoid the appalling
trap depicted by Becker – the evacuation of my selfhood by the pursuit of the self’s security.

‘Limitless dependence’, in the sense of accumulating dependent relationships to things,


persons, institutions, is something quite other than the fundamental dependence we cannot avoid,
dependence on whatever it is that enables our sense of being an agent, a giver. And perhaps it is
how we conceive that primary dependence that determines how vulnerable or how destructive our
‘illusion’ of agency is – how much of an ‘illusion’ in the ordinary sense of the word rather than the
subtler Freudian sense of a belief constructed to meet or cope with the demands of what lies beyond
the psyche. Sebastian Moore, in The Inner Loneliness, identifies our need to imagine ourselves as
agents or givers as a need to know we exist for another. This is a crucial insight: it implies that to
imagine ourselves as agents by imagining ourselves as self-regulating individuals is to misconceive
our fundamental need, which is for identity in relation, conversation, mutual recognition. We can
imagine ourselves as self-regulating entities, but can only make sense of – let alone value or love –
what is thus imagined by adopting the standpoint of another: by presupposing relation. We cannot,
as it were, get behind this and conceive a human identity that is primitively and only an object to
itself. To think ourselves as agents or subjects is to think of ourselves as addressed or
contemplated: “my self-awareness is something I am showing you, and your self-awareness is
something you are showing me”. 21 There is no self-awareness outside the commerce of agents and
speakers. When I think I am imagining myself ‘for myself’, I am actually taking up the position of
someone who looks at or speaks to me; and I couldn’t do this if I did not know what it is to be
looked at or spoken to.

Knowing this is knowing the ‘illusion’ of being a personal centre is one that is not, after all,
created by the solitary ego struggling for a modus Vivendi (as Becker might seem to suggest), but is
the tissue of the language-shaped world into which we are born; something without which we could
not speak to – and so could not see – each other as other. Yet the awareness of my location within
this world carries with it a realisation of the impossibility, for any inhabitant of the world, of being
a pure source of meaning for other inhabitants of the world: all receive before they give, and give
only as a response to their receiving. If my identity is given by the ‘conversation’ I enter at birth,
that conversation is in turn a generated as well as a generating context. Nothing in the world is
absolutely and unilaterally gift; and this can mean a certain persisting instability or insecurity in the
tissue of our world. My meaning is given by the context I depend on; but so are other things –
notably the oppressive cultural definitions that Ruether points to. The commerce in which we
establish our identities is risky because we are also becoming the raw material of other identities: as
in Hegel’s famous metaphor of the lord and the serf, there is the possibility of becoming
instrumental to the self-formation of another person or group in a way which finally does not allow
me to be seen as an agent and a giver. Even if I recognise the basic character of my need, that will
not save me from falling victim to the rapacity of another who still conceives the human task as the
exploitation of an environment to confirm the illusion of individuality. What offers to give me
meaning and security also threatens to lay unacceptable claim upon me. So, when I have made the
breakthrough into acknowledging the impossibility of creating an independent self out of my own
will, when I have grasped that my being as agent depends on my receiving first, my being there,
spoken to, acted on, I can still not be assured of my liberty to act or give because of the risk that I
will be conscripted into the project of another. The fundamental need remains, to a greater or lesser
degree, open, unmet. If I know that no human dependence can serve here, only two options remain:
the constantly fearful and cautious negotiation of my identity, building up what is constructive in
my relation to my environment, and vigilantly looking out for the danger represented by the
‘cultural’ power of others; or an act of trust in my right or capacity to act and give.

The doctrine of creation in its classical form is the religious ground for such an act of trust.
To say, ‘I exist (along with the whole of my environment) at God’s will, I am unconditionally
dependent upon God’ means – at least – the following things. My existence in the world, including
my need to imagine this as personal, active and giving, is ‘of God’; my search for an identity is
something rooted in God’s freedom, which grounds the sheer thereness of the shared world I stand
in. And to see that is already to have that need answered: my needful searching is part of what God
gratuitously brings to be. The secret of understanding our createdness is that it makes both sense
and nonsense of the ‘search for identity’: it justifies our need (ie it displays it as something other
than a neutral fact) and it answers it. Before we are looked at, spoken to, acted on, we are, because
of the look, the word, the act of God. God alone (as supremely free of the world) can bring a hearer
into being by speaking, but uttering (making external, ‘outering’) what the life of God is, in a
creative summons. We shall be returning to think further about the implications of this a little later.

We are here, then, we are real, because of God’s ‘word’; our reality is not and cannot be
either earned by us or eroded by others. And to say that we are unilaterally dependent on God is to
recognise that God alone is beyond the precarious exchanges of creatures who need affirmation.
With God alone, I am dealing with what does not need to construct or negotiate an identity, what is
free to be itself without the process of struggle. Properly understood, this is the most liberating
affirmation we could ever hear. God does not and cannot lay claim upon me so as to ‘become’
God; what I am cannot be made functional for God’s being; I can never be defined by the job of
meeting God’s needs. This is why I suggested earlier that our understanding of what was involved
in depending on God might be helped by the recognition that creation is not an exercise of power by
x over y. We do what we ought to do as creatures not when we attempt to resign from nature by
treating ‘God’ as a successful rival for our attention or devotion ever against the things and persons
of the world, but by our being-in-the-world. This most certainly does not mean (as some of the
more philistine advocates of ‘secular’ theologies used to suggest) that reference to God becomes
superfluous. On the contrary; on this analysis, we learn being-in-the-world precisely by learning
that there is in the world no absolute and independent ‘giver’, no final source of naming, of identity,
not I nor any other individual, nor any corporate identity. We become able to see all attempts in the
world at providing definitions for other persons and groups as attempts to escape the world; only
one ‘power’ is entirely gift, entirely directed away from its needs (for it has none), and all other
powers need to be unmasked or demythologised. The creator’s power-as-resource cannot be
invoked to legitimise earthly power. Here there is only what I have called the ‘negotiation’ of
needs, the patterns of giving and receiving, speaking and hearing – stripped of violence-inducing
anxiety when they rest on the knowledge that the entire process is rooted in God’s free utterance.

Moore’s Inner Loneliness provides some further clues as to what might be involved in
conceiving a God beyond need. I need a sense of active identity, which depends on being there for
another; and clearly the optional form of being there for another is to be the object of another’s
love, the cause of joy in them: “at root, self-love and self-gift are one … self-love flowers in self-
giving, flowers as self-giving” 22 – or, as I’d prefer to say, self-love presupposes self-giving. I can’t
love myself without being a loved object, which means being, in some measure, given into
another’s hands, another’s life. To say that God is without need is to say that God’s identity does
not wait upon being an object for what is not God. God, it seems, ‘needs’ only God. Yet there is a
world, there is what is not God, something for which God is. As creatures, existing because of the
utterance of God, we know that God desires to be God for what is not God – desires the pleasure or
flourishing of what is not God. This desire is groundless, in the sense that nothing other than God
causes it, and that it cannot be a device to assist God in being God, but it is not arbitrary, because
there is no extraneous or random element within God’s being as God. What God utters (as
suggested earlier) is God: the summons to the world to be, and to find its fruition in being in the
presence of God, sets ‘outside’ God the kind of life that is God’s. So if God’s act of creation
gratuitously establishes God as the one who is supremely there for the world, it seems we must say
that God is already one whose being is a ‘being for’, whose joy is eternally in the joy of another;
and since God, as we have said, does not ‘wait upon’ becoming an object to another, we are led to
think of God’s own self as eternal identity in otherness, a self-affirming in giving away. “Love in
God does not result but originates … because God is God, the absolutely original, the absolutely
originating, and eternal process of self-affirming in self-love.” 23

There is a kind of closing of the circle here: what begins in the recognition of God’s liberty
in the saving interruption of history of the world, and leads to the vision of God as that upon which
all things depend, ends in affirming the changeless consistency of God as love – saving interruption
anchored (to borrow Ruether’s words) in “the foundations of being”; the absolute difference
between God and the world presupposed by the doctrine of creation from nothing becomes also a
way of asserting the continuity between the being of God and the act of creation as the utterance
and ‘overflow’ of divine life. Belief in creation from nothing is one reflective path towards
understanding God as trinity; and belief in God as trinity, intrinsic self-love and self-gift,
establishes that creation, while not ‘needed’ by God, is wholly in accord with the divine being as
being-for-another. To put it provocatively: God creates ‘in God’s interest’ (there could be no other
motive for divine action); but that ‘interest’ is not the building-up of the divine life, which simply is
what it is, but its giving away. For God to act for God’s sake is for God to act for our sake. 24

Jacques Pohier’s remarkable and haunting book, God in Fragments, 25 brilliantly sets this
out under the rubric, ‘God does not want to be Everything’. 26 Pohier recalls Aquinas’ startling
denial that we ought to love things or persons as a means of loving God or as leading us to God: we
should love them for their ‘autonomy and consistency’, for what the free love of God has made
them. “God is the reason for loving, he is not the sole object of love”: 27 it is God who makes it
possible to love things and persons for what they are (because to believe in a free creator is to
believe that nothing in the world can enslave us by being ‘God’ for us). But what is more, to treat
God as ‘Everything’, as the immediate totality of meaning for each and every subject in the world,
is to misunderstand the nature of our unconditional dependence on God. God establishes the worth,
the legitimacy, the right to be there, of what is in the world, and in that sense gives meaning; but
precisely what God does not do is to intrude into the integrity of this or that aspect of being in the
world as a justification or explanation for specific events. If the explanation of every event, every
determination of being, every phenomenon or decision were simply and directly God, then the life
of creation would not be genuinely other than God. God grounds the reality and, in the theological
sense, the goodness of the world’s life, but does not answer specific ‘Why?’ questions. To think
otherwise, Pohier suggests, 28 is for us actually to reduce God to ourselves, to define God as the
answer, not to our ‘need’ for reality or identity, but our needs for control and for a world we can
chart in relation to the centrality of ourselves - “and in consequence prevent him from being
himself, being God, being other, being for us the life that he wants to be”. 29 If we need God simply
in order to understand and accept our very reality, then our relation to God in particular
circumstances will not be one of need in the ordinary sense, a desperate effort to make God supply
this or that desired gratification, physical, intellectual or spiritual. We should instead be capable of
receiving God as pure gift, unexpected good news - as the absolutely uncontainable, the irreducibly
different; as God.

III.

It is, then, a doctrine of creation, properly understood, that grounds both our contemplation
and our action. Coheir’s insight means that we properly relate to God in gratitude and in silence:
before God, we can only celebrate the fact that we are, and are free to be human with God for God
and because of God; and wait without clear prediction or absolute conceptual security for the
further perception of and delight in God’s being God. Before the literally inconceivable fact of the
divine difference and the divine liberty, we have no words except thanksgiving that, because God’s
life is what it is, we are. “We give thanks to Thee for Thy great glory.” The contemplation of God,
which is among other things the struggle to become the kind of person who can without fear be
open to the divine activity, would not be possible if God were seen as an agent exercising power
over others, bending them to the divine will. Contemplative prayer classically finds its focus in the
awareness of God at the centre of the praying person’s being - God as that by which I am myself -
and, simultaneously, God at the centre of the whole world’s being: a solidarity in creatureliness. It
is the great specific against the myth of self-creation and isolated self-regulation. St John of the
Cross speaks 30 of the vision of God in the state of union as a vision of the creator, and thus of the
beauty which each creature has of itself from God, as well as “the wise, ordered, gracious and
loving mutual correspondence” among creatures. To see God is to find place in this
“correspondence”. Contemplation, then, cannot properly be a prostration before a power outside
us; it is a being present to ourselves in our world with acceptance and trust. Hence - though this
would need longer to elaborate - the importance of attention to the praying body; the contemplative
significance of taking time to sense ourselves in prayer, to perceive patiently what and where we
materially are.

But to open myself to the divine action is to seek to discover that act which is wholly and
purely the movement of a generosity that finds joy in being for the other. There is no ‘private’ or
individual goal possible: our prayer is supposed to deliver us from what gets in the way of our
immersion in and continuity with the act of God, what blocks our own happiness in each other.
That human life which we believe to have been uniquely open to the divine act, the life of Jesus, is
a life given to the creation of a people for God, a community without limit; and it is by this life that
we begin to orient ourselves at all towards the creator in the first place. Our openness to God is our
readiness for the action of a generosity creative of community to be ‘enacted’ in us - our readiness,
therefore, to challenge and resist the making or remaking of exclusions and inequalities in creation.
The discovery of solidarity in creatureliness has obvious consequences, which hardly need spelling
out, for our sense of responsibility in the material world; it puts at once into question the model of
unilateral mastery over the world. And if we can grasp this, we can also understand, perhaps, how
bizarre a distortion it has been to think that the human spirit ‘imitates’ God by exploitative mastery.
The creative life, death and resurrection of Jesus manifests a creator who works in, not against, our
limits, our mortality: the creator who, as the one who calls being forth from nothing, gives without
dominating.

We shall also know something about resistance to contemporary lies concerning the
possibilities of corporate security in our world. Both the rhetoric and the practice of our defence
policies often seem to offend against the acknowledgement of creatureliness - in two respects, at
least. First, there is the offence against any notion of ‘creaturely solidarity’ implied by the threat
not only to obliterate large numbers of the human race (all weaponry is in that sense a threat to our
common sense of creatureliness) but to unleash what is acknowledged to be an uncontrollable and
incalculable process of devastation in our material environment, an uncontainable injury to the
ecology of the planet. Second, there is the extent to which our deterrent policies have become
bound to a particular kind of technological confidence: somewhere in the not-too-distant future, it
might be possible to construct a defensive or aggressive military system which will provide a final
security against attack, a final defence against the pressure of the ‘other’. If I may repeat some
words written in 1987 about the problems posed by the Strategic Defence Initiative, the Christian is
bound to ask, “How far is the search for impregnability a withdrawal from the risks of conflict and
change? A longing to block out the possibility of political repentance, drastic social criticism and
reconstruction?” 31

These references to our ecological and political infantilism should be a reminder that a
‘creation-oriented’ theology and spirituality cannot - pace Matthew Fox - afford to replace the
concept of original sin with ‘original blessing’, if that means ignoring our deeply rooted aversion to
our own creatureliness. At every turn we encounter this protest: in the kind of radically subjectivist
theology that makes the abstract ego the legislator of spiritual identity and reduces the creator to a
tool in this system; in the kind of religious and political fundamentalism that pins the human value
of a person or a community to the injunctions of an extraneous defining and dominating power; in
the world of personal relations, when people invest themselves totally in another person, not in
covenanted and reciprocal loyalty, but in a desperate need for the other to provide a completeness of
truth and meaning for them; and, as we have seen, in the obsessive games of national security and
technological short cuts to gratification. Being a creature is in danger of becoming a lost art. My
argument in this lecture has been that we are badly in need, not so much of a reworking of the
doctrine of creation designed to eliminate what some have seen as the morally or spiritually
damaging effects of believing God to be absolutely prior to and other than the world, as of a
retrieval of the radical implications of such a belief for an understanding of our liberty before God.
The critique provided by feminist theologies such as these of Ruether and McFague, and the
attempt to conceive a non-dualistic or ‘panentheist’ spirituality in the works of writers like Fox,
have a considerable importance in alerting us to the distortions to which the classical doctrine has
fallen victim - God as monarch, God as imposing alien meanings, God as supremely successful
manipulator of a cosmic ‘environment’. But the simple, undialectical affirmation of God’s identity
with the cosmic continuum (an uncritical maternal image to replace an uncritical patriarchal
image?) will not serve - as I think Ruether and McFague are themselves aware. Authentic
difference, a being-with, not simply a being-in, difference that is grounded in the eternal being-with
of God as trinity, is something which sets us free to be human - distinctively human, yet human in
co-operation with others and with an entire world of differences. To know that our humanness is
not functional to any purpose imposed from beyond is to know also the folly and blasphemy of
treating portions of the human race as functional for the lives of other human beings (which is why
this perspective ultimately reinforces a serious feminist critique, as well as having some
implications about economics and race); and to know the equal folly and blasphemy of interpreting
all creation in terms of its usefulness to transient human needs. Being creatures is learning
humility, not as submission to an alien will, but as the acceptance of limit and death; for that
acceptance, with all that it means in terms of our moral imagination and action, we are equipped by
learning through the grace of Christ and the concrete fellowship of the Spirit, that God is “the desire
by which all live”, 32 the creator. In Anita Mason’s superb novel, The Illusionist, 33 Peter’s vision in
Acts 10 is movingly reworked as a perception of the ‘unimaginable order’ and union in all things:
the passage ends with words which may stand as a summary for much of this lecture. “‘I am the
Giver’, said the voice. ‘Trust me.’” 34

*********

Notes

1
Matthew Fox on ‘Creation-Centred Spirituality’ in Gordon Wakefield’s Dictionary of Christian Spirituality (London
1983), p. 99.
2
Matthew Fox, Breakthough. Meister Eckhart’s Creation Spirituality in New Translation (New York 1980), p. 4.
3
Boston 1983.
4
p. 77.
5
p. 71.
6
pp. 85-92, 214-234.
7
Ch. 10, especially p. 250-8.
8
Philadelphia & London 1987.
9
p. 111.
10
pp. 69-78.
11
p. 112; cf. pp. 72-4.
12
p. 110.
13
n. 14 on p. 201, referring to John Cobb’s essay ‘Feminism & Process Thought’ in Sheila Greave Daveney (ed),
Feminism & Process Thought, (New York 1981).
14
pp. 71-2.
15
p. 73.
16
The Lords of Limit: Essays on Literature and Ideas (London 1984).
17
De Potentia III.3.
18
All this is very helpfully discussed in Gareth Moore’s recent book on Believing in God (Edinburgh 1988), especially
pp. 267-82.
19
New York & London 1973.
20
p. 56.
21
Moore, The Inner Loneliness (London 1982), p. 9.
22
Ibid. p. 24.
23
Ibid., p. 108
24
Cf ibid., p. 25.
25
London 1985.
26
pp. 266ff.
27
p. 268.
28
pp. 303-4.
29
p. 304.
30
Spiritual Canticle B xxxix. 11.
31
Star Wars: Safeguard or Threat? A Christian Perspective, CANA Occasional Papers no 1 (Evesham 1987), p. 6.
32
Moore, op cit, p. 117.
33
London 1983.
34
p. 137.

You might also like