100% found this document useful (1 vote)
77 views14 pages

Understanding Risk-Aversion Through Utility Theory: Ashwin Rao

The document discusses risk aversion and how it can be modeled using utility theory. It introduces the concepts of risk premium, absolute and relative risk aversion, and specifies them using a utility function. It shows how risk premium grows with outcome variance and risk aversion. It also presents the commonly used constant absolute risk aversion and constant relative risk aversion utility functions.

Uploaded by

JitenRana
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
100% found this document useful (1 vote)
77 views14 pages

Understanding Risk-Aversion Through Utility Theory: Ashwin Rao

The document discusses risk aversion and how it can be modeled using utility theory. It introduces the concepts of risk premium, absolute and relative risk aversion, and specifies them using a utility function. It shows how risk premium grows with outcome variance and risk aversion. It also presents the commonly used constant absolute risk aversion and constant relative risk aversion utility functions.

Uploaded by

JitenRana
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 14

Understanding Risk-Aversion through Utility Theory

Ashwin Rao

ICME, Stanford University

February 3, 2020

Ashwin Rao (Stanford) Utility Theory February 3, 2020 1 / 14


Intuition on Risk-Aversion and Risk-Premium

Let’s play a game where your payoff is based on outcome of a fair coin
You get $100 for HEAD and $0 for TAIL
How much would you pay to play this game?
You immediately say: “Of course, $50”
Then you think a bit, and say: “A little less than $50”
Less because you want to “be compensated for taking the risk”
The word Risk refers to the degree of variation of the outcome
We call this risk-compensation as Risk-Premium
Our personality-based degree of risk fear is known as Risk-Aversion
So, we end up paying $50 minus Risk-Premium to play the game
Risk-Premium grows with Outcome-Variance & Risk-Aversion

Ashwin Rao (Stanford) Utility Theory February 3, 2020 2 / 14


Specifying Risk-Aversion through a Utility function

We seek a “valuation formula” for the amount we’d pay that:


Increases one-to-one with the Mean of the outcome
Decreases as the Variance of the outcome (i.e.. Risk) increases
Decreases as our Personal Risk-Aversion increases
The last two properties above define the Risk-Premium
But fundamentally why are we Risk-Averse?
Why don’t we just pay the mean of the random outcome?
Reason: Our satisfaction to better outcomes grows non-linearly
We express this satisfaction non-linearity as a mathematical function
Based on a core economic concept called Utility of Consumption
We will illustrate this concept with a real-life example

Ashwin Rao (Stanford) Utility Theory February 3, 2020 3 / 14


Law of Diminishing Marginal Utility

Ashwin Rao (Stanford) Utility Theory February 3, 2020 4 / 14


Utility of Consumption and Certainty-Equivalent Value

Marginal Satisfaction of eating cookies is a diminishing function


Hence, Accumulated Satisfaction is a concave function
Accumulated Satisfaction represents Utility of Consumption U(x)
Where x represents the uncertain outcome being consumed
Degree of concavity represents extent of our Risk-Aversion
Concave U(·) function ⇒ E[U(x)] < U(E[x])
We define Certainty-Equivalent Value xCE = U −1 (E[U(x)])
Denotes certain amount we’d pay to consume an uncertain outcome
Absolute Risk-Premium πA = E[x] − xCE
πA E[x]−xCE xCE
Relative Risk-Premium πR = E[x] = E[x] =1− E[x]

Ashwin Rao (Stanford) Utility Theory February 3, 2020 5 / 14


Certainty-Equivalent Value

Ashwin Rao (Stanford) Utility Theory February 3, 2020 6 / 14


Calculating the Risk-Premium
We develop mathematical formalism to calculate Risk-Premia πA , πR
To lighten notation, we refer to E[x] as x̄ and Variance of x as σx2
Taylor-expand U(x) around x̄, ignoring terms beyond quadratic
1
U(x) ≈ U(x̄) + U 0 (x̄) · (x − x̄) + U 00 (x̄) · (x − x̄)2
2
Taylor-expand U(xCE ) around x̄, ignoring terms beyond linear
U(xCE ) ≈ U(x̄) + U 0 (x̄) · (xCE − x̄)
Taking the expectation of the U(x) expansion, we get:
1
· U 00 (x̄) · σx2
E[U(x)] ≈ U(x̄) +
2
Since E[U(x)] = U(xCE ), the above two expressions are ≈. Hence,
1
U 0 (x̄) · (xCE − x̄) ≈ · U 00 (x̄) · σx2
2

Ashwin Rao (Stanford) Utility Theory February 3, 2020 7 / 14


Absolute & Relative Risk-Aversion
From the last equation on the previous slide, Absolute Risk-Premium
1 U 00 (x̄) 2
πA = x̄ − xCE ≈ − · 0 · σx
2 U (x̄)
00
We refer to function A(x) = − UU 0 (x)
(x)
as the Absolute Risk-Aversion
1
· A(x̄) · σx2
πA ≈
2
In multiplicative uncertainty settings, we focus on variance σ 2x of xx̄

In multiplicative settings, we also focus on Relative Risk-Premium πR
πA 1 U 00 (x̄) · x̄ σx2 1 U 00 (x̄) · x̄
πR = ≈− · · = − · · σ 2x
x̄ 2 U 0 (x̄) x̄ 2 2 U 0 (x̄) x̄

00
We refer to function R(x) = − UU 0(x)·x
(x) as the Relative Risk-Aversion
1
πR ≈ · R(x̄) · σ 2x
2 x̄

Ashwin Rao (Stanford) Utility Theory February 3, 2020 8 / 14


Taking stock of what we’re learning here

We’ve shown that Risk-Premium can be expressed as the product of:


Extent of Risk-Aversion: either A(x̄) or R(x̄)
Extent of uncertainty of outcome: either σx2 or σ 2x

We’ve expressed the extent of Risk-Aversion as the ratio of:


Concavity of the Utility function (at x̄): −U 00 (x̄)
Slope of the Utility function (at x̄): U 0 (x̄)
For optimization problems, we ought to maximize E[U(x)] (not E[x])
Linear Utility function U(x) = a + b · x implies Risk-Neutrality
Now we look at typically-used Utility functions U(·) with:
Constant Absolute Risk-Aversion (CARA)
Constant Relative Risk-Aversion (CRRA)

Ashwin Rao (Stanford) Utility Theory February 3, 2020 9 / 14


Constant Absolute Risk-Aversion (CARA)
1−e −ax
Consider the Utility function U(x) = a for a 6= 0
−U 00 (x)
Absolute Risk-Aversion A(x) = U 0 (x) = a
a is called Coefficient of Constant Absolute Risk-Aversion (CARA)
For a = 0, U(x) = x (meaning Risk-Neutral)
If the random outcome x ∼ N (µ, σ 2 ),

 1−e −aµ+ a22σ2
E[U(x)] = a for a 6= 0
µ for a = 0

aσ 2
xCE = µ −
2
aσ 2
Absolute Risk Premium πA = µ − xCE =
2
2
For optimization problems where σ is a function of µ, we seek the
2
distribution that maximizes µ − aσ2
Ashwin Rao (Stanford) Utility Theory February 3, 2020 10 / 14
A Portfolio Application of CARA
We are given $1 to invest and hold for a horizon of 1 year
Investment choices are 1 risky asset and 1 riskless asset
Risky Asset Annual Return ∼ N (µ, σ 2 )
Riskless Asset Annual Return = r
Determine unconstrained π to allocate to risky asset (1 − π to riskless)
Such that Portfolio has maximum Utility of Wealth in 1 year
−aW
With CARA Utility U(W ) = 1−ea for a 6= 0
Portfolio Wealth W ∼ N (1 + r + π(µ − r ), π 2 σ 2 )
From the section on CARA Utility, we know we need to maximize:
aπ 2 σ 2
1 + r + π(µ − r ) −
2
So optimal investment fraction in risky asset
µ−r
π∗ =
aσ 2

Ashwin Rao (Stanford) Utility Theory February 3, 2020 11 / 14


Constant Relative Risk-Aversion (CRRA)
x 1−γ −1
Consider the Utility function U(x) = 1−γ for γ 6= 1
−U 00 (x)·x
Relative Risk-Aversion R(x) = U 0 (x) =γ
γ is called Coefficient of Constant Relative Risk-Aversion (CRRA)
For γ = 1, U(x) = log(x). For γ = 0, U(x) = x − 1 (Risk-Neutral)
If the random outcome x is lognormal, with log(x) ∼ N (µ, σ 2 ),

 e µ(1−γ)+ σ22 (1−γ)2 −1
E[U(x)] = 1−γ for γ 6= 1
µ for γ = 1
σ2
xCE = e µ+ 2
(1−γ)

xCE σ2 γ
Relative Risk Premium πR = 1 − = 1 − e− 2

2
For optimization problems where σ is a function of µ, we seek the
2
distribution that maximizes µ + σ2 (1 − γ)
Ashwin Rao (Stanford) Utility Theory February 3, 2020 12 / 14
A Portfolio Application of CRRA (Merton 1969)

We work in the setting of Merton’s 1969 Portfolio problem


We only consider the single-period (static) problem with 1 risky asset
Riskless asset: dRt = r · Rt · dt
Risky asset: dSt = µ · St · dt + σ · St · dzt (i.e. Geometric Brownian)
We are given $1 to invest, with continuous rebalancing for 1 year
Determine constant fraction π of Wt to allocate to risky asset
To maximize Expected Utility of Wealth W = W1 (at time t = 1)
Constraint: Portfolio is continuously rebalanced to maintain fraction π
So, the process for wealth Wt is given by:

dWt = (r + π(µ − r )) · Wt · dt + π · σ · Wt · dzt


W 1−γ −1
Assume CRRA Utility U(W ) = 1−γ , 0 < γ 6= 1

Ashwin Rao (Stanford) Utility Theory February 3, 2020 13 / 14


Recovering Merton’s solution (for this static case)
Applying Ito’s Lemma on log Wt gives us:
Z t Z t
π2σ2
log Wt = (r + π(µ − r ) − ) · du + π · σ · dzu
0 2 0

π2σ2 2 2
⇒ log W ∼ N (r + π(µ − r ) −,π σ )
2
From the section on CRRA Utility, we know we need to maximize:
π 2 σ 2 π 2 σ 2 (1 − γ)
r + π(µ − r ) − +
2 2

π2σ2γ
= r + π(µ − r ) −
2
So optimal investment fraction in risky asset
µ−r
π∗ =
γσ 2
Ashwin Rao (Stanford) Utility Theory February 3, 2020 14 / 14

You might also like