Wordsworth's Panentheism
Daniel Dombrowski
Creighton University, Omaha, Neb.
Most critics seem quite self-assured when they dis-
‘cuss what Wordsworth meant by God, but the conflicts
among. scholars on this topic make one wonder if
Wordsworth’s concept of God is in a state of confusion
Some interpreters see him as a pantheist, such that his
closest philosophical model was Spinoza.! Others deny that
hhe was a pantheist, even if they donot know what sort
of theist he was? Still others see 2 shift in Wordsworth's
thought away fom a pantheistic, naturalistic early period
to some other form of theism later on. These scholars dis-
agree about exactly when and to what extent this shift took
place, but they are alike in having a great deal of difficulty
Aescribing Wordsworth’s later theism, which never quite
fits the traditional Western mold? A resolution of the
problems surrounding Worlsworth’s God can be found,
1 think, fone compares Wordsworth with Whitehead, who
was neither a pentheist nor & classical thest, bt a ps
theist The mistake most interpreters make isto assume
that divive immanence and transcendence are mutually
exclusive.
My purpose in this article is to defend the panen-
theistic interpretation of Wordsworth with the aid of the
greatest living panentheist, Charles Hartshorne, who is
also the greatest living defender of Whitehead, who was
a devotee of Wordsworth himself. ARer analyzing
Hartshomne’s thought about God, I will use his thought
to examine several texts from Wordsworth, Then I will
suggest why it i plausible to claim that Wordsworth was
4 pinentheist in spite of himself, m that he never would
Ihave used the word “panentheism.®
Hartshorne fully accepts the goal of the traditional
Chistian philosophers; ie, logical analysis in the service
of a higher end. But he holds that the classical conception,
of God is internally incoherent. One of the major com-
plaints Hartshome has with classical theism (in philosophy
and theology, 3s opposed to Biblical theism) is that it
either explicitly or implicitly identifies God as active and,
not passive. St. Thomés's unmoved mover is the most ob-
vious example of this tendency, but in general classical
theists see God as a timeless, supernatural being that does
not change. The classical theist’s inconsisteney lies in his
also claiming that God knows and loves. For example, if
God knows God must be a subject on the analogy of
hhuman subjects, and if God is a subject who knows God
rmust be afected by, be passive with respect to, the object
known
It will be to our advantage to get as clear as we can
‘on what we mean by the term “Cod.” For Hartshome,
the term refers to the supremely excellent, or all-worship-
136
fal being. As is well known, Hartshorne has been the most
important defosder of St. Anselm's ontological argument
in this century, and bis debt to St. Anselm is evideat in
this preliminary definition. It closely resembles St. An-
seln’s “that than which no greater can be conceived.” Yet
the ontological argument is not what is at stake here. Even
if the argument fails, which Hartshorne would doubt, the
preliminary definition of God as the supremely excellent
being, the all-worshipful being, or the greatest conceivable
being seems unobjectionable. To say that God can be de-
fined in these ways sill leaves open the possbilty that
Gol is even more excellent or worshipful than our ability
to conceive, This allows us to avoid objections from mys-
tics who fear that by defining God we are limiting God
to “merely” human language. All Hartshorne is suggesting
is that when we think of God we must be thinking of a
being that surpasses al others, oF we are not thinking of
God, Even the atheist or agnostic would admit this mach,
When the atheist says “There is no Cod," he ie denying
that a supremely excellent, all-worshipful, greatest con-
ceivable being, exists
‘The contrast “excellent-inferior” isthe truly invidi-
ous contrast when applied to God. If to be invidious is
to be injurious, then this contrast is the most invidious
one of all when applied (both terms) to God because God
is only excellent. God is inferior in no way. To suggest
that God is in some small way inferior to some other being
is to no longer speak about God but about some being
that is not supremely excellent, or all-worshipful, or the
greatest concetsable, Hartshorne's major criticism of dlass-
fal theism is that it hes assumed that all contrasts, or most
of them, when applied to God are invidious
Let us assume from now on that God exists. What
attributes does God possess? Consider the following two
columns of attributes in polar contrast to each other:
one mary
being becoming.
setivity asivity
permanence change
recessty ‘contingency
self-sufficient dependent
setual potential
absolute relive
abstract concrete
‘Clessical theism tends toward oversimplification. It is com-
pantively easy to say “Cod is strong rather than weak, s0
in all relations God is active, not passive.” In each ease,the classical theist decides which member of the contrast-
ing pair is good (on the left), then attributes it to God,
‘while wholely denying the contrasting term (on the right).
Hence, God is one, but not many; permanent but not
changing This leads to what Hartshome calls “the
monopolir prejudice.” Monopolasty is common to both
classical theism and pantheism, with the major difference
between the two being the fect that classical theism admits
the reality of plurality, potentiality, and becoming as asec-
ondary fori of existence “outside” God (on the right);
‘whereas, in pantheism, God includes all reality within it.
self, Common to both classical theism and pantheism is
the belie that the above categorical contrasts are invidi-
‘ous. The dilemma these two positions face is that ether
the deity is only one constituent of the whole (classical
theism), or the alleged inferior pole in each contrast (on
the right) is illusory (pantheism). 1 will show that
‘Wordsworth avoided both of these positions
For Hartshome this dilemma is artificial. It is pro-
duced by the assumption that excellence is found by
separating and purifying one pole (on the left) and
grating the other (on the right). That this is not the case
can be seen by anelyzing some of the attributes on the
right side. At least since St. Augustine, classical theists
Ihave boon convinced that Cod'e eternity meant not that
Gol endared through all time, but that God was outside
of time altogether and did not. could not, be receptive
to temporal change. St. Thomas identified God, following
Aristotle, who was the greatest predecessor to classical
theism, as unmoved. Yet bath activity and passivity ean
be either good or bad. Good passivity is likely to be called
sensitivity, responsiveness, adaptability, sympathy, and the
like. Insufficiently subtle or defective passivity is called
‘wooden inflexibility, mulish stubborness, inadaptabilty,
unresponsiveness, and the like. To deny God passivity al-
together is to deny God those aspects of passiaty which
are excellences. Or again, to altogether deny God the abil.
ity to change avoids fcklencss, but at the expense of the
ability to lovingly react to the sufferings of others. For
‘Wordeworth this too great a price to pay, at we shal coo
‘The terms on the left side have both good and bad
aspects as well. Oneness can mean wholeness; but also it
‘ean mean monotony or trivalty. Actualty can mean def-
initeness; but also it can mean non-relatedness to others.
‘What happens to divine love when God, according to St
‘Thomas, is claimed to be pure actuality? God ends up lov-
ing the world, bt is not intrinsically related to it, whatever
sort of love that may be. Sel-sufficiency can, at times, be
selfishness.
‘The trick when thinking of God, for Hartshorne, is
to attribute to God all excellences (left and right sides)
and not to attribute to God any inferiortes (right and left
sides). Io short, excollont-inferior, knowledge ignorance,
or good-evil are invidious contrasts, but cne-many, being
137
becoming, et al., are non-invidious contrasts. Unlike cass-
‘cel theism and panthsism, Hartshorne’s theism is dipolar.
Tobe specific, within each pole ofa non-invidious contrast
(eg., permanence-change) there are invidious elements
{inferior permanence or inferior change), but also nos-in-
vidious, good elements (excellent permanence or excellent
change).
Hartshorne does not believe in two gods, ene uni
and the other plural. Rather he believes that what are
often thought to be contraries are really mutually interde-
pendent correlative: “The good as we know itis unity-in-
varity, or variety-in-unity: ifthe variety overbelances, we
hhave chaos or discord; if the unity, we have monotony or
trivalty” (PSG, 3). Supreme excellence, if it i truly su-
preme excellence, must somehow be able to integrate all
the complexity there is in the world into itself as one
spiritual whole. The word “must” indicates divine neces-
sity along with God's essence, which is to necessarily exist.
‘And the word “complexity” indicates the contingency
which affects God through creaturely decisions or feelings.
But in the classical theistic view, God is solely identified
wit the stony immobility ofthe absolute, implying nor-re-
latedness to the world. For Hartshorae, God in the
abstract nature, God's being, may in a way escape from
the temporal lux, but a living God is related to the world
‘of becoming, which entails divine becoming as well if the
world in some way is internally related to God. The class-
ical theis's alternative to this view suggests that all re-
lationships to God are extemal to divinity, once again
threatening not only God's love, but also Gods nobility.
‘A dog's being behind a particular rock affects the dog in
certain ways, thus this relation is an internal relation to
the dog, But it does not affect the rock, whose relationship
with the dog is extemal to the rock's nature, Does this
not show the superiority of canine consciousness, which
4s aware of the rock, o rocklike existence, which Is una-
ware of the dog? Is it not therefore peculiar that God has
been described solely in rocklike terms: pure actuality,
permanence, only having external relations, unmoved,
boing not becoming?
In short, the divine being becomes. or the divine be-
coming is — God's being and becoming form a single re-
ality: *.. There is no law of logic agains atributing con-
trasting predicates to the same individual, provided they
apply to diverse asprcts of this individual... God is
neither being as contrasted to becoming nor becoming 8s
contrasted to being: but categorically supreme becoming
in which there is inferior being” (PSG, 14-15, 24). Thus,
Hartshorne's theism can be called panentheism, which lit-
erally means “all in God.” God is neither completely re
moved from the world, or unmoved by it, asin classical
theism, nor completely identified with the world, as in
ppantheism. Rather, God is, first, world.inclusive in the
sense thet Cod carer forall the world; and all feokngs
in the world — especially suffering feelings — are felt byGod; and, secondly, transcendent in the sense that God
is greater than any other being, especially because of
God's love
My thesis i that Wordsworth was neither a panthetst
nora classical theist. Throughout his career his works bear
the stamp of panentheism. As late as 1835, when many
see him having completely abandoned his supposed earlier
partheism. he states: “And nature God disdained not.”*
‘Wordsworth’s theism was always a nature-oriented theism
of some sort, and at odds with classical theism. Yet at least
as early as 1804, when some suggest he did net see God.
as transcendent, we can see him talk of God as:
the Upholder of the trangul soul,
‘That tolerates the indiguties of Time,
And, from the ceatre of tery
All haste motions overruling, Ines
In glory immutable
(relade, M1, 17-191 (1790-1608),
A pantheistic Cod does not uphold souls, nor can st be
described in such Platonic terms, bat more on Plato later.
More fruitful than a genetic approach to
Wordsworth’s theism is my hypothesis regarding his
lifelong panentkeism, which, when used as a heuristic de-
vice, is quite fruitful.” Has justice been done to these fa-
‘mous lines?
And I have felt
‘A presence that dsturbs me with the joy
‘OF elevated thoughts; & sense sublime
Of something far more deeply iterfused,
‘Whose dwelling is the light of seting suns,
And the round ocean and the living ai,
‘And the blae aby,
‘A motion anda spint, that impels
AAI thinking things, all objects of ll thought,
‘And rolls through all things.
(Tintern Abbey.” I. 98.108 (1708))
in the mind of man:
Granted, the presence that disturbs Wordsworth rolls
through all things, dwells in setting suns, the oceans, the
air, and in the mind of man. But this presence also impels
all thiokiug things, implying that this presence has some
sort of independent existence on its own.
More accurate than the suggestion that God is in
all things is the claim that all things are in God, messing
that all that happens in the world makes a difference to
God. The raind of man becomes: "In beauty exalted, ar
it is itself OF quality and fabric more divine.” (Prelude,
XIV, 453.54). God cares for us even when the world
which is different from God's being if not God's becoming,
does not. Wordsworth speaks
138
In gratitude to God, Who feeds oor hearts
For His avn service; knoweth, loveth us,
When we we unegarded by the worl
(@relede, XM
276-78),
If these lines are inconsistent with pantheism, those in the
remarkable selection below are equally inconsistent with
classical theism. Do they indicate that Wordsworth’s
theism was a panentheism, which, again, means “all in
Goa"? *.. all beings live with god, themselves/ Are god,
Existing ia the mighty whole” It is premature to hold that
“If any language is pantheistic, this surly is," as Rader
claims." Ifthe above lines mean that the whole is greater
than the sum ofthe parts, which is a tenable interpretation
supported by many cther texts, then Wordsworth’s lan-
guage here is not pantheiste.
‘Trying to have one’s cake ancl eat it too is impossible;
crying like Plato's child for both being and becoming
(Sophist, 40D), for divine transcendence and immanence,
is not impossible at al
Listen! The mighty Being is awake,
‘And doth with his eternal motion make
‘A scund lite thurder — everlastingly.
(lt is a beauteous evening,” Il. 6-8)
God is net only “mighty Being” but also “eternsl motion.”
In fact, itis largely God's eternal motion, unlike our tem
porary or intermittent motion, which makes God such a
mighty Being. Regarding the sounds of « mountain echo
Wordsworth tells us to: “Listen, ponder, hold them dear:
4 For of God — of God they are” CYes, itis @ mountain
Echo,” Il 19-20). But conceming a seashell he says, at the
same period in his career, that
ven such a shell the wnlverse ell
1s to the ear of Faith; and there are times
1 doubt not. when to you it doth impart
Authentic tidings of snotible things.
(Excursion, IV, 141-144)
Divine perfection lies, he implies, in dipolaity. After view-
ing Leonardo's “Last Supper’ Wordsworth notices: “The
love deep-seated in the Savior's face" ("The Last Supper,”
1. 9). Yet Wordsworth also believes that the superiority of
the Christian God to pagan deities (nature deities! lies
ln God's impenctrabily (Saggested on a Sabbath mora-
ing” I. 54). Wordsworth avoids the conflict found in class-
ical theism when it cltims thet God is both an unmoved
mover and a God of love. That is, for Wordsworth, God
ie impenetrable because Cou's love is 40 deep-seated.
What have previous interpreters of Wordeworth's
‘concept of God done with the following lines, written
about rocks and clouds? TheyWere all lke workings of one mind, the features
(Ff the same face, blossoms upon one tee:
Characters of the great Apocalypse,
‘The types and symbols of Eternty.
Of fst, and lst, and midst, and without end
(Prelude, VI, 635-640)
God is not only one, which even a pantheist could admit,
but one mind. Its not only the defects in pantheism that
Wordsworth corrects, but also these, perhaps primarily
those, of classical theism: “The immortal Mind craves ob-
jeots that endure” (“Those words were uttered,” 1.12). It
is true that Wordsworth calls God “Etermal Lori!” in the
1897 sonnet by the same name, and holds that, “The wise
man, I aflirm, can find no rest / In that which perishes”
(CNo mortal abject,” I. 9-10, {published, 1807). But he
also believes, and not inconsistently, that God breathes
("The prayers I make,” I. 8), and has a love whick remains
unquenched (Excursion, LV, 50-51).
Al can agree with Wordsworth that the term God
refers to “Supremacy” ("Not utterly Unworthy,”L 1). But
what does it mean to be supreme? To exist necessarily and
to be steadfast, yes; but also to be merciful (Outstretching
flaneword,” 1.2), or beter, to be a fountain of grace ("By
chain yet stronger.” I. 8). a God of peace ("Scattering like
birds,” 114), Supremacy consists in a harmonious balance
of flexibility and duty, which is the “stern daughter” of
God's voice (“Ode to Duty,” Il. 1-2). Notice below, on the
‘one hand, the words “sorrow” and “friend,” and on the
other, “never”
‘Ohl There is never sorrow of heart
‘That shall ack a timely end,
I but to Gad we turn, and ask
Of Him to be our fend!
(The Force of Prayer” H. 65-68)
‘Wordsworth’s panentheism is evident not only in the
poems cited above, which were written in the wide period
between 1798 and 1837, but also in “Ode: Intimations of
Immortality.” Wordsworth wishes his days to be bound
with “natural piety.” and the youth is “Nature's priest.”
But is this theism, which has come to terms with nature,
and has linked nature with God, a pantheism? What is lit-
tle noticed is that the blessed events in nature which par-
ticipate in the divine life ere “Creatures,” with whom
heaven laughs. The term “Creature” makes no sense with-
out a Creator. Nor is it often emphasized, although i is,
mentioned, that Wordsworth’s theism is an affair of the
rind as well as of the heart: his “head hath its coronal.”
We are in the life of Cod in that Cod knows us, feels
us, loves us. But Wordsworth believes in a God “who is
cour home,” and we are not fully at home in this world
‘The childs the one who is a “Mighty prophet, seer blest,”
with *heaven-bor freedom.” We adults notice that the vi-
19
slonary gleam, the glory and the dream, of our home has
faded. However, "We will grieve not, rather find/ Strength.
in what remains behind
My claim is that panentheism is oe of the things
that remains behind, for us perhaps an acquisition of the
“years that bring the philosophic mind.” We human being:
are dipoles, but not supremely so; we become, and yet
have an identity through time. God's supreme becoming,
speaks to us through the rainbow that comes and goes:
the birds, as Hartshome, who is also an expert on bird
song, more than anyone knows; and through timely utier-
ances. Concomitantly: “Our noisy years seem moments in
the being / Of the eternal silence.”
It might be objected that my panentheistic interpre-
tation of Wordsworth is highly unlikely because he never
real Harshome, nor did he ever consider Whitehead's
distinction between God as primordial and Ged as eon-
sequent. This charge may be bit to hasty, however. Al-
‘though the word was not used in antiquity, panentheism,
cor at Toast dipolar theism, is as old as Pato, Just as one
‘ean be a Platorist without knowing it, so one can be a
parenthest. At with regard to Platonism,
‘Wordsworth was a self:conscious participant. He said to
Emerson in 1848 that if the Republic were published as
a new book it would have few readers, yet “we have em-
bodied i al."* We" refers a! least to Wordsworth himself
and Coleridge, but perhaps also to the Cambridge
Platonists, Thomas Taylor (with his researches and trans-
lations), and Scleiermacher (especially his Introduction
to the Dialogues of Hato), all of which were well rep-
resented in Wordsworth’s library at Rydal Mount. The ce
erences to Plato in the Concordance to Wordsworh’s
poetry are perhaps greater in number than those to a
other thirker. Wordsworth refers to “Plato's genius,” his
“re sub id the “everlasting praie” dvc to him.
His truth is that “half of truth” most neglected in Eng-
sland.” ‘the other half, widely accepted, was the Aristote-
lian tradition of empiricism. One scholar goes so far as
to claim that the revival of interest in Plato may be the
‘most important single facet of the Romantic movement.”
In short, if Plato were a panenthest, it would not be an
exctic guess to suspect that it was through him that
Wordsworth got his panentheism.
lest
Certain Platonic texts are obvious sources. In the
Sophist (246-249) the Eleatic Straager develops the ma-
ture Platonie metaphysics, which is opposed by both the
“giants,” who are the materilists (or, we might say, the
pantheists) who drag everything down from the heaven to
faith; and the “gods.” (or, we might say, the classical
theists) who defend their position somewhere in the
heights of the unseen Reality is dyadic for Plato, and is
corstituted by anything (being or becoming) which has
dyramis, the power to affect or be affected by somethinglse* Eyen in the Republic, Plato avoids what many
Plaionists have assumed to be the Platonic postion: un-
bridled worship of being. The tak of the philosopher
(GOIB) fs to glance frequently in two directions: fist, at
the Form of Justin, Beauty, and the like as they are in
the nature of things, but also at this caveike world, where
fone must try to reproduce the Forms to the extent that
‘one can, or atleast recognize the extent to which material
justice or beauty participate in formal reality As has often
been noticed, but seldom understood fully, Wordsworth
had a yearning for the One underlying the Many," but
also an appreciation of the extent to which each of the
many was itself possessive of a certain degree of unity,
or ese each of these would nct be a tree, this cloud, et al
Perhaps the most coavincing studies of Plato's
them, and the dyadie charscter of being in Plato, have
been done by Leonard Eslick, who relies on Hartshome,
whom Eslick cites as the first to recognize Plato as a di
poler theist There are two significant ways in which
Plato talks about God (theos). First he inherited from Par-
renides the notion that being is eternal, immutable, and
selfsame. It is this notion which was the starting point
for the tradition of classical, monopolar theism, “The ex-
tent to which Plato is committed to such an absolute
schism between being and becoming ...would seem to
dictate for him a similar exclusion from divinity of all
shadow of change.” This tendency is evidenced in Book
Two of the Republic, the Phaedo |78-80), and the Sym-
posium (202-203). However, as Eslick and others hold,
there is no textual foundation for the popular identification
(of Plato's God with the transcendent Form of the Good,
nor even with the world of Forms, either as a whole or
in part Even when talking about divine eternity and im-
‘mutability, the Platonic locus for divinity is pyche oF neus.
It comes as a shock to some readers of Plato, who have
only read the Republic, Phacdo, and Symposium, that in
the Phaedrus (245, etc.) Erosis claimed tobe divine. Here
Plato discovers, according to Eslick, a new. dynamic mean-
ing for perfection, similar to the one described abave, and
exemplified in the selections I have chosen from
Wordsworth.” The perfection which is dynamic isthe per-
fection of life itself, trated not only in the Phardrus but
in Book ‘Ten of the Lewy as well
In the Timeus and the Sophist both poles in Plato's
theism are brought together: the perfection of divine im-
mutability and the perfection of divine life, The former
is identified im the Timtus with the Demiurge, who eter-
nally and without change contemplates the ‘srchetypal
models, the etemal Forms. The latter is identified with
the World Soul — which is close to Word:worth’s!®
panpsychism — whose essence is self-motion, and is de-
picted as posterior to the Demiurge ! The motions of psy-
chic life include both actions and passions. In fat, in the
Sophist, as has been noted above, reality is identified with
dynamis o- power; specifically, the power to aflect or be
i)
alfected by others. Even Arstotle attests to the fact shat
realy, for Plato, isthe joint prodoet of the One and the
Tiwlefinite Dyad (tetuphyst, A). Unfortunatly, Aris-
totl’s ov notion of God loses the Platonic character of
divine immanence, of God as the Wordsworthian soul of
the world. Even more unfortunate isthe fact that Plotinus,
and others who became identified as followers of Phito,
‘were with respest to their descriptions of God really Aris-
totelans.
Ik is not unreasonable to speculate that Wordsworth
saw the inadequacies of latter day Flatomists. We have seen
that he claimed about Platonism that “we have embodied
it al.” In the following poem Wordsworth indicates that
truths about God can be searched for in terms of a
Platonic piety. God is the immortal one, henee solitary;
but also 2 builder, although Wordsworth was abvays scep-
tical about talk of Gad as a creator, even if be engaged
in such talk himself at times® God is above the starry
sphere, hence dark; yet not alone, ia that God whispers
to.as and allows us to see God.
Yet Truth i keenly sought for, and the wind
Charged wih rich words poured out in hought’ defense:
‘Whether the Church inspite thit eloquence,
Or & Platonie pity confired
‘To the sole temple of the inward minis
‘And One there is who builds immortal lays,
‘Though doomed to tread in soltary ways,
Dariness before and danger's voice behind
Yet not alone, nor helpless to repel
Sad thoughts; for from above the stany sphere
Cone secrets, whispered nightly to his ear
‘And the pore spit of celestial light
Shines through his soul — ‘that he my sce and tel
‘Of things invisible to mortal sight.”
(CResesiatcal Sonnets, “Latleudinaranlm,” 1821)
Cation must be displayed when putting
Wordsworth into a cetegory, or when alfixing a label to
him?" But even those Wordsworth interpreters who make
this point themselves categorize Wordsworth and affix
labels to him, at least if they are interpreters. The trick
4s to avoid egregious errors in categorization, and to affix
labels without dogmatism so that the texts themselves can
breathe, To call Wordsworth a pantheist or a classical
theist (or an orthodox believer) isto leave something sig-
nificant in Wordsworth's thought unexplained. To eal him
a panentheist sto get alittle closer, I think, to his thought
on God. Yet when dealing with thoughts as rich as those
of Wordsworth, too deep for tears, getting a little closer
may be going a long way.
NOTES
'Sce Helen Darbihire, “Wordsworth’s Prelude,” in W.]Haney and Richard Gravil, eds,, Wordsworth: The Prelude
(0072), p. 05; Herbert Read, Wordseurth (1850), pp. 47, 104;
Johs Jones, The Egotistial Sublime (1854), pp. 36, 4, 74; and
Jonsthan Wordsworth, The Music of Humanty (1960), p. 213,
Who notices that Wordsworth never repudiated his belief in One
Life, and if 1 anderstand Jonathan Wordbworth correctly,
‘Wordsworth never completely abandoned his pantheism, Two
‘other scholars imply, but they aze not explicit, that Wordsworth
was a panthoist. Stephen Pricket, Coleridge and Wordsworth
(097), pp. 80, 96, 105, 194; and Kenneth Johnston, Wordsworth
and “The Recluse” (1988), pp. 15, 9.
2Wilard Spery, “Wordsworths Religion.” in Giert
Dunkin, ed, Wordsworth (1851), p. 185; Pal Sheats, The Mal
{ng of Wordswortlis Poetry, 1786-1795 (1978), pp, 21-213, where
the author ightly holds that Wordsworth's Godis both immanent
and ranscendent, but he doesnot explain indepth how tis could
‘be and Richard Brantley, Wordsword's “Naural Methodem
(0975) pp. 164-165, who alo is correct in dstieguising between
nature a8 the work of God and God ivelf bt he, ke Sheats,
does not stow how Wordsworth theism was “aot finaly
hod.” if orthodoxy const in something, ike what I vail cll
clasca theism
This view & at leat as old as Stopford Brooke's lectures
‘1872. On Brooks's attempt to weal the supposed ambigutior
of Wordsworth’s religious experience into a theologically sound
continuuto, even if Wordkworth somtimes veered toward pan=
theism, see Harvey and Grav op. cit. pp. 2021. Als see HW.
Garned, Wordsworth: Lectures and Essays (1938), ith Batho,
The Later Wordscorth (1933); James Logan, Wordsworthion
Criticism 961), p. 112; and John Hodgson, Wordsworth’s
Philesophical Poctry, 1797-1814 (980), p. 89. Two other scholars
deserve notice: Alin Greb, The Philosyphic Mind: A Study of
Wordsworti’s Poetry and Thought, 1797-1805 (973), pp. 24,93,
238, who sees a shit in Wordsworth from panthelsm to transoen
dental Cistianty; ard Jonathan Wordsworth, William
Wordsworth: The Borders of Vison (1982), pp. 23, 24,26, 180,
320, etal, who modifies the postion of his earlier book in that
he believes William Wordsworth somewhat replaces his parth:
‘slom with human imegination, which takes on Godlike powers
‘Molin Rader comes close to such & resolstion, See
Wordsworth: A Philosophical Approsch (1987), pp. 59, 200; also
see “Whitehead” in the Index. Against the pantheistic interpre-
tation, Rader eltes Wordsworth’s 4 denial of the charge that
hhe was a pantheist, p. 198. Raderis by no means consisent, how
ever, in his treatment of Wordsworth’s panentheism. See pp. 78,
162, 200. Alo ste Alexander Cappon's two studies: About
Wordsworth ond Whitehead (1982), p. 62; and Aspects of
Wordsworth and Whitehead (1983), pp. 122133.
51 wil concentrate on three of Hartshome’s many works
Philosophers Speak of Cod (1959, hereafer: FSG; tights and
Ovenights of Grat Thinkers (1883), and “In Defense of
Wordswors View of Malate.” Phbophy ond Llerature 4
(0980, 0.8,
1
“Eedesiostical Sonnets, “Deplorable his Tot” LL. all
Wordsworth quotations are, unless otherwise noted, from Themae
Hutchinson and Emest DeSelinzout,eds., Werdsworth: Foeical
Works (1974). all words emphasized in Wordsvorth's poems are
my doing.
74 should make st clear that 1 am dealing specticlly with
‘Wordsworth’ consept of God in this artile, not with his attitud»
toward organized religions, popular pretensions to piety, or the
ike Regarding these latter isues Wordswerth's thought did
change, asi evidenced in hi poem “Decay of Piety” (published
1827). However, { am willing to admit a change of emphasis
within Wordsworth’s pasentheism as he got elder.
Rader quotes these lines from Prelude often (pp. 36,198,
te); see Emest DeSelincourt, ed, The Prelude (1926), p. 512
Also see Prelude, VILL 85, where Wordsworth refers tothe soul,
which “pasting through all Nature rest with God.” Quote fom
page 198,
David Newsome, Teo Clases of Men: Patontm end Eng-
sh Romertic That 974, p. 9
"sce Rader, pp. 12°73; Newsome, pp. 26-27
1G.M. Harper, The Neoplatonim of Willam Blake (1961),
p. 964
See my Plto’s Philosophy of History (1981) onthe Seph-
See Newsome, p. 16
Leonard sick, “Plato as Dipolar Theist” Process
Studies, 12 (1982), 243.251. Also see his “The Dyadic Character
of Being,” Modern Schoalman, 21 (1958-1954), 1-18.
Back, “Phto as Dipolar Theis,” p. 244,
"Ip addition to Eslick, see the study of PE, Moore, The
Religion of Plato 0021).
sick, “Phto as Dipolar Theis.” p. 245,
Sec my forthcoming book Not Even ¢ Sparrow Fill:
Harihome, God, and Animalt, especially the chapter on
Wordsworth and my various treatments of parpsychiem or psy-
chicalism, On the relationship between Plato's World Soul and
Wordsworl’s “Ove Life” see Jonathan Wordsworth, Willam
Wordsworth: The Border: of Viton, pp. 39, 14, 419 note 36
nader, p. 5, ressts the contention that Plato's Word
Soul is to be idensified with deity. See Timaus (348) where it
{5 quite clear thatthe Worhd-Soul is a Messed God, and (90-31)
where the World-Soul is described as perfect io the Phiebur
(20) the World-Seul i fairest and most precious; abo ace the
Laws (896-599)Qu creation ex nfo see Hartshorne's Onmipatence and
Other Theclogical Mistates (198)
See a good treatment of Wordsworth’s notion of God In
John Paski, Preface to Wordsworth (1982), pp. 79-05, This a
thor does not Mle Wordsworth being called pastheist, but
stretches his cate a bitin favor of Wordsworth’s orthodoxy with
respect to God. Again, 10 become more orthodox with respect
te raligious cult isnot necessarily to hold the orthodox predicates
applied to God
Presence, Absence, and the Difference: Wordsworth’s Autobiographical Construction of the
Romantic Ego
Eugene L, Stelzig
SUNY College at Genesco
After listening to Wordsworth’s recitation of the
1805 Prelude, Coleridge identified its true subject as “the
foundation and the building wp / Of a Human Spirit” (To
Wiliam Wordsworth,” 5-6). The spirit building or shrine
of The Prelude is an omcular project fairy consistently in-
formed by a heightened Romantic poetics of “presence.”
Right at the start The Prelude strikes a bold note of
spiritual renovation, “prophesy,” and “holy services,” as the
poet finds his voice fully present to himself ("my own voice
cheared me”) (I, 60-64), Yet as students ofthe poem know
too well, this is only half the story for the poet's supreme
assurance of his fitness for his appointed task has a dark
double or shadow which manifests itself, almost im-
mediately, as a halting counter-thetorie of the failure or
encumbrance of the poet's will, voice, end power. This
anxious counter current at once calls into question and de-
fines Wordswort’s autobiography, for his exemplary and
selfassured buthling up of the poet's “spit” ts frustrated
almost at every turn by a sease of “absence,” snd some-
times by a traumatic recognition af the “difference” — to
uote one of the “Lucy” poems — between presence and
absence, 25 well as between present, past, and future
In other words, Wordsworth’ autobiographical con-
struction of the self involves the assertion of a poeties of
presence called into question by an equally powerful pres-
sure of absence, by the nighimare of a faltering self bur-
dened by the loss ofits voice and a coherent sense of its
proper identity. This isa “blank desertion” (1, 422) which
Wordsworth can suffer, paradoxically, even in his supreme
moments of selfconsciousness, the “spots of time,” which
are frequently ambivalent moments of troubled selfex-
perience. Moreover, if Wordworth’s fashioning of the
Romantic ego is threstened by self-doubt, the language
‘of absence which signs this fact sometimes reaches out
to its opposite in a confessional movement of sef-(relas-
surance, a strviag for a recovered, strong ego that is lo
cated somewhere in the past and that the autobiographer
a
hopes can be tansferted to the present and the future
So at the end of the opening bock of the 1805 Prelude,
Wordsworth acknowledges his need to “fix the wavering
balance of (his) mind” as the "hope" to “fetch / Invigorat-
ing thoughts from former years” (648.649). As he charac.
terzes this compensatory plot of converting absence into
presence in that poigrant confessional moment of Prelude
XI, he “would enshrine the spirit of the past / For future
restoration” (341-342). Such an identificble pattern of a
‘weik and anxious self recoiling to past moments of
strength and “the hiding places of (its) power’ (995) is
‘Wordsworth’s distinctive contribution to Romantic suto-
biography:
‘The gap or “difference” between “presence” and
‘absence” might be called the particular location of
Wordswoith’s best confessional poetry. In the symbolic
“Lacy” Iyses, for
through the speaker's elegioc lament at Lucy's untimely
demise: “But she is in her grave, and, oh. / The difference
to me!” (‘She Dwelt Among the Untrodden Ways"). The
threat of absence and loss haunting Wordsworth, his
human fears” CA Slumber Did My Spirt Seal") of mor-
tality — “the memory of whet has been, /And never more
will be” ("Three Years She Grew") —is focussed in the
stark Lucy seript as the graphic reducticn of the human
to the gravitational motion of mere matter ("Rolled round
in earth's diurnal course, / With rocks, and stones, and
trees") ("A Slumber Did My Spint Seal”). The elegiac
dialectic of present absence and absent presence at work
im the “Loey” poems isalso enacted at length in such major
naratives of naked human suffering as Michael and The
Ruined Cottage, where Wordsworth’ anxicties find objec~
tive correlatives through such starkly symbolic signfiers
4s Michael’ unfinished sheepfold and Margarets ruined
‘cottage. This graphic architecture of absence again equates
death with the terminally insensate and material even ax
it movingly commemorates the dear presence of those de-
ance, this “difference” is dramatized