Paradigmatic Faults in International-Relations Theory

Download as doc, pdf, or txt
Download as doc, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 46

Paradigmatic Faults in International-Relations Theory

by

Patrick Thaddeus Jackson

Associate Professor

School of International Service

American University

and

Daniel H. Nexon

Assistant Professor

Department of Government and School of Foreign Service

Georgetown University

Revised and Resubmitted Version of MS 20070308-637-2, International Studies Quarterly

Forthcoming, December 2009


Abstract: American scholars routinely characterize the study of international relations as

divided between various Kuhnian “paradigms” or Lakatosian “research programmes.”

Although most international-relations scholars have abandoned Kuhn’s account of

scientific continuity and change, many utilize Lakatosian criteria to assess the

“progressive” or “degenerative” character of various theories and approaches in the field.

We argue that neither specific areas of inquiry (such as the “democratic peace”) nor

broader approaches to world politics (such as realism, liberalism, and constructivism)

deserve the label of “paradigms” or “research programmes.” As an alternative, we

propose mapping the field through Weberian techniques of ideal-typification.

Acknowledgements: For helpful comments and criticisms, we thank the editorial team at

International Studies Quarterly, a surprising number of anonymous reviewers, J. Samuel

Barkin, Jeffrey Checkel, Raymond Duvall, Stacie Goddard, Peter Howard, Victoria Hui,

Yosef Lapid, Richard Ned Lebow, Jennifer Mitzen, Jennifer Sterling-Folker, as well as

also participants at panels at the 5th Annual Pan-European Conference on International

Relations, the International Studies Association, and a conference on “Realist

Constructivism” sponsored by the Mortara Center for International Studies at

Georgetown University. We are particularly grateful to Michael D. Gordin and Rom

Harré for general comments and suggestions. Finally, we extend special appreciation to

the late Steven Poe, whose careful consideration, honesty, and willingness to take a

chance on this manuscript made its publication possible.


“Paradigmatic Faults” 1 ISQ, December 2009

T.S. Kuhn’s notion of “paradigms” and Imre Lakatos’ concept of “research programmes”

continue to influence how international-relations scholars map our field. Some represent

international-relations theory, at least in the United States, as a three-cornered fight between

realism, liberalism, and constructivism (Walt 1998); they describe each as “paradigms” or

“research programmes” (Geller and Vasquez 2004). Others speak of distinct “research

programmes” such as analysis of the “democratic peace” (Ray 2003), “balance-of-power

theory” (Vasquez 2003), and “power-transition theory” (DiCicco and Levy 1999). In this essay,

we argue that none of these collections of theory qualify as Kuhnian paradigms or Lakatosian

research programmes.

Our core argument is as follows: To qualify as a paradigm, a set of theories must involve

not merely common assumptions and orientations but shared incommensurable content with

respect to some other paradigm. Although Lakatos rejects what he takes to be Kuhn’s

incommensurability thesis, his research programmes are also comprised of theories that share the

same sort of content that Kuhn described as sources of incommensurability.

The problem for the use of Kuhnian and Lakatosian frameworks to describe “theoretical

aggregates” (Elman and Elman 2002) such as “realism,” “constructivism,” and the “democratic

peace” is that the specific theories conventionally associated with them lack shared

incommensurable content; some of the better candidates for sources of incommensurability in the

discipline, in turn, cut across them. It follows that we should not use Kuhnian and Lakatosian

accounts of theory choice to evaluate these aggregates, and that treating them as “paradigms” or

“research programmes” distorts dialogue and debate in the field.

But if neither framework describes these aggregates, how should we understand their

place in international-relations theory? We argue that specific areas of shared research, such as
“Paradigmatic Faults” 2 ISQ, December 2009

power transitions, can be labeled “research programs” so long as we stipulate that this does not

imply Lakatosian philosophical baggage (e.g., Katzenstein, Keohane, and Krasner 1998, 646-

647). But more general aggregates such as realism, liberalism, and constructivism are better seen

as ideal-typifications of core wagers—sometimes implicit, other times explicit—about the nature

of international politics. These ideal-typifications, in turn, produce property spaces within which

many real theories reside. We expand on this argument in the second part of the paper.

Of Paradigms and Research Programmes

In this section, we argue against designating many theoretical aggregates in international-

relations scholarship as Kuhnian “paradigms” or Lakatosian “research programmes.” First, the

specific histories of the natural sciences—and sometimes mathematics—supply the empirical

data for Kuhn and Lakatos. The history of the field of international relations departs markedly,

however, from the history of chemistry, physics, or biology. It lacks, for instance, the

background conditions of concrete, widely recognized, scientific achievements of the kind that

Kuhn and Lakatos take for granted in their analyses of the natural sciences. Whatever the merits

of international-relations scholarship, it has not allowed us to manipulate our environment in

ways equivalent to the natural sciences—it is not unquestionably “progressive” in the same way

as physics or chemistry. Therefore we confront no “puzzle” of scientific progress of the kind

Kuhn and Lakatos assume (cf. Chernoff 2002; Chernoff 2007).1

1
International-relations scholars also embraced Kuhn and Lakatos out of their aspiration for the
field to achieve the status of a “science.” Both provide (or provided) accounts of the nature of
science and scientific progress compatible with disciplinary practices in international-relations
and political-science scholarship. Thus, the familiar narrative that scholars gravitated to Kuhn
because his approach suggested that division into multiple “camps” is compatible with “science,”
but once they recognized his apparent relativism, they turned to Lakatos as a more “scientific”
alternative (see, e.g., Ball 1976). We thank one of our reviewers for raising this issue.
“Paradigmatic Faults” 3 ISQ, December 2009

Second, collections of specific theories constitute a paradigm when they share common

content that renders them incommensurable vis-à-vis other paradigms. A Lakatosian research

programme also requires content that produces what Kuhn would call “local

incommensurabilities” with other research programs. Like the theories that comprise a paradigm,

those belonging to competing research programmes cannot be directly tested against one another.

In consequence, we must appeal to Lakatos’ Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes

(MSRP) to provide second-order, or external, criteria of theory choice. But these conditions do

not obtain for most of the theoretical aggregates that international-relations theorists classify as

paradigms or research programmes.

 Most putative “research programmes,” such as power-transition theory and

democratic-peace theory, are commensurable and comparable.

 Many of the specific theories conventionally associated with the different “isms,”

such as realist and liberal theories utilizing rational-choice analytics, are

commensurable and comparable.

 The most plausible sources of incommensurability in the field involve much

larger debates about how to pursue social-scientific knowledge, complexes of

theoretical terms, and so forth; these sources of incommensurability are

orthogonally related to the “isms.”

It follows that neither such specific research programs nor the “isms” should be treated as

units—whether paradigms or research programmes—for the purpose of theory choice, and that

we need not appeal to second-order criteria to resolve many existing “inter-paradigmatic”

debates in the international-relations theory.


“Paradigmatic Faults” 4 ISQ, December 2009

Kuhnian Paradigms

Kuhn (1970a, 154) sought to make sense of the historical development of science,

specifically the interruption of periods of “normal science” by “scientific revolutions” consisting

of “those non-cumulative developmental episodes in which an older paradigm is replaced in

whole or in part of an incompatible new one.” Kuhn (1970a, 85) argued, at least initially, that the

changes in the history of science between sets of fundamental assumptions about the world and

how to study it are akin to “change[s] in visual gestalt” whereby something that previously

appeared one way to a research community subsequently appears in a different way. Kuhn

(1970a, 122) further suggested that these changes in fundamental worldview arise, contra many

existing accounts, from “a relatively sudden and unstructured event” by which our perceptions

are reordered. Hence, “no exclusively logical criteria can entirely dictate the conclusion” that the

scientist “must draw” from particular empirical observations (Kuhn 1970b, 19). The growth of

anomalies within a paradigm may, over time, lead to an epistemic crisis in the scientific

community and, given the right conditions, paradigmatic change.

Kuhn’s account challenged a number of views of science, but most notably the claim of

deducibility, i.e., that “earlier sciences are derivable from later.” The existence of

incommensurable content in paradigmatic cores precludes the deductibility of pre-revolutionary

theories from post-revolutionary ones (Shapere 1964, 389). A post-revolutionary theory

represents not a simple replacement for a pre-revolutionary theory, but rather a change in at least

some of a theory’s basic ontological categories (Sankey 1993, 770). For Kuhn, in fact, one

cannot unproblematically test paradigms against one another: “the very possibility of scientific

communication and dialogue becomes problematic and the process of theory choice can no
“Paradigmatic Faults” 5 ISQ, December 2009

longer be reduced to the simple picture presented, for example, by the logical empiricists”

(Biaoligi 1993, 211; see also Wight 1996, 296).

Kuhn’s incommensurability thesis (IT) accounts for why we might need to appeal to, for

example, sociological and psychological factors in order to explain the history of paradigmatic

shifts. It also occupies a central role in his distinction between “normal” and “revolutionary”

science. Without paradigmatic incommensurability, major changes in scientific knowledge

would simply be “breakthroughs” that progressively improved upon, or discarded, earlier

theories (e.g., Meiland 1974, 182; Sankey 1993, 761; Szumilewicz 1977, 346). But since for

Kuhn different paradigms divide up the phenomenal world differently, there can be no simple

empirical adjudication between them, and in order to account for the history of science we need a

division between moments of “normal science”—empirical work within a paradigm—and

“revolutionary science”—empirical work that establishes a new paradigm (Chernoff 2005, 181).

Forms of Incommensurability

Kuhn initially offered three sources of paradigmatic incommensurability, which Kitcher

(1982, 690) terms “conceptual incommensurability,” “observational incommensurability,” and

“methodological incommensurability” (see also Pearce 1982, 395; Sankey 1993; Sudhakar

1989). The first involves shifts in the linguistic elements of scientific theories, or what some term

meaning variance across theories (Sankey 1991). According to Chen (1990, 67), “two theories

are incommensurable if and only if they are articulated in languages that are not mutually

translatable or communicable without loss.” Such meaning variance, as Farrell (2003, 80) notes,

implies that “there can be no relations of strict deducibility between any two universal theories.”
“Paradigmatic Faults” 6 ISQ, December 2009

This means that, for example, Aristotelian physics cannot be stated in the terminology of

Newtonian physics (Sankey 1993, 762; Szumilewicz 1977, 346).

The second kind of incommensurability results from differing assumptions about the

nature of evidence that counts for the evaluation of theories. Rejecting a paradigm involves, in

consequence, an often profound shift in scientists’ working observational theories. Thus, even if

“protagonists” in an inter-paradigmatic debate “could formulate their rival claims in a common

language, they could not agree on a shared body of observational evidence against which

competing claims are to be judged.” In the absence of such agreement, progress cannot proceed

through a smooth processes of testing and discarding theories (Kitcher 1982, 690).

Finally, paradigms may involve differences over the very methods that comprise

scientific investigation. Galileo’s opponents, for example, rejected many aspects of his claims,

including the early form of the hypothetical-deductive method he used to adjudicate the truth-

status of the Copernican and Ptolemaic models of the solar system (Kuhn 1957). “As a result,”

notes Kichter (1982, 690), “even given a common language for the formulation of rival claims

and a shared body of evidence, reasonable disagreement could still persist” among proponents

working in different paradigms (See also Meiland 1974, 183-184).

Kuhn faced intense criticism for his claims. Many of Kuhn’s critics reacted against the

implication that the history of scientific progress stemmed from irrational and non-rational

factors, particularly socio-psychological ones, and therefore that no “objective” criteria for

resolving inter-paradigm disagreements exist (cf. Chen 1990, 67; Laudan 1976, 596; Meiland

1974, 179, 184-185; Siegel 1976, 442, 448). These criticisms involved a multi-pronged attack on

Kuhn’s understanding of scientific change, as well as on his formulation of incommensurability.

For our purposes, one of the most important arguments centered on the relationship between
“Paradigmatic Faults” 7 ISQ, December 2009

incommensurability and comparability. Many read Kuhn as arguing that incommensurability

rendered paradigms incomparable. His critics contended that paradigms might involve

incommensurable internal standards, but this did not preclude the existence of objective external

standards to judge between them. In other words, incommensurabilities between the internal

criteria of paradigms do not reflect “upward, in criterial differences at the second level.”

(Scheffler 1982, 84; also Shapere 1964).

Kuhn responded that his opponents deployed an overly narrow understanding of

rationality, chose to ignore the complicated history of the rise and fall of scientific theories, and

mischaracterized his views of scientific progress. In fact, Kuhn repeatedly stressed that the

emergence of a new paradigm owes a great deal to the scientific community’s widespread

recognition of its concrete achievements; Kuhn argued that incommensurability did not render

paradigms literally non-comparable (e.g., Kuhn, 1970c, 139, 143-146; Meiland 1974, 182-187;

Sankey 1993, 762; Siegel 1980, 363; Wight 1996, 305). Kuhn also increasingly shifted the focus

of IT toward a more limited claim about meaning variance, sometimes called “local

incommensurability” (e.g., Chen, 1990, 67-68). So “construed, incommensurability is the

limited ability to translate from a local subgroup of terms of one theory into another local

subgroup of terms in another theory. As such, language peripheral to the non-translatable

subgroup of terms constitutes semantic common ground between theories” (Sankey 1991, 771).

Kuhn notes, in this context, that linguistic-taxonomic architecture often changes in the

history of science and that “it is simply implausible that some terms should change their meaning

when transferred to a new theory without inflecting the terms transferred with them.” Thus, local

incommensurabilities still present problems for the deducibility of some scientific theories from

others (Kuhn 1982, 671). He illustrates this point though the example of phlogiston in
“Paradigmatic Faults” 8 ISQ, December 2009

eighteenth-century chemistry. Although it “appears that modern-language phrases… might be

compounded to produce a modern-language translation of ‘phlogiston’…” this is not the case.

Among “the phrases which describe how the referents of the term 'phlogiston' are picked out are

a number that include other untranslatable terms like 'principle' and 'element'. Together with

'phlogiston', they constitute an interrelated or inter-defined set that must be acquired together, as

whole, before any of them can be used, applied to natural phenomena” (Kuhn 1982, 676).

Lakatosian Research Programmes

Some argue that Kuhn and Lakatos embrace “different epistemologies” or

“incompatible…metatheories” (Elman and Elman 2002, 59). Others claim that the two scholars’

practical accounts of scientific progress are indistinguishable from one another (e.g., Barnes

1983, 61-63; Kuhn 1970c; Nadel 1984, 447-448). Lakatos, in fact, “accepts Kuhn’s thesis that, in

the context of ‘normal science’ theories are relatively immune against falsification” but

“concludes that the immunization strategies that Kuhn had claimed for ‘normal science’ are

rational after all.” Lakatos’ MSRP thus seeks to “develop objective criteria for the appraisal of

various research strategies” (Radnitzky 1991, 277-278). As such, Lakatos rejects the claim that

scientific theories cannot be adjudicated via second-order criteria. But he accepts the claim that

scientific theories cannot simply be compared with one another solely on the basis of empirical

evidence. MSRP, then, is an attempt to preserve objective, if retrospective, second-order criteria

for scientific progress in the light of the difficulties Kuhn identified as stemming from

paradigmatic incommensurability (Vasquez 1998, 30).


“Paradigmatic Faults” 9 ISQ, December 2009

The Architecture of MSRP

Lakatos’ research programmes, as most international-relations scholars know, involve

“leading ideas” that constitute their respective “hard cores.” As Larvor (1998, 51) explains, these

represent “a set of commitments which cannot be abandoned without abandoning the research

programme altogether.” Research programmes also contain a “protective belt” of auxiliary

hypothesis that shield the hard core from direct refutation. This protective belt, although subject

to major alterations and reformulations, remains guided by the research programme’s heuristic,

i.e., “a set of problem-solving techniques for scientists engaged in a particular research

programme.” Lakatos, argued that, for example, “the heuristic of Newton’s research programme

chiefly consisted in its mathematical apparatus: the differential calculus, the theory of

convergence and differential and integral equations” (Larvor 1998, 53).

The “negative” heuristic “instruct[s] us to modify auxiliary hypothesis” rather than to

“change the hard core” and to “rule out radically different sorts of explanatory attempts”

(Koertge 1970, 161). The “positive” heuristic functions to protect “the scientists from becoming

confused by the ocean of anomalies.” It lays “out a programme which lists a chain of even more

complicated models simulating reality: the scientist’s attention is riveted on building his models

following instructions which are laid down in the positive part of the programme.” In doing so,

the scientist “ignores the actual counterexamples, the available ‘data’” (Lakatos 1978, 135).

Lakatos’ MSRP framework therefore reformulates the architecture of Kuhn’s SSR (e.g.,

Koertge 1970, 161; Kuhn 1970c; Nadel 1984, 447). Scientific research programmes take the

place of paradigms. “The interplay of the positive and negative heuristic of a research

programme” operate “to account for Kuhn’s commitments and puzzle-solving of the normal

scientists while the concepts of progressive and degenerative problem-shifts” serve “to explain
“Paradigmatic Faults” 10 ISQ, December 2009

paradigm changes as a result of rational decisions rather than with reference to Gestalt

Psychology [emphasis original]” (Kulka 1977, 325-326; also Lakatos 1970b, 175). Working

within a research program remains rational for Lakatos as long as the program as a whole

continues to generate progressive problemshifts, but becomes increasingly risky as these

problemshifts take degenerative forms. After a certain point, scientists abandon the research

program in favor of another one (Elman and Elman 2002; Yuxin 1990).2

Lakatos and ‘Remediable’ Incommensurability

Most proponents of MSRP in International Relations do not consider the identification of

incommensurable, or incommensurable-like, content as a basis for distinguishing between

research programmes (e.g., Elman and Elman 2002; Vasquez 1998). And not without good

reason: Lakatos rejects IT—as he understood it. Lakatos (1970a, 125n37), for example, explicitly

dismisses the “the psychological incommensurability of rival paradigms” on the grounds that

some scientists participated in multiple, but supposedly incommensurate, research programmes.

But, as Lakatos also argues, the empirical “content” of a theory “depends on our

decision as to which are our ‘observational theories’ and which anomalies are to be promoted to

counterexamples [emphasis original].” Indeed, if “one attempts to compare the empirical content

of different scientific theories in order to see which is ‘more scientific’, then one will get

involved in an enormously complex and therefore hopelessly arbitrary system of decisions about

2
Lakatos’ notion of “progress,” as Dessler (2003, 382) notes, fuses “the answers to the

demarcation and rationality questions in a single argument.” It allows us, in principle, to

differentiate science from pseudo-science: a “discipline is scientific so long as progressive

programmes triumph over degenerating ones” (Larvor 1998, 53).


“Paradigmatic Faults” 11 ISQ, December 2009

their respective classes of ‘relatively atomic statements’ and their ‘fields of application.’” “Such

comparison,” he notes, “is possible only when one theory supercedes another…. And even then,

there may be difficulties (which would not, however, add up to irremediable

‘incommensurability’)” (Lakatos 1978, 111n8).

Here we find the crucial role that, in effect, local incommensurabilities play in MSRP and

Lakatos’ delineation of research programmes. First, although research programmes are not

irremediably incommensurable, we cannot adjudicate between specific theories found within two

different research programmes through a straightforward set of experiments (i.e., they remain

comparable via second-order criteria).3 Second, MSRP provides second-order criteria for

rendering the development of science rational and progressive, and therefore resolves the

problems Kuhn identified with paradigmatic incommensurability. Third, such local

incommensurabilities create sufficient difficulties, in fact, that only retrospective judgments by

the scientific community—along the lines of the criteria found in MSRP—allows it to account

for the failure of any given research programme. As Krasner (1985, 143) argues, “Lakatos,

despite his challenge to Kuhn, is not trying to restore the traditional view in which science is

seeking the one real world, sharply distinguishing between theory and observation, and readily

accepting or rejecting hypothesis on the basis of empirical testing.”

Translation problems between theories play an important role in Lakatos’ attempts to

reformulate Popper and provide an objective theory of scientific progress. Lakatos accepts the
3
Compare Lakatos’ solution, which accepts the difficulty of a direct translation between

theories, with Popper’s reassertion of methodological falsification as the solution to the problems

that Kuhn identifies. Also note that Lakatos, like Kuhn, accepts “normal science” as part of the

activity of science properly understood (Koertge 1970, 161), while for Popper Kuhnian “normal

science” remains just bad science.


“Paradigmatic Faults” 12 ISQ, December 2009

lack of a theoretically neutral substratum of “facts” against which two theories could be

measured. Lakatos (1978, 110) “borrows…from conventionalism…the license rationally to

accept by convention not only spatio-temporally singular ‘factual statements’ but also spatio-

temporally universal theories.” He notes that institutional practices, rather than a firm grounding

in some set of empirical facts, arbitrate scientific truth on a day-to-day basis: “Popper’s great

negative crucial experiments”—which were supposed to have falsified theories—“disappear:

‘crucial experiment’ is an honorific title, which may, of course, be conferred on certain

anomalies, but only long after the event, only when one programme has been defeated by another

one” (Lakatos 1978, 111). Discussing the clash between Galilean and Aristotelian conceptions of

the cosmos, Lakatos (1978, 98) points out that “it was not Galileo’s—pure, untheoretical—

observations that confronted Aristotelian theory but rather Galileo’s ‘observations’ in the light of

his optical theory that confronted the Aristotelians’ ‘observations’ in the light of their theory of

the heavens.” There exists an irreducibly “conventional element” in deciding whether a

particular experimental trial falsifies the entirety of a substantive theory (Lakatos 1978, 107).

What Lakatos calls the “hard core” of a research programme, therefore, consists not

merely of substantive claims, but also contains commitments to particular kinds of observational

theory: ideas about how measurement works, how terms are to be defined, and how auxiliary

hypotheses derived from the theory’s hard core are to be evaluated. The genius of the Newtonian

research programme, Lakatos (1978, 133) suggests, came not merely from its substantive

assumptions about motion, but also from its novel way of “doing science,” which involved the

subsumption of empirical anomalies under a simple set of laws. Similarly, Bohr’s production of a

novel account of light emission involved a relaxation of the standard of theoretical consistency in

the short-term so that new phenomena could be predicted (Lakatos, 1978, 141-142).
“Paradigmatic Faults” 13 ISQ, December 2009

It follows that the “hard core” of a research programme contains not merely a list of

variables that adherents believe to be relevant to their explanations and a set of favored

techniques for gathering and evaluating empirical data, but also epistemological and ontological

differences that preclude naïve falsificationism or other non-MSRP standards of inter-theoretical

adjudication. This produces, not irremediable incommensurability of the sort associated with

Kuhn, but rather something we might refer to as “remediable incommensurability”—that is, a

translation problem that can be worked around without recourse to the imagery of fundamental

discontinuity that incensed so many of Kuhn’s harshest critics.

This also explains why, for Lakatos, judgments about the progressive or degenerating

character of a particular problemshift are retrospective. Some interpreters of Lakatos argue that

the notion of progressive problemshifts between and within research programs “can be used to

advise scholars on how to respond to degeneration” (Elman and Elman 1997, 925). But Lakatos

(1978, 117) criticizes Kuhn (and others) for “conflat[ing] methodological appraisal of a

programme with firm heuristic advice about what to do [emphasis original].” Lakatos

distinguishes between the “internal” and the “external” history of a research programme, arguing

that “normative reconstructions” that provide an internal history “may have to be supplemented

by empirical external theories to explain the residual non-rational factors.”

The history of science is always richer than its rational reconstruction.…

External history either provides non-rational explanation of the speed,

locality, selectiveness, etc. of historic events as interpreted in terms of

internal history; or, when history differs from its rational reconstruction, it

provides an empirical explanation of why it differs. But the rational aspect


“Paradigmatic Faults” 14 ISQ, December 2009

of scientific growth is fully accounted for by one’s logic of scientific

discovery (Lakatos, 1978, 118).

The rational reconstruction of a research programme—as well as its historical twists and

turns—can only be comprehended in hindsight. Only after the scientific community makes a

practical determination about the importance of a particular experiment or controversy can we

make judgments about whether their resolution amounted to progress or degeneration. We

cannot make such a determination in advance, because the answer depends on which research

programme’s terminology and concepts are used to make sense of the controversial issue. As

Lakatos (1978, 113) argues, one “can be ‘wise’ only after the event.”

The contents of a research programme, moreover, may not be identical with any of its

practitioners’ specifications of the research programme: “Prout never articulated the ‘Proutian

programme’: the Proutian programme is not Prout’s programme” (Lakatos, 1978, 119). Rather, a

research programme constitutes, in effect, an ideal-typical specification of how a series of

theories relate to one another; its utility is in the evaluation of that series, not in directing the

series as it evolves. We cannot easily know whether a problemshift was progressive or not until

we see the whole series of subsequent research projects that arose from it. Viewed prospectively,

science is a good deal messier than the abstract series that the philosopher derives from it. As

Lakatos (1978, 131) argues, “no set of human judgments is completely rational… no rational

reconstruction can ever coincide with actual history.” Hence Lakatos’ approach is best suited for

a retrospective, and (Popperian) third-world, account of the progress of research programmes

(Barnes 1983, 61-62).


“Paradigmatic Faults” 15 ISQ, December 2009

(Mis)applications to International-Relations Theory

Our discussion of Kuhnian paradigms and Lakatosian research programmes supports the

two claims we advanced at the outset. Both scholars seek to make sense of the history of the

natural sciences, particularly with respect to how that history confounds earlier universal theories

of scientific progress. Thus, both argue about the specifics of the differences between, for

example, classical physics and quantum mechanics, phlogiston theory and modern chemistry,

and those separating Galileo from his critics. Both Kuhn and Lakatos ultimately appeal to the

judgment of scientific community concerning the existence of concrete, well-recognized

advances in scientific thought.4 We should, therefore, exercise caution when it comes to applying

their accounts of scientific progress to the field of International Relations. We should be

particularly reticent to apply them to contemporaneous theories in the field, as we lack the luxury

of retrospective reconstruction when assessing such putative “paradigms” and “research

programmes.”

But if we still desire to apply Kuhnian or Lakatosian metrics for theory choice, then we

must demonstrate that the theoretical aggregates we classify as “paradigms” or “research

programmes” qualify as such. We need to identify internal incommensurabilities that

differentiate them from other theoretical aggregates in the field and that require recourse to

second-order criteria of theory choice (cf. Vasquez 1998, 187-188). We next turn to a discussion

a number of putative paradigms and research programmes to demonstrate that many of them lack

such local incommensurabilities. But before doing so, we should note two considerations that
4
On this point, Radnitzky (1991, 277-278) notes that “Lakatos falls back on appraisals contained

in the 'normative basic judgments' of 'the scientific elite'. This again leads to a circle: in order to

determine who should belong to 'the scientific elite', we need objective criteria for appraising

past achievement.” See also Farrell (2003, 60-64).


“Paradigmatic Faults” 16 ISQ, December 2009

further caution against deploying Kuhnian and Lakatosian accounts to make sense of the

divisions in our field.

On the one hand, recall that Kuhn largely dropped observational and methodological

incommensurability from his analysis. He “restricted incommensurability to semantic

differences,” i.e., the problem of meaning variance, and focused on the existence of “translation

failure between a localized cluster of interdefined terms within the language of theories” (Sankey

1993, 760). In Kuhn’s later reformulations, he abandoned much of the architecture of SSR

entirely and instead reconceptualized scientific revolutions in terms of the speciation of

disciplines and subdisciplines within the natural sciences (Kuhn 1990).5 This retreat raises doubts

about, at the very least, appeals to such differences (insofar as they are independent from

meaning variance, rather than follow from it) as a basis for identifying paradigms or, in

Lakatosian terms, the need to invoke MSRP to assess theoretical aggregates distinguished by

them.

On the other hand, we agree that some of the practices in our field track with those

identified by Lakatos and Kuhn. Advocates of so-called “research programmes” and

“paradigms” resist abandoning the assumptions associated with theoretical aggregates. They

doggedly insist on the relevance of their approaches while discounting the analysis and evidence

offered by rival scholars. They tend to ignore some phenomena in favor of others. 6 But these

parallels represent, in our view, insufficient warrants for adopting Kuhnian and Lakatosian

frameworks.
5
Adaptations of this later argument to international-relations scholarship might actually prove

interesting, but this is a topic beyond the scope of our analysis.


6
Vasquez (1998) documents this behavior quite well in his seminal work on realism and

paradigmism, but we disagree that it provides a warrant for calling realism a paradigm.
“Paradigmatic Faults” 17 ISQ, December 2009

First, at least some of this behavior may stem from contamination effects. Political

scientists have been using SSR to make sense of divisions in the field since the 1960s, and have

appealed to Lakatos since the 1970s. It would be surprising, in fact, if our constant invocations of

Kuhnian and Lakatosian language failed to influence our scholarly practices.

Second, we can, in principle, explain this behavior through any number of disciplinary

and individual incentives, as well as through other sociological factors. The development of

intellectual cliques, the status that comes with staking out a new framework for understanding

world politics, and a reluctance to abandon modes of thought need not be explained by invoking

“paradigms” or “research programmes” with all their attendant epistemological and ontological

baggage.7

Third, our practices also depart, and in very significant ways, from that of scholars

genuinely operating in “paradigms” or “research programmes.” We frequently construct “two-”

and “three-cornered” tests of the “isms” utilizing common first-order criteria of theory choice.

Some supposed “research programmes,” such as inquiry into the democratic peace, are

comprised of participants from multiple “paradigms” without any serious difficulties of

translation. And scholars seem relatively unmoved by accusations that their research

programmes are degenerative, which, at the very least, lends support to the proposition that

Lakatosian metrics are best suited to rational reconstructions of our disciplinary history.

7
In this light, we might be interested in the pragmatic question of when, and why, scholars

invoke claims about incommensurability. Such claims may serve a number of strategic and

disciplinary interests irrespective of whether or not they involve genuine examples of

incommensurability. See Biagioli’s (1993, 211-244) discussion of “the anthropology of

incommensurability.”
“Paradigmatic Faults” 18 ISQ, December 2009

In sum, absent the identification of the scope conditions for treating an international-

relations theoretical aggregate as a “paradigm” or “research programme”—the identification of

shared local incommensurabilities vis-à-vis some other theoretical aggregate—our practices

provide insufficient grounds for invoking Kuhn or Lakatos to make sense of many relevant

divisions in the field, let alone to assess the comparative merits of such theoretical aggregates

through a recourse to MSRP.

Putative “Paradigms” and “Research Programmes”

International-relations scholars, as we have noted, often describe inquiry into “the

democratic peace,” the study of “security communities,” and “power-transition theory” as

research programmes. If each of these were distinct research programmes, we would expect them

to be differentiated from one another by incommensurable-like content of the conceptual,

observational, or methodological kind in their hard cores. But we find scholars working on, for

example, the democratic peace and power-transition theory deploying the same kind of statistical

methodology and even using the same data sets in their analysis. Their conceptual apparatuses

are commensurable and comparable. One tradition simply claims that democracies are unlikely

to go to war with one another, the other that great-power wars tend to happen during periods of

power transitions. These both present straightforward empirical propositions—in fact,

propositions that need not even contradict one another.

DiCiccio and Levy (1999, 678), for example, use Lakatosian metrics to analyze power-

transition theory. They note that incommensurability does present a problem for comparing two

research programmes, but that they use MSRP for “the purpose of evaluating the development

and progressiveness of a single research programme.” And this is correct, insofar as meaning
“Paradigmatic Faults” 19 ISQ, December 2009

variance presents a problem for any strict reliance on “content increase” as a basis for

determining whether one theory has superceded another (Farrell, 2003, 86-87). But it sidesteps

the crucial issue: which “set of common hard-core assumptions” of power-transition theory

(DiCicco and Levy 1999, 678) render it so theory-laden vis-à-vis other research programmes as

to force us to resort to MSRP as a method for evaluating its internal progress? Their list contains

entirely empirical propositions, such as “the international order is hierarchically organized under

the leadership of a dominant power” (DiCicco and Levy, 1999: 678). None of these reflect the

kind of differences among scientific theories that concern Kuhn and Lakatos; the translation

problems with which Kuhn and Lakatos are grappling are far more serious and severe than the

technical difficulties presented “because different theories have different dependent variables”

(Krasner 1985, 138).

Similarly, scholars sometimes invoke the “democratic peace” as an example of a

Lakatosian research programme (Ray 2003). But the lack of war between democracies is merely

an empirical proposition, and has very little in common with, for example, Prout’s contention

that the atomic weights of pure chemical elements are whole numbers or with Planck’s

calculation of an indivisible unit of action at the subatomic level, i.e., the Planck constant. The

latter both involve contentions about how to do science—about what kinds of evidence “count”

for or against a theory—in a way that the notion of a democratic peace simply does not. It

therefore makes little philosophical sense to speak of a “democratic peace research programme,”

and given the absence of any significant translation problems when trying to compare a

proposition positing a democratic peace with a proposition that does not, the appeal to Lakatos

seems misplaced.
“Paradigmatic Faults” 20 ISQ, December 2009

The same could be said, we argue, of many putative “research programmes” in the field.

Consider Vasquez’s (1997, 903) attempt to delineate a “research programme” on balance-of-

power theory. The “hard core” of the research programme? The proposition that states balance

rather than bandwagon under conditions of anarchy. But this should not be regarded as a “hard

core” assumption any more than “objects fall to the ground when dropped” should be regarded as

a “hard core” assumption of the Newtonian research programme. Rather, both empirical

statements comprise auxiliary hypotheses derived from “hard cores” having to do with the nature

of empirical inquiry and the specific character of the phenomena under investigation.

“Balancing”—like “falling”—is a consequence of the application of broader assumptions, not an

assumption itself (Elman and Elman 1997, 925). There is no need to invoke second-order criteria

to resolve the dispute about whether international systems tend towards balanced power over

time.

The “isms”

Consider three other putative “hard core” assumptions often thought to generate local

incommensurabilities between the “isms”—realism, liberalism, constructivism, Marxism, etc.—

and therefore requiring us to evaluate these theoretical aggregates as cohesive units vis-à-vis one

another, and to utilize second-order criteria in order to do so. These assumptions include claims

about the primary actors in world politics, about the decision-making logic followed by

individual people, and about the malleability of social reality.

Primary actors. On one side of this issue stand the state-centrists who argue that the legal

structure of sovereignty and the concentration of destructive capacity in the hands of state

governments mean that states remain the most important actors on the world stage at the present
“Paradigmatic Faults” 21 ISQ, December 2009

time. This position is usually associated with realism (Forde 1995, 144; Harvey 1999, 866; Waltz

1979, 158-159), but state-centrism can also be found in neoliberal-institutional theory (Baldwin

1993; Lake 1996) and some variants of constructivism (Wendt 1992, 424; Wendt 1999). On the

other side stand those scholars whose work departs from a different set of assumptions: the

primacy of individuals and private social groups (Moravcsik 1997, 516-517), the influence of

international organizations (Finnemore 1996) and transnational social movements (Keck and

Sikkink 1998), and the importance of firms and other economic actors (Keohane and Milner

1996).

But claims such as “states are the primary actors in world politics” (Keohane and Martin

2003, 73) and that “the fundamental actors in international politics are rational individuals and

private groups” (Moravcsik 1997, 161) contain no special philosophical content of the kind

associated with any of Kuhn’s three forms of incommensurability—at least so long as “primary

actors” and “fundamental actors” are defined in an empirically testable way. Doing so would

simply require a precise operational definition of “primary actor” so that we could gather the

appropriate data (Vasquez 1998, 188).

Decision-making logics. Scholars sometimes treat the distinction between “logics of

consequences” and “logics of appropriateness” as the fundamental dividing line between

“rationalists” and “constructivists” (Katzenstein, Keohane, and Krasner 1998, 679-680; Krasner

1999). Rationalists, particularly in the rational-choice camp, adopt models of decision-making

that stress logics of consequence: they hold that “most social action can be explained by goal-

oriented action on the part of actors… as opposed being motivated by habit, tradition, or social

appropriateness” (MacDonald 2003, 553). Constructivists, for their part, stress logics of
“Paradigmatic Faults” 22 ISQ, December 2009

appropriateness: they view social action as governed by the rules, roles, and norms in which an

agent is embedded (e.g., Sending 2002).

At the same time, most constructivists who focus on this distinction also argue that it

does not sharply differentiate constructivists from rationalists. Thomas Risse (2000, 3), for

example, argues that while constructivism and rationalism are “metatheoretical orientations,”

their main point of disagreement is “how far one can push one logic of action to account for

observable practices and which logic dominates a given situation.” Similarly, James March and

Johan Olsen (1998, 952) write that “any particular action probably involves elements” of both

logics; in principle, one ought to be able to investigate the interaction between the two subsets of

voluntaristic decision-making.

Not only do we confront no translation problems, but we are looking at the same

linguistic-taxonomic architecture: the “logic of consequences” and the “logic of

appropriateness”, at least as conceptualized in this debate, 8 comprise partial specifications of a

single approach to the explanation of social action: as rooted in the subjective beliefs of

individuals, whether those beliefs stem from institutionalized norms or economic preferences.

The ontology of social life. Many argue that constructivists embrace a distinctive

ontology then scholars associated with other “paradigms.” Constructivists view international

politics through the prism of the “mutual constitution” of agents and structures, the

intersubjective character of both, and of the significance of social facts. Theorists often contrast

these ontological commitments with, for instance, realism’s putative denial of agent-structure

mutual constitution, its materialist ontology, and its conflation of social facts with objective

conditions (e.g., Dessler 1989; Wendt 1992).


8
As we argue below, social-choice theory may comprise a research programme due to the way it

embeds “logics of consequences” in a broader context of inquiry.


“Paradigmatic Faults” 23 ISQ, December 2009

Many realists, however, accept the ontological co-constitution of agents and structures

but disagree with constructivists about how to cash this out analytically. Realists claims about

the causal priority of military power does not, in fact, imply a rigidly materialist ontology. And,

for many realists, anarchy amounts to a social fact. Realists often differ with constructivists,

rather, over both the plasticity of anarchical structures and whether anarchical environments

produce similar dynamics across time and space (e.g., Goddard and Nexon 2005; Sterling-Folker

2002).

Indeed, constructivism, at its heart, involves the claim that some phenomenon “X need

not have existed, or need not be at all as it is. X, or X as it is at present, is not determined by the

nature of things; it is not inevitable” (Hacking 1999, 6). With respect to any particular

international-political phenomena—German foreign policy, sovereignty, the ban of landmines,

the inevitability of certain consequences associated with anarchy—constructivist arguments

therefore amount to empirical wagers (e.g., Banchoff 1999; Price 1998). Most international-

relations theories involve some level of commitment to the social construction of world politics.

Almost no theorist believes that significant international political outcomes reflect the inevitable

consequence of the “nature of things”—such as the laws of physics or genetic determinism—

rather than the result of historical and agentic contingency (Guzzini 2000). Constructivist claims

concern the degree of social and historical contingency vis-à-vis specific arguments advanced in

the other “paradigms.” In this sense, although characterized by quite significant disagreements,

many constructivist and realist theories are commensurable and comparable.


“Paradigmatic Faults” 24 ISQ, December 2009

Better Candidates

There are, however, better candidates for differentiating between approaches in ways that

produce local incommensurabilities. Robert Cox’s (1996) distinction between “problem-solving”

and “critical” approaches to the study of world politics—and, implicitly, between two different

kinds of knowledge about world politics that one might produce—represents something close to

a genuinely paradigmatic division. Similarly, distinctions between “scientific” and

“traditionalist” approaches to the production of knowledge (Kratochwil 2006; Vasquez 1998, 39-

41) generate sufficiently robust gaps between perspectives that something like MSRP might be

called for. The package of assumptions associated with rational choice theory also looks almost

paradigmatic, since it is not merely a substantive assumption about how people make decisions

but a comprehensive approach to investigating social life featuring such notions as “off-the-path-

equilibria” and a commitment to reconciling observed behavior with a presumption of rationality

(Hardin 1995; MacDonald 2003).

Notice, however, three things about these candidates. First of all, many of their disputes

revolve around epistemological questions about “how to do science” rather than centering on

substantive concerns.9 While this makes them better candidates for classification as paradigms or

research programmes, it takes them further away from the empirical content of most of the actual

scholarship in the field: few if any of us spend much of our time doing work designed to advance

the epistemological projects of “problem-solving theory” or “traditionalism,” and these divisions


9
It is important to regard these as debates about how to do “science,” and not simply regard any

particular intervention as an unproblematic application of the “principles of philosophy of

science” (Vasquez 1993, 43) to the subject-matter of world politics. It is precisely the character

and meaning of “social science” that is at issue in the distinctions that rise to the level of a local

incommensurabilities in international-relations theory.


“Paradigmatic Faults” 25 ISQ, December 2009

only inform our substantive work obliquely. Second, they cut across our putative paradigms and

research programmes: it is easy to find adherents of each of these approaches in any of the

“isms,” to say nothing of the schools of thought revolving around specific empirical puzzles.

There are rational-choice and non-rational-choice realists and liberals (Walt 1999); likewise,

there are problem-solving and critical-theoretic constructivists (Price and Reus-Smit 1998).

Finally, the terms of these distinctions and debates go well beyond those investigated by

Kuhn and Lakatos. For all the seriousness and importance of the distinctions between the various

paradigms and research programmes disclosed by Kuhn and Lakatos, they could implicitly rely

on the notion that all of the natural scientists whose work they discussed were united in an

overarching goal: to increase knowledge of a world presumptively independent of their

awareness of it (Jackson 2008). But the debates within international-relations theory that come

closest to being paradigmatic in character often revolve around precisely this presumption,

raising further doubts about the utility of Kuhnian or Lakatosian assumptions for the evaluation

and adjudication of debates in the field.

The Costs of Misapplication

The terminology of “paradigms” and “research programmes” produces a number of

deleterious effects in the field. It implies that we need to appeal to criteria of the kind found in

MSRP in order to adjudicate disputes that require no such procedures. In order to do so, we

spend a great deal of time specifying the “boundaries” of putative research programmes and, in
“Paradigmatic Faults” 26 ISQ, December 2009

effect, unfairly and misleadingly holding scholars accountable for the status of theories they

often view as rivals to their own.10

Perhaps the most well-known instance of this kind of boundary-demarcation occurs in the

debates surrounding “realism” in international-relations theory. The proliferation of countless

lists of the “core commitments” of a realist “paradigm”—by adherents and critics alike—shifts

the focus of scholarship away from any actual investigation of whether these commitments give

us meaningful leverage on the phenomenal world, and instead promotes endless border

skirmishes about who is and is not a realist (Legro and Moravcsik 1999), whether predictions of

balancing are central to the “realist paradigm” (Vasquez 1998, 261-265), and so forth. Such

debates and demarcations not only distract us from the actual study of world politics, but also

harm disputes over international-relations theory by solidifying stances that ought to remain open

to debate and discussion.

Besides the general problems associated with any attempt to delineate the principles of a

paradigm or research programme contemporaneously rather than retrospectively, a further issue

crops up in the misapplication of Kuhnian and Lakatosian language to debates in the field: the

conflation of specific causal factors and mechanisms with a particular, presumptively


10
Thus, for example, Vasquez (2003, 108) criticizes the realist “paradigm” for being at risk of

becoming “so broad and” containing “so many contradictory predictions” that it “becomes

impossible to falsify.” He then argues that “a critique of balancing cannot logically imply that

other parts of the realist and neorealist research agendas are degenerating or inadequate. These

other research programmes must be appraised separately and by the criteria most appropriate

them.” But one does not falsify a paradigm, one falsifies a specific hypothesis. And if various

realist “research traditions” comprise different units of analysis for the purposes of MSRP, then

realism writ large itself cannot plausibly be described as a paradigm or research programme.
“Paradigmatic Faults” 27 ISQ, December 2009

autonomous, school of thought about world politics. Hence “balancing” and “threatening to use

force” become markers of a realist approach, while discussion of markets and profit are

sometimes annexed to (neo)liberalism.

But there is nothing inherently realist about a mechanism like “balancing,” which, as

recent scholarship demonstrates, self-identified realists actually borrowed from republican and

liberal thought (Boucoyannis 2007; Deudney 2006). One need not, moreover, be a liberal to

acknowledge that actors sometimes reach Pareto-improving compromises, and one need not be a

constructivist to take public diplomacy or symbolic language seriously. Indeed, it is only because

of the politics of knowledge in the discipline—a politics supported by the misuse of Kuhnian and

Lakatosian terminology—that we argue over whether scholars have violated their supposedly all-

important allegiance to their theoretical aggregates if they combine variables and mechanisms

associated with different schools of thought. It is one thing to insist on logical and analytical

coherence, or to identify and label intellectual communities in the field, but another entirely to

approach international-relations scholarship as a form of identity politics.

From Paradigms to Ideal Types

Some may read our earlier arguments as a call for dispensing with theoretical aggregates

entirely. But we believe that rejecting the language of Kuhnian paradigms and Lakatosian

research programmes does not require an abandonment of organizing the discipline into “schools

of thought” or other aggregates. International Relations remains an “eclectic discipline”

encompassing a variety of different methods, methodologies, and areas of study (Katzenstein,

Keohane, and Krasner 1998, 646).


“Paradigmatic Faults” 28 ISQ, December 2009

Maps of the intellectual contours of a scholarly discipline serve several functions, not the

least of which is that they enable scholars to situate themselves and their work vis-à-vis

important conceptual disagreements and theoretical debates (Abbott 2001, 10-14). Casting the

field in terms of major contending approaches allows individual scholars to discuss their findings

with respect to broadly common questions of concern. It also serves important pedagogical

functions. For better or worse, it is difficult to make sense of the last few decades of

international-relations scholarship without teaching the “isms.”

International-relations scholarship needs such common questions, we submit, for two

reasons. First, the parameters of the field are enormous, and only likely to grow. Second,

growing methodological diversity constantly threatens to fragment the field. Thus, if we are to

have what Yosef Lapid (2003) calls “engaged pluralism,” we need some common points of

contention.11 In this respects, one of the chief virtues of dividing the field into camps such as

“realism,” “liberalism,” and “constructivism” is that it focuses us on “big questions” about

international-political processes, such as the relative importance of traditional power politics in

international relations. These kinds of issues are substantive; they are amenable to many different

tools of social-scientific inquiry.

11
We agree that pluralism is not an intrinsic good, i.e., that it is not a license for “anything goes”

and “indiscriminate tolerance.” Yet the existence of disciplinary pluralism, combined with a

recognition that all knowledge is inflected by theoretical perspectives, explains the attractiveness

of “paradigm” and “research programme” language. See Kratochwil (2003, 126).


“Paradigmatic Faults” 29 ISQ, December 2009

Ideal Typification of Disciplinary Debates

For inspiration and guidance we turn to the remarkable methodological essay that Max

Weber (1999) wrote a in which he confronted a situation not unlike the one facing the field of

international relations at present: a diversity of objects of inquiry, and a diversity of analytical

approaches to those objects. Under such conditions, was it even possible advocate for the

specificity of social-scientific knowledge? Was there any difference between social-scientific

scholarship and the anything-goes anarchy of pure perspectivism? Weber strongly believed that

there was such a difference, and articulated a multifaceted solution designed to both preserve

diversity and rigor (Ringer 2004, 77-79).

The most relevant portion of Weber’s discussion for our purposes is the notion of the

“ideal-type.” Every scholarly presentation of empirical facts, Weber (1999, 170) argues, depends

on “special and ‘one-sided’ points of view, according to which—explicitly or tacitly, consciously

or unconsciously—they are selected, analyzed, and representationally organized as an object of

research.” Scholars operate with ideal-typical constructs, rather than with presuppositionless

descriptions. Researchers construct ideal types in order to create an idealization of a

phenomenon’s characteristics that can then be compared against other, related ideal typifications.

Ideal types will never accurately or exhaustively describe the concrete manifestations of a

specific phenomenon, but they do provide benchmarks for the comparison of real phenomena.

Ideal-typical maps, in other words, consist of asymptotic limits within which actual

phenomena reside. A political entity, institution, or other entity can occupy any point in the field

defined by ideal types. A concrete empirical object never occupies the ideal-typical position

itself, but the properties, dynamics, and relation to other objects can be parsed with reference to

how an object combines or depart from aspects of relevant ideal types. Although Weber himself
“Paradigmatic Faults” 30 ISQ, December 2009

used ideal-typification as a procedure for interrogating social and cultural relations, there is no

reason why it cannot be applied to the orientations of disciplines themselves. Scholars regularly

treat the field itself as an object of empirical investigation. They assess the rise and fall of

approaches to international politics; the relative influence of journals, departments, and scholars;

trends in pedagogy; and so forth. In doing so, they make use of all sorts of typologies—whether

ideal-typical or categorical in nature—many of which involve “realism,” liberalism,”

“constructivism,” and other camps within the field.

An ideal-typical approach to the field would flesh out implicit organizing principles of

existing scholarly debates by distilling them to their essential characteristics. Ideal-typical maps

of the field never describe debates and controversies as “they really are,” but instead utilize a

relatively spare set of concepts to locate actual debates and controversies with respect to the

organizing principles tacitly contained within those debates and controversies. These organizing

principles are not ontologically and epistemologically exclusive of one another; rather, they are

more like wagers about how the world is put together—wagers that can give rise to different

sorts of empirical investigations, including ones driven by differing conceptual, observational,

and methodological orientations. The empirical challenge is to disclose a set of wagers animating

debates in the field; we generate these principles though a process of self-consciously

teleological reasoning, starting with existing schools and approaches and then pressing their

logic as far as possible in order to reach an purified, abstracted version of the approach.

Realism, Liberalism, and Constructivism Reconsidered

We focus on ideal-typifying the relationship between realism, liberalism, and

constructivism for the simple reason that these camps currently predominate in mainstream
“Paradigmatic Faults” 31 ISQ, December 2009

discussions of the field in the United States (Peterson, Tierney, and Maliniak 2005). We also

believe that, properly understood, these positions capture a great deal of surplus argument in

contemporary debates stretching beyond American shores, but that is something best resolved

through further evaluation. Our basic argument is this: “realism,” “liberalism,” and

“constructivism” can be recast as ideal-typical positions on two debates of long-standing

significance to the study of world politics: first, the degree to which anarchy operates as a fixed

constraints upon actors; and second, the degree to which power politics can be transcended in

political interactions (see Figure 1). Understood in this way, the camps cease to be concrete

containers for theorists and theories; they represent wagers about world politics towards which

particular pieces of empirical research can be oriented.


“Paradigmatic Faults” 32 ISQ, December 2009

Figure 1: Ideal-Typical Positions in the Field of International Relations

Many consider specific answers to these questions to be among the core claims of realism

(e.g., Schweller and Wohlforth 2000, 60). However, the two dimensions are usually collapsed in

practice, since structural realists (and many so-called “neo-classical realists”) consider anarchy to

be the primary reason, or at least one of the major reasons, why power cannot be transcended in

international politics. Disaggregating them helps make sense of the different wagers associated

with, for instance, neorealism and neoliberalism. It also elucidates emerging terms of debate

between positions a growing number of scholars identify as “realist” constructivism and “liberal”

constructivism (e.g., Barkin 2003). Finally, it does so without requiring that any particular study

or argument falls within a self-contained paradigm or research tradition.

Anarchy as parametric constraint

The concept of anarchy—the absence of a common authority to make and enforce rules

—has long been central to the discipline of international relations. One can plausibly trace the

development of “international theory” in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries to attempts to

understand what differentiates relations between sovereigns from relations within states; one of

the most enduring solutions has been to associate the former with the “state of nature” that exists

in the absence of a sovereign authority (Hobbes [1651] 1951; Locke 1960; Tuck 1999). The

assumption that anarchy leads to different forms of interaction than those found in other political

contexts provides the central justification for international relations as a distinctive discipline

(Schmidt 1998).
“Paradigmatic Faults” 33 ISQ, December 2009

The claim that anarchy operates as a necessary constraint on actors in international

politics is most closely associated with realism (e.g., Snyder 2002). Waltz (1979) forcefully

articulates this position: that anarchy has a spare set of inexorable consequences for patterns of

relations in the international system: self-help, sensitivity to relative power, the lack of a robust

division of labor between actors, and the formation of recurrent balancing equilibria. Many of the

major disagreements within contemporary realism hinge on what the precise implications of

anarchy are for state-level and systemic outcomes. Defensive realists argue that anarchy inclines

states to privilege security over other considerations, offensive realists argue that anarchy

inclines states to maximize power and hegemonic-order theorists see recurrent concentrations of

power as the normal condition of anarchical orders (e.g., Gilpin 1981; Mearsheimer 2001) Some

realists also argue that domestic politics and state interests lead to greater variation in

international outcomes than many structural realists do, but they agree that anarchy strongly

conditions the range of state behavior. States that ignore the implications of anarchy do so at

their peril (Rose 1998).

None of these realists, of course, hold that anarchy overdetermines unit behavior. Even

structurally-inclined offensive realists, for example, adopt positions somewhere short of the

northern limit. Thus, many forms of contemporary liberalism also operate in the same general

domain. Neoliberal institutionalists, for example, also agree that anarchy is a relatively fixed

constraint with crucial consequences for state interaction. However, they contend that the range

of possible patterns of behavior under anarchy includes far more forms of cooperation than

realists suppose, and that such cooperation is more durable than realists admit (e.g., Baldwin

1993, 4-5). As Moravcsik (1997, 536) argues, neoliberal “institutionalism takes state preferences
“Paradigmatic Faults” 34 ISQ, December 2009

as fixed or exogenous, seeks to explain state policy as a function of variation in the geopolitical

environment…and focuses on the ways in which anarchy leads to suboptimal outcomes.”

Those with a more constructivist orientation towards anarchy, however, view it rather

differently. Some argue that anarchy is an “empty structure.” In Wendt’s (1992) phrase, “anarchy

is what states make of it”: structural variations in the culture of anarchy give rise to different

logics and dynamics. Others disagree with the proposition that anarchy is, or ought to be treated

as if it were, fixed. Anarchy describes a particular, but not necessary, social formation that can be

transformed through norms, rules, and processes of agent-structure co-constitution. Indeed, some

kind of orientation towards this position cuts across most forms of constructivist scholarship,

whether critical, post-structural, or mainstream (e.g., Dessler 1989; Onuf 1989).

The status of anarchy as a focal point for ideal-typical disputes in the field follows from

an examination of disciplinary practice—for example, a lot of what realists and constructivists

argue concerns the degree to which anarchy is a fixed constraint. It also follows from an exercise

of ideal-typical reasoning. As we argued above, all (or, at least, most) political phenomena are, in

a trivial sense, “socially constructed.” At one extreme lies the claim that anarchy produces a

certain logic approximating a natural necessity. At the other, the denial that there is anything

natural or necessary about claims associated with anarchy.

Power and its transcendence

The second “big question” in the study of international relations concerns the degree to

which power can be transcended, or tamed, in world politics. The dispute about whether or not

power can be overcome in international relations was the primary marker of the so-called “first
“Paradigmatic Faults” 35 ISQ, December 2009

debate,” and can be traced back at least to Machiavelli’s (1994) criticism of Christian ethical

interpretations of political processes

Realists adopt a relatively straightforward position on this point: power is the ultima

ratio of international relations. Attempts to limit the importance of power and capabilities in

world politics through law, institutions, or regimes may very well prove counterproductive to

state interests and the goal of generally peaceful interstate relations. To the extent that regimes,

law, and institutions are controlling in international politics, that is because they are sustained

and enforced by hegemons or a temporary confluence of interests among powerful states (e.g.,

Krasner 1999).

Liberals, for their part, argue that it is possible to establish international cooperation,

institutions, and regimes that limit the salience of power in world politics (e.g., Keohane 2001;

Moravcsik 1998). Indeed, one of the core wagers of philosophical liberalism is that the proper

design of governing institutions, whether domestically or internationally, can restrict arbitrary

power such that actors are free to pursue their interests and values (see, e.g., Johnston 1994).

No actual self-described “realist” or “liberal” (at least whom we are aware of) actually

believes that power is the only thing that matters or that power can ever be eliminated from

international politics, respectively. These represent, again, ideal-typical positions towards which

the two “camps” orient themselves in their debates. The top position is “realist” because it

combines the wager that power cannot be tamed with the wager that anarchy operates as a fixed

constraint on actors. The right-hand position is “liberal” because it combines the wager that

power can be transcended with wagers about inescapable consequences of politics in the “state of

nature.” In this ideal-typical view, anarchy can be overcome through a process of creating more

robust international institutions, but either only from within the constraints it imposes in the first
“Paradigmatic Faults” 36 ISQ, December 2009

place or through transformation away from anarchy through various forms of interdependency

(e.g., Keohane and Nye 1989; Moravcsik 1997).

This axis maps onto contemporary constructivism in rather interesting ways. It creates a

lower corner we call “liberal-constructivist” and a left-hand corner we call “realist-

constructivist.” The ideal-typical liberal-constructivist wager is that the right distribution of

norms, identities, discourses, and rules can limit the importance of power politics. The ideal-

typical realist-constructivist wager, in contrast, is that the lack of determinate consequences

associated with anarchy does not limit the importance of power politics, because power itself is

productive or generative of social and political relations (Barnett and Duvall 2005). As we slide

“northwest” from the liberal-constructivist intersection we might also find claims that anarchy

lacks determinative effects, but that particular configurations of anarchy are insufficiently plastic

to allow actors to easily reduce the salience of power politics—a skepticism towards

emancipatory projects similar to that found within the English-School tradition (cf. Dunne 1998).

Indeed, whether in the form of Onuf’s emphasis on how agents make rules in order to

govern themselves, or Adler’s arguments about how “cognitive evolution” can produce a more

just and equitable world order, or in Keck and Sikkink’s discussion of how transnational social

movements can “civilize” world politics by enforcing human rights norms against recalcitrant

state leaders, one can find a liberal (or “progressive”) orientation towards the question of power

politics (Adler 1997; Keck and Sikkink 1998; Onuf 1989). In an early programmatic statement,

Wendt (1992) called for an alliance between “strong liberals” and constructivists on the precise

grounds of their shared rejection of the realist argument that self-help behavior was inevitable.

Other-regarding behavior can pave the way for a different way of behaving in inter-state
“Paradigmatic Faults” 37 ISQ, December 2009

relations, effectively transcending power and coercion in favor of something more cooperative

(Wendt 1999, 359-360).

An increasingly liberal-constructivist position highlights how the diffusion of the right

norms and identities can orient states away from power-political concerns (Checkel 1998; Flynn

and Farrell 1999; Tannenwald 1999). It focuses on the ability of principled transnational

movements and interest groups to produce normative environments that privilege values over

power. The recent turn towards Jürgen Habermas’ notion of communicative rationality is

consistent with the liberal-constructivist impulse; it holds that, to the degree that contextual

factors (such as institutional design) approximate Habermas’ “ideal speech condition,” coercive

power can be displaced from interactions in world politics (e.g., Risse 2000).

None of the authors cited in the preceding paragraph would argue that power, and power

politics in particular, can ever be completely banished from international relations. Yet within

constructivism we find disagreement about the relative “pull” of the two ideal-typical poles.

Constructivists agree on the historical and social contingency of social facts and international-

political outcomes, but they come to different conclusions over the implications of this

contingency for the plasticity of power politics. A significant part of the disagreement between,

on the one hand, “post-structural” and “critical” constructivists and, on the other, “modernist” or

“liberal” constructivists turns on precisely this point (e.g., Bially Mattern 2004; Price and Reus-

Smit 1998). But an exclusive focus on the intra-constructivist dimension of this debate obscures

how it situates many self-identified constructivists in a similar domain to self-identified realists.


“Paradigmatic Faults” 38 ISQ, December 2009

Conclusions

We agree that observations are theory-laden, that translation problems often operate

across the technical language of intellectual communities and their theories, and that some of

these problems may rise to the level of local incommensurabilities. But none of these

disagreements correlate with the boundaries of many of the aggregates we refer to as

“paradigms” and “research programmes.” Indeed, as we have seen, trying to turn “realism” and

“constructivism,” for example, into “paradigms” or “research programmes” demonstrates why

Lakatosian criteria are best suited to the retrospective, rational reconstruction of the history of

science: only after the fact can we make clear determinations about the content of a particular

research programme. Thus, at the very least, we confront no persuasive rationale for appealing

to MSRP to evaluate the status of the “isms.”

Recasting the “isms” as ideal-typical limits within which actual scholarship resides

captures many of the benefits of mapping disciplines, but avoids the costs of attempting to

compress various scholars and theories into “paradigms” or “research programmes.” In

particular, it decouples variables, processes, and mechanisms from the putative boundaries of

theoretical aggregates. A “paradigmatic” approach often leads to arguments about, for example,

whether or not integrating domestic political culture into analysis of how states respond to power

transition violates “realist assumptions” and affirms “constructivism.” Our approach implies a

focus on how the implications of the theory, not its inherent architecture, shape our assessment

of value-commitments associated with realism, liberalism, and so forth. All of this allows for

genuine “analytic eclecticism” insofar as scholars are free to interrogate and combine particular

mechanisms, processes, variables, and methodologies—subject to the constraints of logical and


“Paradigmatic Faults” 39 ISQ, December 2009

analytical consistency rather than concerns about the coherence of particular “paradigms” (cf.

Katzenstein and Okarawa 2001/2002; Katzenstein and Sil 2008).

Other scholars may have, or implicitly operate with, different ideal-typical maps. A

continental European map of the discipline might, for example, look rather different than what

we propose. The existence of multiple, competing ideal-typical maps may actually be desirable,

inasmuch as the only scientific way to evaluate the outcome of an ideal-typical procedure is to

see how much insight into a empirical phenomenon it generates. Alternative ideal-typifications

help to make clear precisely what the strengths and weaknesses of each analytical “cut” into

reality are, and would help with what must ultimately be the pragmatic evaluation of diverse

perspectives.

References

Abbott, Andrew. 2001. Chaos of Disciplines. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.


Adler, Emanuel. 1997. “Seizing the Middle Ground: Constructivism in World Politics.”
European Journal of International Relations 3 (3):316-363.
Baldwin, David A. 1993 “Neoliberalism, Neorealism, and World Politics.” In Neorealism and
Neoliberalism: The Contemporary Debate, ed. by David A. Baldwin. New York:
Columbia University Press, 3-25.
Ball, Terence. 1976. "From Paradigms to Research Programmes: Toward a Post-Kuhnian
Political Science." American Journal of Political Science 20 (1): 151-177.
Banchoff, Thomas. 1999. “German Identity and European Integration.” European Journal of
International Relations 5 (3):259-289.
Barkin, J. Samuel. 2003. “Realist Constructivism.” International Studies Review 5 (3):325-342.
Barnes, Barry. 1983. T.S. Kuhn and the Social Sciences. New York: Columbia University Press.
Barnett, Michael N. and Raymond Duvall. 2005. “Power in International Politics.” International
Organization 59 (1):39-75.
Biagioli, Mario. 1993. Galileo Courtier: The Practice of Science in the Culture of Absolutism.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Bially Mattern, Janice. 2004. Ordering International Politics: Identity, Crisis, and
Representational Force. New York: Routledge.
Boucoyannis, Deborah. 2007. “The International Wanderings of a Liberal Idea, or Why Liberals
Can Learn to Stop Worrying and Love the Balance of Power.” Perspectives on Politics 5
(4):703-727.
“Paradigmatic Faults” 40 ISQ, December 2009

Checkel, Jeffrey T. 1998. “The Constructivist Turn in International Relations Theory.” World
Politics 50 (2):324-48.
Chen, Xiang. 1990. “Local Incommensurability and Communicability.” PSA: Proceedings of the
Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. 1:67-75.
Chernoff, Fred. 2002. “Scientific Realism as a Meta-Theory of International Politics.”
International Studies Quarterly 46 (2):189-207.
Chernoff, Fred. 2005. The Power of International Theory: Reforging the Link to Foreign Policy-
Making Through Scientific Inquiry. New York, Routledge.
Chernoff, Fred. 2007. “Critical Realism, Scientific Realism, and International Relations Theory.”
Millennium: Journal of International Studies 35 (2): 309-407.
Cox, Robert W. with Timothy J. Sinclair. 1996. Approaches to World Order. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Dessler, David. 1989. “What's at Stake in the Agent-Structure Debate.” International
Organization 43 (3):441-73.
Dessler, David. 2003. “Explanation and Scientific Progress.” In Progress in International
Relations Theory: Appriasing the Field, ed. Colin Elman and Miriam Fendius Elman.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 381-404.
Deudney, Daniel. 2006. Bounding Power: Republican Security Theory from the Polis to the
Global Village. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
DiCicco, Jonathan M., and Jack S. Levy. 1999. “Power Shift and Problem Shifts: The Evolution
of the Power Transition Research Program.” Journal of Conflict Resolution 43 (6): 675-
704.
Dunne, Timothy. 1998. Inventing International Society: A History of the English School. New
York: St. Matin's Press.
Elman, Colin, and Miriam Fendius Elman. 2002. “How Not to Be Lakatos Intolerant: Appraising
Progress in IR Research.” International Studies Quarterly 46 (2): 231-262.
Elman, Colin, and Miriam Fendius Elman. 1997. “Lakatos and Neorealism: A Reply to
Vasquez.” American Political Science Review 91 (4):923-926.
Farrell, Robert P. 2003. Feyerabend and Scientific Values: Tightrope-Walking Rationality. Vol.
235, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Finnemore, Martha. 1996. National Interests in International Society. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press.
Flynn, Gregory, and Henry Farrell. 1999. “Piecing Together the Democratic Peace: The CSCE,
Norms and the Construction of Security in Post-Cold War Europe.” International
Organization 53 (3):505-536.
Forde, Steven. 1995. “International Realism and the Science of Politics: Thucydides,
Machiavelli, and Neorealism.” International Studies Quarterly 39 (2):141-160.
Geller, Daniel S., and John A. Vasquez. 2004. “The Construction and Cumulation of Knowledhe
in International Relations: Introduction.” International Studies Review 6 (4): 1-6.
Gilpin, Robert. 1981. War and Change in World Politics. New York: Cambridge University
Press.
Goddard, Stacie E., and Daniel H. Nexon. 2005. “Paradigm Lost? Reassessing Theory of
International Politics.” European Journal of International Relations 11 (1): 9-61.
Guzzini, Stefano. 2000. “A Reconstruction of Constructivism in International Relations.”
European Journal of International Relations 6 (2): 147-182.
“Paradigmatic Faults” 41 ISQ, December 2009

Hacking, Ian. 1999. The Social Construction of What? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Hardin, Russell. 1995. One for All: The Logic of Group Conflict. Princeton: Princeton University
Press.
Harvey, Frank P. 1999. “Practicing Coercion: Revisiting Successes and Failures Using Boolean
Logic and Comparative Methods.” Journal of Conflict Resolution 43 (6):840-871.
Hobbes, Thomas. [1651] 1951. Leviathan. New York: Penguin.
Jackson, Patrick Thaddeus. 2008. “Foregrounding Ontology: Dualism, Monism, and IR Theory.”
Review of International Studies 34 (1):129-153.
Johnston, David. 1994. The Idea of a Liberal Theory: A Critique and Reconstruction. Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press.
Katzenstein, Peter J, Robert O. Keohane, and Stephen D. Krasner. 1998. “International
Organization and the Study of World Politics.” International Organization 52 (4):645-
685.
Katzenstein, Peter J., and Nobu Okarawa. 2001/2002. “Japan, Asia-Pacific Security, and the
Case for Analytical Ecclecticism.” International Security 26 (1): 153-185.
Katzenstein, Peter J. and Rudra Sil. 2008. “Eclectic Theorizing in the Study and Practice of
International Relations,” in The Oxford Handbook of International Relations, ed.
Christian Reus-Smit and Duncan Snidal. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 109-130.
Keck, Margaret E., and Katheryn Sikkink. 1998. Activists Beyond Borders: Advocacy Networks
in International Politics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Keohane, Robert O., and Helen Milner, eds. 1996. Internationalization and Domestic Politics.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Keohane, Robert O. 2001. “Governance in a Partially Globalized World.” American Political
Science Review 91 (1): 1-14.
Keohane, Robert O., and Lisa L. Martin. 2003. “Institutional Theory as a Research Program.” In
Progress in International Relations Theory, ed. Colin Elman and Miriam Fendius Elman.
Cambridge. MA: MIT Press, 71-107.
Keohane, Robert O., and Joseph S. Nye, Jr. [1977] 1989. Power and Interdependence. New
York: HarperCollins.
Kitcher, Philip. 1982. “Implications of Incommensurability.” PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial
Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 2: 689-703.
Koertge, Noretta. 1970. “Inter-Theoretic Criticism and the Growth of Science.” PSA:
Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1970:160-
173.
Krasner, Stephen D. 1985. “Toward Understanding in International Relations.” International
Studies Quarterly 29 (2):137-144.
Krasner, Stephen D. 1999. Sovereignty: Organized Hypocrisy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Kratochwil, Friedrich. 2003. “The Monologue of ‘Science’.” International Studies Review 5
(1):124-128.
Kratochwil, Friedrich. 2006. “History, Action and Identity: Revisiting the ‘Second’ Great Debate
and Assessing its Importance for Social Theory.” European Journal of International
Relations 12 (1): 5-29.
Kuhn, Thomas S. 1957. The Coppernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development
of Western Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
“Paradigmatic Faults” 42 ISQ, December 2009

Kuhn, Thomas S. [1962] 1970a. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Kuhn, Thomas S. 1970b. “Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research?” In Criticism and the
Growth of Knowledge, ed. Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1-23.
Kuhn, Thomas S. 1970c. “Notes on Lakatos.” PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the
Philosophy of Science Association 1970:137-146.
Kuhn, Thomas S. 1982. “Commensurability, Comparability, Communicability.” PSA:
Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 2: 669-
688.
Kuhn, Thomas S. 1990. “The Road Since Structure.” PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting
of the Philosophy of Science Association 2: 3-13.
Kulka, Thomas. 1977. “Some Problems Concerning Rational Reconstruction: Comments on
Elkana and Lakatos.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 28 (4): 325-344.
Lakatos, Imre. 1970a. “History of Science and Its Rational Reconstructions.” PSA: Proceedings
of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1970: 91-136.
Lakatos, Imre. 1970b. “Replies to Critics.” PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the
Philosophy of Science Association 1970: 174-182.
Lakatos, Imre. 1978. “The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes.” In Criticism and
the Growth of Knowledge, ed. by Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 91-195.
Lake, David A. 1996. “Anarchy, Hierarchy and the Variety of International Relations.”
International Organization 50 (1):1-33.
Lapid, Yosef. 2003. “Through Dialogue to Engaged Pluralism: The Unfinished Business of the
Third Debate.” International Studies Review 5 (1):128-131.
Larvor, Brendan. 1998. Lakatos: An Introduction. London: Routledge.
Laudan, Larry. 1976. “Two Dogmas of Methodology.” Philosophy of Science, 43 (4): 585-597.
Legro, Jeffrey W., and Andrew Moravcsik. 1999. “Is Anybody Still a Realist? International
Security.” 24 (2): 5-55.
Locke, John. 1960. Two Treatises of Government. Ed. Peter Laslett. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
MacDonald, Paul K. 2003. “Useful Fiction or Miracle Maker: The Competing Epistemological
Foundations of Rational Choice Theory.” American Political Science Review 97 (4): 551-
565.
Machiavelli, Niccòlo. 1994. Selected Political Writings. Trans. David Wooton. Cambridge:
Hackett.
March, James G., and Johan P. Olsen. 1998. “The Institutional Dynamics of International
Political Orders.” International Organization 52 (4):943-969.
Mearsheimer, John J. 2001. The Tragedy of Great Power Politics. New York: W.W. Norton.
Meiland, Jack W. 1974. “Kuhn, Scheffler, and Objectivity in Science.” Philosophy of Science 41
(2): 179-187.
Moravcsik, Andrew. 1997. “Taking Preferences Seriously: A Liberal Theory of International
Politics.” International Organization 51 (4): 513-554.
Moravcsik, Andrew. 1998. The Choice for Europe: Social Purposes and State Power from
Messina to Maastricht. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
“Paradigmatic Faults” 43 ISQ, December 2009

Nadel, Edward. 1984. “Programmes and Paradigms: A Reply to Zandvoort.” Social Studies of
Science 14 (3): 446-450.
Onuf, Nicholas. 1989. World of Our Making: Rules and Rule in Social Theory and International
Relations. Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press.
Pearce, David. 1982. “Stemülller on Kuhn and Incommensurability.” British Journal for the
Philosophy of Science 33 (4): 389-396.
Peterson, Susan, Michael J. Tierney, and Daniel Maliniak. 2005. “Teaching and Research
Practices, Views on the Discipline, and Policy Attitudes of International Relations
Faculty at U.S. Colleges and Universities.” Williamsburg, VA: College of William and
Mary.
Price, Richard. 1998. “Reversing the Gun Sights: Transnational Civil Society Targets Land
Mines.” International Organization 52 (3): 613-644.
Price, Richard, and Christian Reus-Smit. 1998. “Dangerous Liaisons? Critical International
Theory and Constructivism.” European Journal of International Relations 4 (3):259-294.
Radnitzky, Gerard. 1991. “Review: Refined Falsificationism Meets the Challenge from the
Relativist Philosophy of Science.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 42
(2): 273-284.
Ray, James Lee. 2003. “A Lakatosian View of the Democratic Peace Research Program.” In
Progress in International Relations Theory, ed. Colin Elman and Miriam Fendius Elman.
Cambridge: MIT Press, 205-243.
Ringer, Fritz K. 2004. Max Weber: An Intellectual Biography. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Risse, Thomas. 2000. “‘Let's Argue!’: Communicative Action in World Politics.” International
Organization 54 (1): 1-39.
Rose, Gideon. 1998. “Neoclassical Realism and Theories of Foreign Policy.” World Politics 51
(1): 144-172.
Sankey, Howard. 1991. “Incommensurability, Translation and Understanding.” The
Philosophical Quarterly 41 (165): 414-426.
Sankey, Howard. 1993. “Kuhn's Changing Concept of Incommensurability.” British Journal for
the Philosophy of Science 44 (4): 759-774.
Scheffler, Israel. [1967] 1982. Science and Subjectivity. Indianapolis, IN: Hacket.
Schmidt, Brian C. 1998. The Political Discourse of Anarchy: A Disciplinary History. Albany,
NY: State University of New York Press.
Schweller, Randall L., and William C. Wohlforth. 2000. “Power Test: Evaluating Realism in
Response to the End of the Cold War.” Security Studies 9 (3): 60-107.
Sending, Ole Jacob. 2002. “Constitution, Choice and Change: Problems with the 'Logic of
Appropriateness' and its Use in Constructivist Theory.” European Journal of
International Relations 8 (4): 443-470.
Shapere, Dudley. 1964. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. The Philosophical Review. 73
(3): 383-394.
Siegel, Harvey. 1976. “Meiland on Scheffer, Kuhn, and Objectivity in Science.” Philosophy of
Science 43 (3): 441-448.
Siegel, Harvey. 1980. “Review: Objectivity, Rationality, Incommensurability, and More.”
British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 31 (4): 359-375.
Snyder, Jack. 2002. “Anarchy and Culture: Insights from the Anthropology of War.”
International Organization 56 (1): 7-45.
“Paradigmatic Faults” 44 ISQ, December 2009

Sterling-Folker, Jennifer. 2002. “Realism and the Constructivist Challenge: Rejecting,


Reconstructing, or Rereading.” International Studies Review 4 (1): 73-97.
Sudhakar, V. (1989) “Are Scientific Theories Incommensurable?” Social Scientist 17 (3/4): 31-
50.
Szumilewicz, Irena. 1977. “Incommensurability and the Rationality of the Development of
Science,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 28 (4): 345-350.
Tannenwald, Nina. 1999. “The Nuclear Taboo.” International Organization 53 (3):433-468.
Tuck, Richard. 1999. The Rights of War and Peace. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Vasquez, John A. 1997. “The Realist Paradigm and Degenerative versus Progressive Research
Programs: An Appraisal of Neotraditional Research on Waltz's Balancing Proposition.”
American Political Science Review 91 (4): 899-912.
Vasquez, John A. 1998. The Power of Power Politics: From Realism to Neotraditionalism.
Cambrdge: Cambridge University Press.
Vasquez, John A. 2003. “The New Debate on Balancing Power: A Reply to My Critics.” In
Realism and the Balance of Power: A New Debate, ed. John. A. Vasquez and Colin
Elman. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall, 87-113.
Walt, Stephen M. 1998. “International Relations: One World, Many Theories.” Foreign Policy
(110): 29-45.
Walt, Stephen M. 1999. “Rigor or Rigor Mortis? Rational Choice and Security Studies.”
International Security 23 (4):5-48.
Waltz, Kenneth. 1979. Theory of International Politics. New York: Addison-Wesley.
Weber, Max. 1999. “Die ‘Objektivität’ Sozialwissenschaftlicher und Sozialpolitischer
Erkenntnis.” In Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftslehre, ed. by E. Flitner, Potsdam:
Internet-Ausgabe, http://www.uni-potsdam.de/u/paed/Flitner/Flitner/Weber/, 146-214.
Wendt, Alexander. 1992. “Anarchy Is What States Make of It.” International Organization 46
(2): 391-425.
Wendt, Alexander. 1999. Social Theory of International Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Wight, Colin. 1996. "Incommensurability and Cross-Paradigm Communication in International
Relations Theory: 'What's the Frequency Kenneth?'." Millennium: Journal of
International Studies 22 (2): 291-319.
Yuxin, Zheng. 1990. “From the Logic of Mathematical Discovery to the Methodology of
Scientific Research Programmes.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 41 (3):
377-399.

You might also like