0% found this document useful (0 votes)
41 views21 pages

Three Philosophies Behind Public Administration's Research Tradition

This document discusses three philosophies - logical positivism, logical empiricism, and pragmatism - that underlie public administration's research tradition. Logical positivism emphasizes verification and rejects metaphysics. Logical empiricism focuses on falsification and does not fixate on metaphysics. Pragmatism asserts that what works is truth, and considers a variety of experiences to be real. The philosophies differ in their views of epistemology, metaphysics, and the nature of truth and reality.

Uploaded by

Cheryl
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
41 views21 pages

Three Philosophies Behind Public Administration's Research Tradition

This document discusses three philosophies - logical positivism, logical empiricism, and pragmatism - that underlie public administration's research tradition. Logical positivism emphasizes verification and rejects metaphysics. Logical empiricism focuses on falsification and does not fixate on metaphysics. Pragmatism asserts that what works is truth, and considers a variety of experiences to be real. The philosophies differ in their views of epistemology, metaphysics, and the nature of truth and reality.

Uploaded by

Cheryl
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 21

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/36442859

Three Philosophies Behind Public Administration's Research Tradition

Conference Paper · July 1995


Source: OAI

CITATIONS READS
0 4,824

1 author:

Patricia M. Shields
Texas State University
141 PUBLICATIONS   1,104 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

Handbook of Military Sciences View project

Philosophy in Public Administration View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Patricia M. Shields on 07 August 2014.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


Three Philosophies Behind Public Administration’s Research
Tradition

Patricia M. Shields
Southwest Texas State University
Department of Political Science
San Marcos, TX 78666

512-245-2143
[email protected]

Presented at the Trinity Symposium on Public Management Research,


San Antonio, TX July 23, 1995

1
Three Philosophies Behind Public Administration’s Research
Tradition

Patricia M. Shields
Southwest Texas State University

Public Administration has had a history of difficulty and confusion defining itself. Evidence
of this confusion can be found in the theory/practice debate. Part of the confusion stems from the
way the research/theory/practice problem is conceptualized. For example, some academics argue
that the discipline of Public Administration 1 needs more rigor and stature. Using the norms of
science, they seek explanatory theories with empirical import. 2 Another group of academics is
concerned about the norms of science being inappropriately applied to Public Administration.
3 They are critical of the logical positivist philosophic tradition introduced by Herbert Simon (1945)
in Administrative Behavior. Finally, the practitioner asks a wholly different question: What is the
use of theory? How can it help me do my job?
The differences in these perspectives led me to ask; Just what were the philosophic
traditions that underlie the debate and approaches to public administration as either a field of study
or a world of practice? Could confusion over unstated philosophic assumptions be hampering
productive dialogue? Could these seemingly conflicting positions live under one larger umbrella?
This paper is a preliminary attempt to explore three modern philosophical traditions and link
them to Public Administration theory and practice. Logical positivism, logical empiricism and
pragmatism will be examined. In many ways these three philosophical traditions are similar.
Elements of the scientific method such as the importance of empirical evidence and hypotheses are
central to each. In other ways they are diverse; for example, the role of ethics, logic and aesthetics
are treated differently.
To begin addressing this puzzle, I went to a group of philosophers. They suggested Alfred
Ayer as an archetypal logical positivist. After studying Ayer and corroborating his position through
the Encyclopedia of Philosophy, I could see that economics (my home discipline ) followed very
closely the formula outlined by Ayer. However, the logical positivism described by Ayer did not
really fit the type of reasoning that Simon advocated. I had a sense that PA critics of logical
positivism and Simon were not really criticizing this formal ideal type logical positivism. It seemed

1 Barry Bozeman and Jeffrey Straussman (1984:1) distinguish between public administration and
Public Administration. The lower case version refers to the practice of public administration and the upper
case version refers to the discipline or field of study. This is a useful distinction and will be used through the
paper.
2 In many ways the Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory came into being in response to
this concern. Ideally this journal promotes sound explanatory theory which is tested empirically.
3 See for example, Denhardt, 1984; Stillman, 1990; Waldo, 1965.

2
more accurate to say critics were unhappy because Simon was interested in developing a “science
of administration.” His position was less rigid and less sterile than Ayer's logical positivism. The
direction he led PA toward seemed closer to Hemple and Carnap who focused on the philosophy of
science as a field of study. Brauch Brody and Richard Grandy (1989:xii) in Readings in the
Philosophy of Science describe Hemple and Carnap’s position as logical empiricism. It is also
considered the classical view of the philosophy of science. This group of philosophers “produced a
powerful persuasive conception of scientific enterprise that do not agree with the basic
presuppositions of logical positivism.”
Whether it is called logical positivism or logical empiricism there is still dissatisfaction over
its influence within PA. Both of these techniques are far removed from the world of practicing
public administrators. Critics maintain that neither apply to the real world of administration. On the
other hand, the philosophy of pragmatism is firmly planted in the tangled muddy world of
experience and addresses many of the issues from the practitioners perspective (Shields,
forthcoming). In addition, philosophers of science such as Abraham Kaplan (1965) advocate the
pragmatic approach as an underlying philosophic tradition for the social and behavioral sciences.
Hence, pragmatism is an approach compatible with social scientific inquiry and with the “common
sense,” “what works?” world of the practitioner.

Three Philosophic Traditions


In the next section the three traditions are briefly described. The five major branches of
philosophy (epistemology, metaphysics, logic, ethics, aesthetics) and the philosophy of science are
used as a descriptive, organizing device. These criteria were chosen because the traditional
branches of philosophy provide a comprehensive comparative framework. The philosophy of
science was chosen because it is a specific subject matter of philosophy which defines many of the
conflicts in PA research and theory. The comparison is summarized in Table 1.

3
Table 1
Comparison of Logical Positivism, Logical Empiricists and Pragmatism

Subjects of Philosophical School


philosophy Logical Positivism Logical Empiricism Pragmatism
Epistemology -The principal of -The principal of -What works.
verification is used for the falsification is used as a -The truth of a notion is traced
criteria of truth. criteria of truth by its "respective practical
consequences. ... What
-Uses a narrowly defined difference would it practically
(nature of (sense content) make if this notion rather than
knowledge) experimental model -Truth is not fixed or that notion were true" (James,
absolute 1907: 45).
-Analytic and empirical - “True ideas are those that we
verification are can assimilate, validate,
distinguished. corroborate and verify. ...
(James, 1907: 201).
-Truth is not fixed or -Truth is not fixed or absolute
absolute.

Logical Empiricism Pragmatism


Logical Positivism
Metaphysics -Rejects metaphysics as a - Not really concerned -Ultimate causes are not fixed.
legitimate branch of with metaphysics as a -A wide variety of experiences
(nature of philosophy. field of study are considered real e.g.,
reality) emotional, religious, aesthetic.
-Metaphysics cannot be -reality is not fixed or Hence, practical consequences
verified with sense content absolute can be ascertained and the
and is therefore nonsense. pragmatic criterion of truth can
be applied to metaphysical
-"Real" is what is questions.
empirically verifiable. -Reality is a function of ones
-Fact and value are conceptual schemes.
separate -The world is as many ways as it
-reality is not fixed or can cogently be conceived.
absolute

Logic -Logic is concerned with -Concerned with the -Uses a logic of inquiry.
formal consequences of logical structure of -Naturalistic logic for assessing
definitions and not with explanatory arguments human experience.
empirical fact. -concerned with causal -It focuses on pragmatism as a
-Truths of logic are relationships and causal method of learning.
tautologies. laws

4
Ethics -Rejects transcendent - ethics is not part of its -Uses a developmental approach
ethics as a legitimate frame of reference. to deal with ethical problems.
branch of philosophy. - Ends-in-view help to anchor
moral choices.
-Ethics cannot be -Ethical problems may be
verified with sense addressed by forming principles
content and is therefore and generalizations that work.
nonsense. These principles should be taken
seriously and developed with
care. Nevertheless, if conditions
change or if new facts appear
principles, may be revised.
-Moral choices are taken
seriously. The conflict between
good and evil is real.

Aesthetics -Rejects aesthetics as a - Not concerned with -Incorporates and ties aesthetics
legitimate branch of aesthetics as a field of into the practical consequences
philosophy. study associated with experience.
-aesthetics cannot be
verified with sense content -Incorporated emotions as
and is therefore nonsense. legitimate experience in
-Considers emotions assessing working hypotheses or
outside the realm of sense consequences.
experience and therefore
cannot be used to verify -includes a philosophy of art
hypotheses.

Logical Positivism Logical Empiricism Pragmatism


Philosophy of -Verification was Seeks an answer to the Instrumentalism
Science employed as a criteria of “Why” question "It identifies the procedures of
demarcation to draw analyzing concepts by an attempt
distinctions between - Truth rest on to get at the use that is made of
scientific and unscientific explanatory relevance them. ...
statements. (theory) and testability The meaning is scientifically valid
only if what they intend by it
- major focus of logical -Statistical explanation is becomes actual: problems are
positivism legitimate solved and intentions are fulfilled
as inquiry continues" (Kaplan,
-the philosophers “function -major focus of logical 1964: 46).
is to clarify the empiricists
propositions of science by One of many concerns of the
exhibiting their logical pragmatists
relationships, and by
defining the symbols
which occur in
them”(Ayer, 1952:32).
The sources for this table are : Ayer, 1952; The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vols. 5&6 ; Brody and Grandy, 1989;
James, 1907; Kaplan, 1964; Hempel, 1965 and various Dewey references.

Logical Positivism
Logical positivism is an approach which maintains that philosophy should deal with what is
and not what ought to be. Logical positivism emphasizes, empiricism, analysis, and logic. It

5
focuses on epistemology and logic as the only legitimate branches of philosophy. Verification is
used as a criteria for truth. 4 It is a philosophic approach that applies the methods of the hard
sciences to the larger philosophical discourse. It uses hypotheses and focuses on 'facts' that can be
empirically measured or verified through sense content. Ironically, logical positivism as defined by
Ayer has been rejected by modern philosophers because the verification principle cannot be
verified. Nevertheless logical positivism has had enduring influence on social science 5 .
Earlier I suggested that Ayer’s logical positivism really described Economics better than
Public Administration. This parallel came through most clearly in Ayer's discussion of
propositions. Ayer divides the world into propositions that can be verified by sense content and
those that

comprise the a priori propositions of logic and pure mathematics and these
...[are]...necessary and certain only because they are analytic... these
propositions cannot be confuted in experience... that is they do not make
assertions about the empirical world (Ayer, 1952: 31).
Economics like physics uses much of what Ayer would classify as analytic propositions.

The truths of logic and mathematics are analytic propositions or tautologies...


[a] proposition is analytic when its validity depends solely on the definition of
the symbols it contains, and synthetic when its validity is determined by the
facts of experience” (Ayer, 1952: 77-78).
Ayer was using physics as exemplary here. Logical Positivism accepted, for example, the
application of calculus to analytic propositions that had been reduced to mathematical symbols.
By using the algebra of change (calculus) it was possible to “reveal unsuspected implications”
within the propositions.

[T]here is a sense in which analytic propositions do give us new knowledge.


They call attention to linguistic usages, of which we might otherwise not be
conscious, and they reveal unsuspected implications in our assertions and
beliefs. But we can see also that there is a sense in which they may be said
to add nothing to our knowledge. For they tell us what we may be said to
know already.(Ayer, 1952: 79) (italics added).

4 “[T]he principle of verification is supposed to furnish a criterion by which it can be determined


whether or not a sentence is literally meaningful” (Ayer, 1952:.5).
5 It should be noted that many social sciences such as economics, political science, operations
research, etc., have embraced logical positivism and the rational model. Further, over the last 30 years,
policy and management prescriptions based on the logic of positivism and the rational model have been
widely adopted. Not surprisingly, both theory and policy have been criticized. Academics such as Amitai
Etzioni (1988), focus on the absence of ethics and the inaccurate assumptions about human motivation in
their criticism. Hence, critics of logical positivism within Public Administration are part of a larger trend.

6
Science could thus be advanced without empirical verification. Social sciences like Economics
drew from the logical positivist model as they became more mathematical. 6 Ironically, Simon is
concerned about the application of math to social science. Mathematical social science is first and
foremost, social science. If it is bad social science (i.e., empirically false), the fact that it is good
mathematics (i.e., logically consistent) should provide little comfort” (Simon, 1957: 388).
One of the most obvious features of Ayer’s logical positivism is that he has an agenda. He
wants to transform philosophy as a field of study. His first chapter is entitled “The Elimination of
Metaphysics.” Ayer (1952: 34) asserts

[W]e maintain that no statement that refers to a ‘reality’ transcending the


limits of all sense-experience can possibly have any literal significance;
from which it must follow that the labors of those who have striven to
describe such reality have all been devoted to the production of
nonsense. [italics added]
Aside from metaphysics, Ayer asserts that the domains of ethics and aesthetics are beyond the
empirical (cannot be verified with sense content) and thus are not legitimate branches of philosophy
(Ayer, 1952). It is from this rejection of ethics, metaphysics and aesthetics that the fact/value
dichotomy in PA was born.
It is statements such as this which link Simon (1945: 46) to Logical Positivism. 7

To determine whether a proposition is correct, it must be compared directly


with experience-with the facts-or it must lead by logical reasoning to other

6 Between 1938 and 1958 most of its early economic theory had been translated to mathematics. The
problem was no longer teaching math to economists but of teaching “economics in mathematical terms.”
Henderson and Quandt, Microeconomic Theory, viii. For example, in 1948, Paul Samuelson published his
landmark Foundations of Economics Analysis and in 1965, R.G.D. Allen published Mathematical Economics.

Economics is conceptual in much the same way as physics. Engineers use properties of physics to build
bridges and design airplanes. Similarly, systems analysts use principles of economics to design analytical
studies which focus on efficiency and choice among alternatives. The science of physics does not include the
details of design and operation. Furthermore, physicists who delve deeply into the details of design and
operation are seldom rewarded or recognized by members of their profession. Likewise, economists are
seldom rewarded or recognized by members of their discipline when they focus of the problems of
implementing a budget or the specifics of a cost effectiveness study. Often, when critics find fault with
policy they may look to those closest to the policy and be unaware of the role of the ideas behind the policy.

7 In this section of Administrative Behavior, Simon cites Ayer and other logical positivists such as
Rudolf Carnap as the source for his arguments. Simon proposes a fact value dichotomy, which, he argues
provides a better basis for a science of administration and a more appropriate standard for administrative
conduct. Simon divides decision premises into two categories: value premises and factual premises. Value
premises are ethical statements about what should be done. As such, they may be good or bad, but cannot
be true or false (Simon,1945: 47). Factual premises, in contrast, are statements about the observable world.
Consequently, it can be determined whether factual premises are true or false (Simon, 1945: 45-46). The
factual premises of decisions are the perceived relationships between alternatives and their consequences.
Factual premises are true if the alternative selected leads to the predicted set of consequences. (Simon, 1945:
46& 48). They are false if they are not (Fry, 1989: 186)

7
proposition that can be compared with experience. But factual propositions
cannot be derived from ethical ones by any process of reasoning, nor ethical
propositions be compared directly with the facts-since they assert ‘oughts’
rather than facts. Hence, there is no way in which the correctness of ethical
propositions can be empirically or rationally tested (Simon, 1945: 46).

Through logical positivism, Simon redefined efficiency and brought rationality in decision making
to Public Administration. He also brought a fact-value and (by implication) a cognitive-affective
dichotomy (Fry, 1989: 210-212).
My sense is that the modern Public Administration theorists that want to enhance the
scholarly rigor of Public Administration research reject the strict fact/value dichotomy as
introduced by Simon. In addition, no one is calling for a theory of PA similar to neo-classical
economics which is found in micro-economics text books and scholarly Economics journals. Public
Administration scholars interested in more rigor , for example, would have no problem with efforts
to apply Etzioni’s (1988) Socioeconomics theory (which implicitly incorporates a moral dimension
and thus integrates fact and value) to Public Administration. It seems safe to assume that Ayer's
logical positivism is a historical artifact which, like in philosophy as a whole, is not really a living
part of the Public Administration theory debate within academic circles.

Logical Empiricism
Whereas logical positivism clearly seeks to be a general philosophy that is widely applied,
logical empiricism is more narrowly applied and its advocates don’t have an agenda (elimination of
metaphysic, aesthetics and ethics) with the same scope or intensity of Ayer’s. Philosophers such as
Carl Hemple, Paul Oppenheim, Rudolf Carnap and Nelson Goodman examine the philosophy
which underlie science (both social science and physical science). To the extent that
“administration is science” elements of the philosophy of science would apply. Using a
“hypothetico-deductive” method (Kaplan, 1964:9) these philosophers seek to answer the “why”
question. Truth rests on explanatory relevance (theory) and testability. Its logic is concerned with
the structure of explanatory arguments, with causal relationships and laws. It does not reject
metaphysics, ethics and aesthetics as legitimate branches of philosophy, rather, logical empiricism
ignores them. These branches of philosophy are not attended to because they are not within the
sphere of concerns relevant to science.
The epistemology of the logical empiricism uses the criteria of falsifiability. A hypothesis is
falsifiable if it is constructed such that it is possible to obtain information which will refute the
hypothesis. Thus science rests on empirical investigation which may reveal the unsuspected and
refute the expected. This is an important criteria for certain kinds of public administration research
such as program evaluation. Program evaluation research often asks whether a program is

8
effective. 8 The empirical evidence may suggest that the program is not effective. Thus
practitioners of public administration should understand that social science applications to public
administration are legitimate because (if designed correctly) they do not automatically confirm
expectations ( the hypothesis).
When Simon called for a scientific study of administration in Administrative Behavior fits.
He was applying norms of the philosophy of science to administration. His vision was closer to
Hemple than Ayer. It should be noted that logical empiricism also has an implied fact value
dichotomy. Aside from program evaluation, many other analytic techniques used in applied Public
Administration research such as cost benefit and cost effectiveness analysis fall under the
philosophic umbrella of logical empiricism. 9 This umbrella is also inclusive of the PA scholars
who seek testable explanatory theories. The fact-value dichotomy remains as a troubling thorn.

Pragmatism
Pragmatism is one of the major philosophies of the 20th century. In addition, it is the United
States most noted contribution to the world of philosophy. It is broader and more comprehensive
than either logical positivism or logical empiricism. In addition, it is also misunderstood.
The pragmatic philosophy posits a unique epistemology. The truth of a notion is traced by
its "respective practical consequences. ... What difference would it practically make if this notion
rather than that notion were true" (James, 1907: 45). 10 “True ideas are those that we can
assimilate, validate, corroborate and verify. ...The truth of an idea is not a stagnant property
inherent in it. Truth happens to an idea. It becomes true, is made true by events. Its verity is in fact

8 An experienced administrator/MPA student restated this criteria. speaking to other students he


advised “If you use the scientific method (in his case quasi-experimental design) you have to be prepared to
tell your boss what he doesn’t want to hear,” I would like to thank Frankie Waller, Chief of Administration,
Texas Department of Safety, for this example.
9 The Academy of Management Journal is a manifestation of logical empiricism applied to administration
research, the majority of its articles contain carefully constructed hypotheses which are tested empirically. In
addition, the statistical techniques used to test hypotheses tend to be highly sophisticated. Academics
unsatisfied with the state of research in PA probably wish that PA had a journal which more closely
resembled The Academy of Management Journal.
10 William James (1842-1910) has the distinction of being called both "the country's greatest
psychologist" ( Schultz, 1975: 129) and the "most influential American philosopher" (Soccio, 1992: 476).
William James, brother of the novelist Henry James, originally was trained as a medical doctor. He was
drawn to psychology while teaching at Harvard. The Principles of Psychology (1890), his greatest contribution
to the field of psychology, was acclaimed internationally and dominated the teaching of psychology for
decades.
James' pragmatic philosophy was an outgrowth of his psychology. An early and basic
elaboration of the philosophy is James’s Pragmatism (1907). To James, pragmatism was a way to mediate
between the tough-minded empiricist and the tender-minded rationalist. James maintains that the world
of experience (empiricists) and abstraction (rationalist) need each other. Pragmatism plunges one into
the "river of experience."

9
an event, a process” (James, 1907: 201). For example, what is 90 degrees? Is it hot or cold? The
pragmatist would ask, are you boiling water or are you playing basketball? The truth is in the
experience, the problem and the context.
Truth helps us sort between working hypotheses carrying us from one experience to another
(Flower and Murphy, 1977: 676). Effective truth is associated with a plan of action. It mediates
between experiences. It connects the old to the new, it welds theory and fact. In addition, it is
provisional, just the starting point used to address the next day's problem (Flower and Murphy,
1977: 681). Returning to the temperature example, if it is 90 degrees and you are playing
basketball, the plan of action might consist of stopping and getting some water. Last weeks (old),
experience with dehydration and its experience/effects helps provide the plan of action for today’s
decision-- to stop. The truth of 90 degrees being hot (in this context) mediated between yesterday
and today. Theory would also be helpful. Dehydration is a concept with theoretical significance.
Knowing some theory and the stages of dehydration would be useful.
The pragmatist asks about practical differences when settling disputes. “If no practical
difference whatever can be traced then the alternatives mean practically the same thing, and all
dispute is idle." (James, 1907: 45). Hence, pragmatists look for what works when settling disputes
or solving problems.
Theories, also must work or have practical application (James, 1907: 216). Since practical
consequences generally depend on context, pragmatism also allows for multiple realities.
Theories thus become instruments, not answers to enigmas, in which we can
rest. ....Pragmatism unstiffins our theories, limbers them up and sets each
one to work. (James, 1907: 53).
Pragmatism is also, holistic, the whole puzzle, the entire experience, including novelty, is
faced. None of the concrete facts are denied. Like all major philosophies, pragmatism helps one to
exercise powers of intellectual abstraction. In addition, it focuses on making a "positive connection
with the actual world of finite human lives" (James, 1907: 20). It dwells in the world of tangled,
muddy, painful, and perplexing, concrete experience (James, 1907: 21). "It turns toward
concreteness and adequacy, towards facts, towards action and towards power" (James, 1907: 51).
The epistemology and metaphysics of pragmatism seems well suited to the day to day world of the
practitioner. It is also suitable to the behavioral sciences. Unfortunately, this connection has often
been obscured.
Abraham Kaplan (1964: 43) maintains that the “action” criteria described by James has been
“widely misunderstood” because it was applied too narrowly. The more accurate broader
interpretation clearly gives pragmatism unique import for PA theory.
There is a vulgar pragmatism in which ‘action’ is opposed to ‘contemplation,’
‘practice’ to ‘theory,’ and ‘expediency’ to ‘principle,’ ... this vulgar doctrine
is almost the antithesis of pragmatism ... The ‘action’ that is relevant to the
pragmatic analysis of meaning must be constructed in the broadest possible
sense, so as to comprise not only the deeds that make up the great world of
affairs, but also those that constitute the scientific enterprise, whether it be as

10
‘practical’ as performing an experiment or as ‘contemplative’ as formulating a
theory. The ‘usefulness’ that pragmatism associates with truth is as much at
home in the laboratory and study as in the shop and factory (Kaplan, 1964:
43-44).
Hence, pragmatic action incorporates scientific enterprise. William James (1907:54) uses a
hotel corridor metaphore to describe the relationship between theory and practice. Theories
are foune in the rooms. The pragmatist owns the corridor, walking from room to room using
the theories, testing them in practice/context. Thus, pragmatism incorporates much of logical
empiricism. The use of program evaluation, cost benefit analysis etc., fit here.
The logic of pragmatism is very different from the formal logic of logical positivism or
logical empiricism. Pragmatism’s logic is a method of inquiry/learning that focuses on process. It
posits that people learn by experience. Particularly, they learn by using experience in combination
with a loosely defined experimental model. It uses a naturalistic logic to develop and test ongoing
hypotheses. Problems are important because they help to generate experiences, contexts and
hypotheses. 11 The evidence used to verify the hypotheses can be drawn from a variety of
experiences. Aside from measurable, scientific facts, pragmatism embraces the affective. It is, for
example, inclusive of religious experiences, art as experience 12 and nature as experience. The key
which ties them together is the practical consequences associated with the experiences. Without an
awareness of consequences, that which is distinctive about human learning could not take place.
This method-of-learning philosophy draws from the scientific method but not in a
reductionist manner. It allows for a richer set of experiences (or data) to test naturalistic, working
hypotheses. Learning and knowing are connected. Knowing becomes a part of the natural process
of adjustment. The working hypotheses are tested through action. Experiences and consequences
that flow from the action become part of knowing. In this natural process environment, knowledge
and action cannot be divided. (Flower and Murphy, 1977; 813) Hence, learning and action are
connected.
The “method of learning,” “logic of inquiry” model was most fully developed by John
Dewey and is known as instrumentalism (Kaplan, 1964: 46). Analysis of a concept is imbedded in
the ‘problem’ and in its use and in the way it contributes to a solution. The 90 degree as “hot”
makes sense in the basketball context . If the problem is making spaghetti, 90 degrees means
something else.

11 Problems generate experience. We learn by experience when we act and try out solutions to the
problem. Dewey uses cooking as an example, To deal with the problem of hunger one might fry an egg.
How best to fry the egg (how hot the skillet, how much grease, how long to cook, etc.) can be viewed as
working hypotheses. Try and teach a child to fry an egg. What seems natural to an adult is an unknown to a
child. Experience is a critical component. Dewey's How we Think (1910) is one of the clearest presentations of
these points
12 See James (1902) The Varieties of Religious Experience. See Dewey, (1958) Art as Experience,

11
A scientific concept has meaning only because scientists mean something by
it. The meaning is scientifically balid only if what they intend by its actual
problems are solved and intentions are fulfilled as inquiry continues (Kaplan,
1964: 46).
Pragmatist view and judge theories as instruments in problem solving. They are particularly
concerned with consequences associated with problem solving. The problem helps to define the
experience/reality boundary. “Reality begins with a problematic situation which stimulates” action.
(Patterson, 1953: 467 ) 13 The action is then judged considering consequences. This is exactly the
kind of logic useful in the ever changing problem filled environment of PA practice. In addition, the
naturalistic logic of pragmatism underlie much of the growth in qualitative-naturalistic research
methods (Erlandson et al. 1993; Guba and Lincoln, 1981). 14 This is an aspect of pragmatism that
begins to address the issues raised by PA scholars such as Denhart that are concerned with the
influence of logical positivism and who advocate the use of more qualitatitative research
techniques.
Unlike logical positivism and logical empiricism, pragmatism incorporates ethics. 15 “There
is no single touchstone of truth in ethics .... a pragmatic ethics seems to embrace a developmental
approach about how to best deal with ethical problems” (Luizzi. 1993: 28). Ethical problems may
be addressed by forming principles and generalizations that work. These principles should be taken
seriously and developed with care. Nevertheless, if conditions change or if new facts appear,
principles may be revised. For example, for centuries, the rights of women did not include the right
to vote or own property. Clearly, ethical principles dealing with political participation and property
rights played some role in developing these rules. Today, these principles no longer work,
conditions have changed and new ethical principles guide behavior. 16 Keep in mind, however,
ends-in-view 17 are more stable. Regardless of whether women do or do not have the right to vote;
democracy, equity and/or fairness are potential ends-in view.

13 In his discussion of pragmatism, Patterson (1953: 467-469) discusses “problematicism” as a defining


characteristic of the philosophy.
14 In personal correspondence, Erlandson attributed much of his logic to Dewey. Since his book is an
applied methods text, he did not feel the need to incorporate historical material. Hence, Dewey was not cited
or referenced in the text.
15James believed that the moral question of how to live the good life was the most basic practical issue
facing human beings. His morality was not confined to abstract rules or questions of duty. Rather, it was a
series, of never-ending live choices -- choices that made a practical difference. He wanted people to take the
moral choices seriously. The conflict between good and evil was real. Consequently, we need a moral
direction. (Soccio, 1992: 491) .

16 Vincent Luizzi (1993) links legal ethics and pragmatic conceptions of ethics. He argues that legal
ethics are a source for a universal ethic.
17 Ends are never viewed as absolute, rather, they are seen as ends-in-view or an intermediate step in a
larger, never complete quest. "[I]f you follow the pragmatic method," you cannot view any word as "closing
your quest.”

12
Dewey was deeply concerned with the "reality of moral problems and the value of reflective
thought in dealing with them" (Dewey and Tufts, 1927: iii). In 1908, John Dewey and James Tufts
wrote the widely used, Ethics , an undergraduate philosophy text (reprinted in 1927). In it they
developed a theory of ethics congruent with pragmatism. The theoretical portion the book
"affirms that there is a place in the moral life for reason and a place for
happiness, --a place for duty and a place for valuation. Theories are treated
not as incompatible rival systems which must be accepted or rejected en
bloc, but as more or less adequate methods of surveying the problems of
conduct. This mode of approach facilitates the scientific estimation and
determination of the part played by various factors in the complexity of
moral life. The student is put in a position to judge the problems of conduct
for himself. This emancipation and enlightenment of individual judgement
is the chief aim of the the theoretical portion (Dewey and Tufts, 1927, iv-v).
They also developed an ethics equipped to address unsettled societal questions. They
believed that ethical theory without practice was "intolerably academic." Moreover, practice
sharpens theory-- theories must be judged by their practical use (Dewey and Tufts, 1927: v). Thus,
Ethics discussed practical concerns which might be of interest to public administrators such as
distrust of government, administrative efficiency, and conflict between the public and private
interest. It also addressed policy reform such as child labor laws. Ethics was a fundamental element
of Dewey's pragmatism.
During the late 1930s, leading logical positivists tried to forge a connection with
pragmatism through Dewey 18 (Lamont, 1959:11; Westbrook, 1991: 403-408). Although there were

You must bring out of each word its practical cash-value, set it at work within the
stream of your experience. It appears less as a solution, then, than as a program for
more work, and more particularly as an indication of the ways in which existing
realities may be changed (James, 1907: 53).
Ends-in-view can be perceived as ideals. Democracy, justice, freedom, community could all be the
elusive, yet real, ends-in-view. If one asks, “What difference would it practically make if this notion rather
that that notion were true? " The practical difference might be whether one notion of truth enhanced justice.
Hence, values are an important part of pragmatism.

18 John Dewey, (1859-1952) the philosopher-psychologist-educator-social activist, refined pragmatism


as a method of learning and inquiry. Dewey, who was born before the Lincoln Administration and died the
year Eisenhower was elected, accomplished much. Summarizing Dewey's life, philosophy, or causes is
difficult.
Dewey, like James, made early contributions to psychology. He is noted among the world's
important psychologist's as a founder of the Chicago School of Functional Psychology and for challenging
the duality of stimulus-response.18 In addition, Dewey wrote two psychology texts. Thus, it should be
noted, that American pragmatism was refined by men deeply involved in shaping psychology.
Before pursuing a Ph.D. in philosophy from Johns Hopkins, Dewey taught high school. He was,
thus, trained as a philosopher, but experienced as a teacher. His "experienced" based, "context and
consequences" oriented philosophy of inquiry was at odds with the rigid educational practices of the day.
He also lived his action oriented philosophy. Thus, it is not surprising that he helped to lead major
educational reform. Through the "progressive movement" in education, children were taken out of rigid
seating arrangements, memorized less and "experienced" more. Science laboratories, vocational education
programs, field trips and gymnasiums are all credited to the progressive movement. Edwin Patterson

13
similarities (both use of the scientific method and empiricism), Dewey distanced himself from the
logical positivists. His major objection lie in the realm of ethics. The Theory of Valuation (1939)
was his response to the logical positivists. Dewey's naturalistic method of scientific inquiry
incorporated values and emotions. Many of Dewey's concerns about logical positivism are echoed
by today's Public Administration theorists. Clearly, fact and value are not separated by pragmatism.
Hence, using pragmatism as a guiding philosophy, the application of techniques such as cost
benefit analysis and program evaluation would be applied taking into account larger ethical
concerns.
Not suprisingly, the psychologists/philosophers (Dewey and James) also incorporate
aesthetics in their approach (Dewey, 1958 & 1925; James, 1890 & 1902). Aesthetics is tied to the
practical consequences associated with experience. Thus emotions are considered legitimate
experience in assessing working hypotheses or consequences. Art and beauty are also incorporated
into the pragmatic philosophy. Pragmatis would thus incorporate PA professionals who joined The
Section on Humanistic, Artistic and Refelective Expression of the American Society for Public
Administration. Both logical positivism and logical empiricism would disregard or ignore this
subject area.

The Irony of Simon's Administrative Behavior


One noted source to find the influence of William James and John Dewey is Herbert
Simon's pivotal Administrative Behavior. In the introduction of the second edition, Simon indicates
that Chapters 4 (Rationality in Administrative Behavior) and 5 (The Psychology of Administrative

(1953:486) maintains that Dewey's influence on American public school education and its teachers has
probably done more than any other to make pragmatism the "typically American way of thinking."
For the public, Dewey is perhaps most well known for his social activism. Over several decades, the
American people were exposed to Dewey through his extensive writing in the popular print media. Here he
aired his views on many of the key policy debates of the time such as suffrage, child labor laws,
unionization of labor, educational reform, individual rights, the New Deal, the League of Nations. He also
actively supported causes helping to organize the American Civil Liberties Union, the American Association
of University Professors, the New School of Social Research, and teachers unions (Dykhuizen, 1973: 169-
173). In addition, while at the University of Chicago, Dewey worked closely with Jane Addams and was an
active member of the first board of trustees of Hull House. Thus, Dewey, the activist-pragmatism, worked
to solve current social problems and contributed to the debate of many more.
Dewey's liberal activism was steeped in a faith in democracy. His personal philosophy incorporated
“democracy” as an ends-in-view. Throughout his life Dewey developed a theory of democracy. Although in
a minority,Dewey was the most important liberal intellectual of the twentieth century to advocate
participatory democracy. He called for a pervasive democracy which would shape the democratic character
and create a common democratic culture suffusing factories, schools, political parties, and other
organizations (Westbrook, 1991: xv-xvi). He demonstrated a commitment to the principle or ideal of
democracy. An ideal which he believed organizations and governments should strive.

14
Decisions) were the core of the book (1957: xi). The psychologists, Dewey and James are cited
extensively in Chapter 5. 19
In Administrative Behavior Simon's contributed to the understanding of administration by
focusing on individual purposeful behavior and the decision/action. 20 The decision is a pivotal
action used to anchor experience and consequences. Simon uses the decision premise as the focus
for context. These ideas ties to James's psychology which showed how the decision determined our
actions (Flower and Murphy, 1977, 644-645). In addition, James maintained that people "pursued
ends preferentially and behave purposively" (Flower and Murphy, 1977, 640). Simon also uses the
language of pragmatism. In the "Rationality" chapter he uses pragmatic concepts when replacing
the means-ends notion with alternative-consequences. In addition, the psychology chapter uses
concepts such as "practical decision-making", "consequences", "experience" and "practical
problems" to make arguments. (Simon, 1945: 82-83).
Finally, Simon cites Dewey and James extensively when he discusses habit.
An equally important mechanism that assists in the preservation of useful behavior
patterns is habit. 21 Habit permits conservation of mental effort by withdrawing from
the area of conscious thought those aspects of the situation that are repetitive
(Simon, 1945: 88)
Simon extends the notion of habit several pages later when he introduces "standard practices" in
organizations.

The organization establishes standard practices. By deciding once for all (or at least
for a period of time) that a particular task shall be done in a particular way, it
relieves the individual who actually performs the task of the necessity of determining
each time how it shall be done (Simon, 1945: 102).
Through Administrative Behavior and later work Simon changed the direction of Public
Administration. He is credited with bringing the controversial, philosophic doctrine of logical
positivism to Public Administration (Stillman, 1990: 118; Denhardt, 1984: 75). Although his critics
stress the logical positivist connection, which is clearly evident in the fact-value dichotomy, the

19 Simon indicates in a footnote that "most of the references here(ch 5) are to William James, The
Principles of Psychology ...and John Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct "(Simon, 1945:80). One surprising
aspect of Simon's book is that it is poorly indexed. Even though he cites three of Dewey's books in nine
footnotes, Dewey is not in the index.
20 It should be noted that Simon's first psychology reference is to Toulman's Purposive Behavior in
Animals and Men (1932). Toulmin is associated with the "Behavioral" school of psychology. Toulmin both
drew from James and departed from him. Like James, he focused on choice, decision, and purposive
behavior. Unlike James, he gave goal-objects and means-objects more concreteness and emphasized the
cognitive (Toulmin, 1932: 470). To Toulmin there is an end-of-quest. Toulmin's psychology is consistent with
logical positivism. James's is not.
21 This was footnote 8 in the "Psychology" chapter of Administrative Behavior. Dewey (Human Nature
and Conduct, pp.14-131, 172-181) early emphasized the important role of habit in social behavior. James, in
his Psychology, contributed a classic chapter to the psychological literature on habit (chap.iv).

15
above discussion demonstrates the used all three phisophical approaches in Administrative
Behavior. Further, from his perspective the most important chapters relied on James and Dewey.
Simon's use of Dewey and James is ironic. Of all key people in public administration, he
built theory using their ideas most explicitly. By embracing logical positivism, however, he moved
Public Administration away from the influence of pragmatism. The instrumental or contingency
nature of pragmatism makes it compatible with both schools of thought within Public
Administration academic circles. Although not always stated in these terms, the criticism of
philosophy is also a criticism of methods-- quantitative and qualitatitive. Critics are concerned
about an overly quantitative- value free Public Administration. They often advocate naturalistic
methods of inquiry for PA, pragmatism is compatible with both- Ironically, the works of Dewey
also form the basis for much of the explosion in naturalistic methods texts throughout education and
the social sciences.

Conclusion
This paper is a preliminary attempt to explore three modern philosophic traditions and link
them to the public administration theory practice debate. A close inspection suggests that aside
from the fact-value dichotomy, logical positivism has little to do with PA theory or practice.
Logical empiricism is the philosophic tradition associated with analytic techniques used in PA
practice (program evaluation, cost benefit analysis). It is also the philosophic tradition compatible
with the push to develop larger PA explanatory theories. It, however, incorporates a fact value
dichotomy and excludes aesthetics. Only pragmatism appears to be wholistic enough to be
compatible with the larger changing, conflict, value filled world of Public Administration.
Bibliography
Ayer, Alfred Jules. Language Truth and Logic. (2nd edition) New York: Dover, 1952.

Bailey, Mary Timney. “Do Physistics Use Case Studies: Thoughts on Public Administration
Research.” Public Administration Review 52 (Jan./Feb :1992): 47-54.

Bozeman, Barry and Straussman, Jeffrey. (Eds.)New Directions in Public Administration. Montery
CA: Brooks/Cole. 1984.

Brody, Baruch and Grandy, Richard. Eds. Readings in the Philosophy of Science 2nd edition.
Englewood Cliffs NJ: Prentice Hall.

Denhardt, Robert B. Theories of Public Administration. Pacific Grove, California: Brooks/Cole


Publishing Co., 1984.

Dewey, John, and Tufts, James. Ethics . New York: Henery Holt and Co. (first published 1908)
1926.

Dewey, John. "Knowledge and Relativity of Feeling" Journal of Speculative Psychology 17


(1883):56-70.
Dewey, John. “Logical Method and Law.” The Cornell Law Quarterly 10 (1924):17-27.

16
Dewey, John. Art as Experience. New York: Capricorn Book, 1958.

Dewey, John. Essays in Experimental Logic. New York: Dover Publications, 1916.

Dewey, John. Experience and Nature. Chicago: Open Court Publishing Co. , 1925.

Dewey, John. How We Think. New York: D.C. Heath & Co., 1910.

Dewey, John. Logic: The Theory of Inquiry. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1938.

Dewey, John. "Mr. Acheson's Critics: Their Attacks Feared Damaging to Our World Prestige," New
York Times, 19 November ,1950.

Dewey, John. The Public and its Problem. Chicago: Swallow Press. 1954. (First printed 1927
Henry Holt and Co.)

Dewey, John. "The Reflex Arc Concept in Psychology." Psychological Review 3 (1896) 357-370.

Dewey, John. "Theory of Evaluation." International Encyclopedia of Unified Science. Chicago:


University of Chicago Press. Vol II, 1939.

Dykhuizen, George. The Life and Mind of John Dewey. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern
Illinois University Press. 1973.

Edwards, Paul. The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, vol 5. New York:The Macmillan Company

Edwards, Paul. The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, vol 6. New York:The Macmillan Company

Ehrenberg, Victor. From Solon to Socrates: Greek History and Civilization during the 6th and 5th
Centuries. London: Methuen and Co LTD, 1973

Erlandson, David; Harris, Edward; Skipper, Barbara and Allen, Steve. Doing Naturalistic Inquiry:
A Guide to Methods. Newbury Park, CA: Sage, 1993
.
Etzioni, Amitai. The Moral Dimension: Toward a New Economics. New York: The Free Press.
1988.

Flower, Elizabeth and Murphy, Murry G. A History of Philosophy in America. NewYork: Capricorn
Books, 1977.

Fry, Brian. Mastering Public Administration: From Max Weber to Dwight Waldo. Chatham New
Jersey: Chatham House Publishing. 1989.

Guba, Egon and Lincoln, Yvonna. Effective Evaluation: Improving the Usefulness of Evaluation
Results Through Responsive and Naturalistic Approaches. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass
Publishers, 1981.

17
Hempel, Carl. “A logical Appraisal of Operationalism.” in Readings in the Philosophy of Science,
2nd edition. pp.12-20. Edited by Baruch Brody and Richard Grandy. Englewood Cliffs,
New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 1989.

Hemple, Carl. Aspects of Scientific Explanation and other Essays in the Philosophy of Science.
New YOrk:Free Press.1965.

Hempel, Carl and Oppenheim, Paul. “Studies in the Logic of Explanation.” in Readings in the
Philosophy of Science, 2nd edition. pp.151-167. Edited by Baruch Brody and Richard
Grandy. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 1989.

James, William. Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking. Cambridge, MA: The
Riverside Press. 1907.

James, William. Psychology. New York: Henery Holt, 1890.

James, William. The Moral Philosophy of William James. Edited by John Roth. New York:Thomas
Y. Crowell Co., 1969.

James, William. The Varieties of Religious Experience New York: Longmans, Green, 1902.

Kaplan, Abraham. The Conduct of Inquiry: Methodology for Behavioral Science. Scranton PA:
Chandler Publishing Company. 1964.

Kuhn, Thomas. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press,
1962.

Lamont, Corliss. (Editor). Dialogue on John Dewey. New York: Horizon Press, 1959.
Luizzi, Vincent. A Case For Legal Ethics: Legal Ethics as a Source for a Universal Ethic. Albany,
New York: State University of New York Press, 1993.

Morgan, David L. Focus Groups as Qualitative Research. Newbury Park, CA: Sage Publications,
1988.

Novack, George. An apprisal of John Dewey's philosophy: Pragmatism versus Marxism. New
York: Pathfinder Press, Inc. 1975.

Patterson, Edwin W. Jurisprudence: Men and Ideas of the Law. Brooklyn, NY:The Foundation
Press, 1953.

Peirce, Charles Sanders. Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vol. 5, edited by Charles
Hartshore and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1931-35.

Redford, Emmette S. Ideal and Practice in Public Administration. Alabama: University of Alabama
Press, 1975.

Robertson, David and Judd, Dennis. The Development of American Public Policy: The Structure of
Policy Restraint. Glenview, IL: Scott, Foresman and Company. 1989.

18
Rorty, Richard. Consequences of Pragmatism (Essays: 1972-1980). Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press, 1982.

Shields, Patricia, M. “Freud, Efficiency, and Pragmatism.” Transaction/Society , 26,(Jan./Feb.,


1989): 67-72.

Shields, Patricia, M. “Pragmatism: Exploring Public Administration’s Policy Imprint.”


Administration and Society, Forthcoming.

Shultz, Duane. History of Modern Psychology. 2nd edition New York: Academic Press, 1975.

Simon, Herbert. Administrative Behavior (second edition) New York: Free Press. 1957 (first printed
1945)

Simon, Herbert. Models of Man. New York 1957.

Soccio, Douglas. Archetypes of Wisdom: An Introduction to Philosophy. Belmont CA: Wadsworth


Publishing Co. 1992.

Stever, James. "Technology, Organization, Freedom: the Organization Theory of John Dewey."
Administration and Society 24 (February 1993):419-443.

Stillman, II, Richard. Preface to Public Administration: A Search for Themes and Direction. New
York: St. Martains Press. 1990.

Suckiel, Ellen, Kappy. The Pragmatic Philosophy of William James. Notre Dame: University of
Notre Dame Press. 1982.

van Fraassen, Bas. “To Save the Phenomena.” in Readings in the Philosophy of Science, 2nd
edition. pp.58-64. Edited by Baruch Brody and Richard Grandy. Englewood Cliffs, New
Jersey: Prentice Hall, 1989.

Waldo, Dwight. “The Administrative State Revisited.” Public Administration Review, 25,(March
1965) :1-27.

Waldo, Dwight. "A Theory of Public AdministrationMeans in Our Times a Theory of Politics
Also." In Public Administration: The State of the Discipline. pp.73-83. Edited by Naoni B.
Lynn and Aaron Wildavsky. Chatham, New Jersey: Chatham House Publishers, Inc. 1990.

Westbrook, Robert, John Dewey and American Democracy.Ithaca New York: Cornell University
Press. 1991.

Wildavsky, Aaron. Speaking Truth to Power. Boston: Little, Brown and Company, 1979.

Wilson, James Q. Bureaucracy: What Government Agencies Do and Why They Do It. Basic Books,
1989.

Wilson, Woodrow. "The Study of Administration." In Classics of Public Administration, pp.3-17.


Edited by Jay Sharfritz and Albert Hyde. Oak Park, Ill.: Moore Publishing Co., 1978.

19
Yin, Robert. Case Study Research: Design and Methods. Newbury Park CA: Sage
Publications,1988.

20
View publication stats

You might also like