CopyrightX - Lecture Transcripts Book PDF
CopyrightX - Lecture Transcripts Book PDF
Based on the Lectures of Prof. William W. Fisher III, Harvard Law School
Compiled by Marc Pelteret, student of CopyrightX: UCT 2017
There are many ways to learn, and which way is best is up to the individual to decide. Personally, I
find it quicker and easier to read rather than listen to lectures. Because of this, I decided to extract
the transcriptions of Prof. Fisher’s excellent lectures from the YouTube videos. Only later I did I
discover that the FLAX project (http://flax.nzdl.org) had already done this. What the project lacks,
however, is the visual references, and so I decided to continue with my effort to create a
comprehensive set of transcripts, complete with as much referenced material as possible.
This text includes most images, diagrams, graphs and textual material referenced in the video
lectures. Some material was left out because while it is interesting to see, it is not critical to
understanding the subject and would only have extended the length of the text. Many of the
diagrams and graphs were re-drawn, initially just to make a few of them clearer, but later to ensure
they have a consistent look. In a few cases I added extra detail.
Most of the text is a direct transcription of Prof. Fisher’s videos. Some editing was necessary
to refer to figures and tables, rather than the screen. Additional editing was done to correct
mistakes in the transcriptions, remove repetition (particularly in the introduction of each lecture),
and to improve the readability of the text.
Following Prof. Fisher’s example, this work is released under the Creative Commons
Attribution 4.0 License. I may revise it as the lecture videos are updated, but if I do not, others are
welcome to do so. A list of which versions of the videos the text is based on can be found in
Appendix B.
I hope you find this document useful, and the course as enjoyable and interesting as I did.
Many thanks to Prof. Fisher and Dr. Tobias Schonwetter of the Dept. of Commercial Law at the
University of Cape Town for all the work they put into presenting a very worthwhile course.
Marc Pelteret
Student of the CopyrightX: UCT 2017 at the University of Cape Town in South Africa
1.1. Introduction
This is the introduction to a series of twelve lectures on copyright. My hope, in these lectures, is
to provide you the following things:
▪ First, an understanding of the basic principles of copyright law.
▪ Second, an appreciation of the ways in which that law affects, for better and
worse, creativity and innovation in a wide variety of artistic and technical fields.
(To that end, I will be providing you, along the way, illustrations of the ways that
copyright works in literature; music; film; photography; graphic art; software;
comedy; fashion; architecture; and so forth.)
▪ Third, I will try to provide you a critical understanding of the main theories of
copyright by which I mean, the arguments, developed over several centuries by
economists, philosophers, and political theorists, concerning the purposes or
functions of the copyright system.
These theories are not mere matters of academic curiosity and dispute.
Copyright law is changing very fast, in part in an attempt to address new technologies, and
the lawmakers who are making the changes are influenced by and in turn help to shape the
competing theories of copyright. So, to understand where the law is going and certainly if you
wish to affect its trajectory you need to know a fair amount about theory.
This bring me to the fourth and last of the ambitions: By the end of these lectures, I hope
to have increased your ability and confidence to make informed judgments concerning how, if at
all, the copyright system should be reformed.
So, to summarize: copyright law; its impact on creativity; theories of copyright; and ways
in which the system could be improved those are the general themes I will be addressing. The
themes are intertwined, of course, and I will try to identify, in the lectures, the relationships
among them.
The topics of the twelve lectures, in which I will be addressing these themes are set forth
in Table 1. This first lecture is called “the foundations of copyright law.” Once I am finished with
the introductory material, I will discuss three aspects of copyright that can be thought of as
fundamental:
▪ the concept of originality;
▪ the crucial distinctions in copyright law between ideas, facts, and expression;
▪ and the system of multilateral treaties that constrain the freedom of almost all
countries when shaping and administering their national copyright systems.
Along the way, I will discuss some current controversies that those basic principles affect.
The second lecture will examine and contrast two theories of copyright law specifically the
fairness theory, which is especially prominent in countries (like Great Britain, the United States,
and Australia) that have been influenced by the common-law legal tradition; and the personality
or personhood theory, which tends to be somewhat more prominent in countries (including
Continental Europe and Latin America) that have been influenced by the civil-law tradition.
In the third lecture, we will return to legal doctrine. Specifically, I will survey the kinds of
original works that are subject to copyright protection. Some of these (such as novels, musical
compositions, and films) will be unsurprising. Others (such as software, fictional characters, and
three-dimensional useful objects) may be somewhat more eye-opening.
The fourth lecture will concentrate on the most complex of the copyright theories: the
welfare theory, an outgrowth of the philosophic tradition of utilitarianism. As we will see, this
theory has growing influence, certainly among scholars and increasingly among lawmakers, in all
jurisdictions in the world.
The fifth lecture will consider the complex set of rules that define the term, “author” –
and identify the persons and organizations that qualify as authors.
The sixth lecture, entitled “the mechanics of copyright,” considers how the copyright
system works in practice. I will discuss, for example,
▪ what, if anything, an author must do to secure copyright protection;
▪ the preconditions for bringing a copyright infringement suit;
▪ how long copyrights last;
▪ how the rights associated with copyright are transferred from one person to
another;
Figure 1: “The Thinker” by Auguste Rodin Figure 2: “Mona Lisa” by Leonardo da Vinci
Here’s a more plausible example: Rodin’s famous sculpture, “The Thinker,” was created in
1902 – and thus (as we will see) is no longer subject to copyright protection. Suppose that you
make a perfect replica of The Thinker. Do you have a copyright in your replica? In other words, if
someone copies your replica, do you have a legal claim against the copyist? No. The same
principle applies – certainly in the US and probably in other countries – if you take a photograph
of an old painting, like the Mona Lisa, trying to recreate the painting exactly. This is not a
hypothetical example. A few years ago, there was a sharped-edged controversy between the
National Portrait Gallery in England and one Derrick Coetzee, who uploaded to Wikipedia some
3000 high-resolution photos, taken by the Portrait Gallery, of old paintings in its collection.
Coetzee invoked this principle when resisting, successfully, the Gallery’s copyright claims:
because the photos lacked originality, they were not shielded by copyright.
Borrowed the work must indeed not be, for a plagiarist is not himself pro tanto an
“author”; but if by some magic, a man who had never known it were to compose anew
Keats’s Ode on a Grecian Urn, he would be an “author,” and, if he copyrighted it, others
might not copy that poem, though they might of course copy Keats’s.
In other words, if your creation is identical to an already existing work, but you are
genuinely unaware of that existing work, your creation is original, and you get the benefit of
copyright protection. Novelty is not necessary.
To be sure, as Professor Paul Goldstein observes, lack of novelty, though not itself fatal,
may sometimes be introduced in litigation to undermine other aspects of a plaintiff’s case. For
example, it can be used to rebut a presumption that the plaintiff’s work was independently
created – which, as we’ve seen, is required for copyright protection. Or a defendant can
sometimes use the fact that the plaintiff’s work is not novel to argue that the defendant did not
copy the plaintiff’s work, but instead copied the preexisting work. That’s the import of the last
clause in Judge Hand’s statement – “though they might of course copy Keats’s.” If true, that
would get the defendant off the hook. The upshot is that, in practice, novelty helps a plaintiff,
and lack of novelty can hurt. But strictly speaking, novelty is not required for copyright
protection.
Another thing that is not required for copyright protection – at least in the United States –
is intent to be original. To get the benefit of copyright protection, it’s not necessary that you, the
author, try to create something of your own. It’s only necessary that you do so. The classic
statement of this principle in US law comes in an opinion by Judge Jerome Frank in the 1951
Alfred Bell case, which held that, even if mezzotint engravings of old (public-domain) paintings
differed from the originals only inadvertently, they were still copyrightable. “A copyist’s bad
eyesight or defective musculature, or a shock caused by a clap of thunder, may yield sufficiently
distinguishable variations. Having hit upon such a variation unintentionally, the ‘author’ may
adopt it as his and copyright it.” As you might imagine, this issue doesn’t arise often, and one
can find some judicial opinions that seem to cast doubt upon it. But the principle expressed by
Judge Hand is the canonical view in the United States.
A third thing not required for copyright protection is that the work in question be artistic.
If your creation is bad art – or not art at all – you still get a copyright in it. The classic statement
of this principle comes in the 1903 Bleistein case, which involved a copyright claim to three
circus posters, one of which is shown in Figure 3. In some famous passages in the majority
opinion in that case, Justice Holmes rejected the defendant’s argument that these posters did
not enjoy copyright protection because they did not constitute “fine art.” In US law, Bleistein has
come to stand for the principle sometimes referred to as “aesthetic neutrality.” When applying
copyright law, the quality or artistic character of both the plaintiff’s work and the defendant’s
work are said to be irrelevant. A child’s finger paintings are as deserving of copyright protection
as the Mona Lisa. Why? What might justify this stance of strict aesthetic neutrality? Defenders of
this principle commonly make four arguments. The first is that judges (or juries) who would be
called upon to assess the merit of either the plaintiff’s or the defendant’s works lack the
expertise to do so. Justice Holmes emphasizes this point in Bleistein:
The second argument, latent in the last sentence of Holmes’ passage, is fear of elitism –
worry that an upper class would use the opportunity to assess artistic quality to impose their
tastes on the rest of the population. The third, related argument is fear of paternalism – or what
has come more recently to be called parentalism. This argument is tied to the political theory of
liberalism, which continues to have considerable sway at least in western democratic societies.
The basic idea is that governments should not impose on their citizens any particular conception
of the good – or the good life in particular – but rather should create conditions in which people
are free to formulate and pursue their own conceptions of the good. One implication of that
idea, it is sometimes argued, is that the law – specifically copyright law – should not promulgate
a particular conception of what counts as worthy art. In the United States, this attitude finds
expression in periodic campaigns to abolish the National Endowment for the Arts, which
distributes government funds to artists. Most other countries are less hostile to government
support for the arts.
The final argument in favor of the principle of aesthetic neutrality is that to decide what
constitutes good art, one needs to know what art is, and there’s deep disagreement on that
crucial question. As Professor Fred Yen has pointed out, at least three different meanings of art
are in widespread circulation. Formalism, exemplified by the work of Clive Bell, defines art as
things capable of provoking in sensitive people the aesthetic emotion. Some objects have formal
qualities that enable them to cause this reaction while others don’t. Only the former count as
art. By contrast intentionalism, exemplified by the work of Monroe Beardsley, defines art as
“something produced with the intention of giving it the capacity to satisfy the aesthetic
interest.” So, for example, whether people moving in a circle are engaged in a form of art
depends on the nature of their motivation. Their purpose might be religious (as in a ceremony),
it might be political or economic (as in a picket line), or it might be artistic (as in the dance). Only
if their intention falls into the last category does their behavior constitute art. Finally,
institutionalism, exemplified by the work of George Dickie, emphasizes the role of the “art
world” – ““[t]he broad social institution in which works of art have their place.” The members of
this world include artists and viewers who participate in the traditional social practice of
creating, presenting, and appreciating art. Against this backdrop, “objects become art when
someone who believes that he is a member of the art world invites others to view the object
from her. The court eventually ruled that, despite the large number of similar scenes, Haley had
not engaged in copyright infringement. One of the grounds on which the court rejected many of
the plaintiffs’ assertions is that they involved so-called scenes a faire. Here’s the language in
which the court expresses this judgment: “These are incidents, characters or settings which are
as a practical matter indispensable, or at least standard, in the treatment of a given topic.
Attempted escapes, flights through the woods pursued by baying dogs, the sorrowful or happy
singing of slaves, the atrocity of the buying and selling of human beings, and other miseries are
all found in stories at least as old as Mrs. Stowe’s. Other examples include scenes portraying sex
between male slave owners and female slaves and the resentment of the female slave owners;
the sale of a slave child away from her family and the attendant agonies; the horror of punitive
mutilation; and slave owners complaining about the high price of slaves.” All of these images,
the court ruled, constituted unprotected ideas, because they were standard vignettes in the
genre of US slave narratives.
Some more recent, and perhaps surprising, applications of this doctrine of scenes a faire
involve photography. Here too, courts refuse to grant copyright protection to images that they
conclude are standard or typical of a particular genre. For example, in the 2005 case of Bill
Diodata Photography versus Kate Spade, the plaintiff contended that the photograph on the left
of Figure 5, which appeared in an advertisement for women shoes, was infringed by the one on
the right. The court rejected the argument, arguing that the positioning of a model sitting on the
toilet with her feet angled inward, though “seemingly unnatural,” was a common trope;
photographing stylish women in this pose to showcase fashion accessories was an idea “used
often in popular culture.” Similarly, in the 2003 Gentieu case (Figure 6), the photograph on the
right side was held not to infringe the copyright in the photograph on the left side, because,
even if one photographer had been imitating the other, the compositional elements they had in
common were “standard photographic conventions or devices” and thus not copyrightable.
Figure 8: A maps showing the Berne Convention signatory countries (as of January 2016)
Three dimensions of the current version of the Berne Convention are crucial. The first is
the so-called national-treatment principle. Prior to the Berne Convention, some countries had
been chipping away at the widespread practice of discrimination against foreign authors through
adoption in bilateral treaties of the so-called reciprocity principle. As its name suggests, the
reciprocity principle depends upon two or more countries each extending rights to the residents
of the other(s). Country number #1 agrees to grant copyright protection to the residents of
Country number #2 if and only if Country #2 grants copyright protection to the residents of
Country #1. The Berne Convention – and, as we will see, all subsequent multilateral agreements
– repudiate the reciprocity principle in favor of the simpler and more powerful national-
2.1. Introduction
This second lecture turns from copyright law to copyright theory. By theory, I mean arguments
concerning when and why copyrights should be created, and what the scope or limit of those
rights should be. Next week in the third lecture, we’ll return to the law of copyright. Specifically,
I’ll examine the rules in the United States and in other countries that determine what kinds of
works fall within the zone of copyright protection.
Before zeroing in on the specific theories that will occupy us during this lecture, I should
say a bit more about what these theories do and why they matter.
Here’s the first and most obvious role of theory. As you might expect, when expanding or
revising copyright law, lawmakers frequently deploy arguments concerning how much legal
protection creative works ought to get. When engaged in debates of these sorts, lawmakers, or
their advisers, sometimes advert directly to formal theories developed by economists, political
theorists, and philosophers that address that issue, and even more often to less formal variants
of those theories in general circulation in popular discourse. The result is that, in order to
understand how copyright law has assumed over time its current form and how it’s likely to
evolve in the future, you need to know, among other things, the content of the theories that the
lawmakers in practice attend to.
The next role of theory is more instrumental. As you saw in the last lecture, and as you will
see frequently in future lectures, crucial doctrines in copyright law remain ambiguous. As a
result, lawyers, arguing for their clients, frequently are obliged to make normative arguments
about what the law should look like. Consequently, to be an effective advocate, or an informed
litigant, again you need to know the contents of the available theories that pertain to the
appropriate scope of copyrights. It’s not enough to know what the law is. You have to be able to
argue effectively about what it should be.
The third role of theory is, in my view, the most important. My goal is to help you make
your own informed judgments concerning the respects in which our current copyright system is
socially beneficial or pernicious and where the law should go tomorrow. This is a subject that
everyone has a stake in, not merely lawyers. Copyright law is changing very rapidly. Its impact on
2.2. Fairness
In 1783, the author Joel Barlow wrote a letter to the Continental Congress in the United States
urging the adoption of copyright legislation. Here’s the heart of his letter.
There is certainly no kind of property in the nature of things so much his own as the
works which a person originates from his own creative imagination. And when he has
spent great part of his life in study, wasted his time, his fortune, and perhaps his health
in improving his knowledge and correcting his taste, it is a principle of natural justice
that he should be entitled to the profits arising from the sale of his works as a
compensation for his labor in producing them, and his risk of reputation in offering
them to the public.
This letter was both influential and typical. 12 of the 13 American states adopted
copyright statutes, moved in large part by sentiments of the sort expressed in Barlow’s heartfelt
letter. Since then, authors, lobbyists, legislators, and judges have frequently invoked similar
arguments to justify or expand copyrights. An excellent collection of examples can be found in a
1996 article by Stewart Sterk. Here are a few. In 1906, the famous composer John Philip Sousa
sent a telegram to the chairman of the congressional committee considering legislation that
would have expanded public performance rights, in which Sousa argued as follows.
Earnestly request that the American composer receives full and adequate protection for
the product of his brain. Any legislation that does not give him absolute control of that
which he creates is a return to the usurpation of might and a check on the intellectual
development of our country.
An expansive declaration of this general sort of comes in the 1954 decision of the United
States Supreme Court in the case of Mazer versus Stein.
Sacrificial days devoted to such creative activities deserve rewards commensurate with
the services rendered.
Though the Earth and all inferior creatures be common to all men, yet every man has a
property in his own person. This, nobody has any right to but himself. The labor of his
body and the work of his hands, we may say, are properly his. Whatsoever, then, he
removes out of the state that nature hath provided and left it in, he hath mixed his
labor with and joined to it something that is his own, and thereby, makes it his
property. It being by him removed from the common state nature placed it in, it hath,
All of this happens, Locke argued, in a state of nature. In other words, the farmer’s rights
are natural rights, not dependent upon state recognition. But once a state is formed, it has a
duty to recognize and enforce natural rights acquired in this fashion. According to Locke, the
ability of a person to acquire natural property rights in this fashion is, however, limited in three
ways. These limitations are commonly known as provisos.
The first is known as the sufficiency proviso. According to Locke, the acquisition of natural
property rights by the farmer only occurs if he has left, as you’ll recall, as much and as good for
others. This restriction is analytically very important, as we’ll see. But to Locke, it did not seem
especially problematic because, at the time he wrote, the world contained lots of what Locke
thought of as unowned land, most notably in North America. Today, of course, the sufficiency
proviso would impose much stricter limits on the ability of a person to acquire real property
through labor.
The second proviso is known as the spoilage proviso. According to Locke, if the farmer has
grown so many crops that he’s unable to consume them and they rot in his barn, he not only
forfeits his right to the unused crops, but also his right to as much of the land as was necessary
to grow them. In other words, his legitimate holding shrinks. Again, this restriction was not
particularly important for Locke because in his view, it was rendered largely irrelevant by the
invention of money. After the adoption of a medium of exchange, if you grew more crops than
you could eat, you could exchange the surplus for hard currency, which you could then use to
purchase other goods and services. The result? A surplus did not go to waste, and the legitimacy
of your holdings was not threatened.
The third and last of the provisos, less clearly recognized in chapter five but implicit in
other portions of Locke’s work, is sometimes referred to as the duty of charity. This restriction,
emphasized by Wendy Gordon in a pioneering article, entails an obligation to let others share
one’s property in times of great need, so long as one’s own survival is not threatened.
So, that, in brief, is the core of Locke’s general theory of private property. Many nuances
and controversies lurk in this quick summary. In particular, I have not said anything about the
longstanding debate concerning the extent to which Locke should be understood as an apologist
for capitalism. If you’re curious about such matters, feel free to explore some of the materials
listed in the bibliography, to which there’s a link on the map. But we’re going to press on to
consider the application of Locke’s theory of real property to copyright.
It’s widely thought that Locke’s theory provides an even stronger justification for
intellectual property than it does for property in the land. The following circumstances underlie
this assumption. First, the public domain, by which I mean the large body of unowned cultural
In my research, I’ve become convinced that with our current tools, we will never
identify the optimal number of patented copyrighted and trademarked works. Every
time I play the archaeologist and go looking for the utilitarian footings of the field, I
come up empty. Try as I might, I simply cannot justify our current IP system on the basis
of verifiable data showing that people are better off with IP law than they would be
without it. Maximizing utility, I’ve come to see, is not a serviceable first-order principal
of the IP system. It’s just not what IP is really all about at the deepest level.
2.3. Personality
The famous architect Meinhard von Gerkan designed the striking building shown in Figure 9. It
serves as a train station in Berlin. It stands on an historically important spot, in what we used to
Years ago, I was having lunch one day with a cartoonist, Richard Guindon, and the
subject came up how neither of us ever solicited or accepted ideas from others. But
until Richard summed it up quite neatly, I never really understood my own aversions to
doing this. “It’s like having someone else write in your diary,” he said. And how true
that statement rang with me. In effect, we drew cartoons that we hoped would be
entertaining, or at the very least, not boring. But regardless, they would always come
from an intensely personal, and therefore, original perspective. To attempt to be funny
is a very scary, risk-laden proposition. Ask any stand-up comic who’s ever bombed on
stage. But if there was ever an axiom to follow in this business, it would be this – be
honest to yourself, and most important, respect your audience. So, in a nutshell –
probably an unfortunate choice of words for me – I only ask that this respect be
returned. And the way for anyone to do this is to please, please refrain from putting
The Far Side out on the internet. These cartoons are my children of sorts. And like a
parent, I’m concerned about where they go at night without telling me. And seeing
them at someone’s website is like getting the call at 2:00 in the morning that goes,
“Uh, dad, you’re not going to like this much, but guess where I am.”
Two aspects of this letter bear emphasis – first, the contention that public self-expression
is very scary and risky, and the law should help create conditions that enable and encourage it;
and second, the conception of one’s artistic creations as one’s children. The need to control
those creations, Larson argues, is like the need to keep track of one’s kids. When we examined
Locke’s theory of property, we saw that only some of the ways in which he fleshed out his
arguments seemed germane to intellectual property. The same is true here. In my tour of the 10
variants of personality theory, I’ve tried to flag those that seemed most relevant to the interests
of artists. I hope, by now, it’s clear that those are numbers 2, 5, 8, and 10. To review,
maintenance of artists’ ability to control, at least in some ways, their creations is arguably
necessary to respect, first, their privacy; next, their capacity to achieve individual self-realization;
next, their identities; and finally, their opportunities for self-expression. The countries where
belief in these connections had the greatest influence are located in continental Europe. Not
surprisingly, those same countries have the legal systems that are most protective of artists.
Figure 12: The real Vanna White and the image of the robot in the Samsung advert
would be turned not by Vanna White, the actress who had become famous in this role, but by a
robot, which would literally take White’s place.
Shown in Figure 12, on the left side is the real Vanna White, and on the right side, a blow-
up of the image of the robot that appeared in the Samsung ad. White argued plausibly that the
early 20th century, by contrast, they thought it shielded the market value of the underlying work,
no matter how it was expressed. As we’ll see in lecture number seven, the effect of this
reconceptualization was to render illegal, for the first time, many forms of unauthorized use,
including translations, abridgments, and, perhaps most importantly, motion picture adaptations.
Now that we’ve completed a brief historical overview of the growth of US copyright law
during the last two centuries, let’s go back and examine in more detail each of the sectors of
copyrightable subject matter. For this purpose, we’ll be using the map on copyright law, which I
hope is by now familiar to you. As I mentioned, during this survey I’ll highlight the ways in which
the rules governing the different kinds of things now subject to copyright protection vary, and
how, as a result, the business models associated with those types of works also differ. The
underlying thesis, to repeat, is that the copyright system is disaggregated.
As the map indicates, the statutory basis for the subject matter coverage of copyright is
Section 102 of the federal statute. In the first lecture in this series, we discussed subsection
102(b), which embodies, as we saw there, the idea/expression distinction, and related grounds
for excluding work from copyright protection. We now focus on 102(a), which details the kinds
of things that copyrighted law includes. As you can see, the language of 102(a) is capacious. It
itemizes various kinds of things that are subject to copyright protection, but it also includes a
blanket clause indicating that quote “original works of authorship, of any sort, can be
protected”. In other words, the itemized list below is non-exhaustive.
(a) Copyright protection subsists, in accord-ance with this title, in original works of
authorship fixed in any tangible medium of expression, now known or later developed,
from which they can be perceived, reproduced, or otherwise com-municated, either
directly or with the aid of a machine or device. Works of authorship include the
following categories:
(b) In no case does copyright protection for an original work of authorship extend to
any idea, procedure, process, system, method of operation, concept, principle, or
discovery, regardless of the form in which it is described, explained, il-lustrated, or
embodied in such work.
The first entry in the itemized list consists of literary works. Such works are often thought
to be the heart of copyright protection. Included in this category are many things you would
naturally think of as literary – for example, novels, short stories, poems, newspaper or magazine
articles, and so forth. Also included are some less obvious things, such as catalogs, and, as we
saw earlier, advertising copy. Last, but not least, the term “literary works” is now construed to
incorporate computer software. The history and economic implications of this highly counter-
intuitive interpretation are very complicated.
Here’s a brief introduction to the topic of software, a subject to which we’ll return several
times. Before plunging into the details of the law, it’s important to differentiate the kinds of
activities that some – not all – software firms hope to curb.
The first consists of consumer reproduction of object code. By object code, I mean the
collection of ones and zeros that embody the working version of the program. By consumer
reproduction, I mean the behavior of individual software users. So, for example, if I borrowed a
Figure 15: A timeline of the creation of forms of intellectual property for software
Recall our discussion in lecture number one of the principle of aesthetic neutrality, which
is commonly traced in the 1903 Bleistein case. The passage I just read is one of the many
examples of judges ignoring that ostensible principle altogether. The unfortunate effect of such
cases is that some famous and deserving choreographers were left out in the cold. For example,
Agnes de Mille choreographed Oklahoma, which was – and deserved to be – one of the most
popular musicals of all time. Her dances – in particular, the dream ballet – contributed
importantly to the plot of the play. She was paid a modest contract price by the producers,
reportedly $15,000. However, unlike Rogers and Hammerstein, who composed the musical score
for the play, de Mille received no royalties when it was produced, because her choreography,
unlike their musical compositions, enjoyed no copyright protection. The gap in the law – the
absence of protection for choreography – was filled as part of a comprehensive 1976 reform,
which became effective the start of 1978. The result is that today, choreographers enjoy the
same copyright protection as do playwrights. Unfortunately, it’s not always clear what
constitutes choreography. What about figure skating routines, for example? The statute itself
does not define the term. The Copyright Office has developed its own definition:
Courts, when construing the copyright statute, are not bound by this administrative
decision. But they tend to give it weight. As dance and performance art continue to evolve in the
future, tricky questions concerning the scope of this definition are likely to arise with increased
frequency.
A work is fixed in a tangible medium when its embodiment in a copy or phono record by
or under the authority of the author is sufficiently permanent or stable to permit it to
be perceived, reproduced, or otherwise communicated for a period of more than
transitory duration. A work consisting of sounds, images, or both that are being
transmitted is fixed for the purposes of this title if a fixation of the work is being made
simultaneously with this transmission.
The overwhelming majority of works for which authors might seek copyright protection
easily satisfy this standard. Novelists typically write their novels down. Photographers capture
their images in negatives, prints, digital files, and so forth. However, on occasion, potentially
copyrightable works fail to qualify for protection because their creators neglect this
requirement. So, for example, if a jazz musician in a live, unrecorded performance improvises in
an original way on a classic public domain composition, that musician will get no copyright
protection in his innovation. As a matter, this means that a member of the audience, after
hearing the performance, is free to perform or record it himself without fear of copyright
liability.
Here’s a hypothetical case that may suggest the scope of the fixation requirement. A
mandala is a highly-detailed painting typically made out of fine-grained colored sand by Buddhist
monks or priests. Mandalas represent the dwelling spaces of tantric deities. Most are elaborate,
and require a long time to create, but they don’t last long. If they’re jostled, they disappear.
More importantly, it’s conventional, after completing a mandala, to undo it by pouring the sand
into a body of water, often a river. Among other things, this custom emphasizes the
impermanence of possessions and the importance of not being too attached to them.
Traditionally, mandalas were created and dissolved in private religious ceremonies. Recently,
however, the Dalai Lama has encouraged monks to create them in public, in part to educate
people about the culture. Some have been created, briefly, in the United States. In the unlikely
event that a creator of a mandala sought copyright protection in it, would he trip over the
fixation requirement? In other words, would he lose because this work was not fixed in a
tangible medium of expression? Probably not. A mandala is not fixed in the ordinary sense, but it
would seem to qualify under the statutory definition. Its embodiment in sand is “sufficiently
stable to permit it to be perceived or reproduced for a period of more than transitory duration,”
as is evidenced by the existence of the photo above. Parenthetically, the monk might trip over a
separate requirement for copyright – namely, the originality requirement discussed in lecture
number one. The reason is that the mandalas created by monks typically replicate traditional
designs. But the fixation requirement would probably not be a problem.
Returning to the topic at hand. The primary form of creative work that with some
frequency does run afoul of the fixation requirement is choreography. The reason is that
choreographers commonly fail to write down their innovations. In part, this is because it used to
be difficult to do so. Dance notation has existed for a long time, but it’s cumbersome and
incomplete. Nowadays, it’s easier to fix a choreographic work. The standard method is to
videotape a rehearsal. Nevertheless, some choreographers still forget this. In the United States,
the result is that they forfeit copyright protection.
Stepping back from this example. What underlies the fixation requirement in general?
There are two standard answers, but neither is particularly persuasive. The first answer is that
the language of the constitutional provision that, in the United States, underlies copyright law,
limits its scope to “writings.” An ephemeral work, it is sometimes said, does not qualify as a
writing. In light of how broadly the term writing is construed in other contexts – to incorporate,
as we’ve seen, software and photos, for example – this textual argument seems weak. The
second explanation is that there’s an important policy underlying the requirement of fixation –
namely, that it serves an evidentiary function. Supposedly, it forces authors and artists to write
down their works and the result is to provide judges and juries who are called upon to resolve
subsequent disputes good information concerning what exactly those works contained.
This argument is a branch of a policy argument one finds in many fields of the law. The
basic idea is that formalities have important social functions. So, for example, the rule found in
many jurisdictions that a will indicating who gets your property on your death must be written
3.3. Music
Copyrights in music differ from copyrights in literary and dramatic works in several ways.
Perhaps the most important is that there are two different kinds of copyrights that involve
music. The more traditional of the two are copyrights in musical compositions. As you can see,
section 102 (a), refers to these as copyrights in musical works, including any accompanying
words. These have been around for a very long time. The second type, which was added to the
federal copyright statute only in 1972, consists of copyrights in sound recordings. As I mentioned
earlier, in most countries legal rights to sound recordings are known as neighboring rights. In the
United States, however, they are referred to as copyrights.
The legal rights associated with these two types of copyrights and the complex business
models that capitalize on those rights are perhaps best seen by tracing the life history of a
typical piece of popular music. I’m going to tell this hypothetical story using a diagram (Figure
17). As you’ll soon see, the narrative is complicated. Don’t be discouraged if not all features of
the story are clear right now. We’ll return to it several times during this lecture series.
Imagine that I’m a pretty good composer, but not much of a musician. I compose a song.
It has a memorable melody and some conventional sentimental lyrics. I wrote it down on some
sheet music, so I satisfy the fixation requirement. I thereby, as you know, acquire a copyright in
my composition. I could if I wanted retain ownership of my copyright, but as a typical composer I
lack the business skills or time necessary to exploit it effectively. So instead, as is now customary
in the United States, I sign all of my rights to a music publisher. There are tens of thousands of
these in this country. From this point forward in the story, the publisher will retain the copyright
and the composition. In other words, the publisher will not assign it further. Rather, the
publisher will make money for itself and for me by issuing licenses to a variety of other
organizations – in other words, permissions to engage in activities that otherwise would violate
copyright. The most important of these licenses consist of the right to make so-called
mechanical copies of the composition. Typically, such a mechanical license will be issued to a
record company, which is interested in making and selling sound recordings of my composition.
The independent rights of the musician who actually makes that recording we’ll discuss in a
minute. Back to the narrative, the publisher could in principle enter into such a license with the
record company on its own, but it’s customary in the United States to use the services of an
intermediary, namely the Harry Fox Agency.
If the CD and other products embodying the recording of my song are commercially
successful, the music publisher, who as we saw now holds the copyright in it, will begin to
exploit other licensing opportunities. For example, the publisher will likely issue a reproduction
license to one of the four major sheet music printers in the United States, which will then print
and sell sheet music, which in turn will be purchased by amateur guitarists who want to learn
how to play my song. If the song is sufficiently popular and evocative that a movie studio wants
to include in the soundtrack of a movie, then the music publisher and the studio will negotiate a
so-called synchronization, or sync, license. If there’s demand for my music in other countries, the
publisher will likely issue a so-called sub-publishing license to a similar publisher in one or more
other countries. The terms of these several contracts will vary, but it’s typical for the music
publisher to turn over to me half of the license revenues it earns from these various sources,
keeping the remainder, of course, for itself.
So now let’s return to the musician, the performer, whose recorded rendition of my song
is crucial to the success of my composition (refer to Figure 21). As I mentioned earlier, the
creative contributions of the performer will generate a second independent copyright in the
Figure 18: Parties involved in the copyrighting and licensing of sound recordings, and their interactions
The broadcasters, for their part, continue to push back. Set forth in Figure 20 is their own
summary of their stance. Notice that they continue to emphasize the “free promotion” that
Issue
During the past two Congresses, at the behest of the big record labels, a bill was
introduced to impose a new performance fee, or tax, on local radio broadcasters. The
Performance Rights Act would have imposed a devastating new government mandated
fee on local stations simply for airing music on the radio – airing the music that
provides free promotion to the labels and performers. A performance tax could
financially cripple local radio stations putting jobs at risk, stifle new artists trying to
break into the recording business and harm the listening public who rely on local radio.
To date, no performance tax legislation has been formally re-introduced in the 112th
Congress, although Rep. Nadler (NY-08) recently circulated a draft bill to the same
effect.
For better or worse, this is a reasonably good illustration of the way in which lobbying
over copyright typically works. For more details concerning the still ongoing negotiation over this
particular issue, follow the link shown on the left-hand side of these two slides.
Figure 21: Parties involved in the copyrighting and licensing of sound recordings and the payments between
them (in green)
This song has inspired generations of musicians. A few of the many commercially
distributed covers are shown in Table 2. Some of these covers could fairly be described as
faithful adaptations that preserved the essential character of Hendrix’s original. An example
might be the version by Santana and Joe Cocker. Here it is.
I hope you’ll recall from the last lecture our discussion of the powerful bond that many
artists feel with their creations. That bond, you’ll remember, prompted the sculptor Michael
Snow to object when ribbons were hung on the necks of his geese and underlay Gary Larson’s
plea to his fans not to use his cartoons in their websites. The law, as we saw, often comes to the
aid of such artists, particularly in countries that recognize strong versions of moral rights. By
contrast, the law, and consequently the culture, of the music industry is radically different.
Composers know that once they have authorized the commercial distribution of one recording
of their composition they could no longer enjoy what in moral-rights terms is referred to as a
right of integrity. In other words, they can’t prevent other musicians from altering their creations
by making and distributing covers, some of which will be very different from the versions the
composers had in mind. Nor may the first recording artist object when a second recording artist
makes a cover. Interestingly neither composers nor performers seem especially troubled by this
prospect. And the legal privilege of making covers has an important cultural benefit. Each
generation of musicians can test their skills, can show their chops, by attempting their own
recorded renditions of the classic works of their predecessors. Now to be sure, they have to pay
a modest fee when they sell recordings of their adaptations, but they don’t have to ask
permission.
Does this seemingly fundamental difference between music on the one hand and other
fields of art reflect differences in the nature of the cultural products in question? For example,
the fact that most sculptures are unique, whereas sound recordings can be replicated
that’s rare. It’s much more likely that the producer will obtain a license to make a so-called
derivative work based upon the novel, leaving the copyright in the hands of the novelist.
What about the screenwriters, actors, director, and composer, whose work is, of course,
essential to convert the novel into a motion picture? Decades ago, it was common for the
producer or studio to hire such people as long-term employees, in which case their creative
contrib utions would belong to the producer or studio. Today, by contrast, these relationships
are more likely to be arm’s-length, but the legal outcome is similar. The way in which this is
achieved today is 66uthori h so-called work-for-hire agreements, which we’ll examine in detail
in lecture number five. If the movie is filmed on site, rather than in a studio lot, the producer
customarily obtains – and pays for – releases from the owners of the buildings that will appear in
the background of the scenes. It’s far from clear that such releases are legally required. Lawyers
for the producers typically take the position that the owners of the buildings have no
enforceable rights, and, thus, that the producer could, if it wished, make and show the film
without paying them anything. However, the insurance companies that provide the producers’
so-called errors and omissions insurance tend to be highly risk-averse, and demand that the
producers obtain these releases. If the producer wishes to include an existing sound recording in
the soundtrack of the movie, the producer will obtain a so-called master use license from the
record company that owns the copyright in the sound recording, and a synchronization license
from the music publisher that, as we saw, owns the copyright in the composition embodying the
recording.
What do these various artists and copyright owners obtain in return for entering into
these contracts and licenses? In most cases, they’re paid a negotiated flat fee. However, a few of
1909: statute reaches “works of art, models or design for works of art”
In the late 19th century, it was clear that copyright law did not extend to works of this sort.
Three-dimensional works of fine art were shielded, but not the kind of consumer products to
which I directed your attention a minute ago. Then gradually, through a series of steps itemized
on the map (and above), Congress, the Copyright Office, and the courts liberalized the relevant
rules in the United States. Today, the governing general principle is that copyright protection is
available to so-called “useful articles” if, and only, if the aesthetic and functional features of the
article at issue are separable.
The first step in applying this principle is to determine whether a particular object qualifies
as a “useful article” within the meaning of the copyright statute. The reason why this initial
determination is so important is that if an object does not constitute a useful article then the
ordinary more lenient rules of copyright law apply, whereas if it does constitute a useful article it
has to pass more stringent tests. So what does “useful article” mean? The statute defines it as
follows: “an article having an intrinsic utilitarian function that is not merely to portray the
appearance of the article or to convey information.” Some applications of this definition will be
straightforward. For example, Rodin’s sculpture does not constitute a useful article because its
function is to depict itself – to depict a thinker. By contrast, a lamp – no matter how beautiful –
is a useful article because it has a function other than looking good, namely illuminating the
room in which it's located. In other instances, however, application of this definition will be
trickier. If a particular object is deemed to fall into this special category then its creator gets
copyright protection, to repeat, only if its aesthetic and functional dimensions are separable.
How might they be separable? Traditionally there were two options. The first of these
options, which arises rarely, is that the aesthetic and functional dimensions might be physically
separable. For example, as the treatise writer Melville Nimmer suggests, the stylized Jaguar
shape that is attached to the hood of a Jaguar automobile enjoys copyright protection because it
can be physically removed from the car without impairing the car's utilitarian function. Likewise,
the utilitarian components of the car can be removed from the Jaguar without impairing its
aesthetic features. With respect to most useful articles, physical separability of this sort is not
Figure 24: Carol Barnhart Inc. v. Economy Cover Figure 25: Barry Kieselstein-Cord v.
Corporation (1985) – mannequins Accessories by Pearl, Inc. (1980) –
belt buckles
Figure 26: Brandir International, Inc. v. Cascade Pacific Lumber Co. – the Bandir ribbon rack
and the Supreme Court, seeking to resolve the conflict among the various courts of appeals on
this general question, agreed to hear the case. In the end the court, by a vote of 6 to 2, upheld
the Sixth Circuit's judgment that the uniforms did enjoy copyright protection. The majority
opinion, written by Justice Thomas, announced a new test for separability which will govern all
future cases involving useful articles. The key components of the new test are set below.
We hold that an artistic feature of the design of a useful article is eligible for copyright
protection if the feature (1) can be perceived as a two- or three-dimensional work of art
separate from the useful article and (2) would qualify as a protectable pictorial,
graphic, or sculptural work either on its own or in some other medium if imagined
separately from the useful article.
This new test, you should recognize, is a variation on the separate concept test originally
developed by Judge Newman – although, oddly, Justice Thomas did not acknowledge as much.
In his justification for this approach, Thomas expressly repudiated some of the other tests.
Goldstein's variant of the standalone test, Nimmer’s variant of the standalone test, and the
intent of the creator test that, as we saw, drove the Brandir bike rack case. Implicit in Thomas's
opinion is repudiation of the other pre-2017 approaches. The application of this new approach
to the facts of the case, Justice Thomas contended, was simple: one can easily identify the
decorations on the uniforms as features having pictorial, graphic, or sculptural qualities, thus
satisfying test one. As to test two, if the arrangement of colors, shapes, stripes and chevrons on
the surface of the cheerleading uniforms were separated from the uniform and applied in
another medium, they would of course qualify as two-dimensional works of art.
We don't yet know how this new approach will be interpreted and applied by the lower
courts, but already many legal commentators have weighed in and the large majority of
expressed disappointment or dismay. To be sure, a few aspects of the star test have been
praised. For example, by rejecting the subjective intent of the creator test, the Supreme Court
“An ‘architectural work’ is the design of a building as embodied in any tangible medium
of expression, including a building, architectural plans, or drawings. The work includes
the overall form as well as the arrangement and composition of spaces and elements in
the design, but does not include individual standard features.” § 101
Limited to “buildings”
Author = architect
Infringement
Effective 1990
Notice that it's limited to “architectural works,” which are defined as “the design of a
building.” Courts in the United States have construed building to be limited to freestanding
structures. The most important implication of this new statute is that in the United States
architectural works no longer have to run the gauntlet of the conceptual separability test in
order to be protected. To be sure, like all types of copyrighted work, a piece of architecture must
be original to be protectable, but as we've seen the standard for originality is very lenient.
Here's an example of a building design that would clearly pass muster. In 1989, the Polish-
born architect Daniel Libeskind won a competition to design the Jewish Museum in Berlin. Figure
29 shows a photograph of the building taken from directly above it and a second aerial
The new building is full of artistic expression: the architect Daniel Libeskind named it
“Between the Lines” on account of two linear shapes which form its structure. The “Line
of Connectedness” expressed in the window design symbolizes the cultural exchange
between Jews and non-Jews and the ways in which they influenced each other. The
“Line of the Voids” is a series of empty rooms, which runs in a straight but disrupted
line through the building. These empty rooms represent the cultural gaps left in
Germany after the Holocaust.
The groundplan has been interpreted in many different ways. Some see it as a lightning
bolt striking the city of Berlin. Daniel Libeskind, the architect, likens it to a
deconstructed star of David.
The Libeskind building is formed of two main lines: the line of connection, tortuous and
infinite, 78authorized the cultural exchange between Jews and Gentiles and their
mutual influences; a second line, straight but broken into discrete fragments, runs
through the length of the house – it is the line of the void.
His architectural partner and wife, Nina Libeskind, emphasized the theme mentioned at
the end of the second paragraph likening the shape of the building to a broken star of David. In
the late 1990s, the Australian architect Howard Raggatt was commissioned to design the new
National Museum of Australia to be located on a peninsula in the center of Canberra. Raggatt’s
much celebrated design is shown in the aerial photo in Figure 30. Until the Australian Museum
had been finished, no one, apparently, noticed the resemblance between its central building and
the Jewish Museum in Berlin, but once the connection was suggested, the parallelism became
unmistakable (see Figure 31).
This case never resulted in litigation. Had it done so, it most likely would have resulted in
liability. Since 1968, Australian copyright law has extended to, among other things, a building or
model of a building, whether the building remodel is of artistic quality or not. Certainly, if this
standard is construed in the same way that current US standard is construed, Libeskind’s design
would qualify for protection and the Australian building resembling it sufficient to satisfy the
legal standard of substantial similarity. The fact that the case nevertheless was not litigated
bears emphasis. Why not? We can't be sure, but probably two factors were at work. First,
copyright litigation is very time-consuming and expensive; as a result, only a tiny percentage of
potentially actionable cases ever end up in court. Second, architects – at least high-end
architects – seem especially loath to rely on copyright to protect their work. As David Shipley
Figure 31: Compare the National Museum of Australia (left) to the Jewish Museum in Berlin (right)
notes, the large majority of the cases that have been brought alleging violations of the
Architectural Works Copyright Protection Act involved not high-end buildings but mundane
mass-produced works. The designers of noteworthy buildings by contrast seem to rely more on
peer pressure and public condemnation to discourage knock-offs. Indeed, such extra-legal
sanctions were deployed in this particular instance. The Libeskinds publicly expressed outrage
United States Supreme Court, long ago when he was an 3. Opportunities for
assistant professor at Harvard Law School, wrote an article increasing excludability
developing this argument in the context of trade books. through self-help
One of Breyer’s contentions was that the writers and
4. Alternative motivations for
publishers of so-called trade books – for example, the
production
textbooks that are used in US high schools – enjoy at least
5. Philanthropy
a moderate lead time advantage. It takes a while, he
contended, to reproduce and redistribute books of the
sort. During the window of time before competitors can enter the field, the first publisher can
earn quite a bit. Perhaps enough to render uncertain the social need for copyright protection
with respect to such books. Hence the title of Breyer’s famous article, “The Uneasy Case for
Copyright.” Another context in which lead time may be sufficient adequately to support
innovation is fashion, meaning the design of high-end clothes. At least until recently, a fashion
designer enjoyed a window of time between the first introduction of a new design and the
moment when knock offs became available. During that window, the designer could and did sell
his or her dresses and suits for a very high price to wealthy and fashion conscious, or perhaps
prestige conscious, consumers. As a result, innovation has long flourished in fashion, despite the
fact that in many countries, including the United States, new clothing designers do not enjoy
copyright protection or indeed any other type of intellectual property protection. Now, this
argument, I hasten to add, is controversial. Some commentators and designers disagree sharply,
and most commentators acknowledge that the lead time window is getting shorter as the
technologies for quickly reverse engineering and replicating fashion innovations are advancing.
Another circumstance that may reduce the public goods problem and therefore reduce
the need for governmental involvement is the presence of customary or extralegal norms that
*
Benkler, “Coase’s Penguin” (2002) and Benkler, “Sharing Nicely” (2004).
Figure 44: The total profit for month 2 Figure 45: Price experimentation in month 3 and the
resultant revenue gain and loss
Figure 46: Price experimentation in month 4 and the Figure 47: The total profit in month 4
resultant revenue gain and loss
Figure 52: Purchase pricing for the short film Defending Our Lives.
Advantages
1. Relies upon the market to drive research toward areas of high social value
2. Relies upon private parties’ knowledge of the costs of R&D, marketing, etc.
3. Imposes costs of innovation upon (initial) users of the innovations
4. Competition in the quest for the pot of gold fosters fast, focused research
So, the map sets forth an initial catalog. As a mechanism for inducing socially beneficial
creativity, copyright has four main advantages. First, it relies upon the market to drive
innovation toward areas of high social value. Potential creators, knowing that their revenues will
be increased by the number of people who will purchase their products, direct their creative
energies towards zones where there are lots of potential customers and that, usually,
corresponds roughly to high social value. Now, not always. Research on new drugs, which tends
to focus on ailments that afflict the rich and neglects ailments that afflict the poor, is perhaps
the sharpest counterexample, but roughly.
Second, the copyright system does not rely upon government administrators to determine
the best paths for research and innovation. Instead, it places control in the hands of private
Disadvantages
1. Deadweight loss
2. Administrative and litigation costs
3. Impediments to cumulative innovation
4. Patent thickets
5. Rent dissipation
6. Ineffectiveness in digital environment
The first, we’ve already discussed in some detail. The pricing practices enabled by
copyright usually give rise to socially pernicious dead weight losses. To review, when the prices
of films or drugs rise, some people cannot afford them. At a minimum, that’s a cause for regret.
In some contexts, it can be tragic.
Next, copyright and patent systems have administrative and litigation costs. Significant
resources are devoted to lawyers and courts necessary to interpret and enforce authors’ rights.
From the standpoint of social welfare, that’s a waste.
All else being equal, where a plaintiff alleges that he exercised such a high degree of
control over a film operation, including the type and amount of lighting used, the
specific camera angles to be employed, and other detail-intensive artistic elements of a
film, such that the final product duplicates his conceptions and visions of what the film
should look like, the plaintiff may be said to be an author within the meaning of the
Copyright Act.
The principle that underlies this passage is important. To qualify as an author, it’s neither
necessary nor sufficient that you have your hands on the instruments that create the work. If
you direct the behavior of others sufficiently closely, that it’s your ideas that are being
Of genius the only proof is, the act of doing well what is worthy to be done, and what
was never done before. Of genius and the fine arts, the only infallible sign is the
widening of the sphere of human sensibility, for the delight, honor, and benefit of
human nature. Genius is the introduction of a new element into the intellectual
universe; or, if that be not allowed, it is the application of powers to objects on which
they had not before been exercised or the employment of them in such a manner as to
produce effects hitherto unknown.
This attitude was certainly not limited to writing. During this same period, individual
genius became the ideal in almost all fields of artistic endeavor. Closely connected to that ideal
was the image of an artist or author as aloof from the grubby business of commercial and
industrial life. The canonical image of the creative process became that of a solitary writer or
painter alone in the garret, pouring out his soul on paper or canvas. Another closely related idea
is that of art for art’s sake – disconnected from both utility and politics.
During the 19th century, this collection of attitudes – which together form the heart of
Romanticism – was reinforced by the broader ideological current known as classical liberalism.
We touched on this topic briefly in lecture number one. Among the features of 19th century
classical liberalism was a tendency to think of many aspects of individual and social life in terms
of dichotomies – sets of opposed polls. Such dichotomies included public versus private – in
other words, government versus civil society – self versus other, facts versus values, family
versus market, and – last but not least – art versus industry.
Copyright law was taking shape during this same historical period. It should not be
surprising that copyright bears the imprint of these ideas. At the most general level, the steady
expansion during the 19th century of the exclusive entitlements enjoyed by a copyright owner is
attributable, at least in part, to the glorification of artists and authors central to Romanticism.
But many more specific doctrines in copyright law also seem connected, these scholars argue, to
the attitudes associated with Romanticism. Here’s one. You’ll recall from lecture number three
that the 19th century witnessed an abstraction and extension of the concept of the work to
which copyright attaches. Take a novel, for example. As late as the 1850s, the protection
This sense of the past’s compelling pertinence, and of intellectual endeavor as the
medium through which interaction with and transmission of it was possible, permeated
virtually all facets of Chinese civilization. As the noted scholar of Chinese literature
Stephen Owen has observed, in the Chinese literary tradition “the experience of the
past roughly corresponds to and carries the same force as the attention to meaning or
truth in the Western tradition.” Thus, in classical Chinese literature, the past survives
and warrants consideration not merely as an obvious foil for contemporary activity,
but, more important, because “the Confucian imperative insists that in encountering
the ancients, we ourselves must be changed [for] we discover in the ancients not mere
means, but the embodiment of values.”
It should not be surprising that a country influenced heavily by this vision should have
been reluctant to adopt a copyright system centered on the image of an individual artistic
genius. And indeed, vestiges of that resistance continue in China today.
The line of scholarship I’ve been discussing has an important critical dimension. Thus far,
I’ve been emphasizing its explanatory side. If these scholars are correct, the impact of
Romanticism helps us understand how and why copyright law has assumed its current form. But
these scholars also contend that the law as currently configured is misguided – even perverse.
The image of author or artist as individual creative genius was rarely accurate, they argue, even
during its heyday. Since the 19th century, these scholars contend, it’s become ever less realistic
as an account of how most copyrighted works are in fact generated. The way in which software
is commonly produced, for example, bears little resemblance to the image of the painter alone
in the attic. The law, these scholars argue, clings stubbornly to an increasingly outmoded vision
of creativity whose inaccuracy causes both unfairness and misaligned incentives.
Not all intellectual property scholars are persuaded by this thesis. For example, Mark
Lemley – a leading intellectual property scholar now teaching at Stanford – argues that many
important features of modern copyright law cannot plausibly be traced to Romanticism and
States. For the time being, you need to know only that
works for hire are entirely exempt from that portion of the copyright statute. So, to repeat,
roughly half of the registered copyrights in the United States do not give rise to any moral rights.
The rules that we’ll discuss in detail next week concerning the termination of assignments
of copyrights are likewise inapplicable to works for hire. In addition, works for hire are governed
by different rules pertaining to duration. Regular copyrights, as you now know, last for the life of
the author plus 70 years. By contrast, works for hire last for 95 years from the date they are first
published, or 120 years from the date they are created, whichever is shorter. Sometimes this will
result in a longer term, sometimes a shorter term than a regular copyright, but it’s certainly
probably strikes you as odd. Why should the law deny access picture or other
to this particular legal form to some sets of parties? We’ll audiovisual work
come back to that question after we’ve examined these two c. Translation
paths in more detail.
d. Supplementary work
The first of the two paths likely strikes you as the more
(foreword, illustration,
intuitively plausible. Suppose you run a company, you hire
etc.)
someone, part of that person’s job is to create copyrightable
works. It’s not shocking, at least to most US residents, that you e. Compilation
the employer would own the copyright in those works. Millions f. Instructional text
of copyrighted works are born as works for hire in this way. g. Test
Their legal status rarely gives rise to litigation both because it’s h. Answer to a test
clear and to most observers it seems both fair and efficient.
i. Atlas
When litigation concerning this first path does arise, it’s usually
b. not really an employee. If
because the person who created the work can plausibly claim that he’s
he’s a traditional salaried employee, he has no chance of prevailing. But if his relationship with
the putative employer is more attenuated, he might. Until 1989, the legal standards used to
determine whether a creator was truly an employee for these purposes were murky. Different
courts adopted different rules. Finally, the Supreme Court attempted to settle the matter. The
case the Supreme Court chose to clarify the law involved interesting facts.
A nonprofit company called CCNV commissioned a sculptor, named James Earl Reid, to
prepare a sculpture commemorating homelessness. CCNV wanted to display the sculpture on
the mall in the center of Washington DC during the holiday season to sensitize visitors to the
plight of the homeless. CCNV gave Reid a fair amount of instruction concerning what it wanted.
For example, the sculpture should be a modern nativity scene in which the Holy Family is
among the nine types of works that can become works for hire through this path. Second, in any
event, the parties had not agreed in writing that the sculpture would be a work for hire, thus
CCNV was doubly blocked. The upshot was that CCNV’s only plausible theory was that Reid had
been an employee, not an independent contractor. If CCNV could classify Reid as an employee, it
could win under path one because the sculpture was surely within the scope of his employment.
The hard part was to show that he had been an employee. The trial court agreed with CCNV on
this crucial point, but the Court of Appeals and eventually the Supreme Court did not. In the
course of rejecting CCNV’s position, Justice Marshall writing for the Supreme Court announced a
new, or at least a clarified, test for determining when a person should be considered an
employee. It’s distilled in Table 3. Here is the key passage in the court’s opinion:
In determining whether a hired party is an employee under the general common law of
agency, we consider the hiring party’s right to control the manner and means by which
the product is accomplished. Among the other factors relevant to this inquiry are the
skill required, the source of the instrumentalities and tools, the location of the work, the
duration of the relationship between the parties, whether the hiring party has the right
to assign additional projects to the hired party, the extent of the hired party’s discretion
over when and how long to work, the method of payment, the hired party’s role in
hiring and paying assistants, whether the work is part of the regular business of the
hiring party, whether the hiring party is in business, the provision of employee benefits,
and the tax treatment of the hired party. No one of these factors is determinative.
True CCNV members directed enough of Reid’s work to ensure that he produced a
sculpture that met their specifications, but the extent of control the hiring party
exercises over the details of the product is not dispositive. Indeed, all the other
circumstances weigh heavily against finding an employment relationship. Reid is a
sculptor, a skilled occupation. Reid supplied his own tools. He worked in his own studio
in Baltimore, making daily supervision of his activities from Washington practically
impossible. Reid was retained for less than two months, a relatively short period of
time. During and after this time, CCNV had no right to assign additional projects to
Reid. Apart from the deadline for completing the sculpture, Reid had absolute freedom
to decide when and how long to work. CCNV paid Reid $15,000, a sum dependent upon
completion of a specific job, a method by which independent contractors are often
compensated. Reid had total discretion in hiring and paying assistants. Creating
sculpture was hardly regular business for CCNV. Indeed, CCNV is not a business at all.
Finally, CCNV did not pay payroll or Social Security taxes, provide any employee
benefits, or contribute to unemployment insurance or workers’ compensation funds.
Since 1989, courts confronted with analogous disputes have relied on this list of factors to
determine whether an artist in an ambiguous position should be considered an employee. A few
lower courts have tinkered with the test. For example, in one case the Court of Appeals for the
Second Circuit announced that a subset of the factors – specifically those highlighted by an
asterisk in Table 3 – are especially important and should be given extra weight. But most courts
just apply the CCNV list as the Supreme Court formulated it.
Disputes of this sort have not arisen terribly often in the past, but they’re likely to become
more common in the future. The reason is that in many modern economies, certainly including
that of the US, companies are decreasing their reliance on formal salaried employees and
increasing their reliance on people whose relationship to the company is more attenuated.
People hired for short periods of time not given traditional employment benefits and so forth. In
most respects, this trend is bad for the workers. But in one respect it’s potentially good for the
workers and dangerous for the companies – namely, it increases the chances that copyrighted
works created by these workers will not be classified as works for hire. Indeed, copyrights in
these works will belong to the workers. Unless and until tell the workers assign those copyrights
to the companies, their legal position will be stronger. Companies, for their part, should look out
for this legal hazard.
The second path to work for hire status seems more clearly marked. As I’ve already
mentioned, if a work falls into one of the nine categories and if the commissioning party secures
In determining whether any work is eligible to be considered a work made for hire
under paragraph (2), neither the amendment contained in section 1011(d) of the
Intellectual Property and Communications Omnibus Reform Act of 1999, as enacted by
section 1000(a)(9) of Public Law 106-113, nor the deletion of the words added by that
amendment–
As you can see, the current state of affairs is as if the technical amendment – the 1999
technical amendment – never happened.
So, are sound recordings works for hire or not? We don’t know yet and won’t until the
first of the termination rights start to take hold. For the reasons I’ll discuss next week, that, as it
turns out, will begin this year – 2013. If in the inevitable litigation sound recordings are not
deemed works for hire, then older musicians, like Bruce Springsteen and Eric Clapton, will soon
begin to reclaim their copyrights in their early albums and will probably be able to make more
money off them. Conversely, if sound recordings are deemed works for hire, then Springsteen
and Clapton will remain bound by their original recording contracts. So a great deal hinges on
this highly technical and still unresolved issue.
Two general lessons can be distilled from this story. The first is that adjustments in
copyright law are often achieved through lobbying by the representatives of the affected
interest groups. When two or more powerful groups are opposed, the usual result is stalemate.
Only when the relevant groups are aligned does the law move. The technical amendment, so-
called, secured by the recording industry in 1999 is a rare exception to that generalization. But
note that it was very short lived. Once the representatives of the musicians were alerted, the
amendment was rolled back restoring the statutory stalemate. As Jessica Litman has shown, this
dynamic in which copyright law changes if and only if the relevant interest groups want it to is
common in the United States and not quite so common but still frequently seen in other
countries. The second of the general lessons is that in some industries artists are vulnerable.
Their bargaining power is, in most instances, inferior to that of the intermediaries with whom
they have to deal. As a result, if they’re allowed to sign away their rights, they will. Occasionally
the law seeks to mitigate their vulnerability ironically by restricting their contractual freedom. In
The table above summarizes the changing status in US law of the three most important
formalities. I hasten to add that this chart is not comprehensive. It focuses on, as I say, the most
important requirements. If you’re hungry for more information on the subject, follow the branch
of the map that summarizes the history of formalities. You’ll find they are linked to an excellent
article by Professor Jane Ginsburg. On pages 13 and 14 of her article, you’ll find a chart that
contains much more detail than the one on your screen. So, with that cautionary note, let’s
focus on the main themes.
To make sense of this field, you need to differentiate three eras in the legal history of
copyright in the United States – the period between 1909 and the end of 1977; the period
between January 1, 1978 and February 28, 1989; and the period between March 1, 1989 and the
present.
The first of these eras was governed by the 1909 version of the Federal Copyright Statute.
The event that separated the first from the second era was a comprehensive reform of that
statute, which was adopted in 1976 but only became effective at the start of 1978. The event
that separated the second from the third era was the effective date of the statute, that as we
have seen earlier, altered US law enough to enable the United States to join the Berne
Convention. We could, of course, look farther back in time than 1909, but no copyrights
governed by pre-1909 statutes are still alive today, so we won’t.
the copyright, in which case, it would enjoy protection for a second 28-year term, whereupon it
would finally and permanently fall to the public domain. Thereafter, anyone could use it, copy it,
publish it, read it aloud in a public park, and so forth.
For the most part, the system worked just fine for sophisticated novelists, like Margaret
Mitchell, and publishers, like McMillan. They were aware of the statutory requirements, and
complying with them was not hard. But less sophisticated players or the creators of less-
conventional works sometimes neglected the notice requirement, and as a result, lost copyright
protection permanently. The courts, sympathetic to the plight of these unsophisticated players,
begin to tinker with this legal regime, in order to reduce the frequency of forfeitures. They
couldn’t, of course, ignore the statutory requirement altogether. Instead, they began to
construe the term, “publication,” in a way that helped 90% of authors. They were able to do so
because the statute itself did not to find the term publication, but left that up to the courts.
Seizing that opportunity, the courts differentiated two kinds of publication – so-called limited
publication, which would not trigger the notice requirement, and so-called general publication,
which did. The courts then defined general publication narrowly, to exclude lots of things we
would actually associate with the term publication. For example, they held that making and
distributing a sound recording of a musical composition did not result in publication of the
composition and that giving a public lecture did not result in publication of the lecture, unless
you passed out unrestricted copies of the text to your audience.
Here’s an important and illustrative case, the outcome of which hinged on this
counterintuitive definition of publication. On August 28, 1963, the Southern Christian Leadership
Conference organized a march in Washington, DC in support of the civil rights movement.
Roughly 200,000 people gathered on the mall at the center of the city. The march culminated
with a speech by Dr. Martin Luther King Jr, the founder and president of the Leadership
Conference. The latter portions of his speech contained some of the most moving and justly
famous lines in US political history. Here are a few.
As I say, roughly 200,000 people heard this speech live, and millions more saw it on
television. Roughly a month afterward, it apparently occurred to King, or his advisers, that he
ought to enjoy a copyright in the speech and that other people should have to pay him, if they
wished to sell copies the speech. So, on September 30, 1963, King filed for copyright registration
and duly received a certificate of registration on October 2. He then initiated an infringement
suit against unauthorized seller and prevailed.
It’s probably occurred to you that there’s an important policy issue lurking here. Should
political speeches be subject to copyright protection? In the United States, so long as their
authors are not officials of the federal government, they are protected by copyright. And Dr.
King and his estate have enforced their copyrights in his speeches and letters fiercely. I leave to
you the question of whether giving King and his estate this power makes sense on the basis of
any of the theories of copyright we’ve considered thus far in this lecture series, but our primary
concern today is not with that important policy issue, but with of question of formalities.
For decades, no one seems to have challenged King’s copyright in the “I Have a Dream”
speech. Then, in 1994, CBS produced a documentary series on 20th century US history. One
segment of one episode in that series focused on the March on Washington. In it, CBS showed
roughly 60% of King’s speech. CBS did not, before making the film, ask permission and did not
pay the customary license fee. King’s estate predictably brought suit against CBS. CBS’s main line
of defense was that King, and subsequently his estate, lacked copyright protection, because King
had published the speech in August of 1963 without the statutorily required notice. There’s no
question that King had not given any kind of copyright notice when he delivered the speech on
the mall. So, the only issue, at least during the preliminary round of litigation, was whether
making the speech before a nationwide audience constituted publication. The trial court
concluded, yes, and thus that King had forfeited copyright protection. But the Court of Appeals
for the 11th Circuit concluded, no. A general publication, the court ruled, occurs only in two
situations – first, when tangible copies of a work are distributed to the general public in such a
manner as to allow the public to exercise dominion and control over those copies; and second,
when the work is exhibited and displayed in a way that invites unrestricted copying by the
general public, for example, by publicly displaying a sculpture without any restrictions on the
freedom of viewers to photograph it. At the stage of the litigation in which this issue arose, CBS
had not yet established that King had done either of those things when he delivered the speech.
So, he did not forfeit his copyright in it. So, CBS, as a result, had to obtain a license from King’s
Figure 69: The timeline of copyright protection under the current regime
When you share your creativity, you’re enabling people anywhere to use it, learn from
it, and be inspired by it. Take the teacher, who shapes young minds with work and
wisdom from around the globe; and the artist, who breeds beauty out of bits and pieces
she finds online; and the writer, whose stories use ideas and images crafted by people
he’s never even met. These people know that when you share your creative wealth, you
can accomplish great things. They and millions of other people all around the planet
are working together to build a richer, better, more vibrant culture, using Creative
Commons. To understand Creative Commons, you need to know a little bit about how
copyright works. Did you know that when you create something, anything from a
photograph to a song to a drawing to a film to a story, you automatically own and all
rights reserved copyright to that creativity. It’s true. Copyright protects your creativity
against uses you don’t consent to. But sometimes full copyright is too restrictive. What
about when you want all those millions and millions of people out there to use your
work without the hassle of coming to you for permission? What if you want your work
to be freely shared, reused, and built upon by the rest of the world? Luckily, there’s an
answer – Creative Commons. We provide free copyright licenses you can use to tell
people exactly which parts of your copyright you’re happy to give to the public. It’s
easy. It only takes a minute. And it’s totally free. Just come on our website and answer
a few quick questions like – will you allow commercial uses of your work? And will you
allow your work to be modified? Based on your answers, we’ll give you a license that
clearly communicates what people can and can’t do with your creativity. You don’t give
up your copyright. You refine it, so it works better for you. Welcome to a new world
where collaboration rules. It didn’t even exist just a few years ago. But now there are
If you’re persuaded by this video and follow the narrator’s instructions to go to the
Creative Commons website, you will find there six main licensing options which give you and
other authors of a variety of sets of rights that you and they may decide to retain or surrender.
In addition to the six licenses listed on your screen, Creative Commons makes available to
copyright owners a standardized notice known as CC0, that they can employ to give up all of
their rights – in other words, as I’ve said, to donate their works to the public domain. An
important footnote – as you know by now, in some countries, authors enjoy some non-waivable
moral rights, in other words, entitlements that they cannot give up. In those countries, use of
the CC0 label may not be fully effective or at least not permanent. That troubling possibility has
not yet been tested. But this label, CC0, provides authors an easy way to give up as many rights
as they can. In terms of our schematic characterization of the copyright system, here’s what CC0
enables. The current regime, as you’ll recall, works like this. CC makes it easier for copyright
owners to opt out of some more or all of their rights, in other words, to as shown in Figure 70.
The advantage of Creative Commons, as compared to the other two ways of tempering
the unfortunate side effects of our current lack of formalities, is that it in no way undermines the
right of copyright owners who want to retain all of their rights. It is this optional feature that
prompted Jack Valenti, the former head of the Motion Picture Association of America and a
staunch defender of copyright, to endorse Creative Commons.
I’m glad to be here via this video. I wish I could be there in person. But I wanted to say
just few words about Larry Lessig’s concept of Creative Commons. I’m attracted to it for
the following reasons. First, Larry makes it clear that he is respectful of and supports
copyright – copyrighted material that artists create – and he believes it ought to be
The disadvantage of Creative Commons is that the majority of copyright owners do not
and will not use it, either because they were unaware of it, don’t understand it, or simply don’t
want to give up any rights. Creative Commons thus mitigates the troubling impact of our lack of
formalities, but certainly doesn’t eliminate them. What else might we do without sacrificing the
clear benefits of our current regime? I’ll leave that to your imagination and deliberation.
6.2. Duration
In this segment of the lecture, we’ll examine the rules that determine how long US copyrights
last. You’re probably thinking, well, this will be a short segment. How complicated can it be? The
answer, unfortunately, is quite complicated. The reason for the complexity is that the relevant
rules in the United States have been amended several times, but the amendments have been
only partially retroactive. The result is that there are several subsets of copyrighted works that
are governed by different sets of duration rules. Here’s how I’ll try to untangle this knot. I’ll
begin by reviewing the history of the pertinent laws. I’ll then start over and consider the impact
of that history on the duration of different groups of works.
Figure 71 shows the way things worked under the original version of the 1909 copyright
statute. As we’ve seen, the first term of federal protection lasted for 28 years after the date of
publication. If the copyright was properly renewed, it lasted for another 28-year term,
commonly known, for obvious reasons, as the renewal term. Here are a few more details we
have not yet discussed. The application for renewal could be filed any time during the year
preceding the expiration of the initial term. If the author was still alive at that time, he or she
was the person presumptively entitled to apply for and receive the renewed copyright. If the
author had died, his or her surviving spouse or children could do so. If there were no surviving
spouse or kids, the author’s executor had the right, if the author had left a will. If he or she had
not left a will, then his or her next of kin had the renewal right. A technical point that, as we’ll
see later had some important practical effects, the renewal term was not thought of as a
With respect to works first published under the auspices of the 1909 statute, this basic
structure has remained intact, but the length and mechanics of the renewal term have been
adjusted several times. In 1976, the renewal term was extended from 28 to 47 years. In 1998, as
part of the Copyright Term Extension Act, it was extended from 47 to 67 years. In 1992, the
renewals of works that at the time were still in their first term was made automatic rather than
voluntary. The result is that copyrighted works ceased falling into the public domain at the end
of their initial 28-year terms. The 1976 general reform of the copyright statute, which became
effective as we’ve seen at the start of 1978, instituted a radically new regime. As we’ve seen,
works created thereafter acquired federal copyright protection immediately, which lasted for
the life of the author plus 50 years. The Copyright Term Extension Act in 1998 extended that
term to its current duration – the life of the author plus 70 years. Measuring duration by the life
of the author would not work for anonymous works, pseudonymous works, and works for hire,
so these were given terms of years that were meant
to approximate the duration of regular copyrights – How long a US copyright lasts depends
a century from the date of creation or 75 years from on when and how it was created
first publication, whichever happened first. The
1. Works published before 1923
Copyright Term Extension Act in 1998 also extended
2. Works published 1923 – 1963
those terms by 20 years.
3. Works published 1964 – 1977
Lurking in these details are two general
themes. The first, I’ve already mentioned – the 4. Works created but not published
gradual transition from an opt-in to an opt-out before 1978
system. The second, probably obvious, is that 5. Works created in 1978 or later
The simplest group consists of works published before 1923 (Figure 72). Some of these got
the benefit of the extension of the renewal term from 28 to 47 years, but all of them fell into the
public domain before the Copyright Term Extension Act could rescue them and the Act did not
lift them back up. The upshot is that the copyrights on these works have expired.
The second category consists of works published between 1923 and 1963 (Figure 73).
These were rescued before their expiration by the Copyright Term Extension Act. The most
famous and influential member of this group is Mickey Mouse – a copyrighted character, who
first appeared publicly in the 1928 cartoon, Steamboat Willie. Copyrights in these works will
begin to expire in 2018, 95 years after their first publication. Mickey Mouse, himself, will fall into
onto the previous regime. Another important footnote: just because these copyrights are
subject to automatic renewal doesn’t mean that they cannot be voluntarily renewed, and the
system contains some important incentives for people who voluntarily renew. The upshot, as
you might imagine, is that voluntary renewal remained common after 1992. The key point for
our present purposes is that works in this third category have not yet fallen into the public
domain. They will begin to do so in 2018, like their surviving older cousins.
Works in the fourth category overlap the fundamental change in the copyright system
caused by the general reform of the statute in 1976. These were created but not published
before 1978 (Figure 75). Federal copyright protection for these last for the lives of their authors
plus 70 years or the end of 2002, whichever is later. In addition, if they were published by the
end of 2002, they got an extra lease on life until, at a minimum, the end of 2047. The purpose
and effect of this provision was to nudge the heirs of the authors of such things to publish them.
Figure 77: Duration of works created in 1978 or later, for anonymous works, pseudonymous works, and
works for hire
We come, finally, to the newest set of works, those created in 1978 or later. These, as you
now know, last for the life of the author plus 70 years. That means that they will start expiring in
Figure 78: Copyright under the 1909 regime, showing the ability to assign renewal rights
You’ll recall that the 1909 copyright system worked like this: so long as he complied with
the rest requisite formalities, the author of a work received a 28-year initial term of federal
copyright protection. During the 28th year, he could apply for a second 28-year term. If he had
died, his widow or children could apply, and so forth. As I’ve indicated, the renewal term was
House Report
It was urged before the committee that it would be better to have a single term
without any right of renewal, and a term of life and fifty years was suggested. Your
committee, after full consideration, decided that it was distinctly to the advantage of
the author to preserve the renewal period. It not infrequently happens that the author
This passage suggests that the purpose of not giving an author from the outset a single
term of life plus 50 years, or something shorter, like 56 years, but instead requiring him to renew
the copyright in the 28th year, was precisely to give him an opportunity to renegotiate the terms
of any assignment. And the reason why that’s important is that, as the committee explains,
authors tend to be either vulnerable or naive, and therefore, to assign their initial terms for too
little money. In other words, the law was designed to protect authors from their own foolishness
or vulnerability. Permitting them to assign their expectancy interests, along with the first term,
arguably would defeat that goal. The upshot is that there was a plausible argument that these
assignments of expectancy interests were invalid; but for many years, they were used without
being challenged in court. Finally, one composer did so. His name was George Graff. In 1912, Mr.
Graff helped compose the song, “When Irish Eyes are Smiling.” Here’s a brief excerpt of a 1913
recording of the song.
(Lyrics) There’s a tear in your eye. And I’m wondering why, for it never should be there
at all. With such power in your smile, sure a stone you’d beguile, and there’s never a
teardrop should fall. When your sweet lilting laughter like some fairy song, and your
eyes sparkling bright as can be you should laugh all the while, and all other times smile.
And now smile a while for me.
When he first wrote this song, Graff assigned the copyright, in the initial 28-year term, to
a music publisher, Witmark and Sons, in return for some royalties. Five years later, he
encountered financial difficulties. To raise some cash, Graff gave up his royalties for “Irish Eyes,”
and for 68 other songs, and in addition, assigned his expectancy interest in the renewal term for
all of those 69 songs, to Witmark in return for a lump sum payment of $1,600. Subsequently,
“Irish Eyes” became very popular, and earned Witmark lots of royalties, none of which, of
course, went to Graff. In 1939, on the first day of the 28th year of the copyright, Witmark, the
publisher, exercised its right to renew the copyright for an additional 28-year term. Graff,
unhappy, insisted that his 1917 assignment of the expectancy interest to Witmark had been
invalid, and purported to renew the copyright in “Irish Eyes” himself, and then assign it for more
money to a different publisher, Fred Fisher Music. The two publishers then fought it out. The
timeline of the various actions and the parties involved is shown in Figure 79.
Although, as you can see, the case that grew out of this complicated narrative involved
two publishers, it had big implications for all other composers and artists in analogous positions.
If Witmark prevailed, then many authors would not get a second bite at the apple. They could,
and would, assign their expectancy interests, along with the first term of their copyrights,
sometimes for very little money. Then, when the time for renewal arose, they would have no
rights. By contrast, if Fred Fisher Music prevailed, authors in the future would be unable to
assign their expectancies, but on the other hand, would be in a much better bargaining position
at renewal time.
So, the stakes were high. The case proceeded through three levels of courts. The trial
judge ruled in favor of Witmark. The Court of Appeals affirmed, by a vote of two judges to one,
and the Supreme Court affirmed, by a vote of five to three, one justice not participating. The law
was thus settled. Expectancy interests of this sort are indeed assignable. For our purposes, even
more important than this outcome is the language used by the opposing groups of parties and
judges. Two radically different conceptions of authors, their characteristics, and their needs
figured in this case. The first was well expressed by Judge Jerome Frank, who dissented in the
Court of Appeals.
In considering those facts, we should take judicial notice of the economic capacities and
business acumen of most authors. We need only take judicial notice of that which every
schoolboy knows – that, usually, with a few notable exceptions, such as Shakespeare
and George Bernard Shaw, authors are hopelessly inept in business transactions and
that lyricists, like the defendant Graff, often sell their songs “for a song.”
Appreciation of these facts, Frank contended, should prompt us to treat lyricists, and
authors in general, as especially vulnerable, perhaps even a “necessitus class,” and to curtail
their contractual freedom for their own good. Specifically, we should disable them from
It is not for courts to judge whether the interests of authors clearly lie upon one side of
this question rather than the other. We cannot draw a principle of law from the familiar
stories of garret-poverty of some men of literary genius. Even if we could do so, we
cannot say that such men would regard with favor a rule of law preventing them from
realizing on their assets when they are most in need of funds. Nor can we be unmindful
of the fact that authors have themselves devised means of safeguarding their interests.
We do not have such assured knowledge about authorship, and particularly about song
writing, or the psychology of gifted writers and composers, as to justify us as judges in
importing into Congressional legislation a denial to authors of the freedom to dispose
of their property possessed by others. While authors may have habits making for
intermittent want [in other words, they don’t manage their money well] they may have
no less a spirit of independence which would resent treatment of them as wards under
guardianship of the law.
Frankfurter’s vision, his insistence that authors were responsible adults, autonomous
individuals, and should not be treated as wards of the state, prevailed in this particular case. But
Judge Frank’s competing vision, that the law should be crafted to nurture and protect
improvident authors, to shield them from their habitual folly, also had a significant following.
Three of the Supreme Court justices dissented. Instead of writing a dissent themselves, they
merely indicated that they agreed with the analysis of the language and history of the copyright
law in the dissenting opinion of Judge Frank, in the court below.
These competing visions are outgrowths of deeper and broader themes in copyright law,
and in US law in general. Indeed, both of these opposed visions can be found in the legal
systems of most countries, at least in Europe and North America. The broader theme that
underlies the Frankfurter argument is sometimes called individualism. Here’s how Duncan
Kennedy, the scholar who has done the most to identify and explore these ideological currents,
describes it.
An attitude strongly associated with this outlook is a hostility to paternalism, legal rules
that restrict people’s freedom for their own good, such as a rule preventing authors from
assigning their expectancy interest on the grounds that they will be better off if they’re forced to
wait until the end of their initial copyright terms.
Opposed to individualism is altruism. Here’s how Kennedy described it.
The essence of altruism is the belief that one ought not to indulge a sharp preference
for one’s own interest over those of others. Altruism enjoins us to make sacrifices, to
share, and to be merciful. It has roots in culture, in religion, ethics and art, that are as
deep as those of individualism. (Love thy neighbor as thyself.)
The simplest of the practices that represent altruism are sharing and sacrifice. Sharing
is a static concept, suggesting an existing distribution of goods which the sharers
rearrange. It means giving up to another gains or wealth that one has produced oneself
or that have come to one through some good fortune. It is motivated by a sense of duty
or by a sense that the other’s satisfaction is a reward at least comparable to the
satisfaction one might have derived from consuming the thing oneself. Sharing may
also involve participation in another’s losses: a spontaneous decision to shift to oneself
a part of the ill fortune, deserved or fortuitous, that has befallen someone else. Sacrifice
is the dynamic notion of taking action that will change an ongoing course of events, at
some expense to oneself, to minimize another’s loss or maximize his gain.
This orientation tends to sustain a much more favorable posture toward paternalism.
People, viewed this way, should not be left to their own devices. The law should, at least
sometimes, intervene to save them from themselves.
Kennedy’s great essay, from which these passages are drawn, explores in depth the
relationship between these competing attitudes concerning the substance of human relations,
and analogously competing attitudes toward the proper form of legal rules. If you’re curious, I
strongly encourage you to explore that essay (available online†). But our concern here is with the
narrower question of how the attitudes I’ve just summarized find expression in copyright law.
Legislators, when adjusting the copyright statute, and judges, when construing and applying the
statute, are frequently pulled in different directions by these warring impulses. Sometimes, as in
†
Duncan Kennedy, "Form and Substance in Private-Law Adjudication," 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1685 (1976).
http://duncankennedy.net/documents/Form%20and%20Substance%20in%20Private%20Law%20Adjudication.pdf
There are two groups of these rights. The first apply to works created in 1978 or later (see
Figure 80). You’ll recall that federal copyrights in such works arise when they are first fixed in a
tangible medium, and last for the life of the author plus 70 years. The authors of such works, of
course, initially acquire those copyrights, but frequently assign them, or portions of them, to
other parties. For example, as we’ve seen, musicians commonly assign the copyrights in their
sound recordings to record companies. These are known as inter vivos transfers, because they
occur during the author’s lifetime. Typically, such assignments are permanent. In other words,
the assignee gets the full copyright term. And notice, this effect is a bit odd. The assignee’s rights
last for a period of time tied to the lifespan of the author. The longer the author lives, the more
valuable are the assignee’s rights. For those of you familiar with the language of common law
real property law, the effect is analogous to a life estate pur autre vie, plus 70 years. Curious, but
that’s how it works.
Suppose that a particular author assigns her rights for a pittance, and then later comes to
regret her decision. Can she ever get the copyright back? The answer is yes. Section 203 of the
statute gives her the right to terminate the assignment during a five-year window that opens 35
years after the date of the original assignment (refer to Figure 81). If she wishes to exercise that
right, she must notify the assignee between two and five years before the termination itself. If
she has died, her spouse or descendants get the right to terminate, and to recover the copyright.
A crucial difference between this system and the renewal system we examined a minute ago is
that the termination rights are non-waivable. In other words, the author may not, when she
assigns her copyright, agree to waive her rights later to terminate the assignment. If she
purports to do so, that waiver will not be enforced. In other words, Congress, when it created
this system, adopted Judge Frank’s view of the legitimacy and importance of protecting authors
from their own ill-advised decisions, rather than Justice Frankfurter’s hostility to making authors
wards of the state. Who enjoys the copyrights after the original assignments are terminated?
The person or persons who, according to the list in the upper right hand corner of this slide, are
entitled to terminate on the date the notice to terminate is given.
What about older works, specifically those published between 1964 and 1977? Copyrights
in these, you’ll recall, function very differently. Federal copyright protection is attached to them
only upon publication, with appropriate notice, and now lasts for an initial term of 28 years, and
an automatic renewal term of 67 years, for a total of 95 years from the date of publication (see
Figure 82). Suppose that, sometime after 1978, the author, having renewed assigns the
remainder of the renewal term. The assignee will keep it for the balance of the term, unless the
author can terminate the assignment. Again, Section 203 the statute gives her the right to do so
during a five-year window that opens 35 years after the date of the original assignment. These
rights work the same way as the set we just considered.
If the assignment was made before 1978, a different set of termination rules apply.
Section 304 of the statute gives the author – or if she has died, the members of her family – the
right to terminate at any time during a five-year window that opens 56 years after the date of
the original publication. In other words, when federal copyright protection started.
Mechanically, these termination rights work essentially the same way as the set we just
considered, and can be exercised by the same parties. They, too, cannot be waived. If the author
or her family members miss that window, another one opens 75 years after the original
publication.
7.1. Reproduction
We arrive, finally, at the heart of copyright law. In the next three lectures, we’ll examine the
principal rights that a copyright owner enjoys and the corresponding limitations upon those
rights, designed to accommodate the interests of the public at large. Here’s how my
presentation will be organized.
In this lecture and the next one, I’ll be examining the economic rights enjoyed by a
copyright owner. As you’ll see, there are four clusters of such rights – first, the copyright owner’s
exclusive right to reproduce the copyrighted work; second, the exclusive right to make
modifications of the copyrighted work, commonly known as the right to make derivative works;
third, the right to control the distribution, exportation, and importation of copies of the work;
and fourth, the right to control public performances or public displays of the work.
Today, I’ll be examining the first two of those rights – the right of reproduction and the
right of modification. Next week, I’ll take up the third and fourth of the rights. And the week
after that, I’ll discuss the major exceptions and limitations that copyright law imposes upon
these exclusive rights. During this tour, I will focus, as I did during the first half of the course,
primarily on the law in the United States, but I will also identify some respects in which the law
in other countries parallels or differs from US law.
Section 106 of the US Copyright Statute confers on copyright owners a broad and
seemingly unqualified set of rights. Here they are:
17 USC § 106
Subject to sections 107 through 122, the owner of copyright under this title has the
exclusive rights to do and to authorize any of the following:
(4) in the case of literary, musical, dramatic, and choreographic works, pantomimes,
and motion pictures and other audiovisual works, to perform the copyrighted work
publicly;
(5) in the case of literary, musical, dramatic, and choreographic works, pantomimes,
and pictorial, graphic, or sculptural works, including the individual images of a motion
picture or other audiovisual work, to display the copyrighted work publicly; and
(6) in the case of sound recordings, to perform the copyrighted work publicly by means
of a digital audio transmission.
Sections 107 through 122 then carve out of those rights a long list of exceptions. Some of
those exceptions are very specific and narrow; others are broader. The broadest of all is the fair
use doctrine, embodied in Section 107, which we’ll discuss in two weeks. As you can see, the
introductory clause of Section 106 makes the rights it creates “subject to” – in other words,
qualified by – Sections 107 through 122. The result of this structure is that, to get an accurate
sense of the scope of a copyright owner’s exclusive rights, you must oscillate between the
generous grants contained in Section 106 and the myriad exceptions contained in the following
provisions. And that’s what we’ll be doing.
The first and simplest of the rights conferred on a copyright owner by Section 106 is the
right to reproduce – in other words, to copy – the copyrighted work in copies or phonorecords.
This entitlement is commonly considered the core of copyright. The name of this entire field
suggests as much. The heart of copyright is the exclusive right to copy. As it’s used in the law,
the term “reproduction” has three independent dimensions. To prevail, a plaintiff must satisfy
all three.
The first pertains to the way in which the defendant To prove unauthorised
generated the allegedly infringing things. Only if he did so by reproduction the plaintiff must
copying is the defendant liable. The second pertains to the show:
character of the allegedly infringing things. Only if they 1. Copying
constitute “copies” is the defendant liable. And the third
2. What the defendant
pertains to the nature and amount of the material the defendant
created is a “copy”
took from the plaintiff. Only if it rises to the level of “improper
appropriation” is the defendant liable. We’ll consider them in 3. Improper appropriation
that order.
In patent law, as some of you know, independent invention is no excuse. A defendant
cannot escape liability by showing that he dreamed up, on his own, an invention that happens to
match the plaintiff’s patent. Not so in copyright law. There, independent creation is an excuse.
Suppose, for example, I write a poem. Later, you, never having seen mine, write and publish
Everything registers somewhere in our memories, and no one can tell what may evoke
it. Once it appears that another has, in fact, used the copyright as the source of this
production, he has invaded the author’s right. It is no excuse that, in so doing, his
memory has played him a trick.
The most famous case of this general sort involved the following facts. In 1963, The
Chiffons, a popular quartet in the United States, released a recording of “He’s So Fine,” a song
that had been composed by Ronald Mack. Here’s a brief excerpt.
[Music: The Chiffons, “He’s So Fine”.]
The Chiffons’ recording was a hit in both the United States and in England. George
Harrison heard the song, but forgot it. Six years later, he composed and performed “My Sweet
Lord.” Here’s an excerpt.
[Music: George Harrison, “My Sweet Lord”.]
Bright Tunes Music, the assignee of Mack’s copyright, brought an infringement suit
against Harrison and prevailed. Both the trial court and the Court of Appeals credited Harrison’s
testimony that he was unaware of The Chiffons’ recording when he made his own song.
However, they ruled, Harrison could not escape on this basis. Here’s the key passage in the
appellate court’s opinion.
The court then went on to suggest a possible policy basis for this seemingly unforgiving
rule.
As a practical matter, the problems of proof inherent in a rule that would permit
innocent intent as a defense to copyright infringement could substantially undermine
the protections Congress intended to afford copyright owners. We therefore see no
reason to retreat from this Circuit’s prior position that copyright infringement can be
subconscious.
The rule announced and applied by the court in this case bears emphasis. Innocent
copying is still infringement. In this special sense, copyright infringement is a strict liability
offense.
The final, perhaps non-obvious, aspect of the scope of copying is that it encompasses
translation of the plaintiff’s work into a different medium. So, for example, an unauthorized
motion picture version of a novel, a doll that mimics a cartoon character, a still photograph of a
ballet are all covered. So, to summarize, a plaintiff, to establish that a defendant has violated the
plaintiff’s exclusive right of reproduction, first must show that the defendant “copied” the
plaintiff’s work, which means either that the defendant mechanically reproduced it or had the
plaintiff’s work in mind, even subconsciously, when making his own product.
How, then, does a plaintiff prove copying in this sense?
There are four. Techniques to use to prove
First, the plaintiff can introduce direct evidence of copying
copying. Surprisingly often, evidence survives of a defendant’s 1. Direct evidence
conscious intentional use of the plaintiff’s work during the
2. Access and similarity
course of his own creative processes, and that evidence turns
3. Striking similarity
up in discovery. Second, the plaintiff can show that the
defendant had access to his work and that the defendant’s 4. Common errors
work and the plaintiff’s work are sufficiently similar to raise an
inference of copying. For example, the plaintiff may be able to show that the defendant had the
plaintiff’s book on his bookshelf or received the plaintiff’s screenplay in the mail. More
commonly, the plaintiff may be able to show that his work – say, a song or a movie – was widely
performed in areas and at times that would make it highly likely that the defendant heard or
17 USC § 101
“Copies” are material objects, other than phonorecords, in which a work is fixed by any
method now known or later developed, and from which the work can be perceived,
reproduced, or otherwise communicated, either directly or with the aid of a machine or
device. The term “copies” includes the material object, other than a phonorecord, in
which the work is first fixed.
“Phonorecords” are material objects in which sounds, other than those accompanying a
motion picture or other audiovisual work, are fixed by any method now known or later
developed, and from which the sounds can be perceived, reproduced, or otherwise
communicated, either directly or with the aid of a machine or device. The term
“phonorecords” includes the material object in which the sounds are first fixed.
Recently, the Second Circuit Court of Appeals decided a complicated and important case
in which this fixation requirement proved critical. Because the case implicated several other
legal rules, as well, I’m going to describe the facts in some detail. Then, I’ll discuss one of the
issues raised by those facts today and come back to other dimensions of the case next week.
Cablevision is a small cable TV system based in New York City. Like all cable companies, it
aggregates audiovisual programming from several sources. For example, Warner Brothers may
produce a movie, license it to NBC, and then Cablevision picks up NBC’s signal. Cartoon Network
and HBO provide programming directly to Cablevision, and so forth. As you might expect,
Cablevision pays for the right to broadcast this material either according to the terms of
voluntary licenses or through a compulsory license. Those licenses are important and complex.
We’ll touch on them briefly at the end of the next lecture. For present purposes, all you need to
know is that these licenses do not give Cablevision the right to make copies of the TV shows or
movies in question, only to publicly perform them. So, to return to the narrative, Cablevision
combines these various streams of programs into a single, composite, encoded signal, which it
sends via cable, of course, to its customers. Each customer receives the composite signal
through a set-top box, which decodes it, relays it to a television, which, in turn, displays it to the
subscriber sitting on his couch.
If, as is likely, the subscriber doesn’t want to watch all shows at the times they are
broadcast, he’s likely to employ a device to record them. Once upon a time, the device would
have been a VCR. Today, it’s likely to be a digital video recorder, commonly known as a DVR.
Then, when the subscriber wants to watch a given show, he plays the copy stored on the DVR.
So, this pattern should be entirely familiar to most of you, but if you’ve been following this
course of lectures from the beginning, it should make you uneasy. There’s no question that the
DVR recording, represented by the blue dot in Figure 83, is a copy of the television shows in
question. The subscriber who makes those copies does not have a license from Warner Brothers
or Cartoon Networks to do so. Is the subscriber then violating section 106(1) of the copyright
statute? The answer is yes, but that violation, as we’ll see, is excused under the fair use doctrine.
When and how that crucial principle was established we’ll discuss in a few weeks. For now, it’s
enough to recognize that the subscriber can slip the noose by pleading fair use.
Now, back to our story. In 2006, Cablevision had an idea. What if, instead of relying on
individual subscribers to make copies of shows on their home DVRs, it offered to make copies for
them using a cloud-based technology? This would be more efficient and convenient than the
home devices, sufficiently so, that the subscribers would be willing to pay a premium for it. So,
Cablevision created, though it did not immediately implement, what it called a remote storage
DVR, or RS-DVR system. Its main features, in the language of the court eventually called upon to
review the system, looked like this.
Under the new RS-DVR, this single stream of data is split into two streams. The first is
routed immediately to customers, as before. The second stream flows into a device,
called the broadband media router (BMR), which buffers the data stream, reformats it,
and sends it to the Arroyo server, which consists, in relevant part, of two data buffers
and a number of high-capacity hard disks. The entire stream of data moves to the first
So, those are the facts. You can guess what happened next. Cartoon Network and the
owners of the copyrights in the other shows that would be delivered to subscribers through the
system initiated a lawsuit against Cablevision, not because they thought this was a bad idea, but
because they wanted Cablevision to pay them additional license fees to deploy this new feature,
which Cablevision was unwilling to do. The plaintiffs contended that the RS-DVR system would
violate their copyrights in not just one, but three, separate ways.
First, they argued that buffering an audiovisual work, specifically for 1.2 seconds in the
BMR and for a tenth of a second in the primary ingest buffer of the Arroyo server, creates a
series of replicated pieces of the work, which, although each one is stored only briefly, gives rise
in the aggregate to a copy of that work and thus violates Section 106(1) of the Copyright Act.
Second, they argued that making the much more durable copies of their shows on the Arroyo
server hard drives gives rise to a second violation of Section 106(1). Third, they argued that the
delivery of the programming from the Arroyo server to the subscriber at the subscriber’s request
would constitute an unauthorized “public performance” in violation of Section 106(4). We’ll
Copies, as defined in the Copyright Act, are material objects in which a work is fixed by
any method and from which the work can be reproduced. The act also provides that a
work is fixed in a tangible medium and expression when its embodiment is sufficiently
permanent or stable to permit it to be reproduced for a period of more than transitory
duration. We believe that this language plainly imposes two distinct, but related,
requirements – the work must be embodied in a medium, i.e., placed in a medium such
that it can be perceived, reproduced, et cetera, from that medium; and it must remain
thus embodied for a period of more than transitory duration. Unless both requirements
are met, the work is not fixed in the buffer. And as a result, the buffer data is not a copy
of the original work whose data is buffered.
Because the data being channeled toward the Arroyo server reside in no buffer for more
than 1.2 seconds before being automatically overwritten, the court concluded that the duration
requirement had not been satisfied and thus that the defendant’s technology did not result in
the creation of any copies.
For reasons we’ll explore later, the Court of Appeals also rejected the second and third of
the plaintiff’s claims. As we’ll see, the bases of those rulings were also highly technical, and thus
arguably a bit counterintuitive. The net result was that Cablevision was permitted to deploy its
new service. This decision, which the Supreme Court declined to review, has facilitated the
emergence of many analogous cloud-based services, which, in turn, have had huge economic
implications. As Josh Lerner discovered, “VC investment in cloud computing firms increased
significantly in the United States relative to the EU after the Cablevision decision.” The decision,
it appears, led to additional incremental investment in US cloud computing firms that ranged
from $728 million to approximately $1.3 billion over the two and a half years after the decision.
When paired with the findings of enhanced effects of VC investment relative to corporate
investment, this may be the equivalent of $2 billion to $5 billion in traditional R&D investment.
An essential step in the ruling that catalyzed this investment was, as we’ve seen, the court’s
judgment that the fixation requirement had not been satisfied by the buffer copies.
He said that the flute section, which he added, fitted rhythmically to “Down Under” and
the percussion drum section at the start of the song, which is in fact played on beer
bottles with different amounts of water in them. Mr. Ham pointed out that the lyrics,
vocal melody, chords, and bass lines were already established when he heard “Down
Under.” He looked for a complimentary part for his instruments, and especially one
which fell into the “tongue in cheek” nature of the song. He described the flute line as
an Aussie cliché melody, or what he thought was an Irish Australian style melody.
Now, Judge Jacobson did not definitively resolve the question of whether Ham had been
aware when he inserted the riff that had been taken from “Kookaburra,” apparently assuming
that, as we saw in the George Harrison case, subconscious copying is actionable. The decisive
issue in Judge Jacobson’s judgment was the amount taken. Here’s how the court expressed the
relevant standard. Copyright infringement arises when a defendant “has copied a substantial
part of the copyrighted work. The question whether he has copied a substantial part depends
much more on the quality than on the quantity of what he has taken.” That standard, the judge
ruled, had been met in this case. The remedy? The defendants had to pay the plaintiffs 5% of the
The de minimis doctrine is rarely discussed in copyright opinions because suits are
rarely brought over trivial instances of copying. Nonetheless, it is an important aspect
of the law of copyright. Trivial copying is a significant part of modern life. Most honest
citizens in the modern world frequently engage, without hesitation, in trivial copying
that, but for the de minimis doctrine, would technically constitute a violation of law.
We do not hesitate to make a photocopy of a letter from a friend to show to another
friend, or of a favorite cartoon to post on the refrigerator. Parents in Central Park
photograph their children perched on José de Creeft’s Alice in Wonderland sculpture.
We record television programs aired while we are out, so as to watch them at a more
convenient hour. Waiters at a restaurant sing “Happy Birthday” at a patron’s table.
When we do such things, it is not that we are breaking the law but unlikely to be sued
given the high cost of litigation. Because of the de minimis doctrine, in trivial instances
of copying, we are in fact not breaking the law. If a copyright owner were to sue the
makers of trivial copies, judgment would be for the defendants. The case would be
dismissed because trivial copying is not an infringement.
Now, one warning about this otherwise illuminating passage. Judge Leval’s example in the
middle of this paragraph about recording television programs while we are out is not, strictly
speaking, an example de minimis copying. Rather, as I mentioned in connection with the
Cablevision case, that’s an example of fair use, a doctrine that Judge Leval himself has done
more to reshape and invigorate than any other judge. But if you exclude that one instance, the
passage in front of you nicely illustrates the general and unsurprising principle. The law will not
penalize the taking of trivial amounts.
There’s one important exception to the de minimis doctrine. It’s illustrated by the facts of
the 2005 case of Bridgeport Music. The plaintiff in that case owned the copyright in a sound
17 USC § 114(b)
The exclusive right of the owner of copyright in a sound recording under clause (1) of
section 106 is limited to the right to duplicate the sound recording in the form of
phonorecords or copies that directly or indirectly recapture the actual sounds fixed in
the recording. The exclusive right of the owner of copyright in a sound recording under
As you can see, imitating a sound recording does not constitute infringement. With
respect to all other types of copyrighted works, including musical compositions, imitation does
constitute infringement, but not for sound recordings. Only capturing the actual sounds fixed in
the recording gives rise to liability. Dubbing is actionable, but not imitation. This provision
explains why, as we discussed in lecture number three, musicians are free to make covers of
commercially released songs. As we saw there, musicians have to pay the composers of those
songs or their assignees a modest compulsory fee, but they don’t have to get the composer’s
permission. Even more strikingly, they don’t have to pay anything to the owners of the
copyrights in the sound recordings embodying the original rendition of the song, because they’re
not capturing its actual sounds.
Now, the reason why this rule is relevant to digital sampling is that, as the Sixth Circuit
observes, it creates an inexpensive alternative to sampling. As the court explained, “It must be
remembered that if an artist wants to incorporate a riff from another work in his or her
recording, he’s free to duplicate the sound of that riff in the studio. The market will control the
license price and keep it within bounds. The sound recording copyright owner cannot exact a
license fee greater than what it would cost the person seeking the license to just duplicate the
sample in the course of making the new recording.” In other words, the court argues, a blanket
rule that all digital sampling, no matter how small, gives rise to liability would not “stifle
creativity.” Because rap artists and others can either imitate the sounds they want or can obtain
a license, the fee for which will be low, because the licensor is aware that imitation is lawful.
The court’s last argument in support of its ruling is different. Not only would a blanket
prohibition on sampling not stifle creativity, said the court, it’s fair. Why? Because “Sampling is
never accidental. It’s not like the case of a composer who has a melody in his head, perhaps not
even realizing that the reason he hears the melody is that it’s the work of another which he had
heard before. When you sample a sound recording, you know you are taking another’s work
product.” Notice here the echoes of the fairness theory of copyright in general. Intentionally
taking someone else’s “work product,” the court suggests, is wrong, morally wrong, and
deserves to be punished. I leave to you the question of whether these arguments in combination
are convincing.
I hasten to add that the elimination of the de minimis defense for sound recordings does
not necessarily mean that all digital sampling is unlawful. It’s still in principle possible for
Upon any work, and especially upon a play, a great number of patterns of increasing
generality will fit equally well as more and more of the incident is left out. The last may
perhaps be no more than the most general statement of what the play’s about, and at
times might consist only of its title. But there’s a point in this series of abstractions
where they are no longer protected since otherwise the playwright could prevent the
use of his ideas, to which, apart from their expression, his property is never extended.
Nobody has been able to fix that boundary. And nobody ever can. In some cases, the
question has been treated as though it were analogous to lifting a portion out of the
copyrighted work. But the analogy is not a good one. Because though the skeleton is a
part of the body, it pervades and supports the whole. In such cases, we are rather
concerned with the line between expression and what is expressed.
Graphically, this approach might be represented as shown in Figure 84. At the lowest
level of abstraction, in other words the level with the most detail, the plot of a play might be
depicted as shown at level of the diagram. Long lines represent major events, shorter lines
minor events. Abstracted one level, in other words removing some of the minor incidents, the
plot would look like level 2. Abstracted another level, it would look like level 3, and so forth. At
the highest level of abstraction (level 6), the plot is extremely general, something like boy meets
girl, they quarrel and separate, they make up, and live happily ever after. Somewhere in this
sequence of nested patterns lies a line, hard to discern but nevertheless present. Formulations
of the plot sufficiently abstract to fall above the line constitute, within the language of copyright
law, mere ideas. Formulation sufficiently detailed to fall below the line consist of protected
to deal with plots, to software. A software program, the court held, can be arranged into levels
of abstraction just like a plot. The highest level consists of a general description of the function
of the program. At the next level down are major modules or subroutines. At the next level are
finer divisions among parts of modules, until one reaches at the lowest level the source code.
Once the various levels of the program have been separated in this fashion, the Altai test
requires the trier of fact to remove, in other words to filter out, features that do not enjoy
copyright protection. With respect to software, the court ruled, there are many reasons for
disqualifying features. First, the court should identify and then filter out elements of the
plaintiff’s program that are necessary for the program to operate efficiently (Figure 85). For
example, anything necessary to enable the program to sort and search efficiently should be
removed. Next to go are features that are dictated by external factors (Figure 86). These include
features necessary to meet mechanical specifications of the computer, the compatibility
requirements of other programs, the design standards of the computer manufacturers, demands
of the industry being served – in other words, the demands of customers – and widely accepted
programming practices. Finally, and least surprisingly, it should identify and eliminate features
that the original programmer had taken from the public domain (Figure 87). The net result is an
abridged pattern of features, like a comb missing many teeth. The third and last step in the Altai
test is comparison (Figure 88). The features of the defendant’s program are laid alongside the
these formulations as distinct tests analogous to the avowedly distinct tests that are used to
determine conceptual separability with respect to useful articles. Rather, they at least purport to
be different ways of describing the same standard.
Often, courts say that two works are substantially similar if they have “the same aesthetic
appeal.” For example, in the 2001 Boisson case, the Second Circuit said “Generally, an allegedly
infringing work is considered substantially similar to a copyrighted work if the ordinary observer,
unless he set out to detect the disparities, would be disposed to overlook them and regard their
aesthetic appeal as the same.” In the 2005 Mannion case, the district court relied on this test to
rule that a jury could find substantial similarity between a magazine photo of Kevin Garnett and
a photo prepared for a billboard advertising Coors beer (shown in Figure 89).
Another slightly different formulation – in the Ideal Toy case, the same court defined the
relevant test as “whether an average lay observer would recognize the alleged copy as having
been appropriated from the copyrighted work.” Applying this language, a lower court in the
Figure 89: Comparing a magazine photo of Kevin Garnett and a photo prepared
for a billboard advertising Coors beer
1987 Steinberg case concluded that a famous cover of The New Yorker magazine, suggesting the
myopia of residents of New York City, was infringed by a poster publicizing the movie Moscow
on the Hudson (both shown in Figure 90).
Yet another variation – sometimes courts contend that attention should be focused on
“the overall concept and feel of the two works.” For example, in the Krofft case, the Ninth Circuit
relied on that phrase in ruling that the characters, flora, fauna, and layout of an imaginary land
depicted in an advertisement for McDonald’s restaurants resembled sufficiently the
corresponding features of the imaginary land depicted in the Fun Stuff children’s show,
sufficiently closely to give rise to liability (see Figure 91). Individual features, the court noted,
were very similar. For example, “both lands are governed by mayors who have
disproportionately large round heads dominated by long, wide mouths.” But the real basis of
liability was the overall judgment that McDonaldland “captured the total concept and feel of the
Fun Stuff show.” In a similar vein, a district court in the Kisch case concluded that a rational jury
might find substantial similarity in the “underlying tone or mood,” of the two photos depicted in
Figure 92. From what perspective should these judgments be made? In other words, through
whose eyes should the trier of fact view the two works when determining whether they’re
substantially similar? The dominant answer to that question is the average lay observer – in
other words, not an expert in the field of art or literature at issue, but an ordinary lay person.
That answer is subject to two qualifications, however. First, on occasion, courts will adopt the
perspective of the members of the intended audience for the two works. For example, in the
Krofft case, which I just mentioned, the Ninth Circuit at one point sought to assess the degree to
which the Fun Stuff show and McDonaldland would have looked similar to the children at which
both works were primarily aimed. For those of you familiar with trademark law, this maneuver
should remind you of the ways in which courts sometimes assess the likelihood of consumer
confusion that arises when two trademarks are similar.
The second qualification is that courts will occasionally adjust their glasses when the
plaintiff’s work contains some unprotected material, as well as some protected material. As
you’ll recall, I described the two polar positions taken by courts when dealing with such cases –
the so-called totality analysis and the filtration approach exemplified by the Altai case. In
In the Folio Impressions case, part of the plaintiff’s fabric was not original, and
therefore not protectable. We articulated the need for an ordinary observer to be
“more discerning in such circumstances.”
“[T]he ordinary observer would compare the finished product that the fabric designs
were intended to grace (women’s dresses), and would be inclined to view the entire
dress – consisting of protectable and unpredictable elements – as one whole. Here,
since only some of the design enjoys copyright protection, the observer’s inspection
must be more discerning.”
Shortly after Folio Impressions was decided, we reiterated that a “more refined
analysis” is required where a plaintiff’s work is not “wholly original,” but rather
incorporates elements from the public domain. In these instances, “[w]hat must be
shown is substantial similarity between those elements and only those elements that
provide copyrightability to the allegedly infringed compilation.” In contrast, where the
plaintiff’s work contains no material imported from the public domain, the “more
discerning” test is unnecessary.
In applying this test, a court is not to dissect the works at issue, and to separate
components and compare only the copyrightable elements. To do so would be to take
the “more discerning” test to an extreme, which would result in almost nothing being
copyrightable. Because original works broken down to their composite parts would
usually be little more than basic unprotectable elements, like letters, colors, and
symbols. This outcome – affording no copyright protection to an original compilation of
unpredictable elements – would be contrary to the Supreme Court’s holding in Feist
Publications.”
OK, that’s a lot of language. And after all that, it’s still not entirely clear what the court has
in mind. The bottom line seems to be when comparing the two works, don’t filter out the
unprotected material as the court did with software in Altai, but instead adopt a more skeptical
stance than the hypothetical ordinary observer.
As we’ve seen, the emphasis in all of these cases is on some variant of an ordinary lay
observer. Does that mean that expert witnesses have no role in substantial similarity
determinations? Not quite. Although the ultimate judgment must always be made from the
standpoint of an ordinary observer, experts can help in framing the ultimate judgment. The
Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit has developed the most elaborate – some scholars say,
convoluted – system for combining expert and lay analysis. In the Ninth Circuit, there are now
8.1. Distribution
In the preceding lecture, I examined two of the four major economic rights associated with a
copyright, specifically the right to control reproduction and the right to control modifications of
a copyrighted work. In this lecture, I’ll examine the other two major economic rights – the right
to control distribution, and the right to control public performances and displays. As usual, I’ll
spend most of the time discussing the law in the United States, but will also indicate various
issues on which the law in other countries differs.
We’ll begin with the right of distribution. This aspect of copyright law is characterized by a
clash between two powerful sets of impulses. On one side are strong economic interests of
copyright owners. On the other side is an equally powerful set of attitudes, hostile to the
copyright owners’ yearning for continuing control over embodiments of their works. The tension
between these forces has generated and will continue to generate strife and periodic doctrinal
eruptions. The interests of the copyright owners are strong for three reasons. They want to be
able to control what purchasers and possessor of copies of their works do with those copies.
The first, and least important, of those reasons is that such control supplements the
copyright owner’s right of reproduction. Specifically, by enabling the owners to attack
intermediaries who do not themselves make unauthorized copies, but who traffic in
unauthorized copies. In this sense, the distribution right is analogous to the rules in criminal law
penalizing the receipt of stolen property. The second, and more important reason is that
copyright owners would like to suppress, if possible, resales and lending of copies of their works.
In other words, they would like to prevent the first purchaser of a copy from passing it on to
others. Why? Because the result would be to increase demand for copies, and thus to enhance
the copyright owner’s income. For example, novelists would like to be able to prevent sales of
used copies of their books. Movie studios would like to prevent, or to charge for resales or
rentals of DVDs embodying their works, and so forth. Third, copyright owners would like to
prevent arbitrage, which corrodes their ability to engage in lucrative, differential pricing. This
last point is both complicated and important. I touched on it very briefly at the end of lecture
number four. I now want to discuss it in more detail. The following analysis consists of a
condensed version of an argument deployed in much more fine grain in an article I wrote some
years ago on this topic. If you’re curious about this phenomenon, you might wish to follow the
links on my home page.
Differential pricing, otherwise known as price discrimination, consists in the core case of
charging different consumers different prices for access to the same good or service. A subtler
form of differential pricing involves charging different consumers different prices for different
versions of the same good or service when the variation cannot be explained by differences in
the costs of the versions. A familiar example of the core case of differential pricing is when a bus
company or museum charges lower entrance fees to students or senior citizens than it does to
middle aged, non-students. A familiar example of the subtler form is the practice of airlines to
charge vastly more for a business class seat than for a coach class seat for a given trip. Suppose,
for example, that I want to fly from Boston to Los Angeles in the afternoon of June 1, 2014,
roughly three months from right now. I prefer American Airlines, so I visit the website of the
company, and check for available flights and prices. Flight 143, which departs at 4:30 in the
afternoon, suits my schedule well. I now have to choose a class. As you can see in Figure 95,
there are various options. But the major choice involves where in the plane I will sit. Flight 143
uses the Boeing 757-200 aircraft, which is configured as shown in Figure 96. So, if I want to sit in
what’s known as the main cabin, I will pay $400 or $500. If I want to sit up front, in first class, I’ll
pay more than three times as much. The difference between these prices cannot be explained
on the basis of the extra costs associated with a wide seat, better food, and more attentive
service. Rather, it reflects primarily the airline’s shrewd effort to capitalize on differences in the
price sensitivity of the two types of passengers. If I’m wealthy, or I’m able to rely on the
generous business expense account, I’ll choose first class. If neither, I’ll choose the main cabin.
Price discrimination usually increases the profits of the firm that engages in it. Why, then,
is it relatively uncommon? Because, with rare exceptions, the practice of price discrimination is
Figure 97: Market windows for major films from release date, circa 1990
17 USC § 106(3)
Subject to sections 107 through 122, the owner of copyright under this title has the
exclusive rights to do and to authorize any of the following:
(3) to distribute copies or phonorecords of the copyrighted work to the public by sale or
other transfer of ownership, or by rental, lease, or lending
17 USC § 602(a)
Importation into the United States or exportation from the United States, without the
authority of the owner of copyright under this title, of copies or phonorecords of a work
that have been acquired outside the United States is an infringement of the exclusive
right to distribute copies or phonorecords under section 106 actionable under section
501.
(1) importation of copies or phonorecords under the authority or for the use of the
Government of the United States or of any State or political subdivision of a State, but
(2) importation, for the private use of the importer and not for distribution, by any
person with respect to no more than one copy or phonorecord of any one work at any
one time, or by any person arriving from outside the United States with respect to
copies or phonorecords forming part of such person’s personal baggage; or
17 USC § 109
(a) Notwithstanding the provisions of section 106(3), the owner of a particular copy or
phonorecord lawfully made under this title, or any person authorized by such owner, is
entitled, without the authority of the copyright owner, to sell or otherwise dispose of
the possession of that copy or phonorecord.
(i) a computer program which is embodied in a machine or product and which cannot
be copied during the ordinary operation or use of the machine or product; or
(b)(1)(C) Nothing in this subsection affects any provision of chapter 9 of this title.
The financial interests of copyright owners are protected by Section 106(3) and 602(a) of
the US Statute. The first of these, as you can see, gives copyright owners the exclusive right “to
distribute copies or phonorecords of the copyrighted work to the public by sale or other transfer
of ownership, or by rental, lease, or lending.” 602(a) gives copyright owners analogous rights to
control importation and exportation of copies of their works. Now, if these are the only relevant
statutory provisions, they would reflect total victory by the copyright owners, but each of these
provisions is qualified by others. The right granted by 106(3) is curtailed quite sharply by 109(a),
which, as you can see provides that “the owner of a particular copy or phonorecord lawfully
made under this title, or any other person authorized by such owner, is entitled to sell or
otherwise dispose of the possession of that copy or phonorecord.” This provision is widely
known as the first sale doctrine. The basic idea underlying this doctrine is that once a copyright
owner has sold a copy, he cannot control resales, gifts, et cetera. We’ll return to the precise
meaning of this provision in a minute. The right to prevent unauthorized importation of copies is
also qualified in various ways. Three specific exceptions are listed under 602(a). In addition, the
way in which 602(a) is phrased leaves open the possibility that it is qualified, not just by these
specific exemptions, but also by the much broader first sale doctrine embodied in 109(a). How
might this work? Well, you’ll notice that 602(a) refers to unauthorized importation as “an
infringement of the exclusive right to distribute copies under Section 106.” Section 106, in turn,
makes all the rights it grants to copyright owners “subject to sections 107 through 122.”
Included in that list is 109(a), which we’ve already seen. Through this chain of connections, it’s
possible that the first sale doctrine qualifies the importation right, as well as the right to control
domestic distribution of copies of the work. We’ll return to this textual nuance shortly.
The first sale doctrine embodied in section 109(a) is itself subject to exceptions.
Specifically, to the provisions of 109(b)(1)(a). The key language is “neither the owner of a
particular phonorecord, nor any person in possession of a particular copy of a computer
program, may, for the purposes of a direct or indirect commercial advantage, dispose of that
phonorecord or computer program by rental, lease, or lending.” The primary purpose of this
provision was to shut down stores that, at the time of its adoption, were renting audio CDs to
customers who would then copy the sound recordings on those CDs to the hard drives of their
computers, return the CDs to the stores, and thereby avoid the cost of buying CDs of their own.
As you can see, this exception is subject to exceptions of its own. So graphically, the relationship
among these various provisions might be represented as shown in Figure 98 – 106(3) and the
primary portion of 602(a) advance the interests of copyright owners. 109(a) and 602(a) (1–3)
establish limits on those rights, giving expression to the sentiments opposed to the copyright
owner’s interests. 109(b)(1)(a) reinstates a portion of 106(3), with respect to some categories of
works. 109(b)(1)(b) tempers that reinstatement. As I hope you can see from the diagram, this
combination of statutory provisions seeks to manage the deep tension between the competing
forces that shape this field of the law, but the statute is not precise enough to resolve all issues.
The result is that there’s lots of litigation along this fault line. I’ll describe two sets of cases of
this sort. Others will likely come up in the discussions that accompany this lecture.
The reason why the relationship between 109(a) and 602(a) is so important is that it
determines the power of copyright owners to engage in international geographic price
discrimination. In other words, to sell copies of their works at high prices to customers in the
United States, and at lower prices to customers in poorer countries. In lecture number three, I
mentioned one among the many companies that engage in this practice – Omega. Here’s a brief
reminder. Omega has obtained a US copyright on the design shown in Figure 23. Omega
engraves a version of this logo on the underside of its watches. Omega sells those watches all
over the world. Typically, it sells them for lower prices in poor countries than in the United
States. Some years ago, Costco, a discount retailer using an intermediary, purchased some of the
watches that Omega had sold cheaply outside the United States, imported them into the United
States, and then began selling them in its US stores for prices lower than those used by Omega’s
authorized US dealers. Omega brought suit against Costco, contending that the so-called parallel
importation violated Omega’s copyright in the logo. Now Costco had a seemingly strong
defense. In an earlier case, called Quality King vs Lanza, the United States Supreme Court held
that 109(a) did indeed limit the reach of 602(a), with the result that a copyright owner could not
block importation of copies that he or it had sold outside the United States. However, Quality
King involved so-called round trip parallel importation. In other words, a situation in which the
copies of the work in question were lawfully manufactured in the United States, shipped
The Owners’ Rights Initiative hit the streets to see what you think of the Wiley v.
Kirtsaeng case.
Mark, Maryland: I think that once you’ve bought an item, you should be able to do with
it what you want. If you want to resell it, that should be up to you.
John, New York: Because I paid money for it, and gosh dang it, I should be able to do
whatever I want with it.
Toby, United Kingdom: I don’t own anything, I’m just borrowing things from a company
for a long time, which seems to be outrageous.
Jack, New York: How can they tell you that you don’t own what you buy? You used your
own money to buy that.
Mike, Kentucky: I think that would be totally unfair, and against capitalism.
Carolyn & Dan, Indiana: I would say it would be important to everybody, because that’s
just the way of America. We buy, we sell, we trade.
Toby, United Kingdom: Country boundaries aren’t what they once were. So, of course,
you should be able to buy and sell things, regardless of where you get them from.
Lawrence & Montay, Washington D.C.: I’d be very highly upset and pissed off due to
the simple fact that they’re trying to tell me what to do with an item.
Alan, Washington D.C.: It’ll affect everybody. Anybody that has a power to purchase
now will be impacted by this.
Doug, California: For one thing, in college books, it would be a killer. It’s already so
expensive to go to college that you should be able to use whatever textbooks we want,
wherever we got them, without having the threat of the government telling us that
that’s not appropriate to use.
Keenan, California: It really hurts the consumers. I’m really concerned about the
consumers because I’ m a consumer.
Toby, United Kingdom: That seems to add a whole new level of administration that’s
going to cost millions and millions of dollars. And that’s just – all that money going into
having to ask someone if you wants to sell your own things? That seems silly.
Tanisha, Washington D.C.: Just thinking of kind of the gravity of what that would mean.
It would piss me off a little bit.
Kim & Mia, Virginia: If I want to buy it, I’ll buy it. If I want to sell it, I’ll sell it. It’s my
right.
Perhaps moved in part by sentiments like these, the Supreme Court, in the Kirtsaeng case
– somewhat to my surprise – reversed the ruling of the lower court, holding that one way
parallel importation, like round trip parallel importation, is privileged by section 109. The heart
of the court’s rationale was that the statutory phrase “lawfully made under this title” is not a
geographic limitation. So long as copies of a work are made with the authorization of the
copyright holder, they are, in the Supreme Court’s judgment, lawfully made under this title. The
decision by the Supreme Court is widely and rightly regarded as a win for at least some
consumers in the United States, who may, as a result of the ruling, be able to obtain copyrighted
materials more cheaply. On the other hand, the decision disadvantages the residents of poor
countries. The reason is that the sellers of copyrighted materials are likely, in the future, to find
it somewhat harder to engage in international geographic price discrimination. If so, how will
they respond? One option, of course, will be to reduce the prices of their goods in the United
States. If their markets are poor countries are large enough, they may do that, but it’s at least as
Autodesk, not surprisingly, saw things differently. Steps one and two were just as Vernor
described them, but instead of selling the copy to CTA, Autodesk contended that it merely
leased the copy to CTA in return for various promises. CTA then purported to sell to Vernor a
copy it did not know, because 109(a) only applies to “the owner of a particular copy.” It did not
shield this transaction. The purported resale thus violated Autodesk’s distribution rights under
106(3). For the same reason, this last transaction was not shielded by 109(a). Vernor was no
more an owner of the copy than was CTA. Thus, selling the copy on eBay also violated 106(3). In
sum, according to Autodesk, the last two transactions were unlawful (see Figure 101).
We hold today that a software user is a licensee, rather than an owner of a copy, where
the copyright owner
(2) significantly restricts the user’s ability to transfer the software; and
The way in which this decision fits into the overall landscape of the law governing
distribution rights is indicated on the mind map. It’s reasonably well settled that, using Nimmer’s
typology, a transaction involving a copy of a copyrighted work is covered by 109(a), and thus
lawful, if and only if four conditions are satisfied.
When software firms provide customers copies of their programs in return for money,
requirements 1 and 2 are more or less automatically satisfied. However, if the software firm
adds to the transaction enough conditions to make the deal appear to be a lease of a copy, and
thus not a sale, then requirement 3 is not satisfied and as a result, the customer does not have a
privilege to resell that copy. This option is highly beneficial to software firms for two reasons.
First, by suppressing resales of copies, it enables the firms to sell more original copies. Second, it
helps the firm suppress arbitrage of copies sold cheaply to students and so forth, and thus
protects the firm’s primary markets, consisting of adult or commercial users. The result, as you
might expect, makes the software firms happy, but makes their customers much less happy.
Again, a highly technical ruling, which locates this particular transaction on one side rather than
the other of the fault line, has large economic implications.
A summary of the case law affecting provisions 602, 106 and 109 is shown in Figure 102.
8.2. Performances
The statutory provisions that govern the rights of performance and display are relatively few,
but they’re slippery. So, it’s important to be attentive to nuances here. The primary provisions
are subsections 4, 5, and 6 of section 106 (see below). Subsection 4 gives the owner of the
copyright in a literary, dramatic, musical, choreographic, pantomime, or audiovisual work the
exclusive right to perform that work publicly. Subsection 5 is analogous. It applies to the same
types of copyrighted works, plus pictorial, graphic, or sculptural works and the individual images
of an audiovisual work. It gives the owner of such things the right to display them publicly.
Finally, subsection 6. This was added quite recently, specifically in 1996. As I hope you’ll recall
from lecture number 3, before 1996 the owners of copyrights and sound recordings in the
United States did not enjoy any rights in public performance. At that time, the only provision
dealing with public performances was subsection 4, and if you look back at that subsection,
you’ll notice that sound recordings do not appear in the list of types of works that are covered.
Musical works appear. As you know by now, that means musical compositions but not sound
recordings. As I explained in lecture number 3, the record companies that hold the copyrights in
most commercially valuable sound recordings have long complained about this state of affairs.
In 1996 and then with a little bit of adjustment in 1998, Congress responded partially to the
record companies’ pleas and granted them a limited, very limited, public performance right,
which is now embodied in subsection 6. As you can see, it only applies to performances “by
means of a digital audio transmission.” In just a minute, I’ll give you some examples of
transmissions that fit within this phrase.
106: Subject to sections 107 through 122, the owner of copyright under this title has
the exclusive rights to do and to authorize any of the following …
(4) in the case of literary, musical, dramatic, and choreographic works, pantomimes,
and motion pictures and other audiovisual works, to perform the copyrighted work
publicly;
(5) in the case of literary, musical, dramatic, and choreographic works, pantomimes,
and pictorial, graphic, or sculptural works, including the individual images of a motion
picture or other audiovisual work, to display the copyrighted work publicly; and
(6) in the case of sound recordings, to perform the copyrighted work publicly by means
of a digital audio transmission.
17 USC § 101
To “perform” a work means to recite, render, play, dance, or act it, either directly or by
means of any device or process or, in the case of a motion picture or other audiovisual
work, to show its images in any sequence or to make the sounds accompanying it
audible.
To “display” a work means to show a copy of it, either directly or by means of a film,
slide, television image, or any other device or process or, in the case of a motion picture
or other audiovisual work, to show individual images nonsequentially.
(1) to perform or display it at a place open to the public or at any place where a
substantial number of persons outside of a normal circle of a family and its social
acquaintances is gathered; or
The crucial terms in these three statutory provisions are performance, display, and public.
Fortunately, all three are defined in Section 101 of the statute. As you can see, “perform” is a
very capacious definition. I’ll give some examples of its reach shortly. The key word in the
definition of “display” is show. Both performances and displays of copyrighted works can only
give rise to liability if they’re done publicly. Section 101 defines “publicly” as one of two things.
MW: music work; SR: sound recording; private performances are marked in green, public ones in red
Those are the main statutory provisions. Now let’s turn to some examples to give these
provisions a bit of shape. Here’s a hypothetical but not implausible scenario, the purpose of
which is to illustrate these concepts (refer to MW: music work; SR: sound recording; private
performances are marked in green, public ones in red
Figure 103). Suppose:
▪ A sings a copyrighted musical composition into a microphone in a recording
studio.
▪ Record company B records A’s rendition on a record. I know these technologies
are quaint, but bear with me.
▪ C purchases a copy of the record and plays it on a turntable in his or her living
room. Sounds are generated, either from the turntable directly or more likely
from an amplifier and a set of speakers connected to the turntable. Those sounds
spread through C’s living room.
▪ Another copy of the record is purchased by radio station D. A disc jockey working
for the radio station plays the record on a turntable there. The signal generated by
[I]n light of the purpose and text of the [Transmit] Clause, we conclude that when an
entity communicates the same contemporaneously perceptible images and sounds to
multiple people, it transmits a performance to them regardless of the number of
discrete communications it makes.
This language is quite broad. Among other things, it seems to render irrelevant the factor
that the court of appeals treated as so important in Cablevision – namely, whether a
transmission is made to a single subscriber using a single unique copy produced by that
This sentence, although not a model of clarity, would seem to leave a safe harbor for
cloud locker services and arguably for services like Cablevision that allow consumers who have
already paid for programming to watch those programs at later times or in different places.
Finally, Breyer pointedly emphasized “[T]he doctrine of ‘fair use’ can help to prevent
inappropriate or inequitable applications of the [Transmit] Clause.” The potentially expensive
safe harbor that might be built on that sentence will become apparent next week. Sadly, the net
effect of the Supreme Court’s ruling in Aereo is to reduce considerably the clarity that in the
wake of Cablevision stimulated so much investment in cloud-based technologies. For the next
few years, lower courts confronted with challenges to businesses that offer consumers new
kinds of streaming services will have to determine whether they are more like Cablevision or
more like Aereo. Until the dust settles, entrepreneurs and technology innovators will have some
trouble predicting what they can and cannot do.
An additional source of instability is the divergence between the United States and Europe
with respect to the permissibility of services of this general sort. As I hope you’ll call from the
first lecture in this series, one of the multilateral treaties to which the United States is a party is
the WIPO Copyright Treaty of 1996. Articles 6 and 8 of that treaty require member countries to
provide copyright owners a generous version of the right of distribution and a right of
communication to the public. Both provisions use the phrase “make available to the public,”
which arguably encompasses more activities than are reached by US law. Nevertheless, after the
treaty was ratified, the United States took the position that this language did not require any
adjustment in US law because sections 106(3) and 106(4), as construed by the US courts, already
adequately provided such a so-called make available right. That contention was dubious when it
was first made and has become more so over time. In Europe, as professor Jane Ginsburg of
Columbia Law School has shown, the right to make works available to the public is construed
more broadly than in the United States and in particular is less forgiving of cloud-based services
of the sorts we have been considering. The Information Society Directive of 2001, which
17 USC § 110
Notwithstanding the provisions of section 106, the following are not infringements of
copyright:
(2) except with respect to a work produced or marketed primarily for performance or
display as part of mediated instructional activities transmitted via digital networks, or a
performance or display that is given by means of a copy or phonorecord that is not
lawfully made and acquired under this title, and the transmitting government body or
accredited nonprofit educational institution knew or had reason to believe was not
lawfully made and acquired, the performance of a nondramatic literary or musical work
or reasonable and limited portions of any other work, or display of a work in an amount
comparable to that which is typically displayed in the course of a live classroom session,
by or in the course of a transmission, if—
(A) the performance or display is made by, at the direction of, or under the actual
supervision of an instructor as an integral part of a class session offered as a regular
part of the systematic mediated instructional activities of a governmental body or an
accredited nonprofit educational institution;
(B) the performance or display is directly related and of material assistance to the
teaching content of the transmission;
I the transmission is made solely for, and, to the extent technologically feasible, the
reception of such transmission is limited to—
(i) students officially enrolled in the course for which the transmission is made; or
(aa) retention of the work in accessible form by recipients of the transmission from the
transmitting body or institution for longer than the class session; and
(II) does not engage in conduct that could reasonably be expected to interfere with
technological measures used by copyright owners to prevent such retention or
unauthorized further dissemination;
One of the more straightforward exceptions is section 110(1). That provision permits in a
classroom a public performance or display that would otherwise violates Section 106(4) or
106(5) as long as it’s done live, and as long as the copy of the work in question was prepared
lawfully. This means that when I present audiovisual works in the course of outlining case
studies in my classroom, I’m on safe ground, so as long as the material I show was prepared
lawfully. A closely related provision is 110(2), also known as the Teach Act, which deals with
distance learning. It’s a very good idea to have a statutory provision that creates a safe harbor
for distance learning. Unfortunately, in practice this particular provision is almost completely
ineffective. The first thing you notice about 110(2) is that it’s extremely complicated, contrasting
sharply with the simplicity of 110(1). The portions underlined impose upon a defendant who
seeks to invoke this provision many quite detailed obligations. Most importantly, 110(2) is only
applicable to formal instruction of enrolled students. That’s it’s inapplicable to the copies of
these recorded lectures that I make available to the public. It’s also limited to streaming of
materials. If a teacher wishes to invoke this provision, he cannot make copies of any of those
materials available for downloading, nor can he stream copyrighted materials in a way that
enables students to copy them. Again, this restriction renders the provision useless for the kind
of instruction I’m trying to do in this course. Next, the provision is limited to materials that are
not designed for distance education. In other words, the copyrighted works at issue have to have
been designed for some other purpose and then adapted to distance education. A teacher must
accompany those materials with instructions about copyright law. This may not be a problem in
this course, which happens to be about copyright law, but it’s a burden with respect to most
other courses. Finally, the teacher must adopt technologies to prevent the recipients from
17 USC § 110
Notwithstanding the provisions of section 106, the following are not infringements of
copyright:
Section 110(3) is much simpler than 110(2). It deals with public performances of religious
works in the course of services. It’s not obvious that this exception advances social welfare.
Putting aside the constraints imposed by the clauses in the US Constitution pertaining to the
establishment and free exercise of religion, and just doing the provisioning from a policy angle,
the result of 110(3) is to make it a lot easier for churches and other religious establishments to
operate. But it also means that the creators of religious materials, specifically non-dramatic,
literary musical works, don’t get paid as much insofar as often the principal value of their
creations is through performances. Perhaps the premise is that religious composers are
motivated by non-monetary incentives, and thus we don’t need to compensate them in order to
stimulate their work? Not clear.
17 USC § 110
Notwithstanding the provisions of section 106, the following are not infringements of
copyright:
(i) the notice shall be in writing and signed by the copyright owner or such owner’s duly
authorized agent; and
(ii) the notice shall be served on the person responsible for the performance at least
seven days before the date of the performance, and shall state the reasons for the
objection; and
(iii) the notice shall comply, in form, content, and manner of service, with requirements
that the Register of Copyrights shall prescribe by regulation;
Section 110(4) is the so-called nonprofit exception. This one is often neglected, but it’s
actually very important. As you can see, it privileges live performances of a non-dramatic literary
or musical work without any purpose of direct or indirect commercial advantage. Restaurant
waiters, for example, sometimes sing Happy Birthday to patrons. That’s not copyright
infringement as long as there’s no direct or indirect commercial advantage. If the restaurant or
the waiters charge the friends of the birthday boy or girl, they would not be shielded by this
provision, but as long as there’s no independent charge for the performance, they’re probably
on safe ground. Some years ago there was a big controversy that implicated this particular
provision. ASCAP is one of the organizations in the United States that issues blanket licenses,
blanket performance licenses, to many organizations allowing them to publicly perform musical
works. Foolishly, ASCAP apparently decided to seek license fees from the Girl Scouts in return for
permitting the Scouts to sing songs around their campfires. This was a public relations disaster
for ASCAP. The Wall Street Journal wrote a scathing article about it. And in the end, ASCAP
backed down and now grants the Girl Scouts public performance rights for a nominal fee. How
did ASCAP get itself in this position in the first place? In particular, doesn’t 110(4) permit the
Scouts to perform the songs without getting a license? It’s not entirely clear, but the answer
seems to be the Girl Scout camps that the ASCAP threatened with liability were charging for
access to them. That made 110(4) inapplicable.
17 USC § 110
Notwithstanding the provisions of section 106, the following are not infringements of
copyright:
(5)
(i) in the case of an establishment other than a food service or drinking establishment,
either the establishment in which the communication occurs has less than 2,000 gross
square feet of space (excluding space used for customer parking and for no other
purpose), or the establishment in which the communication occurs has 2,000 or more
gross square feet of space (excluding space used for customer parking and for no other
purpose) and—
(II) if the performance or display is by audiovisual means, any visual portion of the
performance or display is communicated by means of a total of not more than 4
audiovisual devices, of which not more than 1 audiovisual device is located in any 1
room, and no such audiovisual device has a diagonal screen size greater than 55 inches,
and any audio portion of the performance or display is communicated by means of a
total of not more than 6 loudspeakers, of which not more than 4 loudspeakers are
located in any 1 room or adjoining outdoor space;
(ii) in the case of a food service or drinking establishment, either the establishment in
which the communication occurs has less than 3,750 gross square feet of space
(excluding space used for customer parking and for no other purpose), or the
establishment in which the communication occurs has 3,750 gross square feet of space
or more (excluding space used for customer parking and for no other purpose) and—
(v) the transmission or retransmission is licensed by the copyright owner of the work so
publicly performed or displayed;
Now, we get to two related exceptions – the so-called home-style exception and the
FMLA, which is an abbreviation for Fairness in Music Licensing Act. The home-style exception
embodied in Section 110(5)(B) is, as its informal name suggests, a privilege for publicly
performing copyrighted works using the kind of apparatus that you would ordinarily find in a
home. That’s a little vague, and it’s changing as technology evolves, but the rough idea is that if
the gizmo you used perform a work is the kind of tuner plus speakers that you would ordinarily
have in your living room, then it’s OK. The standard is vague and not often litigated, but there it
is. As I trust you see, this exception operates to shield some of the performances we were
worried about in the previous segment of this lecture. Unfortunately, it’s not broad enough to
shield stores and restaurants who want to play music to entertain their customers, but need to
deploy apparatuses bigger than you would find in an ordinary home. So, organizations
representing restaurants and stores sought and obtained 110(5)(B) commonly known as the
Fairness in Music Licensing Act. This one is extremely complex. You can read the details at your
leisure. The operators of bars, restaurants, and retailers when deciding how big an operation to
set up and how to outfit it, pay lot of attention to the details here. If they’re able to stay under
these statutory ceilings, they can escape altogether an obligation to pay copyright owners,
particularly ASCAP, any licensing fees. An alarm bell should be going off now. You’ll recall that
the Berne Convention requires member countries to grant certain substantive rights and limits
their ability to carve exceptions out those rights. The TRIPS Agreement, discussed in lecture
number one, incorporates and extends those requirements and creates a mechanism for
punishing WTO countries that fail to abide by them. May the US without running afoul of those
agreements carve out of the performance right an exception this broad? The European Union
thought no and brought a dispute resolution proceeding against the US concerning the FMLA
and won. In other words, the US, in this respect, was deemed to be in violation of TRIPS. So, did
the US Congress amended the statute? Surprisingly, no. Instead, the US responded by submitting
17 USC § 109
(d) The privileges prescribed by subsections (a) and (c) do not, unless authorized by the
copyright owner, extend to any person who has acquired possession of the copy or
phonorecord from the copyright owner, by rental, lease, loan, or otherwise, without
acquiring ownership of it.
The last of the exceptions we’re going to deal with in this lecture concerns not public
performances, but public displays. This exemption is contained not in section 110, which has
occupied us until this point, but in section 109. As we can see here, 109I provides
notwithstanding the provisions of section 106(5). That’s the public display right. The owner of a
particular copy lawfully made under this title to display that work publicly is not violated if he
shows it to viewers present at the place where the copy is located. The upshot is that you can
hang a painting on the wall of your living room, and you can host a wedding reception or a
garden tour in your house, enabling lots of strangers to see the painting without infringing the
painter’s copyright. As you can see, this is a major exception and helps to relieve the otherwise
quite surprising reach of 106(5).
For the past several minutes, we have been examining types of performances that the law
excuses outright. In other words, we’ve been studying statutory provisions that give people an
unqualified privilege to engage in particular sorts of performances and displays without
permission and without paying the copyright owners anything. We turn finally to a set of
provisions that permit people to engage in particular sorts of performances without permission,
but require them to pay the copyright owner’s fees that are set in some way by the government.
As you know now, such provisions are known as compulsory licenses. From the standpoint of the
copyright owners, these provisions are not great because they deprive the owners of the
capacity to control uses of their works and, typically, though not invariably, force them to accept
license fees that are lower than the copyright owners given their druthers would demand. But
from the standpoint of the owners, such provisions are much better than the exceptions we’ve
just finished surveying because the owners are at least paid something.
innovators to produce their creations in the first instance. An unfortunate side effect of the
strategy is that some potential consumers are priced out of the market for copies of the
creation, giving rise to a welfare loss represented by the red zone. That’s regrettable, but we
accept those social costs in order to offer creators sufficiently large carrots to induce them to
make things we need or enjoy. If administered sensibly, compulsory licenses, it is argued, enable
us to improve on the system. Compulsory licenses force copyright owners to accept fees lower
than they would otherwise demand. That, of course, reduces their profits, but the loss is
partially offset by an increase in output. The result is that the blue zone in this picture (Figure
104, right) is smaller than the blue zone in the preceding picture, but not by an enormous
amount. Conversely, as you can readily see when the images are juxtaposed, the imposition of a
compulsory license sharply reduces the concomitant dead-weight loss. The ratio between
incentives and losses associated with uncontrolled licensing markets on the left is lower than the
ratio between incentives and losses associated with controlled markets on the right. Opponents
contend that the administrative costs associated with the system on the right will exceed the
cost savings it enables.
The last of the four arguments is the simplest. Compulsory licenses are sometimes
necessary, it is said, to enable socially-beneficial activities to flourish. This is a hard argument to
make with respect cable re-transmissions, but perhaps easier with respect to public
broadcasting systems. The argument can be expressed in the language of economics. Public
broadcasting has strong positive externalities that the stations are unable to capture, so we
need to reduce its costs if it is to survive. Or the same argument can be expressed in more moral
terms. Public broadcasting helps educate the citizenry, generating a more informed, responsible,
and tolerant electorate. For that reason, we should and do place a thumb on its side of the scale.
You decide who’s right.
In deciding whether to excuse a particular use, one should look to the nature and
objects of the selections made, the quantity and value of the materials used, and the
In several other US cases in the late 19th and early 20th centuries, federal courts followed
Folsom in excusing as fair various activities that appeared to run afoul of the copyright statute.
In these early decisions, the question of what constituted a fair use was not crisply differentiated
from the issue of whether the defendant’s behavior abridged the plaintiff’s exclusive rights. But
by the middle of the 20th century, courts in the US had begun consistently to refer to the concept
of Fair Use as a distinct legal issue. Specifically, as an affirmative defense excusing otherwise
unlawful conduct.
For most of its history, fair use was an entirely judge-made doctrine. That changed in 1976
when Congress revamped the copyright statute, it acknowledged and approved the line of
judicial decisions that had created fair use, and Congress codified those decisions in Section 107
of the reconstructed copyright statute. When codifying fair use however, Congress made
explicit, but it did not intend to “freeze” the doctrine, but rather expected it to continue to
evolve particularly in order to accommodate “rapid technological change.” The text of Section
107 is set forth below.
17 USC § 107
Notwithstanding the provisions of sections 106 and 106A, the fair use of a copyrighted
work, including such use by reproduction in copies or phonorecords or by any other
means specified by that section, for purposes such as criticism, comment, news
reporting, teaching (including multiple copies for classroom use), scholarship, or
research, is not an infringement of copyright. In determining whether the use made of a
work in any particular case is a fair use the factors to be considered shall include—
(1) the purpose and character of the use, including whether such use is of a commercial
nature or is for nonprofit educational purposes;
(3) the amount and substantiality of the portion used in relation to the copyrighted
work as a whole; and
(4) the effect of the use upon the potential market for or value of the copyrighted work.
The fact that a work is unpublished shall not itself bar a finding of fair use if such
finding is made upon consideration of all the above factors.
Although not conclusive, the first factor requires that the commercial or nonprofit
character of an activity be weighed in any fair use decision. If the Betamax were used
to make copies for a commercial or profit making purpose, such use would be
presumptively unfair. The contrary presumption is appropriate here, however, because
the district court’s findings plainly establish that timeshifting for private home use must
be characterized as a noncommercial, nonprofit activity.
Interestingly, Stevens did not mention in his opinion the second statutory factor – the
nature of the copyrighted work, so we’ll leave that box blank. The third factor – the amount of
copying – would seem to disfavor of finding a fair use, insofar as the VCR users were making
verbatim copies of entire shows or films. “Nevertheless, the court ruled that in light of the fact
that “timeshifting merely enables a viewer to see such a work which he had been invited to
In the court’s view, the record in the case – which had been created in 1978 – failed to
establish a likelihood of economic injury to the studios. Accordingly, the court ruled that the
fourth factor inclined in favor of a finding of fair use. Finally, the court pointed to a variable not
included in the statutory list of factors. “The district court’s conclusions are buttressed by the
fact that to the extent time shifting expands public access to freely broadcast television
programs, it yields societal benefits.” Taking all these variables into account, the Supreme Court
affirmed the district court’s judgment that timeshifting should be considered fair.
Justice Blackmun wrote a dissent in the case, which was joined by three other justices.
Blackmun disagreed with the majority of the justices on two main points. First, drawing on the
Ninth Circuit’s opinion, he differentiated what he called ordinary and productive uses of
copyrighted materials. Suggesting that the latter – meaning productive uses – are more likely to
qualify as fair than the former. Here’s how Blackmun made his argument.
The situations in which fair use is most commonly recognized are listed in section 107
itself. Fair use may be found when a work is used “for purposes such as criticism,
comment, news reporting, teaching, … scholarship, or research.” … Each of these uses
reflects a common theme. Each is a productive use resulting in some added benefit to
the public beyond that produced by the first author’s work. The fair use doctrine, in
other words, permits works to be used for “socially laudable purposes”. I am aware of
no case in which the reproduction of a copyrighted work for the sole benefit of the user
has been held to be fair use.
The requirement that a putatively infringing use of the copyrighted work, to be “fair,”
must not impair a “potential” market for that work has two implications. First, and
infringer cannot prevail merely by demonstrating that the copyright holder suffered no
net harm from the infringer’s action. Indeed, even the showing that the infringement
has resulted it in a net benefit to the copyright holder will not suffice. Rather, the
infringer must demonstrate that he had not impaired the copyright holder’s ability to
demand compensation from (or to deny access to) any group who would otherwise be
willing to pay to see or hear the copyrighted work. Second, the fact that a given market
for a copyrighted work would not be available to the copyright holder were it not for
the infringer’s activities does not permit infringer to exploit that market without
compensating the copyright holder.
Applying this definition of potential market to the facts of the case, Blackmun concluded
that the needle tilted toward the studios. And so far as a finding of fair use, we deprive them of
access to the “market consisting of those persons who find it impossible or inconvenient to
watch the programs at the time they are broadcast, and who wish to watch them at other times.
These persons are willing to pay for the privilege of watching the copyrighted work at their
convenience as is evidenced by the fact that they are willing to pay for VCRs and tapes.
Undoubtedly, most also would be willing to pay some kind of loyalty to copyright holders. The
studios correctly argue that they’ve been deprived of the ability to exploit this sizable market.”
The majority of the justices, as you’ve seen, were unconvinced.
In the many briefs filed with the Supreme Court – and in associated congressional
testimony which was being conducted at more or less the same time – the studios and their
allies predicted dire consequences if Sony escaped liability. Most lurid was a statement by Jack
Valenti, the president of the MPAA whom you encountered in lecture number six. Valenti
famously declared, “The VCR is to the American film producer and the American public as the
Boston Strangler is to the woman home alone.” As it turned out, the result of the court’s
decision was not so dire. Indeed, the film industry seems to have benefited from the machines.
Box office revenues did not seem to suffer. Even more dramatically, the widespread distribution
of VCRs made possible the emergence of a new and even more lucrative market consisting of
home video rentals and purchases.
While the courts were dealing with the Betamax case, a second major dispute implicating
the fair use doctrine was brewing. The facts were very different. In the late 1970s, former
President Gerald Ford with a substantial assistance of a ghost writer wrote an autobiography. He
assigned the copyright in the book to Harper and Row in return for a substantial payment. In
The first factor in a fair use enquiry is ‘the purpose and character of the use.’… The
central purpose of this investigation is to see, in Justice Story’s words, whether the new
work merely ‘supersede[s] the objects’ of the original creation, or instead adds
something new, with a further purpose or different character, altering the first with
The principles set forth in this paragraph, as we will see, have colored all subsequent fair
use jurisprudence. Applying this approach to the facts of the Campbell case, the Supreme Court
announced broadly “parody is an obvious claim to transformative value.” What then constitutes
a parody? The court offered several definitions, including the following.
All of the justices, except Justice Kennedy, seemed satisfied that 2 Live Crew’s song fit
within this definition, and thus that the first statutory factor favored the defendant. To be sure,
the Supreme Court did not rule that any work that falls within this definition automatically
qualifies as fair. On the contrary, the court announced that “parody, like any other use, has to
work its way through the relevant statutory factors and be judged case by case in light of the
ends of copyright law.” However, as we will see, the way in which the court worked those
statutory factors strongly favored parodists.
With respect to the second factor, the court conceded that Orbison’s song “fell within the
core of copyright’s protective purposes,” but it discounted the significance of that fact when the
defendant’s work consists of a parody. You’ll recall that in the Harper and Row case, Justice
O’Connor countered the third factor against Victor Navaski on the grounds that he had taken the
heart of President Ford’s biography. In the Campbell case, the Court of Appeals relied in part on
O’Connor’s language when ruling against 2 Live Crew.
If quotation of the opening riff and the first line may be said to go to the heart of the
original, the heart is also what most readily conjures up the song for parody. And it is
the heart at which parody takes aim. Copying does not become excessive in relation to
parodic purpose merely because the portion taken was the original’s heart. If 2 Live
Crew had copied a significantly less memorable part of the original, it is difficult to see
how its parodic character would come through.
The Supreme Court did not definitively resolve the application of the fourth factor, instead
remanding the case to the lower courts for reconsideration of this issue. But the guidelines that
Souter provided the lower courts strongly suggested that the outcome of that inquiry would
favor 2 Live Crew. In particular, the Supreme Court repudiated the “presumption that the Court
of Appeals had quite plausibly derived from the Betamax and Harper and Row opinions. Namely
the presumption that commercial uses of copyrighted materials give rise to injuries to the
market for the original work.” Souter and Campbell limited the scope of that ostensible
presumption to the context of “verbatim copying of the original in its entirety for commercial
purposes.” No such presumption, he contended, is appropriate when the defendant’s use is
transformative as in parody. The likely result, the 2 Live Crew song would qualify as a fair use.
So, this concludes our review of the way in which fair use doctrine in the United States
evolved from its inception in the early 19th century through the Campbell case. The table below
summarizes the application of the four fair use factors in the three cases.
Table 5: The application of the fair use factors in the Sony, Harper & Row, and Campbell cases
Figure 107: Sega Enterprises Ltd. v. Accolade, Inc. (9th Cir. 1992)
Taken together, these facts indicate that although Accolade’s ultimate purpose was the
release of Genesis-compatible games for sale, its direct purpose in copying Sega’s code,
and thus its direct use of the copyrighted material, was simply to study the functional
requirements for Genesis compatibility so that it could modify existing games and make
them usable with the Genesis console. Moreover, no other method of studying those
codes was available to Accolade. On these facts, we conclude that Accolade copied
Sega’s code for a legitimate, essentially non-exploitative purpose and that the
commercial aspects of its use can best be described as of minimal significance.
In this particular case, the link between Texaco’s commercial gain and its copying is
somewhat attenuated, the copying at most merely facilitating Chickering’s research
[Chickering was one of the scientists] that might have led to the production of
commercially-valuable products. Still, we need not ignore the for-profit nature of
Texaco’s enterprise, especially since we can confidently conclude that Texaco reaps at
So where does the combination of these two cases leave us? The answer is,
unfortunately, without clear guidance. When employees within a for-profit enterprise engage in
unauthorized copying whose immediate purpose might be characterized as research or study,
the employer may be able to contend that it should not be hit with the label “commercial.” But
how much latitude it will be given on this score is, unfortunately, hard to predict.
As I said, the question of whether a defendant’s behavior is commercial or non-
commercial in character remains a significant part of the fair use inquiry. However, that sub-
factor is being eclipsed increasingly by the second sub-factor, which asks whether the
defendant’s behavior is transformative. As we saw, this theme was highlighted by the United
States Supreme Court in the Campbell case. Since the Campbell decision, the issue of
transformativeness has grown further in importance. Today, it’s fair to say that defendants
unable to persuade a court that their activities are transformative are unlikely to prevail on fair
use grounds, whereas defendants who are able to assume the mantle of transformativeness are
quite likely to prevail. As one might expect, litigants now spend much of their time struggling
over who has the better of the argument on this issue. Unfortunately, as we will see, there
remains significant ambiguity concerning the possible meaning or meanings of the term
“transformative.” This uncertainty destabilizes fair use analyses and increases the notorious
unpredictability of the doctrine as a whole.
The only dimension of this issue that is clear cut concerns the status of parody. It’s now
well settled that parodies, even bad parodies, do qualify as transformative uses. Plaintiffs no
longer contended parodies of their works are not transformative. Instead, plaintiffs seek to
persuade tribunals that, in borderline cases, the defendants’ works do not constitute parodies.
Much hinges on this issue. When evaluating disputes of this sort, courts commonly make
reference to the definitions of parody that were offered by the Supreme Court in Campbell.
You’ve seen these definitions once before in this lecture. Here they are again.
Modern dictionaries describe a parody as a “literary or artistic work that imitates the
characteristic style of an author or work for comic effect or ridicule” or as a
“composition in prose or verse in which the characteristic turns of thought and phrase
in an author or class of authors are imitated in such a way as to make them appear
ridiculous.” For the purposes of copyright law, the nub of the definitions is the use of
The ambit of this definition is perhaps best illustrated by example. Annie Liebovitz, as you
likely know, is a famous and accomplished photographer. In 1991, she took a nude photograph
of the pregnant Demi Moore which appeared on the cover of the August 1991 issue of Vanity
Fair magazine. The photo plainly alluded to Botticelli’s “The Birth of Venus” (see Figure 108).
In 1994, Paramount Pictures began to promote its upcoming movie Naked Gun 33⅓. One
of its posters included this composite photo of Leslie Nielsen, the star of the film. Liebovitz
brought a copyright infringement suit. Interestingly, Paramount conceded that its poster
violated Liebovitz’s rights under section 106 but sought refuge in fair use. The district court
granted summary judgment for the defendant, and the Court of Appeals affirmed. A key step in
the Court of Appeals analysis was a determination that the poster constituted a parody of the
Demi Moore photo. The court justified that determination in the following terms.
Being different from an original does not inevitably comment on the original.
Nevertheless, the ad [meaning the poster] is not merely different. It differs in a way
that may reasonably be perceived as commenting through ridicule on what a viewer
might reasonably think is the undue self-importance conveyed by the subject of the
Liebovitz photograph. A photographer posing a well-known actress in a manner that
calls to mind a well-known painting must expect or at least tolerate a parodist’s
deflating ridicule. Apart from ridiculing pretentiousness, the ad might also reasonably
be perceived as interpreting the Liebovitz photograph to extol the beauty of the
pregnant female body and, rather unchivalrously, to express disagreement with this
Figure 108: The Vanity Fair cover featuring Demi Moore, a portion of Botecelli's "The Birth of
Venus", and the Naked gun 33⅓: The Final Insult poster that parodies the Vanity Fair cover
A very similar analysis underlay the determination five years later by the Ninth Circuit
Court of Appeals that a series of photos by Thomas Forsythe constituted parodies of Mattel’s
copyrighted character Barbie. Figure 109 shows a familiar image of Barbie. Mattel owns
copyrights to parts of this figure – specifically, in the court’s words, “to the unadorned Superstar
Barbie head and parts of the figure, including revisions to the hands, feet, neck, shoulder, and
buttocks.” Forsythe, without permission, took a series of photos of naked Barbie dolls, which he
called “Food Chain Barbie” (shown in Figure 109).
The Ninth Circuit, when the case arrived at its doorstep, concluded that Forsythe’s photos
plainly qualified as parodies.
Figure 109: Mattel’s Barbie and photos from Forsythe’s series “Food Chain Barbie”
An important procedural issue lurks in this passage. The Ninth Circuit is not interested in
what the public at large thinks of Forsythe’s photos. Indeed, it approved the trial court’s refusal
to consider a survey that Mattel had commissioned on the issue. Why? Because “the issue of
whether a work is a parody is a question of law, not a matter of public majority opinion.”
So, those are two cases in which the defendant successfully invoked the privileged status
of parodies. To repeat, parodies are not per se entitled to the fair use defense, but attaining that
status helps you a great deal. In part because of the importance of this issue, courts are not
always so receptive to defendants’ claims that their works constitute parodies. For example, the
Second Circuit brushed aside the contention of Jeffrey Koons that when he used the photograph
shown in Figure 110 as the reference work for this painted wooden sculpture (shown in Figure
111) he meant to mock the conventional, saccharine character of the photo. The court rejected
Koons’ claim that his work was a parody of the plaintiff’s. Its rejection was based in part on the
fact that the photograph was not widely known to the public, and thus most viewers of the
sculpture would not know what it was aimed at, but in addition, the court was not persuaded
that the sculpture meant to critique the photo.
The problem in the instant case is that even given that String of Puppies is a satirical
critique of our materialistic society, it is difficult to discern any parody of the
photograph Puppies itself. We conclude, therefore, that this first factor of the fair use
doctrine cuts against a finding of fair use. The circumstances of this case indicate that
Koons’ copying of the photograph Puppies was done in bad faith primarily for profit-
making motives and did not constitute a parody of the original work.
The same court was similarly unimpressed by the efforts of the defendants in the Castle
Rock case, which I discussed in the preceding lecture, to establish that their trivia book was a
parody of the Seinfeld television series. The defendant argued that the book “is a quintessential
example of critical text of the TV environment … expos[ing] all of the show’s nothingness to
articulate its true motive forces and its social and moral dimensions”. The court was unmoved.
“Any transformative purpose possessed by the defendant’s book is slight to nonexistent. We
reject the argument that it was created to educate Seinfeld viewers or to criticize, expose, or
otherwise comment upon Seinfeld. The book’s purpose, as evidenced definitively by the
statements of the book’s creators and by the book itself, is to repackage Seinfeld to entertain
Seinfeld viewers.”
So, to repeat, parodies definitively qualify as transformative under factor number one.
What about a defendant’s work that criticizes a plaintiff’s work but does not mock it? These too
are highly likely to be treated as transformative. Here’s an example. One of John Lennon’s most
famous songs is “Imagine.” Portions of its lyrics are critical of organized religion. Here’s an
excerpt.
In this case, the defendant, without permission, included this segment of Lennon’s
recording of the song in a movie that defended theories of intelligent design and criticized
Case color legend: Defendant prevailed (green); Plaintiff prevailed (red); Unresolved (black).
Figure 112: The nature of “transformative” and leading cases involving fair use
[J]ust how much weight within the first factor should a court place on this sub-factor of
bad faith? … Campbell provides … support for the proposition that while the good or
bad faith of a defendant generally should be considered, it generally contributes little
to fair use analysis. … We believe this analysis further supports our conclusion that a
The Harper & Row opinion also included a statement suggesting that customary activities
were more likely to qualify as fair than unconventional ones. “The fair use doctrine was
predicated,” said Justice O’Connor, “on the author’s implied consent to reasonable and
customary use when he released his work for public consumption.” This perspective associates
the concept of fair use with an implicit license issued by a copyright owner. Some scholars – for
example, Lloyd Weinreb in an influential article in the Harvard Law Review – have endorsed this
perspective, but it has little following currently in the case law, in part because so many fair use
cases nowadays involve new technologies as to which custom is essentially irrelevant.
If the first statutory factor focuses on the defendant, the second focuses on the plaintiff.
The basic idea here is that some kinds of copyrighted works deserve stronger protections against
unauthorized activities than do others. The way this is achieved is by making it harder for
defendants to assert fair use when they make unauthorized uses of the former than the latter.
So, what kinds of works are more deserving of protection? There are two well-recognized
answers to that question and one additional answer that is implicit in the case law but not
expressly recognized. The two well-established variables are A, unpublished works get more
protection than published works, and B, creative works get more protection than factual ones.
The Second Circuit’s decision in the Blanch case summarizes these two variables nicely.
Two types of distinctions as to the nature of the copyrighted work have emerged that
have figured in the decisions evaluating the second factor – one, whether the work is
expressive or creative, such as a work of fiction, or more factual, with a greater leeway
being allowed to a claim of fair use where the work is factual or informational; and
two, whether the work is published or unpublished, with the scope for fair use involving
unpublished works being considerably narrower.
This point bears emphasis, because it’s not often recognized. Not all works, it turns out,
enjoy the same degree of protection. The closer you are to the bottom left corner of Figure 113,
the stronger your legal shields. The closer you are to the upper right corner, the weaker your
shields. The implicit supplement to these two variables is that, in practice, computer software
seems to get less protection than other sorts of copyrighted works. In other words, in the
software context, defendants have an easier road to hoe.
11. (1) Notwithstanding the provisions of subsection (1) of section 9, the fair use of a
work, including such use by reproduction in copies or by any other means specified by
that section, for purposes such as criticism, comment, news reporting, teaching
(including multiple copies for classroom use), scholarship or research, shall not be an
infringement of copyright.
(2) The following factors shall be considered in determining whether the use made of a
work in any particular case is fair use :—
(a) the purpose and character of the use, including whether such use is of a commercial
nature or is for non-profit educational purposes ;
(b) the nature of the copyrighted work ;
(c) the amount and substantiality of the portion used in relation to the copyrighted
work as a whole ; and
(d) the effect of the use upon the potential market for, or value of, the copyrighted
work.
(3) The acts of fair use shall include the circumstances specified in section 12.
As you can see, the relevant provision of the Sri Lankan copyright act is virtually identical
to section 107 of the US Act – it has the same preamble and the same four factors. It emits only
the coda of section 107, which makes clear that unauthorized uses of unpublished works can
sometimes qualify as fair.
(2) For the purposes of this Act, the matters to which regard shall be had, in
determining whether a dealing with a literary, dramatic, musical or artistic work or
(a) the purpose and character of the dealing, including whether such dealing is of a
commercial nature or is for non-profit educational purposes;
(b) the nature of the work or adaptation;
(c) the amount and substantiality of the part copied taken in relation to the whole
work or adaptation;
(d) the effect of the dealing upon the potential market for, or value of, the work or
adaptation; and
I the possibility of obtaining the work or adaptation within a reasonable time at
an ordinary commercial price.
Singapore’s copyright statute, amended the year after Sri Lanka’s norm, is similar. Factors
a, b, c, and d once again echo, as you can see, the components of fair use in the United States.
But factor E is new: the instruction to consider “the possibility of obtaining the work or
adaptation within a reasonable time at an ordinary commercial price” has the effect of limiting
the availability of fair use somewhat, because it weakens the position of defendants who could
have obtained a license from the plaintiff but refused to do so. It may also put pressure on
copyright owners to collaborate in the organization of systems – like the Copyright Clearance
Center in the United States – that are designed to facilitate licensing, although that remains to
be seen. If it does the net effect would be roughly analogous to a compulsory licensing system of
the sort we have previously considered in this course. Economists disagree concerning whether
this provision can be shown to have contributed to Singapore’s subsequent economic boon.
(a) Fair use of a work is permitted for purposes such as: private study, research,
criticism, review, journalistic reporting, quotation, or instruction and examination by an
educational institution.
(b) In determining whether a use made of a work is fair within the meaning of this
section the factors to be considered shall include, inter alia, all of the following:
I The Minister may make regulations prescribing conditions under which a use shall be
deemed a fair use.
The Israeli provision adopted three years after Singapore’s adds yet another novel
element. As you can see, the final subsection empowers the Minister of Justice to “make
regulations prescribing conditions under which a use shall be deemed a fair use”. Thus far,
apparently, the government has not exercised this power, but it offers an intriguing potential
way of providing guidance, both to copyright owners and to users, concerning their respective
rights through a mechanism less expensive and fraught than litigation. Another feature of the
Israeli regime that emerges from the case law, rather than the statute or accompanying
regulations, concerns attribution. Professor L. Corcoran has pointed out that some courts in
Israel have taken the position that “appropriate credit must be accorded to the original author in
order for the use to be considered fair”. Such a requirement would implicitly import into the fair
use doctrine one of the components of moral rights. A possible justification for such a move will
emerge from our discussion next week of cultural theory.
Art 35-3: (1) Other than the cases stipulated from Article 23 to Article 35–2, Article
101–3 to Article 101–5 it shall be permissible to use works for purposes such as news
reporting, criticism, education, or research which do not conflict with a normal
exploitation of the work and do not unreasonably prejudice the legitimate interests of
the right holder.
(2) The following four factors must be considered in determining whether a particular
use is fair:
1. the purpose and character of the use, including whether such use is of commercial
nature or is for nonprofit purposes;
2. The nature of the copyrighted work;
3. Amount and substantiality of the portion used in relation to the copyrighted work as
a whole; and
4. The effect of the use upon the actual and potential market or value of the
copyrighted work.
185.1. The fair use of a copyrighted work for criticism, comment, news reporting,
teaching including multiple copies for classroom use, scholarship, research, and similar
purposes is not an infringement of copyright. Decompilation, which is understood here
to be the reproduction of the code and translation of the forms of the computer
program to achieve the inter-operability of an independently created computer
program with other programs may also constitute fair use. In determining whether the
use made of a work in any particular case is fair use, the factors to be considered shall
include:
(a) The purpose and character of the use, including whether such use is of a commercial
nature or is for non-profit education purposes;
(b) The nature of the copyrighted work;
(c) The amount and substantiality of the portion used in relation to the copyrighted
work as a whole; and
(d) The effect of the use upon the potential market for or value of the copyrighted work.
185.2. The fact that a work is unpublished shall not by itself bar a finding of fair use if
such finding is made upon consideration of all the above factors.
The parallel provision of the Philippine statute also deviates slightly from section 107 of
the US statute, but in a way that expands rather than constricts its coverage. As you can see, the
provision invites courts to treat as fair decompilation of computer programs for the purpose of
achieving interoperability with other programs
EU Copyright Directive
2. Member States may provide for exceptions or limitations to the reproduction right
provided for in Article 2 in the following cases:
5.2(a). Photocopying
5.2(b). Private copying
5.2(c). Reproductions by Libraries
5.2(d). Ephemeral Recordings
5.2I. Reproductions by Social Institutions
3. Member States may provide for exceptions or limitations to the rights provided for in
Articles 2 [right of reproduction] and 3 [right to communicate or make works available
to the public] in the following cases:
As you can see, article 5 of the 2001 EU Copyright Directive, which binds all member
countries, sets forth a list of specific exceptions and limitations. Only one of those exceptions is
mandatory under article 5.1: countries must exempt from liability incidental economically
unimportant reproductions of copyrighted works either by Internet intermediaries or that are
necessary to facilitate other lawful activities. All of the other provisions in the directive are
permissive: they identify types of unauthorized use of copyrighted materials that member
countries may permit but are not obliged to do so. The five sub-parts of section 5.2 identify uses
that unless excused would violate only the right of reproduction. The 15 sub parts of section 5.3
identify uses that unless excused would violate both the right of reproduction and the right to
communicate works or make them available to the public. Altogether, there are 21 provisions in
the list; some are extremely specific, such as 5.3(m) which pertains to copying a building plan for
the purpose of reconstructing the building in question, and 5.3(j), which pertains to reproducing
or showing work solely for the purpose of advertising exhibitions or sales of art. Others are
broader and more culturally important, such as 5.3(b), which governs reproductions of
copyrighted works in order to make them a more usable by people with disabilities, 5.3(d),
which pertains to quotation of copyrighted works for the purpose of criticizing them, and 5.3(k),
which governs use for the purpose of caricature, parody, or pastiche activities that – as we’ve
seen – figure prominently in US fair use case law.
To repeat, all of the provisions except for 5.1 are permissive. So, which of these have been
adopted in which countries? It’s a hard question to answer. There are currently 28 member
countries of the EU, although the number will soon shrink to 27. Multiplying 28 countries by 20
optional provisions yields 560 possible implementations. I considered trying to create a chart
indicating which countries have implemented which provisions, but was daunted by the scale of
the task. Fortunately, a selfless group of European copyright scholars have recently done so.
Their work can be found at the website copyrightexceptions.eu.
Figure 114 shows the chart that the scholars have created, indicating the treatment in
each member country of each option. As you can see, some of the directives’ invitations to
create exceptions have been accepted by all or almost all of the member countries. Examples
include 5.2I, which gives latitude to public libraries and museums when reproducing materials,
so long as it’s not used for commercial advantage; 5.3(a), which pertains to reproductions or
communications tied closely to teaching or scientific research; 5.3(b), previously mentioned,
which benefits persons with disabilities; and 5.3(c), which is designed to give the press some
freedom when reproducing or communicating copyrighted materials pertaining to “current
economic political or religious topics”, so long as they give the sources appropriate attribution.
Others are less widely accepted; an unsurprising example is 5.3(l), which pertains to copying for
the purpose of repairing or demonstrating equipment; much more surprising, at least to US
lawyers and residents, is the incomplete acceptance of 5.3(k), which governs parody and its
cousins.
There’s a great deal of information in this chart and I encourage you to pause at this point
and study it. However, one crucial dimension is necessarily omitted from the chart – namely,
how exactly each country has implemented each of the provisions that it has chosen to
incorporate. As Professor Bernt Hugenholtz points out in a recent article, some of the provisions
of article 5 of the directive are drafted in a way that leaves the legislators of the member
countries considerable discretion in this regard, and they have exercised that discretion in very
different ways. Consider, for example, 5.3(d), which permits member countries to privilege
“quotations for purposes such as criticism or review provided they relate to a work which has
already been lawfully made available to the public in which the source is indicated and their use
is in accordance with fair practice and the extent required by the specific purpose”. The
language, and in particular the language I emphasized in the quotation, permits – indeed forces
– a legislature either itself to make a judgment concerning what constitutes fair practice or to
Article 22: In the following cases, a work may be used without permission from, and
without payment of remuneration to, the copyright owner, provided that the name of
the author and the title of the work are mentioned and the other rights enjoyed by the
copyright owner in accordance with this Law are not prejudiced:
China currently employs the same general approach used by the European Union. Article
22 of China’s copyright law contains a list of enumerated exceptions, although it is shorter than
the EU list. Some items are relatively conventional – for example, the ninth exception for
“gratuitous live performances of a published work for which no fees are charged the public nor
payments are made to performers” echoes a provision of the US statute, and the tenth
exception, which privileges “copying, drawing, photographing or video recording of a work of art
put up or displayed in an outdoor public place” is an enlarged version of section 5.3(h) of the EU
directive, which permits countries to privilege “use of works such as works of architecture or
sculpture made to be located in public places”, which in turn echoes but expands upon a narrow
safe harbor in US law. But, two provisions in article 22 of the Chinese statute stand out for their
novelty and scope. Section 9, which creates an expansive privilege for free live performances of
public works, and section 11, which establishes a privilege to translate “a public published work
of Chinese citizen or legal entity from Han language into minority national languages for
publication and distribution in the country”.
Figure 114, displayed earlier, catalogues the implementation of the set of exceptions and
limitations enumerated in article 5 of the EU directive. The green squares identify countries that
have adapted each. Figure 115 includes an overlay that indicates in green which of those
Figure 115: Implementation status of the 22 exceptions and limitations to copyright for all 28 EU member states, with
China added for comparison
Copyright, specially in literary works, is thus not an inevitable, divine, or natural right
that confers on authors the absolute ownership of their creations. It is designed rather
to stimulate activity and progress in the arts for the intellectual enrichment of the
public. Copyright is intended to increase and not to impede the harvest of knowledge. It
is intended to motivate the creative activity of authors and inventors in order to benefit
the public.
Viewed from this angle, the activity of the defendant which had the effect of increasing
sharply the affordability of course materials to students should be excused, so the court ruled.
By contrast, a court in South Korea – one of the countries that employ the open-ended model
number one – recently ruled against the fair use argument made by a company claiming,
analogously, that it’s unauthorized activities would have important educational benefits.
The capacity of courts lying in the middle zone to extend the reach of seemingly narrowly-
crafted exceptions is also evident in recent history of Canada. At the start of the 21st century, the
statutory exceptions in the Canadian copyright statute were not especially capacious. However,
as Michael Geist has shown, the Canadian Supreme Court in a series of important opinions read
10.1. Premises
As you know by now, there are four main theories of intellectual property in general, and
copyright in particular.
The fairness theory, which finds inspiration in the work of John Locke, centers on the
principle that the law should be organized to provide authors and inventors what they morally
deserve. Somewhat more specifically, the law, seen from this perspective, should award them
property interest or monetary rewards commensurate with their creative efforts. The fairness
approach has disproportionate influence in the United States and other countries influenced by
the common-law tradition, but finds some support throughout the world.
The personality theory, which finds inspiration in the work of Kant and Hegel, is founded
on the principles that intellectual products are extensions of the personalities of their creators,
and that the law should be organized to respect and nourish the psychic bonds between creators
and their expressive products. The dimension of copyright law that is most closely associated
with personality theory is the set of so-called moral rights, which are most generously
recognized and enforced in continental Europe, and in other jurisdictions influenced by the civil
law tradition.
The third approach is the welfare theory, a branch of the broad philosophic tradition of
utilitarianism. The welfare theory of copyright starts with the proposition that intellectual
products are public goods, an unusual and especially important subset of products defined by
two related characteristics: they are both non-rivalrous and nonexcludable. Copyright law, seen
from this angle, constitutes a mechanism employed by governments to prevent such public
goods from being produced in less than socially optimal quantities. The general guideline that
emerges from this philosophic tradition is that the law should be adjusted so as to combine
optimally, on the one hand, incentives for innovation, and on the other hand, mechanisms for
ensuring that the fruits of innovation can be consumed or reused by others. This theory has
gained in strength in recent years. It is now the dominant approach to copyright law, at least in
the United States, in part because of the resonance between it and the utilitarian tenor of the
Constitutional clause on which intellectual property rights founded in the United States, and in
10.2. Implications
In the previous segment of the lecture, I outlined the premises of one variant of that approach.
We now turn to some implications for copyright law of that variant. The question I’ll try to
answer is: if for our aspiration were to foster A, opportunities for the good life, and B, the
cultural conditions that sustain such opportunities, how might we adjust the law? Listed on the
next page are 13 zones of possible legal reform. Items 1 through 8 involve copyright law proper.
Items 9 through 11 involve alternatives or supplements to copyright. Items 12 and 13 involve
other intellectual property regimes. In this segment of the lecture, I’ll consider the first eight
which, as I say, concern copyright law itself. In the third and last segment of the lecture, I’ll
consider, among other things, the supplementary implications alluded to in items 9, 10, and 11.
The remainder I’ll leave to another time and place.
This list of possible zones of reform is meant to be illustrative, not exhaustive. It’s
designed to suggest how the theory might be applied, not to provide a comprehensive recipe for
rebuilding copyright.
The first doctrinal implication is probably the most obvious. Copyright law affects
education in countless ways. We should adjust and apply the law so as to enable, not interfere
with, the kind of education I sketched and advocated before the break. For example, in lecture
number eight in this series, I discussed the provision of the US copyright statute that attempts to
The language that is underlined and in quotation marks was taken from Ford’s book. The
remaining language was Navasky’s. Justice Brennan, dissenting in this case, contended that two
aspects of the copyright system should have been construed so as to afford Navasky some
latitude. First, says Brennan, some leeway must be given to subsequent authors seeking to
convey facts, because those wishing to express the ideas contained in factual works often can
choose from only a narrow range of expression. Second, Brennan contended that when
evaluating the fair use defense weight should have been given both to the factual character of
the plaintiff’s work and to its public importance. But even Brennan did not challenge the claim
that quoting 300 of Ford’s words in this way constituted a prima facie violation of section 106(1)
of the statute. Justice O’Connor, writing for the majority, was even less forgiving. Here’s her
language.
The Nation has admitted to lifting verbatim quotes of the author’s original language
totaling between 300 and 400 words and constituting some 13% of the Nation article.
In using generous verbatim excerpts of Mr. Ford’s unpublished manuscript to lend
authenticity to its account of the forthcoming memoirs, the Nation effectively
arrogated to itself the right of first publication, an important marketable subsidiary
right.
Viewed through the lens of the cultural theory I have outlined, this is troubling.
Participatory political democracy, as we’ve seen, is one of the fundamental features of an
attractive and stimulating society. Political democracy is only possible if the citizenry is informed.
It’s hard to imagine an issue more central to political debate and engagement than the precise
reasons why one president decided to pardon another president for a crime.
Copyright law already contains a device that would have enabled the Supreme Court to
respect this consideration. Language of the sort lifted from the manuscript by Navasky could
quite plausibly have been described as a fact. Generalizing the point, we or the Supreme Court
could have declared that any language or material essential to political deliberation and civic
engagement is either a fact or an idea and thus up for grabs in the political arena. That would
have left Navasky off the hook without needing to reach the fair use doctrine, and the result
would’ve been to encourage journalists in the future to make more widely available analogous
utterances by major public figures.
Here’s another example of the same point. You’ll recall our discussion in lecture number
six of the case that considered whether Martin Luther King complied with the statutory
Case color legend: Defendant prevailed (green); Plaintiff prevailed (red); Unresolved (black).
Figure 116: Leading cases where “transformative” was defined as “creative” highlighted by the green ellipse
The situations in which fair use is most commonly recognized are listed in section 107
itself. Fair use may be found when a work is used “for purposes such as criticism,
comment, news reporting, teaching, … scholarship, or research.” … Each of these uses
reflects a common theme. Each is a productive use resulting in some added benefit to
the public beyond that produced by the first author’s work. The fair use doctrine, in
other words, permits works to be used for “socially laudable purposes”. I am aware of
no case in which the reproduction of a copyrighted work for the sole benefit of the user
has been held to be fair use.
Advantages
1. For consumers
a. Large cost savings – they would pay less under this system than under
the current combination of business models
b. Unlimited access to recorded media
Disadvantages
1. Cross-subsidies
a. Result: distortions in consumer behavior, deadweight losses, and
unfairness
b. Vary substantially with the method of taxation
c. Mitigate with Ramsey pricing (Benkler)
2. Moral rights concerns
a. Classic moral rights (rights of Integrity and rights of Attribution)
b. Increased opportunities for creative reuse of digital copies threaten
both
c. Possible responses:
i. Give artists the option to retain or relinquish rights of integrity –
perhaps use financial incentives to increase their willingness to
give up these rights, or a higher payout rate
ii. Recognize that, with respect to cultural products distributed in
multiple copies, rights of integrity are obsolete; by contrast,
One of the most difficult issues currently confronting lawmakers throughout the world is
how, if at all, to shield so-called “traditional knowledge” against unauthorized uses. Roughly
speaking, the term traditional knowledge refers to cultural products developed over long
periods of time, typically by the members of indigenous groups. Examples include traditional
music, dances, fabrics, costumes, folklore, and religious icons. Such things do not fit well the
template of copyright law. In part because the authors of such things are usually collective, hard
to identify, and long dead. In addition, the concerns of the groups who object to the non-
permissive use of traditional cultural expressions (sometimes abbreviated as TCEs) are usually
quite different from the combination of economic and personhood interests implicated by most
copyrighted works. If copyright law doesn’t work well in this setting, what would work better?
That’s far from clear. Countries continue to experiment with a wide variety of models. Various
insight into those possible ways of dealing with traditional knowledge might be derived from the
cultural theory we have outlined here. Unfortunately, those insights conflict. Cultural theory is
thus arguably helpful in identifying some things we should strive to achieve or protect, but not
particularly helpful in telling us how to do so. Here are some of the competing considerations.
▪ The use or performance of TCEs is one of the ways in which some communities
define and sustain themselves. Because preservation of communities is one of the
things commended by cultural theory, we should strive if possible to protect these
practices from corrosion or dissipation.
▪ Protecting TCEs from appropriation by persons or firms outside the indigenous
groups that created and sustained them would also promote cultural diversity by
helping to resist the trend towards global cultural homogenization.
▪ Allowing indigenous groups to charge, or otherwise be compensated for uses of
their TCEs, would also provide them a source of funds that would mitigate their
impoverishment and promote distributive justice. Note however, that this third
consideration is in some tension with the first and second, which seemed to
presume that the TCEs would not spread.
On the other side of the ledger, protections for traditional knowledge are hard to
reconcile with the value of semiotic democracy – the merit of enabling all persons, both
4) gatekeepers whom legal rules can induce to detect misconduct at reasonable cost.
For subtle application of this framework, to override the problems, many but not all of
which involve securities regulation, I encourage you to consult Kraakman’s article, which is
available in the spring 1986 issue of the Journal of Law Economics and Organization. Our concern
here is, of course, not the general theory of gatekeeper liability but with copyright law. As
applied to copyright, Kraakman’s guidelines would suggest that penalties should be imposed on
third parties in hopes of suppressing infringing behavior by others only if:
In many of the contexts I’ll be discussing this lecture, the first two requirements are
probably met. The third and fourth, however, are not so invariably satisfied. When assessing the
imposition of secondary liability in a particular context or case, you should ask yourself, if we
penalize this particular third party, will the incidents of direct infringement diminish? Or will the
direction infringers just find some other enabler? And what are the social costs of imposing
secondary liability in this setting? This last question will be especially salient when dealing with
so-called dual use technologies – in other words, technologies that can be and are used both to
facilitate illegal behavior and to facilitate lawful and socially beneficial behavior. When
considering the use of secondary liability to suppress such technologies, you should consider
carefully whether the social benefits of blocking the bad uses exceed the social harms of
blocking the good uses. If not, then the use of secondary liability reduces rather than enhances
net social welfare.
So, to review: deployments of secondary liability in copyright law can and frequently are
evaluated or justified from one of two perspectives – the immorality of helping someone to
violate the rights of others, and the possible, though not inevitable, net benefits to social welfare
of enlisting gatekeepers to control otherwise resistant forms of misconduct. With those two
perspectives in mind, let’s turn to the law.
17 USC § 106
Subject to sections 107 through 122, the owner of copyright under this title has the
exclusive rights to do and to authorize any of the following:
(3) to distribute copies or phonorecords of the copyrighted work to the public by sale or
other transfer of ownership, or by rental, lease, or lending;
(4) in the case of literary, musical, dramatic, and choreographic works, pantomimes,
and motion pictures and other audiovisual works, to perform the copyrighted work
publicly;
(5) in the case of literary, musical, dramatic, and choreographic works, pantomimes,
and pictorial, graphic, or sculptural works, including the individual images of a motion
picture or other audiovisual work, to display the copyrighted work publicly; and
(6) in the case of sound recordings, to perform the copyrighted work publicly by means
of a digital audio transmission.
The doctrines of contributory and vicarious infringement were developed by the courts
with little or no guidance from the legislature. Sometimes these doctrines are said to be rooted
in the language of Section 106 of the statute, which, as you can see above, gives copyright
owners the exclusive right to “do or to authorize” any of the things we have considered in the
By contrast, to hold a defendant liable for vicarious infringement a plaintiff must show
three somewhat different things.
from playing the songs without permission. Under these circumstances, the owners of the
copyrights in the songs would have three causes of action. A claim against the group for direct
infringement, namely, as you know by now, a violation of the public performance right
embodied in Section 106(4). A claim against the manager for contributory infringement because,
although the manager himself did not publicly perform any compositions, he plainly knew of the
band’s plan and encouraged it. And finally, a claim against the owner of the hall for vicarious
infringement, because even if the owner did not know of the band’s plan, he is profiting from
the band’s behavior and he failed to exercise his clear power to stop them.
All of this is straightforward, I hope. Now, let’s consider a few modern cases where the
application of these principles is less clear-cut.
A prosaic but influential case was decided by the Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit in
1996. The defendant, Cherry Auction, was the operator of this flea market, located in Fresno,
California. A flea market, otherwise known as a swap meet, is a marketplace where a large
number of independent vendors sell merchandise, typically inexpensive or used merchandise, to
customers who come hunting for bargains. In this instance, the vendors, as is typical, paid
modest rental fees to Cherry Auction. Cherry Auction provided those vendors booth space,
operated the parking facilities, and advertised the marketplace. In addition to collecting fees for
the vendors, Cherry Auction collected entrance fees from the customers. Finally, Cherry Auction
reserved the right to exclude any vendor for any reason. The plaintiff, Fonovisa, Incorporated,
owns the copyrights in a large number of Latino sound recordings. Fonovisa complained several
times at Cherry Auction that some of the vendors in the flea market were selling pirated copies
of Fonovisa’s recordings, to no avail. Finally, Fonovisa brought suit against the flea market.
liability are set forth on the right. The second ruling we capable of substantial
discussed in lecture number nine. Our concern here is with noninfringing uses.
the first ruling. The key phrase in it comes at the end: 2. Timeshifting copyrighted
“capable of substantial non-infringing uses.” Using the first programs is a fair use.
letters of those words as an abbreviation, this dimension of
the Sony decision might be called the COSNU defense.
This standard for secondary liability, which the court adapted from a loosely analogous
aspect of patent law, is quite generous to defendants. Taken literally it means that the
manufacturer and distributive of a dual use technology does not need to show that his product
is often used for legal purposes, or even that it is ever used for legal purposes, but merely that it
is capable of being used for substantial legal purposes. Sony of course, easily passed that test
who wished to join the community and gain access to those recordings, would first log into the
website and download from it a free piece of software known as MusicShare. After installing the
software on his computer, the user would sign up by selecting a unique username, typically
fictitious, and a password. He would then create on his computer a “user library” into which he
would copy any recordings, typically in the form of MP3 files, that he wanted to share with other
users. He would then log into the Napster system. His software would talk to the software on
Napster’s servers. One result of that conversation is that a list of the files on his computer would
appear in the Napster directory. The files themselves would not be copied onto the servers of
Napster’s site, just their names. That’s the significance of the hollow circles in the diagram in
Figure 118.
Other users would be doing the same thing. Suppose one of the subscribers, say user
number two, wanted to find some recordings by Eric Clapton. She would submit a search
request using Clapton’s name. If any of Clapton’s recordings appeared in the index, the software
would identify which of the libraries of currently logged in subscribers contained those
recordings, and provide that information to the application on user number two’s computer.
That information would enable her computer to connect directly to one of those host
computers, here belonging to user number one, download a copy of the file directly from the
host computer, and save it on user number two’s hard drive. The fact that the two users’
computers were in direct contact explains the name peer to peer copying. User number two
could then either play the file directly from her computer or, if she had a CD burner and the
popular system developed by a renegade programmer at AOL, but more so than either Napster
or Aimster. In brief, a FastTrack user interested in exchanging files would locate, with the aid of a
central server, one of the set of computers connected to the Internet that functioned as so-
called supernodes, coordinating search requests among clusters of users. Once engaged in the
system, the user could submit a request, let’s say for a particular Clapton recording. If a copy of
the requested recording were located on one of the connected users’ computers, it would be
delivered to the requesting party with no further involvement by Grokster. Partly because of the
structure, the system was used reasonably often for non-infringing purposes, such as
distributing movie trailers, sharing the works of Shakespeare, and locating computer software
for which distribution is permitted, as well as for exchanging recordings unlawfully.
These circumstances prompted the district court judge who first heard the copyright
owners suit again Grokster to deny liability. The Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit also ruled
in favor of Grokster, reasoning that the existence of legitimate uses of the system means that
the defendants could not be charged with constructive knowledge of unlawful uses, just as Sony
could not be charged with constructive knowledge of unlawful uses of its VCRs. Grokster did not
learn of specific illegal uses of its technology until it was too late to stop them, and unlike
Fonovisa, the defendants were not supplying the site and facilities for illegality, and had no
affirmative duty to alter their software to prevent illegality. For all these reasons, in the
[O]ne who distributes a device with the object of promoting its use to infringe
copyright, as shown by clear expression or other affirmative steps taken to foster
infringement, is liable for the resulting acts of infringement by third parties.
The question immediately arises: how does a plaintiff go about proving inducement of this
sort? The court’s answer by offering evidence of “purposeful, culpable expression and conduct.”
I OSPs (store information for mass distribution to others) exempt if comply with notice
and takedown
(d) Search engines (information location tools) exempt if comply with notice and
takedown
(i) Duty to terminate repeat infringers and to “accommodate ... standard technical
measures” used by copyright owners
The details of section 512 are much too intricate to examine in this lecture. What I will do
in the remainder of this segment of the lecture is to sketch the basic principles underlying this
portion of the statute, and to describe the most important of the judicial opinions that thus far
has construed section 512. A subset of the components of 512 are set forth above. Internet
service providers, meaning passive intermediaries who simply carry packets of information from
one party to another, are not liable for copyright infringement, provided that they do not select
the stuff that is sent, or who it is sent to, or modify it en route. This should not be surprising. The
Postal Service is also not liable if some of the letters it carries contain unlawful material. Things
less obvious when we shift from ISPs to so-called OSPs, online service providers, which are
defined in section 512(k)(1)(b) as providers of online services or network access or the operators
of facilities therefore. To qualify for the section 512 safe harbor, such entities must abide by the
requirements set forth in 512(i) – in brief, adopting, announcing, and abiding by a policy for
terminating people who repeatedly abuse their services, and accommodating reasonable
technological protection measures adopted by the copyright owners.
If an OSP qualifies, it enjoys immunity with respect to various activities, including,
unsurprisingly, passive caching of the material that turns out to be infringing. The most
controversial of the activities for which OSPs may secure immunity concerns not carrying
packets from one person to another, or caching it for faster retrieval, but rather storing material
sent to them by one person, and making that material accessible to lots of other people. In 1998,
1. Publicly identify an agent the copyright owners can contact to tell them that
specific works are being stored on their systems unlawfully;
2. Abide by a detailed set of procedures for removing such material from their
systems, or resolving disagreements between the copyright owners and the
posters concerning their legality;
3. Lack the kind of specific knowledge of illegality spelled out in section 512I(1)(a);
and
4. Lack the kind of financial interest spelled out in section 512I(1)(b).
The clauses pertaining to knowledge and financial interest should sound roughly familiar
to you. They pertain to the same kinds of concerns that have long figured in the doctrines of
contributory infringement and vicarious infringement, respectively. But those concepts take
here an unusual form, and serve an unusual role. If an OSP are accused of storing and
distributing infringing stuff and can show that he lacks both of these things, he’s home free. If he
cannot, he’s not necessarily liable, but must run the gauntlet of the doctrines of direct and
secondary liability we’ve considered in the last four weeks. So, much hinges on how exactly
these requirements are construed.
The case that to date has examined these requirements most detail is Viacom versus
YouTube. The basic facts are likely familiar to most of you. YouTube was founded in 2005 by
three former employees of PayPal. The purpose of the initial version of YouTube was not entirely
clear, but its principal function soon became to enable people to post video clips, and make
them available for the world to watch. It grew extremely rapidly. By 2007, YouTube was the
dominant site of its kind, and its lead over its rivals continued to increase. YouTube’s success was
attributable in part to the sophistication and convenience of its technology, and in part to the
support it received from Google, which purchased the company in November of 2006 in a stock
for stock transaction worth roughly $1.5 billion. Last, but not least, YouTube flourished in part
because it was willing, particularly in the early years, to host videos consisting of or containing
commercial copyrighted material, which lots of users wanted to see. The owners of the
copyrights in those materials reacted in various ways to the rise of YouTube. Some shrugged.
Some negotiated licenses with YouTube or Google, permitting them to host their content. And
finally, a few brought law suits.
Included in this last group was Viacom, the entertainment giant that owned the copyrights
in many television shows, episodes of which were uploaded to YouTube without permission by
fans, and then watched by other fans. The numbers were large. In 2007, when it initiated the
lawsuit, Viacom identified 63,497 clips then hosted on YouTube that, Viacom contended,
contained its copyrighted material. YouTube acknowledged that some of the videos on its site
contained copyrighted material and promptly removed the 63,000 clips identified by Viacom.
From “Our Case Against YouTube” by Mike Fricklas in the Washington Post, March
24, 2007:
YouTube has described itself as the place to go for video. It is far more than the kind of
passive Web host or e-mail service the DMCA protects – it is an entertainment
destination. The public at large is not attracted to YouTube’s storage facility or
technical functionality – people are attracted to the entertainment value of what’s on
the site.
And YouTube reaps financial benefits from that attraction through selling the traffic to
advertisers. While an e-mail provider is paid to facilitate and manage the exchange of
e-mail traffic, and competes in that fashion, YouTube lures consumers and competes by
having great content – a resoundingly substantial part of which it did not create or pay
for.
Does YouTube have “knowledge” of copyrighted material on its site? Does it have the
“right and ability to control” the content? Yes and yes. If the public knows what’s there,
then YouTube’s management surely does. YouTube’s own terms of use give it clear
rights, notably the right to take anything down. YouTube actively monitors its content.
For example, its managers remove pornography and hate content and, as was recently
reported, claim they can detect and remove “spam.” Without knowledge and control,
how could YouTube create “channels” and “featured videos” sections on its site?
YouTube has even offered to find infringing content for copyright owners – but only if
they do a licensing deal first.
Is it fair to burden YouTube with finding content on its site that infringes others’
copyright? Putting the burden on the owners of creative works would require every
copyright owner, big and small, to patrol the Web continually on an ever-burgeoning
number of sites. That’s hardly a workable or equitable solution. And it would tend to
disadvantage ventures such as the one recently announced by NBC Universal and News
Corp. that are built on respect for copyright. Under the law, the obligation is right
where it belongs: on the people who derive a benefit from the creative works and are in
the position to keep infringement out of their businesses.
The state of the law governing OSPs after the Viacom decision, might be depicted
graphically as is shown in Figure 120. As you now know, OSPs are potentially liable not just for
direct copyright infringement, but also for any of the forms of secondary infringement:
contributory, vicarious, and, post-Grokster, inducement. Section 512I not only gives greater
specificity to the limits of those doctrine, but also, more importantly, allows OSPs to engage in
some kinds of conduct that, in the absence of 512, would give rise to liability. In particular,
hosting material without enough specific or red flag knowledge that particular pieces are
infringing to trigger the disqualifications of 512I(1)(A), and without the tight level of control
necessary to trigger the disqualification of 512(c)(1)(B).
Exactly what kinds of conduct fall into the zones identified by the arrows in this diagram
will have to be worked out in subsequent litigation. But this seems to be the structure that OSPs
must and may now rely upon, at least if the Second Circuit approach holds.
This concludes our discussion of secondary liability and the especially troublesome issues
presented by so-called dual use technologies. In the next section, we’ll turn to a very different
topic: technological protection measures.
centuries, governments had used five different techniques to 4. Legal reinforcement of self-
provide the necessary stimulus. The five options, with which you help strategies
should now be familiar, are listed on the right. Until this point in 5. Government protects
the lecture, we have been overwhelmingly concerned with the fifth
producers against
option, the essence of which is that the government protects
competition
authors and artists against competition – in other words, forbids
competitors to make, distribute, or perform copies of their works without permission. That, as
you well know, is the fundamental principle of copyright law, at least as seen through the lens of
welfare theory. When the entertainment companies sought the assistance of the law in
buttressing their shaky encryption systems, they were in effect stepping outside the zone of
copyright law and relying on an altogether different approach. In particular, they were
employing a variant of strategy number four. They were relying upon a self-help approach,
specifically technological protections for copies of their works, and soliciting legal reinforcement
for that strategy. In this respect, their approach was analogous to trade secret law. In that
context as well, companies rely on self-help, specifically efforts to keep their innovations secret,
but then turn to the law for aid when economic espionage or faithless employees cause that
secrecy to fail. In short, the entertainment companies’ new approach was not really an example
of copyright law at all, even though, as you’ll see, they plugged the statutory reforms they
sought into the copyright statute in the United States. In truth, this approach is a different
Contracting Parties shall provide adequate legal protection and effective legal remedies
against the circumvention of effective technological measures that are used by authors
in connection with the exercise of their rights under this Treaty or the Berne Convention
and that restrict acts, in respect of their works, which are not 302uthorized by the
authors concerned or permitted by law.
Lehman then returned to the United States and approached Congress with a new
argument. Congress, he argued, needed to modify federal law in the United States to fulfill the
obligations to which the United States would soon be subject under the new treaty. There
ensued a protracted hard fought battle among the relevant interest groups, a battle chronicled
by Pam Samuelson. Lehman and his allies eventually emerged bloody but victorious, specifically
as part of the Digital Millennium Copyright Act (DMCA). They obtained two new provisions now
embodied in sections 1201 and 1202 of the copyright statute. Of the two provisions, 1201 is the
more important. The critical language is below.
17 USC § 1201
(a)(2): No person shall manufacture, import, offer to the public, provide, or otherwise
traffic in any technology, product, service, device, component, or part thereof, that—
(B) has only limited commercially significant purpose or use other than to circumvent a
technological measure that effectively controls access to a work protected under this
title; or
I is marketed by that person or another acting in concert with that person with that
person’s knowledge for use in circumventing a technological measure that effectively
controls access to a work protected under this title.
cases where the plaintiffs have sought to rely ▪ RealNetworks, 641 F. Supp. 2d 913 (N.D.
on these statutory provisions to support Cal. 2009)
business models unrelated to traditional ▪ MDY Industries, 629 F.3d 928 (9th Cir.
entertainment products, the courts have been much less sympathetic. That’s a crude guideline,
2010)
to be sure, but for better or worse it has some explanatory force.
By way of illustration, I’ll describe two of the cases. Here’s the first. In 1999, John
Johansen, a 15-year-old Norwegian, reverse engineered a licensed DVD player and used the
information he obtained to write a short program designed to descramble a signal that had been
scrambled by the CSS security system – the system that is designed to prevent ripping DVD’s.
Johansen’s program, which he called DCSS, was relatively simple. The original version consisted
of 60 lines of computer code. It has since been reduced to seven. Although Johansen’s original
purpose apparently was the relatively benign goal of developing a DVD player that could operate
on the Linux operating system, his creation enabled many other less innocent uses of the video
recordings distributed on DVD’s. Once descrambled, they could be stored, compressed,
reproduced and redistributed. Copies of DCSS spread quickly over the internet. Within a month,
many websites offered user-friendly downloadable versions the program in both source code
and object code. The major film studios, seeking to stop or at least slow the spread of what they
regarded as an infection, invoked the DMCA to demand that the operators of those websites
remove the program from their servers. Some of those operators, including Eric Corely, the
editor of a print magazine boldly named 2600: The Hacker Quarterly, and an accompanying
website refused to comply. In response, the studios brought suit, accusing Corley and others of
“trafficking in circumvention technology.” Judge Lewis Kaplan found that the defendants had
indeed violated Section 1201(a)(2), the ban on trafficking in technology designed to circumvent
restrictions on access to copyrighted works. In his judgment, none of the statutory exemptions
were applicable. He then rejected the defendant’s argument that the statute so construed
would violate the First Amendment’s protection for freedom of speech. In his final ruling, Kaplan
Figure 121: US consumer home entertainment rental and sell-through spending (2010)
17 USC § 502
(a) Any court having jurisdiction of a civil action arising under this title may, subject to
the provisions of section 1498 of title 28, grant temporary and final injunctions on such
terms as it may deem reasonable to prevent or restrain infringement of a copyright.
(b) Any such injunction may be served anywhere in the United States on the person
enjoined; it shall be operative throughout the United States and shall be enforceable,
by proceedings in contempt or otherwise, by any United States court having jurisdiction
of that person. The clerk of the court granting the injunction shall, when requested by
any other court in which enforcement of the injunction is sought, transmit promptly to
the other court a certified copy of all the papers in the case on file in such clerk’s office.
These principles were not developed in the context of copyright infringement lawsuits.
Rather, they were developed by the courts – specifically by the federal courts – to govern
equitable relief in general.
As you can see, the traditional rule was that a plaintiff, in order to obtain a permanent
injunction, must show – first, that she has suffered an irreparable injury; second, that the
monetary damages would be inadequate to compensate her for that injury; third, that she
would suffer more serious hardship if an injunction were denied than would the defendant if an
injunction were granted; and finally, that the public interest would not be disserved by the
issuance of an injunction.
The traditional rules governing preliminary injunctions were slightly different. To obtain
one of these, a plaintiff was obliged to show – first, that she is likely to suffer an irreparable
injury if the defendant’s conduct continues; second, that monetary damages would be
12.2. Damages
The plaintiffs in most copyright infringement suits are interested in money in addition to, or
sometimes instead of, the kind of injunctive relief considered in the previous segment of this
lecture. In the United States, such plaintiffs are able to rely on three different principles when
seeking financial recoveries. First, they could obtain “actual damages”. In other words, enough
money to compensate them for the injuries they have sustained. Second, they can recover
profits made by the defendants attributable to the defendant’s infringing behavior so long as
those profits are not duplicative of the actual damages sustained by the plaintiffs. Last, but not
least, instead of either actual damages or lost profits, plaintiffs may recover so-called statutory
damages – sums of money that bear no necessary relationship to either the magnitude of the
injuries the plaintiff sustained or to the profits wrongfully earned by the defendants.
The first two of these forms of recovery, actual damages and defendant’s profits, are
conventional. Although the methods by which they are calculated in US courts are somewhat
unusual, these two types of monetary recovery may be found in the copyright systems of most
countries in the world and indeed are often granted to the victims of many other kinds of
unlawful behavior, both in the United States and elsewhere. The third form of recovery, by
17 USC § 504(b)
Actual Damages and Profits. — The copyright owner is entitled to recover … any profits
of the infringer that are attributable to the infringement and are not taken into account
in computing the actual damages. In establishing the infringer’s profits, the copyright
owner is required to present proof only of the infringer’s gross revenue, and the
infringer is required to prove his or her deductible expenses and the elements of profit
attributable to factors other than the copyrighted work.
The statutory authority for the first approach is contained in section 504(b) of the statute.
As you can see above, that provision entitles a copyright owner to recover “the actual damages
suffered by him or her as a result of the infringement.” The purpose of this provision is to enable
a successful plaintiff to recoup all of the money she lost because of the defendant’s
infringement. The most clear-cut example consists of profits the plaintiff would have earned had
the defendant not encroached upon her copyright unlawfully. The conventional way of proving
such lost profits by the plaintiff is to introduce evidence of the volume of sales at the plaintiff
likely would have enjoyed in the absence of the defendant’s behavior combined with evidence
concerning the profit the plaintiff would likely have earned on each of those sales. A less well
established variant of this approach permits the plaintiff to recoup losses she sustained if she
was forced to reduce the price of authorized copies of her work in order to compete with the
infringing defendant. This component of actual damages certainly makes sense as a matter of
theory, but case law support for it is thin.
A recent addition to the set of types of actual damages is the so-called value of use theory.
The idea underlying this variant is that a plaintiff should be able to recover from a defendant an
amount of money equivalent to the license fee that the defendant would have paid to the
plaintiff in order to obtain permission to engage in the conduct at issue. Somewhat more
specifically, this variant permits a plaintiff to recover from the defendant the amount that a
willing licensee would have paid a willing licensor for the right to engage in that conduct. In
determining that amount, courts take into account such factors as the customs prevailing in the
industry in question, the terms on which the plaintiff herself had previously granted licenses to
other parties to engage in similar activities, and perhaps special circumstances that would have
prompted the plaintiff to demand unusually high or low licensees.
We come finally to the controversial topic of statutory damages. Here’s how they work.
Section 504I provides that at any point before final judgment in a copyright case, the plaintiff
may renounce the recovery of actual damages and defendant’s profits and instead opt to
recover an amount of money set by a jury or the judge. How much money? The pertinent
statutory provision sets forth some broad ranges, but gives the decision maker lots of discretion
in picking a point within those ranges. The currently applicable ranges are shown in Figure 122.
The default, as you can see, is between $750 per infringed copyrighted work and $30,000 per
infringed work. If the defendant’s conduct was willful, meaning that the defendant knew that his
conduct violated the copyright statute, then the range is between $750 and $150,000. A lower
range, as you can see, applies if the defendant’s
behavior was innocent, meaning that “the
infringer was not aware and had no reason to
believe that his or her acts constituted an
infringement of copyright.” In other words,
innocence in this sense has both a subjective
and an objective component. To qualify for the
lower range, it’s not enough that a defendant
was unaware of the illegality of his actions; it’s
also necessary that his misimpression had been Figure 122: Ranges of statutory damages
reasonable.
Who picks the amount of statutory damages within these broad ranges? Congress, as you
can see from the text of the statute, clearly contemplated that “the court,” meaning the trial
judge, would make that determination. But the United States Supreme Court in the Feltner case
determined that the Seventh Amendment provides a right to a jury trial in all issues pertinent to
an award of statutory damages under Section 504(a), including the amount of the award itself.
The upshot is that every time you see the word court in 504(c), you should replace it with the
word jury. What factors should the decision maker rely upon when setting that amount? The
only guideline the statute itself provides is that it should be the amount that the court considers
just. When, after Feltner, courts delegate this determination to juries, they usually instruct the
juries to pick the amount the juries consider just. Sometimes the judges suggest other factors
that the jury could consider when making their choice, such as evidence of how much the
plaintiff was actually harmed, the need to deter wrongdoing in the future, the nature of the
A. SOURCES
Figure 4: Studio photograph of Oscar Wilde taken by Napoleon Sarony, the subject of Burrow-
Giles Lithographic Co. v. Sarony 111 U.S. 53 (1884), page 10
http://www.oscarwildeinamerica.org/sarony/sarony-photographs.html#item119
Figure 8: A maps showing the Berne Convention signatory countries (as of January 2016), page
36
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/File:Berne_Convention_signatories.svg
Figure 16: Buddhist monks from the Namgyal Monastery creating a sand mandala, page 55
http://www.namgyal.org/mandalas/background.cfm
Figure 19: Press release by the Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA) welcoming
the introduction of the Performance Rights Act, page 60
http://www.riaa.com/newsitem.php?id=7BE7264B-5BC4-C823-777D-73D5B410805A
Figure 20: Press release by the National Association of Broadcasters (NAB) opposing the
introduction of the Performance Rights Act, page 61
http://www.nab.org/advocacy/issue.asp?id=1889
Figure 26: Brandir International, Inc. v. Cascade Pacific Lumber Co. – the Bandir ribbon rack,
page 73
http://www.ribbonrack.com
Figure 28: Five of the cheerleading uniform registrations belonging to Varisty Brand, page 75
https://www.bg.law/u-s-supreme-court-issues-decision-in-star-athletica-l-l-c-v-varsity-
brands-inc-et-al
Figure 29: The Jewish Museum in Berlin, designed by Daniel Libeskind, page 77
http://daniel-libeskind.com
Figure 60: A photo of the bow of the Titatnic wreck, page 112
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/File:Titanic_wreck_bow.jpg
Figure 61: Poster for the musical play “Rent” – Oregon version, page 113
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/File:Rentpostera.jpg
Figure 62: Poster for the musical play “Rent” – Jarkarta version, page 114
http://winminded.deviantart.com/art/Rent-Musical-in-Jakarta-poster-303978929
Figure 64: James Earl Reid's sculpture commemorating homelesness, page 123
http://www.unc.edu/~unclng/display5-05.htm
Figure 67: Copyright registrations (excluding renewals), 1910 – 2000, page 136
From Christopher Sprigman, “Reformalizing Copyright,” 57 Stan. L. Rev. 485, 499 (2004).
Figure 91: The mayor character in the TV show “Fun Stuff” contrasted with the mayor of
McDonaldland, page 176
http://24.media.tumblr.com/tumblr_m6ceznOrWv1r8rcv1o1_500.jpg
Figure 109: Mattel’s Barbie and photos from Forsythe’s series “Food Chain Barbie”, page 235
http://s7d2.scene7.com/is/image/Mattel/N4978_02?$null$ [Barbie]
http://web.archive.org/web/20041210175947/http://ncac.org/store/forsythesphotos.ht
m [Forsythe’s photos]
Figure 114: Implementation status of the 22 exceptions and limitations to copyright for
all 28 EU member states, page 249
http://copyrightexceptions.eu
Figure 121: US consumer home entertainment rental and sell-through spending (2010),
page 305
http://forums.highdefdigest.com/high-definition-smackdown/118789-npd-more-people-
buy-dvds-than-watch-netflix-streaming-3.html
Figure 124: David LaMacchia (right) with his lawyer, page 321
http://tech.mit.edu/V114/N68/lamacchia.00n.html
The following video lectures were used as the basis for this document.
Updated in
Lecture Title Lecture Date Document
Version
01.1 The Foundations of Copyright Law - Introduction 7 January 2016 1.0
01.2 The Foundations of Copyright Law - Originality 7 January 2016 1.0
01.3 The Foundations of Copyright Law - Idea-Expression 7 January 2016 1.0
Distinction
01.4 The Foundations of Copyright Law - Multilateral 7 January 2016 1.0
Treaties
02.1 Fairness and Personality Theories - Introduction 14 January 2013 1.0
02.2 Fairness and Personality Theories - Fairness 14 January 2013 1.0
02.3 Fairness and Personality Theories - Personality 14 January 2013 1.0
03.1 The Subject Matter of Copyright - Literature (and 4 November 2014 1.0
Software) (reformatted)
03.2 The Subject Matter of Copyright - Drama and 4 November 2014 1.0
choreography (reformatted)
03.3 The Subject Matter of Copyright - Music 4 November 2014 1.0
(reformatted)
03.4 The Subject Matter of Copyright - Audiovisual Works 4 November 2014 1.0
(reformatted)
03.5 The Subject Matter of Copyright - Fictional Characters 4 November 2014 1.0
(reformatted)
03.6 The Subject Matter of Copyright - Architectural Works 8 January 2018 1.2
04.1 Welfare Theory - The Utilitarian Framework 13 December 2013 1.0
04.2 Welfare Theory - The Incentive Theory of Copyright 13 December 2013 1.0
04.3 Welfare Theory - Applications and Assessment 13 December 2013 1.0
05.1 Authorship - Sole Authorship 4 November 2014 1.0
(reformatted)