Benedict M. Ashley - The Arts of Learning and Communication PDF
Benedict M. Ashley - The Arts of Learning and Communication PDF
Benedict M. Ashley - The Arts of Learning and Communication PDF
THE ARTS
OF LEARNING
AND
COMMUNICATION
TABLE OF CONTENTS
The author wishes gratefully to acknowledge the very kind encouragement and assistance given
him In preparing this book by the Very Reverend John E. Marr, O.P. Provincial of the Province
of St. Albert the Great the Very Reverend Sebastian L. Carlson, O.P. Regent of Studies of the
Dominican House of Studies, River Forest, Illinois and the Very Reverend William H. Kane,
O.P. Director of the Albertus Magnus Lyceum. Very special thanks are due to the Center for
Liberal Studies in Education of St. Xavier College. Chicago, conducted by the Religious Sisters
of Mercy of the Union In the U.S.A., Chicago Province. This Center through its Curriculum
Committee for Secondary Schools and through the Department of English of St. Xavier College,
has provided the author with invaluable practical counsel, patient assistance In the preparation of
parts of the manuscript. and many opportunities to experiment with this critical analysis program
in St. Xavier College, and several of its associated high schools. I wish also to thank Brother
Joachim Thiel, O.P. and Mr. Dowayne La Porte for their assistance with the manuscript.
Passages from the Confraternity of Christian Doctrine translation of the Sacred Scriptures are
quoted with the kind permission of the officials of the Confraternity. Other quoted material is
acknowledged in the footnotes.
Foreword to Teachers
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
A democratic society is based on the conviction that modern culture with its accumulation of
knowledge, Its instruments of research, record, and communication, and Its leisure provided by
an industrial economy is able to make every normal adult a direct participant in the life of the
intellect.
Education for this life of the intellect should continue through the lifetime of every member of a
democratic society, since we can always advance in this world. Nevertheless, this lifetime
education is divided into two distinct phases, the stage of formal schooling and the later stage of
informal adult-education.
At present for the majority of our citizens the dividing line between these two phases of
education is drawn at the completion of a high school program. For those who go on to college,
the freshman year is commonly devoted to a review and completion of this high school program.
It is obvious that the main content of education cannot be mastered in so short a period. Only in a
traditional society, where there is a fixed body of information and attitudes, could the substance
of education be transmitted briefly and early in life. In a modern democratic society, knowledge
cannot have such a fixed form; even its content of permanent truth is subject to constant
adaptation and reformulation.
Therefore: those who conceive of the high school program in terms of a body of information to
be inculcated and who make high school education into a pocket edition of college education,
emphasizing surveys of facts or the acquisition of some particular vocational skill do not
understand the needs and opportunities of our times.
The chief task of the high school is, on the contrary, to equip the student with a developed ability
to learn on his own. Not every citizen, to be sure, needs to be a discoverer of new truth --
research is the task of special professions; but every citizen must be able, without the formal and
immediate direction of a teacher, to make use of the knowledge already acquired by society.
Otherwise he will not be able to enlarge the fixed and meager content of his high school
education, nor to sift truth from falsehood in the things he hears and reads.
Realizing this, progressive educators have attempted to make our high schools into places in
which the acquisition of the ability to learn is emphasized, rather than the absorption of
information. Nevertheless, for many reasons their efforts have proved ineffectual and have given
ample cause for reactionary criticism. Among the reasons for this failure, the chief, it would
seem, has been the notion that we can train people to learn informally by making learning
informal. School life becomes as amorphous as the adult life which the student must learn to
reduce to order. In what other field would we proceed by such a method? The practice of a
doctor is filled with informal learning, but he is able to profit by it precisely because he has been
given a rigorously formal advance training.
The rigorous formal training which equips the student to learn informally in later life is obtained
through a study of the liberal arts, that is, of those subjects whose very purpose is to enable us to
perform the generalized mental operations which enter into all intellectual tasks. One of the great
disservices of progressivist educational theory was to sell the idea that there are no generalized
operations of thought no "transfer of training," no logic distinguishable from the solution of
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
particular problems. This theory has never been confirmed by the experience of teachers, nor
well-planned experiments, nor accurate analysis.*
*See the summary of more recent views on "transfer of training" given by John J. Ryan and others In Educational
Psychology (College Outline Series, New York: Barnes and Noble, Inc. 1956), pp. 92-104, and Charles E. Osgood,
Method and Theory in Experimental Psychology (New York: Oxford University Press, 1953). p. 524.
The first and indispensable task of a high school is to provide its so-called "terminal student"
with the liberal arts needed to continue his education informally throughout life. Such training
will also make it possible for the student who goes on to college to continue formal education
effectively. Without it the terminal student will indeed terminate his education with his high
school diploma, and the college student will never really begin higher study.
The present book is a tool for the teaching of the liberal arts in high school, or in the freshman
year of college for those students whose high school studies were inadequate. It is intended to be
at once a handbook and a textbook.
As a handbook it should be used by the student throughout his four years in high school in every
course. Every teacher in the school should insist that in each subject of the curriculum the
processes of definition, statement, and argumentation outlined here should be exactly practiced
in the student's reading recitation, discussion, and examination for that subject. In this way the
transfer of training can be made explicit and effective.
On the other hand this work is also a textbook to assist in the learning of these logical processes.
The most appropriate place for its use is in the customary English courses. Here it will not
replace the customary material but it will serve as a guide for teacher and student in using
material to develop the liberal arts.
At the beginning of the freshman year of high school the Introduction (page 3) should be used to
orient the student to the whole work of the high school. A student should have some sense of the
order and interrelation of all his courses. It is suggested that this chapter be read and discussed in
the home-room or the Christian Doctrine class to show the unity of purpose in the life of the
whole school.
The teacher should then present these materials in such a way as to stress definition, judgment,
and argumentation in successive years. The manual is a tool to assist in this task. It should never
be studied in isolation from immediate application to the materials of literature, composition and
grammar.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
During the first year, the study of reading and of composition should stress vocabulary, diction
and description (Chapter I). In the second year, stress should be on sentence structure, outlining
and organization of compositions and clarity of style (Chapter II). The third year should stress
the unity of a composition, its plot, theme or argumentation (Chapter III). The last year should
stress the correlation of all these processes in larger compositions and the subordination of means
to ends, style to content (Chapter IV).
A special feature of this manual is that it treats of all four types of discourse -- the poetic,
rhetorical, dialectical and scientific.*
*These four forms of discourse are not to be confused with exposition, argument, description, and narration
traditional in rhetoric manuals; these are all parts of a rhetorical discourse. Nor should the three processes of
definition, judgment, and argumentation be confused with the "four dimensions of the reading act," perception,
understanding, reaction, and integration, made popular by certain educational psychologists. The three logical
processes are used in each of the last three "dimensions."
The three great logical processes of definition, judgment, and argument are used in each of these
four types of discourse but in contrasting ways. Most courses in English emphasize poetic
discourse and greatly neglect the other three. The English course should teach the whole theory
of these four types, but it may very properly devote most of its attention to the poetic and
rhetorical. In order that dialectical and scientific discourse may be mastered by the student, these
should be emphasized especially in the mathematics courses, but also in natural science, social
science, and Christian doctrine courses.
The following is suggested as a correlation of the different parts of book with a four-year high
school program:
I. FRESHMAN YEAR:
1. Christian Doctrine: "Introduction: The Story of the Liberal Arts.”
This is an orientation of the student to his entire high school career. The teacher of
Christian Doctrine ought to provide this orientation, helping the student to adjust
to the school community and to study, and showing the student that all that he
learns must be integrated in Christ. The Sacred Liturgy should be considered as a
perfect work of the liberal arts (see pages 473 ff.).
2. Liberal Arts:
English and other languages: Part I, Chapter I: "Poetics: The Art of Storytelling."
The problems of word-study, use of the dictionary, and the analysis of simple
stories should be carried on not only in the English course, but in whatever other
languages are taught.
Fine Arts and Music: Part III. Chapter I: "The Master of the Fine Arts."
The teacher should bring out the parallel between word-study which deals with
the matter of literature and the study of the matter of music and the other fine arts.
Mathematics: Part III, Chapter I: "The Science of Number."
This chapter provides a logical approach to algebra, with emphasis on the correct
definition of terms. It makes use of the techniques of definition being studied in
English.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
3. Nature Studies:
If general science or biology is given this year, then the teacher should relate the
discussion in the "Introduction" on the cultural development of man to the
problem of human origins and human capacities to speak, to think, to make, to
invent. Emphasis should be laid on the development of a scientific vocabulary, on
the correct definition of terms, and the use of the dictionary.
4. Social Studies:
The "introduction" should be used to discuss the origin of man and the concept of
culture. How did man develop diverse cultures? How did he invent writing, the
sciences, educational institutions? What is the role of the liberal arts in human
culture? Emphasis should be laid on the development of a scientific vocabulary,
on the correct definition of terms, and the use of the dictionary.
II. SOPHOMORE YEAR:
1. Christian Doctrine:
The teacher should make use of the material of Part I, Chapter II pages 77-80 on
the differences between faith, opinion, and demonstration to show the student the
meaning of revelation and of divine faith and its relation to reason. The analysis
of rhetoric, poetry, figures of speech, and the technique of outlining should be
used to help the student read selections from the Sacred Scriptures (see pages 470
f. and 496 f.).
2. Liberal Arts:
English and other languages: Part I, Chapter II: "Dialectics and Rhetoric: Arts of Discussion and
Persuasion."
The emphasis in this year should be on the conducting of intelligent discussion
and debate, and on the rhetorical analysis of an audience. The study of sentences,
the arrangement of a composition, and its rhetorical tone should also be studied in
the other languages.
Fine Arts and Music: Part II Chapter II: "The Form of the Fine Arts."
The student should study structure (form or design) in the fine arts and music. He
should both analyze designs and make them himself. The discussion on the
mathematics of design in Part III Chapter II should be used in connection with
this. The Greek contribution to the plastic arts should especially he emphasized
during this year.
Mathematics: Part III, Chapter II: "The Science of Magnitude."
The emphasis is on geometry and the notion of scientific demonstration. in Part I,
Chapter II (pages 73-77) a preliminary treatment of the syllogism is given to be
used here, since the full treatment of scientific demonstrations does not come until
Chapter III used in Junior English. Special emphasis should be given to the notion
of axioms, postulates, definitions, which form the main topic of study in English,
Part I, Chapter II (pages 69-72). The mathematical topics should extend to
elementary trigonometry and analytic geometry. During this yew emphasis should
be placed on the Greek origins of mathematics, and the role of mathematics in the
fine arts.
3. Nature Studies:
If general science or biology is taken or continued in this year, then emphasis
should be placed on the forms of living things. The notions of form and structure.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
emphasized in the fine arts and mathematics, should be employed. The rules of
classification and outlining, the concept of first principles in a science, and the
concept of giving evidence for statements -- all of which are stressed in Part I,
Chapter II -- should be used in their scientific application.
4. Social Studies.
Use should be made of the discussion in the fine arts and mathematics section of
Greek culture as the basis of all western culture. This should be compared to
eastern cultures and the contrasts and similarities discussed. The same points of
scientific method listed, above under Nature Studies should be stressed.
III. JUNIOR YEAR:
1. Christian Doctrine:
The method of establishing technical definitions and classifications should be
applied to the study of the virtues and vices. The differences between technical
definitions and biblical examples, and the variety and integration of the moral and
intellectual virtues should be stressed. The teacher should indicate the ordering of
the arts to the liturgy as the supreme act of the virtue of religion.
2. Liberal Arts:
English and other languages: Part I Chapter III: "Dialectic and Demonstrative Logic: Scientific
Method."
During this your special stress should be placed on the application of the methods
of analysis learned in English to the development of methods of study in all
courses. The use of the encyclopaedia and of reference materials both in English
and other languages should be emphasized. Textbooks used in other courses
should be analyzed in class. A similar analysis should be applied to the "mass
media of communication" (pages 90-98). If Cicero is read in the Latin course his
orations should be given rhetorical analysis.
Fine Arts and Music: Part II. Chapter III: "The Purpose of the Fine Arts."
The comparison of the fine arts to other studies and activities should be made.
The concepts of imitation, catharsis, and the division of the arts should be treated
more fully. The use of mathematics in music treated in Part III, Chapter II (page
349 ff.) should be indicated.
Mathematics: Part III, Chapter III: "Applied Mathematics."
The notion of a pure mathematical science as exemplified in algebra should be
considered and then the notion of mathematical physics should be discussed,
using the more detailed analysis of scientific proof and investigation developed in
Part I, Chapter III (page 161 ff.). The mathematics of music should be taken as
one of the examples of applied mathematics.
3. Nature Studies:
During this year elementary physics will be taken by many students and the
emphasis should he on the use of mathematics and mathematical-physical
reasoning in science. Analytic geometry, trigonometry, and the use of vectors
should be developed in this course. See Part III, Chapter III.
4. Social Studies:
The student during this year will probably be considering the history of modern
civilization, the industrial revolution, and the characteristics of American
civilization. The teacher should show how the development of the scientific
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
4. Social Studies:
This year will probably be devoted to American government and social problems.
It should be brought into close connection with the treatment of the Church, the
apostolate, and the student's personal vocation which are being stressed in the
Christian Doctrine course. One of the problems should be the influence of the
"mass media of communication" (see Part I, Chapter II), and these should be
discussed in connection with all that the student has learned about the liberal arts,
and the varied literary media which he is concurrently studying in English (Part I,
Chapter IV). The teacher should prepare the student for his role as a citizen who
must listen, discuss, judge, seek information, and discount propaganda.
If this handbook is used in the Freshman year of college it is suggested that the English course be
based on Part I. "Logic as an Art," and that the other parts be assigned for reading to show the
student how logical reasoning is applied in other fields. Thus with Part I, Chapter I, should be
assigned Part II, Chapter I, and Part III, Chapter I; with Part I, Chapter II should be assigned Part
II, Chapter II, Part III, Chapter II, etc.
INTRODUCTION
ADAM
Adam looked around at the world God had made for him. Was it just a place to eat and sleep?
Was it just a place to work with strength of body and skill of hand? Adam at first did not even
think about eating or sleeping, and he had no need of working. He only thought, "What strange
things I see and hear! They are all mine, but what are they?"
Reaching up he touched the leaves. Bending down he felt the grass and smelled the warm earth
and the flowers. In the sky he saw the sun move to the zenith and begin to descend again. In the
shadow of the woods he saw the animals playing, and in the boughs he heard the song of birds.
As he examined each strange thing, touched it, listened to it, he began to understand its nature.
The lion was different from the rabbit; yet every rabbit was the same as every other rabbit, and
every lion was the same as every other lion. In his mind Adam formed a name for each thing he
saw and understood, a mental word that stood for the nature of the thing. "The man named all the
cattle, all the birds of the air, and all the beasts of the field, but he found no helper like himself"
(Gen. 2:20).
At first Adam was not surprised that he was the only one of his kind, the only thing with a
human nature. He knew that he was very different from the animals about him. He understood
that they were interested only in food and their families. Adam was interested in all things, in
just looking at the universe and trying to understand it. It seemed to him that he could never tire
of exploring the world about him, particularly because he had begun to realize that God, who
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
made so great a world, must be still more great. Sea and sky had their limits, but there was no
boundary to the everlasting wonder of God. How could he ever finish exploring the mystery of
God? Would there be a day when God would finally let Adam see him face to face? There was
only one God, and Adam knew that it was in God's image that he had been made. Why then was
it so strange that just as there was only one God, so there was only one man?
Adam realized that in being king over the world about him, he must imitate God, who is the King
and Father of all things. How could Adam be king and father to his world? He could not create it
anew, but at least he could keep it in perfect order. He could tend the garden, watch over the
animals; but how could he share the greatest of all gifts which God had shared with him, namely,
wisdom and understanding? The animals could not share this wisdom and understanding with
Adam. If only Adam had children of his own kind to whom he might be a father as God was
Father to him, children whom he might teach to understand the wonder of the world, and the
infinite wonder of God!
After sleeping on this problem, Adam awoke to find a companion at his side whom God had
made for him to be his helper in raising a family of his own. Adam understood that this was Eve,
"the mother of all the living" (Gen. 3:20). Adam and Eve were to share the world together, to be
its king and queen. How could they also share each other's thoughts? Adam had named all things
in his mind with mental words or concepts. Some of these were proper names, like the name of
Eve, each belonging to a single thing. Others were common names, representing a universal
concept, as the name, "woman," or "lion," or "bird." These were in Adam's mind, but he did not
know at first how to teach them to Eve.
Around them he heard the animals calling, some with squeaks and growls and some in song.
Adam understood these signs which the animals made by instinct. They were natural signs
because there was a natural connection between the sign and the thing it stood for. When Adam
saw the footprint of a lion, he knew that this was the natural sign that a lion had passed by. When
be heard the lion's roar, he knew that this was the natural sign that the lion was hungry. At first
Adam and Eve themselves may have used only such natural signs. They smiled at each other to
show their love; they pointed or cried out to call each other's attention. This natural language was
enough for the animals who had only their feelings to talk about. Adam and Eve, however,
wanted to talk over all the things that interested them. Eve saw a lion and turned with
questioning eyes to Adam. "What is it?" her eyes said. Adam wanted to explain it to her, to tell
her what he had learned about the nature of the lions. He longed to tell her about all the things he
had explored; about his plans for the future; above all about God their Father, who had made this
world and whom he hoped they might some day see face to face. Natural signs were not enough
to say all this, and Adam, with Eve's agreement, began to invent new sounds to stand for the
natures of everything he knew. These spoken words were not natural signs, but signs whose
meaning came from agreement, conventional signs.
Adam in this new language taught Eve all that he knew about the world and God, and she
listened in delight. Adam explained it all so clearly! Still there was one thing he said that puzzled
her. He said that God had given them the whole world to know and use, but bad forbidden them
to taste the fruit of the tree of the knowledge of good and evil. When she asked why, Adam
explained that he did not know why God had given them this command, but that he was sure that
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
it must be for a good reason. In fact, it was because God wished to test them. He wanted to give
them soon the greatest knowledge of all, the most wonderful secret. He wanted to let them see
him face to face so that their happiness might be complete, since all the beauty of the world is
only a sign of God's perfect beauty. This gift he intended to give them as the reward of their
obedience and trust.
They did not earn their reward. Eve one day listened to another teacher, not to Adam, and that
teacher was the evil one, "who is a liar and the father of lies" (Jn. 8:45). The devil suggested to
Eve the wicked idea that God had forbidden them to eat of the tree because he wished to keep
men in ignorance lest they become his equals. If Eve had asked Adam, he would have explained
how impossible it was for their heavenly Father to be envious of his children. But Eve did not
wait to ask Adam about what the serpent said. Curiously she ate of the fruit, and then persuaded
Adam that, since she had already eaten, he must join her.
After they were cast out of their garden into the wilderness, they found life very hard. Adam had
to work all day to keep his family alive. He had little time any longer to explore the wonders of
the world and little time to give to Eve and the children. Eve too was kept busy all day keeping
the children clothed and fed; she was often tired and impatient with them. Their minds filled with
a thousand worries and their hearts with restless hunger and anger, Adam and Eve often
misunderstood each other and quarreled. Their children grew up missing much that Adam might
have taught them, if he had had more time and if there had been more peace at home. The
children of Adam and Eve grew up without that clear and wonderful vision of the world their
parents once possessed. To these boys and girls life seemed rather puzzling and often very dull.
Today we "poor banished children of Eve" also find the world pretty hard to understand. Often
we give up trying to understand it and are content to be ignorant and bored. Who is there to teach
us the answers? Many false teachers in television, movies, books, and newspapers give us lying
answers when we look for the truth. To get back the beautiful vision of truth and reality which
God gave to Adam and Eve we will have to study very hard.
SAVAGES
Living in the wilderness the family of Adam and Eve and all their descendants struggled to
recover their lost heritage of knowledge and their lost control over nature. Their life was
probably a great deal like that of savage peoples of today, the jungle people of Africa, the desert
people of Australia, or some of our own American Indians.
Yet even such savage people have discovered many arts of making a living and recreation. They
honor as heroes those who invented these arts and taught them to their tribes. In the book of
Genesis it is recalled that Cain and Abel, two of the sons of Adam and Eve, soon learned to earn
the necessities of life by their skill. "Abel was a keeper of flocks and Cain a tiller of the soil"
(Gen. 4:2). Soon they were not content with bare necessities, for we read that among the
descendants of Cain there was a man named Jabel who "was the forerunner of those who dwell
in tents and have flocks. His brother's name was Jubal; he was the forerunner of all who play the
harp and the flute" (4:20-21). Thus there were not only useful arts for the food, shelter and
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
clothing that men require for life itself, but also arts of recreation, like music, which men needed
to enjoy life and to live well.
At times these savages seemed as poor and ignorant as the animals about them, and yet it took
great intelligence to discover and develop any of these arts. It had been easy enough for Adam
and Eve to pluck fruit from trees in the Garden of Eden, but to earn a living in the wilderness
was difficult, and that is why arts were required. To discover even so simple an art as making a
tent, a savage bad to figure out four things:
1. He had to fix clearly before him his purpose or end, exactly what he was trying to
accomplish: to make something that would keep out the rain, yet let out the smoke from
the fire, and which could be easily moved.
2. He had to picture what the form or pattern of such a tent would be like.
3. He had to decide out of what material it would be suitable to make it.
4. He had to find the power and instruments to cut, shape and fasten this material.
As time went by, men discovered how to use even very difficult materials. "Tubalcain was the
forerunner of those who forge vessels of bronze and iron" (4:22).
Nor were the savages content to live their lives in mere work and occasional recreation. Men
cannot be content with the things that satisfy mere animals. Adam and Eve had found their
greatest happiness in exploring the world, and in friendship with each other and with God. Cain
killed Abel because he was jealous of Abel's friendship with God which Cain himself had not
deserved. Seth, the third son of Adam and Eve, had a son named Enos, who taught men how to
pray rightly to God. When men pray to the true God and seek to do his will so that they can serve
him perfectly, they also want to know the truth about the world which God has given them.
Throughout ancient times some men pondered on the law of God and recovered something of the
wisdom which Adam had possessed.
Yet as the human race was scattered over the world, those living in small groups without wiser
men to teach them sometimes became almost like animals in their way of living. Others
developed many arts, but also tried to gain still more power by the practice of magic and the
worship of the evil spirits. Gradually their ideas of God became clouded and colored by their
own cruelties, lusts, and ambitions. Some of them worshipped not God, their Father in heaven,
but the earth, which they thought of as their mother who had given birth to them and to whom
they would return at death. As they forgot the true God, so their ideas about human conduct and
the world of nature in which they lived became twisted and strange.
All over the world these savage people have left their traces: the stone tools which they made,
the pictures they painted in the caves, even their living descendants in the backwoods and
corners of the world. The simplest and oldest of these tribes which remain today still remember
the true God, but many have ideas and customs which seem like a nightmare of fear, cruelty, and
impurity.
When the human race had sunk very low, God brought disasters upon men, such as the great
flood recorded in Genesis, to warn them that they must turn back to seek him or be extinguished.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
After this warning he promised that he would let the human race develop once more and strive to
rise again to the glory it bad lost.
ANCIENT CITIES
Once more men began to struggle and work to rebuild paradise on earth. Some 6000 years ago
men began to build great cities. The first were in the country we now call Iraq, along the Tigris
and Euphrates Rivers, and in Egypt along the Nile River. Somewhat later they were built in
India, in Crete, in China, and finally in Central America.
Today as scientists dig about in the ruins of these cities they find proof that the men who built
them were experts in many arts. Irrigation improved the art of agriculture. With a more ample
food supply men could live in large groups, and each could specialize in a particular art,
exchanging what he made for the other things he needed. Tools and weapons were no longer
made of stone but of copper, bronze, and finally of iron.
The life of these cities also became very colorful as the arts of recreation flourished. In the ruins
are evidences of the physical games of the people: their ball-games, wrestling matches, chariot
and boat races -- as well as such mental games as puzzles and checkers. The fine arts made their
buildings beautiful with paintings and sculpture in which we see also portrayed musicians,
dancers, and actors.
Yet if these city-dwellers had known only such arts, they would still have been savages. It was
their discovery of writing that proves they were truly civilized, because it shows that they had
begun to appreciate the value of human thought. They wrote down business contracts and city
laws because they saw the importance of living according to fixed principles. Thus their social
thought was recorded in writing. They also wrote down records of the movements of the stars
and kept a calendar. This was their thought about nature. Above all they recorded the prayers
and ceremonies by which they worshipped God. To all these thoughts they began to try to give
clear and beautiful language and expression.
Nevertheless, although they appreciated the value of thought, they did not always appreciate the
value of truth. The true ideas they recorded were also mixed with all kinds of imaginings that
grew out of their pride, ambition, rivalry, and hatred. In Genesis we read how men built the
Tower of Babel (11:1-9), not for any useful purpose, nor in order to worship the true God, but
merely to display their pride. As a punishment God made this ambitious undertaking the
occasion of quarreling, confusion, and social division. As society became divided into rival
groups, each city tried to outdo the next in a display of power and skill, and finally each came to
war with the other. Great conquerors like Nemrod (Gen. 10:9) built up huge empires based on
cruel slavery.
Only a few men kept the right idea of human life and of man's relation to God; among them was
Abraham, who lived near Babylon in the city of Ur. At God's command he took his family out of
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
these evil cities and found a home for them in Palestine, where later, after his descendants had
been freed by Moses from the power of Egypt, they built their own holy city of Jerusalem with a
temple dedicated to the one true God. Here they kept the Sacred Scriptures in which they wrote
down -- just as did other peoples -- their laws, their science, their prayers to God, all in beautiful
and exact language. This sacred book, or rather library of books, seemed much like the libraries
of the other people of that period. But while other ancient books, except for pitiful fragments,
have been destroyed, the Bible remains the best-seller of all books today. This is because it was
inspired by God and preserved by his Church.
In this Bible we read about the wisest man of ancient times, King Solomon, and the wisdom
which he taught his people. "God gave to Solomon wisdom and understanding exceeding much,
and largeness of heart as the sand that is on the sea shore. And the wisdom of Solomon surpassed
the wisdom of all the Orientals, and of the Egyptians. . . . Solomon also spoke three thousand
parables: and his poems were a thousand and five. And he treated about trees from the cedar that
is in Libanus unto the hyssop that groweth out of the wall: and he discoursed of beasts, and of
fowls, and of creeping things, and of fishes. And they came from all the nations to hear the
wisdom of Solomon, and from all the kings of the earth who heard of his wisdom" (III Kings
4:29-34). It seemed that Solomon had regained the wisdom of Adam. Yet in his old age he was
led by his pagan wives into foolishness, and to please them be began to worship idols.
GREEKS
It was not in these most ancient lands that the arts and sciences came to full flower, but in Europe
in a more youthful country, in the small and busy cities of Greece. Unhappily, even there slavery
was common, and the useful arts were left to slaves who had no ambition to make new
inventions. It was only in those arts which were thought fitting for free men that the Greeks
showed unique genius.
In the Olympic Games athletics became an art. As men developed a keen appreciation for the
strength, proportion, and control of the human body displayed in these games, they also learned
to make and appreciate buildings, statues, and paintings that were strong, well-proportioned, and
yet graceful. The same sense of balance and symmetry helped them to write stories and plays,
such as the epics of Homer and the tragedies of Sophocles, more dramatically told than those of
former times.
Finally, this search for clarity and order in all that they did led the Greeks to discover the art of
arts, the art of clear and orderly thinking which is called logic. It is the art of arts, because clear
thinking is the basis of every art and science.
To think clearly is to give the precise reason or proof for whatever we claim to be true. There
were many clever men in Greece called sophists (wise men) who were constantly arguing and
talking and proposing new and surprising ideas. What one man said was true, another claimed
was false. Men began to doubt that it was possible to be sure what was really true.
Then appeared a man who was truly wise but refused to be called anything but a "lover of
wisdom" or a philosopher. He showed that the only way to settle an argument about what is true
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
and what is false is to begin by defining your terms. He was named Socrates, and was finally put
to death because he angered men when he pointed out that they were always talking without
knowing what they were saying.
His pupil Plato continued the work of Socrates and showed that to think clearly one must not
only define his terms, but must also state his principles, that is, the basic truths on which
knowledge rests. In youth Plato excelled as a wrestler, and he knew that to throw an opponent in
wrestling one must plant one's feet firmly on the ground. It was in a gymnasium that he
established the first great university called the Academy, and here he made mathematics the
basic study, because it is by the hard intellectual wrestling of mathematics that the mind is
developed in the art of logic.
In the Academy were taught arithmetic (or algebra) and its application to music. These had
already been invented by another philosopher named Pythagoras. Also geometry was taught,
although it was only somewhat later that it was brought to perfection by Euclid and its
application to astronomy fully developed by Ptolemy.
It was the greatest of Plato's pupils, Aristotle, who realized that logic should be strictly applied
not only to mathematics but to all branches of learning. He founded his own school, the Lyceum,
with a museum and laboratories, and there established the first complete curriculum of studies.
He showed that the chief task of logic is not merely to define terms and to state principles, but to
make proofs or demonstrations. He discovered that there are four kinds of proof and hence four
kinds of logic:
1. Sometimes in studying the sciences we can prove that a statement is certainly and
exactly true. This is demonstrative logic.
2. Sometimes in studying the sciences we cannot prove a statement exactly, but we can
give probable proofs and keep searching. This is dialectical logic.
3. Sometimes what is needed to convince people are reasons which persuade them by
moving their emotions so that they will accept the truth and act on it. This is rhetoric.
4. Sometimes what is needed is to entertain people by helping them to appreciate and
enjoy the truth. This is poetics.
The followers of Aristotle founded a still greater school at Alexandria in Egypt, called the
Museum (after it all our museums are named), and from there Aristotle's system of education
spread to the whole western world and became the basis of all our education today. In this
system of education a student has four main subjects to master:
1. The four types of logic and the four types of mathematics just listed. These are called
the liberal arts.
2. Natural science, the study of the nature of man and the world in which he lives.
3. Social science, the study of man's life.
4. Theology, the study of God.
The attempts of savage people to restore paradise on earth by their corrupt arts had ended in such
disasters as the flood. The attempts of the great ancient cities to restore paradise on earth had
ended in warfare and vain schemes like the Tower of Babel. The search of the Greeks after
wisdom seemed at first to succeed, but it too came to an end when the Romans established a
World Empire in which wisdom became only a tool to gain power and wealth. In Rome the
emperor was made a god, and Rome began to go down to the same destruction that had followed
all the foolish pride of previous civilizations.
Of all the people in the world only the Jews had kept the true idea of God, of his law, of the
relation of man to nature; but they kept themselves pure only by remaining narrow. The fate of
their great wise man Solomon had shown them the danger of mixing with foreign nations, and
they knew no way to combine the wisdom of the Greeks with the truth contained in their own
Bible. This truth that the whole world needed was stored up in Jerusalem, and, like grain that is
kept too long in storage, it had begun to mildew. Who would open the granaries of truth and feed
the famished nations?
Mankind had proved that by itself it could not restore paradise. Then from a most unlikely place
the true teacher of mankind, the second Adam of the human race, appeared. He seemed to be
only a poor young workman, a carpenter of the Jewish nation. He was not a student of the
philosophy of the Greeks. Nor was he a king like Solomon. He was the Son of God, who had
become a man like us to save us and to teach all men by his example and his preaching.
Jesus Christ was not a student of the philosophers. He was the supreme philosopher and teacher
who required no one to teach him. He gave an example to those who practice the useful arts by
himself working for years as a carpenter. He gave an example also of fitting recreation, for he
did not hesitate to come to the banquets of the people. In his teaching he used stories which are
masterpieces of poetics and of rhetoric. He corrected our understanding of nature when he
showed how all things in the world follow the law of God's providence and how man has a
dignity above all other visible creatures. He also corrected our understanding of life and society
by teaching that all law, is summed up in the love of God and neighbor. Finally, he revealed to us
the supreme secret about God himself, that he is one God in three divine Persons, a truth hidden
(except in shadowy outlines) from all ancient thinkers.
Now that Jesus Christ has shown us the true way we need never be in any doubt as to where to
find the truth. He taught us all the great truths we will ever need. Until he comes again, we have
only to remain faithful to that truth, strive to understand it better, and use it as a guide in our
search for the lesser truths that will complete the picture. Our Lord has even provided the Church
and the help of his grace to guide us in remaining faithful to his teaching. When he ascended into
heaven he left this Church, headed by his apostles and their successors, the bishops, to educate
the whole human race. He warned his apostles, however, that this work of educating the world
would be a difficult task which would not be completed before he comes again. Many would not
understand what the Church was trying to do and would claim that the bishops were trying to
suppress the truth, because they were correcting teachings which were only partly true.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Jesus promised that gradually the Church would go on gathering together the fragments of truth
wherever they were to be found, cleansing them of error, and fitting them into the broad
framework of his own teaching.
CHRISTIAN EDUCATION
In order to bring the truth of Christ to the world, the Church had to overcome three great efforts
of the forces of darkness to put out the light which she held so high.
The first threat was the effort of pagan Rome to absorb the Christians, when it found that it could
not destroy them by persecution. The pagan philosophers tried to water down the truth of Christ's
teaching and turn it into a mere form of pagan philosophy. The great Fathers of the Church --
teachers like St. Ignatius of Antioch, St. Irenaeus, St. Basil, St. Gregory Nazianzen, St.
Augustine, and St. Jerome -- defeated this threat by showing how much greater was the teaching
of Christ than that of the philosophers, although whatever was true in philosophy might be used
in Christian education.
The second great threat was the period of disorder called the Dark Ages. The Roman
government, weakened by its failure to accept Christianity wholeheartedly, collapsed under the
onrush of Germanic barbarians from the north and Mohammedan barbarians from the south.
During this dark time of war and confusion the Church kept patiently at work building the
foundations of a new civilization. It was in the monastery schools, especially those of the Order
of St. Benedict, that the ancient education was not only kept alive, but purified of its paganism
and given a new and truer form based on the study of the Sacred Scriptures.
Gradually peace was restored in Europe; many of the barbarians were converted, others were
driven back. The Church at last was able to establish the great schools called the universities.
Here the wisdom of the Lyceum and the Museum was restored, except that now on the throne of
wisdom sat a new queen, no longer natural theology, but Sacred Theology based on the teaching
of Christ. In the beautiful cathedrals of the Middle Ages we see Sacred Theology portrayed in
stone, surrounded by all the arts and sciences which made up medieval education. They are
symbolized as follows:
3. Music, symbolized by the figure of Tubalcain (rather than his brother Jubal, because in
the Middle Ages bells were a favorite musical instrument and Tubalcain was the inventor
of metal work).
4. Astronomy, symbolized by the figure of Ptolemy.
II. PHILOSOPHY (science), symbolized by a noble woman with her head in the clouds and her
feet on the earth:
A. Natural science and with it medicine, sometimes symbolized by the figure of Galen, the great
Greek doctor and disciple of Aristotle.
B. Social or moral science and with it law, sometimes symbolized by the figure of Justinian, the
Christian Emperor who codified the Roman law.
C. Metaphysics or natural theology, represented by Plato, who was regarded by the earlier
Middle Ages as the great pagan theologian.
III.SACRED THEOLOGY, symbolized by a queen holding the Sacred Scriptures, or later by St.
Thomas Aquinas, the Common Doctor of the Church.
This system of education was perfected by the great Doctors of the Church (of whom St. Thomas
Aquinas was the chief, along with St. Bonaventure and St. Anthony of Padua, St. Albert the
Great, and later St. Robert Bellarmine and St. Peter Canisius) and by educators like St. Ignatius
Loyola, St. John Baptist de la Salle, and St. Angela Merici. It remains the foundation of all
education today, even of that given in non-Catholic schools.
The third great threat to the Church is still not wholly overcome. The reign of Christ had to be
extended beyond the borders of Europe to the whole world. Yet this very expansion brought
dangerous temptations. The Crusades opened up the East with its romantic luxuries and its
mysterious cults. The discovery of the New World opened up the West as a source of enormous
riches and power. The life of Europe became very colorful with the growth of the interest in
literature and fine arts which we call the Renaissance. Dazzled with worldly riches and glory, the
rulers of Europe began to struggle with each other for supremacy. They even sought to make the
institutions of the Church serve their own purposes rather than those of Christ.
The result was the decay of religious unity which we call Protestantism, and the growth of
indifference to spiritual things which we call Secularism. The progress in art, in science, in
invention, and in geographical exploration were all achievements which had their roots in the
education given Europe by the Church, but men forgot this and began to attack the Church as the
enemy of progress. The Church, in spite of these persecutions which for a long time deprived her
of much of her educational influence in Europe, continued patiently to spread her missions into
other lands.
We are living in a time when the Church has finally become world-wide and is teaching all
nations. Yet the world is full of wars and quarrels that make it difficult for the voice of the
Church to be heard. In our own country we have two systems of schools. There are the Catholic
schools which teach the wisdom of Christ in a complete way. Most of our young citizens,
however, attend non-Catholic schools.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
These non-Catholic schools (which are excellent in many ways) actually had their origin in the
schools of the Church but are now separated from her influence. They still teach much of what
they learned from the Church and from the civilization which she preserved and developed, but
they are required to leave out the teaching of many truths, because there is so much disagreement
about basic principles among non-Catholics.
Your own school is not perfect, because it has been hindered from developing perfectly by all the
confusion and troubles in the world. Nevertheless it has a sound Catholic foundation and is
striving to give you the best possible education, to give you the whole teaching of Christ, and to
show you how all the other knowledge which the human race has discovered can be fitted into
this framework and developed still further.
Because of outside pressures and influences on Catholic schools, the names and arrangement of
courses are often different from our traditional curriculum, although the subjects taught are still
essentially the same. Thus under the term "English" we include all the branches of logic.
Arithmetic is today called "algebra." The term "social science" has replaced the older term
"moral science" or "ethics." Natural science is split into many branches: general science, biology,
chemistry, physics, psychology.
The special work of improving Catholic schools began when Leo XIII in 1879 recommended
that all Catholic teaching be placed under the guidance of the philosophy and theology of St.
Thomas Aquinas. The present Holy Father, Pius XII, has repeated this advice and urged us also
to fill in the Thomistic framework with all the new discoveries of our age.
In your lifetime you will play a part in this great story of the advance of truth. Like all men and
women since Adam, you will find that living involves problems concerning the four great fields
of human knowledge:
1. Liberal arts, or arts of thinking and expression, because it is these arts that will make
it possible for you to think clearly, to study well, to teach and persuade others.
2. Natural science, because our knowledge of the world and of human nature is the basis
of everything we think and do, and of all human progress.
3. Social sciences, because they are our guide in living with others.
4. Christian doctrine, because it tells us about God and the purpose of human life.
Of these the liberal arts must first of all be mastered, since to try to study other subjects without
using the arts of study would be to try to fight without weapons. Already in elementary school
you have been preparing to study all these subjects, but now you are entering a new phase of
education when you will complete your liberal arts studies.
In the rest of this book you will find a guide to this work of completing your knowledge of the
liberal arts. You will learn to think clearly and to read and speak effectively, by mastering four
types of logic:
1. Demonstrative logic.
2. Dialectical logic.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
3. Rhetoric.
4. Poetics.
Everything you say or read, even a comic-book, involves these four types of logic. You will
learn all four together, emphasizing demonstrative logic, then seeing how its rules apply to other
kinds of logic. This means learning to do three things, the three processes which Socrates, Plato,
and Aristotle showed are needed for clear thinking:
Memorizing may seem to be a very tedious task. There is no use in memorizing a great many
random facts, but to memorize definitions and classifications of the fundamental concepts in a
science or art is the most efficient way of studying. Such definitions and classifications
summarize a great deal of orderly information in a very short and easily remembered form. If
you have trouble in studying for examinations, it is probably because you waste much of your
time on unimportant points. If you list the important terms in the subject and memorize their
definitions and their classification, you will be quickly and thoroughly prepared. It is important,
however, to memorize a definition exactly, since every word in a good definition is chosen with
care.
3) Rhetoric guides us in persuading others to right opinion and action, when their
emotions might incline them to the opposite way.
4) Poetics guides us in recreating others with the contemplation of beautiful deeds and
the quieting of restless emotions.
3. A sign is something which leads to the knowledge of something other than itself.
1) A natural sign is something which leads to the knowledge of something other than
itself because of a natural similarity or natural connection between them.
2) A conventional sign is something which leads to the knowledge of something other
than itself because of human custom and usage.
3) A distributive universal sign or concept is one which signifies a nature possessed by
each and every one of many things.
4) A singular sign or concept is one which signifies one single thing.
PART ONE
Logic as an Art
CHAPTER I
Poetics: The Art of Storytelling
Most of us enjoy reading a story more than any other kind of reading. Many readers, however,
find it difficult to enjoy any but the most simple and obvious type of stories such as the
"western" or the "true romance." There is a whole world of enjoyment which is closed to them --
the world of stories which can be appreciated only by those who understand something of the art
of storytelling. A Chinaman at a baseball game does not enjoy it until the rules of the game are
explained to him and he begins to appreciate the art of baseball. The purpose of this chapter is to
introduce you to the fundamental rules of the art of storytelling.
The first reason many people do not know how to enjoy literature is that they do not realize that
the word "literature" covers very different kinds of writing which have very different purposes.
Some people think that all good literature is supposed to teach us a moral, while only cheap
literature is entertaining. As a matter of fact there are at least two great types of good literature.
One is called imaginative, the other persuasive. The art of writing and of analyzing imaginative
literature is called poetics; the art of writing and of analyzing persuasive literature is called
rhetoric.*
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
* The terms poetics and rhetoric go back to the philosopher Aristotle. Do not make the mistake of thinking that
poetics applies only to “poetry" in verse. It applies to many prose compositions, such as the novel and short story.
Also do not make the mistake of taking "rhetoric" in a derogatory sense as in the phrase "mere empty rhetoric."
Much of the greatest writing in the world is rhetorical, for example, the sermons of our divine Lord or the letters of
St. Paul.
Imaginative literature includes a great variety of types: the epic, the novel, the short-story, the
play, the lyric poem, some essays, and many other forms. Literature is imaginative or poetic
when its purpose is to entertain and delight us by telling a story. Its purpose is recreational, but it
gives us a different and more intimate type of recreation than sports or games. Sports and games
primarily recreate and refresh the body, although they also give some rest to the mind and
emotions. But imaginative writing directly and profoundly rests and delights our souls by lifting
our minds and emotions above the cares, confusions, strains, and frustrations of everyday life to
a wider and clearer vision. It is not a mere escape from life. Rather it is a glimpse of the goal
ahead which encourages and inspires us to live more fully and perfectly.
Persuasive or rhetorical literature does not aim at entertainment, but seeks to persuade us to do
something. Propaganda, advertising, selling, the political speech, and the sermon are all
examples of persuasion. The imaginative writer invites us to relaxation and enjoyment, while the
rhetorical writer urges us to action and achievement. The imaginative writer inspires us with a
wider vision of life; the rhetorical writer urges us to a decision about some problem which is
immediately at hand. Thus the aims of imaginative and rhetorical writing are, as it were, opposite
to each other. As a result, in most cases good imaginative writing is bad rhetorical writing, and
good rhetorical writing is bad imaginative writing.
These two arts differ also in this, that the imaginative writer wishes us to notice and to enjoy the
skill with which his story is told, but the rhetorical writer seeks to conceal the fact that he is
trying to influence us.
We must learn to distinguish these two kinds of writing and judge each by its own purpose and
rules. When we ourselves wish to entertain others in conversation or to persuade them in
practical life, we need to understand the techniques of these two arts. When others try to
entertain or persuade us, we must be able to appreciate and enjoy the entertainment and yet not
be unduly influenced by the persuasion.
In this chapter we will be concerned primarily with imaginative writing, in the next with
persuasive writing.
In imaginative writing the soul of the writing is its story or plot. No matter how long a novel may
be, every detail of it is tied together by its plot, just as every part of our body receives its life
from the soul. A part of our body which is separated from the soul dies and is useless. Similarly
any word or incident or character in a story which does not contribute to the plot is deadwood.
The great storyteller Edgar Allen Poe said:
A skillful literary artist has constructed a tale. If wise, be has not fashioned his thoughts to
accommodate his incidents; but having conceived with deliberate care, a certain unique or single
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
effect to be wrought out, he then invents such incidents -- he then combines such events as may
best aid him in establishing this preconceived effect. If his very initial sentence tends not to the
outbringing of this effect, then he has failed in his first step. In the whole composition there
should be no word written of which the tendency, direct or indirect, is not to the one pre-
established design. And by such means, with such care and skill, a picture is at length painted
which leaves in the mind of him who contemplates it with a kindred art, a sense of fullest
satisfaction.
We all recognize this in the telling of a joke. One person tells a joke and it is funny. Another tells
the same joke and no one laughs. Why? Because the artful storyteller makes every word and
every pause contribute to the comic effect, while the dull storyteller spoils the point by
introducing irrelevant remarks and by bad timing. The first rule of the art of storytelling is to
grasp the plot, which is the very soul of the story, and to make every detail contribute to it.
At first sight it seems quite easy to find the plot of a story. Most people can repeat the incidents
of a movie they have seen or a novel they have read. A mere listing of incidents, however, is not
the plot. As Poe indicates in the quotation above, a writer does not begin with a series of
incidents. He invents the incidents to bring out a central effect or idea. It is this central idea, and
not merely a string of incidents, which is the plot.
The central idea of a story, however, is not some abstract thought, it is an action. The plot is
some single action of which the various incidents are only parts. In a long novel this action may
be made up of hundreds of incidents all of which form a single whole. In a short lyric poem this
action may be a single event which takes place within someone's mind and heart. If we can
discover this single action or plot on which the whole story is built, we will truly appreciate it. In
order to learn to do this, we should practice trying to state the plot of each story we read in a
single sentence. Of course such a sentence only gives us a faint notion of the reality of the plot
itself. If a writer could present the plot to us fully in a sentence, he would not have bothered to
write his story in so many pages. But such a summary sentence is a test of whether we have
really begun to see the plot. If we try this exercise, we will soon realize how poorly we have
been reading and how much we have been missing. We will probably find that we have only
been reading incidents and have missed the plan of the whole story. We are like a man who
works in a skyscraper and has been in every room of it, but who never sees the building from a
distance. Such a man has no idea of the size or beauty of the whole building.
Some people, even famous critics, do not appreciate the plot of stories. They think that only
rather trivial writers of mystery stories or adventure stories pay much attention to plot. Such
critics often say that the important thing in a story is the characters, or the thought, or the style. It
is true that in some very fine stories the element of plot may be very simple, while the element of
character or thought or style is very much emphasized. There are plays, for example, in which
the incidents are quite simple, but the psychology of the characters is very vividly portrayed.
There are other plays in which we are most interested in the witty dialogue or thought of the
speakers, and others in which the beauty of style seems to make up for lick of action.
Nevertheless, if we study such plays carefully we will discover that they do not hold our
attention unless the characters, the thought, and the style contribute to making the plot strong and
effective, regardless of how simple it may be. This is especially clear in a play, but it will be
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
found to be true also in all kinds of imaginative writing. The reason for this is that character can
be known perfectly only through action ("by their fruits you shall know them"), while thought is
imaginative and poetic only when it expresses the motives which move people to act. Abstract
thought, separated from human action, does not have an imaginative effect. As for style, human
words are much more suited to narrate actions than to paint pictures or descriptions in static
terms.
Thus we may say that an imaginative work has three objects of representation or imitation'
namely, plot, character, and thought. Of these, plot is primary. All three are the form of a poetic
work, while the style pertains to its medium or matter. *
* Do not confuse the term "form" used of the plot with the term "literary forms," such as the novel, short story,
lyric, sonnet, bank-verse, etc. The true form of a work is its plot. Its literary "form" is merely a convenient
classification of the technique with which it is told, and really pertains to the matter of the work.
What makes a plot good? Not every account of an action makes a good plot. We might write an
accurate account of some battle which would be very poor entertainment. Mere dry fact does not
catch our imagination, nor please us. Yet Shakespeare in many of his plays took such dry
historical accounts and turned them into exciting stories. This was because he knew how to put
feeling or emotion into his account.
Both imaginative and rhetorical writing differ from matter-of-fact writing, because they not only
state facts but also arouse our emotions and feelings. They make us tense and excited about what
comes next, or satisfied and delighted with the way things turn out. Rhetorical writing arouses
our emotions in order to get us to do something. Hence the preacher or salesman attempts to keep
us emotionally keyed-up until we can act. The imaginative writer, on the other hand, is trying to
entertain and refresh us. Hence he not only arouses our emotions, but also satisfies them and
brings them to rest in the contented enjoyment of the beauty of his work. At the end of a good
novel or play we feel calm and at peace, although during the reading or performance we may
have felt fear or excitement, or even have wept. This peace of soul enables us to look back over
the novel or play and see it as a beautiful whole which expresses some deep truth about life
which we had never fully appreciated before, but which seems to us so perfectly embodied in the
artist's work.
This is true even if a story is sad. Some people cannot endure to read a sad story because it
leaves them depressed. This is either because the author has not told his story well or because the
reader does not know how to appreciate the art of storytelling. A good reader enjoys the story
even if it is sad, for he delights in the beauty with which it has been told. In fact, sad stories are
often more truly entertaining than joyful ones, since they seem so true to the facts of life, which
are often very sad, and since they help us to look through this sadness to the great and perfect
pattern of God's providence, which is working to bring eternal beauty and joy out of the sorrow
of this world. Even the Greeks, who as pagans had only a dim notion of God's providence,
realized that in tragedy there is something grand and noble in the restoration of the law of the
universe through the punishment of sin.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
This power of a story first to arouse the emotions and then bring them to rest in the vision of life
was called by the Greeks catharsis (purification), because it cleanses the soul of disturbed
emotions. Most people live a rather petty life of worries, frustrations, and routine. Their emotions
are out of tune, and their vision is narrow and blurred. The magic of the imaginative writer
releases the emotions from their daily worries and sets them in tune like a beautiful melody, so
that they lift the mind on wings to take a broad view of the universe. A wise man or philosopher
(a lover of wisdom) is able to take this broad view at will. Such wisdom comes only after a long
life of discipline and thought, but the poet is able to give us a glimpse of that broad vision even
when we are young and perhaps foolish. Even the wise man grows weary at times and needs the
refreshment of the poet's spell.
If a story is to produce this catharsis and this vision, it must be very vivid and concrete, since the
emotions are not aroused by something dry and abstract. It is only when one can imagine very
clearly how an event took place -- and can sympathize with the people to whom that event
happens that one becomes emotionally involved. That is why a poor reader can enjoy a movie
but not a book. When he reads, be does not know how to imagine the events. But a good reader
finds the book even more vivid than the movie; and when he sees a movie made from some great
book he has read, he usually finds the movie version very thin and uninteresting. The great writer
is the one who has firmly grasped the central idea or single action of his story and then has been
able to render that action entirely concrete and vivid.
Since the plot is the soul of the poetic work it must be unified; otherwise it would not weld the
part of the work into a perfect whole. It is unified when it consists of only one principal action.
There may be other interwoven sub-plots, but these must strengthen the main plot by emphasis or
contrast, and must not confuse or hinder it. Nothing should be admitted to the story that does not
contribute to this main plot, although in some types of writing (particularly the novel), we permit
the organization to be looser than we expect in an intensely moving play, short story, or lyric.
The plot must be complete or it will leave us unsatisfied. To be complete it must have a
beginning, in which a new action arises from some situation. This new action should unfold in a
series of connected events or incidents which form the middle of the story, and these should lead
to a final rest or resolution (the end), in which an the forces set in motion at the beginning work
themselves out. These requirements seem rather obvious; yet many plays and stories win be
found which are faulty because the writer is either too slow in getting his action started, or
because he does not work out the middle in a series of connected but contrasted incidents, or
because -- and this is the hardest task of all -- the writer cannot bring the forces set in motion to a
real rest and conclusion.
Sometimes a plot is simple; then its action moves in one straight line from beginning to end.
More interesting is the complex plot, in which the action seems first to move toward one goal
and then suddenly to reverse itself and move toward a contrary goal. This reversal is also often
called the climax of the play, while the resolution or ending is called the denouement. The
magnitude or length of a story or poem (the number of incidents, etc.) must be sufficient for the
forces set in motion to work themselves out. It should be no longer.
The characters who carry out this action must appear to be consistent and like real human
beings; they must also be appropriate to the type of action they are to perform so as not to make
the plot itself seem improbable. It is in the characters that the reader sees both the outward action
and the inward action or emotion. It is this sharing in the emotions of the characters which helps
one to enter into their experiences and to understand them more fully than if they were only
known in an abstract way.
The characters reveal themselves chiefly through what they do, but if we could see only their
actions we would not fully understand their interior motives. Hence a third element in a story is
the thought expressed in the speeches of the characters and also by the comments of the author.
Unless this thought helps us to understand the action and enter into it, it is irrelevant and boring.
If it is to represent the way in which one character seeks to persuade or influence another, it is
clear that thought must obey the rules of rhetoric. In the next chapter we will study these rules
which must be known by an imaginative writer if he is to express thought well in his stories. The
imaginative writer, however, must be careful in making use of rhetoric that his story does not
become a sermon. Thought and the rhetoric used to express it must be kept strictly subordinate to
plot if a story is to be good imaginative literature.
Plot, character, and thought are the form of the poetic work because they are the objects
represented or portrayed by the writer. They are the pattern which he wishes to embody in his
materials, just as a builder wishes to embody a blueprint in stone and brick, glass and steel. What
are the materials of the imaginative writer? They are words. The great storyteller is one who so
thoroughly understands the magic of words that he is able to use them to make his story, with its
characters and thoughts live in our imagination. This is not to say most authors first work out
their plot completely and then find words for it. As they write, words and plot, matter and form,
body and soul, weave themselves together so that the plot gives form to the words and the words
give body to the plot.
Many people have no conception of the magic powers of words. In the second part of this
chapter we are going to study words very carefully with the purpose of learning something of
this magic. The study of words constitutes the first step in the study of style. Words must be put
together into sentences, sentences into paragraphs, and paragraphs into whole compositions. This
weaving of the matter of a story to fit its plot is what is called style.
Before taking up this study of words let us consider an example of good story telling. In Part IV,
Section I you will find a short story by the French writer, Alphonse Daudet, called The Last
Lesson. This simple story is told with very great art. Let us see how we would begin to
appreciate the storytelling skill of the author.
First we try to grasp its central idea or plot. Some readers if asked for the plot of this story would
say:
An Alsatian boy was late on his way to school. On the way he saw people looking at a notice
before the mayor's office, but be did not read it. When he got to school be found not only the
teacher and the pupils but some of the townsfolk. He learned that this was the last class to be
taught in French, because the occupying Germans were abolishing French in the schools. The
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
teacher was in his Sunday best and he taught the lesson very solemnly. All the pupils, impressed
by the occasion, studied very hard. Franz, the boy in question, did not know his lesson. The
teacher did not scold him, but pointed out that be and all the rest bad not appreciated the French
language when they were free to use it. Now the schoolmaster after so many years of teaching
had to go away. The lesson came to an end when the teacher wrote Vive la France on the
blackboard because he was so overcome by emotion that he could not speak.
This is a summary of the incidents of the story, but it does not at all make clear the plot or central
action. The plot can be much more clearly expressed by a single sentence:
A country which lacked patriotism learned it only on the day when it lost its right to its own
culture.
When we express the plot in this compact way we see that the various incidents, such as the
boy's tardiness, the crowd at the bulletin board, the faulty recitation, etc., were invented by the
author to bring out his central story.
We should now see if this plot is complete and unified. The obvious beginning is the incident of
the boy's running late to school, but this is only a way of expressing the real beginning of the
action:
A country lacked patriotism so that it permitted a foreign country to occupy it without realizing
what it had lost.
This country finally realizes its loss just when it is too late.
This is expressed by the last words of the schoolmaster when he writes "Vive la France" and
closes the school.
The middle is the series of incidents that lead from this beginning to the end. They are:
1. The crowd reading the bulletin board.
2. The boy's surprise at the unusual scene in the schoolroom.
3. The boy's poor recitation and the teacher's speech.
4. The earnest application of the students to their lesson.
5. The sound of packing of trunks upstairs which reveals that the teacher must
leave town.
6. The sound of the clock and of the Prussians returning.
The plot can be judged to be unified if each of these incidents is needed to carry the action
forward to the end. It is complete if the end brings this action to a full rest.
A study of these middle incidents will quickly show us that the plot is indeed unified and
complete. The running boy's glimpse of the crowd at the bulletin board suggests to us what is
about to happen and arouses our interest. This is increased by the strange scene in the classroom.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
At this point we finally understand the situation and the beginning of the story is complete. The
incidents of the teaching and the teacher's sorrowful speech are the climax of the story. Up to this
point we have probably been thinking that the cause of the disaster is merely the tyranny of a
foreign nation. Suddenly at this point we see that the deeper cause is the failure of the French
themselves to appreciate their own culture. It is this that has led to the occupation by a foreign
nation. The fifth incident stirs up our anxiety about how the story will end. Mat will the teacher
do or say before lie leaves forever? Thus the conclusion is complete, because the teacher's words
written on the blackboard express the final outcome of the action: the resolution of all present to
be true patriots in the future. The story seems to end sadly, but it does not end in defeat since
now the village has acquired the patriotism which it lacked before. The author is very skilful in
making the teacher write rather than merely speak these words. The fact that they are written on
the board symbolizes that they are now forever written in the hearts of the village.
We should then ask if this plot is truly imaginative; that is, does it produce a catharsis? We can
answer this by showing that the emotion of anxiety and fear aroused at the beginning of the story
is brought to rest in the act of patriotic determination in the souls of the villagers. At the end they
are sorrowful, but they are also filled with grim courage and loyalty they had not known before.
We can see how the author created this emotional effect. He does not describe emotions, but he
renders his plot in concrete terms. We see the boy running, the crowd at the bulletin board, the
strange scene in the classroom, the sound of the Prussian troops drilling. These scenes create the
impression of fear and anxiety. This is renewed just before the end by the sounds which indicate
the end is approaching. Finally the emotion of determination is expressed by the clear cut action
of the teacher as he writes on the board.
Once we have learned the central idea of the plot, we should then see how the characters and
thought have been employed to bring it out. Why is the story told through a little boy? Why is he
a poor and tardy student? Why is the teacher a rather harsh and unsympathetic teacher? As we
study the characters we will see that the chief character is really the teacher. He is the one who at
this crisis of his life finally wakes up to his own importance. It was his duty to teach the villagers
to be true patriots, and be has never really devoted himself to his task. He has acted as if he were
just a daily drudge driving little boys to learn about participles, instead of the teacher of the
whole village who should have taught noble virtues and ideals. The author has shown us what a
humdrum, uninspiring teacher this poor man was, and yet at the last moment how noble he
becomes. Is this consistent and lifelike? I think we should answer "yes," for the author has
indicated that once this teacher had great ideals, but that he had fallen into a rut.
The little boy stands for the other villagers. He is a symbol of his whole village, in his laziness
and lack of clear-sighted ideals. The author has selected him because a child receives vivid
impressions and suggests to us how the village will have to maintain its determination until its
children have grown to manhood and are able to strive for liberty. Among the other villagers,
only old Hauser is singled out as typical of the older generation. The character of the foreign
invaders is merely hinted at, since the story is not about them. Thus the author has used only
such characters as will contribute to his plot effectively, and these are consistent with
themselves, with their function in the story, and with human nature.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The thought element in the story is found in the speeches of the teacher and in the boy's own
hidden thoughts. The author carefully distinguishes the simple, concrete reactions of the boy and
the dignified but emotional speeches of the teacher. The boy's wandering imagination is
beautifully shown by his fancy that even the birds must learn to sing German, a fancy which slips
itself into his thoughts in spite of his intense concentration on his lesson. This shows how
wandering those thoughts must have been at school on other days. It is noteworthy that in this
very short story the author chose to tell the story in the boy's own words, thus avoiding any
comment of his own.
The art of Daudet in telling his story thus becomes very clear, and the more carefully we read the
tale the more astonished we are at how perfectly every incident contributes to the effect. Can we
find a similar care in storytelling in a poem which at first sight seems to tell no story at all? Let
us look at a short poem, Emerson's "The Concord Hymn," written on a theme similar to that of
Daudet.
"The Concord Hymn" (Part IV, Section I) is a type of short poem called a lyric. In such poetry
the plot is not as obvious as in a narrative work like an epic poem or a novel. Nevertheless there
is a plot. What happens in "The Concord Hymn"? It can be summarized as follows: As we come
to erect a monument on this almost forgotten battlefield, we begin to realize how much we owe
to those who died here and how little gratitude we have shown; and we feel moved to pray that
future generations will better honor and preserve their heritage of freedom. This is a little story,
which has a beginning, a middle, and an end,
Beginning:
We Come to this battlefield to erect a monument to dead heroes. (1st stanza)
Middle:
a. We begin to realize that we had almost forgotten what they did and have
showed little appreciation. (2nd stanza)
b. Our act of raising a monument seems inadequate. (3rd stanza)
End:
But we pray that God, who never forgets, will maintain this memory and this
heritage in future generations. (4th stanza)
Thus we have the story, not of some external action, but rather of the internal thought and feeling
of Emerson and the group for whom he speaks. It will be noticed that what is expressed is not
merely thought, but also the arousal and quieting, or catharsis of feeling which is the
characteristic of all poetic argument. Thus the first stanza indicates a feeling of wonder or desire
to understand, and then awe, a kind of fear which we feel when suddenly confronted with
something great and unknown. Emerson suddenly begins to realize what a great historic spot this
is which he has so often passed without even thinking of it. This awe deepens in the second
stanza into a sense of sorrow and shame, mixed with a certain indignation or anger, on thinking
of the ingratitude and forgetfulness with which the dead have been treated. Then in the fourth
stanza the emotion begins to resolve itself, as he turns to the monument with the determination
and courage to make up for the past by setting up the monument, and yet with a feeling that this
is not enough. Finally, in the last stanza the emotion turns to one of solemn reverence and of
hope -- even joy -- to think that, however men may forget, God, who is eternal and unforgetting,
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
will never let the memory or the example of the heroic dead be lost. Thus accompanying the
thought is a movement of emotion:
This last emotion brings the poem to a close, since all emotion ends either in sorrow and
resignation, or in joy and delight. This emotion reinforces and blends with the thought, so that
our sense of surprise in the first stanza helps us to realize the greatness of the battle and our
feeling of prayer and hope in the last stanza brings us face to face with the realization that the
true honor due to patriotism comes from God, who justly rewards all men.
The story is the chief thing in this poem -- as in every poem -- since it gives the whole shape,
unity, and meaning to the work. Nevertheless, tile story would not be possible unless it happened
to some character or characters. Who are the characters here? Obviously the chief is not a
single individual, but rather the whole group, the people of America who have come to raise the
monument, the "we" of the poem. Does the poet characterize these people in any way? Not
directly. But indirectly, he shows us that they are simple, sincere, and frank; that they have the
nobility to be ashamed of having forgotten, and the humility to admit their weakness; that they
are busy people looking to the future and hence likely to forget; and finally that they are a
reverent and courageous people with confidence in God. One of the reasons this poem is so
beautiful is that the movement of emotions which it contains shows us the soul of the American
people as we like to believe it is: simple, reverent, humble, courageous, The other characters are
the dead -- both the heroic Americans and their foe -- and the Americans of the future. Nothing
much is said about any of these except the dead heroes, and they are shown us in a simple vivid
picture at that great moment of the battle when they fired the first shot. This is enough, however,
to make us think of them as simple (because farmers) but mighty and courageous (they fired the
shot heard around the world). It is better that they be characterized only in this simple fashion
since it makes them a better symbol.
The thought of the poem is the connection of ideas expressed by the chief character. It has an
interest all its own. First of all, in the opening stanza we see a connection established between a
very small event (the first shot) and a tremendous consequence (heard round the world). Why
was this action a world-wide event? Not merely because it began a war, but because the
American Revolution became a model for countries all over the world and encouraged them to
overthrow governments that denied human rights.
In the second stanza there is the interest of the contrast between the men opposed in battle who
now rest side by side, and the philosophical thought that Time runs on, bearing everything away.
In the third stanza our thoughts go into the future. What will become of America tomorrow? In
the last stanza we have the deepest thought of all. Behind Time and Nature is a God. It was his
Providence that made this little battle so important in its consequence. It is his will that men
should be free. He inspired the minutemen to fight. He will not fail to help our country in the
time to come, if we turn to him. We might wonder why Emerson calls God the "Spirit." Is it not
a rather impersonal way to speak of God? Is it perhaps because Emerson is thinking of God more
as a force than as a person?
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
If we consider whether the poet has used plot, character, and thought well, we will notice be has
kept the character in the background and revealed it mainly through plot. This is effective since
character exists to serve plot, not the other way around. The character is thus appropriate to the
plot, and it is also lifelike, since the succession of emotions and consistency of one emotion with
another is maintained. It is very natural that from wonder and awe at the scene of the historic
spot, we should then begin to feel the other emotions mentioned in their proper order. Thus the
plot is unified and complete, because from the first event and emotion the others follow step by
step to a complete catharsis. The thought also in this poem is subordinated to the succession of
emotions which are the main events of the story; yet it is interesting, since Emerson is awake to
the significance of events; lie perceives their irony and at last arrives at a deep understanding of
them.
To learn to read stories well or to tell them, we must first be equipped with a rich vocabulary.
We cannot build a magnificent building out of scraps. We must have a great and rich variety of
materials. Fortunately, we have ready at hand a wonderful supply of such materials in the
dictionary.
The dictionary is a printed vocabulary, a magic chest out of which we can draw every material
we need to build the world of imagination. The words which it contains have been invented by
countless generations of men, women and children who have coined or remade words to express
their personal thoughts and experiences. No one has contributed more to this treasure chest than
the tellers of tales, who are always looking for richer and more striking words.
The big unabridged dictionary contains the most commonly used words. Let us look up a few
entries in it. We will select the two main ideas which we found in The Last Lesson and the "The
Concord Hymn." We found that both concern patriotism, and that each tries to show that
patriotism is a true virtue which few people appreciate properly. We will also make use of a
rhetorical example on the same theme, Lincoln's "Gettysburg Address" (page 413), to show that
persuasive writing uses many of the same methods as does imaginative writing. If we look up
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
These two examples show us the kind of information given us by an unabridged dictionary.
Notice the following:
1. The pronunciation of words. A word is a conventional sign (see pages 5 and 21); that is,
each is a sound that leads to the knowledge of something other than itself because of human
custom and usage. Animals make sounds only by instinct; but men have control over the sounds
they make, and they agree to use particular sounds to stand for definite things. That is why men
have different languages; but every robin has the same song, and every lion the same roar.
Although the connection between the sound and the idea in human language is only a matter of
custom, sometimes a sound is chosen as a word because it resembles the thing it stands for, as
when we call a dog "a bow-wow." This method of making words is called onomatopoeia (on-o-
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
mat-o-pé-ya). Sometimes the sound is not an imitation, but is somehow appropriate to that for
which it stands. Thus the word "gloom" suggests a dark and sad effect because of the long m
which gives it a deep, murmuring sound; the word "shining" sounds bright and clear because of
the high, thin "i's."
The sounds of words can be very beautiful and expressive, a spoken music. When we hear
music, even without words, it fills our minds with images and makes us feel happy or sad,
peaceful or excited. All speech, when properly pronounced in a musical voice, is very pleasant,
charming, and moving to the hearers. When it is mumbled, sloppy, harsh, it repels the listeners
and detracts from the effect of what is said.
The study of sounds as tools of expression belongs to the art of music. Every sound has several
qualities: it is high or low because of its quality of pitch; it is loud or soft because of its quality of
volume; it is rich or thin, etc., because of its quality of timbre.
When a sound has a definite pitch, it is a musical sound and is pleasant to the ear. When it is a
mixture of unrelated sounds, it is a noise and is unpleasant. In speech certain sounds are musical
and can be sting on a sustained pitch. These are called vowels: a, e, i, o, u in their various
pronunciations. Others are sounds made at the beginning or ending of a vowel sound and cannot
be pronounced or sung by themselves. These are called consonants (Latin for "sounding with")
because they have to be pronounced with a vowel. A few consonants (l, m, n, ng, r, w, y) include
a vowel sound; therefore they can be pronounced alone and are called semi-vowels.
In singing, the pitch moves up and down a series of definite tones called the scale. In speaking,
there is no definite scale but only a slight rise and fall of the voice, called inflection. The increase
in volume on the principal syllable of a word is called the accent. A similarity between vowels is
called assonance (Latin for "sounding too"); when this similarity also extends to the final
consonants of a word it is called rhyme. When the similarity of sounds is at the beginning of
syllables, there is alliteration.
If we learn to appreciate and use the music of words, we will find a new pleasure in speaking and
listening, and will be able to influence those with whom we speak.
* * * * * *
In the above entries for "patriotism" and "virtue," the pronunciations are given with the exact
sound of each vowel and with the accent for the principal syllable. In Webster's New
International Dictionary, pages xxii-lxxviii, one finds a very detailed and scientific discussion of
the sounds of the English language and the difference in pronunciation in different parts of
England and the United States. What is meant by a "southern accent" or a "Brooklyn accent" or
an "Irish brogue"?
In "The Concord Hymn" there are many examples of the choice of words whose sound is
musical and appropriate. Notice, for example, the quiet and mysterious effect given by the
second stanza. The alliteration of the s sounds and the l sounds is largely responsible for this
effect. Notice also the pattern of rhymes. In the "Gettysburg Address" the alliteration of f, n, and l
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
helps to make the first sentence very musical. A careful reading aloud will show that Lincoln
took care to choose certain vowels like the long o throughout his speech to give it a solemn and
ringing sound. (See page 413).
2. The origin of words. The dictionary also tells us how a particular combination of sounds
came to stand for a particular idea. This is called the etymology or word-origin. Words usually
were invented to describe something of everyday life. They were concrete, and referred to
something individual and apparent to the senses. Then they came to be used in a more abstract
way to refer to some general idea which could be applied to many things, and which appealed
more to the intellect than to the senses.
Knowing the origin of a word helps us to grasp the basic idea that underlies it, since we too have
to learn abstract ideas by beginning with what is concrete. It takes time and thought to
understand an abstract idea.
* * * * * *
The word "patriotism" had its origin in one of the most fundamental words of our language, the
word "father" (Latin pater), which goes back to a still simpler word "Papa" which is one of a
baby's favorite sounds. The word "virtue" goes back to the Latin for "man," because it is a
quality every real man should have.
In "The Concord Hymn" the word "votive" comes from the word for "vow," and the word "deed"
from an old form of "to do," and "redeem" from the Latin for "buy back." When we realize this,
we understand that a "votive stone" expresses a vow to thank and to imitate the heroic dead,
while "to redeem their deed" means to bring back from the past the memory and example of their
heroic actions.
In reading the "Gettysburg Address," it helps to know that "civil war" means a war between
citizens of the same state because "civil" comes from the word for "city"; that "consecrate"
comes from words meaning "to set aside as something holy"; that "dedicate" means "to declare
that a thing is holy"; and that "vain" means "empty."
Emerson, the author of "The Concord Hymn," in his essay Language advises us to use words
with something of their original meaning if we want to speak or write forcefully:
Every word which is used to express a moral or an intellectual fact, if traced to its root, is found
to be borrowed from some material appearance. Right means straight; wrong means twisted;
spirit primarily means wind; transgression, the crossing of a line; supercilious, the raising of the
eyebrow .... The etymologist finds the deadest word to have once been a brilliant picture.
Language is fossil poetry.
3. The grammatical function of words. The dictionary also indicates to which part of speech a
word belongs. Sometimes a word may serve as several different parts with a slightly different
meaning and perhaps a different pronunciation for each.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
If we had the simplest kind of language, we could get along with nothing but the names of
things. Notice, for example, how the second stanza of "The Concord Hymn" would read if it
were made up of names only:
Each name calls up an object before the mind and we quickly supply the necessary connections
between one object and another. Children love to know and to repeat the names of things.
Prayers and poetry make great use of names.
The names of things are called nouns, and this is the most important of all the parts of speech.
Sometimes, however, it becomes awkward to keep repeating the noun which names some object
we are discussing. Hence most languages also have pronouns, which substitute for a noun
already used. Obviously it is very important that it be clear exactly to which noun a pronoun
refers. To show this connection a pronoun has several forms indicating gender (he, she, it),
number (he, they) and person (I, you, he) which must agree with the noun for which it
substitutes. Pronouns are called personal when they refer to a definite person or thing, or
indefinite (any, some, etc.). They are reflexive when they refer back to the subject (herself, own,
etc.), or relative when they introduce a clause (who, which, what), or interrogative when used in
a question (who? which? what?).
We say, that a noun is the name of some thing, but in the example given above is it true to say
that "silence," "sleepy," "darkness" are things in the same way that "foe," "conqueror," "stream,"
and "sea" are things? Strictly speaking, a thing is a substance; that is, something which can exist
in its own right, not merely as the modification or relation of something else. Thus a man is a
substance which can exist in its own right; but the color of a man's hair, his size, his shape, his
position, and his actions exist only as modifications or relations of a man. In Alice in
Wonderland the Cheshire cat slowly vanished until nothing was left but its smile. A smile, a
shape, a color, a relation cannot exist in its own right but only in something else. Such secondary
aspects of substances are called accidents or attributes of substances. Nouns were originally
invented to name substances. When we use them to name accidents like a smile or a color, we do
so because we are thinking of these accidents as if they could exist by themselves like the smile
of the Cheshire cat.
The philosopher Aristotle tried to figure out very carefully just how many types or categories of
accidents or modifications and relations of substances there are. He found that there are ten
categories corresponding to ten questions that we ask about things. They are as follows-
1. What is this thing? Category of substance; e.g., man, dog, rose, salt, iron,
angel.
2. How many or much of it is there? Category of quantity; e.g., three, one
hundred, whole, part.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
3. What sort of thing is it? Category of quality; e.g., red, melodious, sour, soft,
virtuous, healthy.
4. What are its connections? Category of relation; e.g., similar, different, bigger,
smaller, equal, cause, effect, father, mother.
5. Where is it? Category of place; e.g., here, there, near, up, down.
6. What is its position? Category of position; e.g., upright, bent, prone, standing,
sitting, reversed.
7. Is it covered or uncovered? Category of vestition; e.g., naked, clothed,
armored, harnessed, uniformed.
8. What is it doing? Category of action; e.g., running, sleeping, cutting, building,
flying, talking.
9. What is happening to it? Category of reception; e.g., being cut, being heated,
being built, being plowed.
10. When is it acting or being acted upon? Category of timing; e.g., today,
yesterday, now, then, once.
Fundamental natural science will teach why there are only these ten categories. As we learn each
part of natural science, we will learn each of these classifications. Outlines of them can be given,
as we shall see, but they will never be wholly completed, since science goes on discovering
things to go into each classification.
These categories are used in all human thinking and by every race of men, but each language has
its own way of expressing them. All of them can be expressed by nouns (or pronouns), but since
the nine categories of accidents are not really things, but modifications or relations of things, it is
more satisfactory to have other parts of speech which express these categories as modifiers of
nouns.
The categories of quantities and qualities include modifications of substances (nouns); hence
the part of speech called the adjective was invented as a modifier of nouns especially to indicate
quantities (the numerals) and qualities. The special forms of the pronoun indicate quantity
(plural or singular) and gender (which is a quality). The category of vestition is also indicated by
an adjective since clothing can be thought of as a kind of quality of the thing clothed.
The category of relation is indicated in many languages by a modification of the form of the
noun called case. For example, in Latin vir means man; viri is the possessive case (indicated in
English by 's) which indicates a relation of possession; and virum is the objective case (indicated
in English by special forms of the pronoun: him, them) which indicates reception or relation.
The other categories of place, position, action, reception and timing are not relations, but since
they involve relations also, they are often expressed by prepositions. Action and reception,
however, are extremely important, because we know substances mainly through what they do or
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
through the changes they undergo. Hence almost all languages have a special part of speech, the
verb, to give full expression to these two categories. Thus the noun which names a substance and
the verb which shows how that substance reveals itself through what it does or undergoes are the
two most important parts of speech.
Among verbs, the verb is is called the copula (joiner) because it expresses the act of the mind by
which we join two ideas to make a sentence, as when we say, "The man is patriotic." Other verbs
actually contain the copula, plus the idea of some other action besides the action of our mind.
Hence they can be analyzed into two words, the copula and another word which is the name of
an action. Thus "The man fights" can be analyzed into "The man is fighting." This name of an
action when used as a noun is called a gerund (from Latin gerere meaning to bear, because it
bears the part of a noun) as in "Swimming is fun"; when the action is expressed with to, it is
called an infinitive (from Latin for "without a limit," because it is not limited to a particular
action) as in the sentence "To swim is fun;" when the name of the action is used as an adjective it
is called a participle (because it is part of a verb) as in "The boy is swimming."
Since an action must take place in time, the verb also expresses the category of timing by its
tense. This is the special mark of a verb which distinguishes it from all other words.
In English these ideas are often made clearer by the use of helping verbs or auxiliaries, such as
have, will, shall, etc., which contain the copula plus the idea of time.
Actions can have various degrees of intensity, because they produce their effect more or less
perfectly. Hence adverbs have been invented to modify verbs and to indicate their intensity, as in
the sentences "He ran swiftly" or "He hit hard." Since the effect of an action is often to produce
some quality, adverbs are also used to modify adjectives, as in the phrase "The smoothly
polished surface." Finally, since an action always requires time and place in which to occur,
adverbs often modify a verb by showing the time or place in which the action happens.
Conjunctions (and, therefore, because, but, etc.) also express relations, but these relations are not
between things, but between sentences or parts of sentences. These are mental relations and will
be discussed in the next chapter. Interjections are sometimes classed as a part of speech, but they
express emotion rather than thought.
Thus we see that the parts of speech, although they do not perfectly correspond to the categories,
have been invented to express the categories with a clarity which is sufficient for ordinary
writing and speaking. In order to understand the function of a part of speech we have only to ask
"What does it modify?" and "What type of information does it give and how?" and "What
category does it express?" Unless we know the part of speech to which a word belongs we do not
know its whole meaning.
The diagram on the opposite page of the first stanza of "The Concord Hymn" shows how in a
single sentence many categories of information may be given. This sentence contains all the
categories
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
4. The current meanings of words. It would be very convenient if we had a different word for
every concept, and if every word stood for only one concept. When a word has a single meaning,
it is said to be univocal. Actually, however, the world is too full of things and our minds are too
full of new experiences for language to keep pace with thought. Confronted with a new idea we
grope for a word to express it, and cannot find one ready at hand. Hence we tend to take the
name of something previously known and apply it to the new object. Thus a word acquires
several meanings and is said to be equivocal (from Latin for "equal' and "sound," that is, a sound
which means at least two things). When there is no apparent connection between these meanings,
they are said to be purely equivocal. Pure equivocation is not very common; usually the diverse
meanings have some connection, and hence the term is said to be analogical. If this connection is
one of similarity, we have analogy of similarity or proportionality. If this similarity is a merely
accidental resemblance between things, the analogy is said to be improper or metaphorical. If it
is a similarity which is essential, the analogy is said to be proper.
If the connection is of any sort other than one of similarity, the analogy is called an analogy of
connection or attribution. Such connections when examined will be found to be due to some
relation of cause and effect. These different terms are shown in the diagram on the following
graphic.
GRAPHICS
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
TERMS
If a term has
a. by a similarity
The dictionary shows that the word "patriotism" has been taken from "patriot" and that the latter
has four uses, two of which are now obsolete. These are all connected with each other by
similarity, but meaning 3 is derived from meaning 2 by an accidental comparison (a rebel is not
essentially like a patriot, but only accidentally like him, since both claim to be fighting for
freedom) and hence is used by analogy of improper similarity or metaphor.
"Virtue" has no fewer than ten different usages, all of are based on some similarity which is
essential. Hence all are analogical by analogy of proper similarity.
In "The Concord Hymn" the poet has obviously used "stream" to stand for "time" and
"forgetfulness," since the stream has carried away the bridge that once marked the battlefield just
as time has caused us to forget the battle itself. On the other hand, he uses the "stone" to stand for
remembrance of the battle. These are analogies of similarity; but the resemblance between a
river and time, or a stone and memory is merely accidental or improper. The comparison of
"death" to "sleep," however, is an essential comparison; hence the analogy is proper. We should
notice, nevertheless, that although the former comparisons are improper analogy, this does not
mean that they are poor writing. We will explain below why metaphor is very useful and artistic
in writing and speaking.
The expression "shot heard round the world" is an interesting example of analogy of connection,
and so is the use of the "bridge" as a symbol of the battle, and the "flag" as a symbol of the army.
"The shot" is not similar to the battle, but only connected with it as one of its incidents. The
"bridge" is not similar to the battle, but only connected with it as the place on which it occurred.
The "flag" is not similar to the army, but only something used by it. Yet all of these have
connection with the thing they stand for.
The "Gettysburg Address" contains an analogy of proper similarity which runs throughout the
entire speech, since Lincoln keeps comparing the conception, birth, struggle, and rebirth of our
nation to that of a child. There really is an essential similarity between the birth and growth of an
individual and that of the whole society.
In our selections it is not easy to find an example of pure equivocation, because good authors
avoid purely equivocal expressions. A careless reader of the "Gettysburg Address," however,
might think that Lincoln said "Four score and seven years ago our fathers brought fourth on this
continent a new nation." "Forth" and "fourth" have the same sound, but utterly different and
unconnected meanings. Or this poor reader might mix up the meanings of "vain" in the last
paragraph with those of the word "vane," or "perish" with "parish."
5. The connotations of words. Sometimes two words mean the same thing and are called
synonyms ("together-names"); sometimes they mean opposite things and are called antonyms
("opposite names"). Even synonyms, however, have different "shades of meaning." The things to
which any word can be applied are called its extension, because it extends to cover them all. A
word is said to denote (point out) all the things to which it extends. If it denotes only one
individual thing, it is a singular term. If it denotes many things each one of which is exactly like
the other, then it is a universal term. If it denotes some or a few of these things which are exactly
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
However, two words can have the same extension or denotation and yet have a different content
of meaning. One may tell us only a little about the things to which it extends, another very much.
This is a difference in comprehension or connotation. Words with a rich comprehension convey
a great deal of information, but are more difficult to understand. Ordinarily if a word has a rich
comprehension it has a narrow extension and can be applied to a few things only, since the more
meaning a word has, the fewer are the things which it will fit.
* * * * * *
In "The Concord Hymn" the words "flood" and "stream" are synonyms, as are "votive stone" and
"shaft." "Foe" and "conqueror" are antonyms, as are "sires" and "sons." In the "Gettysburg
Address" "dedicate," "consecrate," "hallow" are synonyms; so are "fitting" and "proper." But
"living" and "dead," "add" and "detract are antonyms.
In "The Concord Hymn:" "embattled farmers" denotes or extends to all the minutemen.
"Conqueror" extends to all the minutemen buried by the bridge; "foe" to all the English soldiers
buried there. "Farmers" is a universal term. "Flag" is a singular term. "The foe" and "the
conqueror" are collective terms since they mean the two armies each taken as a group. If
Emerson bad said that "some of the minutemen are now sleeping in death," then "some of the
minutemen" would be a particular term.
The terms "flood" and "stream" have the same denotation or extension here, but their connotation
or shade of meaning is not the same. "Flood" makes us think of the river as filling its banks,
while "stream" only suggests that it is flowing. The connotations of "dedicate," "consecrate,"
"hallow" in the "Gettysburg Address" are quite different: "dedicate" indicates only that the
battlefield is set aside as a memorial; "consecrate" adds the idea that it is to be used only for this
purpose; "hallow" brings out the fact that it is to be a holy place, worthy of deepest veneration.
A thesaurus is a collection of synonyms, antonyms, and other related words. The most standard
work of this sort is Roget's Thesaurus, but there are many other similar works. Such a work helps
us to discover all the different possible words ,which the language contains to express similar
ideas. By using it we can discover the word which best suits our purpose.
In using words we are always aiming at two goals: clearness and vividness. It is not easy to
achieve both these goals at the same time, because clear words are often very abstract, while
vivid words must be concrete. Clarity comes from the use of exact or technical terms and these
we will consider in the last section of this chapter. Vividness is achieved by using words which
are concrete, rich in connotation and imagery, and pleasant to the ear. Poetry especially requires
this sort of vivid language. Readers often complain that poetry is not clear. This is because the
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
One of the most useful ways to increase the vividness of language is to use words with unusual
meanings, because this attracts the bearer's attention and makes him search his imagination.
These special uses of words are called figures of speech, generally involving some type of
analogy.
The most important figure of speech is the one based on an analogy of similarity (see pages 49-
51), known as metaphor.*
* The term metaphor in Greek simply means "transferred"; hence it was used by Aristotle and is still used by some
authors to mean any figure of speech.
Sometimes this is reversed, so to speak, by using a term which is just the opposite of what we
mean, or which contrasts what we actually say with what is expected. This is called irony. When
a metaphor is made very explicit by using such words of comparison is "like" or "as" it is called
a simile. Sometimes it is not merely a word which is treated as having a hidden meaning, but a
thing. Then we speak of this thing as a symbol or type, as Moses who led his people out of
slavery was a historical symbol or type of our Lord who leads us out of sin.
Besides these figures based on the analogy of similarity there are others based on the analogy of
connection (see pages 49-51). These are called metonymy, or the transference of a word from its
original meaning to something connected with it in some way other than by similarity or
dissimilarity. The most important type of metonymy is called synecdoche, the transferring of the
name of a part to the whole, or of the whole to a part. Sometimes this is done by substituting the
name of a class for a member of the class (genus for species), or vice versa.
There are many other figures of speech based on these two types, but since most of them involve
not only words but sentences and whole compositions, we will treat them in later chapters.
Not only do figures of speech and the choice of words with rich connotations and striking sounds
make language more vivid, but they also produce an emotional effect. This is important in
poetry, but most especially in rhetoric. Juliet argued that "A rose by any other name would smell
as sweet," but nevertheless we are very much affected in our attitudes by the names we give
things. Some suggest the ideal, or the lovable, while others suggest something hateful or
disgusting. In using words we have to consider the audience to whom we are speaking, and
observe its reaction to particular words.
When we use slang or newly invented words, we can often get very vivid effects; but it suggests
to those to whom we speak that we are very young, impressionable, imitative. If we use less
formal or colloquial language we give the impression that we are being friendly and easy-going.
When, however, the occasion demands that we be formal and serious, we must be careful to use
only formally correct language; otherwise people will think that we have no respect for them or
that we are ignorant of good manners. The dictionary usually indicates whether a word is slang,
colloquial, or formally correct.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The great rule in choosing words is to use words which are appropriate to the audience, and as
simple and clear as possible, and yet the composition should be spiced with a few well-selected
figures of speech or less common words to give vividness.
In "The Concord Hymn" the bridge is a symbol of the battle that once took place there and of the
forgetfulness of the people, since it has fallen into ruins and been swept away. The river is the
symbol of time since it destroys the bridge, that is, the memory of the battle. The sea is the
symbol of the past and of total oblivion. On the other hand, the memorial stone is a symbol of
renewed memory. River as used in the poem is a metaphor based on the similarity of the things
compared. A river is like time, because it is perpetually flowing. The bridge is used by
metonymy, since the bridge is not similar to the battle for which it stands, but is merely
connected with it. "The shot heard round the world" stands for the whole battle of which it was
merely the first part; hence this expression is an example of synecdoche. Irony is seen
throughout the poem in the contrast between the glorious deed of the minutemen and the
forgetfulness of their descendants, in the struggle between the two armies and their quiet sleep in
death side by side, alike forgotten, and finally in the fact that soldiers must "die and leave their
children free." In each case the truth is brought out by contrast to its opposite. The poem contains
no explicit similes.
The "Gettysburg Address" also contains no similes. Nor do we find in it any use of metonymy
or synecdoche, although there is something of these in the way in which Lincoln uses the
battlefield to symbolize the battle itself (metonymy) and this single battle to stand for the whole
war (synecdoche). A beautiful metaphor, however, runs throughout the entire speech. Lincoln
compares our nation to a child which was "conceived in liberty," "brought forth" "four score and
seven years ago, " and "dedicated to liberty." It has almost died in the course of the civil struggle,
but is now to have "a new birth of freedom." Irony is found in the contrast between the littleness
of human speech and the greatness of the soldiers' sacrifice, and in the contrast (as in "The
Concord Hymn") between the soldiers' death and the new life given to their country.
USING DESCRIPTIONS
The choice of the right word or phrase, however, is often not sufficient to make our terms really
understood. To make them clear we must define them; that is, replace the name of the thing by an
explanation of it. Such an explanation gives the full comprehension and connotation of the name.
It also gives us its extension by showing exactly to which things the name can be applied.
The simplest way of defining is by a description, and this is the method commonly used in poetic
and rhetorical writing. The description must fit the thing defined and distinguish it from anything
else, that is, it must have the right extension. It should also bring the thing defined vividly before
the imagination if it is to be used for poetry or rhetoric. This is accomplished by selecting the
details which are most characteristic and unusual, and by taking care to appeal to all the senses.
Thus in describing a man we must pick out those features which are most unique and interesting,
and we must mention not only his appearance, but his gestures, his clothing, the sound of his
voice, perhaps even his smell.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
If we remember the categories they will assist us in describing well. We should explain the
nature of a substance by telling what it does or undergoes (action and reception). These actions
must be in a place and a time, and will produce some quality or quantity, some position or
vestition in the substance, and will result in its having certain relations to other things. Thus in
describing a man we should tell how he behaves and when and where, and how this gives him
certain qualities and a certain size, position, and habit of dress, and certain relations with other
people and things. Frequently in writing we make the mistake of describing only the qualities of
a thing by the use of many adjectives, when a careful use of the other parts of speech, especially
of verbs, would give a much livelier picture.
Vivid speech and writing depend largely on the power to present the subject being discussed and
what is being said about it (the two main terms) by striking descriptions. The careful selection of
words and the use of figures of speech are the main tools in giving such descriptions.
* * * * * *
"The Concord Hymn" does not describe its main terms in an obvious way. Nevertheless,
Emerson presents them in a deeply moving manner. We see the "bridge" which is characterized
by two words: it is "arched" over the flowing river, and it is "rude." It stands for the battle that
takes place there. Then the battle is presented to us by the picture of the "flag" flying in the
spring breeze, and suddenly in this cheerful and simple scene we hear the first crack of gunfire,
and its echo, "the shot heard round the world."
All these details describe for us the subject of the poem, the patriotism of the minutemen.
Emerson leaves us to fill in the details for ourselves, having given us very sharply the outline of
the description.
The second idea of the poem is that patriotism should be honored. This notion of honor Emerson
presents to us first by ironical contrast. He pictures the bridge, symbol of heroism, falling into
ruins and being swept away by the dark stream down to the sea of utter forgetfulness. Here
symbol and metaphor are used to picture the reverse or opposite of honor, namely forgetfulness
and ingratitude. Then he pictures honor as the memorial stone set on the green bank, but at once
indicates that the real memorial can only be the determination of future generations to imitate the
minutemen by being true patriots themselves.
Lincoln also avoids obvious description in the "Gettysburg Address" because he aims at lifting
the minds of his audience to a lofty spiritual ideal. He defines "patriotism" by his solemn
references to the dead and to their total sacrifice. He then defines "honor" by using the metaphor
of the "rebirth of the nation," showing that the greatest glory of patriotism is that it produces a
new life for the fatherland.
In The Last Lesson Daudet avoids any detailed description so as not to overload his very brief
and simple story; yet he is very careful to give us enough detail to make clear to us the main
terms. Patriotism is embodied in this story in the form of the schoolmaster. Daudet tells us what
the schoolmaster is like, not by describing his appearance, but by picturing his actions and
attitudes. The height of this description comes in the paragraph which reads:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
From time to time, when I raised my eyes from the paper, I saw Monsieur Hamel sitting
motionless in his chair and staring at the objects about him as if he wished to carry away in his
glance the whole of his little schoolhouse. Think of it! For forty years he had been there in the
same place, with his yard in front of him and his class just as it was! But the benches and desks
were polished and rubbed by use; the walnuts in the yard had grown, and the hop-vine which he
himself had planted now festooned the window even to the roof. What a heart-break it must have
been for that poor man to leave all those things, and to hear his sister walking back and forth in
the room overhead, packing their trunks!
It will be noticed that time is used in the description in a beautiful way to show us the deep,
loving attachment a man has to his home. This makes clearer to us the true meaning of patriotism
than a great deal of talk could do.
The honor due to patriotism is defined for us in the boy who gradually comes to see something
great and honorable in his teacher which he had never before appreciated. It is by the change that
takes place in the boy's attitude, shown in his reception of the schoolmaster's action, that we
come to appreciate the worth of what the teacher stands for.
A careful reading of The Last Lesson will show that while Daudet uses very little visual
description, he makes a special use of sound. The whistle of the blackbird in the first paragraph
and the suggestion of the sound of the sawmill bring before us the loveliness of the country. In
contrast to them is the sound of the soldiers drilling in the field. The same contrast is repeated at
the end in the sound of the Angelus contrasted to the sound of the Prussian bugles. Daudet
obviously intends the sounds of the country and of the church to symbolize the traditional life of
the village, while the sound of the army symbolizes its destruction. This theme is also found in
the middle of the story, where the boy bears the cooing of the pigeons and wonders if they too
must learn to speak German! There are other sounds such as the insect wandering into the room,
the sound of the little students singing "ba, be, bi, bo, bu." Each of these sounds has a special
emotional effect in the story. Can you explain the function of each?
DEFINITIONS
These definitions summarize everything that has been discussed in this chapter. If you memorize
them, understand their meaning, and use them in your reading and writing you have thoroughly
mastered this chapter.
It is suggested that a grammar handbook or workbook be used (such as John Warriner and
Francis Griffith's English Grammar and Composition, A Complete Handbook, or John E.
Warriner and Joseph C. Blumenthal's English Workshop, New Series, Grade Nine; both
published by Harcourt, Brace & Company) and one of the standard anthologies of literature. One
main objective of the year, however, should be to read poetic arguments in complete books other
than the anthology. The work of the year might conveniently be divided into the following units:
Introduction:
Read and discuss "The Story of the Liberal Arts" in home-room period or Christian Doctrine
class as an orientation to the whole work of the high school. See discussion topics at the end of
that chapter.
Unit I: Analyzing stories.
A. Reading:
Study the rules of analysis given in this book and apply to a number of short
stories and poems contained in the anthology. Stress the exercise of trying to state
the plot in a single sentence and insist that in all analyses the student show how
the other elements contribute to this one central idea.
B. Writing:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
At least one short writing assignment should be given weekly. Subjects like the
following are suggested:
conscious of the same connotations given them by their origin? Does he use these
connotations? (See E. C. C., Chap. 20-23.)
B. Grammar:
The parts of speech should be reviewed (E. W., See. 1-3; E. G. C., Part 1, Sec. 1-
3), after studying dictionary examples of words which can very well be used as
several parts of speech, and discriminating among the meanings of each. The
students should give the conventional definitions of the parts of speech; then the
teacher should explain these logically in terms of the categories (pp. 44 to 47).
C. Writing:
The student should rewrite some of the assignments previously written, trying to
improve the vocabulary, sound, quality, and grammatical variety of his
composition. There should be exercises in trying to write the same ideas. It should
be emphasized that the purpose of knowing grammar is not merely to ensure
"correct speech," but mainly to provide a variety of methods of expressing our
ideas so that they will be more clear or more vivid.
D. Speaking:
Some of the stories or poems analyzed should be read aloud (perhaps
memorized). The student should see how well he can bring out the sound effects
intended by the author: the onomatopoeia, the rhythm, the melody, and the
emotional expression of the characters. Proper vocal production and breathing
may be discussed and illustrated.
Unit 3: Using the dictionary: word meanings, figures of speech.
A. Reading:
The major literary selection for the year (perhaps The Merchant of Venice) should
be read and analyzed, using principles studied in Unit 1. Special attention should
be given to word meaning, imagery and figures of speech. The theory given on
pages 49-58 and the examples on pages 424-427 should be studied in preparation
for this. (See E. G. C., Chap. 1.)
B. Writing:
Assignments like the following are suggested to give practice in using the
techniques studied in poetry:
1. Write in rhyme the names of classmates that fit a certain rhythm.
2. In about four lines of verse describe one character of a story:
a. Using the rhyme and rhythm of a poem studied.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
C. Grammar:
The teacher should insist on the value of grammar in interpreting difficult
passages in reading, for example, in Shakespeare. Continue with the study and
application of topics previously suggested, including others as need arises. (Cf. E.
G. C., Part VIII; E. W., Sec. 6 and 7.)
D. Speaking:
Vocal interpretations of passages from the work should be given.
Unit 4: Description
A. Reading:
Anthology selections in which description is well used should be read, along with
theory on pages 56-58 and examples on pages 520 ff. (See also Cleanth Brooths
and B. P. Warren, Fundamentals of Good Writing [formerly Modern Rhetoric],
Harcourt, Brace and Company, Chap. 5.)
B. Writing:
Short essays on topics like the following are suggested:
1. The Most Interesting Person I Have Ever Met.
2. The Most Interesting Place I Have Ever Seen.
3. Students should attempt to imitate the technique of some particular author in
some definitely assigned details.
4. Two descriptions of the same person or thing, trying in one of them to make it
attractive, in the other repulsive.
C. Grammar:
The agreement of subject and verb, pronouns, antecedents, irregular verbs (E. W.,
Sec. 8 to 10; E. G. C., Part II, Sec. 6 to 8). The teacher should review these
matters to correct errors in the foregoing compositions.
D. Speaking:
The year may end with a series of oral book reports of similar or contrasted
works compared to the major work studied during the year. The speaker should
make an explicit comparison of work studied in class with one which he has read
privately. He should build his report around a statement of the plot and the means
used by the author to present that plot.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
CHAPTER II
Dialectics and Rhetoric:
Arts of Discussion and Persuasion
DIALECTICS
THE ART OF CONVERSATION
Conversations become interesting only when there is something to share, and this usually means
that there is some difference of opinion about the topic of conversation. Some people are afraid
of differences of opinion. They say "never talk about politics or religion," because they think that
every difference of opinion is impolite and will lead to a quarrel. Yet it is only when there is
some contest of minds about a topic important enough for people to have definite opinions that a
conversation can become lively. A baseball game where there was only one side would not be
much of a game.
But just as in a sport contest the player must learn how to play hard to win without breaking the
rules of the game or losing control of his temper, so in conversation we need to learn the art of
courteous debate. The art of storytelling is called poetics. The art of conversation, discussion,
debate, and inquiry is called dialectics (from the Greek for "through" and "speak," that is a
"talking through" or discussion of a problem).
It is not only in friendly recreation that discussion and the contest of opinions is important.
Today almost all organizations are run by policy-making boards. In business, in government, in
the army, in clubs, the important decisions are not made by a single man, but by boards of
officials. They meet to exchange and discuss ideas, in order that the final decision may embody
the experience and wisdom of all. Such discussion can be a way of avoiding responsibility,
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
however, if those who engage in them do not discuss with the purpose of coming to a genuine
agreement, and if they do not know the art of good discussion.
The man or woman who knows how to discuss well can be very powerful in such organizations.
It is well known that the influence which some Communists have had in American life was
largely due to their ability to influence other through skillful discussion at public meetings.
Catholics and others who stand for basic principles can also have great influence for good if they
know how to discuss intelligently and effectively.
Sometimes such discussions are held publicly before an audience and are called debates or
forums. The meetings of legislative bodies, like the Congress and Senate of the United States, are
occupied with such debates. In order that such meetings should be carried out in an orderly
fashion, the rules of parliamentary procedure, first developed in the British parliament, are
usually followed.
For all discussions and debates there are three informal rules which ought always to be followed:
1. Try to come to an agreement. There is no use discussing a problem if there is no
possibility of agreement. If you keep this goal before you, you will try hard not to lose your
temper, nor use harsh, cutting words, since these make agreement more difficult.
2. Listen to the other side. You do not know if you agree or disagree with another until you
know what he thinks. Unless you know what he thinks and why he thinks it, you cannot change
his mind. Many people make the mistake of thinking only of what they are going to say next
while the other person is talking. Consequently they do not hear what he says, and do not really
reply to it. If you do not clearly understand what the other person is saying, then question him
until you are sure. Questioning is a very important part of every discussion.
3. Give your reasons for what you think. Too often persons in a discussion keep making
statements over and over again, without ever giving any proof for what they say.
It is this last rule which requires a good deal of study, and which is the key to all effective
discussion and debate. In order to know how to apply it, we must first consider the nature of a
statement, since every discussion consists in making and defending statements of our opinions.
1. What we are talking, about. This is called the subject, because it is the subject under
discussion.
2. What we say about it. This is called the predicate (from, Latin for "about" and "say").
3. The copula, that is the linking word ( copula in Latin means a coupling or joining) which is
either is or is not (see page 161).
Thus if the subject under discussion is women, we may make either the statement "Women are
logical," or "Women are not logical." These two statements have the same subject and predicate,
but the former is an affirmative statement, while the latter is a negative statement. They are made
out of the same material, but they are said to be different in quality.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Why are these three parts the essential parts of any statement? The subject is like the clay used
in a statue; it is a thing which we know in a rather vague and indefinite way. The predicate is a
modifier or form by which we mold the subject and make it more clear and definite in our mind.
This form or mold has to be actually applied to the subject, as a mold must be pressed into the
clay to give it form. The copula signifies this act of the mind by which it actually applies the
predicate to the subject. The copula makes the predicate dynamic, so that a statement is not just
two ideas hooked together, but a single truth in which one idea (the predicate) forms the other
(the subject), just as the figure of a statue gives shape to the clay and produces a single work of
art. If the statement is negative, then the negative copula indicates that the mold will not cut or fit
the material to which we are trying to apply it; the predicate does not fit the subject.
In a debate each side affirms or denies some basic statement, but this statement may also be
either universal or particular, that is, it may affirm or deny a predicate of an entire class of things,
or only of some members of that class. Thus we might argue whether "Every woman is
illogical," or "Some women are illogical." This difference in statements is called a difference in
their quantity. The combination of different qualities and quantities of statements give us four
possible types of statements:*
*Do not confuse this use of "quality" and "quantity" of statements with the categories of quality and quantity (page
46) which are accidents of real things. This is an example of an analogical use of terms.
1. A universal affirmative statement; for example: "Every woman is illogical."
2. A universal negative statement; for example: "No woman is illogical."
3. A particular affirmative statement; for example: "Some women are illogical."
4. A particular negative statement; for example: "Some women are not illogical."
You will notice that it is the copula (not the predicate) which makes a statement negative. Thus
the statement "Every woman is illogical" is affirmative, although the predicate "illogical"
contains a negative idea. Also you will notice that in English we have a rather peculiar way of
expressing the universal negative statement. One would think that it should be "Every woman is
not illogical," but in English this last sentence really means, "Some woman at least is not
illogical," which is a particular statement. Sometimes universal statements are written as " all
women are illogical." This is also correct, but not as clear as "Every woman is illogical," since a
universal statement does not mean that the predicate belongs to the subject taken as a collection,
but that it belongs to each and every member of the class.
DISAGREEMENT
This classification of four basic forms of statements is useful in debate and discussion because it
helps us see just bow strong the disagreement is between two sides of a question.
1. If one side makes a universal affirmative statement, and the other side wishes to disagree
completely, it should make a particular negative statement using the same subject and predicate.
Thus the complete denial of the statement that "Every woman is illogical" is the statement that
"Some women are not illogical" (not that "No woman is illogical"). Such a complete denial is
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
called a contradiction. When two sides take contradictory positions, one must be right, and the
other wrong. It is not possible for both to be right, or both to be wrong.
3. If one side asserts the universal affirmative and the other the universal negative, then their
disagreement is not complete, because although both cannot be right, both may be wrong. Thus it
is possible that both the statement "Every woman is illogical," and "No woman is illogical" are
false, because it may be true that "Some women are illogical and some are not." Such a
disagreement is not a contradiction, but is between contrary statements. In debating we should
try to avoid arranging the two sides in this way, since the audience may very well conclude,
"Why, neither side should win; both are wrong." Similarly a particular affirmative and a
particular negative position do not make a clear disagreement, since both sides may be right or
wrong. These are called sub-contraries.
4. In arguing we may always go from the universal to the particular of the same quality, but
we cannot go in the other direction. For example, if I can prove that "Every woman is illogical," I
have also proved that "Some woman is illogical." Or if I have proved that "No woman is
illogical," then I have also proved that "Some woman is not illogical." But from the fact that
"Some woman is illogical," it is not certain that "Every woman is illogical"; nor from the fact
that "Some woman is not illogical" does it follow that "No woman is illogical." Such statements
are called subalternates, and are a source of a great deal of confusion in discussion and the
cause of many pointless arguments. How often we hear someone argue, "Every Catholic is
dishonest, because Mr. Kelly who is a Catholic is dishonest," or "Every Negro is dirty, because
the Jones' who are Negroes are dirty," or "No Englishman has a sense of humor, because the
Englishmen I have known have had no sense of humor," This is often called illegitimate
generalization.
Hence we should try if possible in a debate to state the problem so that the two sides are
contradictory, so that one side must be right and the other wrong. Furthermore we should notice
that the side which defends the universal statement is the more difficult, since the other side has
only to prove a particular statement in order to win. Thus if one side argues either that "Every
woman is illogical," or that "No woman is illogical," the other side can defeat them if they can
prove a single exception to this statement-if they can point to a single woman who is not
illogical, or a single woman who is illogical. Hence a clever debater prefers to take the particular,
rather than the universal side of the argument. Some debaters, however, make the mistake of
trying to prove too much. They try to disprove a universal statement, not by proving its
contradictory (which is particular), but by trying to prove its contrary (which is universal). This
is much harder to do, and is unnecessary.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
THE SYLLOGISM
Reasons for Basic Statements
We have seen that the chief task of every speaker in a discussion is not only to make statements,
or to contradict the statements of others, but to give reasons to back up his statements. This is
true not only in dialectics, but in every form of writing or speaking, and especially in scientific
writing. Man is a reasonable being, and be is not satisfied to accept a statement without reasons
for it. It is not enough merely to claim that a statement is true, or to repeat this loudly, for it to be
accepted. It is an old rule of discussion that "What is asserted without a reason, can be denied
without a reason." Hence if we are to be sure that a statement is true, we must know the reason
for it.
When we know that a statement is true immediately from our experience it is said to be an
immediate truth or principle. Thus the following statements are seen to be true as soon as we
understand what the words mean and compare them with our experience:
1. The whole is greater than the part.
2. Every effect has a cause.
3. If equals be added to equals the sums are equal.
But other truths are not known to us merely by knowing the subject and the predicate. We must
see that the subject and predicate are connected through a third or middle term, which gives us
the reason why the predicate is connected to the subject. We can write these in parallel columns:
When a statement is said to be true through a middle term, it is said to be demonstrated (from
Latin for "pointed out," because we point out the reason why it is true). It may be written in the
form of parallel columns as above, or merely as a causal statement; for example, "A fish has fins
because it lives by swimming." However, if we wish to make it perfectly clear and explicit we
put it in the form of a syllogism (Latin for a "linking together of words or ideas"); the syllogism
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
points out that this truth in fact depends on two other truths which show that the middle term is
the link between subject and predicate.
M P
1. An animal which eats things
hard to digest, e.g., grass. is one which has many stomachs.
S M
And a cow is an animal which eats things
hard to digest, e.g., grass.
S P
Therefore, a cow is an animal which has many
stomachs.
M P
2. People exposed to X-rays
which injure the bone-marrow
which makes blood are often anemic
S M
And X-ray technicians are people exposed to X-rays
which injure the bone-marrow.
which makes blood.
S P
Therefore, X-ray technicians are often anemic.
M P
3. An animal which has the in-
telligence to see what is
laughable is the only animal which
laughs.
S M
Man is the only animal which has
the
intelligence to see what is
laughable.
S P
Therefore, man is the only animal which
laughs.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
M P
4. Heart-stimulants are frequently able to
revive persons
in a state of shock.
S M
adrenalin is a heart-stimulant.
S P
Therefore, adrenalin is frequently able to revive
persons
in a state of shock.
In the foregoing syllogisms you will notice that the terms are arranged in the following pattern:
Every M is P
And : every S is M
Therefore : every S is P.
There are other forms of the syllogism but this is the most common and the most useful. In it
there are two statements called premises (Latin for "something put first"), in both of which is
found the middle term ( M ), and a conclusion which does not contain the middle term. Of these
premises the one which contains the predicate of the conclusion ( P) is called the major
premise, and is often (but not always) written first. The other premise contains the subject ( S )
of the conclusion and is called the minor premise.
When we wish to form a syllogistic argument (for example, in geometry) we should first ask
ourselves: What am I trying to prove? This will be the conclusion of the syllogism (thesis, or
theorem). Write down the conclusion and mark the subject ( S ) and predicate ( P ). Then place P
as the predicate of a major premise and S as the subject of a minor premise, leaving the place of
the middle term ( M ) blank. For example a biologist might wish to show that "The valves in the
arteries are ones made to face away from the heart." He could then write this in the following
skeleton demonstration:
M P
S M
And: the valves in the arteries are
........................................
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
S P
Therefore; the valves in the
arteries are valves made to face
away from the heart.
His problem is now clearly stated. He needs to find a middle term ( M ) which can be used to
complete these two premises so that both will be true. After thought and investigation he may
find this middle term or cause, and get the following syllogism:
The following is an example from algebra. Suppose that we wish to prove that a = b. We can
write this as the following skeleton syllogism:
x = b
And: a = x
Therefore: a = b
Our problem then is to find an x which will fit in the two first equations, namely, to find some
quantity which we know to be equal both to a and to b. Similarly, in geometry we begin with the
theorem to be proved and then try to discover something which we know to be equal both to the
subject and the predicate of the theorem. Thus in the example on page 566 we prove that vertical
and opposite angles are equal by recognizing that these angles are the remainders of equals
minus equals, which is our middle term.
Ordinarily it is sufficient in our thinking to use the method of parallel columns, or causal
statements given above, but these are only abbreviations for the syllogism, which states
explicitly why we know the conclusion is true. In the next chapter we will show why the
syllogism is the basic form of all reasoning.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
It is obvious that truths known by reasoning are based on premises, but these premises are either
demonstrated themselves (and this merely moves us back another step), or they are immediately
evident. Thus all our thinking rests on a foundation made of immediately evident truths which
are rooted in experience.
Sometimes the experience on which an immediate truth is based is our own personal experience,
and then the truth is said to be evident. Sometimes it is based, not on our own experience, but on
that of someone else whom we know to be trustworthy, and then the truth is said to be known by
faith, or on authority. If we know from our own experience that this person is really trustworthy,
then our faith is reasonable. If we do not know this, then our faith is foolish or credulous. When
we know that a person is truthful we ought to believe what lie says, even if it may seem very
surprising and outside our own experience. Some people refuse to believe anything they have not
seen for themselves, but this is unreasonable and would greatly limit our knowledge. Only if we
take the word of reliable experts can we have a very wide knowledge, for no man can see very
many truths for himself. On the other hand, many people are quick to believe anything they hear
or read, or to suppose that any famous person must be an expert on whatever he says. The
reasonable man makes sure of his authorities before he accepts what they have to say.
In all our reading and listening we should ask ourselves whether the principles stated by the
author are really true from our own experience, or if he gives a good authority for them. If not,
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
then we should not accept these principles, nor the conclusions based on them. In writing or
speaking ourselves we should never expect others to take our word unless we back it up with
facts, or with reliable and well known authorities.
In scientific writing of the demonstrative type it is not sufficient to begin with merely probable
statements (that is, statements which seem to be true, but which possibly will turn out to be
false). Nothing certain can ever be proved from merely probable statements. For a strict
demonstration it is necessary to start with principles which are certain, and which could never be
false. Thus the principles of Euclidean geometry (the axiom, postulates, and definitions) are
certainly true, as we can test for ourselves by imagining the geometrical figures on which they
are based. Again, in history some facts are certainly true, because we have many reliable
witnesses on whose authority we can believe them, although we were not on the scene ourselves.
If someone beginning to study a work of science is not certain of the principles, then lie must go
back to the facts and make sure of these principles before lie proceeds. If a student raises doubts
about such principles the teacher can only refer him to the facts to see for himself. If he still has
doubts, then these can be answered only by the highest sciences (theology and metaphysics)
whose business it is to remove doubts and confusions about the principles of the other sciences.
Thus occasionally one reads today that the principles of geometry have been disproved, because
modern science says that there may be more than three dimensions. The student of geometry can
either make sure that there are only three dimensions to the figures used in the study of geometry
by looking at them for himself, or lie can wait until lie studies philosophy. The philosopher will
show him that it is not true that science has discovered more than three dimensions, but that this
statement is due to a confusion about the meaning of the word "dimension" in science, since this
word is used in several equivocal senses (see page 389).
In dialectics, however, probable statements are a sufficient starting point, since in discussions,
debates, or inquiries the dialectician is only exploring; lie is not yet trying to demonstrate
anything. Hence the dialectician starts with opinions (probable statements, or certain statements
which have not yet been carefully criticized). These can be opinions which almost everyone
holds, or those held by experts, or at least by the group of people with whom we are, discussing.
The dialectician, however, does not remain content with these opinions. He begins to argue them,
showing the arguments for and against them. As lie proceeds be usually revises and modifies the
opinions with which lie began, correcting them so as to make them more and more probable.
Frequently a dialectician uses an opinion in a discussion which lie himself doubts, or is even sure
is wrong, in order to test it or expose its falsity. Thus, a good dialectician knows how to suspend
judgment, to consider a question first from one side, and then from another. He knows how to
doubt systematically. Even the things of which he is sure he tests as if they could be doubted.
This makes some people uncomfortable. They like positive statements, not debates and
difficulties and doubts. In trying to arrive at the truth, or to know the truth more clearly,
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
however, we must make use of this method. On the other hand, we should not fall into the error
of always doubting everything and never coming to a positive conclusion.
The statements of the poetic writer do not have to be strictly true, but only probable. The
probability of poetry is that the story corresponds in its broad outlines to the universal experience
of human life, although the details may be entirely fictitious. Thus the story of Macbeth, who
sought to be king by murder and whose life ended in failure and despair, may have no detailed
correspondence to history; yet it is probable, because we know that it fits the general pattern of
the lives of ambitious criminals.
The details used by the poetic writers also have a kind of probability in that they form I
consistent whole that fits the general story. The more vivid and circumstantial the details of the
story the more probable and life like it appears. When stated in a mere abstract or in a factual
way it may not be very convincing, but when it seems to live before our eyes, then we are
convinced. Hence in poetic writing, merely abstract or factual statements are of little value. If
you have read Defoe's Robinson Crusoe, you know how convincing Defoe makes the story by
his use of detail. In order to bring about this probability the poetic writer must draw on his own
experience and observation, and make us aware of details of our experience on which we may
not have reflected.
Just as some people find it hard to listen to the pros and cons of dialectic, because they prefer flat
dogmatic statements of truth, so many find it hard to accept the attitude of the poetic writer. They
feel that fiction is hardly better than a lie. The dialectician is not a sceptic. He considers both
sides of a question in order to make the truth more evident. A rhetorician is not a flatterer. He
appeals to the opinions of his audience in order to find a common ground between them and
himself on which to consider the truth. The poet is not a liar. He invents a fiction, but only so
that the fundamental and universal truth which lie depicts will become vivid to us in terms of
personal experience.
Misunderstandings arise in our reading, writing, or speaking, only when we fail to see whether
the demonstrative, the dialectical, the rhetorical, or the poetic mode of speaking is the
appropriate one.
EXAMPLES
In Whether Piety is a Special Virtue? (see page 417) St. Thomas has as his thesis or conclusion
the statement: "Yes, piety is a special virtue."
He states two basic principles from which he attempts to prove this thesis:
1. "Piety pays duty and honor to parents and country and to whatever is related
to them."
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
2. "A virtue is special when it relates to some object under a special aspect."
But he does not merely state these principles dogmatically. The first he proves to
be true by showing, that we have a special debt to honor our parents and country,
because they are the "connatural principle of being and government." The second
lie does not explain in this article, because lie has already explained it earlier in
the Summa (see First Part of the Second Part, Question 60.)
In this article we also notice how St. Thomas confirms his thesis by an appeal to in authority,
namely, Cicero: "On the contrary is the statement of Cicero that [piety] is a part of justice, as lie
says in his On Invention at the end of Book II." Cicero, the great Roman orator and philosopher,
was one of the greatest experts on the philosophy of the virtues known to the Middle Ages. In
medieval writing it is usual for a writer to give all authority confirming his opinion, before lie
states and proves his own view. This does not mean that the conclusion is presented to us on
faith, since it is proved by clear reasons, but only that it is confirmed or strengthened by an
additional appeal to authority.
In answering objections we will notice how St. Thomas makes use of his knowledge of the
relations between different kinds of statements.
1. In the first objection it is argued that every act of honor and service is given to
persons because we love them; therefore piety is nothing but love. St. Thomas
answers by pointing out an exception to the principle stated. Certainly we love
God and worship him because we love him, but it has already been proved that
worship (religion) is not the same thing as love. Thus it is clear that the principle
stated by the objection is not universally true.
2. The second objection argues that every act of honor or worship is an act of the
virtue of religion; therefore piety must be the same virtue as religion. The
objection is backed up with the authority of St. Augustine. St. Thomas answers by
saying that some acts of honor and worship (namely, those given to God) are acts
of religion, but not all. Those given to our parents and country are not acts of
religion but of piety. Once again he has pointed out the exception to the too
general statement of the objector. He also backs up his answer by quoting another
authority with whom St. Augustine certainly would have agreed.
3. The third objection argues that whatever relates to the fatherland is a matter of
legal (social) justice; hence piety must be the same as legal justice. St. Thomas
again finds an exception: that some things that relate to the fatherland (namely, as
it is the common good) are a matter of legal justice he admits; but he denies that
every thing, which relates to the fatherland is a matter of legal justice, because
some things relate to it only as it is "a principle of existence." This exception
leaves room for piety to be a special virtue.
Thus St. Thomas proves his own point from solid and universal principles, and answers his
objectors by contradicting their universal statements, showing that they admit of exceptions.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Chesterton in A Defense of Patriotism is dealing not with certain principles but with common
opinions. Throughout his whole essay he takes it for granted that a man ought to love his native
land. No one in his audience would really doubt this, and so he makes no attempt to prove it.
What he wishes to refute is another opinion held by many of his audience because they have
never stopped to think about it seriously, This is the false opinion that patriotism consists in
imperialism, or a "lust of territory," the desire to take away the fatherlands of other nations. In
order to refute this view he makes use of two other opinions shared by his audience:
1. That there is a difference between lust and honorable love. Using this accepted
opinion Chesterton tries to show that there is the same difference between genuine
patriotism and imperialism as between lust and love.
2. That an Englishman is a very sensible and civilized kind of person. Chesterton
uses this to show that in mistaking imperialism for patriotism, and in bragging
about his country's military strength instead of its achievements in science, art and
philosophy, an Englishman is making a fool of himself and acting like the
ignorant savages for whom he has so much contempt.
It will be noticed that in selecting these two opinions Chesterton has a rhetorician's eye for his
audience. He knows that the English pride themselves on their sense of decency (opinion 1) and
on being a most civilized nation (opinion 2), and he shows that these opinions are inconsistent
with their imperialism. Still Chesterton is acting here more as a dialectician than a rhetorician,
since what be desires is not so much to get Englishmen here and now to vote against
imperialism, as to help them wake up and think about the basic principles on which they act. He
is trying to help them untangle their true opinions (namely, that patriotism is noble, and that
England is a great nation), from their false opinions (namely, that imperialism is noble, and that
England is great because of military power).
Notice, however, that Chesterton does not deny all truth to the other side. "Colonies are things to
be proud of, but for a country to be only proud of its extremities is like a man being only proud
of his legs." He is not saying that every colony is bad, but only that colonies are bad if they are
sought for the sake of mere military power. Chesterton's essay, however, tends to fall short of
ideal dialectic, because lie does not sufficiently bring out tile other side of the argument. It is
essentially dialectical, but with too much rhetoric thrown in.
In the works of Emerson and Lincoln it is quite easy to see that both build on the common
patriotic emotions and attitudes of their audiences. Lincoln well understood that the people to
whom he spoke were bitter about the losses and sacrifices of a war. Consequently be did not
ignore this grim feeling but rather used it. He showed them they must be "highly resolved" to see
the task which had cost so much carried through to its finish.
Emerson was not trying to persuade his audience of anything; he only wished them to share his
own insight into the experience which he depicted. He wanted them to see how glorious
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
patriotism is, but he did this by the ironic contrast between the greatness of the battle and the
forgetfulness and quiet peace of today. The probability of his poem lies in the vividness of this
contrast. On the one hand, we see vividly the great historic moment when the first shot was fired
at Concord. On the other hand, we also see vividly this quiet moment on the river bank where
nothing is left to mark the site of the battle except the traces of the graves which cover conqueror
and foe alike. Thus the greatness of patriotism as an abstract truth becomes concrete for us in this
experience of an ironic situation. For a moment we are, suddenly alive to the greatness which we
had almost forgotten.
RHETORIC
Without discussion and debate, free men cannot work together for common goals, and the
inquiry after truth is greatly hampered. Discussion alone, however, seldom leads to agreement
and decision without leadership. Even when a leader is chosen by a group, he still must get that
group to understand and carry out willingly the decisions which he proposes. Of course, as the
lawful authority accepted by the group lie may impose his decision by force when this is
necessary, but no group will long continue to accept a leader who rules by force alone. If he is to
remain a leader he must persuade his followers to accept his decision and put them into practice
willingly and intelligently.
The art of storytelling is called poetics, the art of discussion and inquiry is called dialectics, and
the art of persuasion is called rhetoric (from the Greek for a "speaker").
Poetics aims to produce stories that recreate and refresh us. Dialectics has many applications in
all phases of our life, but it is always used to prepare the way for something more decisive: it is
tentative and exploratory. Rhetoric, however, belongs to the world of practical life: it deals with
action. Nothing is more practical in daily life than this art of persuasion, since success in every
human endeavor, be it business, love, politics, or the Christian apostolate, depends on our power
to persuade others "to see things our way."
SALESMANSHIP
Every American knows that "salesmanship" is essential to business success, but salesmanship is
only one small part of the great and noble art of persuasion which includes "the art of public
speaking," "propaganda," "publicity," "advertising," "journalism," and the "apostolate." We
persuade a friend; we command a subordinate; we beg a superior; we plead with a judge or a
jury; we advertise to prospective customers, and we sell an actual customer; we encourage the
weak; we threaten the enemy; we preach the truth; we pray to God. All these varied processes of
persuasion are only parts of the one great art of rhetoric.
Today, because of the growth of "high-pressure" advertising and the "big lie" of political
propaganda, many people think that all persuasion is dishonest, and that rhetoric is the devil's art
of lying and deceiving, They forget that the greatest master of persuasion was our divine Lord
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
who is Truth itself, and that the Gospels are largely a record of his persuasive words that bad
such power to move the hearts of all kinds of men and women.
We do lot say that medicine is all evil art because there have been wicked doctors who misused
their art of healing to poison and to kill. just as the purpose of medicine itself is to heal, although
it may be misused, so the purpose of rhetoric is to persuade men to act prudently, although it may
he misused to drive them to foolish and wicked acts.
Dialectics is easily distinguished from rhetoric and poetics, because it carefully avoids all appeal
to the emotions. In good discussion or debate we should try to keep clear of emotional appeals,
because once a discussion becomes emotional it becomes inflexible. Each side begins to defend
its position at all costs without any real effort at coming to an agreement. But rhetoric and
poetics both appeal to the emotions. How then are we to distinguish rhetoric from poetics, or are
they really one and the same art?
A poetic writer (as we have seen in Chapter 1) is not immediately concerned to persuade us to do
or avoid anything, but simply to present to us a story which excites our emotions and then brings
them to rest in the enjoyment of the beautiful way in which his story of human life has been told.
To be sure, the habit of reading good literature of this sort does help us develop an appreciation
and admiration of what is noble in human life, and a disgust with whatever is base and mean, but
our immediate aim in such reading is refreshment and delight, not a moral lesson.
The rhetorician, on the other hand, is immediately concerned with persuading his audience to act,
to do or to avoid something. He hopes that at the end of his speech they will hurry away with a
look of determination to put into practice what he has urged them to do. When the coach of a
football team sees his Men run to the field of battle with grim courage, he knows that his talk to
them was a rhetorical success.
If the rhetorician is to get his audience to act lie must help the," to see that the, goal he proposes
is (1) good, (2) important, and (3) possible. No one will act unless by doing so he has real hope
of attaining something really important to him. On the other hand if the rhetorician wishes to
persuade the audience to avoid something or refrain from acting, he must show them that it is (1)
evil, (2) trivial, or (3) impossible.
To achieve this effect the rhetorician has five weapons, two of them of lesser importance, and
three of major importance:
1. His delivery of the speech -- that is, the volume and quality of his voice, his
pronunciation, and his gestures and facial expressions. It is obvious that no matter
how good the contents of a speech it will fail of its effect if the audience cannot
hear what the speaker says, or if they are irritated or bored by his mannerisms.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
2. His style of composition -- that is, the organization of his material, the structure
of his sentences, and his choice of words and figures of speech. A speaker who
expresses himself awkwardly, vaguely, obscurely cannot win his audience
without difficulty.
3. His personal character as it appears to the audience. He will be most effective
in persuading others to follow him if they are convinced that he is himself honest,
well-intentioned, and intelligent. We quickly accept the advice of a man whom we
trust, like, and admire, while we may reject the same advice if it is offered by one
whom we distrust, dislike, or despise.
4. His appeal to the emotions of his audience. A speaker will never get people to
act if they remain cold and indifferent, or if they consider his proposals in a purely
theoretical and objective way. He must move them to be concerned personally
with the problem, and to view it as involving their own pain and pleasure, their
own profit or loss.
5. His appeal to the reason of his audience. A speaker does not want to stir up a
mob of people who blindly follow their emotions. He wants them to have a
reasoned and sane conviction that what lie asks them to do is the practical and
moral thing to do.
Of these five instruments the first two are often the most stressed in classes in public-speaking or
books written about this art, but they are less important than the remaining three, which are often
neglected. Although a good speech is much improved by excellent style and delivery, its effect
will not be totally destroyed by a lack of good style or faulty delivery unless these are extremely
bad. On the other hand, no matter how excellent a speaker's style or delivery may be, he will not
get us to follow him if we dislike him or doubt his reasoning. Ultimately we are persuaded to
take a speaker's advice only because we trust him personally, or because his reasons really move
us and convince us that what he proposes will be profitable for us. Indeed, we might include both
delivery and style as parts of the impression made by the character of the speaker, since it is to
this that they chiefly contribute, although they also serve to enhance the appeal to the emotions
and reason of the audience.
Delivery is better learned by direct guidance than from a book, so that it will not be treated here.
Style is required both in poetic and rhetorical writing and is discussed in Chapter I, and partly in
a later section of this present chapter.
Since the most important instruments of the rhetorician are his character, his appeal to emotion,
and his appeal to reason, he must give much thought and study to using these well. Above all he
must remember that he is assuming the position of a leader, and hence be must show himself to
his audience in the best possible light as likeable and admirable. He cannot do this unless he well
understands what his audience likes and dislikes, and what true arguments appear to them, and
what would be very hard for them to understand or accept. Hence he must understand both the
obvious and the hidden motives of human behaviour. The poetic writer studies the characters
about whom he writes; the rhetorician studies the characters to whom he writes or speaks.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Before writing a speech the rhetorician must ask himself: "What is my audience like? What kind
of people do they trust and admire? What are the things in life which they value or fear? What
rules of conduct do they really respect and follow? What kind of experience guides them in
deciding practical questions?" He must ask himself what the members of a given audience have
in common. Are they united by their virtue and ideals (for example, an audience of priests, of
sisters, doctors, lawyers, or experts of some sort), or by their riches (an audience of
businessmen), or their poverty (a crowd in the street)? He must also consider their nationality,
religion, and education, and whether they are young, middle-aged, or old.
In order to sway all these classes of people the rhetorician concerns himself with arousing love
and hate, anger and benevolence, fear, shame, kindness, pity, or envy. He does not do this,
however, in order to make men act from blind emotion like animals. The propagandist or the
leader of a lynch-mob who whips his audience into a blind frenzy of hate and fear is misusing
rhetoric in a diabolic way. The genuine rhetorician appeals to men's emotions to lead them to
truth and to a more reasonable way of acting. He appeals to what is best in his audience, and he
studies selfish and evil emotions, not in order to produce them, but in order to prevent them from
interfering with right action.
If the rhetorician is to move men to do what is right, he must not merely advertise any product he
is hired to sell, promote any program adopted by his political party, or defend any criminal who
hires him as a lawyer, He must know ethics, or the art of good human living, so that be knows
what is truly virtuous and honorable, and he must have a thoughtful acquaintance with politics
and practical affairs.
EXAMPLE
If we examine the Gettysburg Address , we notice first of all that Lincoln was acutely sensitive
to the attitudes of his audience, and took care to establish his true character with them, because
be realized that the character of the speaker is the first great instrument of rhetoric. Lincoln knew
that his audience at Gettysburg battlefield was doubtful whether be was anything more than a
cheap politician. They rather expected him to make an awkward and tasteless speech defending
himself and his much-criticized administration of the war. They were contrasting him
unfavorably to the polished orator Edward Everett who had just spoken so well and at great
length.*
* See the account of the delivery of the Gettysburg Address in Carl Sandburg's Lincoln.
Consequently Lincoln first of all aimed at giving the impression of great dignity and sincerity.
He showed himself not as a cheap politician but as a great statesman, far above all mere
partisanship, a man who had no desire whatsoever merely to make an impression. He was
simple, solemn, deeply moved. He appeared to them as a man who had eyes only for the future
of his country. This impression (which was a true one) was conveyed by the whole tone of the
speech, It was simple, brief, but sublime in its concentration on the single theme of dedication.
Next we notice the reasons which lie used to persuade his audience. He wished them to agree
with his own view that they should continue the war for democracy. This was the central thought
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
and purpose of his speech. Why should they continue the war? Because this was the best way to
honor the dead.
MASS MEDIA
At one time the most typical work of the art of rhetoric was a formal speech or oration to be
delivered to a limited audience. Today formal oratory seems to play only a small role in public
life. Its place has been taken by what are called "the mass media of communication," which
reach audiences of millions. Every citizen is strongly influenced by these "mass media," and if a
man as a public leader is to influence others he must understand the power and the use of these
new instruments of persuasion.
A detailed study of the mass media of communication pertains to the social sciences, because
these media have originated in the special circumstances of modern society, and their effects
cannot be evaluated without a study of social facts. New as some of these media may be,
however, the principles that underlie their power are the same principles of the liberal arts which
we are studying. indeed, these novel instruments of persuasion are only an extension and
development of time-honored methods. Consequently we will very briefly point out some of the
ways in which our study of the liberal arts can assist us in judging and using the mass media.
The Newspaper
The oldest of these mass media is the newspaper, Nothing is more widely read (except perhaps
the billboards), and yet it is a fact that many people do not read the newspaper at all, or confine
their attention to the comics and the sport-page. When we open a newspaper, the first question
that ought to occur to us is this: What is the newspaper's purpose? Is it a source of information?
Is it intended to persuade us to do something? Is it entertainment? Or is it all these things?
If we begin to compare newspapers we will see at once that there are a few which obviously aim
at giving their readers a great deal of information. If the student compares the New York Times
with most newspapers, he will immediately see that the Times gives much fuller reports of
almost every item of news than do most newspapers. It prints many speeches and documents in
full, and it emphasizes foreign news, political news, economic news, and other areas which are
important but not always very "interesting." The average reader would find the Times rather dull,
and he would find it hard to wade through so much factual material.
At the other extreme a student should examine the sort of newspaper that aims at "reader
interest." He will find the stories short, the headlines startling, the emphasis centered on
personalities and striking events. It is typical of such a paper to try to develop a day-to-day
interest in some currently sensational story. This it works to the limit, and then discards in favor
of some new theme. Clearly, such papers aim more at entertainment than at information. The art
of storytelling dominates them, although it is an art usually badly abused and cheapened.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The strictly persuasive or rhetorical aim is not very evident in our papers. It is supposed to be
confined to the editorial page (not read by most people) and to signed articles by "news
analysts." Yet if we begin to compare papers we will see that actually a rhetorical note pervades
a great deal of the material. Certain policies or groups favored by, the newspaper owners color
the book reviews, the theater news, some comic-strips, and the news reporting itself. By its
selection of topics to emphasize, its manner of reporting the facts, and the sort of reporters and
feature writers that it hires and develops, a newspaper presents an organized view of the world
which can be powerfully persuasive.
We must learn how to read a newspaper well. We should take two papers of widely different
types and read each through. Few people have tried even skimming a paper all the way through,
but we should have this experience at least once, in order to become really aware of what a paper
contains. We should compare the different uses of the same news services, and how the make-up
and style are typical of each paper.
The most important thing is to try to figure out the intention of the editor and his estimate of his
audience. What sort of person does be think you are? What is he trying to make you into? Ask
yourself if you want to be the kind of person the editor thinks you are or wishes to make you.
When we face that question it becomes rather obvious that a truly free man or woman who
wishes to live a genuinely liberal life cannot depend on the newspapers as his chief source of
information. The man whose mind is formed by the newspapers is a slave. Yet a good newspaper
contains many features and many bits of information that can be highly useful to the man who
reads critically.
Advertising
Today advertising appears in all the mass media. Not only is it the common element in them all,
but it is the source of financing for all, or almost all. Advertising is produced by companies who
spend great sums for research on human psychology, and who are always experimenting with
new techniques of persuasion.
The fundamental fact about advertising which makes it different from other kinds of rhetoric is
that its purpose can hardly be concealed. For this reason people are generally skeptical of
advertising claims, and in consequence advertising cannot depend on actually convincing the
public. Rather it works on the fact that the purchasing public today is faced with a large number
of choices and must choose between products which seem very similar and concerning which it
knows very little. In such a dilemma the purchaser is likely to be swayed by the most vague and
tenuous motives. The fact that be happens to remember the name of the brand, or he half-
consciously associates it with some pleasant or attractive idea, or that its package strikes his eye -
- these factors, or one of them, may be decisive in his confused deliberations. If there are 25
brands of breakfast cereal to choose from, all very much alike, the purchaser can hardly help but
be influenced by some such motive that advertising can control.
This means that in reading advertisements we ought to develop two habits: (1) The habit of
discounting this barrage of impressions which the advertiser seeks to implant in our mind; (2) the
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
habit of trying to glean from the advertisement such definite factual information as it may
contain about the nature of the product, its special features, and its price. Only this information
has any real utility for the purchaser. In this way the advertising section of a newspaper or
magazine can be very useful to a reader who studies it to find out what products are being
offered and by what companies. Beyond this we have to learn to free yourself from the
psychological enslavement of advertising impressions.
The vast importance of advertising in modern life is undoubtedly an evil, since it constitutes a
very big expenditure which brings only a small profit to the purchaser. Hence the purchaser
should resist advertising as much as he can, and let companies see that there are many purchasers
who demand reliable information. The person engaged in the advertising business should work to
develop advertising that is more informative and educational. In present circumstances,
nonetheless, he is permitted to compete with other advertisers in using methods of mass-appeal
as long as his advertising is not dishonest and does not appeal to immoral emotions of impurity,
irrational fear, hate, greed, etc., and provided that the product is a legitimate one. This does not
absolve him from his social duty to strive for better practices in his business. Social authorities
have even a greater responsibility gradually to reduce the social waste of excessive advertising
and to forbid or control the advertising, of socially dangerous products.
For many people, radio, television, and the movies take the place of the newspaper as the source
both of information and of entertainment. Most of the time spent on these media is devoted to
entertainment, and should be analyzed in terms of the principles of poetics and the fine arts.
Such an analysis reveals that radio and television provide us with three main classes of
entertainment:
1. Quality programs in which the producer aims at producing a real work of art:
well-played music whether classical or jazz, an effective drama, or a sports
exhibition. These programs are usually a rather small part of the total offering and
the listener must study the program offerings in order to select them. If he selects
only such programs he will probably not give a great deal of time to the medium,
but he will be able to find some excellent entertainment which was once available
only to a few.
2. Mass-appeal programs in which the producer aims principally at getting as
large an audience as possible in order to please an advertising sponsor. These
programs may be of high quality, or they may be exceedingly poor entertainment,
but these considerations are really irrelevant. People watch a program in vast
numbers for all sorts of strange reasons, some of them quite irrational. Defenders
of such programs usually say that they are "giving the people what they want."
We know that such a policy with children is very injurious to the child. The public
is an amorphous group which can be influenced to act like a child or to act like an
adult. If the mass media treats the public as a child it will make it childish.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Nor is it true to say that people are always entertained by the things they watch or
listen to. Curiosity, laziness, boredom, lust, and all sorts of hidden motives drive
people to listen and watch programs which do not truly recreate them, if by
recreation we mean a resting and strengthening for daily tasks and for a higher
human life. People have been known to flock to a movie which left them
frightened and depressed after the momentary satisfaction of a morbid curiosity.
As rhetorical media, radio, television. and the movies at present do not have a very great
function in our society. The codes of these industries and the federal control over the first two
operate at present to keep "controversial" material at a minimum, and this is powerfully
reinforced by the desire of the commercial sponsors not to offend any group. Political speeches
and interview programs on which the principal parties are permitted to buy time, or in some
cases are given equal time, are the obvious places for rhetoric. Speakers have learned to develop
a special style which is more direct and intimate than platform speaking. Of maximum
importance is the speaker's ability to create an impression of sincerity, simplicity, plus the ability
to answer any question on the spur of the moment without betraying anger or lack of
information. Speakers are sometimes expected to have all the charm of a professional entertainer,
and must aim more at being pleasant than at being forceful.
It is obvious that in the future these media may be used more for direct propaganda for a
particular point of view. We have already seen this in war time, and it is current practice in anti-
democratic countries. There is some reason to believe, however, (since it has never proved
possible for a country completely to exclude the reception of foreign broadcasts) that these mass
media are most effective when they give the appearance of the objective presentation of both
sides of a question. When they fail to seem objective, listeners will grow suspicious and listen to
competing broadcasts.
The informational aspect of these media, and particularly of television, can be very great, but at
present it is confined to short news broadcasts which are no real substitute for a good newspaper
article, to views of public ceremonies, etc., and to "educational programs." The educational
programs may grow in number and popularity, although at present they are still of minor
importance. It is not to be expected, however, that the mass viewing of public spectacles will
greatly contribute to people's real understanding of social events, The great events of history are
not ordinarily public events and what the cameras show us is only the outward display.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
In making use of these three media for our own consumption we should try to be selective and to
leave ample time in our life for more rewarding activities, rather than to become a slave to the
mass-mind. In using them to influence others we must realize the serious responsibilities of
which the Popes have frequently spoken, and should learn what these responsibilities are by a
study of the papal encyclicals and the ethical codes of each industry. All of the mass media are
extremely expensive to provide; one consequence of this is that their control is not in the hands
of individuals, but of immense corporate bodies. It is necessary for the individual to work within
such a corporation for the gradual improvement of standards.
Besides the newspaper, we are provided with a vast amount of printing, ranging from pamphlets
to magazines, and through a vast variety of magazines to many types of books. Here the
important thing is to become acquainted with the whole spectrum of available reading material.
There are "pulp-magazines" devoted to time killing popular fiction. There are "slick-magazines"
devoted to a varied fare. There are digests, some devoted to general collections and some to
special fields. There are news summaries and economic summaries, There are magazines like the
Saturday Evening, Post with a mixture of fiction and feature articles that appeal to a business-
class audience. There are magazines like The Atlantic Monthly which aim at somewhat more
"highbrow" audiences, and the "little magazines" of a literary or political character that aim at
very "highbrow" audiences. There are scholarly, professional, and trade journals.
A student ought to spend some time in a library which has a full range of periodicals and become
acquainted with what is available to him both in the way of entertainment and of information.
Especially should the courses lie may be studying in school encourage him to enquire from the
teacher what periodicals or works of bibliography pertain to these particular subjects and to
examine and use them. He will quickly discover that the mass media magazines are only inferior
versions of much better publications from which they copy a good deal of their information.
American publications, however, are generally weak in effective discussion or genuine rhetoric.
The best examples of rhetoric are to be found in the works of a few commentators or public-
spirited men who wish to advocate a definite policy and who write with the plain purpose of
persuading others to accept this view. Such work, if it is not dishonest or based on gross
fallacies, is always profitable; for, even if we are not convinced, at least we obtain a clearer and
broader vision of the problem.
Discussion is often very neglected today. In most American papers and magazines the "letters to
the editor" department does little more than provide us with a gauge of a favorable or
unfavorable public reaction. The letters are too brief, or they are written by extremists. The
serious thinker is not often attracted to write in such columns, so that controversy, once very
popular, does not play a very big part in our press. Americans seem afraid of the direct refutation
of an opponent, and people seem more interested in proving that they are acquainted with both
sides of a problem than in trying to make a judgement.
In spite of the enormous propaganda machines which operated in World War II, and the vast
variety of the devices which they attempted to use, it is admitted by many that one of the most
effective works of persuasion was the series of radio speeches given by the British Prime
Minister, Winston Churchill, during the Battle of Britain. These speeches were rhetoric of the
classical type, which Cicero would have admired. They were effectively timed to anticipate each
crisis, but their chief power came from the way in which Churchill made every Englishman feel
that he and his leaders were all joined together in the same risks and the same heroic defense of a
great tradition.
These speeches were proof that the genuine classical forms of rhetoric still remain great. Only
such rhetoric has the real power to convince, because only in such direct speech are we made to
feel the personal conviction of a leader who appeals to us as free human beings capable of
deliberate choice. The mass media, when they descend from this true rhetoric to the devices of
mere advertising, debase the public and turn it into an irrational animal impulses.
The Christian must use the grace given in confirmation to bear witness to truth, and to resist the
constant pressure of mass thinking. He must critically weigh the sources of his information and
rely only on what is best. He must have the freedom of mind to engage in honest discussion, and
he must have the generosity to listen to men who will accept the responsibility of leadership, and
if treated by them as a free man, lie must be willing to follow them loyally.
In planning to persuade an audience to act as we think right the most important problems are the
ones we have already discussed in the first part of this chapter, namely, how
to analyze an audience and decide which arguments will most appeal to them. Even after these
problems have been solved, however, a further very serious one remains: How to express these
arguments in winning words.
In Chapter I we studied something of the magic power of words to arouse the imagination and
move the emotions. The poetic writer uses this magic to recreate for us some story of human life.
The rhetorician also must use this magic to arouse the attention and sympathy of his audience
and then to move them to accept his arguments. This magic of words consists, not only in the
selection of appropriate words, but also in their organization into sentences. The manner in
which this is done effectively is called style. We say that a person who makes a pleasing
appearance by his manner of dress is "in style." Similarly the clothing of our ideas in neat and
attractive language is called "good style."
To be effective in persuasion we must have a good style of speaking and writing, and good style
has two qualities: (1) It should be appropriate to our audience and our subject matter; (2) it
should express our own individuality, since the character of a speaker is one of the most
powerful means of persuasion. It is often said that "the style is the man," meaning that our use of
words in writing or speaking shows our character to others.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
To have these two qualities of appropriateness and individuality style must first of all be clear
and orderly. A confused presentation of a subject is always displeasing to an audience and
creates a bad impression. A poetic writer will tell a good story, as we have seen, only if he keeps
before him the outline of his plot and makes every word and every detail contribute to that single
effect. So also the rhetorician must keep before him what he is trying to achieve and make every
step of his speech contribute to it. If we examine a well-written advertisement we will soon see
how careful the writer was to choose every single word and sentence to make the strongest
possible impression on the reader in the shortest possible space.
Therefore, the first rule in acquiring a good style is this: begin by making an outline of what
we wish to say.
OUTLINING A COMPOSITION
Any piece of speaking or writing is made up of many sentences or statements, but only a few are
of chief importance, for only a few ideas in any such piece are the chief ideas. just as we try to
find the two main ideas in a composition, so we must look for the chief statement. This chief
statement will be a combination of these two main ideas; we call it the author's thesis or
conclusion. Everything else in the composition is there only to explain this chief statement. Once
we have discovered the two chief ideas, it is obvious that the conclusion will either combine
these, or deny that they can be truly combined. We must either say "Patriotism is honorable," or
"Patriotism is not honorable." The former statement is affirmative, the latter negative.
In making an outline, therefore, our first step is to write down the main conclusion or thesis,
combining or denying the combination of the two main ideas. The second step is to discover the
parts of the composition, and then to find the main statement in each of these parts. Thirdly,
these parts can also be divided into parts, each of which has a main statement. This process of
breaking down the whole into parts, and these parts into smaller parts can be continued until we
arrive at the single sentences of the composition.
In a poetic work the thesis or conclusion will state the plot or story of the poem. The outline will
show the different stages of this plot. In a play these different stages are usually called "acts" and
"scenes"; in a novel they are commonly chapters, and sections of chapters; in a lyric poem they
will often be stanzas.
In a rhetorical work the thesis will be what the speaker is trying to persuade us to do; the
outline will show the steps by which he persuades us. In a dialectical work the thesis is not a
definite affirmation or negation, but the statement of the case on both sides; the parts of the
outline show the stages by which each side makes out its own case. In a scientific work the thesis
is the conclusion to be proved as certainly true or false; the outline will show the steps by which
this proof is made firm and solid.
If we try to make a first draft of an outline of the "Concord Hymn" we might get the following
diagram:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
3. Analysis of the outlines: You will notice that a perfect outline is simply a classification of the
different statements contained in a composition. It is like a branching tree: the trunk is the thesis
of the whole composition, which divides into two great branches ' and these into smaller and
smaller twigs. Each branch and twig represents a subdivision of the main thesis. Many students
make the serious mistake in outlining of merely listing a series of statements. A heap of lumber
is not a tree, and a list of statements is not an outline. An outline is an orderly classification of
statements in which each general statement is divided into lesser general statements until finally
the ultimate unit of statements of the composition is reached. Outlines for other examples will be
found on page 470.
DIAGRAMMING A SENTENCE
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
If the process of outlining is carried out completely, it will classify every single sentence in the
entire composition, It might seem that this would be a complete analysis. But the sentences
themselves can also be broken up into the parts of which they are composed. We call this process
of analyzing a sentence grammatical analysis or diagraming.
The fundamental point in diagraming is to realize that in a complete statement or sentence there.
are only the three principal parts we have already studied (see page 69), the subject, the
predicate, and the copula which joins or separates them.
1. Sentences and modifiers. When we examine sentences, however, we find that some have
several subjects and predicates. When these are linked together by the word "and," the sentence
is compound, and we can easily divide it into several distinct sentences or statements. When,
however, the several subjects and predicates are linked by subordinating conjunctions, then the
sentence has only one principal subject and predicate, and the other sentences (subordinate
clauses) are really modifiers. The chief subordinating conjunctions are the following:
In diagraming, our whole purpose is to discover the principal subject and predicate, and then to
list the other parts of the sentence as modifiers of these. Since the predicate itself is a modifier,
we can actually turn the sentence into a subject with a whole series of predicates. Thus the
simplest way of conceiving the building of any sentence is to think of it as a subject with a series
of modifiers, each,one of which could serve as the predicate of a separate sentence.
2. The moods of verbs. Our notion of a sentence can be still further simplified by noticing
that the verb is either is (or is not), plus a predicate word or series of words.
This is very plain in declarative sentences, which simply state something true or false. Sentences
in which the verb expresses some other manner of speaking (a request, for example, or a
command), rather than a simple declaration of truth or falsity, are said to be in a different mood
(manner of speaking) than these simply declarative sentences, which are in the indicative mood.
But we can make them into declarations in the indicative mood by saying "I am asking or
commanding you...." Thus:
3. Actions expressed by verbs. We should also notice that some verbs name an action which
is clear and definite. These verbs are said to be intransitive; they need no other noun to explain
them. But frequently it is necessary to make a verb clearer by adding to it a noun called its object
: "I made a house." Sometimes it is even necessary to add a second object noun or an adjective,
which is called the objective complement : I made the house a home," or "I made the house
comfortable." Verbs of this kind demanding an object or objective complement are called
transitive.
When a verb names an action which is clear and definite it is said to be intransitive. Frequently,
however, it is necessary to make the nature of this action more definite by indicating its effect,
since action is completed by bringing about some result. This can be done by adding, in one of
several ways, a noun or an adjective which indicates the result or effect of the action:
1. The direct object is a noun which indicates the thing acted upon: "I made a
house."
2. The objective complement is a noun or adjective indicating the effect
produced in the object: "I made the house a home," or "I made the house
comfortable."
3. The indirect object is a noun which indicates the person to or for whom the
action is performed: "I made him a house."
4. The infinitive which is a noun naming an action, can also be used just like a
direct object in order to indicate that one action results in another: "I am trying to
build a house."
All these words which help to make a verb clearer are really its modifiers. The standard method
of diagraming sentences, however, places the object on a straight line with subject and verb, and
thus it incorrectly makes it appear as if an object were a principal part of a sentence.
In the manner just explained, any piece of speaking or writing can ultimately be analyzed into a
series of simple sentences, each having only a subject, predicate, and copula.
An Example of Diagraming
The "Concord Hymn" is made up of four stanzas, each of which is a single sentence. The
simplicity and beauty of the poem comes largely from the way in which Emerson makes his
ideas clear, and yet expresses them in a varied manner by a careful construction of each of these
sentences. All of them are declarative sentences, except the last which is imperative. We can
rewrite this last sentence in declarative form as follows: "We beg thee, Spirit that made these
heroes dare to die and leave their children free, to bid time and nature gently spare the shaft we
raise to them and thee."
If we diagram the first three declarative sentences according to the usual method, we get the
following:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
These diagrams show the relations within each sentence. We see that each compound sentence
(1st and 2nd stanzas) can be broken into separate sentences simply by removing the conjunction.
Similarly the complex sentences (all four are complex) can be made into several separate
sentences by rewriting each subordinate clause in the form of an independent statement. If we do
this we get the following sentences:
1. The embattled farmers, with their flag unfurled to April's breeze, once stood here by the
rude bridge.
2. The rude bridge arched the flood.
3. The farmers fired the shot heard round the world.
4. The foe long since in silence slept.
5. The conqueror also sleeps in silence.
6. Time has swept the ruined bridge down the dark stream.
7. The stream creeps seaward.
8. We today set a votive stone on this green bank by this soft stream.
9. Our purpose is to commemorate their deed.
10. This commemoration will last.
11. Our sons will then be gone.
12. Similarly our sires have gone.
13. We beg thee, Spirit, to bid Time and Nature spare the shaft.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
14. The spirit made those heroes dare to die and leave their children free.
15. We raise the shaft to them and thee.
Thus fifteen sentences are compressed into four by Emerson without any loss of clarity. Indeed
the four sentences are actually clearer, because by the use of conjunctions the author shows us
which ideas are more important and which are of equal importance. An analysis of the
"Gettysburg Address" will show the same skill in putting many ideas clearly in a few sentences.
Study, for example, its last sentence which has become so famous.
In order to see that the ultimate units of all our thinking and writing are subjects and predicates
(that is, a noun and its modifiers) let us take the first sentence of the "Concord Hymn" (see
diagram on page (10-1) and break it down to its ultimate ideas: We can write out these ideas as
follows:
These sentences are too awkward to be good English sentences, but they state the ultimate truths
which are all bundled together in this one single sentence. So rapid is the human mind that it
takes in many such thought-units in one swift movement.
VARIETY IN STYLE
Each part of the composition should be a development of one part of the outline. The main
statement of each part of the outline can frequently be used as the first sentence of a paragraph,
and is then called a topic sentence. The sentences of each paragraph should be arranged so that
the subject of the paragraph is emphasized, and the principal predicate or predicates applied to
it stand out clearly. The other modifiers should be the less important ideas and should not be too
many, so that the sentences are short and uncluttered.
This kind of writing is sure to be clear and ought to be the basic pattern for all writing. Writing
that adheres closely to such a pattern is said to be in the simple style.
The simple style might use words and grammatical construction of three different levels of
usage. The formal style is used for most expository writing and in speeches and lectures given on
formal occasions. The informal style is that of the conversational speech of educated persons and
makes use of colloquial words, contracted forms of speech like "don't" and "won't," and a
simpler and looser grammatical construction. The vulgate level is used by uneducated persons
habitually, and by educated persons occasionally for humorous effects. It makes use of slang
(that is, of short-lived language of popular origin) and of barbarism (that is, of distorted forms
due to ignorance). We may also notice that in speaking or writing to special groups we may
employ -- and, indeed, must often employ -- a restricted usage to which they are accustomed, but
we should beware of attempting this unless we can do it well.
The simple style is not adequate to fulfill all the requirements of rhetoric and poetry. It lacks
"color," that is, it does not arouse our imagination and emotions. Soon it becomes extremely
monotonous and the attention of the reader or listener wanders. The simple style is best in
scientific writing, but in rhetoric and poetry it is necessary to develop it in such a way that,
without losing its clarity, it takes on variety, emphasis, and continuity. Variety holds the attention
of the audience. Emphasis makes the important ideas stand out vividly and in a way that is easy
to remember. Continuity, or the smooth flow of one idea into another, helps the audience to
follow the thought easily and without tiring or getting lost. We will discuss continuity in the next
chapter.
Variety is obtained by the use of the sound of the words, by sentence structure, and figures of
speech.
We have seen that the sound of a word gives it an emotional quality (see pages 41-42). When
words are combined into longer units they take on melody and rhythm as in music. The melody
is the combination of series of sounds differing in pitch according to some pattern or proportion.
In speech, melody is very restricted, and yet beautiful effects can be obtained by the choice and
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
arrangement of high-pitched vowels like i and e and low-pitched vowels like o and u, and by
similar sound in alliteration (similar consonants at the beginning of words), rhyme (similar
sounds at the end of words), and assonance (similar vowels within words) (see page 42). The
basic principle in giving either prose or verse a beautiful sound is to avoid monotony by
contrasting unlike sounds and to achieve emphasis by comparing similar sounds.
Rhythm is the regular arrangement of sounds according to time. The rhythm of speech or song is
marked off either by long and short sounds, or by the arrangements of accents, and it is
reinforced by the melody. When rhythm is regular it is called meter or verse. When it has only a
loose regularity it is called free verse, and if very irregular it is prose. Latin and Greek used a
rhythm based principally on long and short sounds, reinforced by accents. English, however,
uses just the reverse system; its rhythm is based on accents, reinforced somewhat by the length
of the syllables.
There are basically two units of rhythm (called "feet"): One has two beats, and one three. Any
longer unit could be broken up into smaller units. The pattern would be monotonous or
ambiguous if all these beats were exactly alike. Hence the two beat unit is treated as made up of
a full beat, and two half-beats. If the full beat comes first the foot is called a dactyl (- ' ' ); if it is
placed last it is called an anapest (' ' -). In music this rhythm is called 4/4 or common time. The
three beat rhythm is either a trochee (' -) or an iamb (- '). These units can be arranged into longer
units or lines (verses) and into groups of verses or stanzas. Meters are named by stating the foot
and the number of feet to a line. Thus "iambic pentameter" is verse having five iambic feet in a
line ( penta is Greek for 5).
Rhythm itself requires variety and emphasis. Hence in meter it is necessary to substitute some
different feet in the regular pattern. fit prose it is important not to allow the rhythm to become
too regular, since then it begins to sound like imperfect verse. A beautiful sound pattern,
however, is not very useful in either verse or prose unless it lends emphasis to the ideas. Hence
the pattern of rhythm and melody should serve to bring out the sentence structure.
Sentence Structure
Skillful sentence construction is the most important means of creating the emphasis and variety
that are the mark of a good style. The unskillful writer is usually guilty of two errors: (1) He
makes sentences which are confused, and thus emphasis is lost. (2) He makes every sentence
alike, hence variety disappears.
In order to correct these faults, it is important to master the principles laid down in the previous
section. We must understand how to begin with a subject and predicate, and never to let go of
them in constructing the sentence. They are its basic skeleton and must stand out clearly. This
removes the first fault. The second is corrected by the use of different types of modifiers:
subordinate clauses, phrases, and different parts of speech. It is necessary to practice expressing
the same idea in a great variety of ways, so that in writing a composition we can vary our
expression as required.
The final means of achieving this more colorful style is by the use of figures of speech. In
Chapter I (pages 53-54) we treated of figures of speech that depend on the transference of words
from one meaning to another. There are also figures which depend rather on the arrangement of
ideas in a sentence. The most important of these are parallelism and antithesis.
The first of these is the arrangement of sentences, clauses, or phrases so that they are alike either
in grammatical construction or at least in thought. Antithesis is the opposite, a contrast in
structure or ideas. Parallelism and antithesis are often combined so that the grammatical
construction is parallel, while the thought is antithetical.
Related to these is climax, or the arrangement of sentences or parts of sentences (often three) in
the order of ascending importance. Anticlimax is the reverse arrangement. The use of a mixture
of declarative, interrogative, and imperative sentences (see page 102 f.) has the effect of a figure
of speech. To achieve this, inanimate things or abstractions are often treated as persons (
personification ); moreover, both real persons and personifications may be addressed
dramatically as if they were present and listening to us. This is called apostrophe.
A style which makes use of all these devices is called colorful or ornamented. It should still
retain clarity but it cannot possibly be as clear as the simple style. Hence poetry often seems
rather obscure to the reader, but it would never be able to attain its richness and intense
emotional quality in any other way.
Rhetoric also strives for great variety in order to keep the audience awake, but it is not as intense
as poetry. The style of poetry can be delightful for its own sake, since it is intended to entertain,
but the style of rhetoric must avoid attracting too much attention to itself, lest the audience enjoy
the speech and yet go away unpersuaded. Hence rhetoric seeks the medium style, not so plain as
to be uninteresting, nor so elaborate as to be distracting.
Both rhetoric and poetry must take care to maintain a definite mood or tone. They seek to build
up a definite emotion in the audience, and such an emotion can easily be destroyed by a jarring
note. Important in setting the tone of a composition are two figures of speech not yet mentioned.
One is hyperbole, or the use of exaggerated statements to emphasize an idea. The other is litotes
or understatement, the use of statements that are too weak and which also emphasize an opposite
meaning, just as does irony with respect to words (page 53).
The basic rule with regard to style, therefore, should be as follows: Begin with a clear expression
of your basic ideas in a simple style; then if your purpose is poetic or rhetorical choose the
appropriate devices of sound, of sentence-structure, and of figures of speech to achieve variety
and emphasis and to sustain the desired emotional mood. Nothing is gained and much is lost if
these devices of style are merely tacked on to make your writing or speaking "fancy" or
decorated with high-flown language and "purple patches." Unless you are sure that a device has a
definite contribution to make, it is better to stick to the simple style. Indeed good writers
generally revise their work with the purpose of cutting out all devices of style that are not really
effective.
EXAMPLES OF STYLE
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
1. The style of St. Thomas Aquinas. Of our standard examples, that by St. Thomas Aquinas
(page 417) is in the simple style. The original Latin is even simpler and more precise. St.
Thomas is a master of the simple style in which every word and sentence aims at perfect clarity.
He avoids almost all of the devices which we have been mentioning, except for some use of
parallelism and antithesis.
2. The style of Chesterton. The work of Chesterton (page 413) is in the medium style,
because although it is dialectical in its purpose it makes use of a rather rhetorical approach
common in essays. Chesterton is fond of certain sound effects, especially of alliteration
("purifying passion," "there would be no one left to say that lust bore none of the marks of love."
"only in consequence of such a decay could the current love of territory be confounded with the
ancient love of country"). A careful reading will show that he avoids making this too obvious
and that it has a definite purpose, namely, to emphasize his use of antithesis.
It is this use of antithesis that is very characteristic of dialectic and which Chesterton constantly
employs: "If no type of chivalrous and purifying passion remained, there would be no one left to
say that lust bore none of the marks of love, that lust was rapacious and love pitiful, that lust was
blind and love vigilant, that lust sated itself and love was insatiable."
Chesterton's tone throughout is humorous, and hence he makes effective use of hyperbole and
anticlimax : "The conviction must come to him at last that these men do not realize what the
word 'love' means, that they mean by the love of country, not what a mystic might mean by the
love of God, but something of what a child might mean by the love of jam." Obviously "jam" is
here an anticlimax, and it is made all the more effective by comparing it to "the love of God,"
which is a hyperbole, since Chesterton has been using love merely to mean patriotism or
romantic love, not for something so lofty. Note also the anticlimax in "trade, physical force, a
skirmish at a remote frontier, a squabble in a remote continent"; each phrase is less and less
dignified. Notice finally the use of antithesis in the rather solemn close of the last two sentences
of the composition.
3. The "Gettysburg Address." Lincoln's speech is one of the great masterpieces of the
medium style, but its tone is solemn and grand, rather than playful, like that of Chesterton.
Lincoln uses a style which at first sight seems to be simple, and yet on examination turns out to
make use of very many rhetorical devices. Its simplicity is deliberate in order to remove the
impression that the President on this occasion was striving to make a political display. Thus
throughout there is a certain effect of litotes or understatement, especially in such a sentence as:
"it is altogether fitting and proper that we should do this."
Its chief devices, however, are the beautiful use of antithesis and climax, and its solemn and
flowing sound. Notice the rhythm of: "Now we are engaged in a great civil war, testing whether
that nation, or any nation so conceived and so dedicated, can long endure." If we diagram the
sound pattern in this sentence we get something like the following:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
It will be noticed that there is a basic iambic rhythm (' -) running through this whole sentence. In
the first line, however, the rhythm is shifted to emphasize the words "now," "engaged," "great,"
and "war." Then the succeeding four lines are rather rapid because their rhythm is quite regular.
Finally, the succession of short sounds ("dedicated can") prepares for a solemn and slow close on
the two very long, heavy sounds, "long endure." Thus the beginning of the sentence Sounds
solemn and weighty, the middle part is more vigorous, and the conclusion is very solemn. This
effect is enhanced by the parallelism of "that nation/ or any nation" and "so conceived/ and so
dedicated."
1. The first sentence has a solemn, even pace. The subject "our fathers" has no
other modifiers, but several modifiers are attached to the predicate "brought
forth." They tell us when ("four-score and seven years ago") where ("on this
continent") and the result ("a new nation"). This result, "the nation," is defined by
two parallel phrases: "conceived in liberty," and "dedicated to the proposition that
all men are created equal." Thus the mind is fixed at once on the notion of our
"nation and what it stands for.
2. The second sentence is parallel to the first, except that the position of "nation"
is now taken by the term "war," which again is defined by balanced phrases,
"testing whether that nation, or any nation so conceived and so dedicated, can
long endure." If you compare these first two sentences you will see that they have
the effect of balancing each other, and have a rather similar sound.
3. The third sentence is very short and matter of fact. It thus changes the pattern
set by the first two sentences. It is connected with them, however, by a
parallelism: "We are engaged in a great civil war...", "We are met on a great
battlefield of that war."
4. The fourth sentence is parallel to the two preceding, since all three begin alike:
"We are engaged," "We are met," "We have come." Notice the parallelism
between "gave their lives" and "that that nation might live."
5. The fifth sentence again is very brief and matter of fact, with something of the
effect of understatement. You will notice that each time Lincoln refers to himself
and the crowd he speaks in a deprecating, brief manner. When he refers to the
dead and their example, the sentences become rich and solemn.
6. The sixth sentence consists in a beautiful three-membered climax, "We cannot
dedicate, we cannot consecrate, we cannot hallow this ground."
7. The seventh is filled with emotion. Lincoln now directly refers to the heroes
and defines them in simple terms, "The brave men, living and dead, who
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
struggled here. .." Notice how the series of very short words, "far above our poor
power to add or detract," make the last part of the line swift in movement and
suggestive of the weakness and inadequacy which the speaker feels in the
presence of the great.
8. The eighth sentence contains a parallelism: "The world will little note, nor long
remember," and an antithesis: "what we say here"... "what they did here."
9. The last sentence is the longest of all and provides a wonderful climax. You
will notice that the first part of the sentence, "It is rather for us to be here
dedicated to the great task remaining before us," is parallel to the preceding
sentence. Then Lincoln makes a grammatical break, represented by the dash -. We
would expect him to say, "It is rather for us to be dedicated to the great task, and
that we should take increased devotion from these honored dead," This, however,
would have been weak and complicated. So Lincoln boldly drops the sentence
construction with which he began and forms the rest of the sentence on a new
pattern. The rest of the sentence has two parallel members: "that from these
honored dead we take increased devotion," and "that we here highly resolve."
This last member then has three parallel members within itself: that these dead
shall not have died in vain..... that this nation... shall have a new birth," and "that
government... shall not perish." Finally the last of these itself contains three
climatic phrases: "of the people," "by the people," "for the people."
4. The "Concord Hymn." The style of the "Concord Hymn" is the elaborate and intense
style of poetry, although in this case Emerson keeps it relatively simple. He wishes to give it
something of the simpler tone of rhetorical prose, since the poem suggests a memorial speech.
We have already seen how carefully varied are the four sentences that make up the poem. Notice
also that parallelism and antithesis run through the entire poem and are supported by the
arrangement of lines in the stanzas and by the rhymes. Thus in the first stanza the first two lines
are similar in structure, neither one containing the subject or the predicate of the sentence, while
the last two lines each contain a complete sentence joined by "and." In the second stanza this
parallelism is even plainer. This balanced rhythm, the rhyme, and the figures of speech (see page
110) give an emotional tone which is smoother and freer than that of the "Gettysburg Address."
This poem sings, while the music in Lincoln's words is muffled and broken.
The expression "shot heard round the world" is an excellent example of a hyperbole. The last
stanza is an apostrophe, and in it "Time" and "Nature" are personified. We notice that the
descriptive imagery of the poem, "dark stream which seaward creeps," "this green bank," "this
soft stream," would not be very appropriate in the medium style of rhetorical prose, except
perhaps at a moment of great emotion.
DEFINITIONS
(to be memorized)
1. A statement is the verbal expression of a judgment, signifying truth or falsehood, and is made
up of a subject, predicate, and copula.
3. Statements are opposed when they have the same predicates and subjects but different
quantities and qualities and hence differ in some way in truth value.
5. Certitude is a state of mind which excludes doubt; opinion is a state of mind in which one of
two contradictory statements is preferred but without the total exclusion of the other.
1) Merely subjective certitude is a state of the mind excluding doubt, but not
based on objective evidence.
2) Objective certitude is a state of mind excluding reasonable doubt, by means of
objective evidence.
6. An immediately evident statement is one known to be certainly true from the meaning of its
terms and immediate objective evidence.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
7. Faith is a knowing assent to a statement as true, not because it is evident, but on the authority
of another.
The major objective of this year should be the detailed analysis of one standard example of an
excellent rhetorical speech, and the imitation of this speech in a brief talk, carefully written and
delivered, to be presented in class toward the end of the school year. The grammatical exercises
should be directed toward this objective.
A. Studying advertisements.
What are the features contained in several newspapers? What kind of audience
does the newspaper or magazine seek to reach? How much of the material is of
high quality? intended for mass appeal? intended to kill time?
In the anthology or other literary material analyze speeches and essays which are
rhetorical in character. What audience did the writer address? What was his
technique? Why did such works have to be more subtle in their rhetorical appeal
than in advertising?
D. Correlation:
From the history course bring in examples of great men who achieved power
through. their rhetorical ability. Read some of their speeches. Give examples also
from current history. It would be well to read an oration of Cicero in translation
and discuss reasons for taking third and fourth year Latin.
E. Speech:
This material should not be treated as an isolated topic, but should be directed toward a detailed
analysis of essays and speeches, and toward planning the speech to be written in Unit IV.
Several selections of each type of discourse should be read and the student should
formulate the author's thesis in a single clear sentence.
The student should now break the composition up into its main parts, and
formulate the thesis of each part in a single sentence. Then each major part should
be broken up into minor parts, and each of these formulated as a sentence. The
outline should then be criticized (a) for parallelism of division and formulation,
(b) for clear relation between parts and whole, between the theme of each part
and the main conclusion.
C. Grammar review:
Review formation of paragraphs, use of capital letters in titles, etc. The general
appearance of a composition should make its outline clear. (See E. W., Grade
Ten, pp. 179-190, for exercises in paragraph writing.)
D. Diagramming sentences:
(1) The ordinary method of diagramming should be explained (see pages 104-
105). For a good treatment of diagramming see H. C. House and S. E. Harman,
Descriptive English Grammar (2nd ed., Prentice-Hall, 1950). Then drill on
diagramming and correction of sentence faults should be made. (See E. W., pp.
23-24 and pp. 45-66.)
(2) Theoretical grammar: Review the use of the categories, pp. 45-49.
E. Composition:
Select passages from literature written in rather long and complex sentences and
rewrite in short sentences. Then reverse this procedure, turning a composition
written in short sentences into a few well-structured compound and complex
sentences. Discuss the rhetorical value of each style. Which is clearer? smoother?
Which holds our attention best? Which style would be appropriate for different
types of audience?
Take short selections from the anthology to illustrate various types of style, and
the use of devices of sound, sentence structure, figures of speech. The teacher
may expand this section on melody and rhythm. A good treatment will be found in
Enid Hamer, The Meters of English Poetry (New York: Macmillan, 1930).
Study of a long work (novel, Shakespearean play, or other plays) with special
attention to the use of these stylistic devices.
C. Composition:
An essay on the theme of the work just read. Student should make an outline,
decide on the type of discourse, and then should write with attention to style.
After this essay is corrected, it should be rewritten by student in another style
(simpler or more elaborate, etc.).
D. Grammar review:
The writing of the essay should be followed by a review of common errors (see E.
W., Chapters 6-12).
E. Speech:
Students may be asked to give oral book reports on some assigned reading.
Attention should be given to oral style: speaking in complete sentences; beginning
with an outline of what is about to be said, concluding with a summary, and
making clear each step of the talk. What choice of words and sentence structure
sound well
CHAPTER III
Dialectics and Demonstrative Logic:
Scientific Method
ART OF DEFINITION
INTRODUCTION
experiences of the poet and the politician. He tries to eliminate emotion and subjectivity from all
his work.
Yet this impression is false. The world of literature and of science is the same world, the
wonderful world that God has made more full of marvels than even poet or explorer realizes.
Literature, to be good literature, must be essentially true to the world in which we live; it must
imitate nature and human life. Even the most fantastic fairy-story. if it is to have real charm for
us, must reveal the marvels of God's creation under the form of imaginative symbols. On the
other hand, even the most hard-headed scientist is a creative thinker, one who employs his
intuitions and his imagination to find new and ingenious ways to unlock the secrets of nature.
Literature must be true to life, science must be imaginative, or both will die.
Yet it is very true that there is a great difference between the methods and approach of literary
thinking (poetics and rhetoric) and scientific thinking (dialectics and demonstrative logic). The
former seeks to lead us to truth by the way of reasoning and emotion, the latter rises above
emotion to pure truth. We have already seen how dialectics is useful for discussion and debate.
In this capacity it is closely linked with rhetoric, since such discussion and debate prepare for
persuasion. But it is also closely linked with science, since it is through dialectic that we make
preliminary investigations that lead to scientific discovery and proof. Today when we speak of
scientific research we are talking about that part of science which is largely dialectical. It is only
when research is completed that science in the fullest sense begins, the establishment of basic
laws.
Many students and even teachers find literature and rhetoric interesting. These are warm and
human subjects which deal with human problems. Scientific research and thinking at first seem
very cold and dry and obscure. Yet the human reason is at its best only when it is able to attain to
the clarity and sureness of science. This does not mean that science can ever replace literature.
But science gives us a clear and exact knowledge about the world which literature cannot give.
Both are necessary in our life, and both can go hand in hand.
During this year much of our time is to be spent considering the scientific ways of thinking, but
we will not leave literature behind. Rather we will begin to see the difference and contrast
between these two ways of thought, and then see how they have certain basic principles in
common, and how they supplement and assist each other.
When a scientist begins to study a problem such as the problem of cancer, he has two main tasks:
(1) To get the facts; (2) to explain the facts, that is, to find the reasons or causes for these facts.
The gathering of facts, however, is not a mere random process. There are an unlimited number of
facts in the world, and a scientist might go on forever collecting them without getting anywhere
in understanding them. The great problem of investigation is to use one's intelligence to
understand these facts. One must look through the facts to the reality which underlies them and
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
gives them meaning. This is a matter of intuition, just as the poet's insight into life, or the
rhetorician's insight into his audience, is a matter of trained intuition. This intuition into the
nature of things which underlies the facts is nothing other than definition. The first problem of a
scientist studying the problem of cancer is to gather and examine facts with the purpose of
finding out what a cancer is. What makes a cancer different from a healthy organ of the body, or
from some other nonmalignant growth? The only answer to this is found in looking at the facts,
but the facts give an answer only to a trained intelligence that is able to see differences and
similarities.
In Chapter I we studied the dictionary or nominal definition of terms, but in science we must
have much more accurate definition of terms. In scientific thinking and writing, unlike literary
work, what is needed is not vividness but clarity and accuracy. In such writing we should avoid
metaphors and other figures of speech. When analogy must be used, then proper analogy may be
employed, but we should try as far as possible to exclude all equivocation and to use only
univocal terms.
Such accurate words are said to be technical terms and they must be carefully defined. For this it
is not sufficient merely to define the word (nominal definition); rather we need to define the
thing (a real or scientific definition), since science is not so much concerned with words as with
things.
To give a definition of a thing requires a great deal of knowledge about that thing, since we must
know just what makes it different from any other kind of thing. Hence we have encyclopedias
which treat not merely of the usage of words but summarize our knowledge of things themselves.
A great deal of a student's time in studying mathematics, natural science, social science,
philosophy, theology, or even grammar is devoted to learning technical definitions. Without this
accuracy in thought and speech our knowledge of these subjects would become very confused
and false.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The last requirement is not easy to fulfill, but the great philosopher, Aristotle, showed that we
can make a definition complete if we are careful to state the four causes on which the existence
of the thing depends (see Introduction, page 7):
1. Its final cause: that for which the thing exists, its function, use or perfect
development.
2. Its formal cause: what kind of a thing it is, or what it is able to do.
3. Its material cause: what it is made out of, or exists in.
4. Its efficient cause: what produced it.
The efficient and final causes are often very helpful in defining a thing, but they need not always
be included, since often they are obvious once we know the formal cause. But the formal and
material causes should always be included, except in mathematical definitions, where the formal
cause is sufficient.
How can we state the material and formal cause of a thing in a brief way? A thing is made out of
much the same material as are other things similar to it. For example, a monkey and a man have
very much the same kind of tissues, muscles, and bones in their body. Hence we state the
material cause by mentioning the class of things which most resemble the thing to be defined.
This we call its genus. Nevertheless, the thing to be defined differs in some way from all the
other things in its genus because it has its own special sort of form; this we call its difference.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The two taken together state exactly what kind of a thing it is, and this we call its species or
definition. Thus a man is defined as an animal (genus) who can reason (difference).
A species or definition applies to many individual things which are all essentially alike, but
which differ from each other in unessential ways (color, size, location, etc.). These unessential
differences, which are not included in the most perfect definition of a thing, are called
contingents.*
* Commonly the term "accident" is used instead of "contingent." This leads to confusion, however, since "accident"
can mean two things: (1) A real characteristic of a thing other than its substantial form. This is a "predicamental
accident," and is classified in the last nine categories or predicaments. (2) Anything predicated of a subject in a
contingent way. This is a "predicable accident." It seems better to use the term "accident" for the first meaning, and
"contingent" for the second.
When we define a thing by its genus and difference we have a perfect or essential definition.
Unfortunately we cannot always find the precise difference between one thing and another, so
that frequently in defining a thing we have to substitute something in the definition for the
unknown difference. This can be either a property (that is, some difference which, although it is
not the precise one, nevertheless always marks this thing off from others) or it can be a group of
contingents which taken together are equivalent to a property.
Examples of Definitions
1. The definition given by St. Thomas. In Whether Piety is a Special Virtue? we find the
following definition: "Piety is a special virtue pertaining to justice which pays duty and homage
to our parents and country." This states the species of piety. We can divide this definition into
two parts:
1. The difference: That which makes piety the kind of virtue it is and
distinguishes it from every other kind of justice is that it pays duty and homage to
parents and country. This tells us the form of piety, that is, exactly what kind of
virtue it is.
2. The genus: The class of things which most resemble piety are the other virtues
of justice which pay duty and homage to something.
This tells us the matter or subject of piety since (as St. Thomas has already shown
in previous articles of the Summa) all types of justice exist in the human will.
Thus piety exists in the human will as its subject, or material cause. From the
difference or formal cause of piety we can readily see its efficient and final cause:
3. The final cause of piety (that is, its purpose) is the honor of our family and
country.
4. The efficient cause of piety is practice in honoring parents and country, since it
is by repeatedly giving honor to our parents and country that we develop the
virtue of piety or patriotism. "Practice makes perfect," as the saying goes. When
we are speaking about Christian patriotism, we must also remember that the grace
of God is required to produce this supernatural virtue in us, as well as our
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
cooperation with that grace by keeping the command "honor thy father and thy
mother."
This definition fulfills all the requirements listed above. It is equal in extension to the thing
defined because no other virtue accomplishes this work of honoring parents and country, and all
piety has this function. It is clearer than the thing defined since it is made of more general terms -
- like "virtue," "justice,""duty,""homage,""parents,""country" -- which St. Thomas has already
carefully defined earlier in the Summa. It is not circular, since the notion of "piety" is not
repeated in the statement of either the genus or the difference. It is in positive and not negative
terms. It is as brief as possible and yet complete, since nothing is included in it except the four
causes.
Nevertheless, this definition is really in agreement with that of St. Thomas, although it is less
complete. St. Thomas indicates that piety is a love, not only for country, but also for parents, and
be shows that it is a form of justice. Chesterton, however, obviously intends to include the idea
of justice in his notion of "love," since he insists that this "love" is not mere emotion, but a
rational will to serve the country which has given us so much. St. Thomas in saying that it
renders "duty and homage" obviously implies that we honor our parents not merely for physical
goods, but for the spiritual goods they have given us, since only spiritual things deserve true
honor. Thus the definitions are essentially the same; St. Thomas' definition is scientific,
complete, and precise, while Chesterton's is rougher, less accurate, but more suited to bring out
strikingly the contrast between true patriotism and jingoism. It is to be noted that Chesterton also
brings out the efficient cause of patriotism in the later part of his essay when he shows that one
of the ways to develop patriotism in youngsters is by having them study the great men and events
of their country's history.
3. The definitions of Emerson and Lincoln. Neither Emerson nor Lincoln state their
definitions of patriotism in an explicit way; rather they describe patriotism by giving examples of
it. Thus they picture for us the dead heroes of the Revolutionary and Civil Wars who paid their
debt of duty and homage to their country by fighting and dying for her. They show that the genus
of patriotism is justice by showing us the people of the nation meeting to honor men who did
their duty. Emerson symbolizes this by speaking of the beautiful landscape, the monument, the
gathering of the people, since all these imply that something noble, honorable, and just is being
commemorated. Lincoln speaks of the soldiers as "giving their last full measure of devotion,"
and insists that we must imitate them. Both the act of the soldiers in dying for their country and
our act in honoring and imitating them are acts of justice.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The specific character or difference of patriotism from other forms of justice is brought out by
Emerson in the way he ironically dwells on the tendency of men to forget those who have done
so much for them. These men died that we might be free; they are the fathers of their country and
of us, and yet we forget them! Lincoln makes the same point in his use of the metaphor of birth
and death. These dead have died that we might live. They are most truly our fathers since they
have laid down their life for us. How great our duty, therefore, to give honor to them by imitating
them!
Emerson and Lincoln do not dwell on the efficient cause of patriotism, but with Chesterton they
imply that if we only meditate on what the dead have done for us we will be inspired to honor
and to imitate them.
4. Conclusion. Thus all four pieces give the same definition of patriotism. St. Thomas gives it
in precise, technical form, the other non-scientific writers in a broader, more literary way.
Chesterton only brings out the contrast between true and counterfeit patriotism. Lincoln exhorts
us to imitate the patriotism of the dead and to complete their unfinished work. Emerson helps us
to remember and to honor the patriotism of the past and to feel deeply how noble and precious it
is.
Sometimes a technical definition is given us by an expert, but where did he get it? How can we
be sure that it really fits the thing defined? How could we find one for ourselves? Socrates was
famous for stopping arrogantly confident people in the midst of one of their speeches and asking
them to define their terms. Usually they soon revealed by their confused definitions that they did
not really know what they were saying. It is the special task of dialectics to look for technical
definitions, which can then be used for scientific purposes.
In searching for a real definition we usually begin with a tentative nominal definition, and then
gradually correct it by comparing real things one with another until their similarities and
differences are clearly apparent. This dialectical procedure today is often called "the scientific
method." We begin with a hypothesis, or with a tentative definition, and then see if it fits the
facts of experiment. If it does not, we modify it step by step until we arrive at something more
satisfactory.
This method of searching for a definition by comparison and contrast is what is called
classification. To classify things we arrange them according to genus and difference, so that we
can easily see where any terms fits in and how to define it. Classification saves us much time and
effort, since it saves us from comparing the thing to be defined with everything else: we need
only compare it with the things in the same genus. Here is a scheme which is used for every
classification:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
There can be as many subdivisions as necessary, but the last division is into species, not genera.
You will notice that in each case the difference is added to one species and denied of the other.
When we do not know the essential difference, we make use of a property, or a group of
contingents. These five relations shown by the diagram (genus; difference, or property, or
contingent; and species) and are called the predicables.
A complete classification like the one which we have just diagrammed is called a category.
Obviously it would be a great help in learning and research if we had such a category classifying
all those things which have already been studied and defined by previous researchers. Long ago
Aristotle attempted to do this, but discovered that it is not possible to classify all realities in a
single category as long as we use univocal terms. It is possible, however, to put them in only ten
separate categories, each of which supplies the answers to one of the kinds of questions that a
scientist might ask. We have already studied these ten categories in Chapter I, and seen how the
very structure of our language is based on them (see list of questions and categories on page 45).
When you study fundamental natural science you will learn why there are only these ten
categories. As you learn each part of science you learn each of these classifications as far as it
has been worked out by scientists to the present time. On page 441 ff. there is an outline of each
of them, but they will never be wholly completed, since science goes on discovering new things
to go into each classification.
1. The term must be simple. A complex term like "a white man" has to be split
into two terms. "Man" is classified as substance; "white" is classified as a quality.
2. it must be a whole. We define the part of something by placing it in the same
place in the category as the whole to which it belongs. Thus "human foot" is part
of "man" in the category of substance.
3. it must be something natural. An artificial thing, however, can be defined by its
four causes, and it can be put in the category with the natural thing which it
imitates. On page 460 is a diagram of a classification of artificial things.
4. It must be univocal. Analogical terms have many meanings, and each of them
may go into a different category. We define an analogical term by defining the
meaning which we know best, and then we explain the other meanings as similar
and dissimilar to this fundamental meaning.
Some Examples
"Patriotism" and "virtue" are not things (substances) but qualities. You will find them in their
place in the category of quality on page 446. St. Thomas arrived at his definition of patriotism by
asking himself: Is it a thing that can exist by itself? No. Therefore it is not in the category of
substance. Which of the last nine questions does it answer? Obviously it answers the question
"what sort of thing?" since we say that a man is a patriotic or virtuous kind of man.
Then he went step by step through each division of the classification until he located patriotism
in its right place. Emerson and Lincoln did not need such a systematic classification. Chesterton
was speaking dialectically and hence set up a tentative classification. We might diagram it as
follows:
It is apparent that Chesterton was considering only a small part of the category of quality.
Although Emerson did not make any general classification, he did make use of many of the
categories to show us all the aspects of a thing. You will notice that he speaks of the dead and the
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
stone monument (substance, and in artificial thing made of substance), of the "dark stream," of
the "green bank," the "soft stream," and "free children." The words in italics are all qualities. He
gives us little about quantity except that there were a number of soldiers, and that the time was
long. He speaks of relations: "foe and conqueror," "sire and sons," "to them and thee." He tells us
of place: "by the bridge," "here," "seaward," and of position, since the bridge is "arched" over the
river, and the stone is "on this green bank," "the flag unfurled." The poem, however, does not
mention vestition, although Emerson might have mentioned that the minute-men wore no
uniforms, but their work-clothes. It speaks of action, "fired the shot," "sleeps," "sweeps,"
"creeps," "set," "raise," etc., and of reception, since the bridge is "swept away," and the "deed" is
"redeemed." Finally, it speaks of timing, since the battle was "long ago," "sons" will come in the
future to remember and die in their turn, and we raise the memorial "today."
Both Emerson and Chesterton were philosophical writers, and this is apparent in their habit of
looking at the things they wrote about from many different points of view. The habit of thinking
in terms of categories helps us to develop this orderly and thorough way of looking at the world,
and it will make our writing and speaking rich and varied.
ART OF REASONING
At the beginning of this chapter we said that a scientist has two problems: to find the facts, and to
explain them -- or give their causes. We have seen how dialectics helps us to classify the facts
and to arrive at certain definitions from these facts. It remains to see how a scientist arrives at an
explanation of these facts, first by using demonstration to prove the connection between cause
and effect.
1. The discovery of basic statements from which to reason, which are known to be
true directly from the facts.
2. The process of drawing conclusions from these principles.
In Chapter II we have already studied the nature of a principle or basic statement. For example,
in geometry you have learned that in this science you begin with definitions and with axioms and
postulates (basic statements), and you then proceed to reason to theorems. Definitions, when put
in the form of a statement, are themselves a kind of basic statement.
1. Principles which are immediately evident from the facts, or are known by
human or divine faith.
2. Hypotheses, which are not known to be true, but which are assumed as true, in
order to see what follows from them.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
When we have principles, as in geometry, then we can be certain of the conclusion, and we have
strict science. But when we have hypotheses we are still only in the realm of dialectics, since we
are looking for certitude. A hypothesis is tested by seeing if the conclusions which follow from it
agree with the known facts; this is called verification. But it remains only probable until it can be
seen to be true from the facts themselves by intuition.
Thus geometry is built up on principles known to be true from experience. So are many truths in
natural science, for example, our knowledge of the function of the human heart. Theology is
based on principles known to be true from faith. But many areas of science are based only on
hypotheses. For example, in recent science there have been several different definitions of the
atom, all of which were hypotheses, and which were merely probable. For a long time the
arrangement of the sun and planets was explained by a series of hypotheses. Today several
hypotheses as to the nature of cancer are being used by researchers. Some day a true definition of
cancer will be discovered, and then we will be able to explain the various effects that follow
from it.
A principle is known directly from experience, or taken on faith. When it is taken on faith our
only problem is to be sure that the witness or authority is trustworthy and that we have
understood what he says. If it is taken from experience we must know the facts,
have them clearly defined, and see that the subject and the predicate are necessarily connected.
indeed, most principles are simply definitions put in the form of a statement. Thus the principle
that if equals are added to equals the sums are equal is obviously true once we have defined
"equal" and "added."
When we do not have a principle we must choose a hypothesis. To do this we also examine the
facts and select some definition that might fit them. We then verify it by seeing if this principle is
true, and whether all the facts necessarily follow, as well as other new facts.
Whether we have a principle or a hypothesis the way of arguing or reasoning from it will follow
the same plan.
People who are always arguing can be very tiresome, but argument is necessary if we are ever to
know very much. If we knew nothing but what we can see immediately from our own experience
we would know very little. It is only by reasoning from experience that we come to know that
God or atoms exist, since we can see neither God nor atom. Argument consists in asking "why?",
trying to find the answer, and in stating this answer clearly and precisely.
Sometimes even without reasoning we can see that a new statement is true merely because of its
relation to another. In Chapter II (pages 70-71) it was pointed out that there are four kinds of
statements. If we know that one statement is true we can sometimes be sure at once that another
one composed of the same terms is true or false. For example, if I know that it is true that "every
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
On the other hand, if I know that it is false that "every girl is pretty," I also know that:
1. It is true that some girl is not pretty (the contradictory of this second
statement).
2. It may be true or it may be false that no girl is pretty (the contrary), because of
course some girls may be pretty and some not.
3. It may be true or it may be false that some girl is pretty (the subcontrary).
These relations can be conveniently shown by a diagram which is called the Square of
Opposition
If this square is memorized it will save us from making two common errors in thought:
1. The error of thinking that because "some Irishmen have hot tempers" it must be
true that "every Irishman has a hot temper"; or that because "some Germans are
not hot-tempered," therefore "no German is hot tempered." This is the error called
unwarranted generalization.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
2. The error of thinking that if we prove that it is false that every Irishman is hot-
tempered" that we have proved that no Irishman is hot-tempered"; or that if we
have proved that it is false that "no German is intelligent" that we have proved
that "every German is intelligent." This is the error of mistaking a contrary for a
contradictory.
These relations help us to see how certain truths and falsehoods are related. But they are not
reasoning in the strict sense, because they do not give us a new truth; rather they indicate a new
statement of a truth already known, since each of these sets of statements is still composed only
of the same two terms, with different quantities and qualities (see pages 69-70).
To arrive at a really new truth by reasoning we must make use of a third term. Thus when we
say "the front teeth of a dog are sharp," we may know from experience, by looking at the teeth,
that this is true. But we may also know it by reasoning: "The front teeth of a dog are sharp,
because it eats meat." Here we have three terms: the subject (front teeth of a dog), a predicate
(sharp), and a third term which is the cause that the predicate belongs to the subject (because it
eats meat).
All reasoning consists in seeing the connection of a predicate with a subject by means of a third
or middle term. We settle an argument between two sides by finding this middle term.
The third or middle term may be of two sorts: it may be a universal distributive term, or it may
be a particular term (see page 70). It would be an unwarranted generalization, however, to link a
subject with a predicate through a particular term, so that to reason through particulars we must
have a list of them that is equivalent to a universal.
An argument in which the middle term is a universal is called a syllogism (from the Greek for
"linking together of words or ideas"), and an argument in which the middle term is a list of
particulars is called an induction (Latin for "leading to," because it leads from particulars to a
universal).
THE SYLLOGISM
1. In ordinary speech we say, "A is B, because of C; "the teeth of a dog are sharp
because it eats meat." This way of writing a syllogism is very simple, but it is a
complex sentence. If we turn it into simple sentences we get a second way of
writing the syllogism, which is clearer and more accurate.
2. This second way is to state the syllogism in three simple sentences:
In the syllogism written out in this way we have two truths called premises or principles, and a
third, called the conclusion. To see how to form a syllogism correctly, one may begin by writing
the conclusion. The predicate of this conclusion is called the major term (because the predicate
is like the form in a statement, and form is greater than its matter; see pages 69-70). The major
term combined with the middle term makes the major premise. The subject of the conclusion is
called the minor term, and combined with the middle term it makes the minor premise.
Ordinarily we write the major premise first, and the minor second, but this order is not really
important.
You will notice that only the middle term occurs in both premises, but that it does not appear in
the conclusion.
Since the two premises might be any one of the four kinds of statements contained in the square
of opposition (see page 139), we might have a large number of different arrangements or forms
(also called "modes") of the syllogism. Many of these, however, do not produce a genuine
syllogism because in them the middle term is not universal or does not connect the major and the
minor terms in a definite way. When tested (see page 572), only 14 arrangements are found to be
useful. Even these can all be rearranged so as to give only four basic modes, and these are the
ones most commonly used.
In the. Middle Ages these were given rather odd names (the reason for them is explained on page
572. They are:
It is obvious that Darii and Ferio are only weaker forms of Barbara and Celárent respectively, so
that only Barbara and Celárent are of fundamental importance.
The Induction
The induction can be written in the same form as the syllogism, except that the middle term is a
list of particulars. The premise which we used in our example of the syllogism above ("teeth for
meat-eating are sharp") might be proved by an induction as follows:
These two basic forms of reasoning, the syllogism and induction, also have abbreviated forms
and expanded forms. Thus when one or the other of the premises of a syllogism is obvious, we
may omit mentioning it. Sometimes we may merely state the premises and let our audience
dram, the conclusion. These abbreviated forms of the syllogism are called enthymemes. The
induction can be abbreviated by mentioning a single typical case instead of giving the whole list,
For example, in the above induction we might simply have said, "lions, etc. have sharp teeth."
This is called an example.
The most important expanded form of the syllogism is called a hypothetical syllogism., because
its premises are made up of complex sentences rather than simple ones. For example:
If the teeth of a dog are for meat-eating, then they will be sharp.
And: the teeth of a dog are for meat-eating.
Therefore: they are sharp.
A study of this example will show that it can be simplified by rewriting it as a simple syllogism
in the form given above (see page 141). An important type of hypothetical reasoning often used
in mathematics is the reduction to absurdity. It takes the following form:
The article of St. Thomas, Whether Piety Is a Special Virtue? is written in so clear a style that it
can easily be turned into a series of syllogisms (see pages 173 ff.). The easiest way is to work
backward from the conclusion to discover and formulate a syllogism, In his reply St. Thomas
proves the following conclusion: Piety is a special virtue of justice. The subject of this
conclusion will be the minor term and the subject of the minor premise. The predicate of this
conclusion will be the major term and the predicate of the major premise. Consequently we can
at once write the following skeleton of the syllogism:
*You will recall that universal affirmative statements start with "Every" or "All" (the meaning is the same in
English), while universal negative statements start with "No" or "Not any." Particular statements start with "Some."
See page 70.
It only remains to find the middle term (M) which is the cause of the truth of the conclusion. It
can be found by asking, "Because of what is all piety a special virtue?" We see that St. Thomas
answers: "Because it renders a special debt." Thus we can fill in the whole syllogism:
Another example can be found in Objection 2. The conclusion here is: No piety is distinguished
from religion. If we write this out we get:
It will be noticed that the negative is placed in the major premise and the conclusion. Now if we
look for the middle term, we will find that it is: "because piety renders worship to God," and we
can write the following syllogism:
No virtue which
renders worship to God is distinguished from the
virtue of religion.
And: all piety is virtue which renders
worship to God.
Therefore: no piety is distinguished from the
virtue of religion.
The first of our two complete syllogisms has premises which are both affirmative universal
statements, which is the figure ("form" or "mode") called Barbara. The second complete
syllogism has a negative universal major, and an affirmative universal minor, which is the figure
called Celarent. By altering the minor to a particular statement (changing "all piety" to "some
piety") we convert the two syllogisms into Darii and Ferio, respectively.
Example of Induction
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
This article does not contain an obvious example of induction, but it is easy to form an induction
as follows. Write out some universal conclusion to be proved, then form a syllogism just as we
have done before, but instead of a universal middle term find a list of particulars which are
equivalent to a middle term. For example, let us suppose that we wish to prove by induction the
major premises of the two syllogisms we have already given. The result will be as follows:
Our two syllogisms could be converted into enthymemes merely by abbreviating them. Thus:
Enthymeme: All piety is a special virtue of justice, because all piety renders a
special debt.
When the argument is stated this way we assume that the hearer understands the other premise,
namely, that "every virtue that renders a special debt is a special virtue of justice." On the other
hand we might say:
Enthymeme: All piety is a special virtue of justice, because every virtue that
renders a special debt is a special virtue of justice.
Similarly we can convert our inductions into examples simply by giving one clear case, instead
of a list. Thus:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Religion is a special virtue of justice and it renders a special debt; therefore every
virtue which renders a special debt is a special virtue of justice.
Devotion is not distinguished from the virtue of religion and it renders worship to
God; therefore no virtue which renders worship to God is distinguished from the
virtue of religion.
It should be clear from these passages that our inductions and examples are not certain
arguments, but only probable, unless backed up by more evidence. To be certain, an induction
must deal with matters which we know so well that we have certitude that our list of examples is
either complete or a representative sample.
St. Thomas does not use a hypothetical syllogism in this particular article, but it is easy to state
the objections given here as hypothetical and conditional syllogisms. For example, Objection 2
could be written:
USING ARGUMENTS
POETIC ARGUMENTS
At first sight it seems very odd to speak of an "argument" in a poem or novel, although we may
have noticed that sometimes the summary of a play is called its "argument." The purpose of
poetry does not seem to be to prove anything, nor to persuade anyone. Its true purpose is to
recreate us by arousing our emotions and bringing them to rest in the pleasure of contemplating
some beautiful truth about human life. It gives us this refreshment and joy, not by "arguing," but
by representing (imitating) some individual human action; that is, it tells a story.
But a story does contain a real argument. In entering into the story of another person, we come to
see much more than a mere series of particular events. We also become aware of something
universal which is exemplified in this particular story. We begin to see the great truths of human
life and of the order of the universe in which man lives, The philosopher, Aristotle, said that
"poetry is more philosophical than history," because history presents us with particular facts,
while the poet, novelist, or playwright presents a story in such a way that the universal truth
shines through its details.
Furthermore we do not merely watch the unfolding of this story as outsiders. We enter into it
sympathetically, sharing in the emotions of the actors. The rhetorician helps its to see the truth of
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
his conclusion by giving us something of his own feelings. Under the spell of his persuasion we
hate what he hates and love what he loves, The rhetorician is trying to get us to act with him. The
purpose of the poet is different. He casts an enchantment over us, not in order to get us to do
something, but to fascinate us with the beautiful vision which he sees. We seem to enter a
different world than the practical world of every day. We are not persuaded to act ourselves, but
rather to enter by contemplation into the lives and actions of others.
The rhetorician arouses our emotions and focuses them so that we resolve to act. He is successful
if we get up and leave him and set to work carrying out what he has proposed, The poet first
arouses our emotions, but then he brings them to a delightful calm in which we share his vision
of life. We are refreshed to carry on our own work in the light of a deeper insight into life, but
we do not feel that we have been urged to go forth; rather the poet invites us to return to
contemplation as soon as we may.
This special power of the poetic argument over the emotions is called by Aristotle catharsis or
purification. In daily life only the wisest of men are able to look at the world calmly and
contemplatively. Most of us are so "upset" with the problems of life, its desires, its fears, its
anxieties, and its frustrations, that we cannot stand back and see the beauty and pattern of life.
We are like soldiers in a parade who are so busy keeping step that they cannot see the beauty of
the marching formation. The wise man after years of experience and discipline is able even in the
midst of troubles to maintain this calmness and objectivity and to enjoy life as it is. His emotions
are purified and harmonious, like perfect music, leaving his mind clear and penetrating. This
calm philosophical vision is beyond most of us, and even the philosopher grows tired and out-of-
sorts. Consequently the poet, artist, and musician are greatly needed in society, because they
have the secret spell of giving to us for a few passing moments something of this wonderful calm
and clarity of vision. They enchant the boy or girl who is ordinarily too restless to be still, they
awaken the care-ridden adult to think of more beautiful things than business or household
worries, they refresh even the wise man in his times of weariness with this world.
The poet purifies our emotions first of all by arousing them and setting them free from their
fixation on our everyday worries. He does this by helping us to enter into the emotional
experience of others, that is, of the characters in a story. Then he sets these emotions moving in a
harmonious, patterned way as the story builds up in a unified powerful action. And finally, as the
story reaches its close, he brings those emotions to rest in a sense of fulfillment and completion
as we see the pattern of action coming to a perfect end.
As this pattern of action emerges and we begin to see the parts of the story fall into place, the
universal truth which it contains begins to become very clear to us and gives meaning and order
to all that has taken place. Thus as our emotions are brought to a satisfying rest, our minds are
filled with a wide and universal vision of truth. It is like the climb up a mountain. At the moment
that we are able to rest at the top after a long climb, we also look around and see the world
spread out before us below in all its glory.
We should not make the mistake, however, of thinking that the value of poetic argument consists
only in the conclusion. Some people are fond of searching for the "moral" of a novel or play, and
disregarding the story itself, as if it were a mere sugar-coating intended to make the moral "go
down easy." This is just as wrong as to think that the force of a syllogism lies in its conclusion.
Rather the force and power of the syllogism lie in its middle term, because it is the middle term
which is like a light by which we see the truth of the conclusion. Similarly, in the poetic
argument the story and its accompanying purification of emotion is the middle term by which we
see the universal truth. In both cases, once the middle term is removed, the conclusion remains
dark and unilluminated. We know that it is true, but we do not remember why it is true. Only
while we are actually experiencing and enjoying a work of art do we see clearly into the truth
which is contained in it.
Thus the play Macbeth contains the universal truth that "evil ambition works its own
destruction." It is easy to put that truth into a single statement, but it is not so easy to realize that
truth in our own minds. It is only as we watch the actual play unfold, and share the feelings of
Macbeth in his apparent triumph and his terrible failure, that we really appreciate what that truth
means.
Thus, from a logical point of view, a story is a typical case of some universal truth, which serves
as a middle term through which that truth is known. It must therefore be an example or
abbreviated induction (see page 143). It differs from an example used in arithmetic or science
because it not only strikes our minds but also moves our feelings. It differs from an example used
in rhetoric in that it is intended, not to prove that we must do something, but rather to give us a
vision of life. This is why in rhetoric an example is ordinarily merely incidental, while in a poetic
work it forms the whole argument.
Sometimes it is objected that if the purpose of a poetic argument were to show a universal truth,
it would not be so concrete and detailed. The answer is that the more particular and concrete an
example is, the more vivid it will be to our imaginations. This is necessary since nothing moves
our emotions unless it can in some way be imagined. Hence characters in a story which are mere
"types" seem dull and uninteresting. As Shakespeare says, a poet must "give to airy nothings"
(abstract truths) "a local habitation and a name"; that is, he must make them vividly concrete.
That is why the poetic argument is said to be an imitation or representation of life, since it
presents the truth to us embodied in particular people and particular actions which live and move
before us like life itself. On the other hand, such an imitation is not a mere photograph or
historical record. It is an "imitation of nature," that is, of the inner and essential natures of things.
The poetic writer does not merely copy or record outer appearances. He studies life so as to find
truth and meaning in it, and to bring out this inner nature by the careful selection and
manifestation of what is universal and important. In Macbeth, for example, we do not have a
mere record of events. Shakespeare chooses every detail of his story to bring out the truth which
it contains, to manifest the true nature of ambition.
In this way the story, or plot, is the very soul of a poem, novel, or play, that which gives unity to
all its parts. For it is only in action that human beings become fully alive and manifest their inner
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
nature or character. Through the action we know the characters themselves, their emotions,
desires, and feelings. We also know their thoughts, or the reasons and motives which influence
them to act or by which they disguise their real motives. So the objects represented in a story are
first the plot or action (the principal object) and then the characters and their thoughts
(secondary objects). These last two are secondary because thought is important to the story only
as it results in action, and character is known to us and becomes fully itself only in action.
Since the plot is the soul of the poetic work it must be unified; otherwise it could not weld the
parts of the work into a perfect whole. It is unified when it consists of only one principal action.
There may be other interwoven subplots, but these must strengthen the main plot by emphasis or
contrast, not confuse or hinder it. Nothing should be admitted to the story that does not
contribute to this main plot, although in some types of writing (particularly the novel), we permit
a looser sort of organization than we expect in an intensely moving play, short story, or lyric.
The plot also must be complete or it will leave us unsatisfied. To be complete it must have a
beginning in which a new action arises from some situation. This new action should unfold in a
series of connected events or episodes which form the middle of the story, and these should lead
to a final rest or resolution (the end) in which all the forces set in motion at the beginning work
themselves out. These requirements seem rather obvious, but many plays and stories are faulty
because the writer is either too slow in getting his action started, or because be does not work out
the middle in a series of connected but contrasted episodes, or because -- and this is the hardest
task of all -- the writer cannot bring the forces set in motion to a real rest and conclusion.
Sometimes a plot is simple, and then its action moves in one straight line from beginning to end.
More interesting is the complex plot in which the action first seems to move toward one goal and
then suddenly reverses itself and moves toward a contrary goal. This reversal is also often called
the climax of the play, while the resolution or ending is called the denouement. The magnitude,
or length, of a story or poem (the number of episodes, etc.) must be sufficient for the forces set in
motion to work themselves out, but should be no longer than necessary.
Any argument to have value must be true. In a plot the truth consists in the probability with
which one episode leads to another. This probability comes from the universal truth which it
embodies. Consequently we think a plot is very poor and improbable when it is resolved by some
chance event (the rich uncle who dies and leaves our hero a fortune, etc.), because we know that
true human happiness does not depend on chance but on the providence of God and the virtue of
man. On the other hand, we think that a solution to a plot is very good when, in a surprising and
unexpected way, the beginning leads to a result which is seen to be logical and in accordance
with the laws of providence and of human life.
The characters who carry out this action must appear to be consistent and like real human
beings, and they must be appropriate to the type of action they are to perform, otherwise they
will make the plot itself seem improbable. It is in the characters that we see both the outward
action and the inward action or emotion. It is our share in the emotions of the characters which
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
helps us to enter into their experiences and to understand them more fully than if they were only
known in an abstract way.
It seems strange to many that so many great works of art have sad endings. A child or a very
simple person often dislikes stories that end sadly, but as people become mature they also see a
beauty and joy in a sad story or tragedy. Why is this? All emotion begins with love (that is,
seeing that something is good or pleasant), or with hate (seeing that something is bad or painful).
If we see that what we love can be possessed, we begin to move toward it and we experience the
emotion of desire. If we actually possess it and enjoy it, we feel the emotion of joy. Sometimes,
however, we find that there is an obstacle in our way, and this makes it difficult to obtain what
we want. Then our desire becomes hope, or the conviction that by effort we can have what we
want in spite of the difficulty. As we make an effort to overcome this difficulty, we experience
courage, the spirit of effort and of battle, and then at last, if we conquer the difficulty and
achieve our goal, we end in joy.
On the other band, if we see something hateful and see it approaching, we feel aversion, or a
desire to get away. If it actually meets us, then we feel sorrow. Perhaps, however, as the hateful
object approaches us and our aversion grows, we see the possibility of escaping, and of
achieving the opposite good, although at the price of an effort. Then we experience hope,
courage, and, if we succeed, joy. But if we see that the difficulty may be too great either to
escape the evil we dislike or gain the good we desire, then we begin to feel fear or anxiety; and if
it becomes clear that the difficulty is certainly too great, then despair overcomes us. As the evil
finally seizes us we may still struggle for a while , thinking that escape or revenge is still
possible, and then we feel anger. But if no escape is possible, then sorrow begins. Thus all
emotion begins with love or hate, turns to hope or fear if difficulty appears, and ends in joy or
sorrow.
Because of this interplay of our emotions, a story with a joyful ending is pleasant both because it
brings our emotions to rest in the vision of truth, and because joy itself is pleasant. Sorrowful
endings bring our emotions to rest, but sorrow is not pleasant to the normal person. How, then,
can a sorrowful ending be pleasant? The pleasure is not in the sorrow, which is a painful thing,
but in the rest in truth which we have achieved through sorrowful experience. As we see the
death of a hero whom we loved, we feel sorrow, but our mind is also filled with delight that he
has proved his nobility of character even at the price of death. This higher joy is worth the
sorrow. Even when we see a great man punished for crime, we feel a joy in seeing that the law of
justice in the universe has been preserved, and that this noble man has come to acknowledge and
recognize his fault and repent.
This is why a tragedy is sometimes a greater work of art and a more real refreshment of our soul
than is a comedy with a happy ending. The happy ending may give us a superficial joy, but the
joy at the end of a tragedy is deeper and more complete, since it points to eternal things and not
merely to something temporary. A fairy tale ends with "they lived happily ever after," but we are
not so sure that they really did. The story of our Lord's death on the cross, however, is really
much more emotionally satisfying for our souls, for in it we see that he has gained an everlasting
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
victory over sin and death. Thus the catharsis or purification of the emotions in a tragedy is very
deep and great, and it leads to a wonderful peace and insight into the real meaning of human life,
which is sorrowful here in order that it may be joyful hereafter.
1. The plot of the poem. The "Concord Hymn" is a type of short poem called a lyric. In such
poetry the plot is not as obvious as in a narrative work like an epic poem or a novel. Nonetheless
there is a plot. What happens in the "Concord Hymn"? The action can be summarized as follows:
"As we come to erect a monument on this almost forgotten battlefield, we begin to realize how
much we owe to those who died here and bow little gratitude we have shown, and we feel moved
to pray that future generations will better honor and preserve their heritage of freedom." This is a
little story, which has a beginning, a middle, and an end:
Consequently we have the story, not of some external action, but rather of the internal thought
and feeling of Emerson and the group for whom he speaks. It will be noticed that what is
expressed is not merely thought, but also the arousal and quieting of the emotions called the
catharsis of feeling, which is the characteristic of all poetic argument. The first stanza indicates a
feeling of wonder or desire to understand and then awe, a kind of fear which we feel when
suddenly confronted with something great and unknown. Emerson suddenly begins to realize
what a great historic spot this is which he has so often passed without even thinking of it. This
awe deepens in the second stanza into a sense of sorrow and of shame, mixed with a certain
indignation or anger, at the thought of the ingratitude and forgetfulness with which the dead have
been treated. Then in the third stanza the emotion begins to resolve itself as he turns to the
monument with the determination and courage to make up for the past by placing the monument,
and yet with a feeling that this is not enough. Finally, in the last stanza the emotion turns to one
of solemn reverence and of hope, even of joy, to think that God, who is eternal and unforgetting,
will never let the memory or the example of the heroic dead die, however men may forget.
love-desire-fear-anger-resolve-humility-hope-joy.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
This last emotion brings the poem to a close, since all emotion ends either in sorrow and
resignation, or in joy and delight. This emotion reinforces and blends with the thought, so that
our sense of surprise in the first stanza helps us to realize the greatness of the battle, and our
feeling of prayer and hope in the last stanza brings us face to face with the realization that the
true honor due to patriotism comes from God who rewards all things justly.
2. The argument of the poem. How is this an argument? Emerson has told the story of one
group of men who, on a particular occasion, began to realize how much patriotism deserves to be
honored and how frequently it is forgotten. Furthermore he tells us this story in such a concrete
way that we ourselves experience his feelings and his realization of truth. Consequently we have
before us an example, or abbreviated induction, by which we arrive at a general truth, namely,
that "Patriotism is very honorable," or that "Patriotism is a great virtue."
This truth in its abstract statement does not enter our mind as we read the poem. Rather while
simply listening to the story and entering into its emotion we come step by step to see this truth
without formulating it in any other words than those of the poem itself.
the argument of the poem would have been destroyed, because the truth would no longer be
presented to us as embodied in a story or example, and the emotion would be jarred and
destroyed. This is the reason why many people dislike literary writing and especially poetry.
They look for the writer to say "plainly and in so many words" what he means. They do not
understand that the meaning of such an argument has to be conveyed and enjoyed in the story
itself and not outside of it, and that yet there is a meaning, a universal truth, which we realize
very deeply as we come to the end of the story. Indeed, Emerson's poem probably makes us
appreciate patriotism much more than a piece of rhetoric Would do, because its quiet reflective
tone makes us aware of the reality of patriotism without my effort to persuade us or to moralize.
3. The role of the characters in poetic argument. The story is the chief thing in this poem
as in every poem, since it gives the whole shape, unity, and meaning to the work. The story
would not be possible, however, unless it happened to some character or characters. Who are
the characters here? Obviously the chief character is not a single individual, but rather the whole
group, the people of America who have come to raise the monument, the "we" of the poem.
Does the poet characterize these people in any way? Not directly. But indirectly he shows us that
they are simple, sincere, and frank, that they have the nobility to be ashamed of having forgotten
and the humility to admit their weakness, that they are busy people looking to the future and
hence likely to forget, and finally that they are a reverent and courageous people with confidence
in God. One of the reasons this poem is so beautiful is that the movement of emotions which it
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
contains shows us the soul of the American people as we like to believe it is: simple, reverent,
humble, courageous.
The other characters are the dead, both the heroic Americans and their foe, and the Americans of
the future. Nothing much is said about any of these except the dead heroes, and they are shown
us in a simple vivid picture at the great moment of the battle when they fired the first shot. This
is enough, however, to make us think of them as simple (because farmers) but mighty and
courageous men (they fired the shot heard round the world). It is better that they be characterized
only in this simple fashion, since it makes them a better symbol.
4. The thought of the poem. The thought of the poem is the connection of ideas expressed by
the chief character. It has an interest all of its own. First of all, in the opening stanza we see a
connection established between a very small event (the first shot) and a tremendous consequence
(heard round the world). Why was this action a world-wide event? Not merely because it began a
war, but because the American Revolution was taken as a model by peoples all over the world
whom it encouraged to overthrow governments that denied human rights.
In the second stanza there is the interest of the ironic contrast between the men opposed in battle
who now rest side by side, and the philosophical thought that Time runs on, bearing everything
away. In the third stanza our thoughts go into the future. What will become of America
tomorrow? In the last stanza we have the deepest thought of all. Behind Time and Nature is a
God. It was his providence that made this little battle so important in its consequence. It is his
will that men should be free. He inspired the Minutemen to fight; he will not fail to help our
country in the time to come, if we turn to him. We might wonder why Emerson calls God the
"Spirit." Is it not a rather impersonal way to speak of God? Is it, perhaps, because Emerson is
thinking of God more as a force than as a person?
5. Evaluation of the poem. If we consider whether the poet has used plot, character, and
thought well, we will notice that he has kept the character in the background and revealed it
mainly through plot. This is effective, since character exists to serve plot, not the other way
around. The character is thus appropriate to the plot, and it is also lifelike, since the succession of
emotions and the consistency of one emotion with another is maintained. It is very natural that
from wonder and awe at the sense of the historic spot, we should then begin to feel the other
emotions mentioned in their proper order. Hence the plot is probable, because from the first
event and emotion the others follow step by step to a complete catharsis. The thought in this
poem is also subordinated to the succession of emotions which are the main events of the story,
and yet it is interesting because it is awake to the significance of events. It perceives their irony,
and at last arrives at a deep understanding of them.
RHETORICAL ARGUMENTS
The Purpose of Rhetoric
one will try to do what is impossible, nor to take into consideration what is not likely to happen,
nor to concern himself about something which seems trivial.
The poetic writer makes every work into a single example or story. The rhetorician might also
do this (see our Lord's beautiful sermon on the prodigal son), but ordinarily he only uses
examples as an incidental device, and then they are usually historical examples,
because a thing is more convincing in a practical way if it actually happened. The chief argument
of the rhetorician is not the example or shortened induction, but the enthymeme or shortened
syllogism.
In the enthymeme the rhetorician leaves one premise implicit. This premise must be some
opinion which he knows the whole audience will accept without argument. He then bends his
effort to setting the other premise before them in the most favorable light possible. If they will
accept this second premise, then they will readily accept the conclusion. Indeed, occasionally the
rhetorician lets them draw this conclusion for themselves, as, for example, Mark Anthony does
in his funeral oration in Shakespeare's Julius Caesar. This is why the enthymeme is so suitable
for rhetoric, because it builds on a premise already accepted and has only to establish one point
in order to produce the desired conclusion.
Both of these require the rhetorician to understand the likes and dislikes of the people to whom
he has to speak. He must understand the emotions just as the poet does, but be must also know
how to arouse them or quiet them in people of a certain type.
For this reason he must ask himself, before addressing a particular group, whether they are
united by their virtue (for example, an audience of priests, sisters, doctors, lawyers, or experts of
some sort), or by their riches (an audience of businessmen), or their poverty (a crowd in the
street). He must also consider their nationality, religion, and education, and whether they are
young, middle-aged, or old.
In order to sway all these classes of people, the rhetorician concerns himself with arousing love
and hate, anger and benevolence, fear, shame, kindness, pity, or envy. He does not do so,
however, in order to make men act from blind emotion like animals. To do that would be vicious
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
and sinful. The rhetorician appeals to men's emotions to lead them to truth and to a more
reasonable way of acting. He studies selfish and evil emotions, not in order to produce them, but
in order to prevent them from interfering with right action.
If the rhetorician is to move men to do what is right, he must not merely advertise any product he
is hired to sell, promote any program adopted by his political party, or defend any criminal who
hires him as a lawyer. He must know ethics, or the art of good human living, so that he
understands what is truly virtuous and honorable, and be must have a thoughtful acquaintance
with politics and practical affairs.
1. Character of the speaker. If we examine the "Gettysburg Address" for its argument, we
notice first of all that Lincoln is well aware of the attitudes of his audience, and takes care to
establish his true character to them, since the character of the speaker is the first argument in
rhetoric. Lincoln knows that the audience doubts that be is anything more than a cheap politician,
and they rather expect him to make an awkward and tasteless speech defending himself and his
administration of the war. They will contrast him unfavorably with the polished orator, Edward
Everett, who has just spoken so well and at great length.
Consequently, Lincoln first of all aims at giving the impression of great dignity and sincerity. He
shows himself a man who is a statesman far above all mere partisanship, and who has no desire
whatsoever merely to make an impression. He is simple, solemn, deeply moved. And he looks
toward the future with the realization of great responsibility.
2. The argument of the address. Next we notice the actual argument. The main conclusion
is: "We should continue the war for democracy." Why? The cause for this conclusion is:
"Because this is the best way to honor the dead." If we state this as a syllogism we get:
This syllogism is only stated by Lincoln in abbreviated form as an enthymeme. The minor
premise is omitted, because everybody agreed that the dead were patriots to be greatly honored.
To dwell on that point would have been useless. It might even have raised disturbing questions;
some of his audience might have begun to ask themselves: "Were these men fools to enlist in the
army for a war started by politicians like Mr. Lincoln?" Lincoln did not risk stirring up these
prejudices, but took full advantage of the united conviction of the crowd that the dead ought to
be honored. He dwelt only on the idea that no honor for these men could be sufficient, except the
completion of the war in which they had died.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
This idea, however, was not immediately acceptable to his audience, because (as Lincoln well
understood) many of them did not appreciate the greatness of the cause for which these men had
died, or what they had fought to accomplish. Therefore Lincoln made this the main burden of his
speech.
1. He pointed out that mere ceremony and speech-making was no adequate honor
for the dead. This he established very quickly and briefly in the middle section of
his speech, sentences five to seven.
2. He pointed out the greatness of the cause for which these men died. This
occupied most of the speech, both its beginning and its end.
This second part is one of amplification, as it is called -- namely, to show that something is great
and important. Lincoln began in the first sentence of his speech by recalling a previous example
of a great historical event, the founding of our country. He was implying that just as the founding
of our country had consequences for the whole world, so would the Civil War. The founding of
our country was a birth, the Civil War would result in rebirth. In this way he clothed the Civil
War dead with the acknowledged greatness of the founders of the Republic. Lincoln emphasized
this comparison in sentences two and four of his speech. Then in sentences five and seven he
introduced the other part of his argument, the inadequacy of mere words to honor the dead. This
was a problem of depreciation, the reverse of amplification. In sentences eight and nine he
returned to the main point. Sentence eight is really the climax of the speech since it states the
conclusion. Sentence nine drives this home by bringing forward two arguments:
Lincoln saves this last argument for the end, and he clinches it by the saying that ". . . (true
freedom is) government of the people, by the people, and for the people." This is a kind of
maxim, or pithy saying, which is an effective rhetorical device because it sticks in the memory of
the hearers. It can be written thus:
In dialectical and scientific arguments the problem of emotion is left entirely out of
consideration. In these arguments the only problem is that of objective facts and of finding
explanations of facts. It is presupposed that the audience for such arguments is honest and fair-
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
minded and ready to listen to the evidence "without prejudice. If this is not the case, then it is
necessary first to clear away their prejudices by the use of rhetoric.
In objective, scientific research we begin with a problem or question. It can be one of four
questions:
1. Does S exist?
2. What kind of a thing is S?
3. Does S have the property P?
4. Why does S have the property P? (the cause)
If we are not curious about each of these questions we will not want to learn anything. Science
must begin with wonder. If we are curious, then we will ask these four questions in the order
above. For example, Madame Curie, who discovered radium, posed the following problems (see
page 552 ff.).
It took her many years of research to find the answer even to the first question.
In some sciences the first two questions are very easy to answer. In mathematics a teacher can
show us in a few seconds that there is such a thing as a triangle and a circle merely by drawing
them on the blackboard, and she can then quickly show how they must be defined so as to
distinguish a triangle from a square, or a circle from an ellipse. These definitions are first
principles, or immediately known truths. Once we understand them the rest of mathematics is
very clear and certain.
In most sciences, however, the first two questions are hard to answer. We cannot find definitions
or basic principles in these sciences without long research like that of Madame Curie. The
dialectical argument is the one which we must use in this research, since it only requires
probable principles. The strict scientific argument or demonstration (for example, those in
mathematics) cannot be used until we have certain principles and have already answered the first
two of our questions.
The dialectician proceeds to establish a real definition in the way we have already described in
Chapter II. He begins with nominal definitions, which are the opinions that are commonly held.
These may be common opinions, or they may be the opinions of experts. Then he makes a
classification by comparing what is the same and what is different, and arranging his terms
according to the predicables of genus, difference, species, property, and contingent (as we
have already shown), until he finally locates the correct definition. Madame Curie kept trying to
separate, from the mixture in the laboratory, the various chemicals which already fitted into a
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
known classification, until she had isolated a new element and fitted it into a place in the
classification that was previously blank.
The dialectician prepares the way for science in another fashion, namely, by refuting false
opinions or theories. Until these have been eliminated, the true principles will be hard to separate
from the false. Ultimately a theory may be shown to be false by the discovery of some new fact,
but dialectics will often eliminate a theory on the grounds that it is inconsistent, or that it
disagrees with facts already known but whose significance has been missed.
In refuting these false views the dialectician uses the method called distinguishing an argument.
It is based on the fact that many arguments which seem to be true are really the result of
equivocal terms (see page 49). Since a syllogism will be invalid if it contains more than three
terms, we can destroy an opponent's argument by showing that he has used a term in two senses
in his syllogism, thus using four instead of three terms.
For an example, let us suppose that we wish to refute the following theory:
1. By distinguishing the middle term. In this case we use the following method: I concede
the major premise in the sense that "every cold-blooded animal that swims is a fish," but I deny it
if it means that "every animal, even a warm-blooded one, that swims is a fish." As to the minor
premise, I distinguish it in the contrary sense, and deny that "whales are cold-blooded animals
that swim," while conceding that "whales are warm-blooded animals that swim." Thus there is no
middle term found in both premises taken in the sense in which they are true, so that no
conclusion follows.
Written out this would appear as follows, and would be called a contradistinction:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
2. By distinguishing either the major or minor term. In this case we use the following
method: I concede the major premise in the sense that "every animal that swims is a 'fish' as this
word is popularly used," but I deny it in the sense that "every animal is a 'fish' in the technical
sense." The minor I concede. The conclusion I distinguish in the same way as the major,
conceding that "whales are 'fish' in the popular sense," but denying that "whales are 'fish' in the
technical sense." If the minor term is the one distinguished, then the major premise will be
conceded, and the conclusion will be distinguished.
In our example the term "whales" is difficult to distinguish. But it is sometimes used in a strict
sense of the mammal called a whale, and sometimes in a broad sense of any large thing that
swims, that is, in the sense of a sea-monster. Using such a distinction we would get the following
in which we also have an example of the third way in which a premise may be treated, since
when we can neither affirm nor deny its truth, we may pass over it, and deny that the conclusion
has been proved.
In this last case we would not deny the second sense of the minor (since it is true but not
relevant) but would say, "That some whales taken in the strict sense are animals that swim," I do
not deny, but I pass over as irrelevant to the argument. In distinguishing, we should attempt to
distinguish the middle term if possible, since this destroys the whole conclusion. If we cannot
distinguish it, then we should first try the major and then the minor term.
This art of distinguishing makes it possible to refute an opponent and yet to agree with him as
much as possible. It will also permit us to escape the ordinary fallacies in reasoning by which the
opponent appears to prove something without really doing so.
1. Make sure you understand what the opponent is saying, and state the two sides
fairly, so that he will agree with your statement of his case.
2. Try to agree on every point that you can, or to put aside small disagreements
that are irrelevant.
3. Try to reduce the issue to one single question, and then seek to establish how
this question can be settled in objective way.
4. Present the objective evidence or authority for your position.
The use of dialectic should eventually clear the way for us to establish some statements which
are certainly true, that is, which are necessary and cannot be otherwise. These can be the
principles or premises of a genuine proof or demonstration and are known directly from
experience, not as dialectical conclusions. Dialectics has only led the way to discover these
principles; it has not proved them, since dialectical proofs never yield certain conclusions.
A strict demonstration has the cause of the conclusion as its middle term and is called an a priori
demonstration, that is, one that goes from principles (causes) to effects. The following is an
example:
Here the middle term is "12 cylinders compared to 8" and is the proper cause of automobile A
running faster than B. Sometimes, however, the middle term is not the proper cause, but a
common or remote cause. For example:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The middle term here is a true cause, but only a remote one. It is true that A runs faster because it
has a more powerful engine, but our mind is not satisfied by this answer. We still want to know
"Why is its engine more powerful?" Only when we know the proper cause are we fully satisfied.
Sometimes the middle term is not a cause at all, but an effect. For example, in the following
demonstration:
This argument proves the fact that A is faster than B, but it does not tell us why.
1. Perfect demonstration. This is through a middle term which states the proper
cause. Technically this is called a demonstration which is a priori and propter
quid. These are Latin for "from the cause" and "because of what."
2. Imperfect demonstration:
a. Through a remote cause. This is technically called a priori (through a cause),
but quia (Latin for "that"), because it proves that a fact is true, but does not show
exactly why.
b. Through an effect. This is technically called a posteriori (Latin for "from the
effect"). It is also only quia, because it proves that a fact is true, but does not
show exactly why.
The goal of the scientist is to achieve the first kind of demonstration, which completely satisfies
our minds. In mathematics we can have such demonstrations in every theorem because
mathematics deals with simple abstract quantities. But in other sciences it is hard to have such
perfect demonstrations. For example, the proof that God exists is an a posteriori proof. We know
that God exists because he has created the world, but that is not why he exists.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Every science is organized so as to begin with the most general truths and then to proceed to
study the more special truths. In geometry, for example, we study about the triangle in general
before we study about equilateral, isosceles, and scalene triangles, and in zoology we study about
animals, then vertebrates and invertebrates, and then each kind of vertebrate. This is for two
reasons;
There are as many different sciences and arts as there are different sets of such first principles.
Thus algebra (or arithmetic) is one science, while geometry is another, and Christian doctrine
another, because each has a different set of postulates.
In A Defense of Patriotism, Chesterton assumes one opinion as accepted by all, and he disputes
another.
His problem, therefore, is to try to establish a true definition of patriotism by examining different
definitions.
He asks the question: "Are these two definitions identical, as many people seem to think?" He
answers by listing the different properties of "lust" and "love":
Thus he argues that since the properties of lust and love are different, their essential nature or
definition must be different.
3. Patriotism is to be for your country right or wrong. He then disproves this by, a similar
method, showing that:
1) Love is very sensitive of the honor and virtue of the thing it loves.
2) Patriotism that cares nothing for honor therefore is obviously not love, but only
lust.
This completes the first stage of his argument, which has established that patriotism is love and
not lust. He then asks whether it would be right to say:
This he proceeds to disprove by showing that this kind of 'love" is concerned only with trivial
things. He does this by listing the signs of such patriotism:
1) Patriotism as a love for territory is shown by pride over trade, physical force,
victory in petty battles far away, in colonies, in boastful speeches, and in "fists
and boots."
2) Real patriotism ought to be a pride in central, intellectual things of "the head
and heart," in ideals like those of Pericles and Athens.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
In the final and third stage of his argument he asks the probable cause of the faulty reasoning
which has led to this false view, and states a hypothesis which may, account for the mistake so
many have made. It can be formulated in a syllogism thus:
This completes the main course of Chesterton's argument; he has discovered a correct definition
of patriotism. The genus is "love," and the difference is "of one's country as having great
spiritual qualities." The final part of the essay is an inquiry as to the cause why Englishmen do
not know the great qualities of their country. Chesterton suggests that it is "our unique neglect in
education of our national literature." And what is the cause of this? The emphasis in English
schools on Latin and Greek only. This last argument is a hypothesis. It can be stated in a
syllogism as follows:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
This argument is only a probable one because Chesterton has not shown that the minor premise
is really true. It is not obvious that the study of Greek and Latin necessarily involves the neglect
of the study of English. Thus his argument has led to two conclusions, both of them still
dialectical:
1. The definition of patriotism is a love of one's country for its spiritual qualities,
2. The cause of the decline of true patriotism in England is classical education.
The definition is still only dialectical because it is not clear that it has given us the ultimate
difference. May there not be several types of love of country for its spiritual qualities, of which
patriotism is only one? The other conclusion is also open to doubt since it rests on a premise
which is merely probable.
As a piece of dialectic this article might be criticized on the grounds that Chesterton does not
sufficiently bring out the possible arguments for the false definitions, but builds up one side with
rhetorical devices, instead of giving the other side its fair and objective chance. We must
remember, however, that these essays were intended to provoke thought, not to settle a question.
Hence Chesterton defends the less popular side, knowing that his readers have heard the other
side many times from other sources.
Whether Piety Is a Special Virtue? is a strictly scientific piece of argumentation in which St.
Thomas proves his own answer to the question, and carefully distinguishes the objections of his
opponents. Each of these objections is itself a dialectical syllogism, that is, one which does not
argue to a certain, but only a probable, conclusion.
St. Thomas' argument in his reply to the question can be stated formally as follows:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Thus in this proof the premises go back to definitions. If these definitions are real and essential,
then the proof is strictly demonstrative. St. Thomas has already established these definitions in
previous articles (see pages 130 f.).
Furthermore, it is a demonstration through the proper cause (i.e., it is a priori and propter quid),
since the middle term, "a virtue which has a special relation to its object," states the formal
cause that makes a virtue special, and this is exactly and properly the cause, requiring no other
explanation. To see this better we might ask our self: "Why is John the brother of James?" The
answer would be: "Because they are related as sons of the same parents." Thus the relation is the
very definition or formal cause of being a brother. Similarly, the very reason piety is a special
virtue is because it has a special relation to its object.
The second syllogism also gives us the proper reason or cause why piety has a special relation to
its object; it is because its object is to render a special kind of debt.
The objections and St. Thomas' method of distinguishing each can be formulated as follows:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
DEFINITIONS
(to be memorized)
1. An argument is the product of the third act of the mind by which one truth is known through
its dependence on other truths already known.
1) The premises or antecedent of an argument are these previously known truths,
expressed in statements.
2) The conclusion or consequent of an argument is the truth which is known
through its dependence on the antecedent, and which is expressed in a statement.
2. The major term of an argument is the predicate of its conclusion; the minor term is the
subject of this conclusion.
1) The major premise is that which contains the major term; the minor that which
contains the minor term.
2) The middle term of an argument is that to which the major and minor term are
compared in the antecedent, and through which these terms are shown to be
related.
3. The syllogism is an argument in which the middle term is a distributive universal concept.
1) An enthymeme is an abbreviated syllogism in which one premise, or the
conclusion, is not made explicit.
2) The induction is an argument in which the middle term is a list of particulars.
3) The example is an abbreviated induction in which the middle term is a single
typical case.
4. A perfect demonstration (propter quid) is a syllogism whose middle term is the proper
cause of the conclusion.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
prove each topic sentence. Then rewrite composition in smooth prose style. Each
syllogism or induction should form the matter of a paragraph.
D. Grammar:
Review compound and complex sentences, devices for subordination, and the
formation of smooth running sentences (see E.W., Grade Eleven, Chapters V-X,
or E.G.C., Parts 3 and 4). Show how such sentences are used to show
argumentation, or the dependence of one statement upon another.
Unit III: Using Poetic and Rhetorical Arguments
A. Reading:
Read Macbeth (or some other long play or novel).
1. Try to discover the plot or action of the play and state it in a single sentence.
Does it have a beginning, middle, and end? What are they? How does each act
and each scene contribute to the movement of the plot? Are any unnecessary? Are
there subplots? What is their relation to the main plot? What is the series of
emotions aroused by each stage of the plot? Are they brought to a complete
resolution or catharsis? What is the universal truth embodied in the story and seen
as the play moves to its close? Is the plot probable?
2. Who are the characters? Why is each one necessary to the plot? Does the plot
arise from within the characters, or from their situation? Are the characters
consistent? Appropriate and lifelike? How does the writer reveal the characters to
us?
3. Which speeches of the characters have special interest for their thought? Are
the principles of rhetoric obeyed in the construction of these speeches? How do
they contribute to or detract from the plot?
4. Study the style and diction of selected passages to see how these bring out the
emotion, character, and thought effectively.
B. Writing:
Write a short-story or one-act play, trying to make use of the principles of plot
which you have studied to make the story effective. What emotional effect are
you trying to produce? What truth of life are you trying to exemplify?
C. Reading:
Read a speech or essay which is rhetorical in purpose, for example, one of the war
speeches of Roosevelt or Churchill, or a sermon of Bishop Sheen or Monsignor
Knox.
1. State in a sentence the action or attitude which each speaker wishes to produce.
2. How does the speaker present his character to the audience? What sort of an
audience is he addressing? What are their emotions or prejudices? Which attitude
does he wish to arouse toward himself? What aspect of his character does he show
to produce this attitude?
3. What enthymemes does he use? Write them as syllogisms. Why are these
chosen for the audience in mind? Why does be leave particular premises implicit?
What is the most important argument? Does the speaker anticipate objections of
the audience?
4. Study some current editorials or persuasive articles in newspapers and
magazines in the same way.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
D. Speaking:
Give a short persuasive talk on one of the topics studied in the reading, and have
the class criticize it on basis of rhetorical principles.
E. Grammar:
Attention to punctuation and good organization of composition (see E. W., Grade
Eleven, Chapters XI-XV, or E.G.C., Parts 5 and 8).
Unit IV: Using Dialectical and Scientific Arguments
A. Reading:
Read current articles on a controversial topic (race relations, disarmament,
divorce, etc.). Reduce arguments to syllogisms.
B. Speaking:
Hold a formal debate on the topic, with speeches written beforehand, but
delivered without reading. In constructing debate, use dialectical method (page
161ff.), taking care to arrive at definitions of terms, and to criticize opponent's
definition of terms. Solve his objections by the use of distinctions.
The teacher may use this as an occasion to develop the topic of fallacies in
reasoning. (See John Oesterle, Logic, pp. 191204, with exercises.)
A forum on a similar topic may also be held.
C. Reading:
Read an authoritative solution to the above problem presented by a moral
theologian, contained in a Christian doctrine textbook or in a more scholarly
source. Write out the syllogism of proof. How does the author establish his
premises? Are they from authority, or reason, or both? Which are the immediately
evident premises? Most of these are definitions. How did the author get these
definitions?
Is the conclusion certain? Does it settle all the objections raised in the debate?
D. Writing:
Write a short composition stating the scientific proof of some other conclusion
taken from a social science or natural history course, using arguments given in
textbook or collateral reading.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
CHAPTER IV
The Appreciation of
Complete Works of
Liberal Art
GENERAL RULES
In the preceding chapters we have studied the use of terms, of statements, and of arguments. All
of these are used to make a complete work of liberal art, one in which every detail is fitted
together to contribute to a single purpose, namely, to make clear to the reader or listener the
thesis or central truth which is to be communicated.
In this chapter we will see that all we have previously learned can be used in trying to understand
a work of liberal art as a complete whole in which every part serves its purpose.
RULES OF ANALYSIS
From all that has been previously said, it should be clear enough that in analyzing or composing
any piece of writing or speaking' whether it be poetic, rhetorical, dialectical, or demonstrative in
character, we should apply the following general rules:
In reading or listening to the composition of another we should begin with a tentative answer to
the first two questions, saying to ourselves, "I think that this is what the author is trying to say,
and that he is trying to prove it in this type of discourse." We should then see if the details of the
work (rules 3 to 5) are consistent with this supposed thesis. If they are not, we must admit that
we have probably mistaken the purpose of the author, and we should try another hypothesis,
Only after a very serious attempt to find a single thesis which will explain all the details of the
work should we blame the author for being unclear or inconsistent. Poor readers and listeners are
inclined to blame the author, when it is their own superficial analysis which alone is at fault.
In writing or speaking we should follow the same process. First we should formulate our thesis
very clearly and simply and decide which mode of discourse we are going to use to communicate
it (rules 1 and 2). Then we should carefully define our terms, state and justify our basic
principles, and give our arguments for our thesis (rules 3 to 5). Finally, we should revise our
composition to eliminate everything that is unnecessary and to make sure that we have omitted
nothing which is needed (rule 6).
The actual writing usually can be done only when we are "inspired," that is, when we feel in the
right mood and our imagination is working well. After this "inspired" draft (which, however,
should have been carefully prepared for by preliminary work of research, reflection, outlining,
etc.), we must carefully revise and often painfully correct mistakes and strengthen weak points.
SCIENTIFIC EXPOSITION
When we wish to present a truth in the most perfect and certain form, we use a style of discourse
which combines dialectic and demonstration, and which aims at being as clear and precise as
possible. This is sometimes called the "thesis" or "dissertation form," or "scholastic disputation,"
because it was perfected in the universities of the Middle Ages and is still used by candidates for
higher degrees in our modern universities.
B. The proof:
The proof should be stated in syllogistic form. If the
promises used
are not the principles stated above in A3, then we must
demonstrate
each premise by further syllogisms until we come back to
premises
which have already been established in A3.
C. Answers to objections:
The purpose here is to confirm the proof by showing that it
is
sufficient to meet all the difficulties and to save whatever
truth
is in them:
1. The opponent should state his first objection and give a
proof
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
This method makes for the most orderly and courteous type of argument. It is as clear as possible
and avoids all unnecessary verbiage. Sometimes scholars and scientists are tempted to "sound
important" by using many technical terms when nothing is gained but rather clarity and brevity
are lost. The form of the scholastic disputation forces both defendants and objector to eliminate
all undefined terms and to make explicit every hidden assumption.
Notice that this "thesis form" includes two main types of discourse. The proof is strict
demonstration. The statement of the question and the answers to objections, on the other hand,
are dialectical. Such writing is best for scholarly journals or textbooks whose purpose is simply
to record exact scientific thinking. The scientist in his work of research does not follow this
form, but rather that of dialectic. Demonstration can be used only when we have already found
the answer to a problem and wish merely to make it clear to others. Dialectic, however, can be
used when we are still looking for an answer.
DIALECTICS
In the complete scientific exposition outlined above, dialectics is used to state opinions and
refute objections, but it also may be used by itself. In dialectics the author cannot state a definite
conclusion or thesis, since he is still looking for a solution to a question. A dialectical
composition is based, not so much on a conclusion to be proved, as on a problem to be explored.
We have seen in Chapter III that there are four basic questions or problems with which any
investigation can begin:
1. Does S exist?
2. What is the definition of S?
3. Is P a property of S?
4. For what reason (cause) is P a property of S?
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The first question is settled not so much by argument as by observation. The last two questions
are settled by demonstration. Hence the main problem of dialectics is the second one, "What is
the definition of S?" Once we have discovered a real definition we will have an immediately
evident principle on which to base a demonstration which will answer questions 3 and 4.
The method of search for a definition is the one explained in Chapter II. We are always inquiring
about the predicables. We seek the genus and difference in order to know the species or
essential definition. If we cannot find this, then we inquire about a definition through properties
or contingents. We also make these inquiries about all ten categories (see pages 133 ff.).
We ask such questions either in a theoretical or a practical way. A theoretical problem has to do
with the establishment or explanation of facts, like the questions: "Are there men on Mars?
Where did they come from? How do they live?" Practical problems have to do with the choice of
means to some end which we seek, like the questions: "Should we lower taxes in order to
increase prosperity? Or should we raise them in order to strengthen our defenses?"
Some problems do not really interest us in themselves, but we need to answer them in order to
solve other really interesting questions. For example, we may ask, "Is there water vapor in the
atmosphere of Mars?" because that will help us to determine if men could live there. Some
problems concern new facts on which we ourselves have no opinion, like the question: "Is there
anti-matter?" Sometimes they deal with things on which the experts disagree with common
opinions ("Are atomic explosions the cause of so much rain this year?"), or on which experts
disagree among themselves ("Are atomic explosions seriously injuring world health?"). Other
problems are about things on which most people line up on two sides ("is communism a good
thing?"), or about mysterious matters which are so great that no one really knows how to find a
solution ("How old is the universe?").
Ordinarily, however, a dialectical thesis is one which some one proposes and defends in the face
of what is generally accepted. Each of these problems remains a problem for us because we have
not yet arrived at definitions and principles which are certain and which will permit us to
demonstrate an answer. The dialectician attempts to show that the definitions and principles he
proposes are more probable than those usually accepted.
We should not suppose, however, that all things are worth arguing about, or that an argument
should continue forever. Some things are obvious to men of good will, and if someone refuses to
admit the obvious he needs a spanking rather than an argument. Others rest mainly on a question
of fact which must be settled by observation or authority, not by argument. Nor is there much use
arguing about things which cannot be answered with solid probability, nor about things which
can be strictly demonstrated. Dialectical argument is useful only when there are two sides, each
of which is seriously probable, and the discussion is really directed to seeing which is more
probable.
In dialectical argument, just as in demonstration, we use both induction and syllogism. Induction
is more convincing because it is based on particular facts. Syllogism is more useful in refuting
argumentative opponents, since it exposes the weaknesses of their reasoning.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
1. We must find opinions that relate to the problem at hand. For example, if the problem under
discussion is, "is there life on Mars?" we must begin by stating opinions on either side of the
question.
2. We must distinguish the senses of terms and carefully define them. We might say, for
instance, "When you ask if there is life on Mars, do you mean merely plant life, or animal life, or
human life?" It is very important not to let a discussion turn into a mere "war of words." Be
willing to accept the terms in which the question has been put by others, insisting only that their
meaning be defined. Too many arguments are really about words, not about things.
3. We must investigate the differences of things, since many problems arise from overlooking
such differences. For example, we should ask, "But is Mars really like the earth? Isn't it much
farther away from the sun? Isn't it true that there are no oceans on Mars? Isn't it considerably
smaller than the earth?" These differences make it clear that, after all, the argument for life on
Mars is not as strong as one might at first suppose.
4. We must also investigate the likenesses, which will be easier to see after we have noticed
the differences. Likeness is the basis of definition, of induction, and of argument through
analogy. Thus we may argue: "Mars is much more similar to the earth in size and in distance
from the sun than many other planets. It has polar ice-caps. Clouds float across it. Patches that
look like green vegetation seem to spread on its surface during its summer season. Hence it
would seem that Mars has life like the earth."
Thus in analyzing and writing dialectical arguments we can follow a method similar to that used
in the complete demonstration, except that:
Dialectic takes many forms. The most perfect type is that of scientific research. In research the
scientist is already certain about his thesis, not from demonstration, but from observation.
Demonstration goes from principles to conclusion, but research usually begins from a conclusion
already known and seeks out the principles by which this conclusion can be explained.
1. The discovery of radium. For example, Madame Curie,. who discovered the marvelous
element, radium, began with a conclusion which she knew to be certain from her careful
laboratory observations. This conclusion was as follows: "Certain ores are more radioactive than
uranium and thorium, the only known radioactive elements." The problem of her research was to
find the explanation or cause of this conclusion. (See page 552.)
Madame Curie began her reasoning with certain opinions accepted among experts in chemistry,
especially the opinion that there probably exists an element to fit every position in the periodic
table, or classification of the elements. She then proposed a hypothesis which would be
consistent with these accepted opinions and which, if it were true, would give the reason for her
conclusion. Her hypothesis was: "An element, X, exists which is not uranium or thorium, nor any
known element, but which fills one of the gaps in the periodic table and which is highly
radioactive."
She then proceeded to test this hypothesis by seeing whether it would explain the facts in great
detail and be a guide in the discovery of new details. To do this she carefully analyzed the
radioactive ore, applying many chemical processes so as gradually to eliminate all other known
elements, At last she arrived at a concentrated and highly radioactive substance, X, which
behaved like an element. In this manner her hypothesis had stood many tests and had become
highly probable.
She could have continued this dialectical reasoning indefinitely, making her argument ever more
probable, but never arriving at certitude. In this case, however, once she had secured a pure
substance, it became possible to drop her hypothesis and replace it by a genuine principle,
namely, a real definition of X through its properties. She defined X (radium) in terms of its
atomic weight and atomic number, and thus definitely located it in the periodic table. She was
now able to give a strict demonstration: the proper and exact cause of the high radioactivity of
the ore was the presence of a definite element of known definition.
2. The stages of research. Madame Curie was able to carry her dialectic up to the point where
strict demonstration became possible. But it sometimes takes centuries before this last stage in
research is reached. For example, the Greek and medieval astronomers for some 1800 years
worked on a theory of astronomy based on the hypothesis that "the earth is stationary at the
center of the universe." They were perfectly well aware that this was not certain; but as a
hypothesis it was able to explain in a highly probable way all the detailed observations and
measurements of the motions of the planets which they were able to make with the instruments
they had.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Alternative hypotheses were proposed, but none proved so successful in fitting the facts as that
of the astronomer, Ptolemy. Hence scientists made use of this explanation, even though they
knew it was not certain. By the time of Copernicus (16th century), however, the discovery of the
telescope and of new facts little by little suggested another hypothesis. Copernicus held that the
earth moves, a hypothesis which, in the light of the newly discovered facts, seemed more
probable than that of Ptolemy.
Nevertheless, it was not until the time of Newton, over a century later, that the real reason or
cause for the earth's motion was discovered, namely, the law of gravitation.*
* There are, indeed, some scientists today who would say that even the law of gravitation is only a hypothesis, and
that we can never be certain whether the earth moves or not, nor of any other scientific truth. Their reason for this
sceptical position is the fear that if we claim a truth to be certain we will cease to make any more inquiries and
scientific research will come to an end. This fear is groundless. We may know that something is certainly true
without understanding it with perfect distinctness or clarity, or without seeing its consequences. To know these we
must continue Our researches. In fact, the establishment of a certain truth is what gives us confidence to go on with
scientific study, and forms a firm foundation for further exploration.
Once this was discovered, it became possible to demonstrate the motion of the earth and the
positions of the planets through their proper causes.
The Greeks and medievals were not in error about their theory, since they knew that it was only
a hypothesis. It is not an error in dialectics to propose a theory as probable, even though it later
proves to be wrong. Error consists in claiming certitude when one does not have it, or in denying
what has been proved to be certain.
The method of research just described is sometimes called "the scientific method." It is more
accurate to call it "the scientific method of research," since perfect scientific knowledge is found
only in strict demonstration.
3. Proposal of the solution to the problem. After a scientist has been successful enough in his
research to arrive at a true demonstration -- or at least at a hypothetical one -- he should present
his proof in the "thesis form." If he is writing for a more popular audience, he will also have to
make use of rhetoric and even of poetic discourse, in order to interest his audience and make
them receptive and attentive.
The use of vivid anecdotes and examples of a poetic sort make scientific writing pleasant, and
they give to the audience a certain insight into the vision of the scientist, even when they cannot
perfectly follow his scientific argument. Rhetoric gives variety, smoothness, politeness, humor,
appropriateness to scientific writing, and adapts it to the background and practical interests of a
particular audience. It is very important, however, that a scientist should not be carried away by
his poetic and rhetorical style, so as to distort or exaggerate his scientific discoveries.
striking rhetoric that the public believes a "sure cure" has been found, when the scientific
evidence by no means establishes this conclusion. A parade of scientific terms, and an
appearance of great "scientific objectivity" is itself sometimes only a rhetorical device.
The Dialogue
Another form of dialectic made famous by Socrates and Plato is the dialogue, in which people
carry on a conversation, gradually reshaping their views until they approach agreement. In such a
conversation there is usually a leader; otherwise it will not proceed in an orderly fashion, since
people will tend to shift from one side to the other. The leader should require each speaker to
hold to a position as long as he can defend it, and then to admit his error. The dialogue is useful
as a way of showing the steps by which the mind moves toward a conclusion. It is not primarily a
matter of research, but of teaching.
The Debate
The debate is like the dialogue, except that there are two or more parties, each of which holds to
a fixed position until the end of the debate. It is used in courts and legislative assemblies and
many public discussions, where a third person must come to a decision and wishes to hear both
sides of a problem thoroughly explored. The business of the debater is honestly to make out the
best possible case for the side assigned him, in order that the truth can be seen. He need not bold
that his position is the more probable. However, one should not seriously uphold a position
which is known to be false or vicious.
The symposium, forum, and panel are similar to the dialogue and debate. The symposium is
more like a dialogue, and consists of a number of experts stating views on a general question and
then trying to reconcile and synthesize these views by public discussion. The forum is a kind of
open debate in which many people can speak, or question the speaker. A panel consists in a
series of statements by different speakers on the same topic. To these we may compare the
interview or press conference, in which questions are put to a single person.
The essay, editorial, and column, although usually rhetorical in purpose, can also be dialectical.
This happens in the case where the author discusses a problem and current opinions about it
without attempting a conclusive solution, but intending to stimulate thought on the subject.
In all these modes of discussion it is important to preserve certain rules of conduct which prevent
the discussion from becoming rhetorical or emotional. Mortimer Adler in his book, How to Read
a Book, suggests the following cautions:* [*Quoted by permission of Simon and Schuster, Inc.]
1. "You must be able to say, with reasonable certainty, 'I understand' before you can
say any one of the following things: 'I agree,' or 'I disagree,' or 'I suspend
judgment.'"
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
(Adler points out that a good test of this requirement is whether one can repeat
what the other person says in different words.)
2. "There is no point in winning an argument if you know or suspect you are
wrong."
3. "You must regard disagreements as capable of being resolved."
If we can honestly say, "I understand but I disagree," we can then make one of the
following assertions:
4. "You are uninformed"; and then we must point out the facts or sources of facts
which the other person has neglected.
5. "You are misinformed"; and then we must point out the mistake and give the
correct information together with our source.
6. "You are illogical"; and then we must point out the error in logic.
7. "Your analysis is incomplete"; that is, the author has not solved all the problems
raised, or has not used all the material given, or has not seen all the consequences,
or has not made sufficient distinctions. We must point out definitely what he has
emitted.
The great test of good dialectics is to ask whether the author has stuck to his problem and
explored all the arguments pro and con for the various sides. If he is one-sided, then he has failed
to provide us with the help we need to arrive at truth, although we may still profit from him if he
has at least stated his own side plainly.
Today we hear a great deal in all professions and in public life about the need for "research," for
"creative thinking," for "open-mindedness," for the "ability to discuss," and for the "art of
conversation." All of these needs are really a recognition that few people know the art of
dialectics by which they could consider all sides of a question fairly and flexibly.
On the other hand, we must remember that the purpose of dialectics is to prepare for
demonstration whenever this is possible. Some people like to discuss endlessly, but can never
come to a decision. They fall under the condemnation of Saint Paul who mocked at those who
"are ever learning yet never attaining knowledge of the truth" (II Tim. 3:7).
In reading an essay such as Chesterton's A Defence of Patriotism we might apply our six general
rules (see pages 184-185) of analysis as follows:
1. We should notice that the title itself indicates to us the author's thesis or principal
conclusion. He is about to defend patriotism, that is, to show that patriotism is honorable. A
more careful reading will help us to state this somewhat more accurately as follows: True
patriotism, namely, a love of one's country for its spiritual achievements, is honorable. We may
use this as a tentative summary of the author's thesis until we have examined the work more
closely.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
2. We should ask whether the author intends to establish this thesis by poetic, rhetorical,
dialectical, or demonstrative arguments. It is easy to see that the work is not the representation of
an action, or even of thought pictured as the interior action of some character. Hence it is not a
poetic work. Nor does it appear that the author is attempting a strict scientific demonstration of
this thesis. If he were, we would expect him to proceed by stating technical principles, bringing
forward evidence for these principles, and carefully excluding all appeal to emotion.
Indeed, it would seem clear that the work is rhetorical since it is called "A Defence," and it
obviously uses a style that has strong emotional appeal. If we interpret it as rhetorical, we can get
quite a satisfactory explanation of its details, except for one interesting point. In a rhetorical
work we would expect the author to argue his position by enthymemes, but Chesterton is
concerned here mainly with a definition. His effort is to contrast different ideas about patriotism
and to discover the true one.
Hence in spite of its many rhetorical elements, we may suspect that this work is principally a
dialectical one, since it is characteristic of dialectics to search for definitions. This is an example
of the fact that many literary works combine two or more forms of discourse. Nevertheless, they
will be principally one or the other.
3. The third rule deals with the discovery of the author's main terms and how he defines them.
Here we should apply whatever we have learned in Chapter II about terms and definitions. It is
clear from his thesis that Chesterton's main terms are true and false patriotism and honorable.
He does not actually use the latter term, but it is implied in the very idea of a "defence." Since
this is probably a dialectical work, we do not expect the author to give a final definition of these
terms, since that is just what he is looking for. Rather we should list the various definitions of
patriotism which occur in his essay (see pages 169 ff.).
4. The fourth rule leads its to seek the author's fundamental statements or principles and the
evidence offered for them. We can do this by making an outline, as we learned in Chapter III;
such an outline for Chesterton's essay is given on pages 170f. We see that, as is to be expected in
a dialectical composition, there are no strict principles, but only a series of opinions or
hypotheses. Chesterton bases these opinions on the common consent of men, on daily
experience, and on various analogies.
5. The fifth rule brings us to the very heart of the essay, namely, its argument. We have already
discussed this in Chapter III (pages 169 ff). The argument in dialectic consists in showing that if
we accept the opinion in question, then we must accept certain consequences, which we then
compare with other accepted opinions or known facts. Chesterton proposes a series of
hypotheses, each of which is a possible definition of patriotism. He then shows that the
commonly accepted ideas about patriotism lead us to absurd consequences. Only the definition
which he is proposing stands the test. Hence it may be accepted as probably correct.
6. The last rule is to consider whether the author has used all the means required to establish
his argument. To settle this we must consider the outline we have already made. Is the
composition well ordered, or does it ramble? Are the parts in about the right balance and
proportion? Does each paragraph have a unity of its own? What about the length, the continuity,
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
and the variety of the sentences (see Chapter 11, pages 107 ff.)? Is the style chosen suitable for
the argument? Is the choice of words and figures of speech suitable for the style? Finally, does
the rhythm and sound of the words and sentences contribute or detract from the total effect?
When we ask these questions we will see that Chesterton's essay is, on the whole, quite orderly
and free from extraneous matter. His style is characteristic in its great use of antithesis and
paradox. He seeks certain humorous effects, and he especial1y loves alliteration and sonorous
sentences. This style is chosen because its light and humorous quality and its paradoxical
surprises assist his audience to think about rather serious questions without realizing that they are
engaging in dialectics. They suppose the author is joking, writing a little informal essay, while
actually he is writing rather deep philosophy.
The more carefully we study the details of this style, the more we will see how wisely Chesterton
keeps prodding us to think by surprising turns of thought and expression. When we have seen
how every word in the essay contributes to this one effect of leading us step by step to a better
notion of what patriotism really is, then we can say that we have really read his essay.
If we turn now to Whether Piety Is a Special Virtue? we can apply the same six rules:
1. There is no doubt of Saint Thomas' thesis. It is put first in question form and then declared in
his answer to that question: piety is a special virtue and hence something honorable, just as
Chesterton has tried to show.
2. But an application of the second rule shows us at once that Saint Thomas is using a different
type of argument than that used by Chesterton. Clearly there is no appeal to emotions, but only to
cold reason. Hence the work is neither poetical nor rhetorical. Furthermore, it gives every sign of
being an attempt at a strictly scientific demonstration, and not merely a dialectical research, since
Saint Thomas gives a positive and definitive answer to the question he raises. On the other band,
there is some dialectic involved here, since the composition begins with a series of opinions that
are opposed to the thesis. We have here an example of a complete exposition in which dialectic
is used to raise a question, but in which the question is answered by a strict demonstration.
3. It is at once obvious that the chief terms used are piety and special virtue. Saint Thomas
defines piety very explicitly by an essential definition, showing that its genus is justice, and that
its difference is paying the debt of reverence and service due to country and parents.
Furthermore, he defines justice itself as a virtue which pays a debt to another. The term special
virtue he does not define here, but rather refers back to an earlier section of his work where it
has already been defined.
4. The fourth rule leads us to make an outline of Saint Thomas' work and to discover his basic
principles. We see that all the parts of a complete exposition are present but in a different order
than the usual one (see pages 185 f.). The thesis is stated as a question. Then come the objections
and "on the contrary" which serve as a statement of the question, since they give the common
opinions. The definition of terms, however, is included along with the proof in the "I answer
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
that." The reply to objections is in the usual place. We see that the basic principles used in his
proof are the definition of piety which is immediately evident, since it is a definition derived
from experience of human life, and the definitions of justice and of virtue, which he has already
defended earlier in the Summa.
5. The argument contained in the "I answer that" has already been given in syllogistic form on
page 173 in Chapter III, and is logically correct. Moreover, it fulfills the requirements of a strict
proof, because its premises are certain and necessary (see pages 173 f.). Hence Saint Thomas'
answer is certainly true and provides us with the exact reason (middle term) for the conclusion.
6. In applying the last rule concerning the economy and style of presentation, we cannot help
but admire the way in which Saint Thomas has answered a deep scientific question in so brief a
space. Nothing here is wasted. Everything is straight to the point. We cannot judge his use of the
Latin language, since this is only a translation. Experts in Latin literature, however, greatly
admire the purity and simplicity of Saint Thomas' Latin style, although he wrote in the Middle
Ages when Latin bad lost much of its literary polish. We can see, however, even in translation,
his great care to use technical terms that will express ideas accurately, and his avoidance of any
display of mere technical jargon.
If we compare the work of Saint Thomas with that of Chesterton, we can see how Chesterton
by his use of dialectics, with a certain flavor of rhetoric, helps us to become interested in the
problem of what real patriotism is. Once we have been awakened to the problem, Saint Thomas
with clear and simple but exact language gives us a precise answer. Thus rhetoric and dialectics
prepare the way for scientific demonstration.
RHETORIC
THE METHODS OF ORATORY
The Central Point or Thesis
The first step in writing a rhetorical composition is to formulate exactly the main point to be
established, that is, to determine what we want to persuade the audience to do. Next we need to
consider the character of the audience itself, the things that appeal to them, and the things they
dislike. Finally, we should consider what kind of arguments will be convincing to them.
In reading or listening to a rhetorical composition the process of analysis is the same: What is the
author trying to persuade his audience to do? Has he rightly judged their reaction? Is he using the
arguments that are effective for this audience?
In trying to discover a rhetorician's thesis, we must remember that rhetoric sometimes seeks to
keep the thesis concealed until the audience is fully prepared to accept it. Otherwise if it were
presented from the outset the audience might reject it decisively. Thus Mark Anthony begins his
speech in Julius Caesar by saying: "I have come to bury Caesar, not to praise him," because he
knows his audience is in no mood to hear Caesar praised. Only by indirection does he finally
come to speak openly in Caesar's favor.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Sometimes, however, if our thesis is not something which the audience detests, but rather
something to which they are indifferent, we may want to present it frankly at the start so they
will not be suspicious. This thesis must be something morally good and true, or the whole work
will not be genuine rhetoric, but only an abuse of rhetoric.
The Audience
In order to study the nature of the audience to which some speech has been addressed, we may
have to do some research on the history of the period and the situation in which the speech was
delivered. In composing a rhetorical work ourself, we must carefully observe and study the
people to whom we are to speak, trying to know as much about them as possible. Here the
methods of the social sciences are useful when they can be applied. For this reason advertising
firms carefully study the audience to whom they are trying to sell a product by the use of
"opinion surveys," "consumer analyses," etc. When such elaborate methods cannot be applied,
we should at least make careful inquiries, ask the advice of those who know the audience, and
carefully watch the audience reaction during our speech.
Of all the means of persuasion, none is so fundamental as the impression made on the audience
by the character of the speaker. Hence we must consider what the reaction of the audience is
likely to be to our appearance, manner, and approach to the question. A speaker should realize
his weak and his strong points relative to a particular audience, and he should try to counteract
any prejudices they may have formed concerning him.
The second mode of persuasion is an appeal to the emotions of the audience. We must have a
good idea of what will appeal to them and what they will dislike. Frequently a truth put in one set
of terms will seem distasteful to them, while the very same truth differently expressed will seem
pleasing.
These two means of persuasion, powerful as they may be, only dispose the audience to accept a
thesis; they do not actually persuade them. Complete persuasion is achieved only through a third
means, that of rational argument, and it is this which is most characteristic of rhetoric. Rational
arguments must be based on premises readily acceptable to the audience, and they must be
expressed in a forceful manner through enthymemes, examples, and maxims, rather than through
the clearer yet less striking form of the syllogism. In analyzing a rhetorical composition we
should pay careful attention to the arguments which it contains, since these are its very heart.
Frequently readers and speakers make the mistake of looking only at the style, or the emotional
appeal of a speech, and they neglect a study of the arguments in which its chief power really
consists.
The particular form an argument should take depends upon the type of speech. A speech may be
deliberative, that is, one intended to lead all audience to make a decision about some future
action, (for example, a speech in Congress on a proposed law). Or it may be judicial, that is,
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
intended to persuade the audience to make a judgment upon some past action (for example, a
speech in a court of law). Or it may be ceremonial, that is, designed to make the audience
appreciate some present situation or person as honorable or dishonorable (for example, a
commencement speech).
Deliberative Oratory
In deliberative oratory the speaker must understand clearly what the public welfare truly consists
in. He must also understand the characteristics of particular forms of government, and must be
well acquainted with history, geography, war, and economics, so that he can show that a certain
course of action in war or diplomacy, or certain policies with regard to civil liberties, business,
taxes, etc., are really more or less expedient. Men who are to take part in public affairs, or to
stand for public office, must have this kind of wide education in social science, history, and
current affairs if they are to be effective speakers. They must especially be able to present their
character in a favorable light to the public, and they must know how to establish their arguments
by many examples from history and personal experience.
Judicial Oratory
In judicial oratory the speaker is chiefly concerned with crime and its motivation, and With the
character of the criminal and of the victims of his crime. He must also be thoroughly acquainted
both with the law and with the facts in the case at issue. He will appeal to the emotions of the
judge and jury, but he must especially use forceful reasoning in the form of the enthymeme to
prove his case or to refute contrary arguments, since judgment about past events frequently
depends upon inferences from rather scanty evidence.
Ceremonial Oratory
The ceremonial orator must have an especially good knowledge of ethics, so that he has a
profound concept of true nobility of character and is able to show its traits clearly. He makes
especial use of the devices of amplification to help the audience appreciate the greatness of his
subject. It is in this type of speech that beauty of style is of the greatest importance, and it is the
kind of oratory which most resembles poetry.
History and biography (including autobiography, of course) are really forms of rhetoric similar to
ceremonial rhetoric, when they are more than a mere recording of facts. The primary purpose of
history is to broaden our narrow personal experience of life, so that we can make more prudent
decisions in our personal lives and especially as citizens.
The historian is not a mere propagandist. He seeks to establish his facts accurately on the basis of
reliable witnesses, and he seeks to explain these facts in terms of psychology and other sciences,
especially of social science. His explanations cannot be strictly demonstrative, because we
cannot fully explain singular events, since science deals with what is universal. Hence the
historian uses dialectics to make a research into the most probable explanations. He also uses
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
something of the skill of the poetic writer in attempting to recreate a vivid picture of the past.
The historian's ultimate purpose, however, is to help us to make better judgments about life by
following men of great character, and avoiding the mistakes of evil men. This purpose requires
the art of rhetoric.*
*Some believe that history is worth knowing for its own sake as a purely theoretical science like natural science,
mathematics, or philosophy. But these latter sciences are worth knowing for their own sake precisely because they
are about something universal and permanent, and they can arrive at precise and certain explanations. History deals
with events which will never occur again and which we can only imperfectly understand. Hence it cannot be of great
value for its own sake. It is, however, of immense value when used in the manner described above.
STYLE IN RHETORIC
Although ceremonial oratory and history especially require excellence of style, style is of great
importance in all rhetoric. The speaker must select terms which are forceful and which have the
right emotional tone for his purpose. He must avoid whatever is technical or pedantic or
unintelligible to his audience. His sentences must have a smooth rhythmic flow so as not to
impede the course of his thought, and they must be so constructed as to produce interesting
variety and appropriate climaxes. Finally, they must be composed with a view to delivery, since
there is considerable difference between a speech which is effective in reading and in listening.
The style of ceremonial oratory must be very polished. judicial oratory must be vivid and
striking. Deliberative oratory is less literary than either of these, but clear and practical.
No matter how excellent the content of a speech or its style, it will lose all force if it is badly
arranged. We have all become exasperated with the speaker who wanders from one topic to
another, and seems to be getting nowhere. The basic arrangement of every speech is as follows:
1. The introduction, which aims at catching the attention of the audience and
disposing them well to the character of the speaker.
2. The statement of the case, which is designed to put the practical problem
clearly before the audience and make them see bow important it is for them
personally to arrive at the right decision.
3. The argument of the case, in which the reasons for deciding in favor of the
orator's point of view are brought forth. This is the heart of the whole speech.
4. The conclusion, in which the emotions of the audience are particularly brought
to bear to reinforce the argument and to leave them with a definite resolution on
which to act.
It is obvious that these points are essentially the same as in a complete demonstrative exposition,
except that more attention is given to disposing the audience to a good opinion of the speaker in
the introduction, and to awakening a strong emotional conviction in the conclusion. The
statement of the case and the argument, however, are very different in a rhetorical and in a
demonstrative composition, because the demonstration is always trying to bring forward the
exact reason or cause of his conclusion, while the orator is concerned with the reason which
will be most appealing to the particular audience.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
This does not mean, of course, that the rhetorician can use false arguments. His reasons must be
true and good, but they need not be exact and essential. Thus if I wished to demonstrate that
physical exercise is good for health, I would dwell on the fact that our bodily functions are
stimulated by vigorous use. This is the precise reason and cause. But if I wished to persuade a fat
man to take exercise, it might be more effective to point out that if he doesn't reduce people will
laugh at him. This is not the essential reason that he needs to exercise, but it is the one which has
the most emotional force.
In previous chapters we have already given a rather complete analysis of the "Gettysburg
Address" (see pages 159 ff.). Here we will only summarize briefly the steps a skilled reader
would take in analyzing it:
1. A preliminary reading would show that the thesis is probably: "You should imitate the
patriotism of the dead by finishing the war."
2. This makes it clear at once that we are dealing with a rhetorical work, since it is an attempt
to persuade the audience to do something, namely, to imitate the dead by finishing the war.
Hence we must judge everything in the speech in terms of this rhetorical purpose: How does it
contribute to persuading the audience?
Furthermore, we will quickly see from the contents of the speech that it is an example of
ceremonial oratory, since it seeks to glorify the dead, but that it contains also in its main
conclusion an element of deliberative oratory, since it also argues about the course of action to
be pursued in the future. This deliberative purpose, however, is kept subordinated to the
ceremonial purpose.
Hence we should modify our tentative statement of the thesis so as to bring these points out. The
thesis is better expressed, therefore, as follows: "The patriotism of the dead is to be honored
today and imitated by finishing their work in the future," for instance, or something similar.
3. We next consider the main terms, which obviously again will be the patriotism of the dead
and the honor due them. We see that Lincoln has the task of defining these terms in such a way
as to amplify them, that is, to make them seem very great. He amplifies the notion of patriotism
(1) by showing how complete was the offering of these men, an offering of their own lives; and
(2) by showing how great was the cause in which they fought, to carry on the mission of
America of giving an example of free government to the whole world. In this fashion he defines
patriotism in terms of its formal cause (reverence of country shown by sacrifice of one's life) and
its final cause (to preserve the country in its ideals).
Honor he defines by showing that the honor due is beyond all, words. This he does by
depreciating his own words in order to amplify honor. The only fitting honor is imitation, the
carrying out of the task already begun. Hence true honor is defined as reverence shown not in
words but in deeds.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
4. Next the reader should try to outline the speech and to see its most significant statements and
their basis. We have already done this (see page 101). We will see that Lincoln bases his
argument on the principle, accepted by all in the audience, that the United States was founded to
carry on a great ideal, the ideal of free government which is worth the greatest sacrifices. He
gives as his grounds for this assertion the accepted historical fact that this was the purpose, for
which the country was founded (first sentence).
A second principle he uses, but keeps implicit, is that this war is being fought by the North to
defend the true ideal on which the country is based. Of course a Southern audience would not
have accepted this notion. The Northern audience accepts it without question, but Lincoln does
not feel that this is the occasion on which to discuss the point. Hence he leaves it implicit.
5. We have also already analyzed the arguments of the speech (see pages 159 f.). We have seen
that Lincoln realizes that in establishing his own character before the audience he has to
overcome their suspicious of him as a cheap politician. This he does by the simple dignity and
lofty character of his speech as a whole, and especially in the grandeur of its opening lines.
Secondly, he uses their emotions effectively. He knows that this audience is bitter, tired,
suspicious, and filled with sorrow. Hence he tries to raise their emotions to a higher plane of
nobility, to give them a sense of the solemnity of the occasion, its historical significance, and the
hopeful future of the cause. The speech begins solemnly but moves to a strong and resolute
climax.
Thirdly, he makes use of a simple enthymeme (see page 160) which gives them a rational
conviction that if the war for so noble a cause has cost so much already, they must see it through
to the end. Thus he leads directly from their sense of the honor due to the dead to the practical
resolution he wishes them to form.
6. Once we understand this course of the argument the fittingness of Lincoln's style becomes
apparent. The regular rule of ceremonial oratory requires that it have a highly polished style.
This is seen in three features: (1) the simple but noble choice of words;
(2) the use of figures of speech, but especially of the metaphor of death and rebirth which runs
through the whole oration; and especially (3) in the beautiful rhythm of the words rising to the
grand climax of the last sentence. The economy of the speech is notable, and its very brevity
makes it have the character of an epitaph or proverb, something that can be easily memorized
and retained like a motto. Its arrangement shows a very brief introduction, an exposition of the
occasion, the argument, and a brief but powerful conclusion.
The more we analyze this speech the more we see that every detail of it contributes to the total
thesis and that it is complete in all its parts.
POETICS
FALLACIES CONCERNING POETIC WORKS
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
In judging a poetic work, whether it is in prose or verse, whether it is in the form of a novel, a
play, a lyric, or an essay, we must keep clearly in mind the special purpose of such a work. This
special purpose makes it very different from demonstrative, dialectical, or rhetorical works. We
should especially avoid the following mistakes, which lead many readers to wrong judgments
about works of literature and to a failure to appreciate true excellence.
It is a mistake to think that a poetic work can be a good work of art despite the fact that it
presents a false thesis or arouses in us immoral emotions and attitudes. A poetic work, just like
demonstration, dialectic, and rhetoric, must present the truth. To use our power of thought and
speech to produce something which is false or foolish is a misuse of God-given powers. To
arouse immoral emotions or to read a work that arouses them is to place ourselves in the
occasion of sin.
Many who make this mistake argue that certain great writers have written very clever works that
present falsehood. In answer to this we may grant that an artist can misuse his art if he wills. He
then produces a bad work of art as a whole, although this or that feature of it may be very good.
Our admiration of the good features of the work should not blind us to its bad features. On the
other hand, a work of art is not to be condemned totally because it has some incidental
falsehoods or errors in taste or morals. If these are minor and incidental and are not an occasion
of temptation to us, we may overlook them. No human work is entirely perfect.
Again people argue that literature must present life as it is, and hence it must deal with falsehood
and with vice as well as with what is true and virtuous. This is a most illogical argument. All
discourse presents falsehood -- not, however, in order to agree with it, but to refute it. Falsehood
is used to make the truth more clear by contrast. So in literature there must indeed be a
presentation of falsehood and of evil. Nevertheless, the purpose of this presentation of falsehood
and sin must be only for the purpose of making truth clearer and goodness more desirable. The
emotions aroused by the work must be virtuous and not dangerous, so that sin is never presented
sympathetically, although the sinner should arouse our pity, and our fear for our own sins.
The reason for this is clear if we remember that the purpose of the poetic work is to purify the
emotions so that we may be recreated by a vision of the truth. If the work arouses irrational
emotions and presents a falsehood, it cannot give us this recreation.
The second mistake is to think if a work does present the truth and arouse good emotions that it
is a good poetic work. People who do not make the first mistake above frequently fall into this
second mistake,
Any work of liberal art, whether it be poetic, rhetorical, dialectical, or demonstrative, must
present truth; but it is not a good work of liberal art merely because its thesis or conclusion is
true. An argument may have a true conclusion and still be a weak, or even a false, argument.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Rather an argument of any sort is good when it has (1) good logical form, and (2) it presents the
true middle term or cause of the conclusion.
In a poetic work the correct logical form is that of an example, and the middle term in this
example is a story which produces a catharsis of emotion.
Granted that a poetic work presents a truth, it will be a good or bad poetic work insofar as it
presents this truth in terms of such a story. If a poetic writer is a poor storyteller he is a poor
writer, no matter how true and good may be his thesis. Some religious magazines are filled with
pious stories and poems which have a good moral but which are very poor literature and which
are quite unsatisfactory as recreation.
A third mistake is to think that since the story or plot is the soul of the work that a poetic work is
good if it has a good story, Some people think that if they read a digest of a novel, or even a
summary of its plot, they have saved a great deal of time and got at the real heart of the work.
This is not true of any work of liberal art. If it is a good work of art, every word in it has a
purpose, and a mere summary of any argument does not do it justice.
But this is particularly true of a poetic work. The work does not achieve its purpose of purifying
our emotions and leading us to a vision of truth except by helping us enter into the very
experience of the story itself. We must not only "hear about what happened," we must seem to
live it ourselves. For that reason the way in which the story is told, the descriptions, the
characters, the dialogue, the choice of words and figures of speech, the sound and rhythm of the
sentences-all are important. The story or plot is not a mere summary, it is found in every detail of
the work and in every feature of its style, just as our soul is found in every part of the body to
which it gives life.
The reader who reads only for the story and does not appreciate the style and art with which the
story is told is missing most of its true recreative value. This is why he finds little enjoyment in
the lyric, essay, or didactic poem in which the story element is less prominent, and character,
thought, or style is more important.
The fourth mistake is to approach a poetic work with a preconceived idea of its form. Some
critics have attempted a neat classification of the forms of poetic work as if they were natural
species, and have laid down "rules" for each form. In the seventeenth and eighteenth century the
neoclassical school of criticism attempted to impose such rules. They even considered that the
great Shakespeare was a barbarian because his works failed to fit their models. Against this
attitude a reaction called romanticism set in which stressed the idea that there are no rules in
poetry, and that the artist is free to create as he pleases.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Today the romantic attitude is still the dominant one, and yet many fine writers and critics are
again emphasizing that a poem must conform to the rules of some form if it is to be a real work
of art,
In order to balance the classical and romantic positions, we should remember two points:
1. A poetic work represents (or imitates) nature; that is, it tells a story about
human life and it will be successful in presenting such a story only if it is true to
life. Hence no artist is free to create anything, he pleases; he must design his work
so that it achieves this purpose of presenting nature. The neoclassical critics
realized this, and they believed that the great Greek writers had discovered how to
present life truly; in consequence, they thought that the types of literature
invented by the Greeks were the best, and they tried to discover the rules on
which they were based, just as in architecture we still study the Greek temples to
discover how they achieved such marvelous balance and proportion. It remains
true that in developing a taste for literature, or even the ability to write, one
should begin by a careful study and analysis of great works of literature invented
by the Greeks and by later writers who attained success in their art. In this way
the poet must be the pupil both of nature and of past artists.
2. Nevertheless, in imitating nature the artist can invent an infinite variety of ways
to represent it. Human life is vastly complex, and no work of art can present the
whole of it. Each artist sees some aspect of life which others have missed and he
must design his own form in which to present that aspect. Even if he uses some
well-recognized and fully developed form he will have to modify and adapt it to
make it serve his special purpose.
Hence the forms of art and the rules of writing can never be fixed once and for all; they are
constantly being added to and developed. We must approach each new work with an open mind.
This is what the romantics pleaded for. They, too, spoke of a "return to nature," because they
believed that by imitating only the authors of the past writers lose touch with human life itself.
The mistake of romanticism, however, (and it was a greater error even than that of the
neoclassicists) was to think that nature is known by us only through our subjective impressions
and emotions. A romantic poem is really not about nature, but about the poet's feelings about
nature. This view of life denied the power of the human reason to understand the true nature of
man and of the world, and gradually led to a type of literature which pictures life as without
order or meaning. Realism is only the other side of romanticism, since the realistic writer simply
records what he sees without trying to understand it.
A true theory of poetry requires the poet to be true to life as it really is not merely to its
appearances or his reactions to it; but it leaves him free rein to invent new forms and methods by
which to present this truth about life. In criticizing a work we should try first of all to discover
this basic idea, which is the soul of the work. If it is false, then the work as a whole is bad, and
nothing remains but to consider such excellence as its parts may exhibit. If the idea is true, then
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
we must try to see if the artist has invented or made use of the right form in which to represent
this truth down to its last details of word and sound.
In discovering this basic idea or form which is the plot or soul of the work, we have to proceed
by stating it in the form of a hypothesis, and then see if this hypothesis can explain all the details
of the work. Sometimes it is useful to try several hypotheses and
find out which best explains the work. In doing this it is a help to be acquainted with the forms of
poetic work which have already been invented and perfected by previous authors, but we should
not try to force the work we are criticizing into one of these molds. Rather we should try to see
why the author has modified the recognized forms in order to present his own idea more
perfectly.
Differences in Method
Related to differences in manner are differences resulting from the freedom with which the
author deals with his materials. Thus a story may be historical when the author draws the
material from actual history, or purely fictional when be invents it all. He may treat this
realistically by describing daily life in a literal fashion, in which case he may use either an
impressionistic or a documentary technique, according as he builds tip his picture from little
fragments or from a detailed description; or he may write in a romantic style, that is, coloring his
story with the marvelous and imaginary, or at least with the heroic and unusual. He may also
present his story in a literal way by saying directly what is intended; or figuratively, either by
making use of occasional symbolism (metaphors), or by an extended allegory or parable. *
*An allegory is a story which has a hidden meaning corresponding to almost all of its details. A parable has a hidden
meaning also, but one which has only a general correspondence between story and meaning, the details not requiring
any special interpretation.
Differences in Length
A third classification is according to the magnitude or length. Thus the trilogy, the novel, the
novelette, and the short-story differ principally in their relative length. Along with this can be
grouped the classification of works according to their completeness. Thus we can speak of major
works, like the play, the epic, and the novel, all of which are long, deal with all the objects of
imitation (plot, character, thought), and use a rich variety of means; and minor works, which
limit themselves more narrowly. Also we can speak of sketches, essays, descriptions, and
experimental studies which do not aim to present a complete and finished work.
Differences in Form
The third classification just mentioned is closely related to a fourth. This is the most important
and fundamental classification, because it is based riot merely on the matter and mariner of the
work, but on its object or form.
After we have found the approximate form of the work to be criticized, we should try to state its
plot in a single sentence. If it is a work in which plot is emphasized, this will at once give us the
central idea of the whole work. If, however, character or thought are emphasized, the plot may be
reduced to a minimum. In a lyric poem, for example, the plot will probably consist simply in the
stages of emotion which are expressed. In a didactic work it will be the successive stages of
thought and the sentiments which accompany them.
Keeping this tentative statement of the plot, we should ask if it is truly poetic in character; that is,
is it a single vivid, typical example which expresses a universal truth and produces a catharsis?
In deciding this we must ask if it is complete, unified, and probable (see page 150). We should
also divide it into its beginning, middle, and end, and the middle into its various episodes. If in
attempting to do this we find that the plot appears defective, we should re-examine our tentative
statement to see if perhaps we have mistaken the author's real purpose. Only when we have
seriously tried to find a complete, unified, and probable plot, should we conclude that he has
failed.
We should also consider whether the magnitude or length is sufficient for the completeness of
the plot, or whether it is unnecessarily long. In examining the plot we must also consider the
other objects of imitation. How many characters are there? What is the nature of each? How do
they contribute to the action? Are they consistent, lifelike, and appropriate to the plot? If it is a
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
work in which character is emphasize these questions will be the main basis on which to judge
the work.
As to the thought, we must ask whether it follows the rules of rhetoric and at the same time
maintains a contemplative and emotional1y moving tone so as to be genuinely poetic.
Other Questions
After these questions that relate to the object of representation, we should consider the manner.
Has the author rightly chosen the form of a play or is it more suited for a novel? Is dialogue used
effectively? Why has he chosen to present it in first, second, or third person? Why has he chosen
it realistic or romantic tone, etc.?
Lastly we come to the means. Here we have to consider the writer's consistency of tone, his
choice of words, his use of description and figures of speech, and the suitability of his work to be
performed or to be set to music, if that is the intention.
After this careful analysis of the work we may ask ourselves if the author has abused his art by
using it for an unworthy purpose to present what is false or dangerous. Finally, this analysis
should be only the preparation for our own experience and enjoyment of the work.
In the actual experience of a work of art, all the points of which we have spoken are blended
together into a unified whole. We are able to achieve this only when we have developed good
taste. For a person of good taste the process of analysis of which we have been speaking
becomes second nature, so that there is no need to think of it; only the beauty of the work is
present. There is little use in learning rules of literary criticism unless we use them so frequently
that they become second nature. Reference to them, however, will be useful in approaching new
and unfamiliar types of works, and in discussing works with friends. Literary works are a fitting
topic of discussion since such discussion recalls delightful experiences and helps us renew the
refreshment we received from these works. It also helps friends to open up their own souls to
each other, since it is in the appreciation of beautiful works that our gifts and beauty of soul
appear.
In reading the "Concord Hymn" we might apply our six rules in something of the following
manner:
1. We gather first that the central idea of the work is that "patriotism is often forgotten but not
by God." This is another way of saying that " patriotism is to be honored as a virtue," much the
same theme as we have found in the demonstrative, dialectical, and rhetorical pieces we have
already analyzed.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
2. We should not jump to the conclusion that this work is "poetic" merely because it is a short
work in verse. Many so-called "poems" are really rhetorical or even scientific works. In order to
decide if it is a rhetorical or poetic work, rather than scientific, we must ask ourself if it has an
emotional as well as an intellectual appeal? It is clear from the writer's care to speak in concrete
and imaginative terms that he is trying to move us emotionally as well as intellectually. Hence
the work is either rhetorical or poetical. If it is rhetorical it must be aimed at getting us to do
something.
We see in fact that the author has indicated that we ought to honor the dead, just as did Lincoln
in his "Gettysburg Address." But a more careful examination will show that while Lincoln is
intensely practical in his approach, Emerson is content rather to help us appreciate and
contemplate the beauty of patriotism rather than to urge us to do anything about it. This is
apparent especially from the tone of the last stanza. Hence we can safely say that this probably is
a poetic work.
It does not, however, have any obvious exterior plot. The story which it tells is largely an
interior one, since it is not an account of the battle of Concord, but rather the poet's reflections
concerning that battle. Hence we must be dealing with a lyric or didactic poem in which plot is
reduced to a minimum. Analysis shows, however, that thought is not very central in this poem,
since Emerson does not develop intellectual reasons for his conclusions, but rather emphasizes
emotional reasons, namely, our sense of shame at forgetting what the dead have done for us.
Hence it would appear that we are dealing with a lyric poem of the type that represents a poet's
emotional reaction to an event, in this case the occasion of erecting the monument. We see, too,
from the sorrowful tone, that we are dealing with the kind of lyric called the elegy.
Our attempt to appreciate the poem, therefore, must consist in an effort to see bow the writer has
made us share in his emotional experience, an experience which ended in a deeper realization of
the universal truth that patriotism is a noble and honorable thing.
In applying rule 3 (discovery and definition of terms) and rule 4 (basic statements and their
source), we must remember that in a poetic work abstract statements and ideas are replaced by
concrete objects of representation. Thus we see that Emerson does not write about "patriotism"
or "honor," but about the minutemen, who are an example of patriotism, and the Concord
monument, which is an example of honor. Hence in poetic works rules 3 and 4 can be applied
along with rule 5 (argument), by inquiring about the objects of representation, namely, plot,
character, and thought.
The plot here consists in the poet's gradual realization of the honor due to patriotism through an
emotional experience. We see that it is unified because each stage of the poem leads up to this
final realization. It is complete since it has a beginning in the first stanza with the poet's mental
picture of the battle which took place years before on the spot on which he is standing, a middle
in his realization and shame at the neglect and forgetfulness of men shown in the second stanza,
and his determination to set tip the monument in the third stanza, and finally an end in his prayer
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
to God, wherein he realizes that true honor is with God who cannot forget. This is complete, not
only as a thought, but as an emotion, since the awe and shame aroused in the poem come to rest
in the prayerful joy and reassurance of the last stanza. In this way there is a catharsis of the
emotion. The plot is also probable, for this succession of emotions comes from the realization of
a great truth, each step leading naturally into the next.
This argument or plot is made tip of the several stages of thought and emotion which constitute,
as it were, the basic statements of the poem. Thus each stanza can be summarized as a single
statement. The ground for these statements is to be found in the poet's experience communicated
to us in the poem by concrete, vivid pictures. These pictures serve to define the terms of the
poem. Thus "patriotism" appears in the poem in the vivid picture of the minutemen standing at
the bridge "with flag unfurled." "Honor" appears in the poem in terms of three actions: men
forget the dead, they remember and erect a monument, and finally they pray to God. The poet
defines each of these by his use of exact description and of symbol.
Finally we must see how the poet has used words, imagery, symbols and other figures of speech,
and the sound of his words and sentences to represent the foregoing objects. We have already
seen (see page 116) how well Emerson has used all these means of representation. to produce his
work. It is only when we see that every word and every syllable has been chosen with care to
bring before us this single emotional experience in order for us to appreciate a great truth that we
will truly appreciate this poem.
In a novel or drama the plot would probably be much more prominent, and require more careful
analysis, than in a lyric of this sort. Similarly, in a didactic poem we should have to devote much
more attention to the play of thought. But in all cases the same objects of representation and the
same means of representation will be present in different proportions.
DEFINITIONS
1. A literary genre (literary type, or form) is a commonly accepted grouping of literary works
which significantly resemble each other in form or matter.
Note: It has been explained in the previous chapter that such types are not fixed natural species,
but are groupings of highly individual objects, and that an artist may invent new types or
variations of these types. The following definitions, therefore, are nominal rather than real
definitions.
2. A complete demonstration (or "thesis form") is the presentation of a proof for a definite
conclusion, preceded by an introduction in which the terms of the conclusion are defined, the
importance of the problem explained, the principal opinions about it listed, and the proper
principles of solution manifested, and followed by a reconciliation or refutation of opposing
views by means of the art of distinguishing terms.
3. The dialogue is a dialectical exchange between two or more persons aiming at the clarification
of a question and the establishment of principles for its solution.
If the parties defend set positions which are formally opposed it is a debate, and if this debate is
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
open to voluntary participation it is a forum. If the positions are not formally opposed, then it
may be called a symposium, conference, or panel.
4. The essay is a short prose composition (although it is sometimes in verse) which may be in
any of the four modes of discourse. When collected in topical order it is a journal.
6. History and biography as a literary form pertain to rhetoric since they aim to persuade us to
act in accordance with a wider experience of human vice and virtue, but the establishment and
explanation of facts requires a skillful dialectical method, and a knowledge of the sciences.
The autobiography, "profile," memoir, diary, and confession are special forms. The
character sketch may also be typical rather than individual.
8. Tragic literature is a representation of a heroic action in which human virtue is tested by the
most serious trials that expose human pride and thus produce a catharsis of sorrow and fear
ending in a serene contemplation of the divine order in the world.
10. A tragedy is dramatic imitation of a serious and complete action in language appropriately
rich which by incidents arousing pity and fear produces a catharsis of these emotions.
11. A comedy is an imitation of an action which is complete but not serious in language
appropriately rich which by incidents exposing the ridiculous produces a catharsis of the
unseemly emotions by which men are made ridiculous.
12. An epic is like the tragedy, but narrative not dramatic in form.
13. The comic epic is like the comedy, but narrative in form. When it parodies the style of the
epic it is a mock-epic.
14. A romance is drama or narrative in which the marvelous in love or adventure is emphasized.
15. The farce is an extravagant comedy, the melodrama an extravagant romance, the parody an
extravagant imitation of another work of literature.
16. A mystery play (Middle Ages) is one based on a mystery of the Christian religion, while a
miracle play is one based on a miraculous incident in the life of a saint.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
17. A myth is a narrative which seeks to explain historical, theological, natural, psychological,
or moral truths in a metaphorical fashion. Fairy-tales are myths in which Christian writers
replace the pagan gods by "little people." Fables are stories in which animals or even inanimate
objects are personified. A folk-tale is my story handed down by tradition.
18. The parable is a narrative in which the things actually narrated, taken as a whole, are a
metaphor for a hidden meaning. When this comparison extends even to details, the narrative is
an allegory.
19. Proverbs, epitaphs, and epigrams are short statements of moral truth made striking by some
figures of speech. When collected to form an extended work they are wisdom literature.
20. The novel is any longer narrative in prose. Most typically the novel is a comic epic in prose,
but frequently it is tragic, or romantic, or even didactic, or it emphasizes the description of
character.
Special forms of the novel are the picaresque (comic and adventurous), the historical romance
(making use of historical material), the realistic, naturalistic, social protest novel (descriptive
and ethical in purpose), the mystery and murder novels (in which the discovery of the crime is
the chief element of the plot), the horror novel or Gothic novel (melodramatic and sensational),
and various types of novels in series.
21. The short-story is like the novel but it does not treat an action which is truly complete, but
rather an episode. In verse it is usually called merely a short verse-narrative.
22. The lyric poem is a short work in verse which approaches the nature of music since it
principally represents emotion, that is, a transient state of character.
23. An elegy is a lyric representing sorrow for the dead or commemorating past happiness.
There are also patriotic songs, songs of conviviality (drinking songs, etc.), wedding songs
(epithalmia), love songs, and comic songs.
24.The soliloquy is a lyrical poem or speech in which the character dwells on his own thoughts
and feelings in a reflective mood.
25. The ode is a lyric of more elaborate form written in praise of a person, ideal, or thing.
26. The ballad is a lyric which makes use of narrative. The dramatic monologue is a lyric
which resembles an episode of a play.
27. The descriptive poem is a lyric (sometimes, however, rather long) in which emotions are
shown through the description of nature.
28. A pastoral (ecologue, bucolic poem, idyl) is a poem which contrasts the virtues of the simple
country life or of ancient times with modern luxury and vice.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
29. A didactic or philosophical poem is one in which the element of thought is emphasized in
the representation, rather than plot or character.
30. The sonnet is a lyric in 14 lines of iambic pentameter verse divided into a contrasting octet
(8 lines) and a sextet (6 lines).
The definitions of other verse forms and of the complicated "French forms" of verse will be
found in the books mentioned in the bibliography.
The principal task of the first semester should be the preparation of a documented term paper; of
the second semester, the writing of an essay in literary criticism, or an original literary work with
a self-criticism.
The student should read several essays and magazine articles with a view to
contrasting methods of treatment. He should then choose a topic for a term paper
and prepare a bibliography of works to be read in order to gather material for
writing on this topic.
B. Composition:
The student should make an outline of the essay or term paper to be written,
giving careful attention to its logical completeness and following the form of the
exposition given on pages 185-186. (See also E.G.C., pp. 3717-440 and K. and D.
IV, pp. 198 ff.)
C. Speaking:
The student may present a brief preliminary talk on his topic based on the outline
already prepared, making a special effort for clarity. The class should raise
questions and objections, which can then be incorporated in the final paper.
A debate, symposium, or forum may be planned by a committee which will make
use of the material of these talks.
D. Grammar.
During this year there should be diagnostic work on grammar. It is supposed that
the entire theory of grammar has been covered in previous years so that after
diagnosis of the individual student's defects by the teacher, the student should be
required to review these problems himself. In preparing the outline of the term
paper special insistence should be placed on parallel sentences and correct
punctuation. (See also the section on argumentation in K. and D. IV, pp. 240 ff.,
etc.).
Unit II: Rhetorical Discourse (pp. 198-207:)
A. Reading:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Reading with special attention to style. If English literature is being read during
this year, compare Elizabethan, neoclassical, romantic, Victorian, and
contemporary style. If American literature is being read, then consider, for
example, the difference in style between Washington Irving, Hawthorne,
Melville, and Emerson on the one hand, and a similar group of contemporary
writers on the other.
B. Composition:
The student should rewrite the formal term paper as a Popular talk aimed at a
particular audience. He should consider how to keep the clarity of his formal
presentation while gaining in color and interest. See K. and D. IV, p. 33 ff. on
exposition).
There should be class discussion on the problems of analyzing an audience, and of
concealing the rhetorical appeal.
C. Speaking:
The student should deliver his paper as a short speech. There should be discussion
of the difference between written and oral style, and the problems of expressive
delivery.
D. Grammar:
Review should concentrate on sentence structure and variety. (See E.G.C., pp. 11-
19 and K. and D. IV, pp. 240-281).
Unit III: Poetics: Narrative Forms (pp. 207-2291):
A. Reading:
Discussion of the drama, epic, novel, short-story, and short verse-narrative. The
principal theme of discussion should be to show the organic unit), of each work
provided by the action and catharsis. The characters and thought should be shown
as required for the action. Then the use of language, symbolism, meter should be
shown functionally, not as a mere series of "beautiful passages" or rhetorical
figures. The difference between the narrative forms in the subject selected and its
treatment should be thoroughly explored.
B. Writing:
The student should write, a critical essay on a single work showing its organic
unity. An effective device is to ask why the totality of the work would have been
injured by a different treatment of its various features.
Alternatively the student may attempt to write an original work, with a short essay
in self-criticism explaining why he has constructed his work in this way.
C. Speaking:
Students should read scenes from plays and explain and discuss their efforts at
interpretation, Special attention should be given to the art of reading aloud and its
use as family entertainment.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
D. Grammar:
See K. and D. IV, pp. 133 ff. and grammatical problems in narration. On
appropriate vocabulary, review E.G.C., pp. 18 ff.
Unit IV: Poetics: Lyric and Didactic Forms (pp. 207-221):
A. Reading:
Students should attempt the writing of the prose-poems and verse-poems of a lyric
and descriptive character. There should be detailed class discussion of the results.
After discussion the student should attempt to improve his poem.
C. Speech:
Students should listen to records of poets reading their own poems and discuss
their interpretations. Then students should prepare a concert of oral poetry. Better
readers should give solos, others should take part in a verse chorus. The writing of
an oral poem with choral and solo parts as a part of senior graduation program
might be undertaken.
If possible a formal debate or set speeches should form a part of the senior class
activities or graduation program. These should grow out of class discussions and
should not be merely individual activities, but an expression of the school
community.
D. Grammar:
PART TWO:
THE FINE ARTS
CHAPTER I
The Matter of Works of Fine Arts
God is our heavenly Father. He made all things by his creative power, and now he rules over the
world he has made so as to guide its development until it is a perfect and finished work of art.
To us men, whom he made in his own image, he has given a share in this fatherhood. He said to
Adam and Eve, "Increase and multiply, and fill the earth and subdue it, and rule over the fishes
of the sea, and the fowls of the air, and all living creatures that move upon the earth" (Genesis
1:28).
Thus, along with other living things, man has the power from God to multiply, to increase and
perpetuate his kind in the world. Yet this share in creative power is more than the mere physical
reproduction which plants have. Even among animals the parents not only beget their young, but
they feed, shelter, and even train them. Human young need to be carefully raised and guided for
many years. A human father begets his children, and then he must provide for them. Not only
must he gather food from nature, but he must cultivate food, and he must invent means of
clothing and shelter. Hence men develop the useful arts by which to take the things provided by
nature and develop and modify them so that they better serve human needs.
When man applies art to nature, lie is only bringing nature to the perfection which God has
intended it should have. Man by his art co-operates with God in perfecting nature. If, on the other
band, man misuses his art to destroy nature or to turn it to evil uses, then he is taking side with
the devil, who above all desires to destroy God's work and to bring it to naught.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
When a father has provided his family with its material needs by his skill in the useful arts, his
task as father has only begun. Children need food, clothing, shelter, and many material things,
but they have far greater need of education. The father educates them so that the image of God
which is in them may develop, and they may become not only like their earthly father, but like
their heavenly Father. "Be you therefore perfect, as your heavenly Father is perfect" (Matthew
5:48).
A father helps his children develop to perfect maturity in two ways. First he helps them develop
right habits of living, which we call moral virtues, so that they are temperate, and brave, and
just. Without these virtues they would be weak and enslaved by every temptation; with them a
man grows up self-controlled, strong, honest, and truly free. Without his father's guidance,
without his encouragement, and sometimes his punishments, a child would find it very difficult
ever to develop such virtues, But his father knows how to guide the child, because be himself has
the virtue of prudence. Prudence is like art, in that both help a father carry out his work, Art,
however, perfects material things, while prudence perfects human beings in their actions. Thus
prudence is the "art of life" and greater than any useful art.
Secondly, a father teaches his children not only to live rightly, but to know how to live. It is the
intellectual virtues which are the developed powers by which we know things (see diagram, pp.
448 f.). Under his father's guidance the child learns the useful arts himself, and he also learns
prudence to govern himself and others. These are the practical intellectual virtues, and without
them a child could riot become a father and help others. But the father also teaches his child to
know, not only the things which man can make and control, but also the greater things which
God has made, the universe and man himself. Above all be teaches the child to know God, their
heavenly Father. The virtues by which we know these things are the theoretical intellectual
virtues of understanding, science, and wisdom.
Our own earthly father, however, is not able to do for us everything that he would wish. As a
child grows he needs guidance that his family alone cannot provide. Hence part of our moral
development comes not only from our natural father, but also from our civic fathers, the officials
of the government. By their laws and regulations the President, the Congress, the Governor, the
State Legislator, and all the officials of the government help us to become good citizens. Even
when we are adults and have ourselves a share in government, we need also the help of our
fellow citizens and of their representatives to guide our lives and help us become perfect in
virtue.
Similarly, we need not only to be taught by our fathers, but we need also wise and learned men
who have a profounder knowledge to teach us in order that we might develop perfectly in
wisdom. Our universities, our scientists and writers, and our teachers in the lower schools, all
devote their lives to study of the truth and to teaching it to others. Even when we ourselves
become expert in some field of knowledge, we will not be able to know everything for ourselves.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
We will need to seek the help of those expert in some other field, and we will need light from
those great minds who see deeper into truth than we.
These governors and teachers did not give us physical life as did our own father, and yet they are
truly our fathers, since they give us the perfection of our moral and intellectual life. But this is
still not enough. For our heavenly Father has willed that we should be prepared, not only for this
life, but for life with him in heaven. There we will come to know him face to face, and we will
see that he is three divine Persons, Father, Son, and Holy Spirit. Our education would never be
complete unless we were prepared also for this.
For this reason our heavenly Father sent us his Son to redeem us from sin and to begin on earth
his heavenly kingdom, the Church. Our Lord is both a King to govern us in developing the
supernatural moral virtues Which culminate in the theological virtues of hope and charity, and a
Teacher to help us develop the supernatural intellectual virtue of faith which should grow into
wisdom. In order to carry out this mission in his Church as it grows here on earth, he has given
us the Pope as our spiritual ruler and teacher, and under him the bishops and all whom they
commission to guide and teach us. Thus the bishop and priest is most truly our father, for in
baptism he gives us spiritual birth, and by his teaching and guidance and through the other
sacraments he educates us supernaturally for life with God.
Our heavenly Father and our earthly fathers beget and provide for us and educate us because they
love us. Because they love us they wish us to be happy. True happiness is not something that can
be merely given to us; it is something which we must earn and possess for ourselves. Even our
heavenly Father does not give us the joy of heaven until we are prepared for it by a life of merit.
Happiness is a reward and it completely pays for all the effort we have undergone to earn it, The
way to happiness, however, is only by effort and by striving, and hence by suffering.
Our heavenly Father and our earthly fathers, therefore, do not pamper us, or keep us from work
and effort and suffering just because they love us. To keep us from these hardships would also
keep us from earning true happiness. Nevertheless, because they love us, they try to make the
way of effort as easy as possible for us, although it can never be without pain. When God made
Adam and Eve he intended that the road to heaven should be very easy for them, and still he
gave them a test, the test of obedience and of sacrifice. Because they failed that test, be had to
subject them to a harder way.
The way in which God makes our way as easy as possible is by giving us pleasures as the reward
of efforts, just as an earthly father gives his children little treats when they do well. Pleasure is
not happiness, because it is a passing thing, while happiness endures; but pleasure is like
happiness. It is the foretaste of happiness that should lead us on to the real thing.
If we review the various things a father does for his children, we will see that each has its reward
of pleasure. Thus the physical activities of eating, drinking, of begetting children, of sleep, of
comfort, even of physical exercise, all are pleasant, and this pleasure makes it easier for us to
perform them. How tedious having to eat three times a day would be, if there were no pleasure
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
attached to it! When these activities are carried out reasonably and moderately they can make life
very pleasant and healthful, but when they are indulged in to excess they make us sick, or they so
enslave us that we are unable to seek true happiness. The man, for example, who has become a
slave to food, or drink, or sexual pleasure may tell us that he is happy, but truly be is miserable;
and happiness can never be his, neither in this world nor the next.
The useful arts, therefore, not only make useful things for us, but they also try to make these
things pleasant. The cook not only makes food to nourish us, but also to be attractive both to our
eyes and our taste. The furniture maker not only makes a bed in which we can sleep, but strives
to make it one in which we can sleep with comfort and which is attractive to see. All this is good
and a part of civilization. If God has made the physical world not only useful but very very
pleasant, then we also should strive to make our works of useful art not only useful but pleasant.
Yet it is important for us not to become soft and luxurious. The nation that spends too much
effort in making life easy and pleasant soon is enslaved to physical needs and cannot gain true
freedom and happiness.
RECREATION
A wise father not only makes a home a pleasant place to live but he also uses pleasure in a child's
education. He teaches the child moral virtue by obedience and discipline, but be also permits a
child to play. The freedom of play is very pleasant. This pleasure is not merely physical like that
of food and drink which even a tiny infant enjoys. The pleasure of play comes also from our
imagination, skill, and intelligence. A child only gradually learns how to play, and when he plays
he is very much awake and using his imagination and mind. More complicated games are
possible only for youths and grown men.
Why do we need play? Because it gives us pleasure and rests us from serious work and effort,
and yet it is not mere rest and idleness, for it, too, contributes to our power to make a greater
effort. When a soldier is being trained to fight, from time to time he is allowed to play some
game. This is both because it is relaxation after his intense training, and because even while
playing he is hardening his muscles for further effort. Thus recreation is a pleasant form of
activity which rests and restores us for renewed effort. Children play hard. The young athlete
plays hard. Yet for both this is a preparation for something more serious, or it is not true
recreation.
Recreation is of two kinds, corresponding to the two kinds of education and the two kinds of
serious human activity. Moral activity with its constant effort at carrying out one's duty and
responsibilities has its counterpart in the kind of recreation we ordinarily call games whether
physical sports, or intellectual games like cards or chess.
In all such games we find the element of a contest, either against an opponent, or against one's
own score. In this way our emergency or fighting emotions, which are so constantly required in
carrying out our moral duty, find rest in a game in which we have the pleasure
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
of winning, without threat of losing anything really serious. Thus games are character-building
for the youth, teaching him courage, responsibility, and fairness, and for the mature man they
provide a suitable recreation from his duties in which he can still maintain his health.
There are also mental games which have the element of a contest: chess and checkers, cards,
puzzles, etc. These do not have the same advantages for physical health, but when played with
moderation they are good for the health of the mind.
The second kind of activity is the enjoyment of truth or contemplation. Many people are hardly
aware that such an activity exists. To them it might seem a mere waste of time. Yet it is the
highest of all activities and the source of every other activity which is fruitful. God himself rests
forever in contemplation, and yet he has created the entire universe and governs it every minute.
The author of Genesis, knowing how quick man is to ignore this activity of contemplation,
teaches us about it by showing that at the end of the six days in which he created the world, "God
rested." It is to keep this alive in our life that we are commanded to abstain from servile work on
Sundays and holidays, so that we may give some time to rest in the vision of God's truth.
All recreation, whether physical, mental, or contemplative, is a preparation for further activity. It
rests and renews our strength. But contemplative recreation is more than just recreation; it is a
foretaste of contemplation, and contemplation is not a preparation for activity, but the highest
activity of all, the goal and end of every other activity.
The fine arts produce works which are not only useful but beautiful. Something is beautiful when
it delights us merely to look at it. Hence works of fine art have their value, not in being used, but
in being contemplated. When a piece of music is played, or a movie shown, or a novel read, we
do not do anything with it, but simply listen and look and enjoy.
Thus the fine arts provide us with recreation, but it is a special kind of recreation. It is not
primarily physical, like sports, nor is it a mental contest, like chess or cards. It is a contemplative
recreation through which we begin to learn what contemplation is, and why it is so delightful.
The pleasure we get from the fine arts helps us to understand what God's happiness and the
happiness of heaven are like, where eternity passes in the vision of God's perfect beauty. The
man or woman who does not appreciate beauty can never conceive how heaven is a place of
perfect happiness, because they have never experienced any pleasures except those of the body
or of competitive activity.
Making a work of fine art is a combination of all these forms of recreation. It takes physical skill
like a sport. It also is a kind of puzzle in which the artist struggles with his material to arrive it
the form he has conceived for it. Finally, it is a kind of contemplation, because the artist has
always before him the beauty which he wishes
to produce. Hence, of all recreations, the making of something beautiful by singing, dancing,
painting, writing, or acting poetry is the most inclusive.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The contemplation which we first taste in the fine arts is not, however, the end of contemplation.
It is only the opening of a road. Works of art represent reality, but they are not the greatest
realities. Once art has opened tip to us the beauty of the world about us, we want to know that
world better. It is no accident that the Babylonians, the Egyptians, the Greeks, all of whom were
great artists, also became great students of natural science, nor that the advance of science in the
Middle Ages also brought an advance in the fine arts. In natural science we come to contemplate
the order of God's world, as Adam did when he first looked on it.
Art also opens up to us an understanding of human life. Through plays and novels, music and
painting, our experience is broadened and we begin to appreciate the sufferings, struggles, and
joys of other human beings, the drama of the rise and fall of nations and empires. Hence the fine
arts lead us on to the social or moral sciences.
Finally, from the fine arts we wish to come to know Beauty himself, God the Holy Spirit. It is
God's beauty which is reflected in the beauty of our world, It is his love and mercy which are
reflected in the story of human life. It is when we come to meditate about God in the light of
faith and with the love of charity that we come to know him, and that we arrive at true
contemplation. The saints like St. Dominic and St. Francis of Assisi were so fascinated with the
beauty and drama of the world that they thought of God every moment of their lives. So
absorbed were they in thinking of him that they spent many hours in prayer, sometimes whole
nights and days. When we see a movie, we are absorbed in the story for an hour or two and then
we grow tired. What a marvelous vision St. Dominic and St. Francis had that held them
enthralled for days at a time!
The saints enjoyed this contemplation as the fruit of many years of effort to achieve it. In order
that all of us might learn to pray to God in this way, the Church with the most wonderful art has
perfected the liturgy, which is a sacred drama wherein all the fine arts are employed to assist us
in prayer. The Holy Sacrifice of the Mass is the great prayer of Christ in which, through the
priest, he offers himself for all of us. In it is the great prayer of the Catholic Church which
publicly unites itself with Christ in this Sacrifice. Hence it is carried out with all the beauty of a
drama, in a noble setting, with rich vestments and solemn music.
Unfortunately, in the crowded life of today where men are so often starved for contemplation, or
filled with the cheap and monotonous "contemplation" provided by television, the liturgy is often
not celebrated with full solemnity. We become accustomed to a low Mass crowded into a half-
hour, and people often avoid the High or Solemn High Mass where the liturgy is celebrated with
its full rites. One of the most important things in education is to learn to appreciate the Solemn
High Mass, to be able to sing it, and to learn to cooperate with its celebration by the making of
vestments and the serving of the altar.
The diagram on the next pages shows how all the arts are combined in the liturgy and how
historically they grew out of it,
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
In Part One, Chapter I, on the Art of Storytelling (pages 25-58), we have seen that the matter
used by the storyteller is words. In the diagram on the next pages we see that the other arts use
sounds and sights for their material. Words we can find in the dictionary. Is there a dictionary of
sounds and of sights?
As a matter of fact, there are color-charts and color-dictionaries which give us an orderly
arrangement of all the colors, and there are phonograph records and tapes which give us samples
of all the kinds of sounds that can be produced by the human voice or by a full symphony
orchestra. We will here consider only in a very elementary way some of the characteristics of
sounds and sights which are the matter of the fine arts other than poetry.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
COMMON MATTER
The artist begins his work by wishing to form something out of matter. He wishes to carry out
the command of God which gave Adam power over material creation. when man molds and
forms and arranges material things according to some idea in his mind, he is using this God-
given power. When he does this for a good purpose, to produce something which is useful or
beautiful, then he is imitating God himself, who made the world in its original state and gave it to
man that man might help him bring the world to its final perfection. Thus the wise artist is God-
like, but he remains God-like only when he respects the matter with which he works and uses it
as God wishes him to use it.
PROPER MATTER
These various materials, however, are not chosen by the artist because of all their qualities, but
only for certain ones needed in the work of art itself. Hence they are only the media or bearers of
the qualities which the artist actually uses as the matter of his art. What are these proper
qualities? They may be any of those qualities which we can directly sense: color, sound, texture,
hardness or softness, temperature, smell, taste -- all of which we call the proper sensibles.
Actually, however, only color and sound have an important place in art, because only hearing
and seeing give us a distinct impression, and without such clarity beauty is not possible.
It will be readily granted that taste, smell, heat, and cold play little part in works of fine art,
although they may have some importance in poetic works. However, the sense of touch as it
makes us aware of textures, figures, tensions, and motions, does seem to be a real factor in both
the musical and the visual arts. We feel the impact of the beat of a drum, and we would like to
touch the smooth curves and volumes of a statue. Even in painting, the roughness or smoothness
of the paint has a definite effect upon us. Again, in watching a dancer we seem to feel in
ourselves the motions of the dancer's limbs. This "in-feeling" is called empathy, and we
experience it even when looking at buildings which appear to us very massive and heavy, or light
and soaring. Everyone knows how the designers of automobiles try to make the lines of their cars
suggest a feeling of speed.
The reason that touch plays this role seems to be because it is the most certain of the senses and
the one which makes us aware of the actual presence of things. (Did not St. Thomas the Apostle
want to touch our Lord after the resurrection to make sure he was really there?) Thus sensations
of touch reinforce and confirm what we know more clearly, but less certainly, by our sight and
hearing. Hence a play on the stage is somehow more exciting than a movie or television play,
because the actual presence of the actors affects us. Nevertheless, although touch reinforces sight
and hearing, the information it gives us by itself is too vague to constitute the principal material
of a work of art.
Color has three aspects: (1) hue; (2) purity; (3) brightness. In hue colors range through the
spectrum or rainbow, in which we see clearly four primary colors (red, yellow, green, blue) and
two secondary colors (purple and orange), and colors which are transitions between these.*
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
*This is a simplification of color theory which is quite complex. Green is regarded by some as secondary color
blended from yellow and blue. Neither pure purple nor pure red are actually found in the spectrum and can be
obtained only by a mixture of lights.
Of these latter red-green, yellow-blue, purple-orange seem to form contrary pairs called complementaries.
In purity, the colors of the rainbow are (approximately) pure. By adding white to them, a tint (pastel
color) is produced, by adding black a shade. White, black, and their mixture, grey, are neutral colors, that
is, white is a blend of all colors, black a negation of all colors, grey a mixture of white and black. In
brightness, colors may range from very dim to very bright, but dim colors appear as shades, and very
bright colors tend to look whitish. Pure yellow is very bright, pure purple very dark; the other lines are
intermediate.
Similarly sound has three aspects: (1) pitch; (2) quality or timbre; (3) volume or loudness. In
pitch, tones range evenly from very low to very high, but in such a way that any tone sounds
very similar to those tones which have 2, 4, 8, etc., times as many vibrations per second as itself.
Some similarity is felt between a tone and any higher tone (overtone) which is related to it by a
simple ratio between the number of vibrations of each (1:3, 1:5, etc.; see pp. 349 ff.). In timbre,
tones have different qualities owing to a mixture of the lowest tone with various of its overtones.
Thus the quality of a violin is similar to the human voice, but very unlike the sound of an oboe or
French horn. When a tone has no distinct pitch but is an unrelated cluster of sounds it is called a
noise. When it has a definite and sustained fundamental tone it is called a musical tone. In
loudness, tones range from very faint whispers to very loud crashes.
The human power to distinguish the fine differences of colors and tones is very great, but we
must train ourselves by constant observation to make these discriminations. Look at your hand
and see how many different tones of color there are in flesh. Note the color of its shadows. Place
it in different positions and in different lights to notice how these colors shift and change. Listen
carefully to the voices of others. Can you tell just why you recognize the voice of a friend? What
is peculiar about its pitch, its timbre? It is by learning to discriminate colors and tones that we
make ourselves sensitive to what the artist is doing, and by studying the work of the artist we
come also to be more sensitive to color and tone.
QUANTITY IN MATTER
Besides color and tone (and other proper qualities), our senses also perceive aspects of things
that are common to more than one sense (technically called the common sensibles). These are
quantity, position, figure, and motion. Quantity and position, we know, are distinct categories.
Figure is a species of quality, closely related to quantity, since a figure is simply the boundary of
a quantity. Position results from the relation of one part of quantity to another next to it. Motion
is found in every category. To these we might also add time, which is the measure of a motion
and which is known by sensing motion of some sort. Thus we can see the size (quantity) and
figure of a colored square, but we can also know these aspects of the square by touching them,
although we cannot tell its color except by sight. We can see the motion of a fan, and we can also
feel and hear it.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
These common sensibles are all quantitative and measurable, while the proper sensibles are
qualities. From one point of view, it is this quantitative aspect which is most important for art,
since it makes design possible (as explained in Part III, Chapter II, pages 344 ff.). But we must
also remember that unless such designs were presented vividly in color or tone they would lack
something of beauty, since they would not be so clear to our power of knowing which is rooted
in external sensation.
If we consider the words out of which poetry is made as sounds, then they are the same tones we
have already discussed. But words are also conventional signs which bring to our mind
something other than themselves (see page 5). What comes to our mind when we hear a word?
First of all, the essence or nature for which it stands (some words, however, stand only for
grammatical relations) which is known by our intellect; for example, the nature of a dog, the
moon, or a flower. Hence the matter of poetry is, first of all, objective concepts (things known,
see page 59), just as the matter of logic, dialectics, or rhetoric. But along with this concept there
also come to mind the images or phantasms connected with it, as well as other concepts and
images similar to or contrasted to it, which follow it by the law of association (recall and
memory). Hence a single word, like the word "rose," may bring to our mind a flood of ideas, all
of which are matter for the poet.
1) It lacks a direct appeal to the external senses. That is why can appeal to all our senses, exterior
and interior, even directly to memory, while the other arts are all limited. Hence in a way it can
include the matter of all the arts.
2) It has the power explicitly to present to us intellectual concepts, while the other arts can only
imply these.
Thus poetry by reason of its matter is the most perfect of all the arts and in a way includes them.
On the other band, it has certain defects which prevent it from replacing the other arts:
1) It lacks a direct appeal to the external senses. That is why we try to make up for this by
combining poetry with music (the sound of poetry spoken or sung, or even of prose) or acting, as
in the theater.
2) It represents its imagery in a vague way so that it cannot form a true design with mathematical
beauty. The poet may talk of the beauty of the moonlit landscape, or of music, but be cannot
convey to us their actual beauty of pattern.
BENEDICT M. ASHLEY, O.P.: THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION
CHAPTER II
The Forms of Works of Fine Art
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
If we are ever to think clearly about the problem of "form" in art we have to realize that this
word has many meanings; it is an analogical, not a univocal term.
In the broad sense of the word, "form" is relative to "matter," so that whenever we have some
sort of material, some elements or parts put together in a sort of an order, arrangement, or
structure, we may call that structure "form." In this broad sense, all the nine kinds of accidents
(see pages 59 f.) are "forms," because all of them give some kind of order to the thing in which
they exist.
Among the accidents, however, the one which most truly deserves . . . .
In the last chapter (see page 242) we saw that color and sound question, "What kind of thing is
it?" The proper sensible qualities of things which directly affect our different senses may be
called "forms." Color is the form of things perceived by our eyes, sound the form of things
perceived by our sense of hearing. Of these, color and sound especially deserve to be called
"forms" because it is by sight and hearing that we can best discriminate one kind of thing from
another.
In the last chapter (see page 242) we saw that color and sound are forms of the common matter
of the fine arts; the reason for this is that they give different qualities to paint, or glass, or stone,
or to vibrating strings and columns of air. But although they are forms of the common matter,
they are themselves the proper matter of the fine arts.
Although the term "form" may be used in these broad senses to apply to any accident, and
particularly to any kind of quality, in the strictest sense it belongs only to one species of quality,
namely, to figure.
If we ask most people what "form" means, they will spontaneously answer: "shape" or "figure";
and they will probably be thinking of the shape or figure of a beautiful woman. Thus "form"
means "figure." If we wish to distinguish the connotations of the two words, we may say that
"form" means a perfect regular figure. Figure and form are kinds of qualities, but they are
qualities very closely related to quantity, and may be defined as follows:
Thus in geometry we construct and study such figures as the straight line, the curved line, the
triangle, the polygon, the circle, the cube, and the sphere. Each of these is a quantity having a
definite boundary. For example, the circle is an area (quantity) bounded by a curved line
equidistant at every point from the center. These boundaries of quantity are its figure, and this
figure is not itself quantity but a quality of quantity; it is a form of the quantity.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Closely connected with quantity and figure are four other categories: place, position, vestition,
and timing (pages 45 ff.). If I draw the figure of a triangle on a sheet of paper, I can put it in
various places on the page. I can also turn it in various positions; for example, with the vertex
upward or downward. Similarly, the human figure may be in various places, and in various
positions (sitting, standing, lying down), and it may also be clothed (vestition) in "form-fitting"
or in baggy garments. Finally, as the bands of a clock move through various positions on the dial,
we can mark out parts of time to correspond with the parts of the circular figure; or as a runner
speeds to his goal, we can mark off parts of the time to correspond with his progress along a
straight line. Thus timing and the other categories we have just mentioned are closely related,
and we can think of a series of events in time as arranged in a sort of pattern or figure.
Thus "form" strictly means figure, but it may also be applied to other categories closely
connected with quantity. Quantity and the other categories which we have just mentioned all
provide a foundation for various relations (see page 454) of equality and inequality, similarity
and dissimilarity, nearness and distance, before and after, so that in describing figure we must
also take into account these various relations.
It should now be evident that a work of fine art that does not have form in the sense of good
design could not possibly achieve its purpose. A work with poor design would lack the most
basic type of beauty. It might have expensive materials, beautiful colors, or rich Sounds; it might
portray an interesting subject, or tell a moving story, but it would lack form. It would be the
material of a work of art as a pile of bricks is the material of a building, but it would not be the
completed work. A girl may be healthy without being very beautiful.
Oddly enough, many people miss this point. Girls are sometimes admired for beauty who really
do not have it. A girl with bright eyes, a glowing complexion, or a pleasant manner is often
thought beautiful, although actually she does not have regular features nor a good figure.
Similarly, in judging works of art many people are inclined to think that a work of art is good if
it has bright colors, or if it is about some subject that they personally like. A man who likes
hunting is likely to think that a brightly colored photograph of the woods is a fine work of art;
and a woman who likes children is likely to think that a picture of a sweet baby painted in lovely
pastel shades is a masterpiece.
This is not unnatural, and we need not object to people enjoying bright colors and pleasant
subjects. But we must recognize that it is not the work of art itself they are enjoying, but merely
something accidental to it. That is why the opinions of the public and the opinions of experts in
matters of art sometimes seem so far apart. The public cannot understand why a prize at an
exhibition should be given to a rather dull looking picture of some apples on a table cloth, while
a flashy picture of a beautiful girl is passed over by the judges. The difference is principally in
the fact that the judges are looking for the form of a work of art, and in the picture of the apples
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
they find a most complicated and interesting design, while in the flashy picture of the girl they
find very little design at all.
The public, on the other hand, has perhaps not learned to look for design and probably does not
even realize that it is the very essence of art. Good design may be greatly aided, by brilliant,
beautiful colors, and it should tell us something interesting and human (as we will see below);
but without it all the colors and subject-matter in the world cannot produce a work of art. The
same is true of music; brilliant or rich sounds, or easily memorized tunes, or a great deal of lively
and noisy rhythm does not make a good piece of music, nor does the fact that the music is
patriotic, or romantic, or tells a clever story. Without musical form or design such music is like a
collection of pretty silks and laces that has not been cut and sewn to make a dress. It is the
possible material of a work of art and nothing more.
ABSTRACT ART
It is the growing recognition of this true conception of art that has led to the surprising
development of abstract painting and pure music in the last fifty years, a development which has
outraged the public and which they find it very difficult to regard as anything but "insane art," or
"boiler-factory music." In an abstract painting or sculpture the artist gives us a pure design which
seems devoid of all meaning ("What in the world is it supposed to be?") and which frequently is
devoid of appeal in color or careful finish ("A child could do as well!"). By giving us a work
which seems "crude," sketchy, unfinished, the artist is trying to get us to forget about the mere
superficial qualities of color and neatness, and by not picturing anything definite he is trying to
get us to concentrate on the pattern. It is rather like a football coach deciding that the crowd is
becoming more concerned about the hot-dogs, the pennants, the chrysanthemums, the marching
bands, the majorettes, the cheer-leaders, and the mascots than about the game of football itself;
so he decides to cut them all out and give the spectators nothing but a hard-played game by a
team in dirty uniforms. The public would not like that, but the real sport fans wouldn't mind at
all. They would be happy to concentrate on the game. In similar fashion abstract art and pure
music are intended to be works of fine art cut down to the essentials with little appeal to the
ignorant public, but with a very direct and strong appeal to those who really know what art is all
about.
SIGNIFICANT FORM
We have just given the case for abstract art, but we hasten to add that the public is not altogether
mistaken in its astonishment at this type of art. The figure or shape or design of things is only an
accident. The human mind, however, is made to know reality, and the accidents of things,
although real, are only the most superficial aspect of reality. Reality consists of things, of
substances which exist in themselves. Accidents cannot exist in themselves but have reality only
because they exist in substances. Until our mind penetrates accidents and grasps the substances
of things it is unsatisfied. Perhaps at a circus or fair you have bought a paper cone full of pink
"cotton-candy" spun out of sugar, and you remember that when you bit into it you found it was
hardly more than slightly sweet air. The world of accidents is just as unsubstantial to the appetite
of our mind.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Accidents are the natural signs (see page 5) of the substantial nature in which they exist. A man's
color, height, shape, weight, etc., are the outward signs of his human nature. When our senses
take in these accidents our mind at once begins to try to read their meaning and to discover what
they signify. Of all the accidents those which are most significant to us are the figure, the
sounds, and the motions of things. If we see the shadow of a dog, hear its bark, or see it streak
across the lawn after a rabbit, we recognize it immediately and we understand what its nature is.
So habitual is it for us to read the natures of things through their figures that when we sit idly
watching the shifting forms of the clouds or the fire, or when a psychologist shows us an ink-
blot, we immediately see in these random shapes the likeness of animals or human faces. The
same is true of sounds, for if we listen to the wind or the waterfall for some time, or the sound of
the wheels of the train on the track, they may begin to suggest words and voices to us. The
tendency of children or of insane or delirious adults to see figures in the shadows and hear voices
in the wind is only an exaggeration of a universal human tendency to seek for meanings in every
shape and sound.
A form which quickly reveals a nature and which thus acts as an effective sign is a significant
form, in contrast to one which seems meaningless. The reason we resent abstract painting or
music is that it seems to promise a meaning which we can never discover. Purely abstract art is
inhuman, because it offers us a mere surface, a flow of phenomena instead of the reality we
naturally crave.
It certainly is legitimate for the mathematician to abstract from all reality except the accident of
quantity, because he is a scientist, and science sometimes gains by sacrificing depth for the sake
of exactitude (see page 370). The artist, too, may feel that by making his picture very
mathematical he is gaining in clarity of form what he is losing in richness of content, but this
sacrifice becomes too great when nothing but mathematical pattern is left. The history of art
shows that cultures like that of the Jews or the Mohammedans (who, for fear of idolatry,
banished the use of representation in art and confined themselves to abstract designs) did not
achieve artistic greatness.
As a matter of fact, the abstract art of today is really not so abstract as it appears. Most of it
actually has some meaning or significance because it conveys emotion. Very little music has
even attempted to reproduce natural sounds (except as an incidental novelty); yet music does
convey emotion, and has a rich emotional meaning. In an analogous way, visual design which
seems to resemble nothing in particular may have a definite emotional content, and may convey
a sense of joy or gloom, agitation or serenity. If it were not so, then architectural designs would
not convey any mood to us -- and they obviously do. Who has not felt the sense of serenity in the
façade of the Parthenon, or the sense of prayer in the interior of the cathedral of Chartres?
Abstract painting is a visual design which signifies emotion in somewhat the same way as music
does.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
What then about pure music, which seems to be free of any obvious emotional content? When
we listen to the music of Bach, we do not sense, to be sure, the same violent and obvious
emotions as in a piece by Tschaikovsky, or Wagner. We say that the music seems "intellectual."
The reason for this lies in the fact that there are two kinds of emotion. Some emotions are so
violent that they carry us along, blinding our intelligence and clarity of thought. Other emotions
are controlled, measured by our intelligence, kept in balance and harmony by our thought. Such
emotions do not blind us, but rather sharpen our intelligence and help us to think more acutely.
This is not a difference in the intensity of emotion, but in its discipline. Controlled emotion can
be much more profound and intense than sentimental, dissipated emotion. Many people who
compare the music of romantic composers like Wagner to classical composers like Mozart and
Bach at first find the classical music "cold," "intellectual," a mere pattern of sounds; but after
they know it better they come to see that it signifies most intense and deep emotion.
Granted that "abstract" designs and musical patterns often signify emotion, it is rather difficult to
explain bow this can be. We need to recall what an emotion is:
presented to the imagination as pleasant or away from an object presented to the imagination as
unpleasant, with an accompanying physical change.
So, for instance, when we imagine a delicious dish of food we have a hungry impulse that moves
us toward it, and we feel our stomach begin to get active and our mouth begin to water. The
basic emotions are listed on page 152.
In order to signify these emotions by a musical pattern we need to produce a series of notes that
move toward or away from sounds that are pleasant and unpleasant. A pattern of concordant or
related notes seems pleasant, a pattern of unrelated notes seems unpleasant. The pleasant pattern
seems restful and suggests a state of bodily relaxation; the unpleasant pattern is disturbing and
indicates bodily tension. When a design is suggested but not completed, then we are in a state of
anticipation and tension until it is completed. In this way a piece of music is a constant
alternation between the building up and tearing down of a musical design, and this movement to
and from an expected pattern or order signifies the emotions. If we see an expected design
dissolving or incomplete, the emotions of sorrow are signified; if we see it building up in spite of
obstacles, the emotions of joy are signified.
We can now understand why a work of art, if it is to have emotional meaning, must not be
simply a perfect geometrical design or pattern; why it must contain something which is
imperfect, incomplete, ugly, and disordered. It is not possible to present the pleasant in an
effective and intense way without also suggesting the unpleasant, or at least the less pleasant. A
piece of music which was all sweet chords, or a picture which had a perfect balance of pure
colors, would seem emotionally empty because they would not suggest to us the movement of
emotions from the unpleasant to the pleasant. A story with no villain, no conflict, no danger is
bound to be insipid. That is why good works of art at first sight sometimes seem shocking or
strange or depressing. It is because we have noticed the unpleasant element, and have not yet
perceived how this unpleasant element is present only as a means to intensify the emotional
movement toward the pleasant. The apparent disorder exists only to bring us to a profound order,
just as in the universe sin and sorrow exist only to awaken us to the pursuit of true happiness.
This does not mean, however, that there must always be something ugly for there to be
something beautiful. God is Beauty without ugliness of any sort because he is Eternal Beauty.
But creatures arrive at beauty and goodness only by a long journey, and every journey not only
has a goal, but also a place of departure. We journey toward Beauty only by leaving ugliness
behind.
It may appear very surprising that we are able to read the emotional meaning of a piece of music
or a design just by looking or listening to it, even when we have had no training in these arts.
And yet people spontaneously understand the joyfulness or sadness of a great deal of music and
design. The reason is that we are naturally inclined to read this visual or musical language of the
emotions because the appearance of our bodies and the sound of our voices are natural signs of
our emotional states.
Even a small child soon learns to read its mother's emotions from her facial expression, from her
calm or nervous gestures, and from the tone of her voice. When we watch a fine actor we are
amazed to see how his body and his voice seem to reveal his interior feelings by their slightest
changes. Thus the human body in its movements, postures, expressions indicates the interior
tension or repose that accompany emotion (see definition above, page 254), and so does the
human voice which is so affected by the muscular tensions of the face, throat, and chest, and by
our breathing.
When our body is in repose (standing or sitting easily), it forms a perfect symmetrical pattern;
and so, in a similar state, does our face. When we are moved by emotion, this pattern is disturbed
and goes through a series of shifting appearances until we return to repose. In dancing or acting
we see this alternation of repose and movement. The voice also has its rest and repose, silence or
a clear, even tone. When we are moved, the voice rises or falls, grows stronger or weakens, and
then returns again to repose. It follows, then, that the pattern of design or of music of which we
have been speaking is natural to man, so from our acquaintance with the human body and voice
we quickly come to read this natural language.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
ART AS IMITATION
We can now understand the famous saying of the great Greek philosopher, that art is imitation.
In Greek the word is mimesis, the same word from which comes our word "mimic." No doubt
Aristotle particularly had in mind the actor who mimics or imitates a character in a story. He
says, however, that music also is imitative (Politics, VIII, 1340a, 19), because it so subtly
portrays the emotions. By this he means that the work of art is a significant form, as we have
already explained, not that it is a photographic copy of the appearance of something. If he had
meant the latter he certainly could not have cited music as an obvious example of imitation, since
music is no obvious likeness of anything.
Some have argued that "imitation" was taken by Aristotle to mean that the artist does for his
work of art what nature does for the things it produces. According to this theory, just as nature
helps the seed to grow into a beautiful tree, so the artist develops a design from some germinal
idea and embodies it in his material. It is perfectly true that human art does imitate nature in this
way, but this is true of all arts -- of farming, of medicine, of engineering, of teaching -- and
would not be especially characteristic of the fine arts. Yet Aristotle uses the term "imitation" as
the specific difference of the fine arts to, define them in contrast to these other arts.
Aristotle tells us himself (Poetics, IV, 1448b, 4 ff.) that the fine arts are imitations in the sense
that they lead us to knowledge. By comparing the work of art with the thing it imitates we come
to know something which we did not know before. How is that possible? How do we come to
know by comparing the picture of a man with a man?
We can understand the answer to this question if we recall that we human beings learn to define
things by comparing similar things and then noticing the differences. It is in this way that we
come to distinguish between what is essential and important and what is accidental and
insignificant. Hence when an actor "imitates" or mimics someone else, we first make a
comparison between two persons who are unlike each other (the actor and the one he imitates)
and then we notice their similarity, the tricks of gesture, gait, expression, and pronunciation
which make them startlingly similar.
When we recognize this similarity we are very interested, because previously we had never
realized the distinctive personality of the person who is being imitated. But when we see these
traits put on by an entirely different person, we see them plainly and clearly and appreciate them
as we never appreciated them before. The mimic has said to us, so to speak: "Here is the very
essence of Mr. So-and-So. Now you know what Mr. So-and-So is really like, although you never
realized it before."
An imitation, therefore, is just the opposite of a photographic copy. The photograph is the
unselective reproduction of the mere appearance of a thing. An imitation is the selection of a
significant form, of those appearances which reveal the nature or essence of something. A
photograph is made by a machine that is without intelligence. An imitation is the work of an
intelligent man who sees through the accidents to the substantial reality of things and produces a
sign that enables us to do the same. That is why a melody, or an abstract painting, can be a true
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
imitation, although they are far from a mechanical reproduction of anything. Between the
melody or the design and the emotion which they imitate, there is a real similarity, a selective
and interpretative likeness of movement and pattern existing in utterly different materials.
Up to this point we have shown how even when works of painting or music seem very abstract or
"non-objective" they may actually imitate the emotions. But emotions do not exist of themselves,
they exist in human beings. It is the human being who is a substance, and emotion is only one of
his activities. Nor is it the highest human activity. Man fully lives, not merely in feeling and
suffering, but rather in thinking, willing, loving, choosing a course of action, and executing it.
Furthermore, it is not merely in some passing experience that he truly lives; rather it is in his
habitual, deliberate way of life that his character and personality are truly realized. If art were
confined to imitating man's emotions, it would be able to show us only a very fleeting and
superficial aspect of reality.
Hence it is that in poetic works, which are the fullest and most complete type of art, the writer
does not merely portray emotion (this is paramount only in lyric poetry, see page 216), but deals
with human action, that is, with human life as a whole. The scope of the imitation of a poetic
work, therefore, extends beyond emotion to the whole of man's nature and life, and to the world
in which he lives.
Is it possible for the arts which do not use words to go beyond emotions in their work of
imitation? It would seem that music cannot go any further, unless it is united to words or drama
as in a song or opera. Music presents emotion, and in that emotion we sense the control of reason
and of virtue which gives that emotion its own balance and symmetry. But music alone can never
tell us the objects of these emotions (the thoughts), nor the characters that feel them, nor the
situation that provokes them.
In hearing a piece of music we witness someone's noble sorrow, or exultant joy, but we do not
know who it is that feels these emotions, nor why. On this account music is very limited in its
scope, although it compensates for these limitations by its extreme subtlety and power in
imitating what it can imitate. The words of a poet or the expressions of an actor fall far short of
music when it comes to imitating the shades and changes of feeling.
It is for this reason that music is so often used in connection with other arts, along with words, or
as an accompaniment to acting or dancing. This is also the reason why it has such intense appeal
to people of deep emotions, while it may seem tedious and empty to those who are more
interested in the other aspects of life.
Architecture, which has been called "frozen music," has even narrower limitations. It cannot
show the shift or changes of emotion, but only a certain mood or atmosphere of grandeur, or
peace, or comfort, or whatever it may be. It may be said to imitate a habitual state of character or
emotion, rather than the emotion itself. Abstract design has these same limitations, and in spite of
the great fashion at the moment for such designs, we may be sure that people and artists will
soon tire of so limited a medium. Abstract design has neither the power of music, nor the scope
of representational art.
Acting and dancing have a much wider scope, since vision is the most informative of all our
senses. Before the "talking picture" was invented, the silent movies had proved that it is possible
to go very far in telling an effective story without words. Nonetheless, everyone is aware that the
silent movies were very limited in their dramatic scope. Without words it was difficult to express
the shades of motivation, and the story had to be confined to very broad simple effects. The same
is true of the ballet which can tell a simple story and express the related emotions very clearly-
more clearly than can a play. Yet a ballet becomes confusing if the story takes on any
complication or subtlety of plot, character, or thought.
In painting and sculpture even motion is eliminated. Hence these arts cannot effectively tell a
story. The efforts of some painters to suggest a story in a picture is more clever than successful.
To be sure, the technique of the comic-strip may be tried. In Chinese painting, in illustrations for
manuscripts and books, in some primitive Italian and Flemish painting, and in certain large
groups of mural paintings, successful efforts have been made to portray the separate incidents of
a story in a succession of pictures. Even here, however, each picture has to have an interest of its
own, and a single picture conveys a story only feebly.
What these arts can do is to portray the repose that completes or precedes action, and by showing
this repose as imperfect to suggest the action which is coming to rest or about to begin. In the
famous Greek statue of the discus thrower, for example, we see the athlete poised to release the
discus. In Michelangelo's statue of Moses we see the great lawgiver just about to rise from his
seat in righteous anger. In the "Winged Victory" in the Louvre we see the goddess of victory just
coming to rest on the prow of a ship and ready to fold her wings, and in Michelangelo's Pietà we
see Our Lady gazing in silent grief after receiving the body of her Son. The history of Egyptian
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
and Greek sculpture or of the painting of the Renaissance shows the gradual development of the
art by which the artists learned to suggest, in a static design, this beginning or coming to rest of
motion.
In the later periods of Greek and Renaissance art this skill was so abused that the static design
was destroyed by motions too violent for successful portrayal without actual acting or dancing.
In fine, each of the arts tends to be limited in its scope by the effective possibilities of the matter.
It pertains to the perfection of these arts to widen their scope, but not to do violence to it. The
great musician tries to give a dramatic and intellectual quality to his music. The painter and
sculptor attempt to suggest action in repose. The poet seeks to give a vivid pictorial and sound
impression in his poem. All, however, if they respect their own art, will not attempt to compete
with the other arts, nor try to do within the limits of one material what could be better done in
another.
The musician who tries to paint a picture or tell a story, the painter who tries to turn his poem
into a piece of music or a painting, all are striving to do the impossible, and thereby violating the
nature of their own art.
OBJECTS OF IMITATION
Since an imitation receives its form from the object imitated, we need now to ask: what objects
are imitated by the fine arts? The answer must be given in terms of two principles:
1. An artist should seek to imitate what is most beautiful in itself insofar as he can.
If we consider the first principle, then, of course, the most beautiful of all things is the One God
in the three divine Persons. God's Being is seen especially in the Father, his Truth especially in
the Son, and his Goodness in the Holy Spirit. Since beauty is a kind of goodness (namely, the
good of knowledge), the Beauty of God is seen especially in the Holy Spirit. Since beauty is the
splendor of truth, it is especially as the Holy Spirit is the very splendor of the Word of God that
he is Beauty.
After God the most beautiful reality is the Triumphant Church (taking its Head and its members
together) as it will be after the last judgment. This Church will then include all glorified rational
creatures and the whole glorified physical universe as its temple. The damned in hell will remain
to render this glory more clearly, in the same way that something of ugliness remains in a work
of art as the sign of the catharsis achieved. In this Church our divine Saviour and Our Lady are
most beautiful. By reason of his human nature, our Lord, who is a divine Person, is fitted to our
knowledge, and is thus most beautiful to us. But even more evident than the beauty of our Lord
as man is his sublimity, whereas his beauty is found most clearly for us in Our Lady, who so
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
perfectly resembles him. Our Lord's beauty appears especially in his actions, his life, since it is
by these that his Person is manifested to us. For this reason the history of the Church (and in it
the story of our Lord's life) is the most beautiful of dramas. The life of Christ is also strongest in
its catharsis, since we can completely identify ourselves with him who has become our brother,
and his life moves from the extremes of sorrow to those of perfect joy. It is in the Sacrifice of the
Cross and in the Resurrection that this catharsis attains its goal.
Among other human beings, the saints, who most resemble Christ, are most beautiful; and their
heroic actions, especially martyrdom, share the tragic power of his own life. But it is particularly
in the Holy Sacrifice of the Mass (which is a sacramental imitation of the Sacrifice of Calvary,
truly re-presenting it) that this beauty is found at its highest.
It is also found, however, in the humble life of the home where he lived in Nazareth, and in his
daily contacts with weak humanity. In these incidents is found the comic spirit, ranging from the
burning satire of his exposure of the Pharisees, to the gentle humor with which he dealt with his
disciples. The sublime sorrow of his life, however, prevents the comic from being seen there
fully, but it is fully evident in the life of his members in the Church, who alone of men can afford
to laugh at themselves. The sublimity of our Lord's life, on the other hand, is fully seen only in
the entire panorama of history outlined in the Bible and filled in by the details of secular
histories.
Thus it is human action (whether tragic or comic) which is the chief object of imitation in fine
art. For this is the highest object which appears perfectly adapted to our understanding and
sympathy, and hence the one which produces in us the most perfect purification of our emotions
(catharsis, see pages 152 ff.) and the most perfect contemplation of the beautiful. Divine things
and cosmic things are represented, but as they are reflected in human action, as its law and goal.
When we see human life in relation to its ultimate consequences beyond this life, in its relation to
God and the society of the universe, we have a tragic vision. When we see human life in relation
to the less consequential affairs of everyday life in human society, we have the comic vision. In
the former the catharsis is more profound, because it is a lasting joy attained by conquering
sorrow. In the latter the joy attained is less perfect and final; it is the commonplace joy of daily
life.
When we consider things below man we consider them as ordered to man and reflecting human
life, as similar to man and sharing in his beauty or ugliness. Sometimes they appear as obstacles
to his action (hence as ugly), sometimes as the instruments and appropriate setting of his action
(hence as beautiful). Such humble things also have a sublime aspect, since they reflect the
cosmic order of which man is not the highest part. They suggest to us man's subordination to the
Creator who made both man and ant. Thus in looking at apples on a table, not only do we see a
design, but also a reflection of man in his daily domestic life, and, further still, a reflection of the
mystery of the universe in which man finds himself as a part. Seeing the reality of the apples in
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
sunlight we realize that the world is not our work, but the work of someone greater than
ourselves whose art is infinite.
Consequently, the landscape painting, the still-life, the picture of animals, the poetic description
of the weather, are subordinate and minor objects of imitation in art which take their meaning
from their relation to human life and to God.
Since human action is the principal object of imitation in the arts, especially as it reflects the
divine action, we can now consider how we can give a classification of the fine arts. We can do
this by seeing the ways in which this object can best be imitated in the different materials of
words, color, or musical tone, which we have seen are the proper matter of the fine arts. The
division rests on the three possible objects of imitation: action, character, thought, and on the
three possible kinds of matter: words, musical design (which includes both melody and
rhythm), and visual design (spectacle). Words and musical design must include movement, but
visual design may be either moving or static. Words have their significance by convention,
musical and visual design by the natural expressiveness of the human voice and body.
Finally, the difference between the dramatic and non-dramatic manner is basically a difference
between the joint use of the arts to produce a synthetic work (in which human action is
represented on the stage in all its aspects) and the individual work of poetics (where the other
arts are omitted). Thus Aristotle's division of the arts (Poetics, 1) according to objects, means,
and manner is observed in the following division:
Definition: The drama is a work of fine art whose form is the representation of human acts in
their relation to divine and human law, along with the characters who act and their thoughts
about their acts, and whose matter is words, along with moving musical and visual designs
whose significance is derived from the natural significance of the human voice and body in
repose and motion.
B. The individual fine arts, each of which produces a part of the drama but which may produce
independent works:
I: Literature (poetics):
A poetic work excels in representing the element of thought by means of conventional signs or
words, along with spoken musical design.
II: Music:
1. Dancing excels in representing character as it shows itself in the movements of the human
body, by means of a visual design using such movements.
2. Painting and sculpture excel in representing character as it shows in the repose of the human
body, by means of a visual design using this repose.
3. Architecture and the crafts provide an appropriate setting or instruments for human motion or
repose, by a visual design adapted to these.
CHAPTER III
The Purpose of Works of Fine Art
TOWARD A DEFINITION OF FINE ART
A work of fine art is good because of its matter and form, not because it was produced by a
famous or fascinating person. Its purpose should be obvious from the work itself, as a well-made
saw is obviously for sawing. Hence it would seem that the discussion of the matter and form of a
work of fine art, such as that given in the previous two chapters, is sufficient for our
understanding of such works.
Nevertheless, this is not the case. We cannot be sure that the form of a work of fine art is really
excellent unless we have a very clear idea of the purpose of a work of fine art. We cannot say
that a saw is good for sawing if we do not understand just what sawing is. Furthermore, we can
judge that a work of art is well-made only if we have an accurate idea of the possibilities of a
human maker. To expect too little or too much in a work of art would lead us to unfair
judgments. Hence it is necessary to consider not only the internal causes of a work of art (matter
and form), but its external causes as well (the artist and the purpose of art).
In raising such questions, however, we must be careful to confine ourselves to proper causes.
The biography of an artist may be very interesting, but it concerns us only as it deals with his
work as artist. The purpose of a work of art concerns us only as to its artistic purpose. An artist
may be a murderer or a saint, and a statue may have value as a door-stop or a hitching-post, but
these facts are accidental to the work of art itself. A failure to remember this leads to a great
mass of irrelevant art criticism in which the artist is discussed at length, and the reactions of his
audience are detailed, while the matter and the form of the work of art are scarcely mentioned.
We are concerned with the artist only insofar as he produces an artistic form in a suitable matter,
and we are concerned with his purpose and the reactions of his audience only insofar as these are
strictly esthetic.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The answer to these problems will constitute a search for a definition of a work of fine art. We
will first look for the final cause in the present chapter. Then we will relate the matter and form
of art already discussed in Chapters I and II to this final cause. Then in the next chapter we will
deal with the efficient cause. The final and efficient causes have already been briefly suggested
in Chapter I (pp. 237 ff.), but we must now establish them in a more scientific fashion.
In investigating any subject scientifically we must first answer two questions: (1) Does it exist?
(2) What is its definition? (See pp. 231 ff.). In the case of a work of art the first question really
means: Do we need such a work? If a saw were not needed we would not be interested in
whether it existed or not, and if it were needed then we would make it if it did not already exist.
When we have decided whether a work of fine art is needed, we will have established both its
existence and its final cause, and hence have found the first element of its definition.
That we human beings need works of fine art is obvious from the fact that in every country, in
every age, and in every class of people such works have been made and valued. Even the most
"low-brow" family has pictures on the wall at home, and enjoys a movie or a joke. Works of art
are found not only in the highest civilizations but also in the dwellings of the cave-man and the
Eskimo.
Yet some people have actually denied the value of the fine arts for human life. This denial has
come from utilitarians and puritans. Utilitarians are those who say that the fine arts are a waste
of time and money, since they serve no useful purpose. We need food, clothing, shelter, comfort,
they argue, but who really needs an oil painting or a symphony? Would not money paid for
works of art be better spent in building houses or in improving health? Artists, they say, are
weaklings who waste their lives in dreams instead of really working to improve the lot of
mankind.
Puritans, on the other band, argue that the fine arts are dangerous because they make men soft
and luxurious and tempt them into sins of impurity or emotionalism. The puritan fears that a love
of art will only distract a man from saving his soul and the serious business of life. He suspects
that all artists are effeminate, dissipated, and probably drunken, and those who appreciate the arts
are dilettantes and snobs.
In the United States these two objections are often made. The American business man is likely to
be ashamed of a son who wants to be an artist, thinking that he will be a "sissy" and an
irresponsible failure. Yet the experience of mankind proves that these are mistaken attitudes. If
art has been valued in every nation as a noble and glorious thing, and artists honored as
benefactors of the human race, art cannot be evil or a waste of time. The utilitarian is illogical
when he says that only useful things are valuable. So is the puritan when he argues that art is evil
because some artists and esthetes have been evil.
The clearest evidence for the value of the fine arts is that the greatest men of the past and of
today have honored art. Our divine Lord himself loved the poetry of the Psalms which he recited
even on the cross, and he himself was a great artist who in his parables composed great works of
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
literature. The Catholic Church, following his example, has always fostered the fine arts, and
requires their use in its most sacred functions, especially in the Holy Sacrifice of the Mass, and
has condemned the puritans and utilitarians who tried to remove art from the churches.
The dictionary tells us that in present usage the term "fine art" has the following meaning:
Fine art is concerned with the creation of objects of imagination and taste for their own sake and
without relation to the utility of the object produced.
Painting, drawing, architecture, and sculpture (these four being often called the arts of design);
poetry, music, dancing, and dramatic art: -- sometimes restricted to the first four named.
We discover also that this term is not an ancient one. In ancient and medieval times men spoke
of servile art and liberal art (see page 20), but not of fine art. The term began to be used in
English in the 18th century as a translation of a French term, beaux-arts (arts of the beautiful).
If we look up the word "art" we find that it is from Latin and has the same root as the word
"armor" and the word "articulate." This root means fitting, appropriate, or suitable, as armor is
made to fit the body, and as something is articulate when it is jointed (a joint being a fitting
together of two parts). The Greek word arete, which means virtue (from Latin for manly, i.e.,
something suitable for a man) comes from the same root, because a virtue is the power of doing
something which is excellent or suited to the dignity of human nature.
The word "fine" is from the Latin word finis, which means end or goal, and is an adjective
meaning "finished, brought to perfection, subtle, delicate, refined, of marked excellence or
superiority."
Thus the origin of the term shows that the arts are skills or virtues by which a man can produce
something which is suitable or fitting for his purpose, and that the fine arts produce something
which is in a special way finished, refined, excellent, and beautiful. Hence we can see why in
current usage it refers to painting, drawing, architecture, sculpture, and sometimes also to poetry,
music, dancing, and drama, since all of these are beautiful things which are valued, not merely
because they are useful, but because they are enjoyable. Perhaps this is the deeper sense of the
word "fine"; for a thing is useful as a means to an end, but when it is valued for its own sake it is
an end in itself, and finis means end.
This nominal definition can guide us in our search for a real definition. We notice that there are
two things to define:
Which shall we try to define first? Obviously a skill is determined by what it produces, so that it
would seem we must first define the skill required to produce it.
This raises a difficulty, however. We know (see page 134) that only natural things can be
properly placed in the categories and defined. Are works of fine art natural? Some people have
argued that they are, pointing out that birds sing, bees build hives, and many animals have
mating dances. But these are known to be natural precisely because they are instinctive and
always performed the same way by all the animals of a species.
Works of fine art, however, are especially characterized by their inventiveness. Each artist shows
great individuality in his work, and each work itself is unique. It is clear, therefore, that while the
works of animals are produced by instinct and are natural, works of fine art are works of reason.
To be sure, some authors have said that works of fine art are the products of our subconscious
mind and they point to the fact that dreams are like poems, and some poems have actually been
composed in dreams. They point out, too, that children, savages, and even insane people
sometimes produce remarkable works of art, and that a whole school of modern art called
surrealism deliberately seeks to produce an art that wells up from the subconscious without the
control of reason.
However, without entering into difficult problems of psychology, we can see that generally
speaking artists work quite deliberately and are able to explain and criticize works of art. Even
when an element Of the fanciful and the dreamlike enters art, the artist keeps it under Control.
Furthermore, the human subconscious and the imagination
are not merely instinctive but are influenced to some degree by reason, Hence we must conclude
that works of art are not works of nature, but free human inventions.
Some esthetes have gone so far as to say that a work of fine art is of value without any reference
to human needs. This would be the theory of "art for arts sake" in its most extreme form. These
argue that just as the works of God, sun, moon, plants, animals, and men were created just to be
themselves, so man makes works of art just to exist as perfect works. This argument is
insufficient, God does indeed produce creatures each of which has its own value, but the things
less than man have been made for man's benefit, while man has been created (as the Catechism
tells us) "to know, love, and serve God," Irrational creatures are ennobled by serving man and
being used by him. Man is ennobled by serving his God. If this is true of God's works, which are
substances able to exist in their own right, how much more true is it of human works, which are
only modifications of the things which God has made?
When we look at the various things which man makes, we notice that most of them are useful. A
kitchen stove is useful to cook our food, a table is useful to hold our food, a knife, fork, and
spoon are useful to bring the food to our mouth, food itself is useful to nourish us. At first sight it
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
might seem that unless a work of art were useful it would have no purpose or value at all. This is
the opinion of the utilitarian, who says that all things have value only because they are useful.
But this view is self-contradictory. A thing is useful because it is a means to an end. The end
itself is not useful since it is not a means to anything, and yet it must be valuable, since it is
because of the end that the means has value. In fact, if we consider the various useful objects
about us, we begin to see that many of them have a value which is above and beyond their use.
Thus the chair, table, knife, fork, spoon, may not only be useful, but they may be beautiful. We
enjoy looking at them even when we do not use them.
Indeed, this is true, not only of human works, but especially of the works of God. Not only has
he filled the world with things useful to man -- the air, the sunlight, the earth, plants, animals --
but to these things he has given beauty which makes them delightful to look at and to bear.
Moreover, many things in nature for which we have little or no use are still very interesting to
study. A butterfly collector, a collector of minerals, or a botanist eagerly seeks out and preserves
in his collection many natural objects which he will never use.
Thus some works of art are only useful (a trash can, a paper clip); others are both useful and fine
(a beautiful teacup, a handsome automobile); others are only fine (a painting, a piece of music).
We should notice, however, that when a thing is both useful and beautiful there ought to be some
relation between these two kinds of value. In the Victorian age there was a common notion that
beauty and utility are opposites. Consequently when they wanted to make a useful object
beautiful, they tried to disguise its use. They concealed umbrella stands inside statues, they made
stoves look like little iron cathedrals, and they made grocery stores look like Greek temples, This
we can call the error of ornamentalism. That it is an error we can see from looking at the works
of God. The beauty of a horse is not merely due to its mane or its color; it is found in its lean,
clean, swift look. But this appearance is based on the fact that its skeleton and muscles are
perfectly fashioned for the use or function for which they are intended.
Much of the beauty of nature is found, upon careful study, to be a result of the usefulness of
natural objects. Modern artists have begun to realize this, and they have put forward the theory of
functionalism. According to this theory, if we make a building or an automobile or any other
object truly useful, it will automatically be beautiful. Functionalism is an exaggerated reaction
against ornamentalism. The true view is that the beauty of an object ought to grow out of its
usefulness, but that beauty is something above and beyond the useful, not merely a result of it.
Since a work of fine art is not necessarily useful, it must have its value in helping us live well.
Because this is so, one of the commonest views of fine art has been that its purpose is to teach us
morals and to persuade us by its charm to do what is right. This indeed would be a very high
value in a work of art, and without a doubt some works of fine art are most effective in this way.
For example, our Lord's parables are beautifully told short-stories, and they deeply affect us and
lead us to a better life. The great novelist, Tolstoy, argued that all fine art must lead us to love
God and our fellow men, and that this is its real purpose. Similarly, most poets have defended
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
their work by saying that it bad great moral value. "Let me make the songs of the nation," one
said, "and I care not who makes its laws."
But moral teaching and persuasion is not the only value a work of fine art might have in helping
us live well. Man has two kinds of activity which belong to him as a spiritual being. One is
action in the ordinary sense (working, talking, making, leading, governing, loving, playing) by
which he seeks his physical and social needs. We call this the active life, and it is lived by the
business man, the man in government and communications. The other kind of activity (which
seems to many not to be activity at all, but which is really the most godlike) is the activity of
knowing. The scientist, the philosopher, the theologian, the mystic, all live this life which is
most like the life which God himself lives. God lives a life of pure knowledge and love, and he
has created and governs the world without in any way turning from that life of pure
contemplation. It is this life which the saints in heaven share with him, and which we hope will
be ours to share forever.
This contemplative activity is the highest kind of activity, but it is also a wonderful kind of rest
or repose, a vacation of enjoyment, in which our activity is simply to enjoy ourselves. It is the
highest kind of activity, because the active life of business and government exists only as a
means to this end.
It is possible, therefore, that the value of the fine arts lies not in directing our active life but our
contemplative life. Which is it? The answer seems clear enough. In speaking of the fine arts we
always emphasize their beauty. But beauty is that which pleases when seen (see page 339): We
delight simply to look at it; we do not use it, nor does it lead us to do something, other than
simply to look and enjoy. Thus the work of fine art is characterized by the fact that we enjoy
looking at it, we take pleasure simply in knowing it -- and this is just what we have said is the
mark of contemplation. Although a work of fine art may improve us morally, this it shares in
common with many other things, and what is more characteristic of it is that it is of
contemplative value.
Does this mean that works of fine art as such have no moral significance? This again is one of
the ideas of the "art for art's sake" school, and is an exaggeration. The contemplative activity of
man is the goal of his life, but it must be moral. This means that we can take a true pleasure in
contemplation only if what we contemplate is true -- that is, God, or something which God has
made as he intended it to be, or something which we have made which is in accordance with
God's wisdom and law. If we were to take pleasure in looking at things that are sinful or
monstrous or false, we would be going against our own nature which was made to know and love
God. To be sure, a work of fine art may contain a representation of something sinful or evil as
one of its parts, just as in speaking we may sometimes quote words which are false or
blasphemous, but the work as a whole must be true.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Furthermore, not only must the work be true and good in itself, but it must be suitable for a
particular audience. Things that are good or true in themselves may still be an occasion of sin for
those who are weak.
These are negative requirements, but there are also positive ones. The things which we
contemplate and enjoy influence us. We tend to become like those we live with and love, and we
tend to become like the things we contemplate and enjoy. This is not an immediate effect, but
only a remote one, since we are not made evil simply by an occasional meeting with someone or
something evil. But when this association is repeated, then the disposition to evil is produced in
us. Hence the works of fine art which we contemplate have a remote moral effect on us, even
when they do not actually tempt us to sin, or persuade us to do right.
Because of this fact, a work of fine art ought to make us delight in what is true, noble,
courageous, hopeful, pure, charitable, so that we may become like these things. It ought not to
make us habitually ambiguous, petty, fearful, sensual, gossipy. Finally, since human life is short,
works of art which are not positively bad but which are trivial are a waste of time. We might be
rather enjoying those which have a strong and true moral effect, even if this is a remote one. As
we have seen, however, this moral effect is not the proper and specific character of the fine arts.
We have still not found a way to distinguish a work of fine art from many other types of human
works. The things which are worth contemplating are so because they are true and beautiful. If
they were not true, then, as we have said, it would be wrong to take delight in them. On the other
hand, if they are not beautiful they are not delightful.
Of course everything which is beautiful must first be true, since we would not delight in knowing
what is false -- the false is not satisfying to minds like ours made to know the true. When people
do seem to delight in what is false, this delight is perverse and unhealthy. On the other hand,
everything which is true must also be beautiful, since a right-minded person cannot help but
delight in the truth. It would seem, then, that the words of Keats, "Beauty is Truth, Truth Beauty,
that is all you know or need to know," are correct.
This is inaccurate, however. The beautiful adds Something to the true, namely, a fittingness or
appropriateness to the mind of the one who knows. Truth appears beautiful to us only when it is
vivid, clear, perfectly achieved by our power of knowing. Thus all truth is beautiful to a perfect
knower, but to human beings who have only a weak power of knowing, much that is true has
only a hidden beauty. To God and the angels this world appears marvelously beautiful, even
though they see clearly the sin and disorder that fill it, because these evils appear only as the dark
shadows which increase the splendor of its order as a whole. We stand so close to the world that
we cannot see its whole design. We are like men standing at the foot of a skyscraper unable to
see its beauty.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
For us human beings the things that are greatest, most true, and most worth knowing are not
always the most beautiful, while the things that appear most beautiful to us are not always the
things most worth knowing. Works of art excel in beauty, but they need not always excel in the
importance of the truth which they contain. But since time is short in this world, we should not
waste too much of it on beautiful trivialities when it is possible to find works of art which are at
once very beautiful and concerned with great truths.
A work of fine art, therefore, is above all something beautiful; yet this is not enough to define it,
since many beautiful things are not works of art. On another page (248 f.) we have seen that
beauty for us is found principally in mathematical patterns of color or sound. What is peculiar to
the beauty of a work of fine art? It is not to be found merely in the fact that the work of fine art
has a beautiful mathematical design.
We have seen in the last chapter (page 251) that such beauty is not fully satisfying to us because
we naturally desire to know more than surface beauty. Unless the form is significant of some
underlying nature, it seems trivial to us. If human art bad only the beauty of mathematical design
it would be inferior to natural things, whose forms are significant of the nature of the things. That
is why the modern architect admires the functional beauty of natural forms, and despises the
merely ornamental beauty of surface designs.
Hence the form of a work of art must be significant of the underlying nature, and we have
already seen how this is achieved through imitation or representation (pages 256 f.). A work of
art is superior to nature itself in this respect, since the imitation tells us
more than the original about the interior nature; an actor shows the character of the man he
imitates more clearly than the man would reveal himself in real life. The artist by intelligent
selection and emphasis of the significant details or properties of a thing helps us to see what is
essential and unique in it (see page 252). It would seem, then, that imitation is the specific
difference of a work of fine art, and it is by imitation that the artist leads us to contemplation,
which would thus be the final cause of the work.
This is indeed true, but it is still not sufficiently precise. Not every sort of imitation achieves the
effect on us found in a work of art. It might be possible to draw a clever diagram of a plant, for
example, which would be highly instructive as to its inner nature and function, without that
diagram seeming to be a work of fine art. We expect the work of art to appeal to our emotions, to
arouse our sympathy.
We can well understand why this is necessary if we consider that contemplation is hindered, not
only by an unclear, confused, or obscure object, but also by dryness, distraction, weariness on the
part of our feelings. If the artist is to help us contemplate, he must not only show us an object by
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
a clear imitation, but he must also dispose us to gaze at it by arousing our interests and winning
our sympathy. Works of fine art usually have some element of surprise, of the puzzling, of the
dazzling, or of the fascinating, that wins our attention. We might say, therefore, that the work of
fine art is an imitation arousing emotional sympathy, or something of that sort.
But again this does not seem sufficiently precise. What we have just described sounds like an
advertisement or piece of propaganda which is persuasive just because it arouses our interest,
appeals to our feelings, and then conveys its message. A work of fine art is, indeed, very close to
advertising, and yet it is utterly different. The difference is that the advertisement wins our
attention and conveys its message in order to get us to do something, to buy the product. A work
of fine art, on the other hand, wins our attention in order that we might repose in contemplating
its beauty, desiring for the time to do nothing else.
This is indicated by the classical term catharsis, or purifying of the emotions. The advertisement
channels our emotions to action, but it cannot be said to purify them. The work of fine art, after
arousing the emotions of interest and sympathy, goes on to bring them to a repose in the
beautiful object so that our vision becomes crystal clear. The emotions are said to be "purified"
because they now aid us to contemplate, rather than hinder us.
When our divine Lord said, "Blessed are the pure of heart, for they shall see God" (Matt. 5:8), be
was telling us that contemplation requires the purity and harmony of the appetites (the heart) as
its indispensable condition. If our appetites are disorderly, they will never permit the mind to rest
in the vision of beauty and truth. Permanent purity of heart can be achieved only by the virtues
which are acquired by grace and patient effort, but the work of fine art gives to us a transient
experience of this purity of heart. The sinful man hearing a great poem experiences, for the
moment, something of the wonderful calm and clarity of soul which is the permanent possession
of the saint.
Thus the work of fine art has imitation as its formal cause; yet this imitation must be such as to
produce a catharsis of the emotions, ending in the contemplation of what is imitated. This is
possible because the chief object of imitation in art is human action, and with human action we
feel a natural sympathy. In watching a play, we witness the story (imitation) of the life of a man
like ourself. This bond of similarity arouses our emotions. As the story by its significance begins
to show us the order and beauty in human life, our aroused emotions are harmonized and begin
to come to repose in the delight which we feel, and as they come to repose they are Purified, so
that our mind is free to delight in the beauty of the object without distraction.
At this point we seem to have discovered the specific difference Which distinguishes the work of
fine art both from things of natural beauty and from other works that have a merely persuasive
value. But a problem remains. If it is true that the end of fine art is contemplative, and that this
requires a purification of the emotions, and that permanent purity of the emotions is achieved
only by virtue, then it seems that a work of fine art is only a cheap substitute for being a saint or
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
a man of wisdom. While we are being charmed by a work of art, we can look at life with vision
and delight in it -- but only for a few moments, and then the spell passes. The wise man and
saint, however, have this vision and joy in life as their permanent possession.
In answering this objection we must first admit that works of fine art do often serve such
secondary purposes:
1. They have an educational value for the young person. Such a person does not have the virtue
or wisdom or power of concentration to be able of himself to enjoy a contemplative view of the
world. When reading a fine novel, a great play, or listening to beautiful music, be is awakened,
perhaps for the first time, to the wonder of contemplation. It is for him a foretaste or pledge of
what he may achieve by a life of effort to find wisdom. That is why Plato so wisely told us that
philosophy or the pursuit of wisdom begins when the soul is awakened by the beauty of poetry
and art. Without this foretaste of the joy of contemplation we would never make the effort to
attain it. This value of fine art is very great; but if it were the only value, then once wisdom were
attained works of fine art would become unnecessary; they would be only for beginners.
2. They also have therapeutic (healing) value for the person who is emotionally ill. Aristotle's
term "catharsis" is a medical term, and many have emphasized the fact that art has a calming
effect on the emotionally disturbed. By reading a novel or watching a play, or particularly by
listening to music, these morbid emotions are released and calmed, and balance is restored within
the soul. There is no doubt that works of fine art have this healing power and that occasionally --
in times of intense sorrow, of illness, or simply of moodiness -- the enjoyment of art is an
effective cure. However, this again is only a substitutional value, since it makes art useful only to
a few and in exceptional situations.
But there is a primary value in the fine arts even for the wise and healthy man. We have already
said (page 277) that for us human beings beauty and truth are not always proportional. Some
rather unimportant or merely probable truths are very beautiful, while some very great truths are
so far above us that we achieve them only with great effort. We must rise, so to speak, above the
human level to the divine. This is true of the deepest truths of philosophy, but it is even truer of
the supernatural truths which we find so difficult to consider in prayer without distractions.
Hence even for the wise man contemplation is an effort in this life. In the next it will be a bright
vision and perfect repose; here it is a dark and hard way.
Consequently, even the wise man grows weary of the effort, and requires rest and recreation. Yet
because he loves the truth which he seeks to contemplate, he does not wish utterly to put it aside.
It is here that the work of fine art is so great a gift. The work of fine art recreates us
contemplatively. It recreates us because it gives the pleasure of looking at something beautiful in
a way that is effortless -- or at least relatively easy compared with contemplation -- and yet it is
itself a continuation of contemplation. Such recreation is inspirational, since it both rests us and
elevates our soul.
We may therefore conclude that the purpose of a work of fine arts is primarily to give us a
recreative form of contemplation, although secondarily it serves educational and therapeutic
purposes.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
CHAPTER IV
The Efficient Cause of Works of Fine Art
ART AS VIRTUE
INTRODUCTION
It is obvious that works of fine art are made by men and women who are artists; they are
principal efficient causes. They also employ various tools, the paint-brush, the chisel, the
musical instrument. These latter are the instrumental efficient causes of a work of art. The study
of such tools is quite interesting and should not be neglected in trying to understand the arts. We
cannot fully appreciate a symphony or a concerto, for example, unless we have at least some
awareness of the way in which the composer has skillfully employed the tools of his art.
Here, however, we are going to pass over the instrumental causes Of the arts, and consider only
the artist himself and the art which makes him an artist.
Art as Expression
No one doubts that every work of art bears the individual stamp of the man who made it, since an
effect must resemble its cause. Hence we say that a man expresses himself in his art. This is true
of anything that a man makes, but undoubtedly it is especially true of the fine arts since their
content and style depend so much on the individual experience of the artist.
But it is important to remember the difference between an accidental and a proper cause. A
doctor may be a musician as well, but if be sets a broken leg he is acting precisely as a doctor,
not as a musician. As doctor be is the proper cause of healing, but as a musician be would be a
proper cause of music, and only an accidental cause of healing. Similarly, an artist may be a
good man or a bad man, he may have many abilities and peculiarities. All of these are accidental
to his work as an artist, which is good or bad because of his art, and not because of the kind of
man he is, Of course no one doubts that his other characteristics may hinder or help his work as
an artist, but they only indirectly affect the work of art itself.
Hence if we say that fine art is an expression, we either mean that it is an expression of a man as
he is an artist, or that it is an expression of him in his other, non-artistic traits. If the latter, then
we must admit that this is a real defect in a work of art, just as if the doctor while operating
paused to express himself as a musician by singing a song. The artist who intrudes his
personality or his autobiography into a work of art is a poor artist.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
On the other hand, it is perfectly true that the work of art is an expression of the man's art. This
art is greater than any single work which it produces, and it is legitimate for us to admire the
various ways in which the vision of a supreme artist is reflected in his different works. There is
little doubt that the different works of an artist cast light on each other, so that we understand
each play of Shakespeare better by comparison with his other works. Nevertheless, if we concern
ourselves with the greatness of Shakespeare rather than with the greatness of each work, we are
moving outside the realm of 'It into the realm of moral philosophy.
Is an artist "born" or "made"? Experience shows that whether he requires great gifts at birth or
not (we will discuss that below), be cannot become a great artist without acquiring a habit or
virtue of art. Some artists have produced remarkable works when still very young, but the first
works of an artist are never masterpieces, and most artists do not do their best work until after a
number of years of constant effort and practice. That the habit they acquire is truly a habit and
not merely a disposition is proved by the ability of the mature artist to do consistently fine work.
There have been artists who have produced one or two fine works and never been able to
succeed again. In such cases, it is not clear that the quality of these works is more than
accidental; but when the great artists turn out a flood of fine works, even the poorest of which
have distinctive quality, we can be sure that they possess a true habit. Since this is a habit of
producing a work of genuine value for human life (as we showed in the last chapter), it is a
virtue. Since it is the power to plan and direct something in a rational way, selecting the
appropriate means to achieve a definite purpose, it is an intellectual virtue.
The fine arts thus belong among the intellectual rather than the moral virtues, because they give a
special power to our reason, rather than to our appetites. There are five kinds of intellectual
virtue: insight, science, wisdom, prudence, and art. Restraining the immediate impulse to place
the fine arts under "art," we must consider each of these possibilities.
The habit of the fine arts cannot be insight, because insight deals with immediately known
truths. To be sure, there is a strong element of intuition or insight in the fine arts, and the
contemplation of the beautiful is a kind of immediate vision of truth. Nevertheless, the artist
cannot produce a work of art merely by insight. He may have an intuitive view of the ultimate
effect he wishes to produce, but he must choose the means to the goal. This requires deliberation
and reasoning, and we may define art in general as "right reason about making."
Neither can the habit of the fine arts be wisdom, although many have exalted poets as seers,
prophets, and the wisest of men. True wisdom is a knowledge of the ultimate causes of things,
and these ultimate causes are not anything that man can make or control, or even adequately
represent. The habit of the fine arts certainly deals with a work of art which man himself
produces, and hence can be "wisdom" only in a wide sense. An artist may, indeed, be a wise
man, but his wisdom is not his art, nor his art his wisdom.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Could fine art be science? Most people today would immediately reject this suggestion, on the
grounds that art is emotional and intuitive, while science is cold and abstract. Yet it can hardly be
doubted that every art is based on a real theory which establishes certain principles and rules of
artistic construction. Such a theory is science, since science is reasoned knowledge. Some, it is
true, have denied the possibility of an artistic theory or artistic rules, but this is contrary to the
fact that many great artists have expounded such a theory, and many great critics have shown
that such a theory is implicit in all art.
A stronger objection would be to say that the virtue of science, strictly speaking, is a theoretical
and not a practical virtue; it is concerned with knowing, rather than doing or making. Yet the
ancients pointed out that certain theoretical sciences are also liberal arts, because they make a
product which is internal to the mind, namely, the sciences of logic and mathematics.
LIBERAL OR SERVILE?
Poetics and music were considered by the ancients to be liberal arts. How can this be correct? Do
they not seem to produce something external to the mind? The poet or composer must first hear
his composition in his imagination, which is outside the intellect, and then produce it in physical
sounds.
This objection is not fatal to the ancient classification. All human thinking makes use of images.
Since, however, poetics and music are pure instruments of thought, formed spontaneously and
without any deliberate manipulation of physical matter, their use does not require a servile art.
As for the external sounds, these need not be produced by the poet or composer; their work ends
when they write down their piece in words or musical notation.
A skillful reader can recreate the work in his imagination without any physical production
whatsoever, and when a poem is recited or a piece of music performed this can be the work of
some one with a quite different sort of skill than that possessed by the poet or composer. Hence
the arts of composing poetic or musical works do not involve matter external to the mind, and
they remain truly liberal.
LOGIC OR MATHEMATICS?
Granted that poetics and music are liberal arts, should they be classified as logical or
mathematical, or should they be placed in some third division? A third division is not possible
for the following reason: To make something in our mind we must have some kind of matter"
capable of existing in our mind from which to construct it. This "matter" is either real physical
matter or not. If it is real physical matter, then we can make something out of it mentally only in
the sense that we mentally divide it into parts and figures. This is the work of mathematics (see
pages 303 ff.). If it is not physical matter,
then it is "matter" only in the sense of the multitude of concepts which exist in our mind and
which may be combined or ordered in various ways by mental relations. This is the work of
logic.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
1. Art as a kind of logic. Nor is it too difficult to discover the position of poetics among the
various kinds of logic. It certainly is not the same as theoretical logic (logica docens), which is
concerned with proving the validity of logical forms, or establishing the logical requirements of
proof. Rather it pertains to applied logic (logica utens), which considers the employment of
these forms in particular usages. (See pages 18 f.). It is not, however, a demonstrative use of
logic, since this pertains to the diverse special sciences, and poetry can treat of any subject
whatsoever. Nor is it the dialectical use of logic, since the dialectician makes no appeal to the
emotions. Nor is it the rhetorical use of logic, since the rhetorician, although he appeals to the
emotions, does not produce a catharsis leading to contemplation. Thus poetics is a special use of
logic having this last purpose: to produce a catharsis which leads to contemplation.
2. The logical form of art. What forms of logic does it use? A logical form is an argument,
made up of statements, and these statements are made up of terms. The two basic kinds of
argument are the syllogism and induction (see pages 140 f.). The syllogism uses universal
premises, so that in a poetic work which must be an imitation (and hence the representation of
something singular,) such an argument is not feasible. An induction, however, proceeds from the
singular to the universal (or sometimes from singular to singular). The abbreviated form of the
induction called an example is a singular typical case from which we pass to a universal (or to a
similar singular).
This is exactly what a poetic imitation does: the imitation presents a singular in a way which
renders it typical (see page 257). Hence in reading the story of Macbeth, we see embodied in his
example a universal human experience. Rhetoric too uses examples, but in order to lead us to
action (singular to singular), while a poem presents an example in order to reveal the universal.
Thus Aristotle says: "Poetry is something more philosophical and serious than history, because
poetry rather gives the general and history the particular" (Poetics, IX, 1451b, 3).
3. Poetic statements and terms. The statements out of which the story (the example or
argument) is composed must seem plausible. They are things that could or should happen (ibid.,
1451b, 1). Such statements are presented as true; although in themselves they may not be true,
yet they are not lies, because they are intended only to exemplify some universal truth. It is only
when what they exemplify is false that the author may be judged a liar.
The terms of which these statements are made are frequently metaphorical (see page 50).
Aristotle pointed out that both poet and rhetorician use all sorts of figures of speech, but that a
poet especially excels in metaphors: "The greatest thing by far is to be master of metaphor. That
alone cannot be learned, but is the sign of genius, since the right use of the metaphor means an
ability to notice similarities" (ibid., XXII, 1459a, 5).
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The reason that metaphors are especially suited as terms in an argument through example is that
by means of metaphors a poet can represent even very abstract truths in a concrete and sensible
fashion. Today some critics are inclined to define poetry as the use of metaphorical language, but
this is a mistake, since it is not impossible to compose a poetic imitation of human action in
words which are purely literal.
Since music and all the fine arts also make imitations just as poetics does, they too might be
considered as parts of logic, differing from poetics only in that they use natural rather than
conventional signs. Yet their logical character is much less evident, since, as we have seen (page
264), they imitate emotion and character, and only remotely imitate human thought and
deliberate action from which examples can best be drawn. On the other hand, their mathematical
character is quite evident, since they produce musical and visual patterns (see pages 249 ff.).
Thus the ancients were right in regarding music as a mathematical liberal art, rather than as a
logical liberal art, classifying it according to that in which it excelled.
The ancients did not consider the other arts to be liberal, but to pertain to the virtue of art taken
in the strict sense as servile art, producing an external work. Thus the arts of performing poetry
and music (elocution and musical performance) and all the visual arts (dancing, architecture, the
crafts, painting, and sculpture) were considered servile, and were generally grouped together as
theatrical art and architecture (including crafts, painting, and sculpture).
1. Painting and sculpture. Today this seems rather curious, for we honor these arts as liberal
professions. Yet again the ancients had a good reason. None of these arts can produce a work
merely in the imagination nor commit it to notation. A painter must himself execute his own
painting, the sculptor his own statue-or at least he must put the finishing touches to his work, if
the result is to be perfect. This is not accidental. It is due both to the fact that the material of
these arts is more unpredictable than the material of poetics and music, and also to the fact that
these arts do not have so exact a formal theory as does music. The painter and sculptor must
constantly work by trial and error, constantly readjusting the form to the matter. Until they
actually see the result they are not sure whether their idea is good or not.
2. Architecture. The same is true of the actor and dancer, but we might wonder if it is true of the
architect. Certainly the architect can draw up a blueprint and entrust it to a builder. Yet most
building plans are also adjusted by trial and error in the process of the actual building, and the
architect prefers to have control of this adjustment. In any case, there is a second reason which
makes architecture and the crafts servile, namely, that they essentially involve usefulness as well
as imitative value, and all the useful arts are servile.
3. Conductors and directors. An objection might be raised that besides the composer and
performer there are such people as the conductors of music, and the directors of plays. Their art
is a mean between the art of the composer and the art of the performer, since they have to
interpret and complete the score of the composer or the script of the poet. Solo performers have
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
the same character, since they interpret as well as perform, acting, so to speak, as their own
conductors. We must admit that such an art participates in liberal art. But it ought to be
classified as servile, nonetheless, since its chief concern is with the guidance of the actual
execution of the work of art in external matter.
We have seen that the arts of composing poetry and music pertain to the kind of intellectual
virtue called science, while the other fine arts pertain to servile art. What about their relation to
the other type of intellectual virtue, namely, prudence? Prudence directs human acts to the goal
of happiness. The artist need not be a prudent man. His task is complete when he has produced a
good work of art, and some great works of art have been produced by men who seemed quite
imprudent.
Nevertheless there is an intimate relation between fine art and prudence. First of all, because the
artist not only must have the virtue of art, but make good use of it, and this requires prudence.
The history of art shows not a few artists who have wasted their abilities, or used them for
distorted purposes. It is not possible for a man to misuse a moral virtue, but he can misuse an
intellectual virtue. Eventually this misuse of an art destroys the habit in the artist himself.
What is the prudent use of fine art? It must be used for the true end of the art, namely, for
contemplative recreation (page 281). When an artist uses his art merely to make money, or for
rhetorical purposes (even good ones), or as a pseudo-religion, or to tempt others to sin, he
misuses it. Granted even that he uses it for the right purpose, he must also consider other
circumstances. Recreation can be excessive, and must be sacrificed to greater and more
important goods. Sometimes an artist must sacrifice his art to become a soldier, or a teacher, or a
priest, or a mystic. Sometimes, too, he must consider that his pictures will be shown in theaters
to all kinds of audiences, some of whom are very young and some very weak or ignorant. A
work that is itself good for a mature audience might be an occasion of sin to such an audience as
this.
Furthermore, the Christian artist will be guided by a higher supernatural prudence which will
suggest to him that he must take into consideration the great weakness of men which results from
original sin, their materialism, their discouragement, and he will strive to make works that quiet
the passions, raise the soul to a spiritual point of view, and instil a sane hope and a firm courage.
Yet he will also not fail to humble human pride and expose hypocrisy and smugness.
A second reason that prudence affects art is that an artist must make use of his own experience in
imitating human life. Hence an imprudent artist will have great difficulty in imitating life in a
convincing fashion.
If he is a great man, then as an artist he might choose himself as an object of imitation and
produce self-portraits or autobiography. This would have the advantage that he might know
himself and his own experiences very well and be able to render them better than less familiar
objects. Hence there is no doubt that all artists are somewhat limited in their material by their
own personal experiences. Italian painters will paint Italian landscapes, and a Dickens will
choose his characters from the streets of London, and from among his own friends and the
incidents of his own life. Of course, the wider the power of the artist the less this personal
limitation will appear. On the other hand, the artist who makes the mistake of dealing with
subjects utterly remote from his experience can hardly produce a living result.
We have seen that the artist must have the intellectual virtue of art, and he will use this well only
if he also has prudence and experience. All these are acquired. Must an artist also have native
abilities and a certain kind of temperament in order to acquire the virtue of art?
Any normal human being can acquire any of the intellectual virtues with sufficient training and
effort, since they are the proper perfection of the intellect which is essentially the same in all
men. Consequently, anyone can learn to paint, or to compose, or to write a poem reasonably
well. Nevertheless, for some people this would require long effort and very careful guidance, and
only a few persons in the whole population are ever able to produce works of art which have
great or permanent value. It is a false notion, however, that sees the virtue of art as possible only
for a few experts. In a healthy society all liberally educated people have at least one or two of
these arts, so that they can recreate themselves and others.
For the great artist, however, certain native capacities are required. He must have an excellent
imagination and other internal senses, as well as acute exterior senses. All the great composers,
for example, had an extraordinarily good sense of hearing and a strong memory. In the musical
and visual arts the capacity for space-thinking," or ability to form designs and patterns, is
essential. The combination of mathematical and artistic ability is not uncommon for this reason.
With this, however, there must also go emotional sensitivity. Mathematicians, for example, may
have a wonderful capacity for forming patterns, but if they tend to be abstract and cold, remote
from human feelings and sympathies, they will not be able to be good artists. The artist needs
this emotional sensitivity in order to be observant of the human actions and feelings which he is
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
to imitate. To this must be added a long experience of human life and of various types of
characters of mankind, especially of great and good men, if he is ever to be able to portray such
people.
Personal Problems
These very characteristics of acute imagination and feeling give the artist difficult personal
problems. Too often artists become prey to their passions and live a life of misery and
enslavement to lust, drink, or discouragement. So often is this true that the public frequently
thinks of artists as "bohemians" and degenerates. Indeed, the Christian considering the vocation
of the artist must seriously face the moral dangers that beset such a vocation. The actor and
dancer face particular dangers because of the personal vanity to which they are liable and the
irregularity of theatrical life, but the other arts also have perils which are very real. It is for this
reason that fine art so often tends to portray life in its darkest and most degraded aspects, and is
seldom successful in portraying what is really good and noble. This is because often the artist
himself is not noble and neither are the people he knows.
Consequently, the great artist, in order to keep this sensitive and passionate nature in control,
must also be a man of strong intellect and will. He must have an integrity of character and a deep
prudence. Contrary to popular impression, such elements are found in the greatest artists;
although few of them were perfect men, they had a nobility, courage, and wisdom which were
admirable. It is only the lesser artists who lacked these qualities, and they were only able to
succeed in those arts where the imitation of subjective personal emotion is all that is aimed at.
Dependence on Others
It has generally been admitted, however, that even when a man has great natural capacities, and
has acquired the virtue of art, and the prudence to use it well, that he may still not actually
produce great works of art. In addition to the foregoing he requires inspiration. Inspiration is not
peculiar to the artist. No great human work can be accomplished by an individual alone. First of
all, be needs the help of the society in which he lives, which provides him with the education and
the materials and skills of his art. Great artists have usually lived in great cultural ages. The
magnificent flowering of art in Greece in the fifth century before Christ and in the cities of Italy
in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries of our era is evidence of this.
Furthermore, an artist needs to receive the truths that he expresses from wiser men than himself.
The virtue of art is directed more to expressing truth than to discovering it. Hence the artist
normally receives from the philosopher and theologian the truths which he expresses. It is the
tragedy of modern art that the artist has no one to teach him great truths to express in the form of
his art. For this reason, artists without the Christian faith, or even a deep philosophy of life, have
nothing to express in art except their own limited personal experience. This is why today art is so
introverted, psychological, and emotional. Our best novels are largely psychological studies, and
our best painting and music are "abstract" (that is, they imitate emotion).
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
When the artist has been inspired with some great truth, he has still the problem of rendering this
truth concrete and imitable. This requires a wonderful harmony between his feelings, his
experience, his imagination, his intellect, and his will. It is probably because artists particularly
need this harmony of all their faculties that they most keenly feel the need of inspiration. In the
other professions it is possible to produce a work at will, but the artist often finds himself unable
to work as he would like because of factors beyond his control. He has to "feel right."
This fusion and harmony of the artist's faculties is often produced by a strong esthetic and
emotional experience which fills him with a desire to produce a beautiful work. Such inspiration
comes from friendship, from romantic love, from patriotism, from religion, sometimes from the
beauty of nature about him. The artist who is to give us a foretaste of contemplation must himself
be encouraged by the sight of great beauty. Hence in the lives of artists we often find that some
factor of this sort has "inspired" their art. The disciplined artist, however, does not require
constant inspiration of this sort; he is able to revive in himself the vision of beauty which first
awakened him to his vocation. Dante lived all his life under the inspiration of his boyhood love
for Beatrice, whom he did not see for years and who died long before his greatest work.
Finally, the inspiration of the artist, like all inspiration, must come from God, without whom
nothing excellent can be done. No doubt God often helps artists through the ministry of the
angels, who not only protect men from evil but assist them in their nobler works. When the
ancient poets prayed to their "Muse," we may well believe that their angels heard them and
assisted them in their good purposes to make virtue lovable to men.
This brings us back to the point at which we started (see page 281), a consideration of the artist's
likeness to God the Creator. Today it is common to speak of the artist as "creative." This usage
reflects the atheistic atmosphere in which we live, in which there is always a desire to attribute
God's attributes to creatures. Properly speaking, only God is the Creator, and this power, unlike
many of his other powers, he cannot share with his creatures. St. Thomas teaches (Summa
Theologiae, 1, q. 45, a. 5) that God cannot give the power to create to any creature, not even the
highest angel, although he can give such tremendous powers as absolving sins or celebrating
Holy Mass to man.
It would be more reverent, therefore, not to speak of artists as "creative." To create is to make
something from nothing. The artist makes out of matter which he did not make, but which is the
creature of God. Furthermore, in making a work of fine art, he imitates some natural object from
which the beauty of his own work is derived.
We would fall far short of the truth, however, if we did not admit that, even if the artist cannot
create, nevertheless he can originate, he can make something really new which has never existed
before, and in this power to originate he manifests his likeness to God the Creator.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Certainly we are all struck by the originality of art. The fancy of the artist seems to create new
beings, strange animals, undiscovered lands, unique characters. Art seems to take us into a fairy
land, a different order of reality. Moreover, every artist seems to create his own new style and a
new subject matter. There are no really fixed species of art; for every work is unique, and in the
hands of a great artist old forms are completely transformed. This is confirmed by the fact that it
seems impossible for one artist to reproduce the work of another, or the style and subject of
another age. If he attempts this, his work is always inferior, not only to the original, but even to
the less ambitious but more original works of his own contemporaries. A gas-station done by a
good architect today in the contemporary style is usually better architecture than an attempt to
build a Gothic cathedral in the twentieth century. Hence originality seems an essential
characteristic of fine art.
Yet if the artist does not make his matter, and if he takes the form he puts into this matter from
an imitation of nature, then what does he make that is new?
Man's thought and art are essentially imitative of nature and God. Man can, however, co-operate
with God, not in creating, but in perfecting the universe, and indeed God wills that he should.
God has left nature unfinished, so to speak, and wishes man to assist him in finishing it. Since
the fall, nature has been disfigured, so that God also wishes man to assist him in restoring it, and
elevating it to a supernatural perfection.
Nature has two purposes with respect to man. First, it furnishes him with his material needs, and
through the artful use of these materials man further perfects nature. In doing this he imitates
nature, learning its processes and then co-operating with them. The doctor imitates the healing
processes of nature, but also perfects them. the other purpose of nature is to be known by man,
both because it is wonderful in itself and because through it man knows himself, but above all
because through it man comes to know God. This purpose is the more important of the two, and
man also imitates and perfects nature in this second regard. Nature is made to teach man because
it exhibits properties, actions, and order through which man comes to know the essence of
natural things and the God who made them. But these signs are obscured by the potentiality,
materiality, and chance of the natural world. Man, by ordering and beautifying the world, makes
it more intelligible.
It is in this way that the landscape gardener works with nature, but by his cultivation of the plants
he causes nature to become more beautiful and orderly. The work of the experimental scientist is
really the same sort of thing, because his carefully planned experiment and the instruments
which he has devised to extend the power of his senses cause nature to reveal itself more clearly
to the mind. Thus man perfects the intelligibility of nature, first of all by simplifying it, removing
the confusion produced by chance, allowing it to develop fully without hindrance. We have
already seen that the fine artist also does this by simplification and idealization of his object of
imitation.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
In this respect the artist is the cultivator, the midwife of nature, helping her to reveal herself.
Furthermore, he is a parent, since he produces individuals within a species. A father does not
create a new species but he produces a new human being which is his likeness and yet a unique
person. Similarly, the artist does not create man, nor human life, and yet he can individualize
them in unique characters and stories in a particular work. He does this by adding individualizing
characteristics in a new combination, and signifying them through the unique design of his work.
In mathematical designs there can be real origination, because quantity contains a potential
infinity of parts and figures, and we can divide a plane or a solid in ever new ways. These new
parts can then be ordered. This order must already be known by the artist, but in applying it to
new parts he discovers new relations which he did not previously know and which indeed did not
exist. Moreover, he can embody these designs in different materials.
Again, the artist deals with signs, and signs are connected with what they signify by associations,
by cause and effect, and by similarity. All of these connections are indefinite in number, and the
artist is free to discover and use new connections and new signs. Indeed, as Aristotle says, it is
the mark of the poet to notice unsuspected similarities and metaphors which can be used in this
way.
We may ask finally whether an artist can originate new species of things? He certainly can
originate new species of works of art in the ways we have already described, but can be originate
new objects of imitation? What of the figures of mythology or science fiction which were never
seen on land or sea? Such fictions are made by comparing one creature with another. Within the
genera of creatures (animals, plants, etc.), there are unlimited species which God could create.
Many have actually existed during the course of time. Man can conjecture to such possibilities,
although he cannot be sure that the thing he imagines is really possible until it is produced by
guiding natural processes, as we do in synthesizing new chemicals or breeding new varieties or
hybrids of animals.
By collecting the different elements which we have treated in the previous chapters we can now
give a definition of fine art:
A fine art is a liberal or servile art by which is produced a work composed of words, colors, or
sounds, so ordered as to imitate human action and thus provide man with virtuous recreation by
purifying his emotions, so that he may enjoy the contemplation of the beauty in the work.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
In this definition the genus is "liberal or servile art". The difference is provided by a definition
of the work of art itself, since a virtue is specified by its object. The work of art has the following
four causes:
In order to make this a definition of Christian art, we could add to the final cause the phrase "in a
manner that will assist him to attain to the vision of the divine Beauty."
This definition should make plain that the vocation of an artist is a noble one, although not the
greatest of vocations. The artist shares with the priest, the teacher, and the statesman the work of
raising man from merely practical and everyday problems to a consideration of the
contemplative goal of human life. He does not teach with the certainty and the authority of the
priest, teacher, or statesman, but he brings truth to men under the form of beauty, which is so
appealing. The work of art often gains a hearing where other forms of presenting the truth are
ignored. After our Lord's first sermons were rejected by men, he then began to teach in parables.
Hence the Christian ought to regard the vocation of the artist as one which is especially fruitful
in helping souls, since it is directed more to the spiritual than the corporal works of mercy, and
the spiritual works of mercy are the greater. At the same time he must be fully aware of the
moral dangers for the artist of which we have spoken, and not place himself in these dangers
without providing the proper safeguards of prudence, prayer, and penance.
If he undertakes his work to help man and to honor God, with the counsel of wise men, and in a
way which is approved by the Church and civil society, he has an assurance that God will
provide him with the graces needed to make his work good. At the same time he has to realize
that in this world evil and falsehood are permitted by God to try all those who seek what is good
and true. Hence the Christian artist will often find his work misunderstood, undervalued in
comparison to work that is cheap or dishonest, and often neglected even by those in positions of
authority. With humility and courage be must persevere in producing work that he knows to be
according to right principles and the laws of God, the Church, and sound civil culture, not being
tempted by human respect, by money, or by a spirit of bitter independence.
All this is hard, but it is what is expected in every vocation if we are to follow Christ.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
PART THREE
MATHEMATICS AS A LIBERAL ART
CHAPTER I
In the Old Testament the God-inspired authors gave us a summary of the way in which men of
ancient times had come to understand the world about them. In those days men were fascinated
by the numbers and measures of things. Even the most primitive of men counted and measured
things for practical purposes, using their fingers as their standard, so that even today most
systems of counting are based on 10's. In the Old Testament we find the patriarchs counting their
sheep, measuring out their plots of land, weighing grain and money. Many people still do not see
anything more to numbers and measures than their practical use in keeping accounts or working
out engineering problems.
Yet ancient men saw something in measures and numbers which was more important than these
practical values. They saw them as a reflection of God's wisdom in making and ordering the
world. The wise man says to God the Creator, "You have disposed all things by measure,
number, and weight." (Wisd. 11:20). That is why in the poetic account of Creation given in the
first chapter of Genesis the inspired writer arranges the works of creation according to 7, the
perfect number.
Why did they regard 7 as a perfect number? We are not sure, but it is probably because they had
observed that in the heavens, besides the fixed stars, there are seven luminaries that change their
position; the Sun, the Moon, Venus, Mercury, Mars, Jupiter, Saturn, and after these they named
the days of the week (as we still do, using the Germanic names).
As we read both the Old and New Testament, we are struck with how often numbers are
carefully mentioned, and if we study these we will find that many are used as symbols. 1 stands
for God as the source of all things. 3 stands for God also as he is the Blessed Trinity and the One
who contains in his Unity many perfections. 5 stands for a list of duties or obligations, as in the 5
Books of the Law (Genesis, Exodus, Leviticus, Numbers, Deuteronomy) and 5 books of the
Psalms, and 10 Commandments (which include duties to God and neighbor). 7 is the number of
perfect time, of a complete week, and a complete cycle of years. 9 is 3² and therefore an
emphatic three (as in our Kyrie Eleison). Thus the odd numbers are thought of as indicating
perfection, because they are unified and cannot be divided.
The even numbers have a different significance. 2 indicates war or opposition, but it also
indicates friendship, love, marriage, and also the confirmation of a testimony by a witness, since
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
at least 2 witnesses are required at law. 4 is the number of the corners of a square, and was
thought to symbolize the solid earth, or a solid building. Hence the universe was also thought of
as having 4 corners, 4 winds, 4 quarters, 4 elements, and to be presided over by the 4 Cherubim
who had faces like a man, an eagle, a bull, and a lion (the four most powerful living things: the
eagle among birds, the bull among domestic animals, the lion among wild animals, man above
all) with which we are familiar as symbols of the Four Evangelists.
6 was considered the number of evil, because it comes one short of 7 and is like the universe
without God (the six days of Creation without the seventh on which God approved his work).
Hence St. John the Evangelist in the Apocalypse uses 7 × 7 to stand for the Church and 666 (3
6's) to stand for Antichrist, the evil one who pretends to be God (3). 8 is considered the number
of eternity because it is 7 + 1, the eternal day that follows on the week of time. Hence our divine
Lord lists 8 beatitudes, and 7 petitions to the Lord's Prayer, because we pray for the coming of
his kingdom, but the beatitudes are the rewards of those who will enjoy his kingdom forever. 12
is the number of the Twelve Tribes of Israel and of the Twelve Apostles, because as 3 × 4 it
represents a nation (a four-square city) blessed by God (3), and the apostles are the foundation of
the New Israel, the New City of the Church. 144,000 which is 122 × 1000 stands for all the elect
who will enter heaven, namely, a vast multitude who have belonged to the Church.
The ages of the world are sometimes 7, and sometimes 12 (for the number of hours in the day),
and we live at the 11th hour. Finally the number 14 (7 × 2), which is the sum of the letters in the
name of David (using the letters as numerals, as the Jews sometimes did), symbolizes the
Messias, the descendant and heir of David, so that in the genealogy of our Lord in the Gospel
according to St. Matthew the generations from Adam to Christ are listed as 3 × 14.
This symbolism could be superstitious. It becomes so when it is used today in the pseudo-science
called numerology, because numbers can be merely accidental things without any meaning at all.
But as used in the Scriptures it is a beautiful metaphor to express profound ideas, and a
recognition of God's order in the world. We find it not only in the Books of Moses, but
especially in the prophecies of Ezechiel and Daniel, in our Lord's own sermons, and in the
writings of St. John, climaxing in the wonderful symbols of the Apocalypse.
The love of numerical symbolism found in the Bible reflects the culture of the great archaic
civilizations of Mesopotamia and Egypt in the midst of which the Jews dwelt. As the pyramids,
towers, and other great buildings of Egypt and Mesopotamia have been uncovered, we have
come to read their records kept on stone or clay
tablets, and we begin to see what a great part number and measure played in the lives of the men
of these ancient cities.
The proportions, shapes, and arrangements of the buildings show how much men then
appreciated beautiful geometrical forms in the universe and tried to copy these in their own
works, so that their monuments would fit into the plan of God's own mighty creation. The clay
tablets record not only accounts of business transactions, but the patient observation of the stars.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The Wise Men who came to worship our Lord in the manger were star-gazers who learned to
look for the True Light, through many long nights in the desert marking the paths of the planets.
A permanent reminder of these days is our occasional use of the sexagesimal system (based on
60 rather than 102), which was often used in Mesopotamia. It is probable that this originated in
the symbol of the year as a circle. Since the year has approximately 360 days, and these people
knew that if we take the radius of a circle and use it as a chord it will form within the circle a
regular hexagon (six-sided figure), they divided this year-circle into 0360 degrees, as we still do.
Each hour of the day also was given 60 minutes, and each minute 60 seconds.
This interest in numbers as at once practical and symbolic spread from Mesopotamia and Egypt
to all the lands which derived their civilization from them. In Europe in southern Italy it found a
special student in Pythagoras. We do not know much about Pythagoras (although he has given
his name to a famous theorem in geometry), but we do know that be founded a sort of religious
order devoted to a strict life based on the idea of number and measure in all things. Perhaps their
most important discovery was the theory of music, which shows that the relation of musical
tones to each other is due to a ratio between tones (see pages 349 ff.).
THE GREEKS
The discoveries of Pythagoras stimulated a still greater Greek, namely, Plato, to make
mathematics the basic study in his great school, called the Academy. Many of his pupils made
basic advances in mathematics and in the application of mathematics to astronomy, but it was
Aristotle whose invention of logic made it possible to turn mathematics into a true science.
Science means not only to know that something is true, but to show why it must be true. The
Babylonians and Egyptians had discovered many mathematical truths, but they had never
demonstrated them, nor was this possible until Aristotle's discovery of logic.
This scientific approach to mathematics, based on principles, definitions, and proofs, made it
possible to distinguish very clearly between three kinds of quantities:
2. Abstract quantity: 5, 6, x, y, a plane, a solid. This is the pure mathematician's way of thinking
of quantity.
3. Applied quantity: 5, 6, a circle, or square, used to count and measure less abstract quantities.
This is the way we use mathematics in other sciences, for example, physics.
Following Aristotle, mathematics was first organized and formulated in ancient times in the
Elements of Euclid. Modern achievements in mathematics have been very great and are
progressing rapidly today, but they are secure only when they rest on this ancient foundation.
We have seen why the ancients valued mathematics so highly. Is it still of value? We may
formulate the value of mathematics in the following outline:
A. Mathematics is valuable as a liberal art. The liberal arts are tools used by other subjects.
Mathematics is a tool subject in two ways:
The great tool of all thought is logic (critical analysis). Logic teaches us four kinds of argument:
poetic, rhetorical, dialectical, and demonstrative (see Introduction pp. 18 f.).
The first three kinds of argument can be exercised by the student on any kind of material, but
demonstration must be exact and hence it can only be practiced on material which the student
understands perfectly. But a beginning student cannot understand perfectly the material of the
other sciences. Only mathematics has material which is simple enough (the numbers and figures)
that a beginner can see and understand it clearly. This is because mathematics is abstract, that is,
it leaves out the complicated characteristics of real substances and considers only the pure
quantity of things. That is why there have been great mathematical geniuses who were very
young (e.g., Galois), but few very young men who have been masters in other sciences. Hence a
student will never master the art of logical demonstration except by practicing it in mathematics.
a. Natural science constantly uses mathematics, since the relations between the quantities of
natural things are easiest for us to discover. We know little about astronomy or physics without
mathematics.
b. The fine arts use mathematics because the beauty of things is found especially in their
proportions. Thus the theory of music, of poetic rhythm, of painting, sculpture, and architecture,
all make use of mathematical principles.
c. The social sciences use mathematics (statistics) because the complexities of social facts cannot
be reduced to order without mathematics.
d. All forms of engineering use mathematics for the same reason as the above sciences and arts.
B. Mathematics is valuable as a science. Mathematics is inferior to other pure sciences in the subject
which it studies. Quantity is little compared with God whom theology studies, or with the physical
universe which natural science studies. But it is better than logic, since logic studies relations that do not
exist in reality. Yet mathematics is better than all other sciences in its certitude and clearness. For this
reason it is valuable as a pure science, which it is delightful and enjoyable to know for its own sake.
We have said that mathematics is a liberal art, but this raises a problem. A servile art is one
which makes some external, material product. A liberal art is one which makes something in our
mind. How can mathematics make anything in our mind?
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
We make things in our mind by comparing, contrasting, combining, and separating the different
things we know (objective concepts) in some kind of mental order by means of mental relations
(see pages 454 f.). In this way we can construct a number in our minds. If I ask you to make a
number greater than 1091, you can easily make 1091 + 1, although you have never experienced
and could never live long enough to count so great a multitude of things. You can also construct
figures. If I ask you to think of a line and then divide it into two parts which have the relation to
each other of 1091: 1, you can do that, although you have never seen such a line.
We must understand, however, in what sense we "make" a number or magnitude. We can make
in our mind a "dragon" or a "shmoo," even though such things do not exist anywhere, and, as far
as we know, could not exist. We can also make in our mind the notion of a "square-circle,"
although we know positively that such a thing could not exist outside our mind. But the numbers
and figures which we make do exist in reality in some way, namely, in the potentiality of
matter.
There really are quantities in the world which we have experienced, and when we divide them
mentally into any number of parts which we wish, or into any sort of figure, we are merely
marking out mentally the parts which they really (but in a potential way) contain. Furthermore,
we mark out these parts by using points to divide lines, and these lines to divide planes, and these
planes to divide solids; and we produce numbers by counting these parts by the unit. The point
and the unit which we use to mark out parts exist in real things, and the quantity which we divide
is real and really contains these parts, although in a potential fashion. Hence although
mathematics makes something in our mind, it does this only in order to study something which is
real, and which we did not make, namely, quantity.
Hence mathematics is different from logic, because logic studies mental relations which cannot
exist outside our mind (for example: genus, difference, subject, predicate), while mathematics
studies quantity which can really exist outside our mind, even though for purposes of study we
construct it in our minds.* [* Some thinkers do not agree with this statement. We will explain
their opinion below, page 395.]
Since mathematics as a liberal art is a perfect example and exercise in logical thinking, and as
science is the clearest and most perfect of all, it must be taught and studied according to the laws
of logic, as Aristotle and Euclid saw in establishing it as a science.
An exact definition, therefore, must be in terms of genus and difference by which the thing
defined is located in a category. For example: a triangle is a polygon (genus) having three sides
(difference) in the category of quality.
It must also be noted that a definition may either explain the usage of some term (nominal
definition), or the nature of something which is known to exist actually or possibly (real
definition).
2. Exact statement: We must begin our mathematical reasoning with principles that are seen to
be true from the quantities which we have experienced or can imagine. These principles are
either:
a. Axioms: principles which are common to more than one science, for example, a whole is
greater than any of its parts.
b. Postulates: principles which are special or proper to one single science, for example, the
definition of a straight line is proper to geometry, and the definition of the number 2 is proper to
arithmetic.
During the study of elementary algebra all these processes are used, but the first of them, exact
definition, is usually stressed. In the remainder of this chapter we are going to develop some of
the basic definitions used in algebra.
WHAT IS ALGEBRA?
Arithmetic has been familiar to you from your first years in school. Algebra is something new,
but not a new science. The name is from the Arabian, al-jebr; it is derived from the title of a
book, Al-jebr w'al-muqâbalah, written by Mohammed, son of Moses of Kohwarezm (Al-
Khowârizmî), in the city of Bagdad about 825 A.D. This book was very often used as a textbook
in the Middle Ages. We are not sure exactly how the title should be translated. Some say that it
means "restoration and equation," and others that both terms mean "equation," but that the first is
an Arabic and the second a Persian term. In any case, it refers to the science of equations and
their solution ("restoration"). The Arabians derived their knowledge of mathematics from Greek
works preserved by the Christian peoples whom the armies of Islam had conquered.
Thus the actual knowledge of algebra goes clear back to the time of Euclid (about 350-300 B.C.),
although by the Greeks it was simply called arithmetic, or the science of numbers. Arithmetic
deals with equalities and inequalities between numbers (equations), but today we commonly use
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
the term to refer to the elementary study of the subject, while we use the terms number theory
and algebra to refer to a more advanced study of the same subject.
In arithmetic you have become familiar with the use of equations and of the familiar operations
of addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division. These are also basic to the more advanced
study which we call algebra, and to these we must add a less familiar notion, that of a class or set
of numbers.
Definition: A set of numbers is a collection of numbers having some common property that
distinguishes them from other numbers.*
* Note that we speak here of a set of numbers, using "set" in a restricted sense. Ordinarily "set" means a collection
of any kind of objects, called its "elements," whether these are numbers or not; the same restricted sense holds for
the following definitions.
For example, all odd numbers have the property of not being divisible into equal halves, and this makes
them different from all other numbers, and all squares have the property of having equal numbers as their
two factors; hence each collection is a set of numbers. In arithmetic we are used to dealing only with
specific numbers --5, 21, 101, etc. -- but at the level of algebra we go on to consider such classes or sets
of numbers. In order to have a notation for such sets of numbers, mathematicians in the 17th century
invented literal numbers, just as the Hindus at an earlier period had invented our numbers 1, 2, 3, 4, etc.,
to stand for specific numbers. Thus we might use the letter a to stand for all odd numbers, and the letter b
to stand for all even numbers, and the letter n to stand for some number, and we could write:
a = n + n, or a = 2n
b = n + n + 1, or b = 2n + l
The first equation would mean: "Every even number equals the sum of two equal parts"; and the
second: "Every odd number when divided into its two greatest equal parts has a remainder of 1."
Many students are puzzled by this very logical system of notation. To understand it, they should
remember that just as the word "man" stands not just for Peter, or for Paul, but for any and every
man, so a literal number stands for any and every number of a certain set of numbers: it is a
distributive universal term and not a singular term (see page 21). Used in this way, a literal
number is said to stand for a variable, because it might mean any one of the set of numbers.
Frequently, however, we deal in algebra with two sets of numbers which have definite relations
to each other, so that if we choose a number from set A, then we will find in set B another
number which bears this relation to it. For example if we select any odd number from the set of
odd numbers, we can find in the set of even numbers a number which is related to it by the
relation "greater by 1." We call any such relation a function, and we say that the second number
is a function of the first, and that it is a dependent variable, since it depends on our selection of
the first number, The first number, since it is freely selected, is called the independent variable.
Notice the following diagram:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Here are two sets of numbers. If we symbolize set A by the literal number x, and set B by the
literal number y, then x and y are variables, because we may select any of the numbers in set A
as the meaning of x, or in B, as the meaning of y. But if we consider the two sets as related to
each other by a function, and consider x the independent variable, then if we select 3 as the
meaning of x, we must select 9 as the meaning of y, y is said to be dependent on x, and to be its
function. This can be expressed in the following equation:
which means that any x is related to some y as its square root. Thus we can state the following
definition:
Definition: A function is a set of ordered pairs of numbers such that no two pairs in the set can
have the same first element and different second elements.
This means that we can consider A and B as a single set of numbers grouped in pairs having a
definite relation to each other, so that once we have chosen one number we can be in no doubt as
to its partner. Thus in algebra we are concerned not with specific numbers (3, 10, 21), but with
sets of numbers, and our equations state relations or functions connecting two such sets:
a=b2
× + y = z2
2 2
x +y =0
In each case the two sides of the equation represent two sets of numbers related to each other by
a definite function.
We have now seen that arithmetic treats of specific numbers, while algebra goes on to deal with
classes of numbers and the relations between them. But what is a number? In algebra we will
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
find that "number" is used today in a great many very different senses, that is, it is an analogical
term (see page 50). Analogical terms are perfectly legitimate, but they are very dangerous if we
begin confusing the different senses in which a term is used. Aristotle long ago took great care to
remove the vague analogies used in mathematics before his time, especially by his fellow pupils
in the school of Plato, and to replace them by careful distinctions of the senses of a. term, and by
univocal definitions. Since number is the very subject-matter of algebra, we must begin algebra
with a very clear notion of what a number is.
Some say that "number" is an "undefined term," but this need not be the case. A term can be
defined if it can be located in a category (see page 59). If we ask the ten questions which mark
out the categories (see page 45) we will see at once that numbers (5, 10, 21) answer the question,
"How much or how many?" which is the characteristic of the category of quantity.
All the things that exist in the world which God has made from angels down to water and stones
are in the category of substance. Each of these substances has many different characteristics,
which we call its accidents (see page 44). Of these accidents the most basic one in the world of
material substances is quantity.
Quantity, like all the names of the categories, really is an "undefined term," because it is only the
things inside the categories which can properly be defined (see pp. 128 f.), but we can give a
descriptive definition of it:
Definition (descriptive): Quantity is the accident by which a substance has parts, each of which,
if separated, would be another substance.
For example, a man has a definite quantity by which he has such parts as his head, trunk, arms,
legs, hands, and feet. Each of these parts if cut off would still exist as separate (although non-
living) substances. Similarly, if we pour fifteen glasses of milk from a full pitcher, we separate
the original quantity (a "pitcher-full") into fifteen parts, each of which is a separate quantity of
milk.
This is something very strange about quantity-namely, that it can be divided over and over again,
and yet, no matter how small the parts, it is possible (in thought, at least) to imagine these as
further divisible. We may say that quantity as quantity is potentially divisible to infinity,
although it never is actually so divided, since at any moment it actually has a definite number of
parts.
Definition: A magnitude, or continuous quantity, is a whole whose parts have position so that
each part has a common boundary with another part.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Thus in a line one part has position after another, and each part is joined to the next by a point. In a plane
each part lies in order and is joined to the next by a line. In a solid each part is in order and is joined to the
next by a plane. Thus there are three species of magnitude: the line, the surface, and the solid. The point
is not a quantity (since it has no parts), but is the boundary or principle of a line or its parts.
The second kind of quantity comes from considering the parts of magnitude but abstracting from their
position, and is called number or discrete (from Latin for "separated") quantity.
Definition: A number, or discrete quantity, is a whole whose parts have no position or common
boundary.
Below we will explain how we arrive at numbers. As the point is the principle of a magnitude but is not a
magnitude, so the unit (symbolized by 1) is not a number (since it has no parts) but is a principle of
number:
Today we frequently speak of the "number one" and include the unit among the numbers. This is an
example of analogical use of the term "number"; we call the unit a number because it is the cause of
numbers, just as we call a cigarette "a smoke" because it is the cause of smoke when burnt. This is
permissible, if we remember that the word is used in a loose sense only.
We have already said (page 307) that numbers can be concrete, abstract, or applied. Ordinarily
when we apply an abstract number, we apply it to count the concrete things from which it was
abstracted, but we can also use it to count spiritual things which in reality have no quantity since
they have no matter. Thus we can speak of the existence of seven angels or of the three divine
Persons, and these statements are true. Number used to count things without regard to whether
they are material or immaterial is used in an analogical sense which transcends the categories.*
*Do not confuse this with the term "transcendental number" now used in mathematics to refer to pi and other similar
quantities.
Constructing Numbers
We have already noticed that we arrive at numbers by counting the parts of a magnitude. A
magnitude is one quantity (a line, plane, or solid) and a number is one quantity. The magnitude
has parts, each with a position and a boundary, and potentially divisible, and the number derived
from this has corresponding parts without position and indivisible. To make a bigger number we
can divide one of the parts of the magnitude by a point, line, or plane. This gives us a new
number greater than the former number by a unit corresponding to the new part which has been
marked off. All units in number are equal, since they are indivisible. Thus the species of numbers
are determined by the ultimate unit. 2 is the discrete quantity or number formed by counting the
parts of a magnitude which is once divided. 3 is the discrete quantity formed by counting the
parts of a magnitude which is twice divided. This last definition is not circular, because we have
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
already defined the notion of "twice" when we defined the number 2. Thus we are able to define
any desired positive integer (the natural numbers) and to prove that it exists since it can be
constructed.
Number Systems
The system of natural numbers is potentially infinite, that is, we can always construct a number
greater than any given number. We could invent a new name and symbol or notation for every
new number, but this would soon fill a dictionary. Hence men have invented different ways of
naming and noting numbers by a small number of names and signs. Here are some of the systems
that have been devised:
A simple grouping system is a number system that consists of tally marks which are replaced by a
group symbol when the tallies become too numerous. The Roman numerals form a simple
grouping system of numbers.
This is an outgrowth of the simple system. There are special ciphers for the numbers in the basic
group, e.g., 1, 2, .... 9, and a special class of symbols for the higher groups, e.g., t for 10, h for
100, th for 1000, etc.
The ciphers are then used multiplicatively to show how many of the higher groups should be
indicated. This leads to representations of the type: 3,297 equals 3 th and 2 h plus 9 t plus 7. The
traditional Chinese-Japanese numeral system is a multiplicative grouping system.
A third method of number writing may be called a ciphered numeral system. In the case of a
decadic system one would denote the numbers from 1 to 9 by special symbols; similarly the
multiples of 10 up to 90, the hundreds up to 900, and so on, would have their individual signs. All
numbers can then be represented as a combination of such symbols in a very compact form.
Egyptian and Greek number systems are usually ciphered.
Positional number systems are based on the principle of local value, by which a symbol
designates a value or class which depends on the place it takes in the numeral representation. Our
decimal numeral system is a system of this type. For instance, in the three numbers 352, 325, and
235, the digit 2 signifies respectively 2, 2 × 10, and 2 × 100.
Positional number systems are closely related to the multiplicative grouping systems, and one
obtains a positional system from a multiplicative grouping system simply by omitting the special
symbols designating the higher class groups.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The only complication which the positional notation involves lies in the necessity of introducing a
zero symbol to express a void or missing class; for instance, it has to be shown that 204 is
different from 24. The essential discovery in the positional system may be considered to lie in the
invention of this symbol.
The many advantages of the positional system are not difficult to perceive. First, the numeral
notation is very compact and readable. Next, it is possible to express arbitrarily large numbers
simply by the digits in the basic group. Finally, and most important, it is possible to invent simple
rules for performing calculations (addition, multiplication, division) that can only be performed
laboriously in other systems. Although our positional system uses 10 signs and is said to be "to
the base ten," it is just as easy to have systems to other bases, let us say 2, or 12.
Kinds of Numbers
Every number is a species within the genus of number. The difference by which each number is
specified and defined is its last unit which makes it different from the number less than it
(because greater by one part) and also different from the number greater than it (because this last
unit is last). Thus 9 is greater than 8 by a unit, and less than 10, because that unit is its last, while
10 has still another unit.
There are many sub-genera or classes of numbers. Of these we can list the following interesting
classes:
1. An even number is that which can be divided into two equal parts without a unit intervening in the
middle.
a. Evenly even is a number which is capable of being divided into two equal parts and with each
of its parts similarly capable of division and so on until the unit is reached. E.g.: 2, 4, 8, 16, 32,
64, 128, 256, 512.
b. Oddly even is an even number, the halves of which are not immediately divisible into two
equals. E.g.: 6, 10, 14, 18, 22, 26.
c. Evenly odd is an even number which can be divided into two equal parts whose parts also can
be so divided and sometimes even the parts of its parts, but it cannot carry the division of its parts
as far as the unit. E.g.: 12, 24, 48, 96 etc; 20, 40, 80, 160, etc; 28, 56, 112, 224, etc.
2. Odd numbers cannot be divided into two equal parts because a unit always occurs in between.
A prime is one that has no other factors than itself and the unit. (It is called prime because it is
measured only by the unit or prime). E.g.: 3, 5, 7, 11, 13, 17, 19, 23, 29, 31, etc.
b. A composite number is a odd number that is factorable, or that is composed of parts other than
the unit. E.g.: 9, 15, 21, 25, 27, 33, 35, 39, etc.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The natural numbers or positive integers are the only numbers in a strict and univocal sense. We
have seen already that the unit and zero are sometimes called numbers in a wider sense. Besides
these, in arithmetic we are familiar with the signs of operations by which we construct numbers:
+ , - , × , ÷ , < , x² etc. In algebra and higher branches of mathematics many other signs of
operation are introduced. Furthermore, combinations of numbers and signs of operations are used
and referred to as "numbers." These we may call artificial (in contrast to natural numbers) or
operational numbers, understanding again that the word "number" applies to them only by
analogy that is, by an extension or generalization of the concept.
1. Zero. This stands for the operation of not taking a part in constructing a number, Thus 100
means that we take 1 one-hundred, but no ten's, and no units in constructing the number.
2. Negative numbers. These stand for the operation of counting in the reverse order, that is, in
the direction of lesser numbers. Thus - 4 means four units which would have to be added in order
to complete a given number. These were introduced in order to be able to perform the operation
of subtraction when the number to be subtracted is greater than that from which it is subtracted.
3. Fractions. A fraction is not part of a unit, since a unit has no parts. It is a ratio between two
numbers. Thus 3/4 is the ratio of 3 compared to 4. These were introduced in order to be able to
perform operations of division when the divisor is not a factor of the dividend.
The foregoing "numbers" along with the natural numbers form a collection, all of which can be
added, subtracted, multiplied, and divided by each other (excluding division by zero however).
Such a collection is called a field, and this field is named "the field of rational numbers," the
term "rational" indicating that it includes fractions (ratios).
Definition: A "set of numbers" is a field if it is possible to add, subtract, multiply, and divide any
of these "numbers" by any other, excluding division by zero, without going outside the "set."
Notice that in this definition we have widened or generalized the notion of number and hence
also of "set."
There remain, however, many equations which cannot be solved only with these "numbers", for
example, the equation Hence we add the following definition:
4. Irrational numbers. An irrational number is the limit of two converging series of fractions
(rational numbers). For example, in taking the square root of 2 (approximately 1.41421) we got
closer and closer but never reach a value without a remainder. The limit is greater than 1.41421,
but less than 1.41422, etc.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
If we add irrational numbers to the field of rational numbers we get the field called "the real
numbers." But still another type of "number" is necessary in order to solve all equations, If, in
the equation x² = -2, we attempt to take the square root of -2, we find Ourselves in the difficulty
that a negative number × gives a positive number; hence -2 cannot be the square of any number
in the real number system. Therefore we add:
5. Imaginary numbers. An imaginary number indicates the process of taking an even root of a
negative number. It is really no more "imaginary" than are negative numbers themselves.
This "set" of "numbers" is now sufficient to solve algebraic equations of any degree. How may
we now give a univocal definition of the word "number" as we are now using it in such a wide
sense? This is done by defining "number" as follows:
Definition: "Number" (complex number) as used in algebra refers to a quantity which can be
constructed according to the following formula: a +b , where a and b are real numbers.
For example, the number 3 can then be written as 3 + 0 , while the "imaginary number"
can be written as 0 + 1 . Since we can give a single meaning to "number" taken in
this sense, it is a univocal definition. The system of all these "numbers" is called the complex
number system" and it forms a single field. This field of natural and artificial numbers forms the
subject matter of ordinary algebra, which seeks to study the different relations between such
complex numbers.
A. Learning to translate arithmetical problems into literal numbers, and a review of the basic operations of
addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division.
1. The idea of number is clarified (as above) and the student learns to distinguish between
numbers and the system of notation of numbers. Then the use of literal numbers, the nature of a
variable, and of algebraic expressions (polynomials) are discussed. This pertains to the logical
process of definition.
2. The Student learns how to perform the basic operations with algebraic numbers. This has to do
with the logical process of statement, since the student is learning to translate one statement
(equation) into another.
1. Number theory: At this point it would be logical first of all to demonstrate the various
properties of sets of numbers, odd, even, prime, etc. Today this is ordinarily omitted from
elementary algebra courses, although among the Greeks it formed the main part of arithmetic. It
is a very beautiful part of the science, but less practical in application.
2. Equations: Most of the time is devoted to studying the relations between sets of numbers, that
is, algebraic functions. This study is ordered according to the complexity of the equations:
a. Linear equations
b. Quadratic equations
In this study of equations in elementary algebra, operations are stressed as in arithmetic. The
main problem is construction of a number which satisfies a given equation. Actually this is not
the main concern of mathematics as a science, which rather seeks to demonstrate that such a
solution is valid according to the laws of the number system. This demonstrative study of
mathematics is usually taken up only in the study of geometry; hence we will discuss algebra as
strict science in the next chapter along with geometry.
CHAPTER II
The Science of Magnitudes
THE BEGINNINGS
THE GREEKS, SCIENTISTS AND ARTISTS
In the last chapter we indicated that, while mathematical calculation was developed in a practical
way by the people of Mesopotamia and Egypt, and carried still further by the Hindus and
Chinese, it was the Greeks who made it a theoretical study. They transformed it into a true
science, rigorously logical in structure, and a model for all other sciences.
It was these same scientifically minded Greeks who first arrived at a perfect conception of the
fine arts. The art of Mesopotamia was strong and grandiose, but without grace or subtlety. The
art of Egypt was subtle and mysterious, but strangely static and without inner thought or feeling.
Only in the art of Greece is there achieved a living balance of all the elements of beauty. Their
art was classical (from Latin classicus,meaning "first class"), and became a standard for all later
art. Not, indeed, that art of later ages need confine itself to copying the style and subject-matter
of Greek art, as some people have thought but that we can learn from Greek literature, sculpture,
and architecture a true conception of the elements that go into a work of art and of the harmony
with which they should be united.
Today we are inclined to think of science and art as unrelated fields. The artist seems to be all
imagination and emotion, living in a subjective world of free fancy. The scientist seems to be all
facts and abstract theories, living in the objective world of experiment and measurement. Yet the
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Greeks excelled both in art and science. In order to learn something of this lesson from the
Greeks in this chapter we are going to try to get clearer notions of two questions:
Plato (429-347 B.C.) had learned to love the pursuit of scientific knowledge from the great
Socrates. When Socrates was put to death by the Athenians as a "corrupter of youth" because lie
had aroused this love of truth in the young men of the city, Plato left Athens and journeyed far
and wide in search of a teacher. In Cyrene, in Africa, he studied mathematics with an important
teacher named Theodorus. In Italy he met two famous men, Archytas of Tarentum and Timaeus
of Locri, who belonged to the ancient tradition of the Pythagoreans and who also were fascinated
by mathematics. On returning to Athens, Plato opened his school, the Academy, and engraved
over its portal the famous inscription:
Around him lie gathered a number of pupils, some of them especially brilliant in mathematics.
We know from Plato's work, The Republic, Book VII, that arithmetic, geometry, astronomy were
considered by him to be the indispensable foundations for the study of philosophy. Although he
himself was occupied principally with philosophy, be encouraged his followers to develop these
preliminary branches of science. Menaechmus, Dinostratus, Athenaeus, Helicon, and especially
Eudoxs made very important mathematical discoveries. Their names today seem strange to us,
and yet the very mathematical theorems which they first worked out are still taught in our study
of mathematics.
Among these pupils of Plato, Aristotle bad the most universal mind. He did not give special
attention to mathematics because it was by then the best developed of the sciences, and he was
anxious to extend the scientific method to wider fields, especially to physics, chemistry, and
biology. But lie did make a fundamental contribution to mathematics: lie explained and defended
the axiomatic or logical method in mathematics without which it cannot be a true science.
It was not until about 300 B.C. (some twenty years after Aristotle's death) that the first great
mathematical work employing this axiomatic method was written in Egypt, in the city of
Alexandria where the followers of Plato and Aristotle had founded new schools. This was the
book called the Elements, the work of an obscure teacher named Euclid.
We know little about Euclid except this book and a few lesser ones, but a story is told about him
which well illustrates his attitude. A pupil who had just learned the first theorem in geometry
turned to his teacher and asked: "What do I get by learning such things?" Euclid did not answer,
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
but calling for a slave said to him: "Give this fellow threepence [a slave's wages] since he must
be paid for what he learns." For Euclid, mathematics is a theoretical subject to be learned
because it is true and not because it is useful. He called his book the Elements because it contains
the foundations of both branches of mathematics, arithmetic and geometry.
This book has been more widely used than any other book we know of, except the Bible. Not
only was it a basic textbook for Greek, Roman, and medieval schoolboys, but also for the
students of the Mohammedan countries. It was used in schools until about fifty years ago, when
it began to be replaced by easier books. Is this the reason that we find such a deficiency in
mathematics among students today? Can it be that modern youth is incapable of thinking as
clearly as young people did in past times? We are accustomed to think of our age as much more
scientific than days of old, and yet we find it too hard to master the book which has been the
foundation of the whole history of science.
Aristotle knew perfectly well that such a high ideal of knowledge is not easy to obtain and is
rarely actually achieved, but we must measure our knowledge by the most perfect type of
knowledge possible. Euclid hoped to achieve such knowledge at least in the relatively easy field
of mathematics.
You will notice that the difference between science and opinion does not consist in the fact that
science is obtained by experiments or the use of some complicated instrument (like a microscope
or Geiger counter), while opinion is not. Nor is the difference that science uses measurement,
and opinion does not. Nor is it that science is objective, opinion subjective; nor that science is
certain, opinion probable. We can have opinions that are certain, objective, acquired by
measurement, instruments, and experiment -- and they still remain only opinions. We can have
science, on the other band, which involves no instruments, nor experiments, nor measurements
(although it must be certain and objective). What makes science to be true science is that it gives
us the proper reason for a certainly established fact. Until we have discovered such a proper
reason we do not have perfect science, and are still at the level of opinion.
Consequently, mathematicians before Euclid were mainly at the level of opinion, because they
had not carefully built tip the science of mathematics in such a logical and orderly way that they
could see the proper reasons for their conclusions.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
In order to correct this, Euclid kept before his mind the four questions which Aristotle had
outlined as the basic questions that must be asked in every science:
1. Does the thing we are trying to study really exist? For example: Is there really such a
thing as a circle?
Until we can answer this question there is no use going any further. It is impossible to have
scientific knowledge of something that does not exist, or at least which has not existed at some
time. "Scientific" guesses about the future are opinions, not science.
It might seem that we must first have the definition of a circle before we can even ask if it exists.
This is true of the nominal definition (see page 129), which tells us the usage of the word
"circle." But the real definition cannot be given until we have answered Question 1, since there
is no way to find out what a thing is, unless it is (exists).
3. What are its properties? For example: Can a circle be drawn inside a square so as to
touch all sides of the square?
Here, also, we first need a nominal definition of the property. In the case of a property this is
sufficient, since in answering the next question we will also settle whether the property exists or
not.
4. What is the proper reason that this thing (real definition required) has this property
(nominal definition)? For example: Why can a circle be drawn inside a square?
When we know the answer to Question 4, at the same time we know the answer to Question 3.
When we know the proper reason that a property is necessarily connected with its subject, we
know that property must exist.
In setting up his Elements, Euclid tries to answer these questions in the correct order.
If we open the Elements we find that it is divided into thirteen books as follows:
At the beginning of the first book there is a long list of definitions (23 of them), and at the
beginning of most of the subsequent books there are further definitions. These definitions are
nominal ones, merely telling us the meaning of the words Euclid is going to use. A study of these
definitions is very valuable in clarifying our thinking, and we will discover that some of Euclid's
definitions are not perfect. For example, his first definition is: "A point is that which has no
part." It would be better to define a point as "that which is indivisible but which has position," as
Aristotle defined it. Why is Aristotle's definition more exact?
Next Euclid had to answer the first of the scientific questions: Do these things which have been
nominally defined really exist? He does this by stating the following postulates:
The first two of these amount to asserting the existence of points and straight lines of any desired
length (potentially infinite lines). The last three assert the existence of a plane which is perfectly
homogeneous (all parts exactly the same) and perfectly flat; the last of these is the famous
parallel line postulate which has played a very important role in modern mathematics (see
Chapter IV, page 382). Euclid gives these postulates in this form because they are conveniently
stated for use in the construction theorems he is going to give.
Actually, Aristotle had already indicated that it would be sufficient to postulate only two things:
These are both needed because a magnitude (continuous quantity, see page 316) can only be
defined in terms of the simplest continuous quantity, namely, a line, while lines must be
differentiated by their position (given by points). Planes, solids, and any kind of figure in them
can be constructed by means of lines and points, as Euclid actually proceeds to do.
How do we know that these postulates are true? Euclid does not attempt to prove them, because
then they would not be first principles. On the other band, be does not merely assume them. He
takes them as immediately evident to us from our experience of physical quantity, or rather from
our images of physical quantity as derived from such experience.
These postulates are the proper principles belonging to the science of magnitude. Indeed, they
amount to a definition of the subject of that science, since when we define a line and a point we
really define magnitude (continuous quantity). In addition to these, we also make use of common
principles or axioms which the student must know even before he begins to study this science
and without which lie would not be able to understand the teacher. There are many such axioms
(see, for example, pp. 354 f.), but the Elements gives only five, and some authorities believe that
the last two of these were added by writers after Euclid:
1. Things which are equal to the same thing are also equal to each other.
2. If equals be added to equals, the wholes are equal.
3. If equals be subtracted from equals, the remainders are equal.
4. Things which coincide with one another are equal to one another.
5. The whole is greater than the part.
These are axioms and not postulates, since they apply (but in an analogous sense) both to
numbers (discrete quantity) and to things that are not quantities at all. For example, a happy life
(which is not a quantity) is greater (better) than pleasure (which is a part of a happy life).
Euclid actually used other axioms, such as the principle of contradiction (see page 575), but
these are the ones most directly needed in his proofs.
Thus Euclid began his science of magnitude with a secure foundation, as Aristotle had required.
Every science must rest on first principles which are immediately evident from experience.
These first principles are:
1. Axioms, or common principles, required even before we begin to study the subject.
2. Postulates (hypotheses, as Aristotle calls them) which give us the real definition of the
subject to be studied by asserting its existence.
3. Definitions (theses in Aristotle's terminology) of the terms (nominal definitions) or
properties which are to be demonstrated.
4. Middle terms which can connect the subject with its properties.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Given these principles we can form a demonstrative syllogism (see page 75) as follows:
In this syllogism we will notice that the middle term is identical in both premises (otherwise it
would not be a middle term), but that it has two different functions. In the major premise it is
only a nominal definition of the property, while in the minor premise it is the real definition of
the subject. How can this be? A property is an accident (see page 44), and to define an accident
we must include the subject in which it exists. Hence the nominal definition of a property
includes a reference to its subject as the cause of its existence. For example, if I ask, "What is a
smile?" you must answer with the nominal definition: "The word 'smile' means a curving of a
man's lips." In this definition you have mentioned the subject in which the smile exists, namely,
"a man's lips."
Thus the middle term of a demonstration is: 1) The term used in both premises (and not in the
conclusion) of the syllogism; and 2) at the same time a real definition of the subject, and a
nominal definition of the property as it exists in the subject which is the cause of its being. The
smile exists in a man's lips, and it is caused to exist by the man, who exists in himself.
Euclid's first demonstration is the following proposition or theorem: On a given finite straight
line to construct an equilateral triangle.
To put this proof into strict syllogistic form, it is easiest to work backwards, beginning with the
ultimate conclusion (see page 75). This gives us a subject (minor term) and a predicate (major
term) which can be arranged in a skeleton syllogism, thus:
We then have to locate the middle term, which Euclid shows us in his Step 8, namely: three
straight lines CA, AB, BC equal to one another. By placing this in both premises in proper
position, we have a complete syllogism. It is still necessary, however, to prove these premises;
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
by treating each as a new conclusion to be proved, we continue to work backward until we arrive
at nothing but axioms or postulates or definitions. Thus we have the following:
Proof of 2:
Proof of 4:
5. A triangle whose one side
AB is the common radius
of two circles, and whose
other two sides CA and
CB are radii of same two
circles is a triangle formed
by
two lines CA and
CB
equal to its
third side
AB.
6. Triangle ABC on a finite
straight line AB is a triangle whose
one
side AB is the
common
radius of two
circles,
and whose other
two
sides CA and CB
are
radii of the same
two
circles.
4. Therefore: Triangle ABC
on a finite straight line AB is a triangle formed
by
two lines CA and
CB
equal to its
third side
AB.
Proof of 5: Postulate 3.
Every theorem in Euclid can be put into this strict syllogistic form.* A student ought to assure
himself of this by working out several of the demonstrations, after which the abbreviated method
of Euclid himself should be followed. In this method the steps (conclusions) are stated with their
respective reasons (middle terms), but without the explicit statement of both premises. The
reason that it is important to be sure that these proofs can be stated syllogistically is that only
then are we certain that the proof is logically rigorous. If an argument cannot be reduced to the
syllogism, the simplest of all forms of reasoning, it cannot be proved that it is logically valid (see
page 568 ff.).
[* The proof just given is a construction theorem and does not constitute the clearest example of demonstrating a
property of a subject. Rather it demonstrates the form (equilateral) from its parts (three straight lines), which are like
a material cause. In such demonstration the parts are treated as the subject, and their form is treated as a property.
This is common in construction theorems, which aim at establishing the real definition. More typical would be
Theorem 5 of this First Book of the Elements, in which it is proved that every isosceles triangle (subject) has the
base angles equal (property).]
According to Aristotle, a science is well ordered when it begins with the evident and
indemonstrable axioms, postulates, and definitions, and proceeds to problems and theorems
arranged in the following way:
1. We should first prove the properties that belong to the whole subject. For example, the
properties common to all triangles should be proved before we discuss the properties of
equilateral or scalene triangles.
2. We should then divide (classify) the subject into its various species or genera and
prove the theorems, giving the properties of each species. For example, we should divide
triangle into equilateral, isosceles, and scalene, and then prove the properties belonging to
each.
3. We should then subdivide and continue until we get to the ultimate species which are
divided only into like individuals. Thus triangle is completely divided into the three
species just given, but polygon would be first divided into regular and irregular, and
regular would be subdivided into square, pentagon, hexagon, etc.
The reason for this order is to avoid repetition (since what is proved of the genus need not be
repeated for each species) but also, and more importantly, in order to discover gradually the
properties of things. If we first proved that an equilateral triangle has its interior angles equal to
the sum of two angles (180), then we would have to prove it again for all other types of triangles,
until at last we discovered that it is not a property of this or that kind of triangle but of all
triangles. On the other hand, if we have proved that this is a property of all triangles, then we can
use this as a premise in proving some property which an equilateral triangle alone has. This
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
orderly procedure corresponds to the nature of our minds, which most clearly perceive what is
general and simple, and which come to a knowledge of details only step by step.
If we look at the outline of the Elements on page 330, we will see that, in general, Euclid has
followed this order. He begins with the geometry of lines (not very fully treated) and continues
with plane geometry (first four books), working up from triangles to parallelograms, then to
circles, and finally to combinations of circles and other figures. Thus he is moving from the
simpler and more general elements to the more complex. Books V to X deal with problems of
arithmetic and of the application of arithmetic to geometry; we will discuss them in Chapter III
(see below, page 353). The last three books, XI to XIII, deal with solid geometry and again build
up from what is simpler and more general to what is more complex.
Euclid's order taken as a whole is synthetic (from the Greek for put together"), that is, he begins
with simple things and then puts them together into more complex wholes. Thus he begins with
the simplest truths (definitions, postulates, axioms) and works in the direction of more and more
complicated theorems. He also works from lines to planes to solids, and from simple figures to
complex figures. On the other band, some of his proofs are analytic (from the Greek for "take
apart"), that is, they begin with the conclusion and work backward to the simple principles on
which it is based. The syllogistic arrangement which we give above (pp. 335 f.) is analytic, since
we began with the conclusion and worked backward to the premises.* The analytic method is
really more fundamental, since even when we proceed synthetically we must always keep
connecting each new conclusion with the axioms and postulates.
Euclid uses both synthetic and analytic proofs. An interesting type of analytic proof is the
reduction to absurdity (reductio ad absurdum), also called proof through impossibility (per
impossible). In such a proof we assume that the contradictory of what we wish to prove is true,
and then by argument we deduce an obviously false conclusion from this assumption (see page
143). Because the contradictory of a false statement must be true (see page 138), we are then
sure that the original theorem is true.
[* The terms "analytic" and "synthetic" are used in still another sense to refer to propositions in which the truth is
evident from the meaning of the terms (analytic) or only as a matter of fact (synthetic).]
A thing is beautiful when it pleases us just to look at it, hear it, or know it. We are pleased by
well-cooked, well-flavored food, because it fits our appetite for food. We are pleased by a
comfortable bed, because it fits our need for rest. We are pleased by a paycheck, because it fits
our need for purchasing power. We also have an appetite or need for knowledge and experience.
We human beings are creatures full of curiosity, hungry for knowledge, although in some this
appetite has grown dull because of laziness or discouragement. Therefore, when we meet an
object which fits our need for knowledge, we are filled with pleasure.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Such an object which is adapted or fitted for knowledge, as food is cooked and savored for
eating, is a beautiful object. It fills our eyes, or ears, or mind with vivid truth. Thus whatever is
beautiful must be true, but not everything which is true is beautiful; it may be a truth which is not
fitted to our minds, which is dim, obscure, confused, rather than vivid and pleasing. just as tasty
food is usually also nourishing, but not all nourishing food is tasty, so, even more truly, beautiful
things are true, but truth may not appear beautiful to us, because it is not fitted to our capacity. It
follows, then, that the chief thing in beauty is clarity (vividness, brilliancy, splendor, charm).
The clearest and simplest example of something beautiful is a pattern or design, like Design A on
this page. Why is it beautiful? St. Thomas tells us that beauty consists formally in clarity, and
materially in proportion and integrity.
Design A has more clarity than B, because the contrast in color between the black and white
parts of the design makes the pattern clear. If it were also in bright hue (for example, blue and
yellow), it would be still clearer and more beautiful. Thus clarity makes the design stand out, so
that it strikes our eye. This is simply another way of saying that it is fitted to the appetite of our
eye for seeing. When we look at Design B it appears confused, and the eye finds it unpleasant.
But Design A strikes the eye at once as clear and definite, and hence is pleasant.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
This clarity, however, must be the clearness of a pattern. And what is a pattern or design? It is an
arrangement or order of parts to form a whole. Thus C has the same parts as A and B, but they
are not in any order. Order is defined as a multitude related to one. An army is ordered because it
is made up of many soldiers all related to one general; an orchestra is ordered because there are
many players all related to one conductor. Hence a design is a multitude of parts, all of which are
related to some one part (in this case to the center).
Often this is expressed by saying that beauty is "unity in variety." St. Thomas expresses it more
accurately by saying that it must have integrity and proportion. "Proportion" means that every
part has a definite relation to the chief part and thus to the whole. "Integrity" means that all the
parts needed to establish this relation are present. C lacks proportion because one of the parts is
unrelated to the center. D lacks integrity because a part needed to complete this relation is
lacking. Thus a good design must have enough parts (variety), i.e., integrity, and all of these
parts must be properly arranged (proportion or unity), and this arrangement must be fitted to the
knower so that he is able to grasp it vividly (clarity).
MUSICAL PATTERNS
In music, in a similar way, there is a definite pattern of sounds. The basic pattern in music is
what we call the scale. The range of sounds from very low to very high is continuous, as we hear
in a siren, or when the violinist slides his finger along a vibrating string. If all these possible
sounds were to be used in music it would be difficult both for the player and the audience to
follow a pattern. Hence from this continuum of sounds we select certain tones bearing definite
relations to each other, which we call the scale. Between any tone of the scale and any other tone
there is some simple relation based on the relation between the number of vibrations required to
produce each tone. The most important tones of the scale have the simplest relations to each
other, as will be seen in the diagram (page 349). In writing a melody the composer selects tones
of the scale in such a way that the most important tones of the scale form the skeleton of his
melody, and the less important tones fill in this skeleton. When we hear such a melody it has
integrity because all the important tones of the scale are used. It has proportion because the
important tones are in the important positions, so that we hear them as having definite relations.
Finally, the melody has clarity because the composer emphasizes these relations. He emphasizes
them by giving them the longest tones or accented tones (rhythm), by making them louder, by
repeating them, by reinforcing them by harmony, or by giving them the most brilliant quality (by
using the right quality of voice or the right instrument). In this way the proportions or relations in
the melody stand out with clarity and are beautiful.
From this we see that, in producing a beautiful object, pattern or design is extremely important.
This does not mean, of course, that beauty (integrity, proportion, clarity) is found only in such
patterns. If we take a pure color or tone as seen or beard by our external senses, our eyes or ears,
it may be called beautiful too. Its integrity consists in the fact that the color fills a considerable
surface, or the tone endures for a sufficient time. Its proportion consists in the fact that the color
or tone is pure, uniform. Its clarity consists in the fact that the color is brilliant, or the tone
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
brilliant and sufficiently loud. Here integrity, proportion, clarity are analogous to those found in
a pattern, and the beauty is of a different sort.
Similarly, in our intelligence there can also be beauty, for example, in the clear explanation of a
mathematical proof or a proof in Christian doctrine. Here the integrity consists in the
completeness of the explanation, the proportion in the way in which every part of the proof is
perfectly fitted together, and the clarity in the way that the conclusion and the proper reason for it
(the principles) stand out distinctly, so that we are freed of all confusion. Again, this beauty is
analogous to the beauty of a pattern, but not quite the same.
Which of these three kinds of beauty -- sensible beauty (color, tone), imaginative beauty (designs
perceived by our internal senses), or intellectual beauty (abstract truth clearly understood)-is the
most perfect? To answer this, we must realize that, in itself, the deepest, truest beauty is
intellectual beauty, since only our intellects can penetrate the very nature and essence of reality.
Furthermore, it is only the intellect that can know relations. Since beauty is a kind of relation (the
fit of the object to the knower), only our intellect understands what beauty is. When we see a
beautiful color, our eye is pleased, but only the intellect sees that it is precisely the beauty of the
color which is so pleasing. Hence animals, who have no intellect, do not really appreciate beauty
as such. For the bee the beauty of the flower is only a signal that honey is to be found there.
Nevertheless, for us human beings intellectual beauty is not completely satisfying. If we were
angels such beauty would be so perfect that it would satisfy us, but we have very weak
intelligences that can know perfectly only by using our senses. Consequently, when we think of
purely abstract truth it seems cold and dead; it does not wholly fit us, unless we can make it
concrete somehow by imagining it. The result is that when we think of a man as a "rational
animal," our knowledge seems remote and lacking in beauty. When we think of a man with a
clear image of a perfect man to illustrate the abstract idea, then it becomes much more satisfying.
That is why we like illustrations in a book. Such pictures in our imagination are the kind of
patterns we have been speaking of.
On the other hand, a pure pattern without quality, color, or sound also seems cold and
diagrammatic. To make a design perfectly beautiful we want it colored and exhibited in a bright
light. We want a musical score actually performed and in a sufficiently loud tone. While,
therefore, intellectual beauty is most perfect in itself, for us human beings the most perfect
beauty is intellectual truth embodied in a visible and audible pattern. God in himself is most
beautiful, but his beauty appeared to us best when he became a man and dwelt amongst us,
where we could see and hear him.
PERFECT BEAUTY
Thus perfect beauty for us is intellectual, but intellectual truth exemplified in something concrete
and visible. If we compare the three types of beauty we get the following scheme:
3. Imaginative beauty is a mean between these. On the one hand, it is sensible, we can
picture it; yet in a way it is abstract, a pure design.
We see, then, that the most perfect beauty requires all three together, but of the three it is
imaginative beauty which is most truly beauty for us, since without it the others would not be
beautiful. Unless external beauty is somewhat refined by our internal senses, we can never
understand its beauty with our intellect; and unless intellectual beauty were made concrete, at
least in the imagination, it would not be beautiful for us. Thus it is in the designs or patterns in
our internal senses that beauty is found in the plainest way. The other kinds of beauty are
understood as analogous to it.
From these facts we can see why mathematics, which deals with quantities, magnitudes, and
numbers, is so very important in understanding beauty. It is just at this point that the most
obvious kind of beauty is found, in geometrical patterns and in numerical relations.
It will be astonishing to some people to think of mathematics being beautiful, to hear that artists
are concerned with mathematics. Of course, mathematics is not beautiful to those who do not
understand it, because what is obscure is not clear. But to those who study it, mathematics is the
clearest of all subjects. It is also true that many artists do not know mathematics, and work out
their designs or compositions by the mere feeling that the design "looks right." Nevertheless, if
we study the history of art and music we will see that all the great new advances in art and music
were made possible by artists who studied mathematics and learned from it how to make new
and more beautiful patterns. Thus the great achievements in art by the Greeks and by the artists
of the Renaissance were due to men like Leonardo da Vinci who studied the use of mathematics
in art. Similarly, the advance of music from simple unison singing to harmony was made
possible only by mathematical studies. Today modern art is making great use of such
mathematical ideas.
Mathematics helps art both materially and formally. Materially it gives to the visual artist all
sorts of new figures to use in art, and to the musician new scales, harmonies, and instruments. If
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
we look at Greek art we see that the circle, the cube, the triangle, the rectangle, the cylinder, the
pyramid made up almost the whole "vocabulary" Of Greek architecture. But in baroque art, and
now very much in modern art, all sorts of new figures are common; shapes like eggs, like guitars,
like the forms of the amoeba, parabolas, hyperbolas, saddle-shapes, etc., are used very
effectively. These were originated or explained by mathematics. In like manner there has been a
steady growth in the musical vocabulary from simple melodies to harmony, and then to various
degrees of harmonic complexity. Thus the artist has more variety (integrity) to work with, and
understands more complex relations (unity, proportion).
The formal contribution of mathematics to art, however, is in showing how the artist can make
his proportions clear, since it is in this that beauty consists. If we compare Greek art at its best
with its less developed or later degenerate forms. or with other types of less perfect art, such as
that developed by the Babylonians, we see that the reason the Greeks excelled was not because
they had different materials to work with (either physical materials, or figures and quantities),
but that they knew how to emphasize these designs so as to make them clear as crystal. This was
due to the Greek insight into mathematical relations. Similarly, in listening to music we realize
that the development of music in the classical period (say from Bach to Mozart) was one of
increasing understanding of pure form. In modern art the effort of some of our greatest artists is
to take the rich but confused material provided by romanticism and again give to it a clarity of
formal structure.
We cannot here go into the details of how mathematics can do this. We can give a simple
example, and then show the basic principle on which this theory must be based. If we look at the
human body, we see that it is very complicated and that in no two human beings are the
proportions the same. An artist, wishing to make a picture of a man and to make it as beautiful as
possible, seeks to find in the body some kind of clear order. To do this he can simplify the
pattern of the body by thinking of the head as a sphere, the neck as a cylinder, the trunk as two
cubes, one for the chest, one for the abdomen, etc. But to find unity in the whole body he looks
for a common unit to which all others can be related and by which they are measured, since order
means relation to a principle or unit. This unit is called mathematically a modulus. Generally
speaking, in the human body the length of the head is such a natural modulus, so that the
proportion of the rest of the body can be calculated from it. Here is Leonardo da Vinci's calculus:
The architect Vitruvius states in his work on architecture that the measurements of a man are
arranged by Nature thus: -- that is, that four fingers make one palm, and four palms make one
foot, six palms make one cubit, four cubits make once a man's height, and four cubits make a
pace, and twenty-four palms make a man's height, and these measurements are in his buildings.
If you set your legs so far apart as to take a fourteenth part from your height, and you open and
raise your arms until you touch the line of the crown of the head with your middle fingers, you
must know that the centre of the circle formed by the extremities of the outstretched limbs will
be the navel, and the space between the legs will form an equilateral triangle.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
From the beginning of the hair to the end of the bottom of the chin is the tenth part of a man's
height; from the top of the breast to the crown of the head is the sixth of the man; from the top of
the breast to where the hair commences is the seventh part of the whole man; from the nipples to
the crown of the head is a fourth part of the man. The maximum width of the shoulders is in
itself the fourth part of a Man; from the elbow to the tip of the middle finger is the fifth part;
from this elbow to the end of the shoulder is the eighth part. The complete hand will be the tenth
part. The center of a man is at the crotch. The foot is the seventh part of the man. From the sole
of the foot to just below the knee is the fourth part of a man. From below the knee to the crotch is
the fourth part of the man.
The parts that find themselves between the chin and the nose and between the places where the
hair and the eyebrow start, each of itself compares with that of the ear, and is a third of the face.*
[* The Notebooks of Leonardo Da Vinci, arranged, rendered into English and introduced by
Edward MacCurdy (London: Jonathan Cape, 1938) Vol. 1, pp. 225 f.]
The same thing can be applied in architecture, where a building can be fashioned so as to have
all its parts related to one modulus or standard unity.
Mathematical Proportion
What is the principle behind this? It is the principle of mathematical proportion. In arithmetic
we learn that if we compare any two numbers they are said to have a certain ratio (relation) to
each other, which we call a "fraction." Thus 1/2, 2/4, 4/8, 25/50 are pairs of numbers having the
same ratio to each other, that is the relation of half, while 2/1, 4/2, 8/4, 50/25 have the ratio or
relation of double.
All of arithmetic really deals with such numerical relations or ratios; in a musical or visual
pattern all the relations are ratios. But if we are to make each relation clear (and this is required
for beauty), we must somehow make it as determinate as possible. We must define it. We have
already learned in logic that, in order to define something and to make it clear, we compare one
thing with another. Hence to define a ratio very exactly we may compare it to another ratio, and
such a comparison of one ratio with another is called a proportion (we have already met this
notion in studying analogy; see page 50). If we state the ratio 2:4, for example, it might have two
meanings: either that 4 is double 2, or that it is the square of 2; but when we write 2:4 :: 3:9, then
we determine this relation to mean that of square, and in this way make it clear.* [* Ordinarily
such proportions are not written in arithmetic, every proportion being taken in the sense of a
fraction, i.e., of simple multiplication.] It is in this way that proportions enable us to specify,
clarify, or emphasize ratios or relations. Hence we can understand that when we say a design
must have proportion, we mean that it must have similar ratios between each part and some
principal part or the whole; it must have order. For example, in a circle divided into four
quarters, each quarter has the same ratio to the center and to the whole circle as does each of the
other quarters; hence they are in proportion.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
A simple proportion must have four terms. Any proportion with more than these is compound
and can be divided into a series of simple proportions. It cannot have less than four terms,
because it must be a comparison of two relations, and each relation (ratio) must have two terms.
However, it is possible to repeat one or two of the terms in a proportion. Thus we can have 2:4 ::
4:8, or a:b :: b:c.
In a proportion, the first and fourth terms are called extremes, the second and third, the means.
The various kinds of proportions and the rules of operation which govern them are studied in
algebra. Continuous quantities, or magnitudes, lines, and areas, can also be com pared so as to
form proportions.
The artist who studies such proportions will be able in his paintings or music to produce
wonderful new designs having integrity, proportion, and clarity-and hence beauty.
MATHEMATICS IN MUSIC
MUSIC AND PROPORTION
If we strike a stretched string it will vibrate as a whole, but its parts will also vibrate at the same
time; the shorter the part, the more rapid will be its vibration and the higher the tone it emits. All
these partial tones blend together to form what sounds to our ear like a single rich tone. By
shortening the string with our finger at the proper point, however, we may obtain these various
partials. The result will be as follows:
Thus our scale has chosen the tones do, mi, sol because they stand in a simple natural ratio to
each other as its most important tones. Re also is an overtone, but fa, ti, la are not. These other
tones are chosen by what is called the "circle of fifths" (a major fifth being the interval between
do and sol) which gives the following proportion:
fa:do::do:sol::sol:re::re:la::la:mi::mi:ti
We cannot go further because the distance from ti to fa is shorter than the other intervals. The
resulting scale, called the major diatonic scale, is as follows:
The ratios are between the number of vibrations per second of the tone compared with those for
do. In the second column they are ratios of the vibrations of the succeeding note to the previous
note, i.e., the ratio of the interval. Note that the whole steps are actually of two sizes, but in
practice this is ignored. Such a scale gives the following intervals, which are mainly simple:
If we determine the frequency ratios of all the intervals in the scale larger than a whole-tone and
less than a seventh in the scale, we find that there are 29, of which 23 are perfect because they
can be formed as simple ratios. Four others are quite close to other intervals that are perfect.
Only the tritones are without definite proportion. Thus the superiority of the just or Ptolemaic
scale is apparent because it contains so many consonances.*
[* See a longer discussion in H. B. Lemon and M. Ference, Jr., Analytical Experimental Physics (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1943) p. 464.]
The scale can be constructed by taking the pattern of the most important tones do, mi, sol, which
form a chord or major triad (the I Chord). If this is then constructed with sol as the root or
bottom tone, we get sol, ti, re (the V Chord). Finally, if we construct a chord so that do is the
upper tone, we get fa, la, do (the IV Chord). This gives a complete scale arranged in the
following pattern:
It will be noticed that there are intervals of three sizes, but for practical purposes the whole steps
are all counted as equal. Thus the scale has the pattern (naming the steps):
Thus harmony is based on the I Chord (do, mi, sol) as the most Perfect (indicating the whole
scale), on the V Chord (sol, ti, re) and the IV Chord (fa, la, do) which tend to move or resolve to
it, and on any other chords tending to it through the V and IV.
The integrity of the scale, therefore, is due to the fact that it has only those tones required for
these three chords. Its proportion comes from the fact that the same pattern (the major triad) is
found in each of these chords, but that one of them (the I Chord) is primary, and the other chords
are ordered to it. The clarity comes from the fact that I Chord is made up of the strongest
overtones, standing in simplest relation to the basic tone (tonic) of the scale, so that we clearly
feel these tones as the most concordant (similar or blending) possible.
We may ask, however, why the pattern do, mi, sol is clearly proportioned? It is because it
suggests the complete scale made of two proportions:
do:re::mi:fa :: sol:la::ti:do
In this pattern, the two halves of the scale are alike and the alternate tones are concordant with
each other, since they suggest this pattern. It is not necessary, however, to play ti, because the
first proportion gives us the pattern, and sol indicates that the pattern will be repeated using sol
as the base instead of do. It is this principle of proportion which is the proper reason for the
concords and discords in the scale.
We might also ask whether some other selection of tones would not be preferable, and we may
answer:
1. Any number of tones other than a multiple of 4 would not form perfect proportions.
2. 4 tones would be too few, because we need to be able to imitate a motion which must
have a beginning, middle, and end.
3. 12, 24, etc., would be divided into 3 parts, but then they could not form larger
proportions having 4 terms.
4. Therefore, 16 or 8 tones are best, and 8 is more practical.
5. The intervals should not be all the same for the sake of variety (integrity).
6. The small intervals should be at the end of ascending motion because the effort increases
with rising pitch.
The other possible scales are inferior to the major diatonic scale in the above respects.
BENEDICT M. ASHLEY, O.P.: THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION
CHAPTER III
Mathematics Pure and Applied
PURE MATHEMATICS
ALGEBRA AS A SCIENCE
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
We have studied Euclid's Elements as an example of a pure science, the science of geometry, but
we saw also that Books VII, VIII, and IX deal with the science of arithmetic, or (as we would
now call it) with the science of algebra. If we wish to see such a pure science of number
developed even at great length, we should examine the work which became standard among the
Greeks, Romans, and medievals, both Mohammedan and Christian, the Introduction to
Arithmetic of Nicomachus of Gerasa, who lived about one hundred years after the birth of Our
Lord. It deals with that basic study of numbers which we today call Number Theory.
The term "algebra" was introduced to indicate a growing interest in the art of calculation, rather
than a demonstrative study of the properties of numbers. just as there is a science of logic which
seeks to prove the rules of logic (see page 568 ff.) and an art of logic which is concerned with
using these rules, so the science of number is concerned with proving the properties of numbers,
while the art of calculation is concerned with applying a knowledge of these properties to the
solution of particular problems.
Today, however, algebra includes both the art of numerical problem-solving and the science of
numbers, but the elementary study of algebra usually lays emphasis on its problem-solving
aspect. Now that we have analyzed geometry as a science, we need to review algebra from the
same point of view and see how it might be set up as a pure science.
The axioms of algebra and geometry are the same, since an axiom is a principle common to
several sciences. Algebra and geometry are very closely related; but they are, nevertheless,
distinct sciences and hence they have different definitions and postulates.
The definitions of algebra we have already discussed in Chapter I of this Part. We must have at
least nominal definitions of the unit, of every natural number, of all the operations of algebra, of
the operational numbers, and of the various properties and combinations of numbers, such as
"odd," "even," "sum," " ratio," etc.
It is not so easy, however, to decide on the postulates of algebra. Each postulate will state the
existence of one of the things which we have nominally defined (in other words, it will be a real
definition), or it will be a truth immediately evident from these definitions. One of the first
mathematicians to attempt to state the postulates of algebra in a rigorous form in accordance with
modern methods was the Italian mathematician, Giuseppe Peano (1858-1932), who proposed the
following five postulates:
1. 0 is a number.
2. The successor of any number is a number.
3. No two numbers have the same successor.
4. 0 is not the successor of any number.
5. If s is a class to which 0 belongs and also the successor of every number belonging to s, then
every number belongs to s. (This is called the principle of mathematical induction.)
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
This list raises many difficulties, particularly because it uses zero to define number, instead of
the other way around (see page 320). A more satisfactory statement of essentially the same
principles is as follows:
The weakness of these postulates is that they leave "integer" as an "undefined term," whose
meaning is determined only by the postulates and their application. Rather the meaning of the
postulates should be derived from the meaning of integer.
as a substance, which is abstractly considered as indivisible and without position. (See page 315).
The two definitions are nominal, but they are made real by the postulates, which assert the
existence of the thing defined. These two postulates are sufficient because all the theorems of
algebra can be proved to follow from the definition of numbers, and, as we have already shown
(pp. 317 ff.), all the numbers can be constructed by means of the unit.
2. That subtraction is valid, but only if a lesser number is taken from a greater.
3. That multiplication is valid, both commutative and associative, and also distributive with
respect to addition and subtraction.
4. That division is valid, when the divisor is smaller than the dividend and commensurate with it.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
By commutative we mean that if we perform an operation with numbers taken in one order, the
same operation with the same numbers taken in the reverse order will give the same result. Thus
6 + 4 + 2 = 2 + 4 + 6 and 6 × 4 × 2 = 2 × 4 × 6, but 6 - 4 - 2 2 - 4 - 6 and 6 ÷ 2 2 ÷ 6. By
associative we mean that if an operation is performed on three or more numbers, the result is
independent of the manner in which they are grouped. Thus 6+ (4+2) = (6 + 4) +2 and 6 (4 × 2)
= (6 × 4) × 2; but 6 - (4 - 2) (6 - 4) - 2 and 12 ÷ (6 ÷ 2) (12 ÷ 6) ÷ 2. By distributive with respect
to addition and subtraction, we mean that a (b+c-d) = ab+ac-ad. By commensurate we mean that
the divisor will "go into" the dividend an integral number of times without a remainder.
We will not prove these theorems here formally, but it is obvious that we can prove the result of
any operation of addition to be a number by showing that it is equivalent to a collection of units.
Thus 3 + 4 = (1 + 1 + 1) + (1 + 1 + 1 + 1). Since our Postulate 2 tells us that a whole composed
of units is a number, and since we can recognize a unit by Postulate 1, this proof is valid. Since
addition is valid, its converse (subtraction) can be shown to be valid in the same way.
Multiplication and its converse (division) can be shown to be abbreviations of addition, since 4 ×
3 = 3 + 3 + 3 + 3.
Inasmuch as we have shown in Chapter I that all the artificial numbers (0, negative numbers,
fractions, irrationals, imaginary, and complex numbers) can be defined as natural numbers with
some operation, and these operations are fundamentally reducible to the above four, there is no
difficulty about proving the validity of the entire complex number system.
The addition of these operational numbers makes it possible to prove that the four laws of
operation may be extended to all elements in the complex number system. For example, if we
admit negative numbers, we can subtract any number from any other number. If we also admit
fractions and irrationals, we can divide any number by any other, etc.
Since all of ordinary algebra is limited to the complex number system, it is evident that we can
reduce every problem in this algebra to our two postulates, just as in geometry every theorem can
be reduced to a small set of postulates.
Students often do not realize that every solution to an equation is a theorem, since the answer is
correct only when it can be proved to have been obtained by operations which are valid
according to the postulates. If these laws of operation are violated, then the result is not proved to
be true, although by accident it may be true.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Thus when we write 3 × 4 - 2 = 10, we are asserting the theorem that "three fours minus a two
are equal to ten, because of the laws of multiplication and subtraction." Thus we are giving a
reason, or middle term, for our conclusion. When we write "a - 2
6, therefore a = 8," we are saying: "If a number minus 2 is equal to 6, then that number is 8
because of the law of subtraction." If we have simultaneous equations such as "a × b = 6 and a -
b = 1, therefore a = 3, and b = 2," we are saying: "If two numbers multiplied equal 6, and if the
lesser subtracted from the greater equals 1, then the numbers are respectively 3 and 2 because of
the laws of multiplication and subtraction."
It will be noticed that many algebraic theorems are conditional. They state that if a certain
relation (function) holds between two quantities, then these quantities are such and such, or
belong to such and such classes. This means that we begin with a definition of the number in
terms of its properties, and then seek to discover what number has these properties. For example,
if I say, "4 x2 = 36," I am saying: "What number has the property of equaling 36 when squared
and multiplied by 4?"
But in number theory, which is the more fundamental part of the science of number, we may
begin with the number and seek to prove its properties. For example, we might ask whether
65,537 is a prime number (which it is).
The Pythagoreans were fond of the saying, "The essences of all things are numbers." Hence they
liked to show the close connection between magnitudes and numbers. They spoke of
"triangular," "square," and "cubic" numbers, and they were fascinated with the problems of both
incommensurable magnitudes and irrational numbers. Finally, they took a special delight in the
study of the five regular or Pythagorean solids, because there seemed to be some mysterious
connection between them and the integers.
Plato and his followers were very Pythagorean in this respect. Since number is more abstract
than magnitude, they considered arithmetic a science superior to geometry, and wondered if
perhaps the lower might not be replaced by the higher science. In opposition to this, Aristotle
argued that the science of number and the science of magnitude are not merely a perfect and an
imperfect form of the same knowledge, but are specifically distinct, although related, sciences
which cannot be reduced to one science.
In general the Greek mathematicians adhered to Aristotle's teaching and kept geometry and
arithmetic unmixed. Nevertheless, in Euclid's Elements we see that they very well perceived how
close the relation between the two disciplines is. The Elements is devoted principally to
geometry, and yet it culminates in the last book in a discussion of the Pythagorean solids as if
this were the supreme geometrical study. Furthermore, Book V is devoted to the topic of ratio
and proportion because this is a topic common to both arithmetic and geometry. Then after
Books VII-IX which are devoted to pure arithmetic, Euclid deals in Book X with the problem of
incommensurables, so closely related to the problem of irrational numbers. Thus Euclid seems
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
always to be about to combine the two sciences, without ever actually doing so. If he had been
thoroughly Aristotelian lie would have divided his work into two distinct parts. The first would
have been devoted to arithmetic, since Aristotle agrees with Plato in holding that this science is
more perfect and abstract, but the second would have been a geometry independent of arithmetic.
TRIGONOMETRY
The mixture of the two sciences went further in trigonometry (the science of measuring
triangles). Ptolemy, the astronomer of Alexandria in Egypt, who lived in the second century after
our Lord, introduced the use of a numerical measurement of angles into degrees, derived from
the Babylonian division of the circle into 3600 (see page 306). Then mathematicians began to
make tables showing the sine, cosine, tangent, and cotangent ratios between the sides of triangles
in terms of numbers.
Thus trigonometry is a mixed science, developed from the study of ratio and proportion common
to both geometry and arithmetic, but making the study of geometry easier by reducing
proportions between lines to proportions between numbers which are precise and easy to
manipulate.
ANALYTIC GEOMETRY
The real step was not taken, however, until René Descartes (1596-1650), whose discovery of
analytical, co-ordinate, or cartesian geometry*
[*It is called "cartesian" from Descartes' name (Des Cartes). It is called "co-ordinate" because it is based on the use
of co-ordinates by which positions in space are measured numerically. It is called "analytic" because it analyzes
magnitudes into numbered parts which are easier to manipulate. The student should not confuse the terms "analytic
geometry" and "synthetic geometry" (i.e., Euclid's pure geometry) with the terms "analytic proof" and "synthetic
proof," which are used in all types of mathematics (see page 338).]
was one of the most important factors in producing our modern culture. When we think of "modern
times" and contrast them with "medieval times," we are usually thinking about two aspects of modern
life. On the one hand, we see the immense growth of modern science and engineering which has
transformed our way of traveling, communicating, and producing our food and shelter. On the other hand,
we think of the lack of unity in thought and religion and the widespread sense of uncertainty which makes
today's world so different from the unified world of the middle ages. Strangely, this single mathematician,
Descartes, is largely responsible for both results, although he certainly did not anticipate any such
outcome. His discovery made possible the rapid advance of mathematics and the whole system of modern
technology based on it, but his confusion of the two sciences also led men to doubt the possibility of
certain truth. The last outcome was especially ironical, because Descartes thought that his methods would
make mathematics and all branches of knowledge much more certain than they had been. He did not
realize that long ago Aristotle had pointed out that those who confuse the branches of mathematics are
sure to end by casting doubt on the possibility of a certain knowledge of the material world. Aristotle was
keenly aware of this danger because some of his fellow-students in the school of Plato had already fallen
into this error, and were teaching that truth is to be found only in some other world.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The essential feature of Descartes' discovery was this: It is possible to represent a point or
position on a surface by two numbers, or in a space by three numbers, by means of two or three
measurements made on arbitrary scales, showing the distances between that point and other
arbitrarily chosen lines called co-ordinates. From this it seems that every geometrical magnitude
can be perfectly described in terms of numbers, and the relations between these magnitudes can
then be reduced to relations between numbers. In this way the science of geometry which deals
with the relations of magnitudes can be reduced to the science of algebra which deals with the
relations of numbers.
Since numbers are so much easier to manipulate and use in calculation than magnitudes are, this
opened the way to the marvelous modern advance in mathematics and the engineering sciences
based on them. On the other hand, since it seemed to show that the principles of geometry,
formerly considered to be immediately evident, are only a kind of approximation, it casts doubts
on all human knowledge. If we cannot trust our senses which show us that magnitudes are not
numbers, then we must correct our senses by our reason. This was what Descartes was inclined
to do. But then if our reasoning does not rest on the evidence of our senses, where does it get its
certitude? From "innate ideas" given by God, said Descartes. This had been Plato's answer, and,
as in Plato's time, men quickly pointed out that there is no proof that we have innate ideas. Hence
the modern world has drawn the conclusion, which Descartes would have viewed with horror,
that since we can have certitude neither from the evidence of our senses nor from the
unsupported assumptions of our reason, therefore certitude is impossible.
Both Descartes and the sceptics went too far and fell into error. Descartes' discovery is a
perfectly valid one, if we do not claim too much for it; nor does it destroy the independence of
geometry and the certitude of the first principles of geometry.
We have seen in Chapter I that number, or discrete quantity, is derived from an abstract
consideration of magnitude (the continuum). Physical reality is made up of magnitudes, or things
whose parts can be divided again and again ad infinitum. The parts of magnitude have both
divisibility and position, since one part is joined to the next. Yet these parts are numberable in an
abstract way. By leaving out of consideration the divisibility of the parts and their position, we
can consider each actual part as a unit, and taken together they form a number.
Nevertheless, this divisibility of a magnitude is potentially infinite, so that no matter how small
we make the unit of magnitude, that unit is still divisible. Since the unit of number is
indivisible, we can never reduce magnitude to number. The error has been repeatedly made in
history of supposing that a magnitude is made up of infinitesimals, that is, of parts so small that
they cannot be further divided. Others have made even a worse mistake by holding that a
magnitude is made up of points. If an infinitesimal could not be divided, then it would be of a
different nature than a magnitude, which is divisible; but a whole and its parts must have the
same. nature if they are uniform. A mathematical line or solid is conceived by us as something
perfectly uniform. Hence just as a whole line or solid is divisible, so must its parts be ever
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
divisible. If a magnitude were made up of Points, the same difficulty would follow, since even an
infinity of points could not fill the smallest space.
The proper solution is not to make contradictory guesses like those which introduce such
unknown entities as infinitesimals and actual infinities, but to stick to the known facts. The fact
is that the world is made up of physical magnitudes which can be divided beyond any limit we
know of. Furthermore, the abstract quantities which we can imagine are potentially divisible ad
infinitum. We can mentally divide any quantity into units as small as we wish, but we can never
exhaust its divisibility. Hence the numbering of magnitude is only approximate, but it can be
made as accurate as we wish. Thus it is a limit, which we can approach but never reach, just as
the circle is the limit of an inscribed polygon of n sides. The polygon can never be made into a
circle, but it can be made to approximate it as closely as we like.
2. It permits us to represent algebraic problems graphically, that is, by a diagram which helps our
imagination.
Thus by elevating geometry to algebra we get greater intellectual precision; by lowering algebra
to geometry, we get greater imaginative vividness.
We make an error in this matter only when we claim that the approximation is more than an
approximation.
In the first ratio, the relation is one of distance: A is a certain distance from B. In the second
ratio, the relation is one of order: a and b occupy a certain position in a number series. Obviously
the distance of A from B is an essentially different kind of "distance" than that from 3 to 10.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
If such comparisons are mistaken for identities, so that we think that a point is a number, then we
are equivocating and thinking in a confused fashion, just as if we were to make the following
analogy:
and conclude that the kind of "distance" between intelligence and stupidity is the same kind of
distance as between Chicago and Timbuctoo.
This is the reason why the Greeks were fearful of mixing geometry and arithmetic. They realized
that reasoning which rests on equivocation cannot be scientific demonstration, but only dialectic
(see page 162). Euclid's geometry was a true science, but in the eyes of Aristotle this analytic
geometry of Descartes would have appeared to be only dialectic.
This is certainly the case unless we take great pains in the presentation of analytic geometry to
remove equivocation. This can be done in two ways:
1. We may use analytic geometry merely for the purposes of giving a graphic representation to
our algebraic reasoning. In this case the diagram is merely a help to our imagination and does not
actually enter into the algebraic argument, any more than a diagram of a syllogism enters into
syllogistic reasoning itself.
Actually this is the chief function of analytic geometry today. In this case our advance in
knowledge has been a development of pure algebra, and analytic geometry has merely
served as a convenient instrument. On this score Descartes' discovery was not really of
much theoretical importance; rather it was a technical help, like the improvement of
mathematical notation when Roman numerals were replaced by Arabic numerals.
2. We may use the methods of analytic geometry to give us approximate solutions of geometry
problems, The results in this case are still dialectical, since they do not give us the proper reasons
for our conclusions; but equivocation is removed because we make explicit the fact that our
conclusion is approximate. Furthermore, so clear are the objects of mathematics that in this case
we can make our approximation as close as we please, approaching the limit to any degree of
accuracy required.
Thus analytic geometry can be understood in two ways: 1) as pure geometry algebraically
expressed; 2) as pure algebra graphically expressed. In both cases the expression is approximate
and dialectical. Descartes, we may conclude, gave to mathematics a very powerful technical
instrument, but he did not really disprove the separate and irreducible character of the two
sciences of geometry and arithmetic.
This is produced when mathematical quantities are used to assist us in understanding physical
quantities, which are not abstract at all. This procedure most properly deserves the name applied
mathematics, since in this case we apply the abstract to the concrete. It is also properly called
mathematical physics, that is, the application of mathematics to physics or natural science. This
in turn can have two branches, theoretical mathematical physics, and practical mathematical
physics which has many branches (all types of engineering of accounting, and of statistic-
making). We may illustrate this by means of the diagram below. Notice that the word "applied"
is used in three different senses, indicated by the three arrows in the diagram.
Thus "application" can mean: 1) the application of algebra to geometry; 2) the application of any
type of mathematics to natural science; 3) the application of theoretical mathematical science to
practical problems. It is the second sense which particularly concerns us in the rest of this
chapter .
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Applied mathematics as a theoretical study was developed by the same group of scholars in
Plato's Academy who first developed pure mathematics. Plato pointed out to his pupils that the
movements of those heavenly bodies we call the "planets" is very mysterious. The other stars
move across the sky with a regular motion every 24 hours Without ever changing their relative
positions. The Big Dipper, for example (the Greeks called it the Great Bear), turns about the pole
star every 24 hours, but never alters its pattern. The planets, on the other hand, seem to wander
across the sky from week to week in a strange fashion, gradually working their way east-ward
but not without frequently reversing their movements. Hence the very name "planet" means a
"wanderer."
Plato said that a celestial being could not be moving aimlessly. There must be a pattern to these
movements that could be reduced to a definite law. Therefore he suggested to his followers that
they seek to find an order in these seemingly confused movements and express it by a
mathematical diagram. just as an artist looking at nature disentangles its beautiful patterns from
apparent confusion, so the astronomer should detect the mathematical order of the heavens.
Astronomy
Hence it was that the first important application of the geometry of the Greeks was a
mathematical theory of the motion of the planets which would agree with careful observations
which had been kept for a long time by the priests of Babylon and to which the Greeks added
still better measurements. This theory was worked out by Eudoxus and gradually improved by a
long series of astronomers. They suggested many possible theories, some of them placing the sun
at the center with the earth and planets moving about it, others placing the earth at the center
with the sun and planets moving about it, sonic supposing that the center is hidden from us.
According to the facts which they were able to gather without the aid of a telescope, the theory
that the planets and sun move about the earth was found to be the most satisfying for two
reasons: 1) It best accounted for the known faces; 2) it could be given the most simple and clear
mathematical diagram. It was Ptolemy (page 359) who gave the most perfect mathematical
theory based on this arrangement. He knew that it might not really be true (as it is not, since the
earth moves about the sun), but he showed that according to the known facts it was more
probable than the other theories.
This study of astronomy also led to the use of mathematics in the study of light and its reflection
from mirrors and its refraction by water and glass. Euclid himself wrote an Optics, showing
some of the mathematical laws which determine the path of a ray of light. This science was also
sometimes called perspective, and it made it possible for painters to represent three dimensions
on a flat surface, so that some Greek and Roman paintings had the appearance of great depth and
roundness.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
We have already seen that Pythagoras applied numbers to explain the musical scale, and the later
Greeks and Romans made further progress in this branch of science called acoustics.
Mechanics
Still more interesting was the application of mathematics to building machines, some using water
power (hydraulics), some using steam power (pneumatics). This study in all its branches is called
mechanics. It was originally a practical application of mathematics, but it soon led to interesting
theoretical applications in natural science. The great name in this field was Archimedes who
lived about a generation after Euclid (about 287-212 B.C.). It is said that he claimed, "I could
move the earth if I had a fulcrum on which to put the lever." It was he who showed how
mathematics could be made to apply to all sorts of physical problems if it were only used with
ingenuity and imagination, so that all who read his work could clearly see that mathematics is an
indispensable tool for natural science.
Why is this the case? Students beginning their study of science often wonder why it is necessary
to use so much mathematics. It appears to make the subject very complicated, difficult, and
abstract, while a more popular, descriptive approach to science would be much more easy and
pleasant. It is because of the use of mathematics that so many people fear to study science, and
find its reasoning meaningless and remote from daily experience.
There is some real sense in this objection. The physical world in reality is not a set of
mathematical formulae or geometrical diagrams. It is a colorful, moving, tangible collection of
things, each of which has its own inner nature and way of behaving. The richness and the unity
of the real world can never be reduced to a mere formula. Natural science is not all mathematics,
nor is it even basically mathematics. Mathematics deals with something abstract and idealized,
figures and numbers which we construct in our imagination, while natural science deals with
something very concrete which we do not imagine but bump into all around us. Aristotle at the
very beginning of natural science protested against the inclination of his fellow pupils in the
Academy of Plato to treat the world as if it were only a mathematician's diagram. He insisted that
natural science must keep close to sense observation of the material world, and explain that
world in its own terms.
Yet Plato, Aristotle, and Archimedes all agreed that we cannot understand the material world if
we neglect its quantities. Quantity, according to Aristotle, is the first of all the accidents (see
page 344), so that every other accident has a quantitative aspect. Furthermore, the quantity of a
substance is one of its properties; hence if we know the quantity that naturally belongs to a
thing, we can define it in terms of quantity, and we can come to an understanding of its essential
nature. Figure, the kind of quality intimately connected with quantity (see page 249), is one of
the best indications we have of the nature of a thing since it shows us the proper quantity in its
connection with proper quality, and from this all the other properties of the thing are explicable.
Hence natural science must give special attention to the proper quantities of things if it is to
discover their inner natures. We may take as an example the experiment of Pythagoras with the
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
musical string. Tones are qualities, not quantities. Yet when we discover that a certain quality of
sound or tone is produced by a certain length or quantity of a string, and that another tone is
produced by a different quantity, and that the relations between one quality and another resemble
the relations between one quantity and another, we are beginning to understand the nature of
sound. When we understand the nature of sound we also come to understand the nature of the
vibrating body (a substance) in which this accident exists.
It was an obvious step, therefore, but a very important one, which the Greeks took when they
developed mathematical physics, that is, an application of mathematics to natural science.
Unfortunately, not all of them kept clearly in mind the warning of Aristotle that we must not
confuse mathematical quantity (which is abstract) with physical quantity (which is concrete).
The number 2, and 2 apples, are very different things. When we say that a pair of apples are 2,
we say something very true and very important, but we are far from telling the whole truth about
the apples. It is an equivocation (see page 59) to use the word "two" of apples and of the number
2, unless we carefully distinguish the different senses of the word.
This means that mathematics and natural science are distinct and separate sciences, although
both treat of quantity. Natural science treats of concrete quantity as it actually exists as a
property of changing things. Mathematics treats of abstract quantity considered apart from the
nature and other accidents of the thing which has quantity. The triangle which we study in
mathematics is considered without deciding whether it is of paper, or wood, or metal, or what
produced it, or what it is to be used for.
Mathematical physics is a combination of these two distinct sciences. How can we combine two
sciences which are distinct without running into confusion? We can do this in two ways:
1. We know that if we prove something is impossible in abstract quantity, then it will also be
impossible in concrete, quantity.
For example, if we know that it is impossible to construct a regular polygon with 11 sides in
geometry, then we will never find a crystal in nature that has this shape. Thus mathematics will
eliminate for us many guesses about the natural world, because it will prove their impossibility.
2. If we know that a natural object has a certain definite figure or number, then by mathematics
we can show that it must have certain other quantitative properties that belong to such a figure.
For example, if we know that a drop of water is round, we know at once that it is exposing the
least possible area per unit of volume to the air, since a sphere has the least possible surface per
unit of volume.
It may be objected, however, that natural figures are never perfect, and that even in counting
natural units it is often very difficult to be accurate. Hence it would follow that in applying the
conclusions of mathematics drawn from perfect figures and numbers we cannot be sure that our
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
application is anything more than approximate, and hence our conclusion will be probable and
not certain.
This objection is a very good one. A very slight change in a measurement in science may lead to
an entirely different mathematical figure. After all, the difference between a polygon of many
sides and a circle is very small in measurement, and yet these two figures have completely
different definitions in mathematics. The result is that when we apply mathematics in science we
become more exact in one sense, and less exact in another.
1. We are more exact in that mathematical relations are perfectly definite and clear (6 is exactly
twice 3).
2. We are less exact in that we are substituting a mathematical quantity for the physical quantity
which actually exists, although they are only approximately equivalent.
It is not surprising, therefore, that a very large part of mathematical physics is only probable and
not certain, since an improvement of measurement may greatly change the theory. Thus if we
consider what parts of Greek science still remain valid today, we see that:
1. Greek pure mathematics still remains valid, with only minor corrections.
2. Greek natural science of the non-mathematical sort (e.g., biology) still remains essentially
sound, although many corrections (some quite important) are needed.
3. Greek astronomy, which was mathematical physics, has had to be completely revised, although
some parts of it are still valid (theory of eclipses, method of measuring the earth).
Mathematical physics is thus the most shifting part of science and is constantly undergoing
revisions. Does this mean that mathematical physics never gives certain Conclusions? It can give
certitude if we can be certain of the range of the physical measurements to which it is applied.
For example, if we know that the earth is approximately a sphere and that its flattening at the
poles is not greater than a certain maximum nor less than a certain minimum, then we can treat it
mathematically as if it were a sphere, and be sure that our conclusions as to its properties are
valid within that range. If we extend our argumentation beyond this range, then, of course, it
becomes merely probable. If, moreover, we do not know the range of validity with certitude,
then our whole theory will be only probable.
Consequently, the astronomy of Ptolemy which put the earth at the center of the universe was
never more than a probable theory, because there was no way to be certain of the range of
accuracy of the measurements used. Ptolemy assumed that the fixed stars were close enough to
the earth that, if the earth moved, at least a small displacement of these stars should be observed.
Since such a displacement was not observed, he concluded that the earth did not move. As a
matter of fact, the stars are very remote, and consequently their displacement is very small, too
small to be measured without very fine instruments. Since Ptolemy could not estimate the
distance of the stars, he had no way of being sure that his argument was conclusive. Hence his
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
whole theory was probable. On the other hand, the theory much later devised by Newton was
known to be certain within a given range, although, as we now know, it is not accurate beyond
this.
Hence it is a mistake to believe that in science new theories are constantly overthrowing all
previous belief. Some theories which were always regarded as being merely probable are being
replaced by more probable theories, or finally by ones which are genuinely certain within it
given range of accuracy.
MEASUREMENT
1. There must be a standard of measurement which is as invariable as possible, and whose range
of variation is known within limits. The best standards are those which are natural (for example,
the rotation of the earth as a standard for the day), because their variation is held within a definite
range by natural causes.
2. We must try to isolate the thing to be measured from as many disturbing factors as possible.
For example, if we wish to measure a metal rod we must keep its temperature constant.
3. We must perform the measurement repeatedly. This shows us the range or limit of error within
which our measurement is accurate.
In every case we are not merely looking for the measurement of an individual quantity but of a
natural regularity. For example, the height of John Jones or the temperature of this sick man is
not itself a scientific fact. Rather the range of height for any human being, or the normal
temperature of a man, or the maximum temperature of a sick man who will survive are scientific
facts, because they regularly recur in nature and are properties of some natural thing.
Often our measurements are statistical in character, that is, they are expressed in terms of a ratio
between quantities. For example, we may discover that the height of 3 men out of 4 falls within a
certain range, or that 7 out of 10 times a certain chemical reaction occurs. We speak then of the
statistical probability. Actually there is true certitude in these measurements, since the existence
of the ratio is certain. The probability lie s in the individual cases, since if we are asked whether
in a given case the chemical reaction will occur, we may say, "It is more probable that it will,
since it occurs in 7 out of every 10 cases."
Indeed, we may admit that all measurement has a statistical character; for whatever quantity we
find to be a property of natural things admits of some variation, and the operation of
measurement which we perform on it is also of varying accuracy. This does not destroy the
certitude of our knowledge, because science is not concerned with individual cases but with what
is true in most cases.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Natural laws are not infallible; they are subject to interference from the carrying out of other
natural laws or of the action of free wills not compelled to obey or to limit themselves to these
laws (the wills of men, angels, and of God.) The interference of one natural force with another
we call chance. Chance is possible because the universe is made up of a multitude of different
substances, each following the end of its own nature, and because in the material world things by
reason of their matter are constantly subject to outside influences. In his wisdom God rules over
this whole multitude of natural things and through his angels keeps this conflict of natural forces
from destroying the general order of the universe. Yet since he rules things according to their
natures, he permits chance events, as part of the pattern of the world, although he keeps them
within limits.
Furthermore, God permits free creatures, the angels and men, to share in guiding their own lives.
Because of the sin of the angels and of men there is more chance and disorder in the world than
God intended in the beginning, and he wills to remove this undesirable disorder through his Son
and the Church and man's intelligent and right use of his own power over lower things.
In studying the world of nature, therefore, and also the world of human society, we need to lay
bare the order often obscured by chance and by moral evil. Because quantity is the basic
accident, natural order is very clearly manifested in quantitative order. Hence mathematics can
play a great role in helping us to sort out regularities.
The branch of applied mathematics called statistics (from late Latin for "a statesman," because
statistics were first used by government officials) deals with this attempt to discover regularities
in quantitative data (measurements).
Statistical Methods
Statistics is concerned (1) with describing in a clear fashion the actual results of measurement,
and (2) with induction of some generalization from this data. In carrying out the first of these
tasks, the statistician arranges his data in an array from the smallest to the largest item. He then
attempts to fit an equation or curve (using analytic geometry) to this array so as to show a
frequency distribution. It will commonly be found that the items fit a normal curve in which
must of the items have a central tendency. For example, if he has repeatedly measured the weight
of a quantity of material, the actual measurements will spread out over a considerable range, but
most of the results will cluster around one value, and this value, therefore, is probably the true
one.
Various types of averages (mode, median, arithmetical mean, geometrical mean, etc.) can be
calculated which serve as a convenient approximation to this true value, It is necessary also to
indicate how the deviant values are "scattered" around this center; hence the statistician attempts
to measure this variability, to estimate the lack of balance or skewness in the curve, and to
estimate the bunching of cases around the average (the flatness of the curve). Mathematical
formulae and indices have been developed which express this central tendency and variability in
different ways, each of which gives a better approximation for different types of data.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Besides a simple curve showing such a frequency distribution, descriptive statistics also deals
with complex curves that show, for example, the variation of a quantity through a series of time
periods, as in the familiar business chart.
In actual fact, however, correlations are not perfect, so that again it is necessary to resort to a
statistical procedure to determine whether the deviation between the expected values and the
actual values is so great as to render the correlation meaningless.
Basic to all these statistical processes is the theory of probability. A mathematician knowing, for
example, that in throwing dice only a certain number of results are possible, and that they are
independent of each other and due to so many different factors that the individual result is pure
chance, can predict an ideal pattern to which the successive throws will approximate as a limit. If
this pattern is not actually realized, then we must suppose that, besides chance, some special
cause (loaded dice) is operating. Hence the knowledge or probability makes it possible both to
perceive order in data, and to eliminate what is pure chance.
Finally we may mention that mathematics can help to sort out the operation of several
independent causes (factor analysis), For example, in testing human intelligence by a variety of
tests we may get very complex data. The mathematician determines whether this complexity
could be explained by the fact that human beings have several relatively independent abilities,
some being superior in memory, others in the use of words, etc. Once these factors have been
hypothetically isolated, special tests may be designed to test each.
Once we have established by measurement that a certain quantity regularly occurs in a natural
thing and hence is its property, we can draw further conclusions by syllogistic reasoning. In a
mathematical-physical argument the middle term must be a measurement which is known to be
a physical fact, but which can be treated as an abstract mathematical quantity. Take, for example,
the demonstration given by Aristotle from biology:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Thus in the demonstration the middle term can be considered concretely and physically (a wound
whose area, etc.), or abstractly and mathematically (a figure whose area compared to its
circumference is greatest). Considered abstractly, it can be treated as a part of mathematics, and
its various properties and relations can be demonstrated mathematically. The conclusion of the
syllogism, however, is not a mathematical truth, but a physical truth: Round wounds heal slowly.
The Greeks had a very clear picture of these three types of science: 1) mathematics; 2) natural
science; 3) mathematical natural science (physics); and of their mutual relationships. During the
five hundred years after Aristotle had proposed the program of research in these fields, the
Greeks made a remarkable advancement in them all. Then a strange decline set in, and scientific
progress became very slow.
Many factors played their part in this decline, but the most obvious one is that the Greeks had
already exhausted the possibilities of advance without the introduction of better instruments for
gathering facts. The Greeks had no telescope or microscope. They did not know much about the
various methods of purifying and combining chemicals. They made only a meager use of
dissection in studying living things. It was not that they were totally ignorant of the advantages
of such methods, but that they never carried any of them very far.
Why was it that such a brilliant people did not develop the technology which would have helped
them extend their science? Most historians believe it was because Greek and Roman civilization
was built on the institution of slave-labor. A slave is not much interested in inventing new
methods of doing things, because he does not own what he produces. On the other hand, those
who own slaves are likely to feel that such problems are beneath them. At any rate, Greek and
Roman civilization were weakest in just this technological aspect of culture, so that when Roman
civilization was at its height, the interest in science was in decline.
Then came the terrible period of the civil wars in the Roman Empire, the invasions by
barbarians, and the disruption of transportation and city life. There were few places that men had
the leisure or the opportunity to study, although men like the Roman senator Boethius (who died
a martyr at the hands of a barbarian king in 525) labored earnestly to try to restore education. Yet
during these Dark Ages the Christian Church was able to check the downward course of
civilization which had resulted from the corruption of paganism, and to begin to build a firmer
Christian civilization. The basis of this new civilization was an education which combined the
study of the Sacred Scriptures with the study of the liberal arts which bad come down from the
schools of Plato and Aristotle.
By the thirteenth century the Church was able to revive these schools in Christian form in her
great universities in western and southern Europe. Fortunately, in eastern Europe (the Byzantine
Empire) the learning of Greece had been preserved, if not greatly advanced, while the
Mohammedans who had overrun the rest of the Byzantine Empire in the East and in Africa had
taken over this learning from the Christians. Hence the West was able to obtain the works of the
great Greeks -- either in Greek manuscripts from the
Byzantines or in Arabian translations from the Mohammedans -- and have them translated into
Latin. In this way Aristotle, Euclid, Ptolemy, and finally, Archimedes were studied diligently;
mathematics, natural science, and mathematical Physics began to revive and to develop once
more. At the new University of Oxford the great Bishop of Lincoln, Robert Grosseteste,
especially awakened interest in science, and he was soon followed in other places by St. Albert
the Great, Roger Bacon, and St. Thomas Aquinas, who all promoted these studies.
What was even more significant was that this time real advances in the technological side of the
sciences were being made. The Mohammedans had already made advances in astronomical
measurement and in chemistry (alchemy), and now the Christians added to this the mechanical
clock, the use of lenses, new metallurgical processes, etc. The time was ripe for an immense
flowering of science. During the 14th and 15th centuries, however, this progress was slowed
down by the social upheavals of the period and the decline of the universities under the influence
of the type of philosophy called Nominalism.
Galileo
In the 16th century, however, and especially in the 17th, very rapid scientific progress was made,
the great University of Padua being especially influential. This University was strongly
Aristotelian, and it fostered the great interest in natural science and the direct observation of
nature which is to be found in Aristotle's works. Among the men whom it produced was the great
Galileo (1564-1642), who took the final steps in establishing the method of mathematical
physics. Galileo was the first to make effective use of the telescope, and at the same time,
through his study of Archimedes, he was able to apply mathematics in a brilliant fashion to the
new facts he was discovering. Thus it became clear to all that the way for the advance in
mathematical physics would be through an improvement of methods of observation and
measurement, combined with the analytic geometry of Descartes and the subsequent
development of higher mathematics. The method of Galileo and Descartes remains dominant in
science today, and Newton and Einstein were happy to follow in their path.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The career of Galileo, however, well illustrates a danger to which mathematical physics is
subject. Aristotle had made clear that physics of this kind is not the whole study of nature. Not
all aspects of nature can be known by a quantitative procedure, and even those which are known
in this way have to be interpreted in the, light of the nature of a thing which underlies its
quantity. This was well understood by the great biologist, William Harvey (1578-1657), who had
also studied at Padua and who discovered the circulation of the blood.
This discovery was as great an advance over the knowledge possessed by Aristotle as were
Galileo's discoveries about falling bodies, but it was not arrived at by mathematical methods (see
the proof on page 586). Galileo, however, was a genius of a very impetuous sort, and he wished
to forget the whole past and to rush forward with his mathematical methods without attempting
to control these methods by other types of investigation. He claimed to have proved things that
actually he had not proved (for example, his claim to have shown that the tides were due to
rotation of the earth). He lacked the critical and conservative thinking which are required for a
perfect scientist.
It is little wonder that such a man eventually went too far. Although a Catholic, be was led by his
enthusiasm for his own scientific guesswork to reinterpret the meaning of the Bible. The
interpretation of the Bible belongs only to the Church to whom God has given that right, and a
scientist is stepping outside the limits of his science when he attempts to do so. As a result,
Galileo was required by the authorities of the Church to retract his teachings, if he was to remain
a Catholic, and as a penance he was required to remain the rest of his life in house-confinement,
although he was allowed to continue his studies. This penalty today seems to us severe, but the
Church well understood how important it is for scientists to remain within the field of science,
and within that field to proceed by the scientific method of carefully testing their discoveries. If
later scientists had submitted to this guidance as Galileo finally did, the world would be further
advanced along the road of sound science than it is today. The theologians who condemned
Galileo were wrong in some of their own scientific ideas, where he (genius that he was) was
right in some guesses; but they were right about the strict standards of the scientific method, and
he was wrong.
The period from Galileo to our own has seen a marvelous development of mathematical physics,
but it has also seen the weaknesses of Galileo multiplied a thousandfold. The philosophical bases
of science which Galileo treated so lightly have been ignored by many scientists, until today
science has broken up into a thousand specialties which cannot be put back together again. What
is worse, it is often at odds with religion, philosophy, art, and morality, because the common
foundation which united them all has been shattered.
Before us lies a new age of science in which the advance will probably include a return once
more to a sounder foundation for modern science. On the part of the students, this requires that
they learn mathematics as a pure science, and also mathematical physics as an independent
science and a tool for natural science. At the collegiate level they should begin their study of
natural science itself with a consideration of its fundamental principles, through which all the
different branches of science can be integrated.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
CHAPTER IV
Wider Vistas in Mathematics
THE RICHES OF MODERN MATHEMATICS
The Elements of Euclid did not exhaust the mathematics known in his day, but they gave a good
survey of the principal topics which had then been studied in pure mathematics. A look at a
modern library of mathematical works gives at once a bewildering impression of the immense
growth in the number and the complexity of topics in mathematics. One of the sources of this
complexity is that each time some new idea in mathematics is discovered, mathematicians then
make haste to apply it to all the topics previously known, so as to give to each of them a new
treatment. It is like walking into a hall of mirrors in which we see in one mirror reflections of
other mirrors and in each of them also reflections of others and so on. Thus in every field and
branch of mathematics all the other fields are reflected.
This makes it very difficult to give the beginner a map of mathematics in the way that we might
outline, for example, the branches of natural science. Yet it is important that a student who has
become acquainted with elementary geometry and algebra should have seen that these
fundamental mathematical studies are the door to a whole world of mathematics.
ADVANCES IN GEOMETRY
EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRY
In ancient times many interesting theorems were added to those contained in Euclid's Elements.
A student can get an idea of this achievement by examining the Conic Sections of Appolonius of
Perga (260-170 B.C., a generation after Archimedes), in which a beautiful theory is given of the
figures and curves produced by a plane intersecting a cone at various angles.
The middle ages (lid very little to advance geometrical studies because the mathematicians of
that period were more concerned with algebra, and this tendency continued even in modern times
because of the invention of analytic geometry, which is algebraic in character. Nevertheless, the
extension of algebra to new theorems continued.
More significant, however, is the effort to give the Euclidean geometry a more rigorous logical
structure. The Greeks themselves made many criticisms of Euclid's definitions, axioms,
postulates, and proofs, and showed that many of them could be made more exact. In particular,
they attempted to show that the complicated parallel line postulate (see page 331) was not a
postulate, but a theorem, although they never succeeded in this attempt.
Modern geometers also have been chiefly interested in this problem of making geometry
rigorously exact. To do this it is necessary to admit nothing in geometry that is not entirely
justified by the explicit postulates. Furthermore, these postulates must be exactly stated, and be
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
independent of each other. By "independent" is meant that one cannot be proved from another.
The clearest proof of such independence, of course, is had when it can be shown that one
postulate can be contradicted without contradicting the others.
In applying these strict standards to Euclid, numerous defects were found. In listing only five
postulates, Euclid had implicitly included others which needed to be stated. Once this point had
been cleared up it was also necessary to show the mutual independence of the postulates. Once
again suspicion centered on the parallel line postulate. Was the statement that through a point
outside a given line one and only one parallel can be drawn* [*This is equivalent to Euclid's own
statement of the postulate, given on page 331.] a theorem or a postulate? The only way to settle this
question was either to prove it as a theorem, using the other postulates, or at least to show that it
was dependent on the other postulates by showing that to assume its contradictory would lead to
it contradiction of the other postulates. If this last proved impossible, then Euclid would have
been vindicated, and it would be evident that this statement is not a theorem but a true postulate
independent of the others.
Since after hundreds of years of effort no positive proof had been found that it was a theorem,
Father Geronimo Saccheri, S.J. (1667-1733), attempted the negative approach of assuming the
contradictory of the postulate and seeking to show its dependence on the other postulates in this
way.
NON-EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRY
The importance of this new approach was not recognized until the 19th century. The Russian,
Nicholas Lobachevski, and the Hungarian, John Bolyai, assumed that in fact there are many lines
parallel to a given line passing through a point outside the line. The German, Bernhard Riemann,
took the opposite assumption, that there are no parallel lines. In both cases the geometers were
able to show that geometries of this sort are self-consistent. Hence Euclid was quite right in
holding that his postulate was not a theorem, but a statement independent of the others.
This proof of the independence of the parallel line postulate did not, of course, prove that
Euclid's postulate was false, nor that it was a mere assumption. Nor did it prove that either the
assumption of Lobachevski-Bolyai, or that of Riemann, was true. What it showed was that if this
postulate is not taken as a first principle, then the complete Euclidean system with its use of
similar figures cannot be demonstrated.
On the other hand, besides the geometry of Euclid there now existed a group of Non-Euclidean
systems (other sub-varieties besides the two we have mentioned were soon added), which as self-
consistent systems of propositions were quite marvelous and as rich
in arguments as the Euclidean geometry. How were these to be understood? It was soon seen that
all these geometries, including that of Euclid, could be considered as forming a more general
type of geometry. This more general geometry shows the analogy between various different
figures.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Thus in Euclidean geometry distances are measured by straight lines. On the surface of a
sphere, however, distance is measured by a curved line (called a geodesic, "earth-line"). Hence
there is an analogy between a straight and a curved line in this respect. Not every curved line on
a sphere, however, is the shortest distance between two points, but only a certain type of line
depending on the curvature of the sphere itself. Even on a sphere, therefore, it is possible to
distinguish between two classes of lines, and we may consider the geodesic as straight, and the
other as curved. Since this is only an analogy, however, the properties of a geodesic are not
altogether the same as the properties of a straight line-for example, all geodesics on a sphere
intersect.
Hence "straight lines" on a sphere cannot be parallel, and in this sense the assumption of
Riemann is valid for the surface of a sphere. Similarly, concave solids can be constructed on
whose surfaces the geodesics are such that many never meet (at least on the limited surface of
such solids). For such surfaces, then, the assumption of Lobacbevski and Bolyai holds.
So the Euclidean and Non-Euclidean geometries are not contradictory, but apply to surfaces or
spaces in which the measurement of distance is made by lines which have zero curvature
(Euclidean geometry), positive curvature (Lobachevski-Bolyai), or negative curvature
(Riemann). Between figures of these three sorts there is thus revealed a beautiful analogy, since
in each of the geometries there are similar theorems which can be translated into each other by
an appropriate change in the definition of the terms. For example, the figures on the surface of a
sphere do not have the same definition as figures drawn on a flat surface, and yet for every figure
on a flat surface there is a corresponding figure on the sphere and corresponding theorems can be
proved of it.
In this way a greater unity is given to the whole of geometry. For it becomes apparent that once
we have proved a theorem for a figure on a flat surface, we will be able to prove many analogous
theorems which apply to a great variety of curved surfaces.
PROJECTIVE GEOMETRY
The Euclidean and Non-Euclidean geometries are often called metric (Greek metron means
"measure") geometries since in them the measurement of distance is of fundamental importance,
and they differ as to the way in which this measurement is made by a straight or curved line. It
was discovered even by the Greeks that it is possible to compare one figure with another,
abstracting from considerations of measurement.
This discovery was made in the applied mathematics called perspective, in which a painter tries
to solve the problem of representing a three-dimensional object on a two-dimensional surface. As
we all know, in such a representation parallel lines (a railroad track, for example) must be shown
as converging to a distant point, and all objects appear as foreshortened. Again, the circular top
of a vase or cup appears as an ellipse in a painting, although in reality the edge of the cup is at all
points equidistant from the center. Thus in the painting the distances of the parts are greatly
altered, and yet a very exact analogy between the real figures and their representation is
maintained; otherwise they would not look alike.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
We have no practical difficulty in interpreting a picture, but the history of art shows us that it
was no mean feat for painters to learn this trick of perspective. Geometers attempting to develop
an exact theory of such perspective soon realized that it had important implications for pure
geometry. This development began in modern times with the Frenchmen, Girard Desargues
(1593-1662), and the great Blaise Pascal (1623-1662), who was noted alike as a physicist,
mathematician, and Christian apologist.
Projective geometry considers the relations between figures which correspond to each other
point for point, although their shape, size, and proportions may be quite different. The name is
derived from the fact that one figure is then thought of as being altered into the other by a
process of projection on a different surface or a different part of surface. We can, for example,
cause a movie camera to cast its picture on a flat surface facing the camera, or on the ceiling or
walls which are perpendicular to the camera, or on the curved surface of a pillar. The picture
undergoes all sorts of stretching and shrinking, and still every point of the picture as it appears on
the flat surface appears also in its other projections.
Obviously the properties which are common to classes of figures related to each other in this way
are very fundamental ones, and projective geometry is therefore a very penetrating and profound
study. The postulates which are required to prove its theorems are of it very general type relating
to the order of points in space. As Non-Euclidean geometry omits the similarity of figures, so
projective geometry abstracts from the congruence of figures.
TOPOLOGY
It is possible, however, to abstract still further, leaving out not only the similarity and congruence
of figures, but even the point-to-point correspondence which still remains in projective geometry.
Just as we imagined a figure projected on another surface so that the distances between its points
is stretched or shrunken, so now we may imagine it as twisted, bent, knotted, or deformed in any
fashion, provided it is not torn or divided. Even when treated in this fashion a physical figure
retains certain properties. A circle of wire, for example, can be twisted and crushed into a ball,
yet this does not alter the fact that it is a single line which is endless. A rubber balloon could be
forced into the shape of an egg, of a dumbbell, or made to fill the interior of a square box; it
remains a closed surface.
Topology (Greek topos, a place) is the study, only recently developed to any extent, of the
properties of figures which are of this fundamental character and which imply only the
connectedness or continuity of the parts. With it we reach the limits of pure geometry, since if
we go a step further and remove continuity we cannot properly be said to be in the science of
geometry. Actually, this further abstraction is made, as we will see below.
NUMBER THEORY
We have seen how the science of magnitudes has been pushed to deeper and deeper depths of
analysis. What of the development of the science of number? The problems of number theory
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
raised by Euclid and Nicomachus (see page 353) have continued to occupy mathematicians, and
are still of very great interest. For example, the following two problems dealing with prime
numbers have never been solved:
1. Is it true that any even number (except 2, which is itself a prime) can be represented as the sum
of two primes? If you try it with 4, 6, 8, 48, 100, etc., you will see that it is true in these cases. Is
it always true? No one knows. This is called Goldbach's conjecture after an obscure
mathematician in the 18th century who first suggested it.
2. Are there infinitely many pairs of primes which differ by 2? There are many such pairs -- for
example, 3 and 5, 11 and 13, 29 and 31. Is this a regular recurrence throughout the series of
natural numbers?
Thus it is apparent that the study of the properties of natural numbers is far from exhausted.
Indeed, as we shall see below, all modern mathematics ultimately rests on the theory of numbers.
ALGEBRA
We have seen in Chapter I of this part (see page 311) that algebra arose from the emphasis on the
construction of whole classes of numbers bearing certain relations or functions with respect to
one another. Thus for algebra the fundamental concept is that of function.
We have also seen that, in order to construct such classes of numbers, it was convenient to
enlarge the concept of number so as to include various types of operational or artificial numbers
which signify not a quantity (as do the natural numbers) but the construction of a quantity by a
certain operation. Each of these artificial numbers can be defined as a certain process involving
the fundamental operations of addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division, performed on
specified natural numbers or classes of natural numbers. In this way, zero, negative and positive
numbers, fractions, irrational numbers, and complex numbers were all devised and proved to
form a number field which is closed under the four fundamental operations. This means that any
process of addition, subtraction, multiplication, or division (with the sole exception of division
by zero) on numbers in this field will construct another number pertaining to this same field (see
page 321).
This does not mean, however, that "numbers" cannot be found which cannot be constructed in
this fashion. Transcendental numbers have been discovered, such as (3.1415...), which are not
algebraic numbers and which cannot be constructed by algebraic processes (that is, they cannot
be roots of all algebraic equation with rational coefficients). Furthermore, George Cantor (1845-
1918) introduced transfinite numbers, concerning which there has always been much
mathematical controversy, but which certainly have some mathematical meaning. Cantor pointed
out that it is possible to distinguish different infinite sets of numbers, and to give arguments to
show that one infinity is greater than another, while some infinites are equal, It then becomes
possible to assign a cardinal number to these infinities by ordering them according to smaller and
greater, and then perform some of the ordinary mathematical operations upon them. The results
are very curious. For example, we must admit that the set of odd and the set of even numbers are
both infinite, as well as the set of all natural numbers. Yet we must also admit all three sets are
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
equal to each other, since we can find an odd and even number for every natural number as
follows:
natural number: 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10
odd number: 3 5 7 9 11 13 15 17 19 21
even number: 2 4 6 8 10 12 14 16 18 20
From this it would appear that axioms such as "the whole is greater than the part" do not apply to
such sets.
In order to introduce numbers other than the integers, the concepts of a series of numbers and of
a limit were required. Thus an irrational number can be defined as the limit of a series of
fractions, a limit which is approached more and more closely the further this series is
constructed, but which is never reached.
Given these numbers all constructed by means of fundamental operations which are justified by
postulates, the work of algebra is to study functions, or the relations between classes of
numbers. Such a relation is expressed by an equation which indicates that certain operations on
certain classes of numbers (variables) will yield a number which can also be constructed in a
different (or sometimes identical) fashion. So 3² + 4² = 5² means that the same number, 25, can
be constructed by two different operations. a² + b² = c² means that there are classes of numbers
for which this same relation holds.
In elementary algebra the student is taught to solve many such equations of the simplest types,
generally simultaneous equations (equations of first degree) and quadratic equations (equations
of second degree), named from the coefficients which occur in the equation. The Greeks by the
time of Diophantus (who died about 330 A.D.) had advanced this far in algebra. The general
equations of the third and fourth degree were solved by the Italians, Nicholas Tartaglia and
Ludovici Ferrari, and first published by Girolamo Cardano in 1545.
For a long time mathematicians attempted to find general solutions for equations of higher
degree; such efforts were unsuccessful, although they advanced rapidly in solving particular
types of equations, Finally, a Norwegian, Niles Abel (1802-1829), showed that this search was
hopeless, since equations of the fifth degree and higher have no general solution. Henceforth it
became necessary to deal rather with the immense array of particular types of equations, and the
brilliant Evariste Galois (who died in the year 1832 when lie was only 21) laid a general
foundation for this higher algebra by showing a way to classify the various types of equations, so
that each group could be dealt with as a whole.
ANALYTIC GEOMETRY
In the meantime, the development of algebra was being strongly influenced by the great effort to
reduce geometry to algebra. We have already seen (page 359) how the basis of such a reduction
had been provided by Descartes (1596-1650) in his system of analytic geometry. This
completed the work of trigonometry (see page 359), which had already provided a method of
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
expressing the ratios of lines and the size of angles in numerical terms. By an extension of
Descartes' method of co-ordinates, any geometrical figure -- whether plane or solid, even those in
the Non-Euclidean and projective geometries -- could be expressed agebraically. Each point in
space could be specified by three numbers, each line and plane by an equation, and thus
geometry seemed to be immensely simplified.
Even more surprising was the fact that by pursuing this method it became possible to speak of
geometries of more than three dimensions. Since in algebra a point in space is defined by 3
numbers giving the distance of that point from certain fixed lines (co-ordinates), there is no
algebraic reason why it should not be possible to speak of points which require 4 such numbers,
or any set n of numbers to determine its location. Each such number required to determine a
position may be called a "dimension," and any number of such dimensions can be dealt with in
algebra. The fourth dimension could even be pictured graphically by projecting it upon a solid or
a plane, just as it is possible in perspective to project a solid figure of three dimensions on a
plane of one less dimension.
THE CALCULUS
The method found is called the calculus (method of calculating), which is spoken of as
differential when it is used to determine the slope of a line for a given difference of the variable,
and integral when it is used to determine the area bounded by the line (i.e., to determine the rate
of change in a function, or the accumulated change). It consists essentially in the use of the
concept of limit.
We can convert a continuous line into a series of numbers by dividing the line into units as small
as we please, so that the series approximates to a description of the line as closely as we wish to
make it. So also we can convert a curved line into a series of straight lines (tangents to
successive points in it) of varying slopes, with as perfect an approximation as we wish, by
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
considering as small a segment of the curve as we wish. For each such small segment the slope
of the curve is roughly the same as a certain tangent straight line. The smaller we make this
segment the more accurate our description, although the exact description is a limit which cannot
be attained.
Such a study of the approach of a series to a limit can also be applied to many types of problems
other than those of geometrical curves. For example, when we speak of the velocity of a moving
body we are considering a relation between a change in time and a change in distance, so that if
we speak of the velocity of a body at an instant of time, we are speaking of a limit, namely the
change in distance during a smaller and smaller interval of time.
It is possible, therefore, to generalize the calculus so that it becomes the branch of algebra which
considers any type of problem dealing with the ratio between the difference of a dependent
variable required when the independent variable is made to differ by a smaller and smaller
amount (differential calculus), or problems dealing with the sum of a series of such difference
(integral calculus).
Of particular interest in studying functions in this way is the determination of whether they are
continuous or not, and also the determination of their maximum and minimum values.
This reduction of geometry to more and more general systems such as topology (which we have
described), then its reduction to algebra, and the advance of algebra to methods of studying every
type of function by a general method of calculating every possible value of a variable-this could
not but lead on to a still more general study of mathematics.
We have already mentioned Galois, who showed that an approach could be made to the solution
of equations of higher degree by classifying them. This idea was soon extended to all of
geometry and of algebra, so that mathematicians became interested, not merely in particular
equations, but in whole classes of transformations. By this is meant that we can find very
general classes of mathematical objects which have some properties in common, so that they
could be transformed into each other by a finite number of specified mathematical operations.
Thus in our survey of geometry we saw, as we advanced from Euclid's geometry to topology,
that we were dealing with more and more basic properties which applied to wider and wider
groups of figures. In topology a circle could be classed with a vast number of other closed
figures, into which it could be transformed by a series of operations of twisting and bending and
rearrangement. Similarly, as we advanced in algebra we saw that mathematicians were ever
seeking to group equations into great classes, each of which could be solved by a series of
defined operations.
In order to reach this generality, it is necessary first to find analogies between unlike things.
Thus projective geometry finds an analogy between a solid figure and its projection on a plane.
In somewhat the same way analytic geometry finds an analogy between a line and an equation,
and algebra finds an analogy between a rational and irrational Dumber, or a number and an
infinite collection. Such analogies, however, can lead to all sorts of confused and paradoxical
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
thinking. Hence the tendency of mathematics has been to try and reduce these to univocal
definitions, which are extremely generalized. When this is carried to a limit, the result is called
set theory.
In set theory the mathematician begins with definitions and postulates which abstract from all
geometric notions and which reduce numbers to sets of collections of unspecified objects. These
objects might be interpreted as points, as lines, as spheres, as integers, as real numbers, as
irrational numbers, or in any other fashion, just so long as they form a collection or set which can
be defined by some common property. It then remains possible to perform operations on these
abstract sets according to operational laws which are taken as postulates. In this way we may add
sets, divide them, consider the part they have or do not have in common, etc.
Such a theory seems to satisfy the famous definition of mathematics by Bertrand Russell:
"Mathematics is a science in which we do not know what we are talking about, or if what we are
saying about it is true." Yet it is extremely powerful. In set theory it is possible to prove
theorems so general that they will apply to any part of geometry or algebra. These theorems
make it apparent that most of the theorems previously proved in these sciences are only special
cases of more general theorems, in which the basic relations involved are much more evident. In
consequence, set theory casts light on the whole of mathematics and gives it an orderliness never
before suspected.
We have still not reached the end of our survey. As soon as the ideal of rigor in mathematics
began to be prominent in modern mathematics, it was evident that a mathematician in making a
demonstration must not only list his mathematical postulates, but also must state his logical rules
of reasoning as well. We saw in Chapter II that Euclid's proofs are not convincing unless we can
show that he also observed the rules of syllogistic reasoning. Hence arose the attention to
mathematical logic, or the methodology required in mathematics, and attempts were made to
make very explicit the logical rules which were being followed.
As soon as this was done, mathematicians were rather horrified to discover that "traditional
logic" -- that is, the logic current in the schools of the 19th century -- was itself not a very
rigorous science. They attempted, therefore, to improve logic by the same methods of explicit
postulation and careful definition as they were using in mathematics, and to facilitate this they
introduced a mathematical type of notation. This new rigorous system of logic using a
mathematical type of notation is what we call symbolic logic. Again, this was only reviving an
idea which Aristotle had glimpsed, and which was later considered by the medieval thinker,
Blessed Ramon Lull, in the 13th century, and again by Leibnitz in the 17th. But in our times this
new logic has been developed with amazing perfection.
We will not describe this system of logic here in detail, but only mention the following features:
1. It has a notation, similar to that used in mathematics, by which all logical relations found in
formal logic can be expressed. This notation includes
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
a. Letters which stand for variables, just as in mathematics, except that in this case the variables
are classes of statements or terms. For instance, the letters p and q may each stand for any
statement belonging to a particular set of statements.
b. Symbols which indicate logical relations. For example, the symbol ~ placed before a
propositional variable (one standing for a set of statements) negates it, so that ~ p is the denial of
the statement p. Again, the symbol connecting two variables indicates their conditional relation,
so that p q means "If the statement p is true, then the statement q is true."
2. It begins with a small number of axioms expressing such basic relations. If it introduces
symbols other than the primitive ones, it defines these new symbols in terms of the primitive
symbols. Furthermore, it has rules of inference which are similar to the rules of operation in
mathematics, and which permit theorems to be proved by reduction to the axioms. Finally, it may
have formation rules which regulate the formation of statements from terms, and combinations of
statements from simple statements. All these axioms, definitions, and rules are assumed without
proof. It has been shown that, just as a number of geometries or algebras are possible depending
on the axioms assumed, so many logistic systems are possible in the same way.
3. From these axioms theorems are deduced according to the assumed rules of inference. These
theorems are of two sorts:
a. Theorems which are the various laws of logic; for example, the moods of the syllogism, etc.
b. Meta-theorems which deal with the completeness and order of logic as a science. For example,
if we prove our list of the moods of the syllogism to be complete, this conclusion is a meta-
theorem. These meta-theorems are, so to speak, the logic of logic itself. (See page 568 ff.).
Once this logistic system is complete we have a full set of logical rules which can be used to
regulate the development of some particular science. The particular sciences themselves can then
be formulated in the same fashion, by adding new symbols which stand for their special terms,
and axioms containing these terms. It may also be necessary to provide some special logical rules
for a given science, but these can be either postulated or proved in the logistic system.
To date it has been found too complicated to formalize in this rigorous way any of the sciences
except mathematics, and here a curious result has been achieved. It is the contention of Alfred
North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell, who at the beginning of this century were leaders in the
revival of logic, that when mathematics is formalized it becomes possible to reduce it to logic,
because the postulates required for mathematics all relate to numbers, and numbers can be
defined in purely logical terms. Russell defines number as "the set of all those classes whose
members have a one-to-one correspondence." Thus the set of all couples is the number 2, the set
of all trios the number 3, etc. Since in this definition no terms except logical terms ("set," " class
... .. correspondence") are used, it is argued that number can be defined as a purely logical entity.
If this attempt had succeeded, then the final outcome would be that mathematics would turn out
to be pure logic. However this result has not been universally accepted, so that at present there
are four well-known opinions about the ultimate nature of mathematics:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
1. The Logistic Theory of Whitehead and Russell, which holds that pure mathematics is a branch of
logic, expressed in their famous book Principia Mathematica (1913).
2. The Formalistic Theory, of which David Hilbert (1862-1943) was the leader, according to which
mathematics is the science of the formal structure of symbols. This school admits that
mathematics is not logic since it concerns the structure of real objects, but they contend that it is
possible to replace this structure by symbols which represent this structure. Once a correct
symbolization has been achieved, then mathematics consists in the study of the structure of these
symbols and only indirectly in the study of the real things.
3. The Theory of Intuitionism, of which L. E. J. Brouwer is the leader, holds that mathematics
must be based on the natural numbers which we are intuitively sure we can construct.
4. The Aristotelian Theory, which prevailed in mathematics before Descartes, according to which
geometry and algebra are essentially distinct sciences of real quantity.
This survey makes clear that in mathematics as in every other science there is progress, but at the
same time there is often an increase in confusion and error. As every field of learning advances,
brilliant ideas are proposed which often rapidly develop and become the fashion. Some of these
eventually prove to be false, but their exposure usually brings to light some new truth or at least
makes us understand an old truth better. In the history of mathematics, the many "proofs" of the
parallel line postulate are an example of how errors may be made even by great thinkers, errors,
however, which eventually are profitable.
Other new ideas prove to be true, but even in this case they are often proposed at first in an
inaccurate and paradoxical fashion. Expressed in this incorrect and exaggerated fashion they
often seem to overthrow the truths which have already been achieved, and there are always
enthusiasts who claim that a new discovery has destroyed all that men previously thought to be
true. Thus the success of the calculus led some (including one of its discoverers, the great
Leibnitz) to suppose that at last it bad been shown that a line is made up of points. But this
conclusion was due to inaccurate definitions of terms; it has been removed by a better
understanding of the notion of a limit.
The lesson which this must teach us, and which the history of mathematics so well illustrates, is
that we must constantly analyze and criticize each new theory until we are sure that it is correctly
expressed and basically sound. In the elementary study of a subject (and this is specially true of
mathematics) textbooks and teachers often find it convenient to define terms in a loose and
metaphorical way. If the student takes this illustrative language literally lie will fall into many
errors.
For example, many terms used in mathematics seem to imply motion or change. We define a
circle as "a line described by a point moving, at a constant distance from another point." We
speak of "constructing" a geometrical figure or a number, of a "variable" and
congruence. All such expressions are only figures of speech derived from physical quantity.
Hence in giving accurate definitions in mathematics we should seek to eliminate all implication
of motion. Even the term "operation" must be understood very accurately, since we do not really
make anything in mathematics (see pages 309 f.).
Another sort of confusion which we have pointed out several times is to be found in the
analogical use of terms. The term number, for example, strictly applies only to the natural
numbers, beginning with 2. Zero, the unit, negative numbers, fractions, irrational numbers,
imaginary numbers, complex numbers, transfinite numbers, all are numbers only in an analogical
sense. Similarly, the term "dimension" and the term "space" have many meanings. Nothing could
be more absurd than the idea of some people that modern mathematics has proved the existence
of a fourth dimension in the sense that length, breadth, and depth are dimensions.
Fortunately the last fifty years has seen mathematicians become very careful about distinguishing
these different senses of terms, but the student will find them still often misused in mathematical
writing and reasoning.
Yet even when these confusions in the use of terms is cleared up, a basic weakness in modern
mathematics remains. It is the same weakness which Aristotle criticized in the mathematics
which he learned in Plato's Academy, namely, the failure to distinguish between science and
dialectics. Aristotle showed that no matter how beautifully constructed and how logical a system
of thought might appear, it remained only dialectical unless it could be shown to rest on first
principles (axioms and postulates) which are immediately evident. A building is only as firm as
its foundations and a house built on sand will fall. The problem about modern mathematics,
therefore, must be whether it is built on immediately evident first principles.
Modern mathematicians generally concede that it is not. Indeed many deny that any such
principles are possible. The modern view is that mathematics begins with "axioms" which are
pure assumptions and which do not have to be known to be true or false. They concede then that
mathematics is not a science in the Aristotelian sense, but only a dialectical system, and they
deny that it can ever become a science.
What is the cause of this strangely pessimistic attitude? Mathematicians generally give two
reasons:
1. The use of this method of basing mathematics on assumptions has proved wonderfully fruitful. If
we compare the mathematics of Euclid with modern mathematics, we see that modern
mathematics is incomparably richer and more powerful.
2. 2. The classical example of immediately evident first principles -- namely, the axioms and
postulates of Euclid -- has been shown to be a set of assumptions whose contradictories can just
as well be assumed as a base for mathematics.
The consequences of this position are serious. If all of mathematics is only probable, and
mathematics is the most certain of all sciences, then all knowledge is only probable. Since it is
contradictory to hold that all knowledge is probable (see page 79), this leads to the admission of
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
contradiction or absurdity in the real world, and hence to complete scepticism and to atheism.
The Catholic Faith tells us very plainly that the human reason is capable by its own power of
arriving at certain truth, and this is also evident from our own daily experience in which
everyone is aware of many truths which cannot be reasonably doubted.
Pessimism and scepticism in this matter, as in many others, is the result of failure to analyze
conflicting views in a critical way. Confusion leads to a despair of finding the truth. Let us
consider the two main difficulties:
1. It is not surprising that the use of assumptions is fruitful in mathematics. We have seen (page
187) that in every science dialectics is required in opening up new problems. In mathematics also
new discoveries have been made by beginning with an assumption and drawing out of it a series
of conclusions. If paradoxes were then encountered the assumptions had to be abandoned. If the
results seemed self-consistent, then the investigation was continued until it became possible to
connect the system with the evident axioms and postulates of mathematics. In this manner the
calculus was developed quite extensively before it was possible to show in a precise way how it
could be given a secure foundation by the concept of the limit. Hence it is not necessary that a
particular mathematical system be abandoned merely because it is dialectical. We need only
acknowledge that it is tentative and imperfect, and so open to further research.
2. It is not true to say that the development of the Non-Euclidean geometries proved that the
parallel line postulate is not immediately evident. They only proved that it is a true postulate
independent of the other Euclidean postulates. The NonEuclidean geometries as originally posed
were based on an arbitrary assumption of a substitute for this postulate. As such they were merely
dialectical. Eventually it was shown that these geometries could be verified in Euclidean space if
geodesics of positive or negative curvature were taken as analogous to a straight line. Thus in
Euclidean space it is possible to have Non-Euclidean figures. That Euclidean space is the true
space of geometry is. by no means disproved. In it alone are there similar figures and zero
curvature. Other spaces have to be constructed by us as modifications of this space. Furthermore,
it is a three-dimensional space, since it cannot be proved that any other space can be constructed,
except in an analytical geometry in which "dimension" is only used in an analogical sense.
The same thing is true of arguments drawn from Cantor's transfinite numbers (see page
388), for which the whole is not greater than the part, etc. These are supposed by some to
disprove the very axioms of Euclid. If we consider such arguments carefully we will find
them riddled with equivocation. Can we see that an infinite multitude is a whole with
parts? The term "whole" implies some kind of unity, but we cannot conceive how an
infinite multitude could have any kind of unity of itself, and it certainly cannot have unity
from our counting its elements in a series, since we cannot count to infinity. In
mathematics we have the potentially infinite; for example, a line or any magnitude can be
divided and subdivided as often as we please. Similarly, the series of natural numbers or
the length of a line can be made as great as we please. But we can never construct an
actually infinite magnitude or number. As the criticisms made by mathematicians of the
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Intuitionist school (see page 396) have shown, the assumption of actually infinite
quantities is only dialectical. We cannot prove that such quantities are not contradictory,
although conversely (as St. Thomas Aquinas pointed out in the 13th century) it seems
difficult to prove them impossible.
Some have tried to argue that the only test of mathematical truth is the self -consistency of a
system based on a set of assumptions -- a defense given by many for the Non-Euclidean
geometries. If only this test is met, however, a system is dialectical and not scientific. A poem
can be self -consistent, to all appearances, and still be a mere fiction. But as a matter of fact even
this test is not possible in a mathematics based on assumptions.
It has been proved by Goedel and other modern mathematicians that it is not possible to prove
the self -consistency of a system from within the system. The mere fact that a contradiction has
not yet been discovered in a system does not prove it consistent, since in a science it is usually
possible to draw an unlimited number of conclusions, and therefore such a contradiction may
appear in the next theorem. Furthermore, since it is possible for contradictory conclusions to be
deduced from a false premise, two systems contradictory to each other but each consistent with
itself might both be deduced from the same false assumptions.
Hence in actual practice mathematicians have never been content with resting a theory on self-
consistency. Ordinarily they justify it by an existence theorem in which it is shown that the
theory is valid in a particular case, or that it is strictly analogous to something which is known to
be valid. This is the way in which the Non-Euclidean geometries, and in general any system of
this type, is validated, by showing that it is analogous in a strict way with Euclidean geometry, or
with the series of natural numbers. Indeed, as we have seen, all modern mathematics has been
developed in such a way that it is ultimately tested by reference to the natural numbers.
Quantity
Since this is the case, it also appears why it is not true to say that modern mathematics is no
longer about quantity, but merely about relations. Relations (see page 60) cannot exist of
themselves. They must be relations between things, and they must have a foundation in things.
The relations with which modern mathematics deals are those studied in set theory. What is a
set? It is defined as "a collection of my kind of objects having some common property." If we
examine the word "collection" we see that it means "a multitude having some type of unity."
Thus none of the relations studied in modern mathematics of the most advanced type can be
considered or defined except in terms of "unified multitudes."
angels we make use of transcendental quantity conceived analogously to the quantity which is
in the categories (categorical or predicamental quantity). There must be, therefore, a science of
quantity before there can be any set theory. If set theory is considered as embracing spiritual
beings, it properly belongs to metaphysics and it presupposes another distinct science of
mathematics which treats of the quantity of material objects. This objection holds also for
Russell's definition of number, which is supposed to eliminate quantity but which still makes use
of the notion of a "collection," or "class" in the sense of a collection, and which is therefore a
circular definition.
The only alternative to this is to say, with Russell, that mathematics is not about real things, but
about logical beings, and that the relations in question are purely logical. However, if this is the
case, then the things studied by mathematics cannot exist in physical reality, since a mental being
is one which cannot exist outside the mind. Since mathematicians know very well that they deal
with many things which do have an extra-mental existence, and which are not merely creations
of the mind, this view of mathematics would destroy almost the entire existing body of
mathematical doctrine.
We may conclude that modern mathematics is still about quantity when it is accurately
developed, although it often deals with extremely general quantitative relations.
CONCLUSION
In surveying mathematics we cannot help but be struck by the way in which the two branches of
geometry and arithmetic have survived in spite of all the attempts to reduce them to a single
science. The fact is that modern mathematicians in general grant that there is a genuine and
irreducible distinction between continuous and discrete quantity, between lines and numbers.
Of course numbers are more abstract and clear than are magnitudes. Hence it will always be
highly useful to use analytic geometry and other methods to approximate geometry by means of
algebra; but this approximation of numbers to magnitudes is an approach to a limit, it can never
be realized. The reason has already been given by Aristotle. Geometrical objects are infinitely
divisible, while arithmetical objects are made tip of units which are indivisible. Thus the two
sciences remain essentially distinct, with different sets of definitions and postulates which are
only analogous to each other.
INTUITION
Our knowledge of immediately evident principles comes from the power of our intelligence,
which moderns call "intuition" or "insight." We must not be scandalized at the many attacks
made on "intuition" by formalists in mathematics and logic. They usually disparage intuition by
pointing out the fact that very frequently in mathematics and logic we discover surprising
conclusions which "at first sight" we would have thought unlikely, for example, the possibility of
Non-Euclidean Geometries, the irrationality of relations like, etc.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
If by "intuition" is meant our rough, uncritical impressions of reality, then of course " intuition"
has to be eliminated from scientific knowledge -- and replaced by precise and accurate
knowledge. This is just what Euclid was trying to do when he produced his Elements; in this
work the rough "intuitive" guesses and imperfect demonstrations of earlier mathematicians were
given critical and scientific form. His efforts were imperfect, but in recent years the efforts of
every logician and mathematician to construct perfect systems have also been shown by critics to
contain many weak spots. The great Principia Mathematica of Russell and Whitehead has been
found to be riddled with difficulties more fundamental than any in Euclid's Elements.
But if by "intuition" we mean critical intelligence, then all mathematics must rest on the power
of the human mind to abstract from experience certain things which it sees to be certain and
evident. Those selected by Euclid have never been shown to be false, and must be used today as
the basis of all mathematics, although we can formulate them more precisely than he did. They
are true because they are not assumed arbitrarily, but abstracted from experience by a clear
intelligence.
The efforts of modern thinkers to turn mathematics into a strictly formal system in which the
conclusions can be deduced by purely mechanical methods and without thinking is not to be
rejected. Mathematics at all times needs a system of calculation. As we have seen, arithmetic in
our ordinary modern sense, and much of algebra and calculus, is a method of calculating; it is
only an instrument of the science of mathematics, whose business is not the working of problems
but the demonstration of truths. Such calculations can be very well carried out by electric-
brains, but an electric-brain cannot see why its results are true. Only the human intelligence can
see truth.
In learning mathematics, therefore, the student must constantly seek to understand why an
answer is true. This means that he must trace it back to fundamental axioms and postulates,
which he is certain are true from his own experience. Only then does he have scientific
knowledge. If he cannot base a conclusion on these truths, but only on assumptions, then he must
regard it as tentative or dialectical reasoning, which may or may not turn out to be true on further
examination. The fact that such dialectical reasoning appears at the same time both highly
plausible and yet in contradiction to the axioms or postulates should not surprise him in the least;
on the contrary, it should be a stimulant for him to reconcile it with these axioms and postulates,
or to discover its inherent fallacy.
This is the straight road which Euclid gave to mathematics, and it is only by traveling it that
mathematics has advanced.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
PART FOUR:
Examples and
Analyses
SECTION I
The following are the five examples of the kinds of discourse to which reference is made
throughout the text of Part One. Examples I and II are poetic, the first in prose and the second in
verse. Example III is rhetorical. Example IV is dialectical, although it makes use of many
rhetorical devises, because its principal purpose seems not to be merely to persuade us, but to
help us arrive at a correct definition of a commonly confused idea. Example V is scientific in
mode. These particular examples have been chosen because they are very brief, and because they
aim at essentially the same conclusion, namely, that patriotism is honorable.
ALPHONSE DAUDET
(Note: This is a translation by Blanche Colton Williams of a story by a French author.* [*From A Book of Short
Stories, by Blanche Colton Williams, copyright 1918, by D. Appleton and Co. Reprinted by permission of Appleton-
Century-Crofts, Inc.] It refers to the occupation of the formerly French province of Alsace-Lorraine by the Prussians
at the end of the Franco-Prussian War in 1870.)
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
That morning I was very late in going to school, and was much afraid of being scolded; all the
more so, as M. Hamel had told us he would question us upon the participles, and I did not know
the first word. For a moment I thought of playing truant and setting off across the country.
One heard the blackbirds whistling at the edge of the wood, and in the Rippert meadow, behind
the sawmill, the Prussians who were drilling. All that tempted me much more than the rule of
participles; but I had the strength to resist and I ran fast to school.
In passing by the mayor's office, I saw that a group of people had stopped at the little bulletin
board. For two years all the bad news had come to us from there, lost battles, requisitions, orders
from headquarters; and without pausing I said: "What is it this time?"
Then, as I crossed the square on the run, the blacksmith Wachter, who was there with his
apprentice engaged in reading the notice, cried out to me:
"Do not hurry so, youngster; you w ill arrive soon enough at your school!"
I thought he was making fun of me, and out of breath I went into M. Hamel's little yard.
Usually at the beginning of a class, there was a great uproar which could be heard in the street-
desks opening and closing, lessons being repeated all together at the top of the voice, the pupils
stopping their ears with their fingers the better to learn them, and the big rule of the master
tapping upon the table.
I counted on all this din to reach my seat without notice, but as luck would have it, on this day
everything was quiet, as on Sunday morning. Through the open window I saw my schoolmates
already in their places, and M. Hamel pacing back and forth with the terrible iron-tipped rule
under his arm. I had to open the door and enter in the midst of the great stillness. Well you may
think I blushed and was afraid.
But nothing happened. A Hamel looked at me without anger and said to me very gently:
"Go quickly to your place, my little Franz; we were going to begin without you."
I stepped over the bench and sat down at once at my desk. Then only, a little recovered from my
fright, I noticed that our master had on his beautiful green frock coat, his carefully plaited shirt-
frill, and the skull-cap of embroidered black silk which he wore only on the days of inspection
and distribution of prizes. Besides, there was something unusual and solemn about the whole
class. But what surprised me most was to see at the end of the room, on the benches that were
usually vacant, the men of the village seated and silent like us; old Hauser with his three-
cornered hat, the ex-mayor, the former postman, and others. They all seemed sad; and Hauser
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
had brought an old dog-eared spelling book, which he held wide open on his knees, with his big
spectacles placed across the pages.
While I was marvelling at all this, M. Hamel had gone up into his chair, and in the same gentle
and serious voice with which he had greeted me, he said to us:
"My children, it is the last time I take the class. The order has come from Berlin to teach only
German in the schools of Alsace and Lorraine.... The new teacher comes tomorrow. Today's is
your last French lesson. I beg you to be very attentive."
These few words overwhelmed me, Ah, the villains, that was what they had posted at the
"mairie!"
And I who hardly knew how to write.... I should never learn. I should have to stop there! How I
blamed myself for the time lost, for cutting classes, to hunt bird's eggs or to practice sliding on
the Saar. Mv books, which only a moment ago I found so tiresome, so heavy to carry, my
Grammar, my Scripture History, seemed to me old friends from whom I should find it hard to
part. It was the same with M. Hamel. The idea that lie was going to leave, that I should never see
him again, made me forget punishments, blows from the ruler.
Poor man!
It was in honor of this last lesson that he had put on his handsome Sunday clothes; and now I
understood why the old men of the village had come to sit at the end of the room. It was as if to
say they were sorry they had not come more often to this school of theirs. It was also a way of
thanking our master for his forty years of good service, and of paying their respects to the
departing fatherland.
Such was the course of my thoughts, when I heard my name called. It was my turn to recite.
What would I not have given to be able to say front the beginning to end the famous rule of the
participles, in a loud, clear voice, without a mistake! But I got tangled up in the first words, and I
stood swaying against my bench, with a bursting heart, not daring to raise my head. I heard M.
Hamel speaking to me:
"I shall not scold you, my little Franz; you should be punished enough. That's the way of it.
Every day one says to oneself, 'Bah! I have time enough. I will learn tomorrow.' And then you
see what happens. . . . All, it has been the great misfortune of our Alsace always to put off
learning until tomorrow. Now these people have the right to say to us: 'What! you pretend to be
French, and you do not know how to speak or write your own language?' In all that, my poor
Franz, it is not you who are most guilty. We have all a good share of reproaches for ourselves.
"Your parents have not sufficiently cared to see you instructed. They liked better to send you to
till the fields or to work at the spinning mills, for the sake of a few extra sous. As for myself,
have I nothing with which to reproach myself? Have I not often made you water my garden
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
instead of working? And when I wished to go fishing for trout, did I hesitate to give you a
holiday . . . ?
Then, from one thing to another, M. Hamel began to talk to us about the French language, saying
that it was the most beautiful language in the world, the clearest, the most solid, that it should be
kept among us and never forgotten; because when a people falls into slavery, so long as it holds
fast its language it holds the key of its prison. Then lie took a grammar and read us our lesson. I
was astonished to see how well I understood. Everything he said seemed to me easy, easy. I
believed also that I had never listened so well, and that as for him be had never put so much
patience into his explanations.
One would have said that before going away the poor man wished to give us all his knowledge,
to make it enter our heads at a single blow.
When the lesson was over, we went on to writing. For that day, M. Hamel had prepared for us
entirely new examples, on which he had written in a beautiful round hand: "France," "Alsace,"
"France," "Alsace." They looked like little flags waving all around the class, bung to the rods of
our desks. It was something to see how each one applied himself, and in what silence. There was
nothing to be heard but the scratching of the pens on the paper. Once some beetles flew in, but
nobody paid any attention, not even the very little ones, who were busy tracing their strokes with
a courage and conscience, as if even the pot-hooks were in French. Upon the roof of the
schoolhouse pigeons cooed low, and listening, I said to myself:
From time to time when I lifted my eyes from my page, I saw M. Hamel motionless in his chair,
taking a long look at the objects around him, as if be wished to carry off in his mind's eye all the
little schoolhouse. . . . Think! Forty years he had been there in the same place, with his yard in
front of him and his class just the same. Only the seats and the desks had been polished, rubbed
by use, the walnut trees in the yard had grown taller, and the hop-vine which he had himself
planted wreathed about the windows and up to the roof. What a heart-break it must have been to
the poor man to leave these things, and to hear his sister as she went and came in the room
overhead, packing their trunks. For they were to go on the morrow, to leave the country forever.
All the same he had the courage to go on with the recitation to the end. After the writing, we had
our history lesson; and then the little ones sang the BA, BE, BI, BO, BU. Away at the end of the
room old Hauser had put on his spectacles, and holding his A, B, C book in both hands, he
spelled out the letters with them. He, too, was visibly applying himself; his voice trembled with
emotion, and it was so funny to hear him that we all wanted to laugh and to cry. Ah! I shall
remember that last lesson!
Suddenly the church clock struck noon, then the Angelus. At the same moment the trumpets of
the Prussians who were returning from drill blared under our windows.... M. Hamel rose, very
pale, from his chair. Never had be appeared to me so tall.
Then he turned to the blackboard, took a piece of chalk, and bearing on it with all his strength, he
wrote as large as he could: "VIVE LA FRANCE!"
Then he came to a stop; his head pressed against the wall, and without speaking he signed to us
with his hand:
II
Emerson was asked to write this poem for the dedication of the Battle Monument erected at Concord,
Massachusetts, in 1837, in honor of the minutemen who died there in the American Revolution.
III
ABRAHAM LINCOLN
Four-score and seven years ago, our fathers brought forth upon this continent a new nation,
conceived in liberty and dedicated to the proposition that all men are created equal.
Now we are engaged in a great civil war, testing whether that nation -- or any nation, so
conceived and so dedicated -- can long endure. We are met on a great battlefield of that war. We
have come to dedicate a portion of that field as a final resting place for those who here gave their
lives that that nation might live. It is altogether fitting and proper that we should do this.
But, in a larger sense, we cannot dedicate, we cannot consecrate, we cannot hallow this ground.
The brave men, living and dead, who struggled here have consecrated it far above our poor
power to add or detract.
The world will little note, nor long remember what we say here; but it can never forget what they
did here.
It is for us, the living, rather, to be dedicated here to the unfinished work which they who fought
here have thus far so nobly advanced. It is rather for us to be here dedicated to the great task
remaining before us; that from these honored dead we take increased devotion to that cause for
which they gave the last full measure of devotion; that we here highly resolve that these dead
shall not have died in vain; that this nation, under God, shall have a new birth of freedom, and
that government of the people, by the people, and for the people, shall not perish from the earth.
IV
G. K. CHESTERTON
G. K. Chesterton wrote this essay during the period of growing ultranationalism in Europe which
eventually led to the First World War. He was especially concerned about the attitudes in
England which had led to the South African or Boer War (1899-1902) and which identified
patriotism with imperialism.
The decay of patriotism in England during the last year or two is a serious arid distressing matter.
Only in consequence of such a decay could the current lust of territory be confounded with the
ancient love of country. We may imagine that if there were no such thing as a pair of lovers left
in the world, all the vocabulary of love might without rebuke be transferred to the lowest and
most automatic desire. If no type of chivalrous and purifying passion remained, there would he
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
no one left to say that lust bore none of the marks of love, that lust was rapacious and love
pitiful, that lust was blind and love vigilant, that lust sated itself and love was insatiable. So it is
with the "love of the city," that high and ancient intellectual passion which has been written in
red blood on the same table with the primal passions of our being. On all sides we hear today of
the love of our country, and yet anyone who has literally such a love must be bewildered at the
talk, like a man hearing all men say that the moon shines by day and the sun by night. The
conviction must come to him at last that these men do not realize what the word "love" means,
that they mean by the love of country, not what a mystic might mean by the love of God, but
something of what a child might mean by the love of jam. To one who loves his fatherland, for
instance, our boasted indifference to the ethics of a national war is mere mysterious gibberism. It
is like telling a man that a boy has committed murder, but that he need not mind because it is
only his son. Here clearly the word "love" is used unmeaningly. It is the essence of love to be
sensitive, it is a part of its doom; and anyone who objects to the one must certainly get rid of the
other. This sensitiveness, rising sometimes to an almost morbid sensitiveness, was the mark of
all great lovers like Dante and all great patriots like Chatham. "My country, right or wrong," is a
thing that no patriot would think of saying except in a desperate case. It is like saying, "My
mother, drunk or sober." No doubt if a decent man's mother took to drink he would share her
troubles to the last; but to talk as if he would be in a state of gay indifference as to whether his
mother took to drink or not is certainly not the language of men who know the great mystery.
What we really need for the frustration and overthrow of a deaf and raucous jingoism is a
renascence of the love of the native land. When that comes, all the shrill cries will cease
suddenly. For the first of all the marks of love is seriousness: love will not accept sham bulletins
or the empty victory of words. It will always esteem the most candid counsellor the best. Love is
drawn to truth by the unerring magnetism of agony; it gives no pleasure to the lover to see ten
doctors dancing with vociferous optimism around a death-bed.
We have to ask, then, Why is it that this recent movement in England, which has honestly
appeared to many a renascence of patriotism, seems to its to have none of the marks of patriotism
-- at least of patriotism in its highest form? Why has the adoration of our patriots been given
wholly to qualities and circumstances good in themselves, but comparatively material and trivial:
-- trade, physical force, a skirmish at a remote frontier, a squabble in a remote continent?
Colonies are things to be proud of, but for a country to be only proud of its extremities is like a
man being only proud of his legs. Why is there not a high central intellectual patriotism, a
patriotism of the head and heart of the Empire, and not merely of its fists and its boots? A rude
Athenian sailor may very likely have thought that the glory of Athens lay in rowing with the
right kind of oars, or having a good supply of garlic; but Pericles did not think that this was the
glory of Athens. With us, on the other hand, there is no difference at all between the patriotism
preached by Mr. Chamberlain, and that preached by Mr. Pat Rafferty who sings "What do you
think of the Irish now?" They are both honest, simple-minded, vulgar eulogies upon trivialities
and truisms.
I have, rightly or wrongly, a notion of the chief cause of this pettiness in English patriotism of
today, and I will attempt to expound it. It may be taken generally that a man loves his own stock
and environment, and that he will find something to praise in it; but whether it is the most
praiseworthy thing or no will depend upon the man's enlightenment as to the facts. If the son of
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Thackeray, let us say, were brought up in ignorance of his father's fame and genius, it is not
improbable that be would be proud of the fact that his father was over six feet high. It seems to
me that we, as a nation, are precisely in the position of this hypothetical child of Thackeray's. We
fall back upon gross and frivolous things for our patriotism, for a simple reason. We are the only
people in the world who are not taught in childhood our own literature and our own history.
We are, as a nation, in the truly extraordinary condition of not knowing our own merits. We have
played a great and splendid part in the history of universal thought and sentiment; we have been
among the foremost in that eternal and bloodless battle in which the blows do not slay, but
create. In painting and music we are inferior to many other nations; but in literature, science,
philosophy, and political eloquence we can bold our own with any. But all this vast heritage of
intellectual glory is kept from our schoolboys like a heresy; and they are left to live and die in the
dull and infantile type of patriotism which they learnt from a box of tin soldiers. There is no
harm in the box of tin soldiers; we do not expect children to be equally delighted with a beautiful
box of tin philanthropists. But there is great harm in the fact that the subtler and more civilized
honour of England is not presented so as to keep pace with the expanding mind. A French boy is
taught the glory of Molière as well as that of Turenne; a German boy is taught his own great
national philosophy before he learns the philosophy of antiquity. The result is that, though
French patriotism is often crazy and boastful, though German patriotism is often isolated and
pedantic, they are neither of them merely dull, common, and brutal, as is so often the strange fate
of the nation of Bacon and Locke. It is natural enough, and even righteous enough, under the
circumstances. An Englishman must love England for something; consequently he tends to exalt
commerce or prize-fighting, just as a German might tend to exalt music, or a Flammand to exalt
painting, because he really believes it is the chief merit of his fatherland. It would not be in the
least extraordinary if a claim of eating up provinces and pulling down princes were the chief
boast of a Zulu. The extraordinary thing is, that it is the chief boast of a people who have
Shakespeare, Newton, Burke, and Darwin to boast of.
The peculiar lack of any generosity or delicacy in the current English nationalism appears to
have no other possible origin but in this fact of our unique neglect in education of the study of
the national literature. An Englishman could not be silly enough to despise other nations if once
he knew how much England had done for them. Great men of letters cannot avoid being humane
and universal. The absence of the teaching of English literature in our schools is, when we come
to think of it, an almost amazing phenomenon. It is even more amazing when we listen to the
arguments urged by headmasters and other educational conservatives against the direct teaching
of English. It is said, for example, that a vast amount of English grammar and literature is picked
up in the course of learning Latin and Greek. This is perfectly true, but the topsy-turviness of the
idea never seems to strike them. It is like saying that a baby picks up the art of walking in the
course of learning to hop, or that a Frenchman may successfully be taught German by helping a
Prussian to learn Ashanti. Surely the obvious foundation of all education is the language in
which that education is conveyed; if a boy has only time to learn one thing, he had better learn
that.
We have deliberately neglected this great heritage of high national sentiment. We have made our
public schools the strongest wall against a whisper of the honour of England. And we have had
our punishment in this strange and perverted fact that, while a unifying vision of patriotism can
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
ennoble bands of brutal savages or dingy burghers, and be the best thing in their lives, we, who
are -- the world being judge -- humane, honest, and serious individually, have a patriotism that is
the worst thing in ours. What have we done, and where have we wandered, we that have
produced sages who could have spoken with Socrates and poets who could walk with Dante, that
we should talk as if we have never done anything more intelligent than found colonies and kick
"Diggers"? We are the children of light, and it is we that sit in darkness. If we are judged, it will
not be for the merely intellectual transgression of failing to appreciate other nations, but for the
supreme spiritual transgression of failing to appreciate ourselves.
Objection 1. It would seem that piety is not a special virtue distinct from other virtues. For the
rendering of services and honor to other persons proceeds from love. And this pertains to piety.
Therefore piety is not a distinct virtue from charity.
Objection 2. Furthermore, to render worship to God properly belongs to religion. But piety also
renders worship to God, as St. Augustine says in The City of God, Book X, Chapter 1. Therefore
piety is not distinguished from religion.
Objection 3. Moreover, since piety renders honor and duty to the fatherland, it seems to be the
same as legal justice, which relates to the common good. And legal justice is a general virtue, as
is evident from what the Philosopher says in his Ethics, Book V, Chapters I and 2. Therefore
piety is not a special virtue.
On the contrary is the statement of Cicero that it is a part of justice, as he says in his On
Invention at the end of Book II.
I answer that a virtue is special when it relates to some object under some special aspect. Since,
then, the definition of justice consists in rendering another person his due, whenever a special
aspect of something is due to a person, there must be a special virtue. But a thing is indebted to
its connatural principle of being and government in a special way, and piety relates to this
principle insofar as it pays duty and honor to parents and country, and to whatever is related to
them. Therefore piety is a special virtue.
Reply to Objection 1: just as religion is a kind of testimony of our faith, hope, and charity by
which man is first of all ordered to God, so also piety is a kind of testimony of the love which a
man has to his parents and country.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Reply to Objection 2: God is the principle of our existence and governance in a manner far more
excellent than our father or fatherland. And therefore the virtue of religion by which honor is
rendered to God is a distinct virtue from piety, which renders honor to parents and fatherland.
But things relating to creatures are predicated of God according to excellence and causality, as
Dionysius says in his On the Divine Names, Chapter 1, Lesson 3; whence the worship of God is
called "piety" of a more excellent sort, just as God is also called more excellently "our Father."
SECTION II
The following examples are especially pertinent to Part One, Chapter I. Some of the figures of
speech, however, are treated in Chapter II.
A. Onomatopoeia:
1. For the night-wind has a dismal trick of wandering round and round an old church, and
moaning as it goes; and of trying, with its unseen hand, the windows and the doors; and seeking
out some crevices by which to enter. And when it has got in, as one not finding what it seeks,
whatever that may be, it wails and howls to issue forth again: and not content with stalking
through the aisles, and gliding round and round the pillars, and tempting the deep organ, soars up
to the roof, and strives to rend the rafters: then flings itself despairingly upon the stones below,
and passes, muttering, into the vaults. Anon, it comes up stealthily, and creeps along the walls,
seeming to read, in whispers, the inscriptions sacred to the Dead. At some of these, it breaks out
shrilly, as with laughter; and at others, moans and cries as if it were lamenting. It has a ghostly
sound too, lingering within the altar; where it seems to chaunt, in its wild way, of Wrong and
Murder done and false Gods worshipped, in defiance of the Tables of the Law, which look so
fair and smooth, but are so flawed and broken. Ugh! Heaven preserve us, sitting snugly round the
fire! It has an awful voice, that wind at Midnight, singing in a church!
But, high up in the steeple! There the foul blast roars and whistles! High up in the steeple, where
it is free to come and go through many an airy arch and loophole, and to twist and twine itself
about the giddy stair, and twirl the groaning weathercock, and make the very tower shake and
shiver! High up in the steeple, where the belfry is, and iron rails are ragged with rust, and sheets
of lead and copper, shrivelled by the changing weather, crackle and heave beneath the
unaccustomed tread; and birds stuff shabby nests into corners of old oaken joists and beams; and
dust grows old and gray; and speckled spiders, indolent and fat with long security, swing idly to
and fro in the vibration of the bells, and never loose their hold upon their thread-spun castles in
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
the air, or climb up sailor-like in quick alarm, or drop upon the ground and ply a score of nimble
legs to save one life! High up in the steeple of an old church, far above the light and murmur of
the town and far below the flying clouds that shadow it, is the wild and dreary place at night: and
high up in the steeple of an old church, dwelt the Chimes I tell of.
The musical suggestiveness of poetry is often more subtle than obvious onomatopoeia. Study the
emotional effect of various sound devices in the following:
1. The word mystery commonly today brings to mind a "mystery story" which concerns the
discovery of a murderer, but we are also familiar with its use in the Catechism in the phrase "a
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
mystery of faith." From this latter use we speak of the "mysteries of the Rosary." Similar to this
last use is the term in medieval literature "a mystery play," which was not about a murder, but a
play based on some biblical incident or an incident in the life of some saint. The Latin word
mysterium is from the Greek mysterion referring to one of the secret religious societies into
which Greeks were initiated. The word comes from muein, "to initiate." This in turn is from mu
which means "to keep closed," that is, to close the mouth (or eyes), obviously because the initiate
was required to keep secret the ceremonies of the initiation. Our word mute has the same origin.
Very possibly this word has an onomatopoetic origin, since mu is like a murmuring sound made
with closed lips.
2. The word heresy which means the upholding of some false teaching contrary to the Catholic
faith comes through French and Latin from the Greek hairesis and this from haireo, which
means "to take or choose" (notice the same root in such words as "adhere" or "coherent"). This is
because at the time heresies first arose in early Christianity when Greek was still widely spoken,
they were seen to originate in the desire of some people to select or choose something from
Christian teaching which pleased them and to reject other teachings which they found hard or
unpleasant.
3. Lady, now used to mean any woman referred to in a respectful manner, meant in the older
English a noblewoman who was head of a large household. Hence it still remains a title in
England for the wife of a Lord, and it is used of Our Lady, because she is Queen of Heaven.
Originally, however, it came from the old Anglo-Saxon hlaef-dige which meant a "bread-
kneader" because the woman of the household in early times was the one who baked the bread.
4. Senior and junior are Latin words meaning respectively " elder" and "younger." Sophomore is
from the Greek words sophos, "wise" (see "philosophy," "sophistry," sophisticated") and moros,
"foolish," because a sophomore is half-wise, half-foolish. Freshman is from a Germanic root,
and means a "new man." It is equivalent to another word derived from Latin, "novice," which
also means a "new man." Veteran is from Latin and means "an old man."
5. Anatomy, now used in English to mean the human or animal body and the study of this body,
comes from the Greek words ana and temno, " up" and "cut," because we study the human body
by cutting it up, or dissecting it. The same root is found in atom, for an atom is something that is
"non-cutable," which cannot be divided. This is because what we now call an atom was
originally thought to be the smallest possible particle, although now we know that it is made up
of still smaller ones.
6. Lethal, familiar to us in the phrases "a lethal gas" or a "lethal weapon," meaning something
which kills, comes from a Latin word for death (see also the Greek "River of Lethe," the river of
forgetfulness that flowed through the regions of the dead, and ultimately from a word still found
in Sanskrit, meaning "to dissolve," because death is a kind of dissolution.
7. Panic comes from a Greek -word derived from the name of the god Pan, the god of the woods,
because it was thought that by making strange noises in the forest or at night he was the cause of
sudden fear.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
8. World comes from Anglo-Saxon for a "generation of men," wer meaning man, and uld an age.
(See wer-wolf, a "man-wolf," and elder, "an aged one"). Earth comes from a very ancient word
meaning "the ground." Universe comes from Latin unus, "one," and versus "turned," and
indicates all created things "turned into one." Cosmos is from a Greek word meaning "harmony"
or "order" and indicates the universe as an orderly whole.
9. Matter comes from the Latin materia and this from mater " mother," because things are made
out of matter as a child is from its mother. Form is from the Latin forma, which originally meant
"face," and this from fero, "to carry," because a man wears his face like a mask. Efficient cause is
from Latin ex, "out," and facere, "to make," since an efficient cause produces something out of
the matter. Cause is from Latin causa, and this from cadere, "to fall" or "to happen," because a
cause results in a happening. Final cause is from Latin finis, which is from findo, "to strike,"
because we "put an end" to something by striking or cutting it.
10. Sacrament and sacrifice, and sacred and consecrated, are all from the Latin sacer meaning
something "set apart." It is also connected with our word sane (from Latin for "healthy") and
safe, which all go back to an original word sa meaning "whole." The word holy and whole are
related and also go back to this same word sa through a series of language changes which turned
the sound s into the sound h. The words heal and hale are also connected with it. Thus in the
word sacrament is contained both the notion of something set apart, and of something which
heals us spiritually.
11. Religion is from the Latin re, "back," and ligo, "bind." It has the meaning both of "restrain"
from sin, and "bind back" again or unite to God.
12. Month is from Anglo-Saxon for moon, because a month is measured by the change of the
moon from full-moon to full-moon. But the word moon itself comes from the root ma meaning
"to measure," from which "measure" itself is derived, because the moon is the measurer of time.
1. bark:
a. A sound like that made by a dog (from Anglo-Saxon beor-can, obviously onomatopoetic).
b. The rind or covering of a tree or other plant (from Scandinavian word bark).
c. A three-masted square-rigged sea-vessel, also spelled barque (from French and Latin for a
boat).
2. sound:
a. The sensation received by the organ of hearing (from Latin sonus, a sound).
c. A long and narrow body of water (Anglo-Saxon sund from swimmam, "swim").
3. wax:
1. stone:
b. It is transferred as a verb to mean "to line with stone," or "to hurl stones at," or "to remove
stones from." Thus the actions are named from the thing to which they are applied; the name of
the effect is applied to its efficient cause.
c. It is transferred to something made out of stone, thus we speak of a "memorial stone," and
"stone-work."
d. It is transferred to the effect or final cause when we say that "St. Stephen was stoned," meaning
that he was dead because he had been stoned.
e. It is transferred to formal cause, when we make the adjective "stony" to indicate things which
are hard like stone. Also in England it is applied to a weight or measure equal to about 14 pounds,
because things are sometimes weighed with stones as a measure.
2. show:
a. Originally the word for "see," it was transferred to something to be seen, "a show or spectacle."
Thus it was moved from its effect (seeing) to the thing which produced sight.
c. Then it is frequently transferred to other things connected in various ways with this act of
showing: a show-place (sometimes simply called "a show" or theater), a show-bill (a poster
indicating the time and title of a show), a showgirl (one who acts in a show), showy, the quality
that attracts the eye, etc.
3. light:
b. Transferred to mean the action of lighting a fire, or the fire used to light another.
c. Also to the state produced by light as when we say "It is light now."
d. Also it is transferred to the thing which is lighted as an "electric-light," meaning the bulb which
is illuminated.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Notice that the word light when used to mean something without weight is purely equivocal with this
word, although perhaps in the remote past there was a connection.
C. The following are examples of analogy of improper similarity (see also below under
metaphor as a figure of speech):
2. "I am the true vine, and my Father is the vine-dresser. Every branch in me that bears no fruit
he will take away; and every branch that bears fruit he will cleanse, that it may bear more fruit." -
- Jn. 10:7-9.
1. "Beloved, let us love one another, for love is from God. And everyone who loves is born of
God, and knows God. He who does not love does not know God; for God is love." -- I Jn. 4:7-
8.
2. "Let wives be subject to their husbands as to the Lord; because a husband is head of the wife,
just as Christ is head of the Church, being himself savior of the body. But just as the Church is
subject to Christ, so also let wives be to their husbands in all things." -- Eph. 5:21-24,
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
3. "Therefore, if you, evil as you are, know bow to give good gifts to your children, how much
more will your Father in heaven give good things to those who ask him!" -- Matt:7:11.
1. The following are similes used to convey a single truth in the form of a proverb. Notice bow
the comparison makes the abstract moral truth concrete and easily remembered.
2. Samuel Johnson, the great literary critic, considered the following comparison "perhaps the
best that English poetry can show" because "it has no useless parts, yet affords a striking picture
by itself; it makes the foregoing position better understood, and enables it to take faster hold on
the attention; it assists the apprehension, and elevates the fancy.
3. The following shows a series of metaphors all explaining the same thing, but so arranged as to
give us a progressively deeper and fuller understanding of it:
4. The following lyric is an example of the type of metaphor (often called a "conceit") which
attempts to awaken our imagination by comparisons which are "far-fetched," that is, a
comparison of things which at first sight seem very unalike. Such metaphors are similar to
humor; if they are very light and to the point, they are very effective; but if they miss fire, they
are disastrous.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
5. The following is an example of metaphor used in a rhetorical fashion, to give us a sense of the
need for action:
"And this do, understanding the time, for it is now the hour for us to rise from sleep, because our salvation
is nearer than when we came to believe. The night is far advanced; the day is at hand. Let us therefore lay
aside the works of darkness, and put on the armor of light. Let us walk becomingly as in the day, not in
revelry and drunkenness, not in debauchery and wantonness, not in strife and jealousy. But put on the
Lord Jesus Christ, and as for the flesh, take no thought of its lusts." -- St. Paul, Rom. 13:11-14.
6. The following is also a rhetorical simile used by Socrates in his defense of himself before the
Athenians. He was on trial for his life on the charge of irreligion and of corrupting the youth. He
wishes to make his audience understand the meaning of his mission, which was to awaken the
Athenians to the need to seek for spiritual rather than material goods:
And now, Athenians, I am not going to argue for my own sake, as you may think, but for yours, that you
may not sin against God by condemning me, who am his gift to you. For if you kill me you will not easily
find a successor to me, who, if I may use such a ludicrous figure of speech, am a sort of gadfly, given to
the state by God; and the state is a great and noble horse who is tardy in his motions owing to his very
size, and requires to be stirred into life. I am that gadfly which God has attached to the state, and all day
long and in all places am always fastening upon you, arousing and persuading and reproaching you. You
will not easily find another like, and therefore I would advise you to spare me. I dare say that you may
feel out of temper (like a person who is suddenly awakened from sleep), and you think that you might
easily strike me dead as Anytus advises, and then you would sleep on for the remainder of your lives,
unless God in his care of you sent you another gadfly. . . . -- Socrates, The Apology.
7. The following is also a rhetorical metaphor. Emerson is exhorting scholars to think for
themselves and not to be satisfied with popular opinions and material rewards:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Why should you renounce your right to traverse the starlit deserts of truth, for the premature comforts of
an acre, house, and barn? Truth also has its roof, and bed, and board. Make yourself necessary to the
world, and mankind will give you bread, and if not store of it, yet such as shall not take away your
property in all men's possessions, in all men's affections, in art, in nature, and in hope.
-- Ralph Waldo Emerson, Literary Essays.
B. Irony
2. Jonathan Swift wrote A Modest Proposal "for preventing poor people in Ireland from
becoming a burden to their parents or country, and for making them beneficial to the public." It
is a fierce attack on the indifference of the landlords to the condition of their poor tenants. The
whole is written in an apparently calm and factual style, the climax of which is the "modest
proposal":
I shall now therefore humbly propose my own thoughts, which I hope will not be liable to the least
objection. I have been assured by a very knowing American of my acquaintance in London that a young
healthy child well nursed is at a year old a most delicious, nourishing, and wholesome food, whether
stewed, roasted, baked, or boiled; and I make no doubt that it will equally serve in a fricassee or ragout. I
do therefore humbly offer it to public consideration that of the hundred and twenty thousand children
already computed, twenty thousand be reserved for breed, whereof only one-fourth part be males; which
is more than we allow to sheep, black cattle, or swine. . . . That the remaining hundred thousand may, at a
year old, be offered in sale to persons of quality and fortune through the kingdom; always advising the
mother to let them nurse plentifully in the last month, so as to render them plump and fat for a good table.
A child will make two dishes at an entertainment for friends; and when the family dines alone, the fore or
hind quarter will make a reasonable dish, and seasoned with a little pepper or salt will be very good boiled
on the fourth day, especially in winter. . . . I grant that this food will be somewhat dear, and therefore very
proper for landlords, who as they have already devoured most of the parents, seem to have the best title to
the children.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
C. Parallelism
1. This device is the basis of the poetry of the Hebrews and is found throughout the Bible:
2. Ordinarily in English, parallelism is not used in so obvious a way as by the Hebrews. Note,
however, its less obvious uses in such a prose passage as the following.
Nature is the incarnation of a thought, and turns to thought again, as ice becomes water and gas. The
world is mind precipitated, and the volatile essence is forever escaping again into the state of free thought.
Hence the virtue and pungency of the influence on the mind of natural objects, whether inorganic or
organized. Man imprisoned, man crystallized, man vegetative, speaks to man impersonated, The power
which does not respect quantity, which makes the whole and the particle its equal channel, delegates its
smile to the morning, and distills its essence into every drop of rain. Every moment instructs, and every
object: for wisdom is infused into every form, It has been poured into us as blood; it convulsed us as pain;
it slid into us as pleasure; it enveloped us in dull, melancholy days, or in days of cheerful labor; we did
not guess its essence until after a long time. -- Ralph Waldo Emerson, Nature
D. Antithesis
The following is from Samuel Johnson's comparison of the English poets Pope and Dryden:
Dryden knew more of man in his general nature, and Pope in his local manners. The notions of Dryden
were formed by comprehensive speculation, and those of Pope by minute attention, There is more dignity
in the knowledge of Dryden, and more certainty in that of Pope.
Poetry was not the sole praise of either, for both excelled likewise in prose; but Pope did not
borrow his prose from his predecessor. The style of Dryden is capricious and varied, that of Pope
is cautious and uniform; Dryden obeys the motions of his own mind, Pope constrains his mind to
his own rules of composition. Dryden is sometimes vehement and rapid; Pope is always smooth,
uniform, and gentle. Dryden's page is a natural field, rising into inequalities, and diversified" by
the varied exuberance of abundant vegetation; Pope's is a velvet lawn, shaven by the scythe, and
leveled by the roller.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Of genius, that power which constitutes a poet; that quality without which judgment is cold and
knowledge is inert; that energy which collects, combines, amplifies, and animates -- the
superiority must, with some hesitation, be allowed to Dryden. It is not to be inferred that of this
poetical vigor Pope had only a little, because Dryden had more; for every other writer since
Milton must give place to Pope; and even of Dryden it must be said, that if he has brighter
paragraphs, he has not better poems.
E. Climax:
The following passage is from Cardinal Newman's great sermon, The Second Spring. Notice how
carefully every phrase and word is chosen so as to build up a higher and higher pitch of emotion,
and to avoid breaking this wave of feeling:
My Fathers, my Brothers in the priesthood, I speak from my heart when I declare my conviction, that
there is no one among you here present but, if God so willed, would readily become a martyr for His sake.
I do not say you would wish it; I do not say that the natural will would not pray that the chalice might
pass away; I do not speak of what you can do by any strength of yours; -- but in the strength of God, in
the grace of the Spirit, in the armor of justice, by the consolations and peace of the Church, by the
blessing of the Apostles Peter and Paul, and in the name of Christ, you would do what nature cannot do.
By the intercession of the saints on high, by the penances and good works and the prayers of the people of
God on earth, you would be forcibly borne up as upon the waves of the mighty deep, and carried on out of
yourselves by the fulness of grace, whether nature wished it or no. I do not mean violently, or with
unseemly struggle, but calmly, gracefully, sweetly, joyously, you would mount up and ride forth to the
battle, as on the rush of angel's wings, as your fathers did before you and gained the prize. You, who day
by day offer up the Immaculate Lamb of God, you who hold in your hands the Incarnate Word under the
visible tokens which He has ordained, you who again and again drain the chalice of the Great Victim;
who is to make you fear? what is to startle you? what to seduce you? who is to stop you, whether you are
to suffer or to do, whether to lay the foundations of the Church in tears, or to put the crown upon the work
in jubilation?
F. Anticlimax:
The following is from Thomas De Quincey's humorous essay, Murder as a Fine Art, After
discussing this art at length he ends by saying that be personally has always refrained from
murder, and he gives as his reason the following:
For, if once a man indulges himself in murder, very soon be comes to think little of robbing; and from
robbing he comes next to drinking and Sabbath-breaking and from that to incivility and procrastination.
Once begun upon this downward path, you never know where you are to stop. Many a man has dated his
ruin from some murder or other that perhaps lie thought little of at the time.
H. Hyperbole:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Humility is the luxurious art of reducing ourselves to a point, not to a small thing or a large one, but to a
thing with no size at all, so that all the cosmic things are what they really are -- of immeasurable stature.
That the trees are high and grasses short is a mere accident of our own foot-rules and our own stature. But
to the spirit which has stripped off for a moment its own idle temporal standards the grass is an
everlasting forest, with dragons for denizens; the stones of the road are as incredible mountains piled one
upon the other, the dandelions are like gigantic bonfires illuminating the lands around; and the heathbells
on their stalks are like planets hung in heaven each higher than the other. Between one stake of a paling,
and another there are new and terrible landscapes; here a desert, with nothing but one misshapen rock;
here a miraculous forest, of which all the trees flower above the head with the lines of sunset; here, again,
a sea full of monsters that Dante would not have dared to dream. These are the visions of him, who, like
the child in the fairy tales, is not afraid to be small. Meanwhile, the sage whose faith is in magnitude and
ambition is, like a giant, becoming larger and larger, which only means that the stars are becoming
smaller and smaller. World after world falls from him into insignificance; the whole passionate and
intricate life of common things becomes as lost to him as is the life of the infusoria to a man without a
microscope. He rises always through desolate eternities. He may find now systems, and forget them; he
may discover fresh universes, and learn to despise them. But the towering and tropical vision of things as
they really are -- the gigantic daisies, the heaven-consuming dandelions, the great Odyssey of strange-
coloured oceans and strange-shaped trees, of dust like the wreck of temples, and thistledown like the ruin
of stars -- all this colossal vision shall perish with the last of the humble.
I. Litotes
1. In Shakespeare's Romeo and Juliet is a scene in which Mercuric has just been fatally
wounded in a duel:
Mercutio: No. 'Tis not so deep as a well, nor so wide as a church-door; but 'tis enough, 'twill
serve: ask for me tomorrow, and you shall find me a grave man. . . .
After the Storm:* [*Reprinted with the kind permission of the author and Charles Scribe's
Sons, from The Short Stories of Ernest Hemingway.]
It wasn't about anything, something about making punch, and then we started fighting and I
slipped and lie bad me down kneeling on my chest and choking me with both hands like he was
trying to kill me and all the time I was trying to get the knife out of my pocket to cut him loose.
Everybody was too drunk to pull him off me, lie was choking me and hammering my head on the
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
floor and I got the knife out and opened it up; and I cut the muscle right across his arm and he let
go of me. He couldn't have held on if he wanted to. Then he rolled and hung onto that arm and
started to cry and I said: "What the hell you want to choke me for?" I'd have killed him. I
couldn't swallow for a week. He hurt my throat bad.
J. Personification:
1.
2.
Do you not think that you should leave the city? If I saw that I was even undeservedly so
suspected and hated by my fellow citizens, I would rather flee from their sight than be gazed at by
the hostile eyes of everyone. And do you, who, from the consciousness of your wickedness, know
that the hatred of of all men is just and has been long due to you, hesitate to avoid the sight and
presence of those men whose minds and senses you offend? If your parents feared and hated you,
and if you could by no means pacify them, you would, I think, depart somewhere out of their
sight. Now, your Country, which is the common parent of all of us, hates and fears you, and has
no other opinion of you than that you are meditating her murder; and will you neither feel awe of
her authority, nor deference for her judgment, nor fear of her power?
And she, O Catiline, thus pleads with you, and after a manner silently speaks to you:
"There has now for many years been no crime committed but by you; no atrocity has
taken place without you; you alone unpunished and unquestioned have murdered the
citizens, have harassed and plundered the allies; you alone have had power not only to
neglect all laws and investigations, but to overthrow and break through them. Your
former actions, though they ought not to have been borne, yet I did bear as well as I
could; but now that I shall be wholly occupied with fear of you alone, that at every sound
I should dread Catiline, that no design should seem possible to be entertained against me
which does not proceed from your wickedness, this is no longer endurable. Depart, then,
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
and deliver me from this fear; that, if it be a just one, I may not be destroyed; if an
imaginary one, that at last I may at least cease to fear." -- Cicero, First Oration against
Catiline
K. Apostrophe:
1.
"Jerusalem, Jerusalem! thou who killest the prophets, and stonest those who are sent to thee! How
often would I have gathered thy children together, as a hen gathers her young under wings, but
thou wouldst not! Behold, you house is left to you desolate. For I say to you, you shall not see me
henceforth until you shall say, 'Blessed is he who comes in the name of the Lord!"' -- Matt. 23:27-
29.
SECTION III
Throughout Part One the categories are used both to explain grammatical relations and as a help
to the correct definition of technical terms. The following materials may be of assistance in the
study of the categories.
In using the following tables the student should recall that, strictly speaking, only natural, real
entities can be properly classified in the categories. Mental relations and artificial numbers, for
example, are included in these tables only reductively, as bearing a resemblance to the natural
and real entities with which they are grouped, since art imitates nature. These tables are based on
the writings of St. Thomas Aquinas and his noted follower John of St. Thomas. The table of
artificial things was suggested by the classification given by Hugh of St. Victor and St.
Bonaventure.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
GRAPHICAL TABLES
A. DESCRIPTIVE DEFINITIONS
1. Poetic description:
a.
2. Rhetorical description:
a. The following is taken from a speech for the prosecution given by Daniel Webster in a well-known
murder trial:
An aged man, without an enemy in the world, in his own house and in his own bed, is made the victim of
a butcherly murder, for mere pay. Truly, here is a new lesson for painters and poets. Whoever shall
hereafter draw the portrait of murder, if be will show it as it has been exhibited in an example, where
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
such example was last to have been looked for, in the very bosom of our New England society, let him
not give it the grim visage of Moloch, the brow knitted by revenge, the face black with settled hate, and
the bloodshot eye emitting livid fires of malice. Let him draw, rather, a decorous, smoothfaced,
bloodless demon; a picture in repose, rather than in action; not so much an example of human nature in
its depravity and in its paroxysms of crime, as an infernal nature, a fiend, in the ordinary display and
development of his character.
The deed was executed with a degree of self-possession and steadiness equal to the wickedness
with which it was planned. The circumstances, now clearly in evidence, spread out the whole
scene before us. Deep sleep has fallen on the destined victim and all beneath his roof. A healthful
old man, to whom sleep was sweet, the first sound slumbers of the night held in their soft but
strong embrace. The assassin enters, through the window already prepared, into an unoccupied
apartment. With noiseless feet he paces the lonely hall, a hall lighted by the moon; he winds up
the ascent of stairs and reaches the door of the chamber. Of this, he moves the lock, by soft and
continued pressure, till it turns on its hinges without noise; and he enters and beholds his victim
before him. The room was uncommonly open to the admission of light. The face of the innocent
sleeper was turned from the murderer, and the beams of the moon, resting on the gray locks of
his aged temple, showed him where to strike. The fatal blow is given; and the victim passes,
without a struggle or a motion, from the repose of sleep to the repose of death! It is the assassin's
purpose to make sure work; and he yet plies the dagger, though it was obvious that life bad been
destroyed by the blow of the bludgeon. He even raises the aged arm, that he may not fail in his
aim at the heart, and replaces it over the wounds of the poniard! To finish the picture, he explores
the wrist for the pulse! He feels for it and ascertains that it beats no longer! It is accomplished.
The deed is done. He retreats, retraces his steps to the window, passes out through it as he came
in and escapes. He has done the murder -- no eye has seen him, no ear has heard him. The secret
is his own, and it is safe! -- Daniel Webster, "Exordium in the Knapp Murder Case."
B. SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS
General Description. -- Length, 10 inches. Upper parts, brownish-gray; under parts, white and
gray. Bill, shorter than head; wings, long and rounded; tail, longer than wing, rounded, the
feathers moderately broad with rounded tips.
Color. -- Above, plain brownish gray; wings and tail, dull blackish-slate with pale slate-gray
edgings, these broadest on secondaries (especially the terminal portion, where sometimes
inclining to white); middle and greater wing-coverts, narrowly tipped with dull white or grayish-
white, forming two narrow bands (these indistinct in worn plumage); primary coverts, white
usually with a subterminal spot or streak of dusky; base of primaries, white, this most extended
on the two innermost, where occupying at least basal half of both webs, often much more, that on
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
the longer quills sometimes entirely concealed by overlying primary coverts; outermost tail-
feather, white, sometimes with a trace of dusky or grayish on outer web; second, with outer web
mostly blackish, the inner web mostly white; third, blackish or dusky, was about half of the
terminal and basal portions white; a very indistinct stripe over eye of pale grey; eyelids, grayish-
white; lores, dusky; sides of bead, grayish, indistinctly streaked with whitish; space below the
eyes and checks, dull white, usually faintly barred or transversely flecked with grayish or dusky;
chin and throat, dull white, margined along each side by a dusky streak; chest and sides of breast,
pale smoke-gray, passing into a more buffy hue on sides and flanks; the under tail-coverts, pale
buff; abdomen and center of breast, white; bill, black.
Nest and Eggs. -- Nest: Composed of twigs, grasses and weeds, lined with fine rootlets, moss,
and sometimes cotton; placed in many different locations but usually in a deep bramble thicket
or hedge; as a rule they are located within ten feet of the ground, never on it, and have been seen
built fifty feet above the earth. Eggs: 4 to 6, bluish-green heavily freckled with several shades of
brown.
Distribution. -- Eastern United States; northward regularly (but locally), to Maryland, southern
Ohio, southern half of Indiana and Illinois, Missouri, etc., irregularly to Massachusetts,
southeastern New York (Long Island, etc.), New Jersey, Pennsylvania, northern Indiana and
Illinois, and Iowa, sporadically to Maine, Ontario, southern Wisconsin (breeding), and southern
Minnesota; breeding and resident throughout its range, except where occurring accidentally;
southward to southern Florida and along the Gulf to eastern Texas, and to the Bahamas;
introduced into Bermuda (1893).
Habits. -- The Mockingbird stands unrivaled. He is the king of song. This is a trite saying, but
how much it really means can be known only to those who have heard this most gifted singer
uncaged and at his best in the lowlands of the Southern States. He equals and even excels the
whole feathered choir. He improves upon most of the notes he reproduces, adding also to his
varied repertoire the crowing of chanticleer, the cackling of the hen, the barking of the house
dog, the squeaking of the unoiled wheel barrow, the postman's whistle, the plaints of young
chickens and turkeys and those of young wild birds, not neglecting to mimic those of his own
offspring. He even imitates man's musical inventions. Elizabeth and John Grinnell assert that a
Mockingbird was attracted to a phonograph on the lawn where, apparently he listened and took
mental notes of the performance, giving the next day, a week later, or at midnight an
entertainment of his own and then repeating it with the exact phonograph ring. Even the notes of
the piano have been reproduced in some cases and the bird's vocalization simulates the lightning
changes of the kaleidoscope.
The Mocker is more or less a buffoon, but those who look upon him only as an imitator or clown
have much to learn of his wonderful originality. His own song is heard at its best at the height of
the love season, when the singer flutters into the air from some tall tree-top and improvises his
music, pouring out all the power and energy of his being in such an ecstacy of song that,
exhausting his strength in the supreme effort, he slowly floats on quivering, beating pinions
down through the bloom-covered branches until, his fervor spent, he sinks to the ground below.
His expanded wings and tail flashing white in the sunlight and the buoyancy of his action appeal
to the eye as his music captivates the ear. On moonlit nights at this season the inspired singer
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
launches himself far into the air, filling the silvery spaces of the night with the exquisite swells
and trills, liquid and sweet, of his unparalleled melody. The son, rises and falls as the powers of
the singer wax and wane, and so he serenades his mate throughout the livelong night. One such
singer wins others to emulation and, as the chorus grows, little birds of the field and orchard
wake just enough to join briefly in the swelling tide of avian melody.
The Mockingbird seldom holds himself aloof from mankind, but often makes himself at home in
the dooryard, sits on the chimney top and, like the Robin in the North, "knows all the folks." The
negroes close the shutters of their cabins at night, but they say that the Mocker sings down the
chimney." Often the nest is placed in shrub or hedge close by the house; as soon as the young are
hatched the parents take pains to proclaim their whereabouts that all may, know. Therefore, the
young, which are in demand as cage birds, frequently are taken and sold into captivity.
The Mockingbird has many traits that endear it to all. It is brave and devoted, attacking birds
twice its size, dogs, cats, and even man himself in defense of his young. Its cries of alarm give
warning to all other birds nearby. When kindly treated it may even come in at the door or
window. Thus it has won for itself a high place in the regard and affection of the Southern
people.
-- Edward Howe Forbush in Birds of America, edited by T. G. Pearson.
a. Grammar:
The following are definitions of a verb given by a number of different grammars. Which is best?
See also the definitions given at the end of each chapter in this book.
b. Geometry:
(1) A circle is a line all points of which are equidistant from a fixed point called the center.
(2) A triangle is a three-sided closed plane figure.
(3) A parallelogram is a closed plane figure whose sides are straight lines and whose opposite sides are
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
parallel.
(4) A rectangle is a parallelogram with one right angle.
c. Algebra:
d. Biology:
In the maintenance of its life, every living thing exhibits a phenomenon which consists essentially in the
breaking down of complex substances into simpler ones, with consequent release of energy. This
phenomenon has been called "dissimilation" in contrast to "assimilation" in which simple substances are
absorbed and built up into the organism in the form of substances of greater complexity and higher
energy content. Although this dissimilation affects different materials in different species, it very
commonly involves the breaking down, by oxidation, of carbohydrates and fats, the end-products being
carbon dioxide and water. The dissimilation process thus involves an exchange of gases between the
organism and its environment, oxygen being absorbed and carbon dioxide evolved. This exchange of
gases, so characteristic in animals, is equally characteristic of the vast majority of plants. Hence the term
"respiration," used to denote this gaseous exchange and the processes of which it forms a part, is
equally applicable to animals and plants.
Although the term respiration at first referred to the exchange of gases between the organism and
its environment, so that, in the case of animals, it was synonymous with the term breathing, it has
for many years now been more usual to regard respiration as involving the whole of the
dissimilation process. The leading workers of the second half of the nineteenth century, such as
Sachs, Pfeffer and Palladin, who were responsible for the modern conception of respiration, all
gave the word respiration this wider meaning, and in this book respiration in plants is taken to
include all the phenomena of dissimilation, the characteristics of which are the breaking down of
complex substances into simpler ones with a consequent release of energy.
-- W. Stiles and W. Leach, Respiration in Plants * [* Reprinted by permission of Methuen
and Company, Limited.]
e. Physical Science:
(1) To be strictly accurate, an element is a substance, all of whose atoms contain the same number of
protons. However, until you study more about the structure of atoms it will be useful and accurate to
think of an element as a simple substance which cannot be broken up into any simpler substances by
ordinary chemical means. When a chemist attempts the analysis of an element such as iron, be finds
that it is made up entirely of iron. He has reached the limits of chemical analysis.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
(2) What causes lightning? Scientists do not know certainly what causes lightning. The following
theory is as good as any,
When a liquid is broken up into a spray, friction charges the larger droplets positively and the
smaller ones negatively. In a thundercloud there are huge upward winds with velocities as great
as 200 miles per hour. These winds break up raindrops and carry the smaller, negatively charged
drops to the top of the cloud, while the larger, positively charged ones remain behind. Often the
charges jump from one part of the cloud to another in a lightning stroke. Sometimes a wind
carries away the minus-charged top of the cloud. Then the positively charged remainder is likely
to be discharged to the earth.
What causes thunder? A lightning stroke heats the air through which it passes, and the air
expands suddenly, causing thunder. -- O. H. Blackwood, W. B. Herron, and W. C. Kelly, High
School Physics (1951)* [* This and the following quotation are reprinted by permission of the
authors and Ginn and Company, Boston.]
You have learned that a force is a push or pull and that you must exert a force to lift a market
basket. You have found also that a force is required to overcome friction when you move an
object. Now you will see how a force can do work in lifting a body or in overcoming a friction.
The word work is one of the oldest in the English language. It often means effort, perhaps
unpleasant, for which you get paid. Thus we say that a golf caddy "works" when he stands idly
by, watching a player hit a ball. A watchman "works" as he sits at a railroad crossing. You
"work" a problem in algebra. In physics we try to give only one meaning to every word; it is
important that you know just what physicists mean by work.
When you carry a suitcase upstairs, you do work: for you exert an upward force on the suitcase,
and you lift it upward. A horse does work in pulling a plow over a field, for lie exerts a forward
force which moves the plow forward. To do work on a body, you must exert a force on it and
must move it in the direction of the force.
We define work as the product of the force exerted on a body times the distance that the body
moves in the direction of the force.
f. Christian Doctrine:
(2) Baptism is the sacrament that gives our souls the new life of sanctifying grace by which we become
children of God and heirs of heaven. The priest is the usual minister of baptism but if there is danger
that someone will die without baptism, anyone may and should baptize. It is given by pouring ordinary
water on the forehead of the person to be baptized, saving while pouring it: "I baptize thee in the name
of the Father, and of the Son, and of the Holy Ghost."
(3) The Church is the congregation of all baptized persons united in the same true faith, the same
sacrifice, and the same sacraments, under the authority of the Sovereign Pontiff and the bishops in
communion with him, founded by Jesus Christ to bring all men to eternal salvation.
(4) A mortal sin is a grievous offense against the law of God, which deprives the sinner of sanctifying
grace, consisting in a thought, desire, word, action, or omission which is seriously wrong, of whose evil
the sinner is mindful at the time of acting, and to which he fully consents.
4. Verbs:
premises of an argument.
IV. OUTLINING
St. Thomas Aquinas, O.P., in his commentaries gives excellent examples of how to outline a
work in preparation to explaining it. The following explanation of the Lord's Prayer shows how
his method proceeds:
The Lord's Prayer is most perfect, because, as Augustine says, "If we pray rightly and fittingly, we can say
nothing else but what is contained in this prayer of our Lord." For since prayer interprets our desires, as
it were, before God, then alone is it right to ask for something in our prayers when it is right that we
should desire it. Now in the Lord's Prayer not only do we ask for all that we may rightly desire, but also
in the order wherein we ought to desire them, so that this prayer not only teaches us to ask, but also
directs all our affections.
Thus it is evident that the first thing to be the object of our desire is the end, and afterwards
whatever is directed to the end. Now our end is God towards whom our affections tend in two
ways: first, by our willing the glory of God, secondly, by willing to enjoy his glory. The first
belongs to the love whereby we love God in himself, while the second belongs to the love
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
whereby we love ourselves in God. Wherefore the first petition is expressed thus: Hallowed be
thy Name, and the second thus: Thy kingdom come, by which we ask to come to the glory of the
kingdom.
To this same end a thing directs us in two ways: in one way, by its very nature; in another way,
accidentally. Of its very nature the good which is useful for an end directs us to that end. Now a
thing is useful in two ways to that end which is beatitude: in one way, directly and principally,
according to the merit whereby we merit beatitude by obeying God, and in this respect we ask:
Thy will be done on earth as it is in heaven; in another way instrumentally, and, as it were,
helping us to merit, and in this respect we say: Give us this day our daily bread, whether we
understand this of the sacramental Bread, the daily use of which is profitable to man, and in
which all the other sacraments are contained, or of the bread of the body, so that it denotes all
sufficiency of good, as Augustine says, since the Eucharist is the chief sacrament, and bread is
the chief food: thus in the gospel of Matthew we read, supersubstantial, i.e., principal, as Jerome
expounds it.
We are directed to beatitude accidentally by the removal of obstacles. Now there are three
obstacles to our attainment of beatitude. First, there is sin, which directly excludes a man from
the kingdom, according to I Cor. 6:9-10: "Neither fornicators, nor idolaters, etc., shall possess
the kingdom of God"; and to this refer the words, Forgive us our trespasses. Secondly, there is
temptation, which hinders us from keeping God's will, and to this we refer when we say: And
lead us not into temptation, whereby we do not ask not to be tempted, but not to be conquered by
temptation, which is to be led into temptation. Thirdly, there is the present penal state which is a
kind of obstacle to a sufficiency of life, and to this we refer in the words, Deliver us from evil."
-- Summa Theologiae,II-II, q. 83, a. 9*
[*Reprinted from the Summa Theologica, Benziger Bros. Inc., publishers and copyright owners.]
Thesis: The seven petitions of the Lord's Prayer include all the
things we rightly desire and in the right order of importance.
I. The thing which we must desire above all things is God, who
is our end
and our beatitude.
1. We must first desire that God should be glorified in
himself, and
hence we pray: "Our Father who art in heaven, hallowed be
thy name."
2. We must desire that God should be glorified in us, that is,
that
we should enjoy his glory; and hence next we pray: "thy
Kingdom come."
II. Whatever else we desire we must desire as a means useful to
achieve
our end, which is God, our beatitude.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The following sample analyses are very schematic and are only intended to illustrate how it is
possible to approach a literary work from an organic point of view, using the principles discussed
in Part one. A complete critical analysis of any work would be much more detailed. In particular,
the treatment of the matter of each work is only briefly indicated.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
(Object of imitation)
The Action:
The principal form of a drama which unifies the entire poetic work is its action or plot:
Jesus Christ, the God-man, offers himself to his heavenly Father as a sacrifice for the sins
of the whole world to obtain the rebirth and glory of his Church.
This is an action with a tragic catharsis, since joy is achieved only through Christ's heroic
sacrifice of himself. It begins with sorrow, yearning, and hope (Confiteor, Kyrie, Gloria, and
Collects), then passes through the act of supreme sacrifice and victory (Offertory and Canon) in
which there is a reversal and a discovery, since it is by humbling himself that Christ triumphs
and by death that lie is proved to be God. Finally, it ends in the perfect jaw of victory and
reunion. Furthermore, it is an action of the most sublime magnitude, since it involves the entire
universe and is the climax and summary of all history.
In the Holy Sacrifice, however, there is also something of the comic catharsis, since in it there is
an ironic exposure of human vanity (see the parable of the supper, Lk. 14:15-24) because all men
of every condition are invited to the banquet of the King who has appeared in the form of a slave
(Phil. 2:7). The Eucharist is a rejoicing and a festival of common human fellowship as well as a
heroic tragedy.
Beginning: Jesus Christ, the God-man, comes into the world and reveals himself as our
Redeemer. This is shown in the Introit, Kyrie, Gloria, and Collects in which mankind prays for
the coming of the Saviour and celebrates his presence.
Middle:
Episode I: Jesus Christ announces the Truth or Gospel which he has come to witness:
1. The Lesson, Epistle, Gradual, Alleluia or Tract are a less perfect presentation of truth by the
forerunners of Christ (prophets and apostles).
2. Gospel, Sermon, Creed are the perfect teaching of Christ, faithfully received by the Church.
Episode II (climax and reversal): Jesus Christ offers himself on the cross in proof of the Truth,
rises and ascends to heaven as King of the Universe.
2. Canon: in which Christ (and the whole Church militant and triumphant) offers himself on
the cross, rises, and ascends to his heavenly throne.
End: Christ in glory invites his Church to share that glory in a heavenly banquet, received here
below as a pledge.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
1.Our Father, Fraction, and Communion Prayers are a petition for the coming of the Kingdom
and for a share in it.
2. The Communion, or union of the Church with Christ at the heavenly wedding-feast.
3. Post-Communion Prayers, Blessing, Last Gospel are the thanksgiving and petition for the
final eternal fulfillment.
Characters:
1. The chief figure is Jesus Christ represented through the priest. He is a divine hero.
flow then does he have the moral flaw expected in a tragic hero? He has no
personal sin or defect, but he has assumed human nature which itself is under the
curse of sin, and hence he appears a criminal and suffers in our place. Because of
his perfect goodness we pity his sufferings, and because we know that he suffers
for our sins, we fear the punishment which we have deserved, not he. Hence the
tragic catharsis through pity and fear is achieved. Our Lord's character is perfectly
appropriate to his role as Redeemer and King. It is lifelike because he is so
entirely human in his thoughts and feelings, and it is utterly consistent, because in
the Mass we see him unhesitatingly carry out the will of his Father.
2. The secondary characters are all the members of the Church forming Christ's
Mystical Body: the angels, the saints in heaven, the souls in purgatory, and all
classes of men, women, and children. They are represented through the ministers
of the Mass (deacon, subdeacon, acolytes) and by the congregation itself. The
unseen angels and saints and the dead are commemorated in words and also by
the statues and paintings, and by the choir which expresses their sentiments.
These secondary characters are appropriate, lifelike, and consistent because they
include representatives of the entire range of humanity. Each of us can find some
saint, for example, with whom we can identify ourself, and some sinner who has
met the fate which would be ours except for the grace of God. The function of
these secondary characters is to manifest the greatness of Christ by their special
likeness to him, by their proof of his grace and forgiveness, or by the defeat of
their opposition to him.
Thus we see that only our Lord is a hero capable of the sublime action of the
Redemption.
Thought:
In the text of the Mass we find the thought of God himself expressed through passages of
Scripture, less perfectly formulated in the psalms, lessons and epistle, and most perfectly
formulated in the Gospel. We also find the responding thought of the Church in the Collects and
other Prayers, in the Sermon and Creed, and in the Canon of the Mass itself. This thought of the
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Church grows out of the Scriptures and is a commentary and answer to it. All of the greatest
mysteries of the faith are expressed in the Mass, but most especially the doctrine of the Trinity
(Gloria, Creed, Canon, and the ever recurrent doxologies), the Incarnation and Redemption (the
conclusion of every prayer, the Gospel, the Canon, and the constant use of the sign of the cross),
and the theological virtues of faith, hope, and charity. Along with this there is constant emphasis
on man's duty of contrition, humility, obedience, and profound reverence of his Creator and
Redeemer.
The thought of the Latin rite liturgy is characterized by its great simplicity, and its emphasis on
the idea of religion, man's debt in justice to worship God and to return all things to him. The
Romans, even when still pagans, had a profound sense of justice, piety, religion, and this is
reflected in the Latin rite. It may be compared to the Eastern rites which express much more
complicated statements of dogma, a reflection of the theological studies and controversies that
took place in the East in the earlier days of the Church.
The Latin rite does not impede the action by too much talk. The thought is directly subordinated
to what is being done. Read the Canon and see how businesslike it is.
THE MATTER
(Means of imitation)
The Mass is presented dramatically (manner) but in a symbolic and sacramental fashion, not
literally.
Words:
In studying the diction of the Mass the three following points should be emphasized:
These three characteristics make the Mass dramatically effective because they are appropriate to
the grandeur of the action, to the historical character of Jesus Christ who as a Jew and the
Messias spoke in the biblical language, to the character of the Church which is centered in Rome,
and to the thought which is sublime and yet given to the common people.
Under this heading we should study the Gregorian Chant, and also the rhythm of the text of the
Mass, especially considering:
1. Why is the Chant especially the music of prayer? Consider its simplicity, freedom
from all technical display or sensual effects; its use of the modes which give to
the melody an effect of incompleteness and dependence on the words, its free-
rhythm which is less sensual and also dependent on the Words; and its spiritual
emotion.
2. The text has the rhythm of Hebrew verse and prose based on parallelism and the
linkage of one phrase to another, With the use of antiphons and refrains. The
Latin text has the rhythm of periodic structure. Notice also the "circular"
arrangement of the parts of the Canon around the Consecration.
Spectacle:
We should consider the visual beauty both of the human participants and of the place and sacred
articles:
1. Actions: The Church excludes actual dancing from her liturgy as too inclined to
the frivolous or sensual, and she permits only men to take part in the action within
the sanctuary for the same reason. Three points needs to be considered especially:
a. The processions which express the desire of men to come to God and to bring
him as King into the world. The Introit, the Gradual leading up to the Gospel, the
Offertory, the Communion, and the Last Gospel at a Solemn Mass each involve a
procession. What is the significance of each?
b. The ministering. In a Solemn Mass, and especially a Pontifical Mass, the
celebrant carries out only the principal action. In everything else he is served by
the ministers. The purpose of this is to indicate that God makes use of his
creatures in carrying out all his works, but he alone can bring them to ultimate
success. Notice how this etiquette (Emily Post once advised attendance at Mass as
a perfect lesson in good manners) is derived from the ritual of a court, in which
the king is given honor in all things.
c. The gestures. Study the use of genuflections, how kisses (the kiss of peace, and
the kissing of sacred objects), folded hands, the gesture of prayer with arms
raised, the sign of the Cross used both as a blessing and as pointing out a sacred
object which has been mentioned in Word, the incensing, etc. Each of these is
marked by humility, dignity, sobriety, and moderation, and by an air of vital joy
and recollection.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
By a study of these actions we come to see that the action of the Mass is portrayed
visually by a wonderfully expressive dance, but a dance which is free of a fixed
rhythm and all sensuality, just it's the music is free of these elements.
2. Sacred articles:
a. The vestments combine a symbolism taken from the Old Testament (study the
descriptions in Exodus, in the prayers for vesting and in the rites of Ordination
and Episcopal Consecration) with the styles of the late Roman Empire. Notice
that when properly made they are free of all suggestions of effeminacy or vanity,
but are dignified, rich, and noble. They signify the "internal garments of the heart"
(see St. Gregory's Pastoral Rule for an explanation of their symbolism), that is,
the various virtues of Christ which his representatives ought to share.
b. The sacred vessels, the altar and its fittings, the processional cross, etc. Each
of these has a definite function which it must be made to serve properly. Each also
ought to lend dignity, beauty, and symbolism to the action of which it is an
instrument. For example, does the chalice suggest the Precious Blood of the
sacrifice which it is intended to hold? Does the altar fittingly act as the place of
sacrifice, the table of the heavenly banquet, and the symbol of Christ all in one?
c. The church represents the Church Militant, the Church triumphant (heaven),
and the entire universe as the Kingdom of God. We need to study its various parts
to see whether each performs its function and carries out its symbolism. Does the
entrance suggest the holiness of the place? Does the body of the Church suggest
the unity and participation of the faithful? Does the sanctuary suggest a Holy of
Holies and the heavenly sanctuary? Is it properly arranged and of sufficient size
for the liturgical action? Do the statues and paintings fittingly bring to mind the
unseen presences of the saints and angels?
The Action: A noble warrior is tempted by the honors given him by his king to kill that
king, usurp the throne, and maintain himself by further murders which finally provoke a
rebellion and his own destruction.
Beginning: Macbeth, rewarded by King Duncan for his valor in battle, is tempted by ambition,
the powers of hell, and his own wife to usurp the throne, and yields to the temptation. ACT I
Scenes 5-7: Lady Macbeth receives the news, Duncan and Macbeth arrive, and
Macbeth and his Lady prepare the plot. It is only at this point that we are sure that
Macbeth has really given into the temptation and will carry through his crime.
Middle:
Scene 1: Banquo tries to check Macbeth. Macbeth's vision of the dagger, a second
warning, and foreshadowing of the madness that may follow his crime.
Scene 2: The murder carried out.
Scenes 3-4: Discovery of the murder, flight of Malcolm and Donalbain, Duncan's
sons. Macbeth will succeed to the throne.
Scene 1: Macbeth says goodby to Banquo and then arranges his murder.
Scenes 2-4: The fear of Macbeth and Lady Macbeth, then the murder with the
escape of Fleance (Banquo's son), and the banquet scene in which Macbeth
betrays his guilt.
Scenes 5-6: The witches prepare for Macbeth's downfall and talk is going on in
the court that Macduff is in England to prepare the return of the rightful heir.
It is in Scenes 2-4 that the climax, discovery, and reversal take place. Fleance's
escape insures that Banquo's heirs will succeed to the throne, while Macbeth's
betrayal of himself (discovery) at the banquet scene marks the beginning of his
public downfall, since now the lords will not hesitate to rebel against him, seeing
that he is losing his grip.
Scene 1: Macbeth comes again to the witches who drive him to desperation by
showing that Banquo's line will succeed and by giving him false assurances that
he cannot be killed. Word comes that Macduff has fled, and Macbeth sends to kill
Macduff's wife, a final act of cruelty that insures he will receive no mercy from
the rebel lords.
Scenes 2-3: The murder of Lady Macduff and son is carried out, while in England
Macduff gains the consent of Malcom, the rightful heir, to head the rebellion, and
to become a good king like St. Edward of England. The arrival of news of the
murder of his wife and son clinches their resolution.
End: Macbeth, driven on by his illusion of invulnerability, deserted by all and his wife dead, in
final impenitence and despair is killed by Macduff, and Malcolm the rightful heir regains the
throne which will someday pass to Banquo's line.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Scenes 1-5: While the army of restoration is advancing on the castle with the ruse
of carrying the branches of Birnam wood, Lady Macbeth goes mad and dies.
Macbeth left alone is in the state of despair, yet relies on the witches' promise of
victory, when word comes that the "wood is marching."
Scenes 6-8: Still relying on the last promise of invulnerability Macbeth enters the
fight, then learns that Macduff was "not born of woman." He is killed off-stage,
and his head brought in as the new king commemorates his victory by creating his
generals new Earls of Scotland.
Catharsis: The difficulty of this plot was to make Macbeth seem sympathetic and therefore to
make him arouse our pity, since be is to die unrepentant and completely guilty. Hence it is made
very clear that his yielding to dreadful temptation was something very human, since this
temptation is strengthened by the devil (the witches) and by the counsel of his wife. Thus we feel
pity for a man so blinded, and fear when we see how the delusions of sin lead from one crime to
another and finally to despair and damnation. Macbeth is not saved, and the serenity we feel at
the end of the play comes from our relief to see that tyranny produces inevitable opposition and
the rising of the forces of justice to restore order. Our sympathy for Macduff and Malcolm, who
are made very human, assists in confirming this effect.
Macbeth is thus different than most tragedies in that it deals with a hero who is finally damned. It
would be a mistake to think that his crime is excused by the force of temptation. In the play it is
in no way excused, but merely made to appear something we might ourselves do without God's
grace, that is, something pitiable and fearful.
Characters:
1. Macbeth is shown at the beginning as a noble warrior who would make a good
king, who is naturally tempted when he finds himself rising in honor above the
other lords. His flaw of ambition, however, blinds him, so as to make him the
ready victim of the delusive temptation from the witches, and the passionate
rashness of his wife. On the other hand, his soliloquies show him a man who
would ordinarily be very prudent and cautious in action, and his relations both
with Banquo and Lady Macbeth show that ordinarily he would have been a man
of tender friendship and love.
2. The other characters seem developed to reflect the various aspects of Macbeth's
own character:
a. Banquo (prudent, cautious), and Duncan (noble, generous), who have admired
Macbeth, show us the kind of man he appeared at his best, like them. St. Edward
is referred to as showing the ideal of kingship.
b. The witches and Lady Macbeth show us the evil side of Macbeth's character.
Lady Macbeth corresponds to his emotions or passions. She is a driving force at
the beginning of the play, but then goes mad, and leaves him in cold despair, just
as passion drives man to sin, then torments him by remorse, and finally leaves the
sinner in emptiness. The witches are sin itself, which blinds the mind by vain
promises which lead the sinner deeper and deeper into damnation.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
c. The other characters represent the sanity of the social order. There is the
interesting contrast between the high-spirited young Siward, and the hesitating,
inexperienced Malcolm, who must become king. Macduff, Ross, and the other
generals are presented as manly, human, sympathetic people.
d. The Porter and Old Man give a comic touch, which in this play, however, is
kept to a minimum and used only to heighten the unrelieved terror. Lady Macduff
and her son are also shown as light, innocent people who might have had their
place in a comedy but who are here caught in dreadful tragedy.
1. The terrible soliloquies of Macbeth, the promptings of his dreadful Lady, and the
vile songs of the witches, all of which show the sophistry of temptation, the effort
to find reasons for sin.
2. Thought on the duty of a good king (Duncan, Edward) and the spirit of liberty
expressed by the lords. The chief thought running through the play turns on the
majesty of good kingship and the terrible wickedness of tyranny.
If we consider the relations of Action, Character, and Thought in this play we see that the action
is thoroughly probable, since it develops inevitably from Macbeth's initial blind decision to yield
to the temptations of ambition. The outcome is inevitable because crime leads to crime, one blind
delusion to another. That Macbeth does not repent is also probable, because his blindness is
willful and his crimes increasingly cold-blooded. It is also probable that Lady Macbeth, whose
strength is only in emotion, not in real power of will, should in the long run be the first to fail.
The revolt is also painted convincingly, since we see the various stages of hesitation,
irresolution, and indignant determination by which it proceeds. Some would criticize the witches
as mere machinery, but it seems very right that the blindness of sin should be dramatized by this
ghastly and unsubstantial trickery. The tragedy gains in stature in that it is not the mere sin, of an
individual but a picture of tyranny and of the restoration of justice and the social order which is
painted.
THE MATTER
(not analyzed in detail)
Such a study will show the consistency of the atmosphere created by the first two types of
language and the relief into which it is thrown by the other two.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Melody and Rhythm: Notice the crazy jingle of the witches' songs, the use of prose in the
porter's scene and in the sleep-walking scene. Notice, too, the complex rhythm of Macbeth's
early soliloquies expressive of his tortured state of mind, and the strange, dead monotony of
despair in "Tomorrow and tomorrow and tomorrow, etc."
Spectacle: Everyone recognizes the wonderful stage-effectiveness of the witches' scenes, the
dagger and banquet scene, and the sleepwalking scene. Harder to make effective is the final
scene of battle, which must. be presented so as to give the impression of clear daylight dawning
after a nightmare.
Problems: Many problems can be raised about this play, for example:
1. Is it not, after all, the story of a bad man meeting a bad end, which Aristotle says
is one of the worst of plots since it arouses no emotion but disgust?
2. Are not Acts IV and V weaker than the preceding acts?
3. Is not Act II, Scene 4 a clumsy transition? Why the Hecate scene (Act III, Scene
5)? Is not Act III, Scene 6 superfluous? Are not the concluding battle scenes
rather weak and confused? Why the passage about St. Edward of England?
The above analysis suggests how most of these problems might be answered.
Plot: A Christian merchant in order to assist his dearest friend in his courtship pledges his
life to a usurer who secretly hates him so that the merchant seems compelled by misfortune
to pay the forfeit, but is rescued through his friend's good fortune in love.
Subplots: The subplots have as their chief purpose to make clear the nature of the true love of the
friend (Bassanio) and Portia, since it is to further this love that the merchant Antonio makes his
sacrifice and through it that he is rescued. The subplots are:
1. Bassanio wins Portia in a trial required by her father's will by choosing the casket
which symbolizes that true love is deeper than appearances.
2. Portia tests the love of Bassanio by giving him a ring and then getting him to give
it up by a trick, but only in such a way that he shows he values nothing more than
her love except virtue and honor, and hence that his love is true. The wooing of
Nerissa, Portia's maid, by Gratiano, Bassanio's companion, parallels their love
and emphasizes its nobility by contrast.
3. Lorenzo steals away Jessica, the daughter of Antonio's enemy, along with her
father's money, has her baptized a Christian, and marries her, obtaining the rest of
the father's ill-gotten fortune. This parallels the theme of love overcoming evil; as
Antonio by love gains all, his enemy by hate loses all.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The "comic relief" of the servant Launcelot Gobbo, who runs away from Shylock and assists
Lorenzo, is a part of this subplot and serves the same purpose at a lower level. Shylock loses the
fidelity, not only of his daughter, but even of his servants.
The merchant of Venice, Antonio, put himself in the power of the usurer Shylock (who secretly
hates him because he opposes usury) by borrowing money needed by his friend Bassanio to carry
on his courtship of the noble lady Portia, on the agreement to forfeit a pound of his own flesh if
he does not pay at the appointed time, which payment depends on the return of his many ships.
Scene 1: The love of Antonio for Bassanio is shown by his willingness to obtain the money
required by Bassanio to woo lady Portia.
Scene 2: Beginning of chief subplot, whose purpose is to show that the love between Bassanio
and Portia is the truest sort, yet not as noble as Antonio's love. Portia loves Bassanio but by her
father's will must give her hand to the suitor who is wise enough to pick the casket with the right
motto; in other words he must be not only attractive but a man of true love.
Scene 3: Antonio makes the bargain of the pound of flesh with Shylock to obtain the money
Bassanio needs to woo Portia. It is revealed to the audience that Shylock hates Antonio because
of his generosity, while Antonio despises Shylock because of his avarice. We thus see that
Antonio's love is one of perfect generosity, and that Shylock provides the contrast and test of
this.
Middle:
Episode 1: The first episode in the action is the coming of news that some of Antonio's ships are
lost, and his refusal to recall Bassanio, thus putting himself another step in danger. The rest of
the act is occupied with the subplots. ACT II.
Scene 1: The Prince of Morocco arrives at Belmont to make his choice of the
casket. The theme of mismating (a Moor of different race and religion) is
emphasized.
Scenes 2-6: The two Gobbos, and the intentions of young Launcelot to run away
because of Shylock's ill-treatment. Then the love of Lorenzo and Jessica, and the
plot for the elopement, with Jessica taking her father's ill-gotten jewels. The
elopement is carried out with the help of Gratiano (Bassanio's servant) and
masquers, but the masque is stopped by Antonio, who announces that the wind
has changed and it is time for Bassanio to leave for Belmont.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The purpose of these scenes is to put forward the daring young love of Lorenzo
and Jessica. Here again is the theme of mismating (she is a Jewess and the
daughter of the villain), but this time the ardor of young love overcomes evil.
Thus suspense is created for Bassanio's choice of the casket; yet we are prepared
by this parallel love story, where daring wins all.
Scene 7: The choice of the Prince of Morocco, who chooses the golden casket
(symbol of outward worth) and receives a death's-head as reward.
Scene 8: The outcry of Shylock on discovering his daughter's elopement and the
loss of his jewels. He runs to the Duke to complain and stop Bassanio, but it is too
late. At this moment news arrives that some of Antonio's ships are lost, but
Antonio refuses to recall Bassanio.
Scene 9: The Prince of Aragon comes to choose and takes the silver casket
(symbol of self-love). He gets a fool's bead. This scene is put shortly and directly
without the preparation of the Prince of Morocco's scene, in order not to be
repetitious, and also to quicken the pace.
At the end Nerissa announces the coming of Bassanio, and reveals her interest in
Gratiano.
Episode II: Antonio's ships are lost but he gains the victory for Bassanio; Shylock in a fury of
revenge. ACT III.
Scene 1: Antonio's ships are lost, and Shylock sees how to take his revenge. This
is a discovery. It has no special probability, since the loss of the ships is not due to
anything in the plot. Yet Shakespeare has rendered it more probable (1) by,
showing, that Shylock was willing to bet that they might be lost, (2) by giving the
news in two stages, since in Act II, Scene 8, we have already heard of the storm.
Scene 2: Bassanio's choice of the leaden casket (symbol of true inner love and
humility). He Wins Portia. This scene of triumph follows immediately on the
previous disaster and thus makes a dramatic contrast. Bassanio's happiness has
been purchased by Antonio's sacrifice.
Rings are exchanged by the lovers and by Gratiano and Nerissa. just then Lorenzo
and Jessica (third pair of lovers) arrive with news of Antonio's disaster. Bassanio
and Portia agree to marry at once, but postpone their married life until they have
rescued Antonio. We thus see Antonio's love inspiring nobility and sacrifice in
others.
Episode III: Antonio arrested, and the subplot united to main plot. ACT III,
Scene 3: Antonio taken to jail. He attempts to win mercy from Shylock, who
refuses it. This scene shows Antonio come to understand Shylock's real purpose
and jealousy, and his resignation to his fate.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Scene 4: The subplot now begins to join the main plot, since Portia prepares to
rescue Antonio.
Scene 5: "Comic relief," banter between Launcelot and Jessica, then love scene of
Jessica and Lorenzo, With praise of Portia. This scene is not very effective, but its
purpose obviously is to begin to reveal Portia in her role as rescuer, and to play
up the theme that she and Bassanio have delayed their love-making for Antonio's
sake.
Episode IV: The Trial. In this we have the climax and reversal since Shylock's villainy is turned
on himself by Portia. In this the true grandeur of Antonio is shown, and also the nobility of the
love which he has inspired in Bassanio, and the worth of Portia. Act IV.
Scene 1: The trial. The theme of the trial is the nobility of mercy, generosity, and
true love, in contrast to Shylock.
Scene 2: At the end of the trial, the giving of Portia's and Nerissa's rings by
Bassanio and Gratiano, to the same women in disguise. This links the intense
action to the final act.
Conclusion: ACT V.
The beautiful moonlight love scene of Jessica and Lorenzo, awaiting the return of the others,
indicates to us Bassanio and Portia's anticipation of their own union.
Portia and Nerissa return. Then comes Bassanio and Antonio with Gratiano. The quarrel over the
rings. Antonio pledges himself once more for Bassanio, showing his love never changes. Word
arrives that Antonio's ships have returned after all.
Catharsis: At the beginning Antonio is in a state of melancholy because as a man of noble soul
he is weary of a world that values only what is material and false. The middle of the plot at first
seems to show that he is a fool, since he puts himself in the power of the most avaricious and
false of men to help Bassanio, a not too bright young man, risk a fortune on trying to win a
capricious woman. But the conclusion shows that his love was very wise. Bassanio, through
love, makes the right choice of the casket, and the woman he loves, Portia, turns out to be very
wise herself and Antonio's rescuer. Hence at the end Antonio is freed from sorrow and rejoices in
serenity at the pure love of his friends. The false values of Shylock and the Princes have been
exposed, and even the ships return safe.
This is a true comic plot since there is an exposure of avarice, envy, and false standards of love
(social values) without serious consequences to anyone. Even Shylock is better off in that he was
prevented from committing a crime and ends a Christian. (The play takes for granted that his
forced conversion would in tile end prove genuine and permit a reconciliation with his daughter.)
Characters:
1. Antonio is a merchant, and such a character is not usually pictured as noble, since ordinarily
he would be too occupied with money. But here this is used to show him by contrast as a man
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
indifferent to the world's standards, and saddened by an inexplicable sorrow. It is only through
the play that we begin to feel that he is melancholy. It is because be is disillusioned with the
world, as is manifested by his world-weary wittiness. Yet in the last scenes he becomes serene
and joyful as he sees that be has engendered a true love in Bassanio and Portia. In the end he is
still witty, still a spectator of the world rather than a participant, but one who nevertheless is
consoled that not all in the world is falsehood.
It is a puzzle of the play that Antonio, the central character, still is in the background. Many
interpretations of the play, and many performances of it, treat him as a mere foil to Bassanio.
This misses the subtlety of Shakespeare. It is hard to show a noble spirit without making him
seem stuffy and unreal. Hence Antonio is revealed to us, not through himself, but through his
friends who reflect his nobility.
2. Bassanio is the perfect young lover, and his relative lack of wit compared to his brilliant wife
adds a comic note to his love. Yet he shows up very well by his humility in the choice of the
casket, his determination to stand by Antonio, his sense of gratitude to the "lawyer." He shows us
a man who is capable of great romantic love and yet who will not sacrifice his friendship, nor his
duty of gratitude, to it.
3. Portia is a woman whose superior intelligence would make her capable of rivaling any man,
and yet who for that reason well understands her role as a woman of modesty, an obedient wife,
and a friend to her husband's friends; but she is not above playing a joke on her husband. Her
warmth, her chastity, her wit, and her tenderness are beautifully blended.
4. Nerissa, Gratiano, Jessica, Lorenzo are spirited young people, generous, witty, with a good
deal of the thoughtlessness and unconscious cruelty of the young, Their comparative shallowness
throws into relief the richer characters of Portia and Bassanio.
5. The Prince of Morocco and the Prince of Aragon are properly ceremonious and pompous. At
the other extreme, the two Gobbos by their crudity and silliness are foils to the elegance of the
other characters and to the malicious cunning of Shylock.
6. Shylock is admitted by all to be a great portrait. He is not sentimentalized, nor justified by the
author, as romantic critics supposed. He is truly eaten up by avarice, envy, and malice, but this
wickedness is credible because we are shown its root in natural human feelings. Shylock is a
genuine human being, but a bad one. Yet be is comic, not a tragic figure, because he is
essentially a dupe, a man who cannot succeed in his wickedness because be is outwitted by two
women, his own daughter and Portia. The scene in which he bemoans the loss of his daughter
and his money-bags is the perfect revelation and exposure of his true character. His function in
the play is to be the very reverse of Antonio, and yet to be a plausible human being, not a stock
villain.
Thought:
This is a witty play in which there is a constant exchange of pointed moral comments. The main
themes turn around fidelity in love and friendship. The theme of the witty woman and the theme
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
of the apparent conflict of mercy and justice are also aired. Shylock's famous speech (Act III,
Scene 1, lines 44-60) is a fine example of rhetoric which is at the same time ironic in its dramatic
setting, since Shylock himself is without mercy. It would be a mistake, however, to consider that
this play deals with the problem of anti-Semitism as some modern writers seem to think.
MATTER
Diction:
The play sparkles throughout with brilliant descriptions and a witty eloquence. Special study
should be given to the colorful talk of the merchants in the first act, the use of biblical
phraseology by Shylock, the high-flown courtliness of the two suitor princes, the light banter of
the women, the nobility of the trial scene in which the phrases of the New Testament are used
against the Old Testament quotations of Shylock and in which the legal language is so cleverly
employed, and finally the lyricism of the last act with its moonlight and music. The low language
of the Gobbos seems like the earth from which all these flowery phrases grow. Noteworthy is the
imagery of the ship with its cargo, and the theme of gold and jewels throughout the entire play.
In contrast to this theme of gold are the themes of the "pound of flesh" and of the human heart,
which are warm and living.
In studying the diction of each scene it is important to see how this use of several languages
(language of business, language of law, language of wit, language of love, Shylock's language) is
managed so as to bring out the conflict of the various elements in the plot.
Melody:
A study needs to be made of the use of prose for comic scenes (for example, Shylock's big
speech in Act III). There is also a marked contrast between the lyric quality of the speeches in
the last act, and the grand music of many of the speeches in the trial scene. This play is notable
for its very lively and highly varied rhythms and sounds, from the loud outcries of Shylock to the
dulcet music of the last act.
Spectacle:
The great feature of the play is, of course, the trial to it is the repetition of the scene with caskets
and the concluding night scene. The elopement of Jessica, combined with the masquers, and
Shylock's frantic running about the stage, are visually very effective. Striking, too, is the contrast
between the colorful quay of Venice, the solemnity of the Duke's court, and the peaceful
elegance of the country estate at Belmont. Can you imagine the use of Venetian paintings by a
scene designer for this play? Might the rapid alternations of the scene, in the third act, for
example, be managed by multiple or revolving stages?
The Action:
When Troy is destroyed through the hatred of the goddess Juno, Aeneas, son of the king of
the city and the goddess Venus, escapes by his mother's aid, and after enduring many
hardships sent by Juno, including the sacrifice of his personal happiness, succeeds in
reconciling the gods and founding a new Troy that will become imperial Rome.
This story is tragic, since it involves the greatest consequences, namely, the founding of an
empire, and this is achieved only by the suffering of a hero who sacrifices all for the common
good, although he is not put to the test of ultimate failure. The catharsis is through pity and fear,
since we admire Aeneas as a great patriot who suffers for the common good, but we are also
filled with fear to see how much the duty to our country requires us to sacrifice of personal
happiness.
Beginning: The beginning of the plot is Aeneas' flight from Troy with his household goods and
his son and father (symbols of his future destiny), but without his wife (symbol of personal
happiness). This is related, however, by a flashback technique in Books II-III.
Middle: The middle has two larger episodes, divided into many smaller ones. The larger
episodes are the journey to Italy (Books I-VI) and the Wars in Italy (Books VII-XII).* [Vergil thus
cleverly combines the two themes of Homeric epic: the perilous voyage (Odyssey) in Books I-VI, , and the fortunes
of war (Iliad) in Books VII-XIII.]
Book 1: Aeneas is shipwrecked on the shores of Carthage by Juno and the god of
the sea, but by the help of his mother Venus he regains his crew at the court of
Dido, Queen of Carthage, who receives them graciously.
Book II. At a banquet given by the Queen, Aeneas relates the fall of Troy by the
trick of the horse, his loss of his wife, and his flight..
Book III: He continues the account of his wanderings (the harpies, the temple of
the sun, his meeting with his brother Hector's Widow, Andromache, the passage
of Scylla and Charybdis, the cave of the Cyclops, and the death of his father
Anchises in Italy).
Book IV: The love-story of Aeneas and Dido, Summoned to his mission by the
gods, Aeneas leaves, and Dido commits suicide.
These four books form, as it were, a single episode, whose theme is the effort of Juno to entangle
Aeneas in the pursuit of his own personal romantic happiness. Carthage and its queen are for this
epic a symbol of a merely personal happiness, based on love, riches, and pleasure, in contrast to
the nobler ideal of Rome based on patriotism and glory.
Book V: The funeral games for Anchises in Sicily. While these are in progress,
Juno inspires the Trojan women to burn the ships. Aeneas escapes with part of the
fleet, but loses his steersman Palinurus.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Book VI: Aeneas descends into the Underworld to see the spirit of his father, and
there learns the meaning of his mission, the future founding of the Roman
Empire.
Book VI marks the climax of the epic, since here Aeneas realizes the meaning of
his life. Book V serves as a transition to this climax, completing the previous
themes, The burial of Anchises is the final end of Aeneas' duty to the past, and the
attempt of the women is a last echo of the Dido episode. Palinurus' death
terminates the story of the voyage.
Book VII: Aeneas arrives in Latium and is engaged to Lavinia, daughter of the
native king, intended by her mother Amata for the native prince Turnus. Juno
inspires this outraged pair to foment a rebellion.
Book VIII: Aeneas, faced with the war, learns in a vision from the god of the river
Tiber that Juno is the cause of his disasters. He is advised to placate Juno and seek
an alliance with Evander, King of Arcadia. Aeneas goes to the King who relates
to him the history and mythology of the land, gives him an army and his own son
Pallas, and advises another alliance with the Etruscans. The Etruscans have lately
expelled the tyrant Mezentius, who has become an ally of Turnus.
Book IX: Turnus attacks the fleet of Aeneas, which is turned into a band of sea-
nymphs by the goddess Cybele. Then occur the fierce battles of Turnus, the first
exploits of Ascanius, son of Aeneas, and the sad episode of the friends, Nisus and
Euryalus, who die for each other. Turnus is turned back.
These three books constitute a first great episode of the war in which Turnus is defeated, but not
decisively. Aeneas' departure serves to heighten the tension and give the lesser warriors their
chance, while Evander gives us a picture of the background and primitive times of the land
where the new Troy is to rise.
Book X: Quarrel among the gods, but Jupiter resolves to let the battle go on.
Aeneas is returning with an Etruscan fleet, and meets his own fleet turned into
sea-nymphs. Turnus attempts to prevent the landing and kills Pallas, then is driven
back. Aeneas kills Lausus, son of Mezentius, and then Mezentius himself.
Book XI: The funeral of Pallas and the grief of his father Evander. Envoys arrive
from Diomed, King of the Argive settlement, with his refusal to assist the rebels.
King Latinus is ready to surrender, but Turnus refuses and begins a new attack,
sending the warrior maiden Camilla to hold off the troops. She performs great
feats but is slain by Arrnus, who is then slain by Diana, protectress of Camilla.
End:
Book XII: Turnus wishes to fight Aeneas alone in spite of the protests of King
Latinus and his queen. Juno sends Juturna, nymph of the streams, to assist Turnus,
who is her brother. Aeneas and Latinus take an oath to make a treaty if Aeneas
wins. Juturna in disguise provokes the Latins to break the truce to save Turnus. In
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
the fighting Aeneas is hit by an arrow, but healed by an herb sent by Venus.
Aeneas pursues Turnus, but is deceived by Juturna, so that he turns on the city to
attack it. The Queen kills herself thinking Turnus is already dead. Turnus stops
Juturna and demands the single combat with Aeneas. Jupiter on Olympus
reconciles Juno to Aeneas' triumph by promising that the now nation will be
called Latin and not Trojan. Aeneas defeats Turnus, and, because of his cruelty to
young Pallas, puts him to death.
These three books built up to the defeat of Turnus and the reconciliation of Juno. They are
arranged to maintain suspense to the end, and Book XI in particular makes us accept the death of
Turnus, by showing that in spite of his bravery be is cruel. The death of Camilla and the young
men adds to the pathos of the war, since Aeneas sorrows at it all and would have prevented it if
he could.
Characters
1. Aeneas is shown as the mail of patriotism (piety), who does his duty to his father, to his
nation, and to the gods. He is shown as superior to Paris (man of romance), Odysseus (man of
adventure), or Achilles and Hector (men of war). He is the father of his people who suffers over
them, and is strong both to endure and attack, but is above all a man of justice. Yet he himself
suffers because of human weakness and personal attachments, first of love (Dido) and then of
affection for his countrymen and allies (Pallas, and others).
2. The many subordinate characters are typical, rather than individual, and yet each is aptly
characterized. Ascanius is the youth Of promise who has to make good. Anchises, Latinus, and
Evander are the wise old men. Dido and Amata are typical women of emotion. Turnus, the hero,
and Pallas and Lausus are the young men of fiery courage, but rash rather than prudent. Camilla
and Lavinia are two virgins contrasted to each other, one the "tom-boy," the other the retiring
maiden. Vergil makes these types real by his power in depicting contrasted types and in showing
the struggle of the passions. Thus in Dido we see the struggle between love and hatred of a
woman scorned. In Turnus we See the struggle of courage and despair of one who knows he will
fail, but cannot Submit to failure. Aeneas is not shown as struggling, but rather as suffering with
a firm resolve.
3. The gods and goddesses are depicted as grandly noble personifications of the forces of nature
and fate that affect human life. Venus is not shown as favoring romance, but rather as the "higher
love" who favors Aeneas because he is carrying out the law of progress which requires the
creative work of fathering a new nation. Juno is depicted, on the other hand, as a conservative
force attempting to defend the established order. When Aeneas succeeds and shows himself
respectful of tradition and custom, she finally accepts him. Jupiter shows himself as the mediator
and harmonizer of these two forces of progress and conservatism.
Thought:
Throughout the poem there are very many speeches of debate and deliberation, both among the
gods and among men (for example, the discussions of whether to yield or continue the war in
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Book XI). The theme of most of these is the problem of man's submission to destiny. The
necessity of leadership, of firmness of purpose, of the spirit of peace and reasonable compromise
in order to construct a great nation are all discussed. There is not much of a highly philosophic
character, but the thought of the poem is impressive by reason of its sense of the power of
political prudence to dominate the raging sea of human passions. Book VI contains a kind of
philosophic picture of the world and of human destiny. Vergil was an Epicurean by training, but
his philosophy is a sort of pantheism which might just as well be Stoic, and the general tone of
the poem is a defense of duty against personal pleasure or gain.
THE MATTER
(not analyzed in detail)
Words:
It is generally admitted that the style of Vergil in this poem is beyond praise (although the poem
was never finally polished, and the Poet wished it destroyed). Full advantage is taken of the
power of Latin (as of Greek) to use a complex word-order to hold ideas suspended until clinched
by a final operative word (periodic sentences). The style is highly varied and colored but kept
very close to an even, moderate tone, and it rejects complex ornamentation. There is great
economy in exposition so that each book has its special and novel interest in description and
incident, so that each could stand alone. It is also generally admitted that Vergil is not equal to
Homer in dramatic boldness, freshness, and power. However, he probably excels Homer in
economy, variety, and clearness of structure. Vergil particularly excels in two elements: 1)
description, particularly of landscapes, and of the effect of light; 2) in the pathetic, emotional
quality which gives much of his poem the tone of pastoral elegy.
Read the well-known tribute of Tennyson to Vergil. The dactylic hexameter is taken over from
Greek epic poetry, and is used because it is rapid in movement and permits a great variety of
rhythm by substituted feet and variation in the pauses. Vergil does not have Homer's vigor in the
use of this meter, but produces verses of great smoothness and grandeur that often take on a lyric
quality. Where Homer is famous for his effects of great sound volume (the sound of the sea and
the clamor of battle), Vergil is famous for his effects of moonlit silence and shadowy forests.
The Action:
A girl from a financially embarrassed family, although urged to a wealthy marriage by her
scheming mother, refuses a wealthy gentleman because of his and her own pride, and
because mistakenly she believes him dishonorable, until he proves himself humbled by love,
and truly honorable and generous, and wins her apology and her hand.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
This plot is of the comic variety because it turns on the failing of vanity and over-sensitive
suspicion (pride and prejudice) which are without grave consequences. The chief characters are
good, but not heroic, while the other characters are largely absurd in their vanities and
pretensions. The catharsis comes through the gradual exposure of the incongruous attitudes, and
ends in laughter and joy when true love is found underneath the illusions. The truth which is
finally seen is that even noble characters misunderstand each other when they are infected by the
vanities and prejudices of those less noble with whom they live.
Beginning: The beginning is the ball at which the Bennet girls make various impressions, while
Elizabeth Bennet meets the eligible but haughty Mr. Darcy and overhears his slighting remark
about her.
End: The end is Elizabeth's and Darcy's final recognition of their mistakes and their true love for
each other.
These are united to the main plot because they, too, are an effect of Mrs. Bennet's effort to marry
off her daughters, and they cause much of the complication in the main story.
Characters:
1. Mr. and Mrs. Bennet set the stage by the sharp opposition between her worldly
foolishness and his world-weary wisdom. She judges everything superficially and
by the most worldly standards. He is a man who despairs of changing the silly
people be finds about him.
2. Elizabeth is the daughter of both. Like her father she has complete personal
honesty of character and an ironic sense of humor, but this pure character is
somewhat clouded by superficiality and vanity of judgment which have resulted
from contact with her mother. Not that she judges as her mother does, but that she
has become suspicious of others through seeing her mother's way of acting.
3. The other daughters provide the appropriate contrast to Elizabeth. Jane is simply
good and innocent, while Lydia is very much like her own mother. Similarly,
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Throughout, the characterization emphasizes the contrast between simple people unaffected by
their situation, absurd, superficial people; and Darcy and Elizabeth, who are in the middle,
honest but not simple enough to be free of the effects of their environment.
Thought:
The thought stays strictly on the level of a discussion of the social problems of money, marriage,
and social position, without any wider implications, Elizabeth, Darcy, Mr. Bennet, and Miss
Bingley are all notable for their sharp and witty exchanges. An interesting play is kept up by the
contrast between their clear minds and incisive speech and the prejudices which affect them. The
depth of the humor, however, is found in the way it is made clear that the best people have a
great deal of difficulty in not being trapped by the "climate of opinion" which surrounds them.
THE MATTER
Words:
A study of the style will show that it is characterized especially by its simplicity (very little
elaborate description or ornamentation) and by its constant but deft employment of irony. The
author makes occasional comments on the situation, but they are very brief and dry. Everything
that is sensational or exotic is avoided. Even the elopement is treated in an anticlimactic fashion,
without moralizing. There is genuine pathos in Mr. Bennet and in the suffering of the two
principal characters, but it is treated very quietly. It is characteristic of the author's method that
the action moves ahead chiefly by conversation, in which a considerable number of different
characters engage and are played off against each other.
Austin uses a very pure prose style without poetic ornamentation, but she is very effective in
reproducing the rhythm and inflection of conversational speech, and in setting it off against a
background of social movement, all of which is suggested in the prose rhythms.
VI. A PASTORAL:
THE BOOK OF RUTH
THE FORM
The Action:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
A foreign woman and a widow, out of loyalty to her widowed mother-in-law who is a
member of the Chosen People, returns with her to Bethlehem, and there by her obedience
to the counsel of her mother-in-law obtains a rich husband Booz, and thus becomes a
member of the Chosen People and ancestress of King David and the Messias.
This is a pastoral whose intention is comic in that it is intended to rebuke the vanity of people
who bad forgotten that the glory of the Jewish Kingdom rested on humble foundations of piety
and virtue. This is, of course, a very quiet kind of comedy, whose effect is ironic and not
boisterous. The catharsis ends in joy achieved through a share in the humiliation and anxiety of
the two women, and even of Booz, the puzzled bridegroom. In the poem, however, there is
something of epic grandeur, by reason of its relation to the Messias.
Beginning:
1. The story of the Jewess Noemi, who was left a widow in the land of Moab, and
how her sons married Moabite women and finally died.
2. Noemi decides to return to Bethlehem in her own land. One daughter-in-law,
Orpha, says farewell, but the other, Ruth, returns with Noemi at the harvest time.
Middle:
First Episode: Chapter II: Ruth goes to reap the field of Noemi's relative, Booz, to help Noemi.
Booz sees her and acknowledges her as a relative, inviting her to reap, protecting her from the
young men, and letting her partake of the harvest meal. She tells Noemi of his kindness.
Second Episode: Chapter III: Noemi gives Ruth advice as to how she is to conduct herself so as
to attract Booz' attention and modestly indicate to him the possibility of their marriage. Booz
treats her with courtesy, gives her barley, and sends her home to Noemi.
Third Episode: Chapter IV: Booz bargains With the nearest kinsman for the right to wed
Noemi. This takes place in the presence of the elders who call down blessings on the pair.
End: End of Chapter IV: Booz marries Ruth. Noemi receives congratulations over the birth of
her grandson Obed, and the genealogy of the House of David is given.
Characters:
1. Noemi is the type of the widow. We see her many sorrows, her bitterness and shame over her
lot, her resolve to return to her people in spite of her shame at her misfortunes, and her dawning
hope when she hears of Booz' interest in Ruth. Then we see her experience and prudence in
bringing the matter to a successful and proper conclusion.
2. Ruth is contrasted to her sister Orpha. There is something mysterious in Ruth's wonderful
fidelity to Noemi. Why did she love her so? Was it not because she recognized the superior
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
virtue of Noemi, born of Noemi's faith in the true God, which made her superior to the women of
Moab? Ruth shows her generosity also in her willingness to go to work to support both of them,
without being asked. Before Booz she is modest; yet in her suit she shows both her courage and
her chastity. Note that after her marriage nothing is said in detail of her, she is only praised as
"better to thee (Booz) than seven sons" (4:15).
3. Booz is shown as a man of humanity and kindness. He is an older man, chaste and humble, but
very just and resolved to fulfil all his duties to the law. "Thy later kindness has surpassed the
former, because thou bast not followed young men, either rich or poor" (3:10) are his words to
Ruth, and they show his humility about himself, and his deep joy in her love for him.
4. The kinsman (Chapter IV) is not characterized. The elders form a kind of chorus, and the
women who congratulate Noemi another chorus.
Thought:
As always in Scripture, the thought expressed is supernatural and profound. We notice in Ruth's
wonderful speech of fidelity that, although she is still a pagan, there is alive in her a longing for
better things. Admiring Noemi, she says, "and thy gods, shall be my gods," Not realizing that she
will be led by her fidelity to know the One True God. We also admire the justice and prudence of
the two older people, Noemi and Booz. Finally, in the two choruses of elders and of women we
hear of the justice and mercy of God, who does his work through the humble.
THE MATTER
(Means of imitation)
Words:
Even in translation the beautiful simplicity of the style with its flavor of antiquity is evident.
Notice the use of genealogies as an opening and closing of the story. The speeches are couched
in a kind of epic style, in which there is a use of the favorite Hebrew device of parallelism.
Notice the play on the names of Noemi and Mara (1:20), and the blessing's and curses (1:16;
2:12; 2:20; 3:10; 4:11; 4:14). Characteristic of the pastoral is the use of rustic details and the
description of quaint customs; for example, the gleaning customs, the manner of eating the
harvest meal, the sleeping in the fields, and the customs connected with marriage.
We can appreciate the rapid movement of the prose, rising to a poetic prose in the speeches, and
to actual poetry in the choruses. Notice the use of parallelism in rhythm throughout. Study the
sound in the translation of Monsignor Knox. Notice also the effect given by the genealogies with
their sonorous and mysterious names.
The Action:
An elder son who has always seemed a model of virtue reveals his selfish motives when he is
angered by his good father's rejoicing over the return of a prodigal younger brother.
This parable has been understood in different ways. Many think that the story concerns the
prodigal son (hence it is often called The Parable of the Prodigal Son), others think it centers on
the father. But the point of the whole story concerns the older brother, since if this is not the case,
the ending of the story would be an anticlimax.
The story has a comic catharsis, because its aim is the exposure of the elder brother's vanity and
pettiness. It is told with great wit, which conceals the real point of the story until the last. We
suppose that we are hearing a story with the simple, expected moral, crime does not pay." Then
when the story seems to have wound up, we have a surprise ending: it turns out that the real
prodigal was the respectable brother who stayed at home. Since we have been identifying ourself
with this self-righteous attitude, we feel ourselves suddenly exposed with him.
This work is rhetorical as applied to the sinner, for it does move us to repent. Nevertheless, the
main point is the exposure of vanity. Hence the sermon ends in a catharsis and is rhetoric which
closely approaches the manner of poetry.
Beginning: The young son departs with his inheritance, but the older brother stays (verses 11
and 12).
Middle:
1. The younger son squanders his money in riotous living and is reduced to want
(13-16).
2. The younger son repents and decides to return home (17-20).
3. The younger son is met by his father and invited to a banquet (20-24).
4. The older son returns and angrily refuses to enter (25-28).
5. The older son rebukes his indulgent father (28-30).
End: The father by a word exposes the selfishness of the older son. (31-32).
The Characters:
1. The younger son is thoughtless in his first demands. The same thoughtlessness leads him into
dissipation and utter destitution. His attitude is always materialistic but straightforward. Like a
person with such an attitude he is completely sorry because of the consequences of his
foolishness and resolves on abasing himself totally by offering to become his father's servant.
The fact that he believes his father would accept such an offer shows how little be really
appreciates his father's attitude. When he returns and finds his father forgiving, he confesses his
sin, but does not offer to become a servant. We feel that he quickly forgot his troubles and joined
gaily in the dancing and the good times, perhaps only a little wiser for his lesson.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
2. The father is a marvelous picture of a wise old man. He lets the younger boy go, biding his
grief at the boy's ingratitude, understanding the youth has to learn the hard way. He longs for the
boy's return, and when he sees him runs to kiss him without any reproach. He is especially
anxious to hide the young man's shame (although, as we have seen, the young man's shame is not
really so deep) by giving him the dignity of a robe, a ring, and a party.
No one ever need know the disgraceful tale. Nevertheless, the father is not merely fond and
foolish, for when he is rebuked by the older son, he answers him with a marvelous and
penetrating reply. Yet he ends on a note of rejoicing ("for thy brother was dead, and has come to
life; he was lost, and is found") rather than of reproach.
3. The older brother is built up for us by contrast with the others. We know that he is everything
the prodigal was not. Yet as he comes soberly in from the field where he has worked so patiently
and hears the music and the dancing, be suddenly flies into a bitter rage and refuses even to see
his brother. Then when his father comes to get him, he answers him with a very bitter speech,
praising and justifying himself: "I have never transgressed one of thy commandments," and
implying that he has worked for his father for pay. He calls his brother "thy son," and throws in
the nasty detail, "who has devoured his means with harlots."
4. The servant and the friends merely fill in the picture and are not characterized.
Thought:
This is a parable which implies a deeper meaning. It refers to the Pharisees and all self-righteous
persons who think themselves just and reject the Gentiles and sinners, while they themselves are
even more guilty through their ingratitude and lack of love of God, since they serve him only for
material benefits. This profound moral truth is brought out through the wit of the story, all
summed up in the three speeches in which each man characterizes himself: the speech of the
prodigal admitting his sin, the speech of the elder son justifying himself and condemning his
brother and father, and the wonderful speech of the father exposing the self-righteousness of the
older son. In a parable the details need not have meaning, but there can be little doubt that the
"inheritance" symbolizes the heavenly inheritance of grace, the confession of the prodigal
symbolizes the sacrament of penance, and the banquet the Holy Eucharist and heaven.
THE MATTER
(Means of imitation)
Words:
The story is told with utmost economy and wit. Note the quickness of the beginning, and the
delicate passing-over of the details of the "riotous living." A modern author would feel
compelled to picture all this in a "realistic" fashion. Then notice the vivid and direct picture of
the prodigal with the swine, and the telling detail, "And he longed to fill his belly with the pods
that the swine were eating, but no one offered them to him." Note, too, the vividness of the
contrast between the swine-pen and his dream of his father's home, and then the reality of that
home which is more perfect than the dream itself. There is drama in the fact that the older son
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
becomes aware of the prodigal's return by the sound of music as he returns from work. The
phrase, "The father came out and began to entreat him" is a powerful one, and the last speech of
the father is marvelous in its complete simplicity and antithesis of ideas ("death" contrasted to
"life").
The parable has an oral style, effective in oral delivery. For this reason it uses the devise of
repetition (the repeated speech of the prodigal, first to himself, then to his father; then the speech
of the father to the prodigal and its repetition by the servant to the elder son, and its quotation by
the elder son back to his father; and finally the father's repetition of his own speech to the
prodigal at the very end of the story. See 18 and 21; 23, 27, 30; 24 and 32). Also notice the
constant use of parallelism and antithesis.
THE FORM
(Object of imitation)
The Action:
A man is helped by his brother to elope, but in the flight the brother is wounded and the
man leaves him to die in order to escape with his bride, who too eventually dies, leaving
him with nothing but remorse.
This plot is told by a flashback device: A white traveler stops at nightfall at a native
clearing on a jungle lagoon at a haunted house, where lives an exiled Malayan, Arsat,
whose wife Diamelen is dying. During the night Arsat explains how he loved her, but could
not win her from her jealous mistress, Inchi Midah, wife of a ruler, until he,
with his brother's help, escaped. During the flight Arsat saw his brother fall wounded, but
did not turn back to save him. Since then he has lived alone on the lagoon, feared by the
natives and inwardly eaten with remorse. At dawn Diamelen dies, and Arsat decides to go
back to his own land for an empty revenge. As the traveler departs by boat he sees Arsat
gazing blindly, at the new day.
The story seems tragic, dealing with a man of courage and great love who through his love
sins against gratitude to his brother, but comes at last through the loss of his love to see the
futility of sin. However, the story falls short of the tragic in that it is a purely personal story
without social consequences. We feel pity at the intense suffering of this man because of
remorse and death, and we feel fear because it is implied that this story is typical of the
strange tangle of human life.
The method of narrating the story (manner) is chosen to make the feeling of fear and
anguish very intense, until the telling of the story and the final death of the woman is a
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
relief from an unbearable strain. It is the catharsis of confession but not of absolution. It
might be asked, however, whether there is not something pointless to it all, since it is not
clear that this confession brings any ultimate peace. It would appear pointless if
represented as tragic in the full sense, but its exotic setting, etc., make it a mysterious
personal incident, the sad fate that befalls some individuals and which leaves us pondering.
The resolution, therefore, does not really come from the action, but from the satisfaction of
our curiosity, our desire to understand and experience. It is thus more an adventure story
than a tragedy, and its catharsis is not in the action, but rather in the traveler who bears
the story. This explains why the author chose the form of a short story, and his peculiar
method of narration which makes the action an incident or episode, rather than something
complete in itself.
Beginning: The traveler arrives and finds the strange man and his dying wife.
Middle: The flashback explaining the action; the story told by Arsat:
1. Arsat's relations with the traveler, and with his own brother.
2. The wooing of Diamelen and the obstacles to their wedding.
3. The flight.
4. The death of his brother, and his remorse.
End: The death of the wife, Arsat's determination to return and seek revenge, and the
traveler's departure.
The Characters:
1. The traveler is characterized only by his power as a silent observer, who is objective,
touched by the events without being involved in them. The narrator seems to take the same
point of view as the traveler.
2. Arsat is an exotic character who speaks a poetic kind of language. His motives are simple
and primitive, and we feel that although he expresses himself well it is only with difficulty
that be is able to reflect over his experience and formulate it. He is first characterized for
us by the fear and dislike of the natives, who sense that he is a man with a secret. Then we
see his strange calm at his wife's approaching death. Then at last he reveals himself. As the
traveler leaves him at the end, we seem to see him receding from us and once more involved
in mystery.
3. Diamelen does not speak, and we know her only through her husband's description as a
woman who responds completely to Arsat's love.
4. The brother of Arsat also is known to us only through Arsat's description, but he stands
out very vividly in his desperate courage.
5. The natives form a kind of chorus in the background, not speaking but by their fear
making vivid to us the idea that Arsat is a man marked by fate.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The Thought:
The story presents us with three interpretations of the same facts: (1) The interpretation of
the natives who regard the man as accursed; (2) the interpretation of the white traveler
who pities Arsat and sees him as man whose life has been wasted in delusions of romance,
of remorse, and of revenge; (3) Arsat's own interpretation of himself as fated, yet guilty.
Back of all seems to be the reflection of the narrator, who is pondering on the mystery of
human destiny set against the background of the immense pattern of nature. The author
senses the mystery of life and seeks to render this in his story, but without being able to
give any key to it. In a larger work this would seem very inconclusive and unsatisfactory,
but in a short story we are content with a less complete effect.
THE MATTER
(Means of imitation)
Words:
In this story, elaborate, lyrical description is extensively used to produce a mood, a feeling
of the immense, strange, and pitiless setting of nature in the midst of which human beings
live their little lives. Word-painting is used to give us a vivid sense of evening, of the long
night, and of the dawn. In contrast to this lyrical description is the narrative of Arsat,
which is told in a primitive, but poetic language, that reminds us a little of the kind of
narrative we find in a folk ballad. It is also evident that the lagoon takes on a symbolic
meaning, It seems to stand for the remorse within the soul of Arsat, which is at first
mysterious and whose meaning is gradually revealed to us. Study how the rich vocabulary
and careful choice of adjectives and verbs helps to create these effects.
The rhythm of the evening, night, and dawn, and of the coming and departure of the boat,
forms a setting for the story. There is also a suggestion of the tense rhythm of the woman's
fever and her husband's hidden anguish, bursting forth at last in the overflow of his
confession. The prose rhythm, which is very strong, indicates this tension and overflow.
Notice too how sound-effects (onomatopoeia) are used in the description.
Spectacle:
If this story were made as a movie, the setting would play a very large role in its effect, The
writer includes this setting in his narrative by use of extensive descriptive effects. We have
explained the symbolism of this setting above.
The Action:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
An old maid takes out her precious fox-fur to go for a walk, During which she watches the
city life about her and feels herself an actress playing an important role in the drama until
a couple of young lovers laugh at her fur and she returns to her lonely flat in tears to put it
away.
In this story the action is reduced to a minimum and directed to the revelation of character.
The story is comic in that it reveals character through the exposure of the spinster's absurd
little pleasures and vanities, but it is a pathetic type of comedy ending in pity. Nevertheless,
it does not end in mere pathos, since ill exposing Miss Brill's absurdity we also come at the
end to see her inner human dignity, which is deep and fine, Thus the catharsis is the
removal of our own tendency to regard such people as absurd and grotesque, and results in
a deeper insight into the real beauty of human character. In this way the sorrowful element
is less deep than our new joy in human dignity.
It might be thought that the author is not altogether successful in achieving this positive
resolution, and that we are left suspended in a mere sense of "Oh, the pity of it all!"
Nevertheless, the effect intended is a very delicate one, and to many it will seem that she hit
a very good balance. To be more emphatic about the positive aspect of Miss Brill might
have been very heavy-handed. It seems better to let the reader draw his own conclusion.
Middle: She takes her walk and shares the life around her, until she overbears the young
couple making full of her.
The Characters:
A single character is portrayed for us. The other characters are types, who merely provide
the occasion for Miss Brill's thoughts. Even if the young couple had not laughed, no doubt
her story would have ended the same way, since she could never sustain her gay mood of
illusion.
Miss Brill is shown to us as a person who by nature had great capacity for sensitivity, for
laughter, for human friendship, for beauty. Her reactions are all essentially refined, but all
this has taken on a grotesqueness and absurdity from the emptiness of her life. We feel that
she has not had the courage to enter into more real relations with people, because failure
would have been so painful to her. We might question, however, whether the author has
not somewhat sentimentalized this figure. Would not a Miss Brill in real life have some
element of bitterness? Would it not be more evident that the emptiness of her life was also
due to real defects of character, which were in her own power to correct? Has not the
author "stacked the cards" in favor of Miss Brill by making it appear that her story is
wholly pathetic?
The Thought:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The story is told us chiefly through the inner stream of consciousness of Miss Brill herself.
She is not a woman who really thinks, but only one who imagines. Yet there is a certain
element of thought in the passage in which Miss Brill thinks of herself as an actress playing
a role. This is as close as she comes to trying to understand her own character. Is there not
here an implication that, after all, the pathetic bystander actually sees more of the reality of
life than the participants, who are so engaged in living that they cannot reflect on it or
appreciate it? THE MATTER (Means of imitation)
Words:
The effect of the story depends on the mincing, finicky, delicate style in which the most
minute things are noticed and mentioned. Typical are the description of the fur piece and
the reports of the inane conversations which Miss Brill overhears. This style reflects the
point of view of Miss Brill. We feel her delicate, sharply observant, nervous, exclamatory,
shy personality in the choice of adjectives and the multiplication of details,
The broken, frequently qualified sentences, the light touch of sound bears out the tone of
the diction. For example: "Although it was so brilliantly fine -- the blue sky powdered with
old and great spots of light like white wine splashed over the Jardins Publiques -- Miss Brill
was glad that she had decided on her fur." Notice how the word "decided" at the end of
this sentence makes the whole sentence seem pathetically comic.
X. A LYRIC POEM:
PSALM 125
When the Lord brought back the captives of Sion,
we were like men dreaming.
Then our mouth was filled with laughter,
and our tongue with rejoicing.
Then they said among the nations,
"The Lord has done great things for them!"
The Lord has done great things for us;
we are glad indeed.
Restore our fortunes, O Lord,
like the torrents in the southern desert.
Those that sow in tears
shall reap rejoicing
Although they go forth weeping,
carrying the seed to be sown,
They shall come back rejoicing,
carrying their sheaves.
THE FORM
(Object of imitation)
The Action:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The Jews returned from exile recall the joy they felt upon their return and in the midst of
present hardships in building up the city pray that at last that joy will be renewed when
their work is accomplished.
In a lyric poem the action is reduced to a movement of emotion. In this poem the emotion is
one of hope and supplication, and it has a heroic (tragic) tone.
Beginning: The Jews recall their joy when they returned from exile (by implication they
are now in difficulties), line 1.
Middle:
Stanza 2: Grant, O Lord, a return of that joy as the reward of present labors!
End: The Jews anticipate the joy at harvest (reward of labor), last two lines.
The Characters:
In a lyric poem, since the action is reduced to an emotional experience, what is chiefly
revealed to us is the habitual character of the singer. In this poem we have depicted the
ideal character of one who believes in God. In the first stanza we see the profound
attachment of the Jews to their own land. This attachment is not only one of patriotism, but
of religion. They know that God has a special providence over their nation (the symbol of
the Catholic Church), and hence, when they returned to the Holy Land, they knew that it
was the promises of God that were being fulfilled. In the second stanza we see that this
religion is not something superficial, but that it has been tested by suffering and labor, and
that it is firm in hope. Thus the character depicted to us is one in whom the virtues of
patience and hope are very great.
The Thought:
In Sacred Scripture the thought is always profound and supernatural, The thought of this
poem is twofold: (1) Great blessings come to us only from divine providence, which has
favored the Jewish nation of old and the Church today above every other people and
institution. It is noteworthy that Our Lady (who is a type of the Church) uses the last two
lines of the first stanza in her own Magnificat. (2) God will give the reward to our labors,
but we must suffer to obtain it. Thus the answer to the great philosophical problem of the
reason for evil in the world is contained in this little poem.
THE MATTER
(Means of imitation)
Words:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
This poem has in translation (and in the original) a very simple diction, suitable to its
brevity, and its direct, strong emotion. This is enriched, however, in several ways:
The verse is based on parallelism. There are two stanzas, each with four parallel couplets.
The other effects present in the Hebrew cannot be carried over into the translation.
The Action:
A traveler stops to listen to a Highland girl singing as she works in the harvest, and, musing
on the meaning of her song, comes to realize, as he rides away, that his own sorrow is only a
part of the universal sorrow expressed in the songs of humanity.
In this poem we se a catharsis of our narrow personal sorrow which takes place by
identification with the sorrows of other men and which ends in the contemplation of the
dignity of all men. It belongs to the tragic rather than the comic view of life, since our pride
in our own importance is replaced by the sense of the universal or cosmic order.
Beginning: Stanza 1: The traveler pauses and is aroused from his own thoughts to listen to
the wonderful song of the peasant girl which seems to fill the whole valley.
Middle: The middle consists in the poet's reflection on the meaning of the girls song.
Stanza 2: This homely song is more beautiful than the most exotic melody:
1. More beautiful than the song of the nightingale in an oasis in the Arabian
desert.
2. More beautiful than the song of the cuckoo in the isles of the Hebrides.
End: Stanza 4: The girl continues working, while the traveler departs carrying the song
in his heart.
Stanza 3: The images awaken a desire for understanding, which comes at the end of the
stanza.
Stanza 4: This understanding is stored in the memory and reflected upon. (Wordsworth's
famous "emotion recollected in tranquillity.")
Thus there is a movement from the external senses to the imagination, and then to the
depths of the intelligence.
The Characters:
In a lyric poem the action is reduced to a movement of emotion, which is of interest chiefly
because it reveals the character ("personality") of the singer. The poet here is waking up to
his own real self. At the beginning of the poem he is probably absorbed in narrow personal
thoughts (this is implied without being actually stated, since he compares himself in the
second stanza to someone weary of the desert or the ocean). Meeting the simple peasant
girl, he gradually begins to become. aware that between them there is a deep bond, the
bond of common humanity. As he departs he has come to realize his deeper inner self
which is greater and nobler than he had supposed.
Thus the traveler is revealed to us as a man of sensitivity and sympathy who is, however,
often dull and introverted until awakened by beauty to a realization of the deeper more
universal things of life.
The Thought:
The thought of the poem is made explicit in Stanza 3, lines 5 to 8. It is the thesis so common
in Wordsworth's writings that the deepest things of human life are not necessarily
spectacular public actions but the common experiences of all men, which may be found in
their clearest forms in the life of the common man.
This is the idea expressed by many writers of the Romantic period and emphasized by
Rousseau and other philosophers of the democratic movements of the 18th and 19th
centuries. Is it true or false? We may grant that it is true if stated in a moderate form (as in
this poem), since it is indeed true that the common consent of mankind is a strong evidence
of truth, but if taken in the exaggerated sense that "the people are always right," or that
sentiment is better than disciplined reason, it is very false.
THE MATTER
(Means of imitation)
Words:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The diction of this poem is almost perfect and deserves close study. In general it is very
simple and harmonizes with the mildness and intellectual serenity of the speaker. Many of
the words are monosyllables and of Anglo-Saxon origin, and the last stanza is plainest of
all.
Stanza 1: The apostrophes, "Behold her . . . "Stop here, or gently pass," "O listen!" are
intended to show that the poet has been suddenly brought to life by the beautiful sound; yet
because they are rather rhetorical, they give us the impression that the poet at first is
merely admiring the view and the music, and is not yet deeply affected. In this stanza there
are two dominant notes:
Stanza 2: In this stanza the words become more fanciful and unusual because the
imagination of the traveler is now aroused. Again two pictures are presented:
the morning twilight, close to shore, with the cuckoo's voice coming across
the water.
Stanza 3: This stanza is more prosaic, indicating that the poet is now trying to formulate
and rationalize his feelings. The song is in Gaelic or a dialectic, and the poet (asking himself
a rhetorical question) wishes for a translator. He can only guess the meaning for himself.
Again there are two distinct ideas:
Stanza 4: The last stanza suddenly shifts tense to the past, indicating that the action of the
poem is reaching its end. The traveler sees the girl move away, becoming a symbol. Her
song has "no ending" as she keeps working on, moving into the distance. The last half of
the stanza brings the traveler into objective relief and we finally sees that he is a traveler
who must move on. He stands for a moment, then moves on, but as he goes he find himself
changed. The music (i.e., the realization of the universality of human problems) remains in
his heart. The words in the last two lines are the simplest of the poem (all monosyllables
except music and after). The last line, "Long after it was heard no more," indicates very
plainly the movement of the whole poem, namely, a passage from the mere hearing of a
sound to a change of inner attitude of mind and the heart.
We have noticed the symmetry of the four stanzas: a beginning, a middle of two episodes,
and a conclusion. The first three stanzas form an ascending movement (sensation,
imagination, reflection), and the last is a summary balanced against the other three and
contrasted to them by its tense. In each stanza there are two quatrains, each of which has
its own unity:
8. I go away changed.
This parallelism is so exact that it gives the poem a classic balance and strength which
sustains its delicate mood.
The rhyme scheme is a b a b c c d d, except that in the first and last stanzas the a lines
do not rhyme, although they have the very imperfect rhymes field - self, and sang - work.
This imperfection is hardly a fault, since it mutes the rhyme which might seem too assertive
and does not jar us (frequently in quatrains only two lines rhyme). The use of two couplets
(c c d d) in the second half of each stanza helps make a more intense ending, and in each
case the emotional tension of the words is also greater. The lines are iambic tetrameter,
which is appropriate because it is the most ordinary rhythm, often used in folk-songs. It is
varied by frequent trochaic Movements (reaping, breaking, etc.). There are frequent breaks
in the lines: "Behold her/single in the field," "Stop here/or gently pass," "O listen/ for the
vale profound." These seem to indicate the pausing motion of the traveler. In the second
stanza each half is grammatically and rhythmically very smooth. The fourth stanza has a
rather prosaic, but gentle rhythm. In the last stanza there is a marked antithetical effect,
couplet by couplet, which indicates the contrast and separation between singer and traveler
who now part.
Throughout the poem here is a very smooth, gentle, melancholy melody. In the first stanza
this is indicated by the onomatopoeia of "melancholy strain," "Oh listen! for the vale
profound/Is overflowing with the sound." The last stanza in its last part is filled with m
sounds which give it a muted, quiet effect. Throughout the poem there is a great use of 1,
m, n, sounds which contribute to its smooth flow.
Our interpretation of this poem is confirmed by the fact that Dorothy Wordsworth, the
poet's sister, tells us that the poem was " suggested to William by a beautiful sentence in
Thomas Wilkinson's Tour in Scotland." This sentence contained the thought found in the
last two lines of the poem. We thus see that the poet began with this "formative idea" of the
change wrought in our attitude by listening to folk-songs and from this his poem took
shape, using the Scottish setting.
1. There is in admixture of the 18th century rhetorical style. Notice "Behold," "Yon,"
"Stop here or gently pass!", "O listen!", "melancholy strain," "vale profound," "chaunt,"
"Will not someone tell me what she sings?", "plaintive numbers," "humble Jay,"
"What'er the theme." Are not these clichés?
Answer: It will be noticed that most of these expressions, except " melancholy" and "vale,"
appear in parts of the poem which are more reflective and hence properly somewhat more
prosaic and conventional. "Chaunt" is appropriate precisely because it is archaic and fits
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
the exotic imagery of the first part of the second stanza. The phrases "melancholy strain"
and "vale profound" are justified by the magnificent sound effect which they give.
Answer: The poem is not intended to be intellectually intricate. its subtlety comes, not from
the ideas, but from the gradual movement from the exterior sensation to the interior
change of attitude. This last stanza does not break the unity of the work, since it is still
concrete and experiential. The traveler sees the girl move away, and as he departs is
surprised to find the continuance of her song in his changed attitude. It will be especially
noticed that the sound of these last lilies with their o's are a wonderful echo of the sound
given at the end of the first stanza.
3. The catharsis is incomplete, since we still do not understand why men must suffer.
Answer: It is true that this poem remains at a somewhat shallow level, typical of much
romantic poetry. Nevertheless, its resolution is not a false one, since such experiences do
give us a more universal outlook, and it is proportionate to the brevity and
unpretentiousness of the poem.
Conclusion: We have here a very perfect lyric, especially notable for a well-maintained
tone, for the way in which its sound sustains the meaning, and for its balance between
sensation, imagination, feeling, and reflection. It is somewhat weak in thought content, and
its emotion is very passive.
Shined in my angel-infancy!
Before I understood this place
Appointed for my second race,
Or taught my soul to fancy aught
But a white, celestial thought;
When yet I had not walked above
A mile or two from my first love,
And looking back at that short space,
Could see a glimpse of His bright face;
When on some gilded cloud or flower
My gazing soul would dwell an hour,
And in those weaker glories spy
Some shadows of eternity;
Before I taught my tongue to wound
My conscience with a sinful sound,
Or had the black art to dispense
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The Action:
Plot:
A man meditates on his childhood and is crushed by the thought of his fall from innocence
until be realizes he can regain it by a Christian death.
Middle:
In this plot the catharsis moves from a joy recollected in sorrow, through fear to hope, and
ends in a resigned courage. Thus the poem as a whole is sorrowful throughout, but the
sorrow changes from the intense pain of the contrast between recollected joy and present
misery, to patience (resigned courage). There is a resolution or catharsis, but of the
imperfect sort found in sorrowful songs and poems. How can we say that this is an end to
the poem, when it seems like a return to the beginning? It is an end in that it implies a firm
determination of the will to return to innocence. This action belongs to the class of the
tragic, but since this is a lyric the poet does not actually show us moral determination and
decision but only an attitude which is habitual with him. In other words, a lyric rather
emphasizes character (a habitual condition) than action in the full sense.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Character:
Since this is a lyric, character is emphasized. The person speaking, is deeply spiritual, early
awakened to the reality of spiritual things, but this spiritual clarity has become confused by
the trials and failures of life. Yet his sins are not malicious since he continues to realize
keenly his spiritual destiny. He is a person who feels himself different from others, a
stranger in this world. Others look forward to worldly success. He feels himself to be one
who is fortunate to regain what he has lost. He is of a temperament inclined to reflection, a
character rather sensitive and timid, yet deep in his faith and firm in his ultimate
determination. This is shown us through the intense contrast he feels between his ideal and
the actuality of his own character; but it is not confused feeling, it is a feeling which is
clearheaded and rational.
Thought:
This poem emphasizes thought rather than emotion. The thought is in the terms of
Christian theology. The speaker sees himself in childhood as living in the state of grace
through baptism, close to the angelic world, separated from the ways of this world, and
with charity toward God. His faith then was enlightened by the gifts of the Holy Spirit so
that he could almost see God, and could know his reflection in the beauties of nature. Then
sin came to him first by the sins of the tongue (lying, uncharitable speech), then by a
yielding to the sins of the five senses. Before his body had something of the purity of the
glorified body; now it is wounded.
Thus in the first part of the poem he pictured baptismal innocence in clear terms. In the
last part he sees the good life as a straight path through this world to heaven, which lies
ahead like an oasis in the desert. He bewails his departure from this plain path. He can
conceive his goal ahead only by recalling what he has left behind. Nevertheless, his faith
makes him confident that he can regain innocence at death. The last stanza states very
clearly the ambiguity of the state of the Christian who falters in his way, who is at once
alive and dead, and who waits for death to become fully alive once more. It is not a mere
pious platitude which he utters, but the real experience of a man struggling with himself.
Words:
The diction is very simple but achieves a certain richness by a few vivid and surprising
touches that are borrowed from the imagery of the liturgy and the technical language of
theology.
The first sentence sets the tone of the poem by an exclamation which is like a sigh. "Shined
in my angel-infancy" contains a paradoxical idea, since a child is not an angel. "Before I
understood this place/Appointed for my second race": Here we have the idea that the child
is placed in a strange home which is unsuited to it, and which it views with surprise and
alarm to find that it must run a new race on a new path, so different from the angelic paths
which seem natural to it. The notion of the path is the basic image of the poem. "Or taught
my soul to fancy aught/But a White celestial thought" indicates that the child was in a
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
sense his own teacher, since he learned to sin only by his own free will. "White celestial
thought" echoes the angel image, so that throughout the poem the
"While yet I had not walked above/A mile or two from my first love" the image of the path
continues. Note the simplicity of diction in the following line: "And looking back at that
short space/Could see a glimpse of His bright face." The child is pictured as walking away
from its father, making its first steps, but turning back to the father for encouragement.
Note the mysterious quality of the description of God only as a "bright face." "When on
some gilded cloud or flower/My gazing soul would dwell an hour, /And in those weaker
glories spy, /Some shadows of eternity." As the child continues in the path he stops to
admire a flower, or a cloud in the distance. They are "gilded" because their beauty is not
their own, but comes from the sun of God's face. This beauty is now only a shadow.
"Before I taught" recalls the third line, "Before I understood." Again the child teaches
himself to sin by lying. The tongue "wounds the conscience with a sinful sound," because
the tongue is sharp, lying, and uncharitable. "Sinful sound" suggests the amazement of the
child to find himself telling a he. He hears his own voice with amazement, he had never
thought that he would be a liar. "Or had the black art to dispense/A several sin to every
sense." "Black art" is diabolic magic, and indicates the strange perverse cleverness of
deliberate sin. "Black" contrasts with the image of light and whiteness that has pervaded
the first part of the poem. The words "dispense" and "several" indicate the deliberate
character of sensuality. The notion of the sin of the five senses recalls the ritual of the
sacrament of extreme unction, in which each sense is anointed to remove the sin committed
through it. The final lines of the stanza. "But felt through this fleshy dress/Bright roots of
everlastingness," very vividly indicate that the body was originally intended as the pilgrim
garment underneath which was hidden the inner glory of baptismal innocence destined for
eternity. The term "roots" indicates the idea of scholastic theology that the powers of the
body, in this case the senses, are rooted in the essence of the soul. It also indicates the idea
that "race is the "seed of glory," intended to grow up to the full fruition of eternal life.
The second part of the poem is marked by a new exclamation: "Oh, how I long to travel
back/And tread again that ancient track." The track or path to heaven is ancient, not
merely because he trod it in his own youth, but because it is the path to heaven which all
the saints from Adam on have taken. "That I might once more reach that plain/Where first
I left my glorious train, /Front whence the enlightened spirit sees/The shady city of palm
trees." The path passes through a plain, not through mountains, because it is the straight,
low way of humility, and on it march the whole caravan of glorious beings who follow the
light of spiritual faith to a shady city of palm trees, the place of rest and of victory.
Undoubtedly we have here the familiar Old Testament and liturgical image of the Hebrews
marching across the plain through the desert to the promised land and the Holy City.
Notice the use of the image of light again, of shade as the symbol of rest, and of the fertile
oasis city as a new garden of paradise which is like the final flowering of the roots spoken of
previously.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The last part of the poem also has a sigh: "But ah! my soul with too much stay/Is drunk,
and staggers in the way." This is perhaps the most intense and dramatic couplet of the
poem, marking the beginning of the resolution. "Stay" indicates the weariness of the
journey, like that of the Hebrews. The intoxication is the dizziness both of weariness and
despair through which many stragglers drop out of the caravan and wander from the path.
"Some men a forward motion love" is perhaps the strangest line of the poem. It is an
abstract scholastic statement, the familiar philosophical principle that motion goes toward
a term and that love sets this term. This line prefaces the intellectual paradox which is the
conclusion of the poem, and its oddity and abstractness arouse our attention. "But I by
backward steps would move,/And when this dust falls in the urn,/In that state I came,
return." Notice the complexity of the motion indicated. There is a forward motion, a falling
motion of the dust, and a returning motion of the soul set free from the body. The thought
is suspended until the last word. To "go back" is ordinarily to fail, but the poet sees this as
really a return to his goal, since he has fallen from the way. The dust of the body sifting
into the urn is chosen as something utterly sterile and dark, in contrast to the images of
growth and light.
Rhythm: The grammar of the poem makes it fall into the following symmetrical
arrangement, each major part beginning with an exclamation:
The meter is iambic tetrameter, but with very frequent trochaic beginnings of lines (e.g.,
first two lines). The use of frequent spondees or heavy endings of lines ("second race,"
"fancy aught," "first love," " short space," "bright face," "sinful sound," "
everlastingness," "Palm trees," etc.) makes the movement of the verse slow and sad in
sound, an effect also increased by the constant use of lines loaded with words of one syllable
("When yet I had not walked above/A mile or two from my first love," or "That I might
once more reach that plain"). Notice also the effective rhythm of "Is drunk, and staggers
by the way," which seems to stagger, and the completeness of the closing line "In that state
I came, return."
Melody: Throughout the sound is sombre, but with a contrast between high sounds ("But a
white, celestial thought," etc.), symbolic of light, and the prevailing low tones. There is
constant modulation of vowel sounds as in "When on some gilded cloud or flower/My
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
gazing soul would dwell an hour,/And in those weaker glories see /Some shadows of
eternity," where there is a wonderful variation between faint and deep tones. Notice, for
example, the phrase "weaker glories" where the word "glories" is an organ-toned word,
while weaker" is very faint and lifeless. Notice also the hissing in "My conscience with a
sinful sound" and ". . . to dispense a several sin to every sense." The use of rhyme
throughout contributes both to the sombre and meditative rhythm, and to an emphasis on
the thought. Notice how frequently the rhyme word contributes an important element to
the thought.
Might we not say that there is something unhealthy in the poet's idea that Christian
perfection is simply regressing to childhood innocence? Is it not pessimistic and Calvinist in
tone! This is undoubtedly a poem in the style of Mannerism. Mannerism was an artistic
transition movement which liked to picture ambiguous, uneasy effects, in which the
catharsis seemed incomplete. Its purpose was to indicate the reality of the other life in
contrast to the darkness and confusion of our world. The pictures of El Greco are
wonderful examples of this tendency. Vaughn is entirely Christian in his concept that we
must become like little children to enter the kingdom of heaven. In order to make us wake
up to this too familiar truth, he states it in terms of a personal confession and in a
paradoxical style.
These two poems really form a single poem, since the second answers the first and shows
the superiority of the life of contemplation to the life of pleasure. Hence they can best be
analyzed together.
The Action:
A young man delights in thinking of a life of innocent pleasure in the country and the, city,
then reflects on the higher delights of the life of contemplation in the enjoyment of nature,
of reading, of meditation, and of prayer, and judges these as the greater.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Beginning (L'Allegro, lines 1-10): The young man dismisses Melancholy (his conception of
the contemplative life) and calls upon Mirth.
Middle:
Apparent ending: The young man resolves to live always with mirth (last couplet of
L'Allegro).
New Beginning: (Il Penseroso, lines 1-10): The young man now dismisses Mirth and calls
on Melancholy.
Middle continued:
True end: The young man resolves to choose the contemplative life.
The catharsis in this poem comes from the fact that the young man passes from a fear of
melancholy at the beginning, and a delight only in more superficial pleasures, to a
realization that what he feared can be a higher joy. Thus there is a reversal by which what
first appeared sorrowful turns out to be joyful.
The Characters:
There is a single character who has two phases. He is a young man sensitive to all the
variety of life and finding it hard to decide what he really wants. He imaginatively enters
into both ways of life, and finds both good. The pleasure to which he is attracted is an
honorable and temperate pleasure, not a dissipated one. Hence it is natural that a person of
this noble temperament would be even more attractive by the higher pleasure of the
contemplative life. The special beauty of this poem is the way in which it succeeds in
showing two contrasting moods as both very good, although one is better than the other.
The poem does not actually say that the character is a young man, but it is manifest from
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
the fact that he is still deliberating on a choice of life. In a mature man such variation of
mood would not be appropriate.
In order, however, to make the description more concrete, the device of personification is
used. Thus Mirth is pictured is a beautiful young goddess (see the famous picture of
Botticelli called The Allegory of Spring accompanied by a gay crew of gods and nymphs,
but then dismissed in the second part as a fantastic dream. Melancholy is pictured as a
hideous, dark-clad figure with snaky locks accompanied by a raven, but then is
transformed in the second poem into a virgin goddess like a Nun, walking with her quiet
companions, but preceded by Contemplation who is a winged Cherub that guides
a fiery-chariot by which she (Melancholy) may return to heaven and become Joy.
The Thought:
The poem has little of thought. Since the young speaker has only an imaginative insight
into the two lives he depicts, he does not have any real intellectual understanding of their
significance, which would be inappropriate to his age. Nevertheless, it is the work of a
young man of keen intelligence occupied at the moment with observing the English country
and town life about him, and relating it to his studies of the Latin and Greek classics.
THE MATTER
(Means of imitation)
Words:
We have already mentioned the use of personification and of classical allusion. Note that in
the first poem the characters are revealed to us through their laughter and their dancing
motions, as a crew following their leader in a kind of bacchanal, while in the second poem
we seem to see a solemn procession.
After these very formal openings to the poems, the succeeding descriptions are wonderfully
fresh and real, although classical allusions and English folklore are mixed with observation
to give it greater richness. It will be noted that Milton is rather sparing in the use of purely
visual words, but uses many sound effects (the birds, the cock, the hounds and horn, the
echoes, the whistling plowman, the singing milkmaid, the counting shepherd, the bells, the
musical instruments, the stories, the flail, the wind, the hum of the city, the sound of
revelry, the poetry of plays, etc.). Notice also the constant use of verbals (see lines 64 to 72
of the first poem, for example).
In the first work the general symbol of a lively dance moves through the entire poem in its
two cycles and gives the impression of a rapidly shifting, colorful display. In the second
poem the grave procession or quiet walk with frequent pauses is felt. In the first poem
sunlight and torchlight are emphasized. In the second, moonlight and firelight. A detailed
study will bring out a wonderful felicity in almost every word.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Rhythm:
We have already noted that the first poem has a dancing effect, the second the effect of a
quiet stroll. The opening of each poem is in alternate trimeter and pentameter lines, which
gives each a slow opening and then moves into the very smooth meter of the tetrameters of
the rest of each poem. The basic meter is really iambic tetrameter, but in order to get a
dancing effect in the first poem, Milton makes most of it trochaic by starting lines with an
accented syllable. Frequent feminine endings ("offended-descended") give lightness to the
movement of both poems. The wonderful variety of meter in both poems is beyond praise.
For example:
Notice how here "midnight hour" and "high lonely tower" give the heavy sense of
loneliness and elevation. The run-on line, "or unsphere the spirit of Plato," gives an eery
quality by breaking the regular rhythm, while the subsequent three lines run together to
give the impression of the soaring spirit. The line, "In fire, air, flood, or underground," is
like a magical incantation.
Melody:
The fluidity of sound is wonderful and abounds in special effects (the description of
Shakespeare's verse in the first poem, line 134, or of the organ, second poem, line 161 ff.).
The use of rhyme is appropriate in poems which have a light, imaginative character, and
used here with a mixture of masculine and feminine endings and run-on lines is not at all
tedious.
For a fine study of the verse of these poems see Hilaire Belloc, Milton (Philadelphia: J. P.
Lippencott, 1935) pp. 98 ff. Belloc feels that Il Penseroso does not quite sustain the level of
the first poem, and contains some weak lines, for example, "Or if the air will not permit"
(line 77).
The Action:
A poet ponders the relation of writing to criticism, conceding that a poem must meet
critical standards, rejecting the unfairness of criticism, and yet submitting his own work to
the judgment of any fair critic.
Beginning: The paradox of the poet and the critic; their apparent conflict (I, lines 1-8).
Middle:
A. The true role of a critic (Part 1, lines 9 ff.).
1. Nature is the true standard of poetry.
a. A true critic is as rare as a great poet (9-18).
b. Yet taste is natural to men before they are spoiled (10-25).
c. Why so many wish to be critics (26-45).
d. We ought to know our own limits as critics (46-67).
e. But we must form our judgment by nature (68-87).
f. And improve it by a knowledge of the rules, which are nature methodized (88).
2. The classics embody this standard, and are therefore our models.
a. The rules of ancient poetry (88-110).
b. We must study these models, especially Homer and Vergil (120-138).
c. Licenses from the rules (140-180).
d. Praise of the ancient poets (181-200).
B. The obstacles to just criticism (Part II).
1. Pride (201-214).
2. Ignorance.
a. Little learning (215-232).
b. Judging by parts and not the whole (233-288).
3. Prejudice.
a. Singling out one's pet interest (289-383).
b. Being too critical or too lavish in praise (384-393).
c. Partiality to some sect, ancient or modern (394-407).
d. Pure prejudice (408-423).
e. Singularity (424-429).
f. Inconstancy (430-451).
g. Party-spirit (452-455).
4. Envy,
a. Envy (456-507).
b. Praise of good nature in a critic (50S-525).
c. Severity is sometimes necessary (526-558).
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The Characters:
The poet reveals himself as sensitive, disturbed by conflict, zealous for his honor as a poet,
but resolved to maintain his integrity in the face of unjust criticism by adherence to the
rules of his art. He wishes above all to be all artist who is balanced.
In the poem he characterizes many types of good and bad poets and good and bad critics.
The method of characterization is that of epigram, that is of brief witty statements that
seize on some significant detail. These characterizations are often individual, but are
intended to indicate types. See for example the Flattering Critic (416-421-3), the Hyper
critic (610-629) or the Learned Critic (4224-429).
Thought:
In a didactic poem the thought is the dominant object of imitation. The poet does not
merely present us thought in the abstract, but as a concrete expression of the personal
attitude of the character who speaks. The whole poem is like the witty remarks of a
character in a play or novel and is to be judged such as a speech would be judged, more as
the clever presentation of a point of view, than as pure doctrine.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The ideas which the speaker presents are not original but are largely derived from
Boileau's L'Art Poetique (1647), which in turn is based on the Ars Poetica of Horace (about
10 B.C.) and were commonplace in Pope's time. This theory of poetry is by no means equal
to that of Aristotle, since it chiefly emphasizes style, rather than the imitation of action, as
the principal element of poetry, and thus tends to confuse poetics and rhetoric. Although
inadequate, it is sound as far as it goes, and Pope illustrates it very aptly from his own
personal experience with critics. Throughout, however, we have the narrow-minded
rationalism so common in the 18th century (notice the stock criticisms against the
scholastic thought of the Middle Ages in lines 440-446, for example). The chief
characteristic of this thought is that it is clear, reasonable, balanced, yet vigorous in
its concrete human examples drawn from life, and in its brilliant wit.
THE MATTER
(Means of imitation)
Words:
Pope has a remarkable ability to use this conventional diction in order to give subtle effects
(as in lines 484-493), or to combine it smoothly with colloquial conversation (as in lines 279-
283).
Rhythm:
The heroic rimed couplet is used by Pope because it makes possible a very smooth type of
verse, in which the antithesis of ideas is clearly marked by the parallelism of the lines and
the rhyme, and which at the same time permits great variety. It is in giving this constant,
shifting variety without destroying the smoothness and balance that Pope excels. Study, for
example, the variety found in lines 68-78.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Melody:
The most remarkable example in this poem is, of course, the famous passage on style (lines
337-382) in which Pope himself gives examples of sound effects. Study also lines 626-642, or
the highly "rhetorical" passage in lines 181-200, where be so successfully gets a volume of
sound.
The Action:
The "essay" may be poetic, rhetorical, dialectical, or scientific. What is often called "the
familiar essay" is frequently poetic. It resembles the didactic poem in that it emphasizes
thought, and reduces the action to a certain emotional experience. It differs from dialectical
or scientific writing in that it is intended to express the thought or attitude of a concrete
personality who is revealed to us this way, and it differs from rhetoric in that its principal
purpose is to amuse us.
A man expresses his pleasure in traveling alone where be can take in the view without
explaining his reactions to anyone, enjoy living at an inn without immediate cares, and
escape his ordinary point of view, but he prefers to have company when visiting ruins or
ancient buildings, or when abroad, and does not wish to get too far from home.
Middle:
1. I can best take in the view without having to express my thoughts and
feelings to others.
2. I even prefer to be alone when stopping at an inn, where I can eat, think,
imagine, and read by myself.
3. When traveling, one's whole point of view toward things changes.
4. However, I would like companions when visiting ruins, or when abroad.
The Characters:
Somewhat in the manner of a lyric poem, the speaker reveals to us a definite personality
(which, of course, is an artistic creation; it need not be the true character of the writer). We
see this speaker as a very lively, observant man, who makes little attempt to organize his
thoughts systematically, but who would rather absorb as many impressions as possible. He
is sociable, but be often finds that be cannot communicate his lively sympathies to others.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
He is incorrigibly English, devoted to the democratic ideal, and very much attached to
home.
In the course of the essay he also paints other incidental characters for us, for example, his
friends Coleridge and Lamb, and the guide at Blenheim castle. These serve only to
illustrate and enliven his own impressions.
The Thought:
In this essay the thought is very light, and is principally psychological. Hazlitt is telling us
about the psychological laws which require us to take in impressions from outside before
we have any material to think about, and he shows us how being alone and in a strange
place may greatly heighten our receptivity to our surroundings, but that if the place is too
strange we are so upset that we are less observant.
THE MATTER
(Means of imitation)
Words:
We notice at once that Hazlitt's style is a very easy and lively one. His sentences are short
and varied. In general the vocabulary is simple and direct, a very pure kind of English, but
he enlivens it by many devices. Among these are his use of quotations (poetic and prose,
and even in foreign languages), his allusions to books, places, events, characters which we
need to recognize and which bring to mind a host of associations. He also makes use of
vivid little descriptions, and he is constantly speaking of things in terms that display his
personal emotional reaction to them. We are made to feel that be reacts to everything about
him; nothing is merely stated in an objective fashion. Metaphor is also used with effect.
If studied carefully, this essay will indicate how a prose style can be colorful without
becoming poetic.
In prose it is necessary to avoid a rhythm that is too pronounced. Hazlitt attempts to keep
his prose running along very rapidly, and constantly varies its pace. The student will easily
discover some of the methods which he uses to achieve this, if he reads the essay aloud,
trying to give it the informality and liveliness of good conversation.
SECTION V
[ * It is not certain whether this great speech was accurately reported by Plato, or composed by him on the
basis of the historical facts.]
Although Socrates is apparently pleading for acquittal, he does not expect to achieve this, and his
real purpose is to exhort the Athenians to virtue. He believes that, although in the heat of mob-
violence they will condemn him, later they will remember his words, and these words will have
their effect. Consequently, he aims above all at leaving an indelible impression on their minds.
OUTLINE
Introduction (17-18):
1. He will plead his case very simply, since he was never on trial before.
2. 2. He will take up the old charges first, because they have bad the deepest influence on the jury.
Socrates does not make a separate exposition, because the charges against him have already been
stated by other speakers. He merely repeats them in the course of giving arguments to refute
them.
I: What kind of speech? It is judicial since the speaker wishes the audience to pass judgement
on a past action; yet its ultimate purpose is political, looking to the future,
1. In the introduction Socrates at once tries to establish his character with his audience.
a. He shows his intelligence by his ironic wit in pretending that the other speakers have almost
convinced him of his own guilt.
b. He shows his good moral character by indicating that, although he is an old man, he was never
before brought into court on any charge.
c. He shows his good will by saving that he is amazed that the other speakers had warned the jury
that he was a clever speaker, since his real difficulty is that he is too plain-spoken, and that they
will forgive him if he, an old man, continues this habit of plain speech with them.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
2. Throughout the rest of the speech Socrates is chiefly concerned, not with obtaining an
acquittal, but with convincing them of the fact that he has always acted for a public-spirited
motive. He knows that because of their prejudices they may not accept this at once, but that it will
sink in and convince them after his death.
1. Render them of good will. This is very difficult, since they have been prejudiced from youth by
the plays of Aristophanes and by other gossip to believe him a sophist. He attempts to drag this
unconscious prejudice out into the open, so that they will ask themselves whether it really has any
solid basis.
2. Render them attentive. He promises to attack his opponents, and makes the jury anticipate an
interesting clash of wits.
3. Render them docile. He does this by a clear ordering of the charges, and by his interesting
explanation of the origin of things they have always beard, but whose foundation they had never
known. By appealing to God he also makes them realize their responsibility to listen carefully.
C. The arguments:
It would take too long to analyze each of the arguments, The outline above shows how expertly Socrates
makes use of all the methods of argumentation, enthymemes, maxims, examples, signs, etc. It will be seen
that he aims at the following:
1. He drags out into broad daylight the old, half-conscious prejudices, and showing their flimsy
foundation. This he does in the answer to old charges. (A in outline).
2. He strives to discredit his accusers by direct cross-questioning which reveals their insincerity
and stupidity. (B 1).
3. He then explains his own conduct, using a whole series of arguments drawn from literature,
history, and commonly accepted moral principles to show that his strange conduct is in
accordance with the traditions of Athens, (B 2 a).
5. And he concludes by pointing to the history of his life, and calling on the audience to witness
to it, (B 3).
Style: The style is of marvelous beauty in every respect. Notice especially the use of:
He even concludes (as Aristotle later advised) with an asyndeton or broken sentence, indicative of solemn
emotion. "The hour of departure has arrived, and we go our ways -- I to die, and you to live. Which is
better, God only knows."
Arrangement: This is shown sufficiently by the outline. Especially noteworthy are the cleverness of the
introduction and the very great beauty of the conclusion.
This is, of course, an epistle on a spiritual topic, and nevertheless it is very similar to a political
speech. In it St. Paul writes as he would have spoken to the Galatians if he had been present, and
seeks to lead them to a definite course of action as a community.
Conclusion: In the future put your faith in Christ and do not worry about the ceremonies of the
Old Law.
OUTLINE
Introduction:
1. Greetings (1:1-5).
2. Appeal to their attention (1:6-10).
Argumentation:
A. Doctrinal arguments:
1. Justification is from faith in Christ and not from the Old Law.
a. Proved by the Galatians' own experience (3:1-6).
b. Proved by the example of Abraham (3:7-29).
2. The Christian life is a life of freedom:
a. Proved from the nature of slavery and freedom (4:1-20).
b. Proved by the example of Ismael and Isaac (21-31).
B. Practical application:
1. General counsel: Do not depend on the ceremonies of the Law,
but on the New Law of Charity (5:1-26).
2. Special counsels:
a. Fraternal correction (6:1-5).
b. Good works (6:6-10).
I. What kind of speech? It is a political speech, since it aims at leading this community to a
definite future action, namely, the rejection of Jewish ceremonies and the following of St. Paul's
leadership and of his teaching on faith in Christ and the commandments of the New Law.
St. Paul in this epistle especially aims at showing his character by a very frank revelation of his feelings:
a. He shows his intelligence (see especially 1:11-24) by showing that he was educated in the
Jewish Law, but that his teaching comes from God and not from men, and is approved also by the
authorities of the Church.
b. He shows his good moral character by referring to his conversion (1:15), and his acceptance
by the apostles (1:18 and 2:6-10), and his courage in rebuking even St. Peter (2:11-14).
c. He shows his good will toward the Galatians by his whole tone of indignation and loving
anxiety in chapters 1 and 2. What better proof that a man seeks our welfare than that he is so
disturbed and broken-hearted to hear of our difficulties?
The whole narration of Chapter 2 is especially devoted to giving the history of St. Paul and showing what
kind of man he was.
The occasion of the epistle was the news that his Galatian converts, mostly Gentiles, were being
won over by certain "false brethren" to the doctrine that Gentile converts to Christianity had to
keep the Jewish law as Christ and the apostles did. Acceptance of this doctrine would logically
have led to the conclusion that faith in Christ and the redemption of the Cross were insufficient
for salvation, and would have made the conversion of the Gentiles very difficult. These Judaizers
had gone to Antioch (Acts 15:1 ff.) and there, it seems, had wrongly alleged that all the apostles
taught their views, hence that St. Paul was no real apostle. Then some of them had come to
Galatia and spread the same story.
Their chief argument was that the Law of Moses was everlasting, since Christ had said that he
did not intend to destroy the Law but to fulfill it.
St. Paul realized that his audience were sincere people, only anxious to do the right thing, but
they were Gentiles and not yet very well instructed. His method is to make them ashamed that
they have been taken in so easily, to arouse in them their rightful pride as Christians in their
newly found liberty, and finally to appeal to their generous desire to live a new and perfect life.
Thus be seeks to destroy their fear and anxiety by infusing in them a righteous anger, and a
healthy shame of their own timidity, and finally great confidence and hope.
C. The arguments:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The outline sufficiently shows the argumentation. Notice that he first speaks to them
theoretically in terms of the Bible, but then hastens to make this very practical by translating
doctrine into a way of life.
St. Paul argues both from the Galatians' own experience and from examples taken from the
Bible. The last is appropriate because this proves his own mastery of the Jewish Law, and refutes
the manner of arguing used by his opponents. He also makes use of analogy, in comparing civil
slavery and freedom to spiritual slavery and freedom.
So impassioned is St. Paul's utterance that at first sight it may not appear very logical; but if
analyzed section by section, it will be seen to be based very squarely on principles. St. Paul bases
his argument on a revealed principle which the Galatians had learned at baptism, namely, that
they had been saved by Christ crucified. However poorly instructed or ignorant they might be,
this truth had been made very clear to them and they had accepted it. Hence St. Paul begins with
this principle on which all agree (even his opponents), and argues by means of the following
enthymeme, which is stated in various ways:
If justice is from the law, then Christ died in vain (2:21). This is an abbreviated form of a
hypothetical syllogism: If justice is from the Law, then Christ died in vain.
Therefore: justice is not from the Law (i.e., you need not keep the ceremonies of the Law).
The minor of this syllogism is the principle which all the Galatians had learned and accepted and
which, therefore, St. Paul can implicitly assume.
D. Style
St. Paul's style is not polished, but fiery, vehement, with one thought tumbling after another. This
is appropriate, since it conveys his overwhelming sincerity. His hearers could not help but
believe so earnest a man. At the same time he makes very clever and careful use of scriptural
quotation and argument, and toward the end of the epistle he quiets down to simple but earnest
practical advice, given in a much calmer style.
E. Arrangement:
This is shown by the outline. Note that here St. Paul gives an especially long exposition, because
in this case he needs to make the background of the whole matter very clear. Note also that in a
letter like this the introduction and conclusion are put in a conventional form common in letters.
The following is taken from a letter written by Jefferson to Walter Jones after Washington's
death, It does not have the form of a full ceremonial speech, of course, but it well illustrates the
tone of such a speech. Since the text follows, the student may supply his own outline.
I think I knew General Washington intimately and thoroughly, and were I called on to delineate
his character, it should be in terms like these.
His mind was great and powerful., without being of the very first order; his penetration strong,
though not so acute as that of a Newton, Bacon, or Locke; and as far as he saw, no judgment was
ever sounder. It was slow in operation, being little aided by invention or imagination, but sure in
conclusion. Hence the common remark of his officers, of the advantage he derived from councils
of war, where hearing all suggestions, he selected whatever was best; and certainly no general
ever planned his battles more judiciously. But if deranged during the course of the action, if any
member of his plan was dislocated by sudden circumstances, he was slow in readjustment. The
consequence was, that he often failed in the field, and rarely against an enemy in station as at
Boston and York. He was incapable of fear, meeting personal dangers with the calmest
unconcern. Perhaps the strongest feature in his character was prudence, never acting until every
circumstance, every consideration, was maturely weighed; refraining if he saw a doubt, but,
when once decided, going through with his purpose, whatever obstacles opposed. His integrity
was most pure, his justice the most inflexible I have ever known, no motives of interest or
consanguinity, of friendship or hatred, being able to bias his decision. He was, indeed, in every
sense of the words, a wise, a good, and a great man. His temper was naturally irritable and high
toned; but reflection and resolution had obtained a firm and habitual ascendency over it. If ever,
however, it broke its bonds, he was most tremendous in his wrath. In his expenses he was
honorable, but exact; liberal in contributions to whatever promised utility; but frowning and
unyielding on all visionary projects, and all unworthy calls on his charity. His heart was not
warm in its affections; but be exactly calculated every man's value, and gave him a solid esteem
proportioned to it. His person, you know, was fine, his stature exactly what one would wish, his
deportment easy, erect, and noble, the best horseman of his age, and the most graceful figure that
could be seen on horseback. Although in the circle of his friends, where he might be unreserved
with safety, he took a free share in conversation, his colloquial talents were not above
mediocrity, possessing neither copiousness of ideas, nor fluency of words. In public, when called
on for a sudden opinion, he was unready, short, and embarrassed. Yet be wrote readily, rather
diffusely, in an easy and correct style. This he had acquired by conversation with the world, for
his education was merely reading, writing, and common arithmetic, to which he added surveying
at a later day. His time was employed in action chiefly, reading little, and that only in agriculture
and English history. His correspondence became necessarily extensive, and, with journalizing his
agricultural proceedings, occupied most of his leisure hours within doors. On the whole, his
character was, in its mass, perfect, in nothing bad, in few points indifferent; and it may truly be
said, that never did nature and fortune combine more perfectly to make a man great, and to place
him in the same constellation with whatever worthies have merited from man an everlasting
remembrance. For his was the singular destiny and merit, of leading, the armies of his country
successfully through all arduous war, for the establishment of its independence; of conducting its
councils through the birth of a government, new in its forms and principles, until it had settled
down into a quiet and orderly train; and of scrupulously obeying the laws through the whole of
his career, civil and military, of which the history of the world furnishes no other example.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
How, then, can it be perilous for you to take such a man on your shoulders? I am satisfied that
the great body of republicans think of him as I do. We were, indeed, dissatisfied with him on his
ratification of the British treaty. But this was short lived. We knew his honesty, the wiles with
which he was encompassed, and that age had already begun to relax the firmness of his purposes;
and I am convinced he is more deeply seated in the love and gratitude of the republicans, than in
the Pharisaical homage of the federal monarchists. For he was no monarchist from preferences of
his judgment. The soundness of that gave him correct views of the rights of man, and his severe
justice devoted him to them. He has often declared to me that he considered our new
Constitution as an experiment on the practicability of republican government, and with what
dose of liberty man could be trusted for his own good; that he was determined the experiment
should have a fair trial, and would lose the last drop of his blood in support of it. And these
declarations he repeated to me the oftener and more pointedly, because he knew my suspicions
of Colonel Hamilton's views, and probably had heard from him the same declarations which I
had, to wit, "that the, British constitution, with its unequal representation, corruption, and other
existing abuses, was the most perfect government on earth, and that a reformation of those
abuses would make it impracticable government." I do believe that General Washington had not
a firm confidence in the durability of our government. He was naturally distrustful of men, and
inclined to gloomy apprehensions; and I was ever persuaded that a belief that we must at length
end in something like a British constitution, had some weight in his adoption of the ceremonies
of levees, birthdays, pompous meetings with Congress, and other forms of the same character,
calculated to prepare us gradually for a change which he believed possible, and to let it come on
with as little shock as might be to the public mind.
These are my opinions of General Washington, which I would vouch at the judgment seat of
God, having been formed on acquaintance of thirty years. I served with him in the Virginia
legislature from 1769 to the Revolutionary War, and again, a short time in Congress, until he left
us to take command of the army. During the war and after it we corresponded occasionally, and
in the four years of my continuance in the office of Secretary of State, our intercourse was daily,
confidential, and cordial, After I retired from that office, great and malignant pains were taken by
our federal monarchists, and not entirely without effect, to make him view me as a theorist,
holding French principles of government, which would lead infallibly to licentiousness and
anarchy. And to this he listened the more easily, from my known disapprobation of the British
treaty. I never saw him afterwards, or these malignant insinuations should have been dissipated
before his judgment, as mist before the sun. I felt on his death, with my countrymen, that 'verily
a great man hath fallen this day in Israel.'
More time and recollection would enable me to add many other traits of his character but why
add them to you who knew him well? And I cannot justify to myself a longer detention of your
paper.
ANALYSIS
Conclusion: George Washington was a man of greatest integrity who would have remained
Jefferson's friend if he had not been deceived by slanderers.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
This letter was written when many eulogies of Washington were being made, and people were
curious what Jefferson, who had once been close to Washington and then had become his chief
political opponent, really thought of him. This was embarrassing, since Jefferson could not
denounce a great man admired by all and recently dead, and on the other hand be could not
praise the former leader of the other political party. It is therefore a letter similar to a ceremonial
speech, but one given in awkward circumstances, demanding considerable tact. Jefferson
undoubtedly knew that this letter might very well get into public print.
Jefferson wishes to appear as one who knew Washington very well and has a right to speak about
him (this shows Jefferson's intelligence); he also wishes to appear as one who is very fair and
objective, able to appreciate the good qualities even of an opponent (this shows Jefferson's good
character); and be wishes to show that he and the members of his party (called "Republican" but
actually the first form of our present Democratic Party) were never opposed to Washington as an
individual (this shows their good will to the public, i.e., they have only opposed Washington for
the public good, and not for personal motives).
He achieves this by his tone of great moderation. He avoids everything that would be undignified
or envious, although he makes occasional thrusts at his opponents (e.g., "I am convinced he is
more deeply seated in the love and 'gratitude of the republicans, than in the Pharasaical homage
of the federal monarchists").
Jefferson knows very well that the public admires Washington's memory and would never
endure any attack on it. On the other band, be also knows that many of them fear a return to
strong one-man government. Hence be takes care to praise Washington, but to imply that he was
too favorable to the Federalist Party and filled by the Federalists with pessimistic fears about
democracy. By showing these two sides of Washington he hopes to leave the impression in the
audience that Washington was a great man, but that his party is dangerous to popular liberties
and is only using Washington's prestige to further this aim.
Jefferson realized that "the people" are always afraid that their liberties will be removed by some
group of powerful men, and are easily made suspicious of such groups. He also knows that " the
people" are likely to be hero-worshipers and hence to accept a party which had so great a leader
as Washington.
3. The arguments:
1. First he gives a very balanced picture of Washington's great qualities, and his limitations.
These limitations make the picture seem realistic and convincing. We are inclined to be sceptical
of a eulogy which mentions only good points. His general point is that Washington was a man of
very solid character, but somewhat limited in his intellectual capacity. (First paragraph).
2. He then shows that Washington had a rather tentative belief in the republican form of
government. He wished to give it a fair trial, but he was really sceptical it would succeed.
3. He then explains that Washington became estranged from him both because of the gossip of
the Federalists and because of lack of confidence in republican government.
The conclusion obviously is that Washington was a man of great character, but of very real
limitations, which explain his failure to support Jefferson's party. Thus the letter consists in the
use of two devices: amplification of Washington's moral character, diminution of his political
judgment in supporting the Federalist Party.
III. Style:
This letter does not have all the polish of some of Jefferson's more famous writings. It shows,
however, the carefully balanced and clear sentences common in the prose of the eighteenth and
early nineteenth century. It conveys the impression of "good-sense" and moderation.
The student will notice that some of the words would seem strange today in Jefferson's usage.
For example, "his colloquial talents," "pompous meetings," etc.
IV. Arrangement:
The arrangement is simple and orderly. Jefferson states his purpose and then devotes a paragraph
to each of the three points of the argument given above, although these paragraphs seem
somewhat long for present day style.
SECTION VI
Samuel Adams (1722-1803) was one of the chief leaders of the American Revolution, and
remained throughout his life a supporter of those who favored more democracy in government,
allying himself with Jefferson's party. His second-cousin, John Adams (17351826), the second
president of the United States, who had been with Jefferson on the committee which drew up the
Declaration of Independence, was inclined to an aristocratic form of government, and was a
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
leader of the Federalist Party which opposed that of Jefferson. The following are excerpts from
the correspondence between these men in 1790.
This debate is quite rhetorical in tone, but it well illustrates how debates usually involve a
dialectic concerning the definition of some key term. Both these men helped to found the
American Republic, but they differ sharply as to what a "republic" is.
. . . you agree that there are undoubtedly principles of political architecture; but, instead of
particularizing any of them, you seem to place all your hopes in the universal, or at least more
general, prevalence of knowledge and benevolence. I think, with you, that knowledge and
benevolence ought to be promoted as much as possible; but despairing of ever seeing them
sufficiently general for the security of society, I am for seeking institutions which may supply in
some degree the defect. If there were no ignorance, error, or vice, there would be neither
principles nor systems of civil or political government.
I am very willing to agree with you in fancying that, in the greatest improvements in society,
government will be in the republican form. It is a fixed principle with me that all good
government is and must be republican. But, at the same time, your candor will agree with me,
that there is not in lexicography a more fraudulent word. Whenever I use the word republic with
approbation, I mean a government in which the people have collectively or by representation an
essential share in the sovereignty. The republican forms of Poland and Venice are much worse,
and those of Holland and Bern very little better, than the monarchical form in France before the
late revolution. . . . Are we not, tiny friend, in danger of rendering the word republican
unpopular in this Country by an indiscreet, indeterminate, and equivocal use of it? ... If in this
country the word republic should be generally understood, as it is by some, to mean a form of
government inconsistent with a mixture of three powers forming, a mutual balance, ,ve may
depend upon it that such mischievous effects will be produced by the use of it as will compel the
people of America to renounce, detest, and execrate it as the English do. With these
explanations, restrictions and limitations, I agree with you in your love of republican
governments, but in no other sense . . . .
. . . but, on the other hand, the nobles have been essential parties in the preservation of liberty
whenever and wherever it has existed. In Europe they alone have preserved it against kings and
people, wherever it has been preserved, or at least with very little assistance from the people.
One hideous despotism, as horrid as that of Turkey, would have been the lot of every nation of
Europe, if the nobles bad not made stands. By nobles, I mean not peculiarly an hereditary
nobility, or any particular modification, but the natural and actual aristocracy among mankind.
The existence of this you will not deny. You and I have seen four noble families rise up in
Boston, -- the Craftses, Gores, Daweses, and Austins. These are as really a nobility in our town
as the Howards, Somersets, Berties, etc., in England. Blind undistinguishing reproaches against
the aristocratical part of mankind, a division which nature has made and we cannot abolish, are
neither pious nor benevolent. They are as pernicious as they are false. They serve only to foment
prejudice, jealousy, envy, animosity, and malevolence. They serve no ends but those of
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
sophistry, fraud, and the spirit of party. It would not be true, but it would not be more
egregiously false, to say that the people have waged everlasting war against the rights of men.
"The love of liberty," you say, "is interwoven in the soul of man." So it is, according to La
Fontaine, in that of a wolf; and I doubt whether it be much more rational, generous, or social in
one than in the other, until in man it is enlightened by experience, reflection, education, and civil
and political institutions, which are at first produced, and constantly supported and improved, by
a few, that is, by the nobility. The wolf in the fable, who preferred running in the forest, lean and
hungry, to the sleek, plump, and round sides of the dog, because be found the latter was
sometimes restrained, had more love of liberty than most men. The numbers of men, in all ages,
have preferred ease, slumber, and good cheer to liberty, when they have been in competition. We
must not, then, depend alone upon the love of liberty in the soul of man for its preservation.
Some political institutions must be prepared to assist this love against its enemies. Without these,
the struggle will ever end only in a change of impostors, when the people who have no property
feel the power in their own bands to determine all questions by a majority, they ever attack those
who have property, till the injured men of property lose all patience, and recur to finesse, trick,
and stratagem, to outwit those who have too much strength, because they have too many hands,
to be resisted in any other way. Let us be impartial, then, and speak the whole truth. Till we do,
we shall never discover all the true principles that are necessary. The multitude, therefore, as
well as the nobles, must have a check. . . .
There are a few popular men in -- Massachusetts, my friend, who have, I fear, less honor,
sincerity and virtue than they ought to have. These, if they are not guarded against, may do
another mischief. They may excite a party spirit and a snobbish spirit instead of the spirit of
liberty, and produce another Wat Tyler's rebellion. They can do no more. But I really think their
party language ought not to be countenanced nor their shibboleths pronounced, The miserable
stuff that they titter about the well born is as despicable as themselves. The eulgeneis of the
Greeks, the bien nées of the French, the gewellgebornen [sic] of the Germans and Dutch, the
beloved families of the Greeks, are but a few samples of national expressions of the same thing,
for which every nation on earth has a similar expression. One would think that our scribblers
were all the sons of redemptioners or transported convicts. They think, with Tarquin, "in novo
populo, ubi omnis repentina atque ex virtute nobilitas sit, futurum locum forti ac strenuo viro. . .
."
Let us do justice to the people and to tile nobles, -- for nobles there are, as I have before proved,
in Boston as well as in Madrid. But to do justice to both you must establish an arbitrator between
them . . . .
JOHN ADAMS
. . . a republic, you tell me, is a government in which "the people have an essential share in the
sovereignty." Is not the whole sovereignty, my friend, essentially in the people? Is not
government designed for the welfare and happiness of all the people? And is it not the
uncontrollable, essential right of the people to amend and alter or annul their Constitution and
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
frame a new one, whenever they shall think it will better promote their own welfare and
happiness to do it? That the sovereignty resides in the people, is a political doctrine which I have
never heard an American politician seriously deny. The constitutions of the American States
reserve to the people the exercise of the rights of sovereignty by the annual or biennial election
of their governors, senators, and representatives, and by empowering their own representatives to
impeach the greatest officers of the State before the senators, who are also chosen by themselves.
We the people, is the style of the Federal Constitution: they adopted it; and, conformably to it,
they delegate the exercise of the powers of government to particular persons, -- who, after short
intervals, resign their powers to the people; and they will re-elect them, or appoint others, as they
think fit.
The American Legislatures are nicely balanced. They consist of two branches, each having a
check upon the determinations of the other. They sit in different chambers, and probably often
reason differently in their respective chambers on the same question: if they disagree in their
decisions, by a conference their reasons and arguments are mutually communicated to each
other; candid explanations tend to bring them to agreement; and then, according to the
Massachusetts Constitution, the matter is laid before the First Magistrate for his revision. He
states objections, if be has any, with his reasons, and returns them to the legislators, who, by
larger majorities, ultimately decide. Here is a mixture of three powers, founded in the nature of
man, calculated to call forth the rational faculties, in the great points of legislation, into exertion,
to cultivate mutual friendship and good humor, and, finally, to enable them to decide, not by the
impulse of passion or party prejudice, but by the calm voice of reason, which is the voice of God.
In this mixture you may see your natural and actual aristocracy among mankind operating among
the several powers in legislation, and producing the most happy effects. But the son of an
excellent man may never inherit the great qualities of his father; this is a common observation,
and there are many instances of its truth. Should we not, therefore, conclude that hereditary
nobility is a solecism in government.? . . . Much safer is it, and much more does it tend to
promote the welfare and happiness of society, to fill tip the offices of government, after the mode
prescribed in the American Constitutions, by frequent elections of the people. They may, indeed,
be deceived in their choice; they sometimes are. But the evil is not incurable, the remedy is
always near; they will feel their mistakes and correct them.
I am very willing to agree with you in thinking that improvements in knowledge and
benevolence receive much assistance from the principles and systems of good government. But
is it not as true that, without knowledge and benevolence, men would neither have been capable
nor disposed to search for the principles or form the system? Should we not, my friend, bear a
grateful remembrance of our pious and benevolent ancestors, who early laid plans of education,
by which means wisdom, knowledge, and virtue have been generally diffused among the body of
the people, and they have been enabled to form and establish a civil Constitution calculated for
the preservation of their rights and liberties? This Constitution was evidently founded in the
expectation of the further progress and extraordinary degrees of virtue. . . .
Among the numbers of men, my friend, are to be found not only those who have "preferred ease,
slumber, and good cheer to liberty," but others who have eagerly sought after thrones and
sceptres, hereditary shares in sovereignty, riches and splendor, titles, stars, garters, crosses,
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
eagles, and many other childish playthings, at the expense of real nobility, without one thought
or care for the liberty and happiness of the rest of mankind. . . .
But by "nobles," who have prevented "one hideous despotism as horrid as that of Turkey from
falling to the lot of every nation of Europe," you mean, "not peculiarly an hereditary nobility, or
any particular modification, but the natural and actual aristocracy among mankind," the existence
of which I am not disposed to deny. Where is this aristocracy found? Among men of all ranks
and conditions. The cottager may beget a wise son; the noble, a fool. The one is capable of great
improvement; the other is not. Education is within the power of men and societies of men; wise
and judicious modes of education, patronized and supported by communities, will draw together
the sons of the rich and the poor, among whom it makes no distinction; it will cultivate the
natural genius, elevate the soul, excite laudable emulation to excel in knowledge, piety, and
benevolence; and finally it will reward its patrons and benefactors by shedding its benign
influence on tile public mind. Education inures men to thinking and reflection, to reasoning and
demonstration. It discovers to them the moral and religious duties they owe to God, their
country, and to all mankind. Even savages might, by the means of education, be instructed to
frame the best civil and political in situations with as much skill and ingenuity as they now shape
their arrows. Education leads youth to "the study of human nature, society, and universal
history," from whence they may "draw all the principles" of political architecture which ought to
be regarded. All men are "interested in the truth"; education, by showing them "the end of all its
consequences," would induce at least the greatest numbers to enlist on its side. The man of good
understanding, who has been well educated, and improves these advantages as far as his
circumstances will allow, in promoting the happiness of mankind, in my opinion, and I am
inclined to think in yours, is indeed " well born." . . . Believe me, your sincere friend,
SAMUEL ADAMS
St. Augustine (354-430) was converted to the Catholic faith after a youth passed in heresy and
sin. After his baptism by St. Ambrose, he entered into a retreat in the country. Making use of his
literary gifts (for he was a teacher of rhetoric), he began the composition of several philosophical
dialogues. These were modeled after the dialogues of Cicero, which in turn were imitations of
the dialogues of Plato, themselves based on Socrates' method of teaching.
The purpose of these first writings of St. Augustine was to show that reason and philosophy lead
man toward the true, supernatural faith, which bad just been given him. One of these dialogues is
the De Beata Vita (The Happy Life)* [* Translated by Ludwig Schopp in The Fathers of the Church, ed. by
Ludwig Schopp (Cima Publishing Co., Inc., 1948), with permission of the translator and publishers. ] which is an
inquiry about the causes of human happiness. It opens with a sort of dedication to his friend
Manlius Theodorus on the importance of philosophy, and then proceeds in dialogue form as
follows:
Continuation of CHAPTER I
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
On the Ides of November fell my birthday. After breakfast light enough not to impede our
powers of thinking, 1 asked all those of us who, not only that day but every day, were living
together to have a congenial session in the bathing quarters, a quiet place fitting for the season.
Assembled there -- for without hesitation I present them to your kindness, though only by name -
- were first, our mother, to whose merit, in my opinion, I owe everything that I live; my brother
Navigius; Trygetius and Licentius, fellow citizens and my pupils; Lastidianus and Rusticus,
relatives of mine, whom I did not wish to be absent, though they are not trained even in
grammar, since I believed their common sense was needed for the difficult matter I was
undertaking. Also my son, Adeodatus, the youngest of all, was with us, who promises great
success, unless my love deceive me. While all these were paying attention, I started in the
following manner.
CHAPTER 2
While all gave their assent, Navigius replied that he was not sure about it.
I asked him then: "Do you really know nothing at all, or is this matter just one of the things that
you do not know?"
"Certainly," he said.
"If it is not difficult," I continued, "let us be told." When he hesitated a little, I asked him: "Do
you at least know that you are alive?"
"Yes," be answered.
"You know, therefore, that you possess life, since no one can live without having life."
He said: "Yes."
"Then you know already that you consist of body and life?"
"You have no doubt, therefore," I continued, "of the existence of these two, the body and the
soul. But you are uncertain whether there is anything else necessary for the filling out and
completing of man."
Then I said: "The character of this other element we will examine at another time, if we are able
to do so. However, since we all now agree that man cannot exist without body and without soul,
I ask all of you: For which of the two do we try to obtain food?"
But the others hesitated and in various ways discussed among themselves how food could appear
necessary for the body, since it was obtained for the purpose of life, and life belongs only to the
soul.
At this point I asked: "In your opinion, does not food appertain to the part that we see grow and
become vigorous?"
All except Trygetius agreed. He said: "Why, then, have I not grown according to my greedy
appetite?"
I answered: "All bodies have by nature received a measure that they cannot exceed, although
these measures may decrease by lack of food, as we notice more easily in cattle, and nobody has
any doubt that through lack of nutrition the bodies of all living things grow lean."
"To grow lean," said Licentius, "does not mean to become smaller."
"This is satisfactory for the purpose I have in mind," I said. "For the question is whether food
appertains to the body. It does so appertain, because, if it is withheld, the body becomes lean."
What about the soul?" I asked. "Is there no food proper to the soul? Or do you think that
knowledge is its nutrition?"
"Obviously," said our mother. "I believe that the soul is not nourished except by the
understanding and knowledge of things."
When Trygetius showed doubt about her statement, she asked: "Did not you yourself today
demonstrate from what and where the soul finds its nourishment? For, according to your own
statement, you noticed only after a certain part of the breakfast which bowl we were using, since
you had been thinking of some other things I do not know, although you helped yourself from
that course and ate it. Where, then, was your mind at the time when it did not pay attention to
what you were eating? From there, believe me, and by such meals is the soul nourished, that is,
by those speculations and thoughts by which it is able to gain knowledge."
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
When there was a buzz of questioning about this point, I asked: "Do you not concede that the
souls of wise men are by far richer and greater, in their way, than the souls of the uneducated?"
"Then we state correctly that the souls of people not scientifically trained and unfamiliar with the
liberal arts are, as it were, hungry and famished."
I believe," said Trygetius, "that their souls also are full, but full of faults and worthlessness."
"There exists, believe me," I said, "a certain real sterility and hunger of the soul. For, as the body
when its nutrition is withheld is generally ill and scabious, bodily faults that indicate hunger, so
are souls filled with ills through which they betray their impoverishment. Thus, according to the
ancients the very word nequitia (worthlessness) -- the mother of all vices -- springs from
nequicquam, that is, from that which is a nothing. The virtue which is opposite to this vice is
called frugalitas (frugality), for, as this latter is called after the word frux (fruit), i.e., after fructus
(enjoyment), because of a certain fecundity of the souls, so is nequitia (worthlessness) named
after this sterility, i.e., after nihil (the nothing); nihil (nothing) is all that flows, that is dissolved,
that melts and steadily perishes (perit). Because of this, we consider such men lost (perditi).
"But a thing really has being when it remains, stands firmly, and is always the same, as in the
case with virtue. The greater and most beautiful part of this is called temperantia (restraint) and
frugalitas (frugality).
"Although this may be too obscure for your understanding at present, you certainly will concede,
when the souls of the uneducated are filled, that there are likewise, as for bodies, two kinds of
food for souls: one healthful and beneficial; the other unhealthful and harmful.
"On the strength of this, I think that on my birthday I ought to serve a somewhat richer meal, not
only for our bodies, but also for our souls, since we all agree that man consists of two things:
body and soul. The quality of this meal I will reveal, if you are hungry. For, in case I tried to feed
you against your will and taste, my undertaking would be in vain and prayers should be said that
you would be more desirous for those meals than for the ones of the body. This will be the case
if your souls are healthy, for sick souls, as can be seen in a diseased body, refuse their food and
spit it out."
By the expression of their features and by their words of approval, all said they were ready to
accept and eat whatever I bad prepared.
The dialogue now continues with the main question, namely, the search for a happy life.
Notice in the foregoing bow the dialogue form makes it possible to present both sides of a
question in a vivid, dramatic way. In a Socratic dialogue the questioner states a proposition: "Is it
clear that we are composed of body and of soul?" Then one of the
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
others denies the proposition. Then the questioner proceeds step by step to uncover the difficulty,
using the dialectical devices of definition by comparison and difference. When he has finally got
the other to admit his proposition to be true in some sense, he then proceeds to raise a new
problem. This continues, moving always, however, to the discovery of an answer to one main
question, in this case, "What is the happy life?"
The following is a selection from the biography, Madame Curie,* [* Doubleday, Doran and Co., New
York, 1939, with permission of Doubleday Co .] by Eve Curie, her daughter. It gives us a vivid idea of
the process of reasoning and experimentation by which scientific knowledge is extended. An
analysis of it is given in this text , pages 190 ff.
At this moment she was like a traveler musing on a long voyage. Bent over the globe and
pointing out, in some far country, a strange name that excites his imagination, the traveler
suddenly decides to go there and nowhere else: so Marie, going through the reports of the latest
experimental studies, was attracted by the publication of the French scientist Henri Becquerel of
the preceding year. She and Pierre already knew this work; she read it over again and studied it
with her usual care.
After Roentgen's discovery of X-rays, Henri Poincaré conceived the idea of determining whether
rays like the X-ray were emitted by "fluorescent" bodies under the action of light. Attracted by
the same problem, Henri Becquerel examined the salts of a "rare metal , uranium. Instead of
finding the phenomenon be had expected, he observed another, altogether different and
incomprehensible: he found that uranium salts spontaneously emitted, without exposure to light,
some rays of unknown nature, A compound of uranium, placed on a photographic plate
surrounded by black paper, made an impression on the plate through the paper. And, like the X-
ray,
these astonishing " uranic" salts discharged an electroscope by rendering the surrounding air a
conductor.
Henri Becquerel made sure that these surprising properties were not caused by a preliminary
exposure to the sun and that they persisted when the uranium compound had been maintained in
darkness for several months. For the first time, a physicist had observed the phenomenon to
which Marie Curie was later to give the name of radioactivity, But the nature of the radiation and
its origin remained an enigma.
Becquerel's discovery fascinated the Curies. They asked themselves whence came the energy --
tiny, to be sure -- which uranium compounds constantly disengaged in the form of radiation. And
what was the nature of this radiation? Here was an engrossing subject of research, a doctor's
thesis. . . !
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The candidate for the doctor's degree set her first task to be the measurement of the "power of
ionization" of uranium rays -- that is to say, their power to render the air a conductor of
electricity and so to discharge an electroscope. The excellent method she used, which was to be
the key to the success of her experiments, bad been invented for the study of other phenomena by
two physicists well known to her: Pierre and Jacques Curie. Her technical installation consisted
of an "ionization chamber," a Curie electrometer and a piezoelectric quartz.
At the end of several weeks the first result appeared: Marie acquired the certainty that the
intensity of this surprising radiation was proportional to the quantity of uranium contained in the
samples under examination, and that this radiation, which could be measured with precision, was
not affected either by the chemical state of combination of the uranium or by external factors
such as lighting or temperature.
These observations were perhaps not very sensational to the uninitiated, but they were of
passionate interest to the scientist. It often happens in physics that an inexplicable phenomenon
can be subjected, after some investigation, to laws already known, and by this very fact loses its
interest for the research worker. Thus, in a badly constructed detective story, if we are told in the
third chapter that the woman of sinister appearance who might have committed the crime is in
reality only an honest little housewife who leads a life without secrets, we feel discouraged and
cease to read.
Nothing of the kind happened here. The more Marie penetrated into intimacy with uranium rays,
the more they seemed without precedent, essentially unknown. They were like nothing else.
Nothing affected them. In spite of their very feeble power, they had an extraordinary
individuality.
Turning this mystery over and over in her head, and pointing toward the truth, Marie felt and
could soon affirm that the incomprehensible radiation was an atomic property. She questioned.
Even though the phenomenon had only been observed with uranium, nothing proved that
uranium was the only chemical element capable of emitting such radiation. Why should not other
bodies possess the same power? Perhaps it was only by chance that this radiation had been
observed in uranium first, and had remained attached to uranium in the minds of physicists. Now
it must be sought for elsewhere. . . .
No sooner said than done. Abandoning the study of uranium, Marie undertook to examine all
known chemical bodies, either in the pure state or in compounds. And the result was not long in
appearing: compounds of another element, thorium, also emitted spontaneous rays like those of
uranium and of similar intensity. The physicist had been right: the surprising phenomenon was
by no means the property of uranium alone, and it became necessary to give it a distinct name.
Mine. Curie suggested the name of radioactivity. Chemical substances like uranium and thorium,
endowed with this particular "radiance," were called radio elements.
Radioactivity so fascinated the young scientist that she never tired of examining the most diverse
forms of matter, always by the same method. Curiosity, a marvelous feminine curiosity, the first
virtue of a scientist, was developed in Marie to the highest degree. Instead of limiting her
observation to simple compounds, salts and oxides, she had the desire to assemble samples of
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
minerals from the collection at the School of Physics, and of making them undergo almost at
hazard, for her own amusement, a kind of customs inspection which is an electrometer test.
Pierre approved, and chose with her the veined fragments, hard or crumbly, oddly shaped, which
she wanted to examine.
Marie's idea was simple -- simple as the stroke of genius. At the crossroads where Marie now
stood, hundreds of research workers might have remained, nonplussed, for months or even
years. After examining all known chemical substances, and discovering -- as Marie had done --
the radiation of thorium, they would have continued to ask themselves in vain when came this
mysterious radioactivity. Marie, too, questioned and wondered. But her surprise was translated
into fruitful acts. She had used up all evident possibilities. Now she turned toward the
unplumbed and the unknown.
She knew in advance what she would learn from an examination of the minerals, or rather she
thought she knew. The specimens which contained neither uranium nor thorium would be
revealed as totally "inactive." The others, containing uranium or thorium, would be radioactive.
Experiment confirmed this prevision. Rejecting the inactive minerals, Marie applied herself to
the others and measured their radioactivity. Then came a dramatic revelation: the radioactivity
was a great deal stronger than could have been normally foreseen by the quantity of uranium or
thorium contained in the products examined!
"It must be an error in experiment," the young woman thought; for doubt is the scientist's first
response to an unexpected phenomenon.
She started her measurements over again, unmoved, using the same products. She started over
again ten times, twenty times. And she was forced to yield to the evidence: the quantities of
uranium and of thorium found in these minerals were by no means sufficient to justify the
exceptional intensity of the radiation she observed.
Where did this excessive and abnormal radiation come from? Only one explanation was
possible: the minerals must contain, in small quantity, a much more powerfully radioactive
substance than uranium and thorium.
But what substance? In her preceding experiments, Marie bad already examined all known
chemical elements.
The scientist replied to the question with the sure logic and the magnificent audaciousness of a
great mind; the minerals certainly contained a radioactive substance, which was at the same time
a chemical element unknown until this day: a new element.
A new element! It was a fascinating and alluring hypothesis -- but still a hypothesis. For the
moment this powerfully radioactive substance existed only in the imagination of Marie and of
Pierre. But it did exist there. It existed strongly enough to make the young woman go to see
Bronya one day and tell her in a restrained, ardent voice:
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
"You know, Bronya, the radiation that I couldn't explain comes from a new chemical element.
The element is there and I've got to find it. We are sure! The physicists we have spoken to
believe we have made an error in experiment and advise us to be careful. But I am convinced
that I am not mistaken."
These were unique moments in her unique life. The layman forms a theatrical -- and wholly false
-- idea of the research worker and of his discoveries. "The moment of discovery" does not always
exist: The scientist's work is too tenuous, too divided, for the certainty of success to crackle out
suddenly in the midst of his laborious toil like a stroke of lightning, dazzling him by its fire.
Marie, standing in front of her apparatus, perhaps never experienced the sudden intoxication of
triumph. This intoxication was spread over several days of decisive labor, made feverish by a
magnificent hope. But it must have been an exultant moment when, convinced by the rigorous
reasoning of her brain that she was on the trail of new matter, she confided the secret to her elder
sister, her ally always.... Without exchanging one affectionate word, the two sisters must have
lived again, in a dizzying breath of memory, their years of waiting, their mutual sacrifices, their
bleak lives as students, full of hope and faith....
By the force of her own intuition the physicist had shown to herself that the wonderful substance
must exist. She decreed its existence. But its incognito still bad to be broken. Now she would
have to verify hypothesis by experiment, isolate this material and see it. She must be able to
announce with certainty: "It is there!" . . .
Marie and Pierre looked for this "very active" substance in an ore of uranium called pitchblende,
which in the crude state had shown itself to be four times more radioactive than the pure oxide of
uranium that could be extracted from it. But the composition of this ore had been known for a
long time with considerable precision. The new element must therefore be present in very small
quantity or it would not have escaped the notice of scientists and their chemical analysis.
According to their calculations- " pessimistic, calculations, like those of true physicists, who
always take the less attractive of two probabilities -- the collaborators thought the ore should
contain the new element to a maximum quantity of one per cent. They decided that this was very
little. They would have been in consternation if they had known that the radioactive element they
were hunting down did not count for more than a millionth part of pitchblende ore.
They began their prospecting patiently, using a method of chemical research invented by
themselves, based on radioactivity: they separated all the elements in pitchblende by ordinary
chemical analysis and then measured the radioactivity of each of the bodies thus obtained. By
successive eliminations they saw the "abnormal" radioactivity take refuge in certain parts of the
ore. As they went on, the field of investigation was narrowed. It was exactly the technique used
by the police when they search the houses of a neighborhood, one by one, to isolate and arrest a
malefactor.
But there was more than one malefactor here -- the radioactivity was concentrated principally in
two different chemical fractions of the pitchblende. For M. and Mine. Curie it indicated the
existence of two new elements instead of one. By July, 1898, they were able to announce the
discovery of one of these substances with certainty.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
"You will have to name it," Pierre said to his young wife, in the same tone as if it were a
question of choosing a name for little Iréne.
The one-time Mlle. Sklodovska reflected in silence for a moment. Then, her heart turning toward
her own country which had been erased from the map of the world, she wondered vaguely if the
scientific event would be published in Russia, Germany, and Austria -- the oppressor countries --
and answered timidly:
We believe the substance we have extracted from the pitchblende contains a metal not yet
observed, related to bismuth by its analytical properties. If the existence of this new metal is
confirmed we propose to call it polonium from the name of the original country of one of us. . .
Iréne can walk very well, and no longer goes on all fours.
On January 5, 1889:
Between these two notes -- that of October 17, 1898, in which Iréne no longer goes on all fours,
and that of January 5 in which Iréne has fifteen teeth -- and a few months after the note on the
gooseberry preserve, we find another note worthy of remark.
It was drawn up by Marie and Pierre Curie and a collaborator called G. Bémont. Intended for the
Academy of Science, and published in the Proceedings of the session of December 26, 1898, it
announced the existence of a second new chemical element in pitchblende.
The various reasons we have just enumerated lead us to believe that the new radioactive
substance contains a new element to which we propose to give the name of RADIUM.
The new radioactive substance certainly contains a very strong proportion of barium; in spite of
that its radioactivity is considerable. The radioactivity of radium therefore must be enormous.
of King Henry VIII, and paved the way for the apostasy of the English nation from the Catholic
Faith.
One of the charges which has been made against him is that be was secretly responsible for the
execution of the Duke of Buckingham as a traitor. Buckingham was an obstacle to Wolsey's
ambition and he gained by having him out of the way. Did he conspire to bring this about?
Belloc tries to answer this question in the following passage, which illustrates how a historian
frequently must use a dialectical procedure to arrive at the most probable answer to a question of
fact.
Tradition took it for granted that the prime mover in the destruction of the Duke of Buckingham
was Wolsey. Tradition in these large matters of motive and character, particularly when it comes
from the very source and can be traced to contemporaries, is so generally right that any academic
case against it must require heavy positive proof in its favour.
It has been the academic fashion since the last third of the 19th century to exonerate Wolsey.
This came in part from the general academic contempt for popular opinion, but also from
exaggerating the use of documents against tradition; the great flood of documents on this period
having been printed for the first time in the later part of the 19th century.
But when I look at those documents, and consider the academic arguments advanced to
exonerate Wolsey I can see nothing to support the new conclusion. All seems to me in favour of
the old, and Wolsey remains indubitably the author of Buckingham's tragedy.
What are the arguments in favour of Henry's being the true initiator of the business?
The first argument is that Henry, like all the Tudors (and like James the First, for that matter)
was in terror of rival claims to the throne. But if that was Henry's motive why had neither he nor
his father been affected by that motive during so many years? On the contrary, he and his father
heaped honours on Buckingham. One hears nothing of this sudden dread of a rival till
Buckingham is 42 years old, and till he has been the intimate companion and friend of the King
for many years.
The suspicions against Buckingham did not begin to arise till Wolsey started them in 1518.
Against this it may be urged that Henry may not have suspected Buckingham of any likelihood
to press his claims until news came to him thus late. Well, who put forward that news?
Undoubtedly Wolsey. It was the anonymous letter which Wolsey had in his hands, some weeks
before Henry could make up his mind to move, which is the starting point of the whole affair.
A second argument continually put forward to show that the specifically initiative cannot have
been Wolsey's and must therefore have been Henry's is that Polydore Vergil, the contemporary
specifically accuses Wolsey, is a tainted witness because Wolsey had put him in prison and he
was Wolsey's enemy. The argument is only of value against a better argument on the other side.
Because a man is prejudiced against another it is probable that be will lie in his disfavour; but it
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
is not probable that in repeating a common opinion and a likely one, and one for which there is
no contemporary contradiction, be should be lying. French and English propaganda against
William II during the Great War gave rise to many lies. But it did not lie when it accused
William II of having made warlike and menacing speeches.
General considerations, which are the best of all in such matters, can I think determine us. Put
yourself in the place of Wolsey in that year 1521, remember his character, his power of restraint
and calculation, the affronts he had suffered the hatred felt for him by the class of which
Buckingham was the best representative, the Cardinal's dread lest anyone should supplant him or
weaken him in the ears of the King, the recent conspicuous role of Buckingham in the splendid
feasts of 1520, the Cloth of Gold; remember also the effort Wolsey was at to exclude
Buckingham from shining in the tourneys, and the way in which none the less the King
continued to befriend him, and you have before you a situation which makes Wolsey's initiative
against him not only reasonable but inevitable.
On the other hand, put yourself in the place of Henry, impulsive, readily influenced, readily
taken in acting suddenly upon suggestion, very much attached to the Court traditions be had
inherited from his father, receiving unexpected and terrifying notice that his friend and relative
was intriguing against him, receiving after two years of suggestions, that anonymous notice from
Wolsey, by whom be was completely dominated. Ask yourself whether Henry's action in early
1521 when be was moved to such wrath and fear in the matter of Buckingham looks like a policy
thought out by his own brain.
The student will find a convenient collection of examples of typical studies in the field of the
social sciences in American Social Patterns, edited by William Petersen, a Doubleday Anchor
Book (paperbound). The following brief analyses of three articles contained in this book will
give an idea of the kind of dialectical reasoning involved in the social sciences.
1. Problem: Everyone recognizes that interracial housing conflicts are a crucial issue at the present time
in some of our big cities, but actually little is known of what actually occurs. The authors distinguish two
situations: (a) where white and Negro families are "integrated" in apartments which are assigned without
consideration of race; and (b) where they live in different buildings or sections of the same housing
project. The problem is to discover the differences between behaviour in these two situations.
2. Hypotheses: On the basis of their general theory of human behaviour in social situations, the authors
made six hypotheses:
a. There will be more social contact among people the closer they live together.
b. The more social contact, the more they will tend to like each other.
d. There will be more serious interest in developing interracial relations in the integrated projects.
e. This mutual working together on a problem may even create more friendly relations within the
white group.
f. White tenants in integrated projects will have less prejudice than those in segregated projects.
3. Research procedure:
a. The authors tried to select two typical projects, one integrated and one segregated, which would
be as alike in all other respects as possible.
b. They tried to collect as accurate a social description of the two groups as possible, mainly from
white housewives selected at random.
c. This was done by interviews (an hour to two hours long) in which they tried to ascertain the
housewives' attitudes to living in the project, their attitudes to the other race ' the amount of
contact they have with the other race, the social support they received for their attitudes, and
finally the characteristics of the housewife interviewed.
e. They attempted to control this data by various means which were designed to distinguish
between attitudes acquired by the housewife after she came to live in the project and before.
4. Results: The results were then tabulated in a series of charts which showed that in general the
hypotheses had been verified. Nevertheless, the result was not certain, because the controls used were
imperfect, and hence it was not possible to be sure that the situation observed was entirely due to the
difference in the housing arrangements.
1. Problem: Popular biographies have become a very popular type of reading since the beginning of this
century. This seems to indicate that there is a social need seeking gratification in this type of literature.
What is this social need?
2. Research method: A "content analysis" was made of material printed in the Saturday Evening Post
and Collier's for the period from April, 1940, to March, 1941. Other studies had already shown that since
1901 the type of biography has shifted from those which idolized business and professional people as
examples of success in life to ones which idolize people in the light entertainment world. The present
study classified the content of the biographies published in its type magazines according to similar
categories. This classification was then put in tabular form to show trends.
a. The trend toward the idolization of people in the entertainment world has continued, and
particularly for those in the lightest forms of entertainment.
b. In these biographies much time is devoted to the details of the persons' private lives.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
c. The biographies neglect to show the subjects' personal development through effort, their
personal control over their own success, or any solitary inner life, although at an earlier period
these were much stressed.
d. The success of the person is usually pictured in terms of social adjustment and conformity to
group standards.
e. The presentation of the personality is in extravagantly superlative terms and strives to give a
sense of intimate contact.
4. Hypothesis: The author suggests that these facts could be accounted for if we suppose that people in
our society feel a great need for a better understanding of human relations, and that they believe that
reading such biographies will help them to understanding. The author points out that, in fact, the popular
biographies only apparently meet this need. They do not actually have much educative value, because
those who read them are not prepared for critical thinking about human relations, which they might find
too disturbing.
ARTICLE C: "The People's Choice," by Paul F. Lazarfeld, Bernard Berelson, and Hazel Gaudet.
1. Problem: How and why did people decide to vote as they did in the presidential campaign of 1940?
This may cast light on general problems of voting behaviour.
2. Research Method: The method was that of interviewing a test group of people at regular intervals
about their voting intentions.
a. A staff of 12 to 15 trained interviewers, mostly women, visited every fourth house in Erie
County, Ohio, and then selected from these 3000 people interviewed four groups of 600 persons,
each of which were matched so as to constitute similar samples.
b. One of these was selected as the test group and was carefully studied so that its members could
be classified by their socio-economic status. This group was then interviewed once a month from
May to November. The interviewers sought to learn why each person changed his intended vote,
if he changed, and what propaganda influences or social pressures might have led to this change.
c. The other three groups were used as controls. They were each interviewed only once, one in
July, one in August, and one in October. It was hoped that this would give a check against the
possibility that the test group was being influenced in its behaviour by the very fact that it was
being interviewed so often.
3. Results:
a. Class differences:
1) There was a correlation between socio-economic status and party affiliations, the working class
groups being more Democratic. This did not depend so much on actual occupation as on the
voter's belief that he belonged to the laboring class.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
2) There was a correlation with religion, the Catholics being more Democratic. This was not
merely a reflection of a. above, since it held also at every socio-economic level.
3) There was a correlation with age, older people tending to be Republican on the whole, but
among Catholics the older people tended to be more Democratic.
4) The rural vote was more Republican, the urban vote more Democratic.
b. Ideological differences: It was found that the arguments used by voters for their choice were
quite stereotyped. Those for Roosevelt believed be would be for the laboring man and that he was
right about foreign affairs. Those for Wilkie believed would be better for business, and were not
much interested in foreign affairs. Those for Wilkie were against a third term. Those for
Roosevelt did not favor third terms, but apologized for it in this case. After the election people
were, on the whole, reconciled to the victor.
c. Political interest and participation: In general those with better education and higher socio-
economic status showed more interest in the election and had more opinions about it. There was
little difference in this regard between rural and urban populations. Men showed more interest
than women, but older people were more interested than younger people of the same educational
level. Actual voting or abstention agreed perfectly with degree of interest, except that fewer
women voted than were interested.
d. Time when final decision was made for whom to vote: Some 13 % changed their minds in the
weeks just before the election, and in general the group that was subject to the most cross-
pressures was the last to make up its mind. There were "crystalizes" who took some time to make
up their mind, "waverers" who changed and then went back to original vote, and "Party changers"
who changed their mind and stuck to it. Many had their mind made up by the European crisis.
1) Activation effect: It could be predicted how a voter would choose if one knew whether he was
Catholic, a laborer, and urban, but it took some time for these influences to lead to a decision in
many cases.
2) Reinforcement effect: Many who bad their minds already made up were kept in line by the
campaign.
3) Band-wagon effect: Many waverers were effected by their conviction that a certain man would
win to whom they were already inclined.
In general the campaign does not convert many people to another party, and few voters
make much of an effort to weigh both sides of the question.
f. Group and individual influences: In general people vote with their group and their family
tradition. Only some 4% of the voters reported that a member of their family voted differently
than themselves. People were more influenced by some leader within their own social group who
bad strong political convictions than by any other source of persuasion.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
REMARKS:
The student will notice that in each of these three studies the results are, on the whole, about
what would be expected by an experienced person. The purpose of the scientist is not to discover
something utterly unexpected, but to clarify the details of the social situation, and to reveal
underlying connections. The logical clarity of the reasoning in each case depends:
This is a dialectical process, since the reasoning rests on hypotheses which have to be reshaped
according to the facts, and the results are not more than probable. Two defects are apparent in
these studies:
1. The authors do not make clear the practical problem they are attempting to solve, although it is
apparent that in the background of all these studies are practical social problems which need to be
solved, and which give value to the research. Such studies are mere curiosity unless they have
practical importance, since none of them lead to fundamental theoretical knowledge.
2. The authors do not attempt to connect their dialectic with more basic and solid psychological
principles. Dialectic is a tool of science, and ought to aim at strict scientific knowledge even
when this cannot be obtained.
SECTION VII
We begin this section with examples from mathematics, because these are always simpler and
clearer than in other sciences. We give one from arithmetic which is so simple as to appear
entirely trivial, but it illustrates a method which is the same for every arithmetical or algebraic
proof, no matter how complicated it may be.
Major: This is a definition of an even number, namely, "A number is even which can be divided
into two equal and largest parts."
Minor: This is the definition of an odd number, namely, "All odd number is one which cannot be
divided into two equal and largest parts without the remainder of a unit."
Someone might object that 1 is neither odd nor even; but as we have seen, 1 is not a
number.
3. It is through the proper formal cause, since it is made through the definition of the two kinds of
numbers.
Theorem: If two straight lines AB and CD cut one another, the vertical or opposite angles a and
b are equal:
Proof: (Premises marked with an asterisk* are proved below): 1* The remainders of equals
minus equals are equal. 2* And: every pair of vertical angles (such as a and b) are the remainders
of equals minus equals. Therefore: every pair of vertical angles are equal.
Proof of 1* : This is an axiom (it means the same is, "If equals are subtracted from equals, the
remainders are equal).
Proof of 2* :
6.* This is a previous theorem, namely, that "The angles which one straight line makes with
another straight line on one side of it are equal to two right angles (i.e., a straight angle). We omit
this proof.
In this handbook we have studied logic as an art, learning its rules and practicing their
application to various kinds of materials. How do we know that these rules themselves are true?
Logic is not only an art, but it is also a science which proves its own rules.
The following demonstration taken from Aristotle's Posterior Analytics is the most important
rule of all of logic, since it tells us how to form a scientific demonstration. Aristotle explains this
demonstration at great length, and we give it here only in abbreviated form. The various
premises which require to be proved are numbered in order with an asterisk, thus 1*.
Therefore:
a scientific demonstration is a syllogism whose premises
contain a real essential definition
(or its equivalent) of the subject
as cause of its properties.
Proof of 4*: A scientific demonstration must have premises which satisfy these six conditions,
for the following reasons: They must be:
1) true, since only a true premise could cause true knowledge.
2) primary, since otherwise they would depend on previous truths.
3) indemonstrable, because eventually we must get to immediately evident truths.
4) prior, since the conclusion depends on them.
5) better known than the conclusion, since through them we know the conclusion :
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
6) cause of the conclusion, since science is perfect knowledge, and we have this only when we
know both the fact and its proper cause.
We have assumed in the above argument (1.*a) that a syllogism is a valid argument, and in fact
we had to use a syllogism in order to prove the above conclusion. Hence we must be sure that the
syllogism is valid. This cannot be demonstrated, since it would be circular to prove that a
syllogism is valid by using a syllogism.
Aristotle in the Prior Analytics shows how we can establish the validity of the syllogism in the
First Figure, not by a demonstration, but by showing it is an application of the principle of
contradiction. Then we can establish the validity of the other forms of the syllogism by reducing
them to the First Figure:
1. First Figure in which the middle term is once a predicate and once a subject in the premises.
2. Second Figure in which the middle term is a predicate in both premises.
3. Third Figure in which the middle term is a subject in both premises.
C. Each of these figures has special laws, based on the general laws above, as follows:
(NOTE: To understand the following proofs, we must recall that in affirmative statements the
predicate is taken particularly, while in negative statements it is taken universally. Thus when
we say "Every man is an animal," we do not imply that "Every animal is a man"; but when we
say "No man is an angel" we do imply that "Every angel is not a man.")
1. Law of First Figure: The major must be universal and the minor affirmative.
Proof:
a) Either the major would also be negative and this violates general law 3 above;
b) Or the major would be affirmative, and then the major term being in predicate position in this
figure would be particular, while in the conclusion it would be universal, because the conclusion
would be negative (general law 7), and this would violate general law 5.
2) Major must always be universal. Since we have just proved that the minor is affirmative, its predicate
is particular; this predicate is the middle term, which is thus undistributed in the minor premise. Since the
middle term must be distributed in one premise (general law 2), it must be distributed in the major
premise, where it is the subject. Hence the major premise must be universal.
2. Law of the Second Figure: The major must be universal and one premise negative.
Proof:
1) If both premises were affirmative, the middle would not be distributed since it is in the predicate place
in both premises and is therefore particular.
2) The major must be universal since we have just proved that one premise is negative, and hence that the
conclusion is negative (general law 7); hence the major term is universal in the conclusion and must be
universal in the premises (general law 5).
3. Law of the Third Figure: The minor must be affirmative and one premise universal.
Proof:
2) The minor must be affirmative. If it were negative, then the conclusion must be negative (general law
7), and its predicate, which is the major term, will be universal; hence it will also be universal as the
predicate of the major premise (general law 5). Then this major premise must be negative, and both
premises would be negative, which violates general law 3. Hence the minor must be affirmative.
D. Using these special laws we may now eliminate many possible forms of the syllogism as invalid, as
follows:
There are four possible kinds of statements, A,E,I,O (see page 70), and there are three possible
figures, as we have just shown. Hence we can have 4 x 4 x 3, or 48, possible combinations of
premises. The following table shows why some forms are invalid. The names given to the
possibly valid forms are memory words chosen so that the vowels indicate the kinds of
propositions which make up the premises and the conclusion. Thus "Barbara" is the name of a
syllogism made of three A propositions; "Celarent" is the name of a syllogism made of EAE
propositions; etc.
41. IA Disamis
E. Next we show that these syllogisms in the Third and Second Figure are equivalent to ones in
the First Figure, by reducing them. We can do this by the following operations:
1) We can simply convert (symbolized by s) E and I propositions. This means simply to exchange
the subject and predicate. We can do this because in E and I propositions the predicate is no wider
in extension than the subject. If it were, then conversion would change the truth of the statement.
We cannot convert "Every man is an animal" (A) but we can convert "Some man is an animal"
(1), without changing the truth of the statement.
3) We can exchange (symbolized by m for "mutate") the premises, since this makes no essential
difference to an argument.
If we apply these four processes to the syllogisms left over from D, we find that they can all be
reduced to syllogisms in the first figure.
The consonants in the memory-names tell us bow to do this. Those which begin with B can be
reduced to Barbara, those beginning with C to Celarent, etc., if we perform the operation on a
proposition symbolized by the consonant which follows it. Thus in Cesare we take the first E
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
proposition and simply convert it (c E s are). Consonants other than the ones given above have no
significance.
F. Now how can we be sure that the four syllogisms in the First Figure, namely, Barbara,
Celarent, Darii, and Ferio, are valid?
1. Obviously Darii and Ferio are valid if Barbara and Celarent are valid, since they are respectively only
weaker forms of the latter.
a. These two modes are a simple application of the following principle (called in Latin the dictum
de omni et de nullo, "what is said of all and of none"):
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Whatever (P) is universally distributively affirmed of some subject (M) ought to be affirmed of
everything contained under its extension (S); and whatever is universally distributively denied of
some subject ought to be denied of everything contained under its extension.
b. And this principle is only a special case of the broader principle (called the principle of
agreement and disagreement):
Whenever two things are the same as one third thing they are the same as each other; and
whenever of two things one is the same as a third thing, and the other is not the same as this third
thing, they are not the same as each other.
c. This principle of agreement and disagreement must be true, because if we assume its
contradictory, we violate the principle of contradiction (namely, that a thing cannot both be and
not be at the same time and in the same respect), as follows:
If two things were the same as a third thing, and not the same as each other, then they would be X
(the third thing) and not be X (since each is the same as X, but they are Dot the same as each
other) at the same time, and in the same respect (with respect to X).
d. The principle of contradiction is true, because it is the first principle of all knowledge, which
men cannot doubt in their minds, although they may say they doubt it.
Thus we have reduced the valid forms of the syllogism to the most solid possible basis. If these
forms are not valid, then the principle of contradiction is not valid, and all knowledge is
impossible.
G. The following are examples of the valid forms of the syllogism. It will be noted that:
1. The First Figure in Barbara alone can give universal affirmative conclusions. Hence only
Barbara can give us a perfect scientific demonstration.
2. The Second Figure is useful for refuting others because it always yields a negative conclusion.
3. The Third Figure is also useful in refutation by proving an exception to a statement, since it
always ends particularly.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
"Your question, how I came first to think of proposing the experiment of drawing down the
lightning, in order to ascertain its sameness with the electric fluid, I cannot answer better than by
giving you an extract from the minutes I used to keep of the experiments I made, with
memorandums of such as I proposed to make, the reasons for making them, and the observations
that arose upon them, from which minutes my letters were afterwards drawn. By this extract you
will see, that the thought was not so much "an out-of-the-way one," but that it might have
occurred to any electrician.
'November 7, 1749. Electrical fluid agrees with lightning in these particulars. (1) Giving light. (2)
Colour of the light. (3) Crooked direction (4) Swift motion. (5) Being conducted by metals. (6)
Crack or noise in exploding. (7) Subsisting in water or ice. (8) Rending bodies it passes through.
(9) Destroying animals. (10) Melting metals. (11) Firing inflammable substances. (12)
Sulphurous smell. The electric fluid is attracted by points. We do not know whether this property
is in lightning. But since they agree in all particulars wherein we can already compare them, is it
not probable they agree likewise in this? Let the experiment be made. . . .'"
" As frequent mention is made in public papers from Europe of the success of the Philadelphia
experiment for drawing the electric fire from the clouds by means of pointed rods of iron erected
on high buildings, and it may be agreeable to the curious to be informed that the same
experiment has succeeded in Philadelphia, though made in a different and more easy manner,
which is as follows:* [* Franklin was lucky in his experiments. Many people have been killed
trying to reduplicate these experiments. No student should attempt them, as they are extremely
dangerous.]
Make a small cross of two light strips of cedar, the arms so long as to reach the four corners of a
large thin handkerchief when extended; tie the corners of the handkerchief to the extremities of
the cross, so you have the body of a kite; which being properly accommodated with a tail, loop,
and string, will rise in the air, like those made of paper; but this being of silk, is fitter to bear the
wet and wind of a thundergust without tearing. To the top of the upright cross is to be fixed a
very sharp pointed wire, rising a foot or more above the wood. To the end of the twine, next the
hand, is to be tied a silk ribbon, so that where the silk and twine join a key may be fastened. This
kite is to be raised when a thundergust appears to be coming on, and the person who holds the
string must stand within a door or window or under some cover, so that the silk ribbon may not
be wet; and care must be taken that the twine does not touch the frame of the door or window. As
soon as any of the under-clouds come over the kite, the pointed wire will draw the electric fire
from them and the kite, with all the twine, will be electrified, and the loose filaments of the twine
will stand out every way, and be attracted by an approaching finger. And when the rain has wet
the kite and twine, so that it can conduct the electric fire freely, you will find it stream out
plentifully from the key on the approach of your knuckle. At this key the phial may be charged;
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
and from the electric fire thus obtained, spirits may be kindled, and all the other electric
experiments performed, which are usually done by the help of a rubbed, glass rod or tube, and
thereby the sameness of the electric matter with that of lightning completely demonstrated."
Analysis:
A. The first quotation is an excellent example of dialectical reasoning in which Franklin is seeking a
definition of lightning in terms of its material cause by comparing it (similarities and differences) with
something better known, namely, the "electrical fluid" used in laboratory experiments.
1. He lists 12 similarities. Notice that they relate to qualities (light, color, shape, sound, smell), to
its motion, and its action (passes through metals and ice, rends bodies, kindles fuels, melts
metals).
2. He notes one possible difference, not yet tested: "electric fluid" is attracted by points. (When it
had been established that this was true also of lightning, the way was opened to the invention of
the lightning rod).
Since the identity of the two things seems probable, Franklin frames a hypothesis: Lightning is
composed of electric fluid. This is a tentative definition of lightning in terms of its material cause.
Franklin carefully describes his apparatus and the manner of performing the experiment.
Although this apparatus was quite crude, nevertheless his description makes it possible to repeat
his experiment and thereby to generalize (induction) from its result.
In this case the experiment did not merely confirm the hypothesis as probable, but rendered it
truly certain, since once lightning bad been "captured" in this way it became possible to test it
repeatedly for all the characteristic properties of "electrical fluid" and therefore to be sure that
they are identical. Here we have an example of how dialectical reasoning prepares the way for an
observation from which a real definition (not merely a tentative one) can be obtained. Such a
definition is certain, not from demonstration, but from immediate evidence.
C. Once this real definition bad been established by Franklin, then it became possible to demonstrate
some of the properties of lightning with certitude. For example, we might form the following
demonstration, as Franklin actually did in inventing the lightning rod:
Minor: This is what Franklin had first guessed at dialectically, and then established with
certitude from observation. It is a definition, although an incomplete one, of lightning.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The following is a typical practical problem which can be solved by elementary mechanics:
Problem: A log 11 feet long is used as a first-class lever (see diagram) to lift the wheel of an
automobile out of the mud. The wheel is supporting 1500 pounds weight. The fulcrum of the
lever is placed 1 foot from the axle, and the axle is at the end of the log to lift stands on the other
end of the log. How heavy must he be wheel?
Answer:
2. ideal effort required E = resistance R = 1500 = 150 lbs. (the man's weight).
ideal M 10
The student is likely merely to learn such a formula and apply it to problems in a routine fashion.
A scientist however is not so much concerned with working problems as understanding the
reason why.
The law as a general fact: This law of the first class lever can be tested experimentally and
found to be approximately true. That is why we say "ideal mechanical advantage" because in
actual experimentation various factors interfere with its being perfectly
realized, and the lever is found not to be quite as effective as the law would predict. However,
we can be sure that the law is true in every case within very narrow limits, and by removing
disturbing factors we can make this accuracy greater and greater.
The reason for this fact: This can be stated in syllogistic form as follows:
The ratio of arcs RR' and EE' is equal to the ratio of the
distances EF and RF
And: in a lever the ideal
mechanical advantage is equal to ratio of the distances
moved by the effort and the
resistance, i.e., the ratio
of arcs RR' and EE'
Therefore: in a lever the
ideal mechanical advantage is equal to the ratio of the distances
EF and RF,i.e., to the ratio of
the effort and the resistance arm.
Major: This is a theorem which can be proved in geometry. It applies in the present case, because the
angles RFR' and EFE' are equal (they are vertical angles). Hence it is possible to lay off the distance FS
and FS' equal to FR and FR' and then the arc SS' will be equivalent to the arc RR'. Then it is easy to prove
that the arcs within this segment of a circle have the same ratio as their radii, namely, that SSI: EEI : : FS:
FE'.
Minor: This is a nominal definition of "mechanical advantage" and is based on the physical fact
that a small amount of energy will move a large body through a small distance.
It will be noticed that in this proof the major premise is purely mathematical and rests on
mathematical axioms and postulates. The minor, on the other band, is purely physical, since it
deals with the characteristics of moving bodies. The middle term is common to both. In the
major premise it is taken in the sense of a relation between abstract quantities, in the minor
premise as a measurement of concrete or physical quantities, since the distances spoken of are
physical distances through which physical bodies are moved by physical forces. The application
of mathematics to physics takes place in the conclusion, which states a physical law in
mathematical terms.
This demonstration is through a proper cause from the mathematical point of view, since the
proper cause for this equality of proportion is the equal angle of the arcs.
William Harvey (1578-1657) corrected the most serious mistake of Greek and medieval biology,
the wrong conception of the function of the heart. His proof that the true function of the heart is
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
to circulate the blood opened the way to the whole modern development of physiology, which is
the basic part of biology. Consequently, Harvey is sometimes pictured as a scientific
revolutionary. In fact the opposite is the case; his work is a proof of the continuity between
ancient and modern biology, since Harvey was a thorough Aristotelian. He had learned the
Aristotelian method of accurate observation and acute reasoning during his studies at the
University of Padua, the stronghold of Aristotelian science in Europe, and this method is
beautifully exemplified in his great work, An Anatomical Disquisition on the Motion of the Heart
and the Blood in Animals.
The student who wishes to understand the scientific method should study this work carefully. He
will find that it is a very clear example of a complete exposition, as the following outline
indicates (compare with pages 185 ff).
1. Introduction: Reviewing opinions of previous writers about the pulse and function of the
arteries and the heart, Harvey shows that these opinions leave serious problems unsolved.
CHAPTER I: Why the author is writing; the difficulty of the subject, etc.
Harvey uses his introduction, which is quite lengthy, to give a historical account of the opinions
held before his time. Then be uses Chapter I to give a rhetorical introduction in which he wins
the favor, attention, and interest of his reader. We might have expected the reverse order, but
Harvey well realized that nothing would better establish himself with his readers, who were
professional medical men and biologists, than to show his thorough acquaintance with the whole
history of the problem. Only after this does he then attempt a more formal beginning. This is an
example of the way in which the form of a complete exposition can be varied and adapted to
different circumstances.
CHAPTER IV. The motion, action, and function of the heart: a summary of what has been shown
in the preceding chapters. The definition of the heart arrived at is as follows:
"The chief function of the heart is the transmission and pumping of blood through the arteries to
the extremities of the body. Thus the pulse which we feel in the arteries is nothing else than the
impact of blood from the heart."
This still pertains to the state of the question, because it consists in stating the principle by which a
solution to the problem can be reached, namely, a definition of the heart. Definitions are not
demonstrated, but can be arrived at only by an analysis of experience; hence Harvey carefully prepares
the way for his definition by a series of beautiful experiments in which false definitions are eliminated,
and the true one exposed. The definition arrived at is in terms of the four causes, since (as the student can
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
verify from the text of Harvey's work) he establishes the composition, structure, and function of the heart
(i.e., its material, formal, and final causes). The efficient cause of the heart is not treated in detail in this
work, as it is a problem of embryology which Harvey develops in another famous book. Furthermore,
Harvey makes clear that he does not suppose his definition to be complete, since he is not sure whether
the heart is only a pump, or whether in addition to this it acts on the blood chemically. This latter problem
be leaves for further study, and indeed it can not be solved until much later when the nature of oxidation
has been discovered by chemists. He has defined the heart as a pump, but he has not yet proved that it is a
property of the pump to circulate the blood.
B. The Demonstration:
CHAPTER VI: The course by which the blood is carried from the vena cava into the arteries, or
from the right into the left ventricle of the heart.
CHAPTER VII: The blood percolates through the substance of the lungs from the right ventricle
of the heart into the pulmonary veins and the left ventricle.
CHAPTER VIII: How Harvey came to discover the circulation of the blood.
CHAPTER X: The first proposition presupposed in this proof freed from objections and
confirmed by experiments. Here Harvey shows that the heart pumps too much blood into the
arteries for this blood to be newly made.
CHAPTER XI: The second proposition presupposed is defined. Here Harvey shows that the
blood in the arteries is too great to have been newly made.
CHAPTER XII: Shows that, from the forgoing two premises, circulation is a necessary
conclusion.
CHAPTER XIII: A third proposition implied in the proof, namely, the veins bring the blood back
to the heart.
CHAPTER XIV: Final statement of his conclusion, namely, that circulation is proper to the blood
and the heart.
It will be noticed that in giving his demonstration Harvey first gives a dialectical preparation for it in
Chapters VI-VIII. The first two of these chapters remove the chief difficulty to understanding his proof,
namely, certain mistaken ideas about the relation of the lungs to the heart. Chapter VIII tells how Harvey
hit on the idea of circulation, namely, from the analogy between the vascular system and cyclical
processes in non-living nature.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Next Harvey gives his proof in short form in Chapter IX, and then proceeds to establish the
premises on which the proof is based. The major premise is immediately evident, but the minor
premise presupposes three other statements, and these Harvey establishes in Chapters X to XIII.
Then in Chapter XIV he actually puts together his complete proof, as follows:
And now I may be allowed to give in brief my view of the circulation of the blood, and to
propose it for general adoption.
Since all things, both argument and ocular experience, show that the blood passes through the
lungs and heart by the action of the ventricles, and is sent for distribution to all parts of the body,
where it makes its way into the veins and pores of the flesh, and then flows by the veins from the
circumference on every side to the center, from the lesser to the greater veins, and is by them
finally discharged into the vena cava and right auricle of the heart, and this in a quantity or in
such flux and reflux thither by the arteries, hither by the veins, as cannot possibly be supplied by
the ingested food, and is much greater than can be required for mere purposes of nutrition; it is
necessary to conclude that the blood in the animal body is impelled in a circle, and is in a state of
ceaseless motion; that this is the act or function which the heart performs by means of its pulse;
and that it is the sole and only end of the motion and contraction of the heart.
Minor: That the heart is such an organ can be establish from three propositions:
1. Too much blood leaves the heart to be produced from food in a single day. This can be seen
from the capacity of the heart, the number of beats per minute and its structure as a pump.
2. Too much blood leaves the arteries to be produced from food in a single day; shown in a
similar way.
It will be noticed that this proof depends on the quantity of blood, but nevertheless is not a
mathematical-physical proof, since what is involved is not an exact quantity, nor any special
property of quantity, but merely a rough proportion, as can be seen from the very round figures
which Harvey uses.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Harvey does not give a special section of his exposition to answering objections because be finds
it more convenient to take up these objections chapter by chapter, but he does confirm his proof
by a series of arguments which are plausible, but which do not give the proper reason for his
conclusion. In his main proof the proper reason assigned is from the material cause (the quantity
of blood), but it also involves the formal cause, since Harvey has already established that the
structure of the heart is obviously pump-like.
The following is part of the argument for the natural right of private property given by Leo XIII
in his great encyclical, Rerum Novarum (1891), in which he refutes the theories of socialism and
proposes the Christian doctrine on the rights of labor.
For every man has by nature the right to possess property as his own. This is one of the chief
points of distinction between man and the animal creation. For the brute has no power of self-
direction, but is governed by two chief instincts, which keep his powers alert, move him to use
his strength, and determine him to action without the power of choice. These instincts are self-
preservation and the propagation of the species. Both can attain their purpose by means of things
which are close at hand; beyond their surroundings the brute creation cannot go, for they are
moved to action by sensibility alone, and by the things which sense perceives. But with man it is
different indeed. He possesses, on the one band, the full perfection of animal nature, and
therefore he enjoys, at least as much as the rest of the animal race, the fruition of the things of the
body. But animality, however perfect, is far from being the whole of humanity, and is indeed
humanity's humble handmaid, made to serve and obey. It is the mind, or the reason, which is the
chief thing in us who are human beings; it is this which makes a human being human, and
distinguishes him essentially and completely from the brute. And on this account -- viz., that man
alone among animals possesses reason -- it must be within his right to have things not merely for
temporary and momentary use, as other living beings have them, but in stable and permanent
possession; he must have not only things which perish in the using, but also those which, though
used, remain for use in the future.
This becomes still more clearly evident if we consider man's nature a little more deeply. For
man, comprehending by the power of his reason, things innumerable, and joining the future with
the present-being, moreover, the master of his own acts-governs himself by the foresights of his
counsel, under the eternal law and the power of God, whose Providence governs all things.
Wherefore it is in his power to exercise his choice not only on things which regard his present
welfare, but also on those which will be for his advantage in time to come. Hence man not only
can possess the fruits of the earth, but also the earth itself; for of the products of the earth be can
make provision for the future. Man's needs do not die out, but recur; satisfied today, they demand
new supplies tomorrow. Nature, therefore, owes to man a storehouse that shall never fail, the
daily supply of his daily wants. And this he finds only in the inexhaustible fertility of the earth.
Nor must we, at this stage, have recourse to the State. Man is older than the State and he holds
the right of providing for the life of his body prior to the formation of any State.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
And to say that God has given the earth to the use and enjoyment of the universal human race is
not to deny that there can be private property. For God has granted the earth to mankind in
general; not in the sense that all without distinction can deal with it as they please, but rather that
no part of it has been assigned to any one in particular, and that the limits of private possession
have been left to be fixed by man's own industry and the laws of individual peoples. Moreover,
the earth, though divided among private owners, ceases not thereby to minister to the needs of
all; for there is no one who does not live on what the land brings forth. Those who do not possess
the soil, contribute their labor; so that it may be truly said that all human subsistence is derived
either from labor on one's own land, or from some laborious industry which is paid either in the
produce of the land itself or in that which is exchanged for what the land brings forth.
Here, again, we have another proof that private ownership is according to nature's law. For that
which is required for the preservation of life and for life's well being, is produced in great
abundance by the earth, but not until man has brought it into cultivation and lavished upon it his
care and skill. Now, when man thus spends the industry of his mind and the strength of his body
in procuring the fruits of nature, by that act he makes his own that portion of nature's field which
he cultivates -- that portion on which he leaves, as it were, the impress of his own personality;
and it cannot but be just that he should possess that portion as his own, and should have a right to
keep it without molestation....
Minor: Other animals live by instinct, but a rational animal lives by deliberate planning for the
future.
Proof of Minor: This is the definition of man established by the science of psychology.
Objection: The state can provide man with his material needs.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Answer: Man's duty and right to provide for himself is prior to the state, and cannot be taken
away by the state.
Another objection: Man may have a right to what he produces, but not the land.
Answer: Since man has a right to what he produces from the land, he must also have a right to
keep the land in order to produce from it.
In the above demonstration the student will note that Leo XIII argues from the following
principles:
1. Man is a rational animal. This is a definition which comes from the theoretical science of
psychology.
2. Man has a moral right to those things which are necessary for him to live a good human life.
This is a basic principle of ethics.
3. Man's need for permanent possession of material things, and his ability to acquire them by
labor, is prior to the state. This is a basic principle of politics.
Leo XIII's proof is certainly scientific and leads to a necessary conclusion. However, as he
himself indicates when he points out that the laws of individual society limit this right, this
general conclusion has to be applied to the particular circumstances of each society. It is not
wrong for the state to take over ownership of certain kinds of property if this is necessary for the
common good, as long as it does not violate the basic right of the individual to own what he
needs. The conclusions of the social sciences usually admit of such modifications in practice
according to differing circumstances, except in cases where what is involved is intrinsically evil
and contrary to nature, in which case the action is always wrong, whatever the circumstances.
The following is from the Summa Theologiae, Part III, Question 35, Article 4.* [*Reprinted from
the Summa Theologica, Benziger Brothers, Inc., publishers and copyright owners.]
Objection 1. It would seem that the Blessed Virgin should not be called the Mother of God. For
in the divine mysteries we should not make any assertion that is not taken from Holy Scripture.
But we read nowhere in Holy Scripture that she is the mother or parent of God, but that she is the
mother of Christ or of the Child, as may be seen in Matthew 1:18. Therefore we should not say
that the Blessed Virgin is the Mother of God.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Objection 2: Further, Christ is called God in respect of his divine nature. But the divine nature
did not first originate from the Virgin. Therefore the Blessed Virgin should not be called the
Mother of God.
Objection 3: Moreover, the word God is predicated in common of Father, Son, and Holy Ghost.
If, therefore, the Blessed Virgin is Mother of God, it seems to follow that she was the Mother of
Father, Son, and Holy Ghost, which cannot be allowed. Therefore the Blessed Virgin should not
be called Mother of God.
On the contrary, in the chapters of Cyril, approved in the Council of Ephesus, he read: "If
anyone confess not that Emmanuel is truly God, and that for this reason the Holy Virgin is the
Mother of God, since she begot of her flesh the Word of God made flesh, let him be anathema."
I answer that, as stated above (Question 16, Article 1), every word that signifies a nature in the
concrete can stand for any hypostasis** [** Technical term used by the Greek Fathers equivalent
to substance. ] of that nature. Now, since the union of the Incarnation took place in the
hypostasis as above stated (Question 2, Article 3), it is manifest that this word God can stand for
the hypostasis, having a human nature and a divine nature. Therefore, whatever belongs to the
divine and to the human nature can be attributed to that Person: both when a word is employed to
stand for it signifying the divine nature, and when a word is used signifying the human nature.
Now conception and birth are attributed to the person and hypostasis in respect of that nature in
which it is conceived and born. Since, therefore, the human nature was taken by the divine
Person in the very beginning of the conception, as stated above (Question 33, Article 3), it
follows that it can truly be said that God was conceived and born of the Virgin. Now from this is
a woman called a man's mother, that she conceived him and gave birth to him. Therefore the
Blessed Virgin is truly called the Mother of God. For the only way in which it could be denied
that the Blessed Virgin is the Mother of God would be either if the humanity were first subject to
conception and birth, before this man were the Son of God, as Photinus said; or if the humanity
were not assumed unto unity of the Person or hypostasis of the Word of God, as Nestorius
maintained. But both of these are erroneous. Therefore it is heretical to deny that the Blessed
Virgin is the Mother of God.
Reply to Objection 1. This was the argument of Nestorius, and it is solved by saying that,
although we do not find it said expressly in Scripture that the Blessed Virgin is the Mother of
God, yet we do find it expressly said in Scripture that "Jesus Christ is true God" (as
may be seen, I John, 5:20) and that the Blessed Virgin is the Mother of Jesus Christ, which is
clearly expressed in Matthew 1:18. Therefore, from the words of Scripture it follows of necessity
that she is the Mother of God.
Again it: is written (Romans 9:5) that Christ is of the Jews "according to the flesh, who is over
all things, God blessed forever." But he is not of the Jews except through the Blessed Virgin.
Therefore he who is "above all things, God blessed forever" is truly born of the Blessed Virgin as
of His mother.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Reply to Objection 2: This was an argument of Nestorius. But Cyril, in a letter against Nestorius,
answers it thus: "Just as when a man's soul is born with its body, they are considered as one
being: and if anyone wish to say that the mother of the flesh is not the mother of the soul, he says
too much. Something like this may be perceived in the generation of Christ. For the Word of
God was born of the substance of God the Father: but because be took flesh, we must of
necessity confess that in the flesh he was born of a woman." Consequently, we must say that the
Blessed Virgin is called the Mother of God, not as though she were the Mother of the Godhead,
but because she is the mother, according to his human nature, of the Person who has both the
divine and the human nature.
Reply to Objection 3: Although the name God is common to the three Persons, yet sometimes it
stands for the Person of the Father alone, sometimes only for the Person of the Son or of the
Holy Ghost, as was stated above (Question 16, Article 1). So that when we say, "The Blessed
Virgin is the Mother of God," this word God stands only for the Incarnate Person of the Son.
In the body of this article St. Thomas states his proof positively and negatively:
A. Positive demonstration:
Minor: Mary is the Mother of Christ, who is a divine Person having a divine nature from all
eternity and a human nature taken from Mary (Question 33, Article 3).
Notice that the major here rests on a philosophical truth (namely, the right way to give names)
while the minor is a revealed article of faith. This is typical of theological reasoning, that
frequently one premise is taken from faith and one from reason, although sometimes both are
taken from faith.
B. Negative demonstration:
If one holds that Mary should not be called the Mother of God, this must logically be because he
holds either that:
1. Christ only became the son of God after he was born of Mary.
2. Or that in him there was not one single divine Person, but a divine and a human person.
But: both of these positions have been condemned by the Councils as heresy.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
Therefore: to deny that Mary is to be called the Mother of God is equivalent to heresy.
We can briefly formulate these objections and the distinctions by which St. Thomas answers
them as follows:
BIBLIOGRAPHY
The teacher and student will find the Great Books of the Western World, edited by Robert
Maynard Hutchins (Encyclopaedia Britannica, Inc., Chicago, 1952), an invaluable collection for
the further study of the liberal arts. The second and third volume of this set are called The Great
Ideas, A Syntopicon, edited by Mortimer J. Adler and William Gorman. This contains very
valuable bibliographies of the classical, ancient, and modern works on the liberal arts, and useful
articles outlining the main problems and topics of controversy concerning them. Especially
recommended are the following articles: ART, ASTRONOMY, BEAUTY, DEFINITION,
DIALECTIC, INDUCTION, INFINITY, JUDGMENT, KNOWLEDGE, LANGUAGE, LOGIC,
MATHEMATICS, MECHANICS, POETRY, QUALITY, QUANTITY, REASONING,
RHETORIC, SIGN AND SYMBOL. In using this work, however, it must be re membered that
some of the "great books" in this collection are forbidden by the Index or by Canon Law and
cannot be read by students, or by teachers, without a dispensation of the Bishop, because they
argue against the natural law or the Christian Faith in a sophistical manner. The very fact that
they are the work of very clever and gifted writers make them dangerous for any except those
with adequate theological and philosophical training, since these writers lead man from truth by
appealing to the weaknesses of human appetite, especially intellectual pride and intellectual
despair.
It is also important that a teacher or student of the liberal arts should be acquainted with
educational history. For this purpose the following are recommended:
1. Kane, William T., S.J., A History of Education, considered chiefly in its development in the
Western World (Chicago, 1954). This book, which contains good bibliographies and which
shows a good acquaintance with original sources, will serve as a brief introductory picture to the
history of education.
2. Brickman, William W., Guide to Research in Educational History (New York: University
Bookstore, 1949). This contains extensive bibliographies of works on the history of education.
The last item lists the many lines of approach to the history of education which may be taken. I
would like to recommend only that the teacher make an acquaintance with the following books,
as a beginning to recovery of the liberal arts tradition:
1. Marrou, Henri I., History of Education in Antiquity; translated by George Lamb (Sheed and
Ward, 1956).
2. Highet, Gilbert, The Classical Tradition, Greek and Roman Influence on Western Literature
(Oxford University Press, 1953).
3. Marrique, Pierre, S.J., History of Christian Education; 3 vols. (Fordham University Press,
1924-32).
4. Rashdall, Hastings, The Universities of Europe in the Middle Ages; revised by F. M. Powicke
and A. B. Emden, 3 vols. (Oxford University Press, 1936).
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
5. Abelson, Paul, The Seven Liberal Arts, (Teachers College, Columbia University, 1906).
6. Gauss, George Edward, St. Ignatius' Ideal of a Jesuit University (Marquette University Press,
1954).
This study of the history of the liberal arts, however, cannot in way substitute for direct
acquaintance with the classical works in these fields, The Syntopicon (see above) contains
excellent bibliographies on these arts. In the following the basic classical work on the subject,
and one or more modern works which will introduce student or teacher to modern conceptions of
the art are suggested.
A. Logic:
1. The classical works are Aristotle's Organon, Rhetoric, and Poetics. They are on the whole very
superior to subsequent works on the subject, both in their completeness and their scientific
method. They are available complete in translation in the Great Books, Vol. 8, and in the Oxford
translation published by the Oxford University Press, and edited by W. D. Ross, A good selection
is included in The Basic Works of Aristotle, edited by R. P. McKeon (Random House, 1941). The
Poetics and Rhetoric are available in bandy form in the "Modern Library." The Greek texts with
English translation are available in part in the "Loeb Classical Library" (the Organon is not yet
complete).
2. The Poetics and Rhetoric are quite easy even for the beginner. The Organon is difficult for
even the most advanced. Hence it is recommended that the beginner start with a simple textbook
in logic written from a genuinely Aristotelian point of view. Many of the so-called "traditional
logics," even those claiming to be Thomistic or scholastic, actually present a very degenerated
"tradition." The following two books are sound:
Oesterle, John A., Logic -- The Art of Defining and Reasoning, (Prentice-Hall, 1935).
3. For advanced students in Aristotelian logic the commentaries of St. Albert the Great on the
whole of the Organon, of St. Thomas Aquinas on parts of it, and the summary of Sylvester
Maurus on the whole are indispensable. However these have not yet been translated into English,
with the exception of St. Thomas Aquinas, Commentary on the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle
(mimeographed edition); translated by Pierre Conway, O.P. (Doyon, Laval, Quebec 1950).
Also useful are the commentaries which reflect a sound Aristotelianism in doctrine, but
not in their manner of ordering the subject.
John of St. Thomas, Outlines of Formal Logic; translated by F, C. Wade, S.J. (Marquette
University, 1955).
John of St. Thomas, The Material Logic of John St. Thomas; translated by Yves Simon
and John Glanville (University of Chicago Press, 1956).
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
4. Logic underwent marked changes in the period of latter scholasticism and then entered into a
long period in which the "traditional logic" was taught in a very poor form and without any
extensive research. In the middle of the 19tb century interest began to revive in the form of
symbolic or mathematical logic. To begin a study of this subject the following are recommended:
Copi, Irving M., Symbolic Logic (Macmillan, 1953). This is an elementary text.
Veatch, H., Intentional Logic (Yale, 1952). This is a criticism of modern logic by an
author who shows its nominalistic implications.
In beginning the study of modern logic the student should note that it is essentially a
calculus, related to Aristotelian logic in much the same way that algebra is related to the
classical arithmetic. Hence it cannot stand by itself. Unless it is an instrument of logic in
Aristotle's sense, it becomes a merely arbitrary system of marks on paper, a kind of parlor
game. Used as an instrument of logic it is undoubtedly useful, although to date it has
actually been shown to be of use only in mathematics. It cannot substitute for Aristotelian
logic, because it does not solve the basic problems of logic which have to do, not with the
manipulation of signs, but with mental relations, founded on the nature of the mind and
of things.
1. Basic to the study of these arts is the study of language. Mario Pei, The Story of Language (J.
P. Lippincott Co., 1949), will serve as an initial introduction to the problems of language. The
Syntopicon, articles on Language, and Sign and Symbol will furnish an introduction and
bibliographies to more philosophical problems of language. Otto Jesperson, Growth and
Structure of the English Language (Doubleday Anchor Book, 1955), will show how these
problems are found in our own tongue.
2. Crane, Ronald and Olsen, Elder, Critics and Criticism, Ancient and Modern (University of
Chicago). This work, and especially the historical articles by Richard P. McKeon, distinguish and
trace the various strands of opinion on the subject of these arts.
Crane, Ronald, The Language of Criticism and the Structure of Poetics (University of
Toronto, 1953), is the most accurate analysis of the poetics and an excellent confrontation
between it and the contemporary revival of interest in critical theory.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
The "Chicago school of criticism" represented by these two books is undoubtedly the
most authentically Aristotelian. Its chief defect is that, in anxiety to distinguish poetry
accurately from rhetoric and other disciplines, it has not taken care to show how it can be
integrated with the other intellectual and moral virtues. Consequently, these critics
somewhat exaggerate the autonomy of the work of art, fearing to explain "imitation" in a
way that subordinates the work of art to its object, and also fearing to show the
subordination of poetics and fine art to prudence.
3. Wellek, René and Warren, Austin, Theory of Literature (Harvest Harcourt Brace, 1956). This
work, which has very good bibliographies, lacks sound theoretical principles, but is an excellent
introduction to the problems and opinions of literary criticism.
4. Brook, Cleanth and Warren, Robert Penn, Fundamentals of Good Writing (formerly Modern
Rhetoric) (Harcourt Brace, 1950). This textbook, which contains excellent readings, serves to
show the state of modern rhetoric. It will be noted that it also lacks the solid theoretical
foundation of Aristotle's work.
5. The teacher should also become acquainted with modern propaganda and advertising
techniques. The popular book of Vance Packard, Hidden Persuaders (McKay, 1957), will serve
as an introduction.
6. The general problems of esthetics are well listed in Jarret, James I., The Quest for Beauty,
(Prentice-Hall, 1957).
7. The field of theoretical writing on music is very extensive. Such a text as David D. Boyden, An
Introduction to Music (Alfred A. Knopf, 1956), will serve to show the scope of the present study
of music, and the bibliographies will lead into the field.
There is no really classical work on musical theory, because such works as Boethius, De
Musica, treated only of the mathematical theory of music and left its imitative character
untouched. Herbert T. Schwartz in a doctrinal dissertation, An Aristotelian Analysis of the
Elements, Principles and Causes of the Art of Music (Columbia University; published in
Cleveland, Ohio, 1936), showed how the principles of Aristotle's Poetics can be applied
to music as regards its mathematical structure. He has not published a detailed analysis of
its manner of imitating the emotions.
The little work of Percy Goetschius, The Structure of Music, (Theodore Presser Co.,
1934), can be recommended for its clear presentation of the basic principles of music, and
the brilliant series of six lectures by Igor Stravinsky, Poetics of Music (Vintage Books,
1956), for its explanation of the present state of the art. Stravinsky emphatically denies
that music is "imitative," bu this must be must be taken in the sense that music does not
imitate particular objects, but the emotions.
8. Writing on the plastic arts is also very extensive, and most of the "explanations" or defenses of
"modern art" contain very much the same arguments. For the problem of Christian art the work of
Anton Henze and Theodor Filthaut, Contemporary Church Art, translated by Cecily Hastings and
edited by Maurice Lavanoux, (Sheed and Ward, 1956), is excellent.
THE ARTS OF LEARNING AND COMMUNICATION: A handbook of the Liberal Arts
C. Mathematics
2. Newman, James R., ed., The World of Mathematics, 4 vols. (Simon and Schuster, 1955), is an
excellent collection of material which will give the beginner a very good notion both of the scope
and the problems of modern mathematical thought although containing serious philosophical
errors.
4. Black, Max, The Nature of Mathematics (Humanities Press, 1950), presents the controversies
on the foundations of mathematics. Also recommended is the article MATHEMATICS,
FOUNDATIONS OF, in the Encyclopaedia Britannica, Vol. 15, p. 82, by S. C. Kleene.
5. Aristotle did not leave a treatise on mathematics, but his thought is very well reconstructed by
Hippocrates George Apostle, Aristotle's Philosophy of Mathematics, (University of Chicago
Press, 1952).
It might be noted that the "general mathematics" of which Apostle speaks is probably the
metaphysics of quantity, rather than a distinct mathematical science, like geometry and
arithmetic.
6. The student and teacher should become familiar with the classical works of Euclid, Apollonius,
Archimedes, Nicomachus, and Ptolemy contained in Great Books, Vols. 11 and 16.
D. In addition I would recommend to the teacher who is looking for easy materials in natural science:
1. Robinson, Edward M., and George Polk, Science: How? Why? Wherefore (The Priory Press,
Dubuque, Iowa, 1957).
2. Kane, William H., and collaborators, Science in Synthesis (The Priory Press, Dubuque, Iowa,
1957).
3. Scientific American Books (Simon and Schuster, New York). These are paperbound reprints of
the excellent articles from the Scientific American Magazine.