Darrigol (2008)
Darrigol (2008)
Darrigol (2008)
During the past twenty years, historians have disagreed over the meaning of
the quanta which Max Planck introduced in his black-body theory of 1900.
The source of this confusion is the publication, in 1978, of Thomas Kuhn’s
iconoclastic thesis that Planck did not mean his energy quanta to express a
quantum discontinuity (Kuhn, 1978). The aim of the present essay is a com-
parison of the opinions of various historians on this issue.1
Whether or not Planck introduced a quantum discontinuity is an import-
ant question, for it affects our understanding of the origins of the quantum
theory of Niels Bohr and Arnold Sommerfeld. Yet the focus on this question
could bring with it a few misconceptions, which should be cleared out from
the start. Firstly, one should not infer that the true meaning of the energy
quanta was a central issue for Planck himself around 1900: what Planck
emphasized was the introduction of two universal constants, h and k, and
their power to bridge gas theory and radiation theory.2 Secondly, one should
not assume that historians of Planck’s radiation theory completely disagree
with each other: a consensus exists on many important features of Planck’s
program. Lastly, my focus on the intricacies of Planck’s thoughts should not
be mistaken as an indication that quantum theory was started in an exclus-
ively individual manner. On the contrary, most early quantum concepts
emerged through the confrontation and combination of the views of several
physicists.3
The first section of this paper gives a classification of the various attitudes
historians have taken towards Planck’s quanta. In the second section, a corre-
lation is established between the attitudes and the arguments used to support
them. Next, the validity of these arguments is shown to depend on the his-
torian’s interest and methodology. In particular, it turns out that the his-
torians who see in Planck the discoverer of quantum discontinuity relied not
only on Planck’s publications but also on the ways other physicists perceived
and used his work. A last section is devoted to the consequences of a rigorous
attention to the development of Planck’s program in Planck’s own under-
standing. Although Kuhn’s thesis about the quantum discontinuity is thus
corroborated, his overall account turns out to be seriously flawed. The mean-
ing of the steps taken by Planck in 1900 must instead be based on Allan
Needell’s profound study of Planck’s attitude toward thermodynamic irre-
versibility (Needell, 1980).
As a preliminary, it may help to recall aspects of Planck’s radiation theory
on which most historians would agree. In 1895, Planck started an ambitious
program in which he hoped to provide an explanation of thermodynamic
irreversibility based on electrodynamic processes. He was not satisfied with
Boltzmann’s similar attempt based on gas theory, for it led to a statistical
understanding of irreversibility and thereby contradicted Planck’s belief in
the absolute validity of the entropy law. Besides, Planck knew from Gustav
Kirchhoff that thermodynamic considerations could be applied to radiation
at thermal equilibrium – the so-called black-body radiation – to derive the
universality of its spectrum. Planck hoped that a simple electrodynamic
model of the thermalization of radiation would lead to this fundamental
spectrum, in which Berlin experimenters were increasingly interested for
metrological reasons. The model he selected was a set of electric resonators
(one for each frequency) enclosed in a cavity with perfectly reflecting walls.4
After a humbling exchange with Ludwig Boltzmann, Planck admitted that
he could not obtain an irreversible evolution of his system without the ad hoc
assumption of ‘‘natural radiation,’’ a formal counterpart of the assumption
of molecular chaos which Boltzmann had introduced in order to justify his
own irreversibility theorem (the H-theorem of 1872). Thanks to this assump-
tion, the uncontrollable, irregular aspects of the evolution of the system were
eliminated to yield a deterministic, irreversible evolution. In the case of equi-
librium, Planck established the relation unΩ(8pn2/c3)U between the spectral
density un of thermal radiation and the average energy U of a resonator at
Planck’s Quantum 221
1. Histories
Statements on the meaning of Planck’s energy quanta fall into three cate-
gories. According to the first category, in 1900 Planck introduced the idea
that some microphysical entities (his resonators) could only have discrete
energy values. According to the second, Planck did not know himself what
222 O. Darrigol
the precise meaning of the energy quanta was. According to the third, Planck
still believed that the energy of his resonators varied continuously, and he
had no intention to revolutionize the laws of dynamics. Table 1 indicates the
position of various historians in this scheme.
225–226). Kangro here alluded to the analogy between Planck’s and Boltz-
mann’s combinatorics: what Boltzmann did not intend to be revolutionary
could not be either in Planck’s tentative transposition of Boltzmann’s reason-
ing. In his dissertation and in later writings, Allan Needell offered other
reasons to leave the meaning of Planck’s energy quanta in the dark: ‘‘Planck
was not concerned with describing details of the motion or behavior of an
oscillator.... The question of whether Planck introduced quantum discontinu-
ities in 1900 is not a major issue; the answer depends on the attitude toward
physical concepts and on the level of commitment one requires to credit
someone with such an introduction’’ (Needell, 1988, p. xix). Therein Needell
made a historical point, that Planck, in his program, deliberately left the
detailed behavior of his resonators undetermined; and a methodological
point, that historians should distinguish different degrees of commitment of
a given actor on a given issue. In a review of the Klein-Kuhn controversy
published in 1981, Peter Galison adopted a similar stance: ‘‘The question of
the continuum vs. discreteness as such, which for us is of such overwhelming
interest, was entirely peripheral to Planck’s other concerns.... It is not always
possible to impose a self-consistent, fully articulated set of beliefs on a scien-
tist’s view of his problem, especially at periods of great upheaval’’ (Galison,
1981, p. 82).8
The third kind of historian of Planck’s quantum is the continuist one, who
makes the energy of Planck’s resonators a continuous variable despite
Planck’s formal use of energy-elements. Thomas Kuhn inaugurated this trend
in 1978 with his book on Black-body theory. A typical statement of Kuhn’s
reads: ‘‘The concept of restricted resonator energy played no role in [Planck’s]
thought until after the Lectures [of 1906]’’ (Kuhn, 1978, p. 126). In 1988, I
have defended the same thesis on a different basis and with a twist: whereas
Kuhn made Planck a persistently classical physicist, I believe with Needell
that Planck left a non-classical behavior of his resonators open (Darrigol,
1988). Moreover, Needell has rightly noted that the word ‘‘classical’’ points
to a post-quantum-theoretical idealization of nineteenth-century physics that
does not apply to the multiple, open, evolving theories of the turn of the
century (Needell, 1988).
Interestingly, Planck’s own retrospective appraisals of his 1900 break-
through do not corroborate the discontinuist account. Instead they must be
situated somewhere in-between the indeterminist and the continuist cate-
gories. In his Nobel lecture of 1920, Planck wrote (Planck, 1920, p. 127):
Planck’s Quantum 225
‘‘Whereas [the constant h] was indispensable – for only with its help could
the size of the...’elementary domains’ or Spielräume of the probability be
determined – it proved to block and resist every attempt at fitting it into the
frame of classical theory.... The failure of all attempts...soon left no doubt:
either the quantum of action was only a fictitious quantity, or the derivation
of the radiation law rested on a truly physical thought....Experiments have
decided in favor of the second alternative. But science does not owe the
prompt and indubitable character of this decision to tests of the law for the
energy distribution of thermal radiation, and even less to my special deri-
vation of this law; it owes that to the unceasing progress of the researchers
who have put the quantum of action to the service of their investigations. A.
Einstein made the first breakthrough in this domain.’’
Clearly, Planck did not regard the physical significance of energy quanta
as established by his own work on radiation. In his own view, the decisive
steps in this regard were Einstein’s and others’ applications of the quantum
to non-thermal phenomena such as the photoelectric effect, specific heats,
and atomic spectra. Planck never claimed responsibility for the revolution of
which a long historiographical tradition makes him the hero. ‘‘The introduc-
tion [of the constant h],’’ he pondered at the close of his life, ‘‘meant a much
more radical break from classical theory than I had initially suspected’’
(Planck, 1948, p. 397).
2. Arguments
1) Tradition
Hund, Jost
2) Planck’s proof of 1900
3) Statistical thermodynamics Klein
4) Contemporary readings
5) Planck’s asserted goals Kangro, Needell, Galison Kuhn, Darrigol
6) Formal heuristics
Table 2: Arguments
226 O. Darrigol
detail that is easily filtered out by a prejudiced reader. The one physicist-
historian who does quote the embarrassing sentence, Res Jost (1995), pro-
nounces his anti-Kuhn ‘‘verdict’’ right after it.9
Another argument in favor of the discontinuist interpretation appeals to
the fact that statistical mechanics, if properly applied to a classical radiat-
ing system, necessarily leads to the Rayleigh-Jeans law. In many textbook
accounts, Planck is said to have been aware of this fact and to have intro-
duced quantum discontinuity in order to avoid this absurd consequence of
the classical theory. Klein rightly rejected this view and suggested instead
that Planck was too unfamiliar with statistical mechanics to understand
the fact. But Klein still used his own knowledge of classical implications to
infer that Planck’s demonstration only made sense if the resonators were
quantized. More exactly, Klein assumed that in 1900 Planck adopted
Boltzmann’s relation between entropy and probability; this relation could
only lead to Planck’s law if the resonators were quantized, against Boltz-
mann’s original intentions and against the consequences of classical stat-
istical mechanics (which included the equipartition theorem).10
By using this kind of argument, Klein imitated early interpreters of
Planck’s paper such as Hendrik Lorentz, James Jeans, and Albert Einstein.
In his review of Kuhn’s book, he insisted that these early readings of
Planck revealed the essence of Planck’s theory: ‘‘The quanta were there in
[Planck’s] theory, and some of his readers did draw attention to them: Lor-
entz in 1903, Ehrenfest and James Jeans in 1905.... Lorentz wrote in 1903
about Planck’s use of ‘a certain number of finite portions’ of energy. I see
this as Lorentz’s recognition of what Planck had done in his papers of
1900 and 1901’’ (Klein, 1979, p. 431). In his paper of 1962, Klein already
used Jeans’ and Ehrenfest’s readings of Planck to characterize Planck’s de-
parture from Boltzmann’s methods. In particular, he agreed with Ehrenfest
that ‘‘Planck’s energy elements amounted to a radical change in the a
priori weight function introduced into phase space’’ (Klein, 1962, p. 475):
whereas Boltzmann assumed a uniform weight, Planck allowed only dis-
crete energy values.
Klein was also sensitive to the programmatic aspects of Planck’s radiation
theory. He rightly emphasized that the meaning of entropy was the leading
thread of Planck’s program, and gave as much importance to the evolution of
Planck’s concept of entropy as to the steps necessary to his derivations of the
black-body law (Klein, 1963). However, Klein did not pursue his exploration
228 O. Darrigol
3. Methods
Table 3: Interests/arguments
First suppose that we are trying to decide what the discoverer, Planck,
thought he was doing in 1900. In this case, we need to handle traditional
accounts with systematic suspicion, for it is well-known that the simple narra-
tives generated and stabilized by a given community of scientists may have
little relation with the actual performance of the discoverer. We must also be
weary of trusting the appearances of the formal apparatus of past demon-
strations, for we may unconsciously interpret this apparatus in terms of later
knowledge that may be incompatible with the discoverer’s views. Similarly,
we should be alert to possible contradictions between these views and those
projected by contemporary actors on the discoverer’s work. We must of
course retrace the discoverer’s path, because it usually contains important
implicit aspects of his final reasoning. Formal, technical details of this path
may thereby help, for they have every chance of being intimately connected
with more qualitative elements. They are basic data to anyone interested in
the process of theory construction.
A historian may, however, be less interested in the idiosyncrasies of
Planck’s approach than in the way his work was used by other proto-quan-
tum-theorists. Then he would give significantly different answers to our meth-
odological questions. If used with sufficient care, traditional accounts may
be more helpful to him, because they often reveal features of the early recep-
tion of the discoverer’s work: the canonical story of a discovery (if there is
any) is usually formed little after its impact has been recognized, on the basis
of the most common perception of the discovery, which may differ from the
discoverer’s own perception. The early users of the discoverer’s work are in
fact often reinterpreting this work: they extract some elements of this work
and combine them with other elements and views that may be incompatible
with those of the discoverer. The purely formal aspects of the discoverer’s
work may then be essential, for they may be all that the users retain. So can
230 O. Darrigol
4. Quantum continuity
The previous discussion raises doubts on the soundness of the method fol-
lowed by discontinuist historians. It is not sufficient, however, to disprove
their claim regarding Planck’s introduction of quantum discontinuity. For this
purpose, a more detailed consideration of the arguments of indeterminist
and continuist historians is necessary.
Kuhn’s continuist thesis is essentially based on three arguments (Kuhn,
1978, pp. 125–127). Firstly, Planck needed the classical theory of radiation
in order to derive the relation unΩ(8pn2/c3)U between the spectral density un
of thermal radiation and the average energy U of a resonator at the frequency
n. Therefore, he could not assume a quantization of the resonator without
contradicting himself. Secondly, in his combinatorial derivation of the black-
body law, Planck proceeded by analogy with Boltzmann’s combinatorics of
1877. Therefore, his recourse to a distribution of energy-elements is likely to
have been only a shortcut to Boltzmann’s fuller consideration of equiprob-
able energy-intervals (or cells in velocity space): for the counting of com-
plexions, it does not matter whether a complexion is defined by giving to
232 O. Darrigol
5. Conclusion
in his review of Kuhn’s book Klein wrote: ‘‘In my opinion Kuhn tries too
hard to establish the internal consistency of Planck’s position. He seems to
be unwilling to consider the possibility that Planck himself was not always
completely clear about what he was doing’’ (Klein, 1979, p. 431). The objec-
tion seems even more pertinent for accounts such as Needell’s and mine
which convey to Planck’s thoughts more coherence than Kuhn himself per-
ceived. The problem is whether the coherence is artificially introduced by the
historian or is a genuine characteristic of the described thoughts.
Klein’s doubts are understandable in the case of Kuhn’s book, for Kuhn
makes assumptions of internal consistency (his first point) and temporal conti-
nuity (his third point) for which he gives no textual evidence. Moreover, Kuhn
appears to have arbitrarily made Planck consistent on some issues and incon-
sistent on others. Do these charges also apply to the accounts given by Needell
and myself? I do not think so, for these accounts follow very closely Planck’s
expressed justifications. For example, Needell’s crucial point that Planck
understood the combinatorial probability as a measure of elementary disorder
is completely explicit in the quantum papers of 1900–01. Planck [1900b, p. 698]
starts his reasoning with the words ‘‘Entropie bedingt Unordnung,’’ and goes
on to characterize the kind of disorder affecting his resonators. It is in fact eas-
ier to locate statements of Planck’s corroborating Needell’s account than to
understand why previous historians overlooked them.
In short, I believe the coherence which Needell saw in Planck’s approach
to the radiation problem to be real. Coherence, however, should be confused
neither with consistency nor with completeness. Let us define consistency as
the lack of logical contradiction in an entirely explicit, closed, conceptual
system. Consistency in this sense is never achieved during the construction
of a theory. It can only be reached in a later stage of consolidation and
axiomatization. In contrast, coherence refers to a harmonious weaving of
arguments without easily perceptible contradictions. Planck’s theory was co-
herent in this soft sense; but it could not be made consistent in the hard
sense. For example, if Planck had provided a physical mechanism for the
thermalization of his resonators (such as encounters with gas molecules), he
would have been forced to the absurd Rayleigh-Jeans law. His theory was
incomplete in a way that hid potential contradictions.
Incompleteness was an essential characteristic of Planck’s theory, as empha-
sized by Needell and myself. Accordingly, Planck had no definite opinion of the
exact meaning of his new quanta. He strove to remain as close as possible to
238 O. Darrigol
received dynamical conceptions, but he did not know what the exact dynamics
of the resonators would be. He did not introduce quantum discontinuity, he did
not intend a sharp break from received theories, but he believed that his quan-
tum of action signaled yet unknown aspects of small-scale physics.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Darrigol, O.
1988: ‘‘Statistics and combinatorics in early quantum theory,’’ Historical studies in the
physical sciences, 19, pp. 17–80.
1992: From c-numbers to q-numbers: The classical analogy in the history of quantum theory
(Berkeley, 1992).
Galison, P.
1981: ‘‘Kuhn and the quantum controversy,’’ British journal for the philosophy of science,
32, pp. 71–85.
Hermann, A.
1969: Frühgeschichte der Quantentheorie (1899–1913), Mosbach.
Hund, F.
1967: Geschichte der Quantentheorie, Mannheim.
Jammer, M.
1966: The conceptual development of quantum mechanics, New York.
Jost, R.
1995: ‘‘Planck-Kritik des T. Kuhn,’’ in Das Märchen vom Elfenbeinernen Turm. Reden
und Aufsätze, Berlin, pp. 67–78.
Kangro, H.
1970: Vorgeschichte des Planckschen Strahlungsgesetzes, Wiesbaden.
Klein, M. J.
1962: ‘‘Max Planck and the beginnings of the quantum theory,’’ Archive for the history
of exact sciences, 1, pp. 459–479.
1963: ‘‘Planck, entropy, and quanta, 1901–1906,’’ The natural philosopher, 1, pp. 83–108.
1966: ‘‘Thermodynamics and quanta in Planck’s work,’’ Physics today, 19:11, pp. 23–32.
1970: Paul Ehrenfest, vol. 1: The making of a theoretical physicist, Amsterdam.
1979: Contribution to ‘‘Paradigm lost? A review symposium,’’ Isis, 70, pp. 429–433.
Kries, J. v.
1886: Die Principien der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung, Freiburg.
Kuhn, T. S.
1977: The essential tension, Chicago.
1978: Black-body theory and the quantum discontinuity. 1894–1912, Oxford.
Needell, A.
1980: Irreversibility and the failure of classical dynamics: Max Planck’s work on the quan-
tum theory: 1900–1915, Diss., University of Michigan, Ann Arbor.
1988: Needell, Introduction to Planck, The theory of radiation, Los Angeles: Tomash.
Planck, M.
1900a: ‘‘Über eine Verbesserung der Wien’schen Spektralgleichung,’’ Deutsche Physikalis-
che Gesellschaft, Verhandlungen, 2, pp. 202–204.
Planck’s Quantum 239
NOTES
1. I thank John Stachel and Alfred Tauber for their hospitality at the Boston Colloquium,
Edward Jurkowitz and Jürgen Renn for helpful comments.
2. On this point see, e.g., (Klein, 1962, p. 471) and (Kuhn, 1978, pp. 110–113).
3. See J. Büttner, J. Renn, and M. Schemmel’s comments on the Einstein-Planck connec-
tion in their contribution to this conference.
4. Cf. (Rosenfeld, 1936), (Klein, 1962, 1963), (Kuhn, 1978), (Needell, 1980), (Darrigol,
1992, part I), and (Kangro, 1970) on the experimental side.
5. Planck could only obtain the spatial homogenization of radiation. The resonators could
not change the spectrum of the radiation, as Ehrenfest and Einstein later noted.
6. Cf. Dieter Hoffmann’s contribution to this issue.
7. Armin Hermann adopted a similar attitude in (Hermann, 1969, pp. 34–35).
8. J. Mehra and H. Rechenberg (see the first volume of their history of quantum theory),
could also be regarded as indeterminist, for they simply paraphrase Planck’s paper and
do not offer any interpretation of their own.
9. The sentence is not in Planck’s subsequent Annalen paper (Planck, 1901).
10. Cf. [Klein, 1962, p. 474]: ‘‘It is obviously of the very essence of Planck’s work that e
should not vanish, if the proper distribution law were to be reached. Planck apparently
did not even consider the possibility of taking this limit. This is undoubtedly related to
Planck’s apparent unawareness of the equipartition theorem and all it implied.’’
11. See the contribution to this conference by J. Büttner, J. Renn, and M. Schemmel.
12. For Planck’s identification of Spielräume and Elementargebiete, see (Planck, 1920, p.
127); Kuhn (1978, pp. 121, 286) notes Planck’s reference to Kries, but overlooks its
meaning. I thank Michael Heidelberger for discussing the matter with me and for lend-
ing me a copy of Kries’ book.
13. Cf. (Kuhn, 1977, p. xii): ‘‘I offer [students] a maxim: When reading the works of an
important thinker, look first for the apparent absurdities in the text and ask yourself
how a sensible person could have written them. When you find an answer, I continue,
when those passages make sense, then you may find that more central passages, ones
you previously thought you understood, have changed their meaning.