KantEthicsSlides2020 PDF
KantEthicsSlides2020 PDF
KantEthicsSlides2020 PDF
CHALLENGE:
Kant’s Answer: “For a will that brought that about would conflict with itself, since instances
can often arise in which the person in question would need the love and sympathy of others,
and he would have no hope of getting the help he desires, being robbed of it by this law of
nature springing from his own will.”
The world in which the maxim was universalized would be similar to Hobbes’s state of
nature, in which self-interested agents compete against eachother for scarce resources in a
hostile natural environment.
According to Hobbes, life in the state of nature would be “solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and
short.”
Kant and Respect for Humanity
The Little Provided your intended end was to make her feel
White Lie? better, and assuming that your lie succeeds in
achieving this end, was your lie morally
acceptable?
CHALLENGE: Your friend is struggling from
The Formula depression after being rejected at a casting audition
for a musical. To help make her feel better, you tell
of Humanity: her that she has an “amazing singing voice”: to your
ear, she has a terrible voice. Your fib cheers her up.
The Little Provided your intended end was to make her feel
White Lie? better, and assuming that your lie succeeds in
achieving this end, was your lie morally
acceptable?
APPLYING KANTIAN ETHICS
CLASS DEBATE
CHALLENGE
The Second 1. Without knowing what happened
Formulation: next, did you see anything morally
wrong in the video clip? Does your
answer depend upon what happens
The Formula next?
of Humanity
2. Assume that the woman swings
safely as planned: Does this change
your response?
“A person, an end in itself, is a free cause, which is to say a
first cause. By contrast, a thing, a means, is merely a mediate
CHALLENGE: cause, a link in the chain…Any action that prevents or diverts
you from making this initiating decision is one that treats you
as a mediate rather than a first cause, hence as a mere
Christine means, a thing, a tool."
Korsgaard, a
contemporary "Coercion and deception all do this. And deception treats you
as a mediate cause in a specific way: it treats your reason as
Kant scholar and a mediate cause. The false promiser thinks: if I tell her I will
ethicist at Harvard pay her back next week, then she will choose to give me the
University: money. Your reason is worked, like a machine: the deceiver
tries to determine what levers to pull to get the desired results
from you. Physical coercion treats someone’s person as a tool;
lying treats someone’s reason as a tool. This is why Kant finds
it so horrifying; it is a direct violation of autonomy.”
Vienna, Austria 1943. There is a Nazi officer at the door asking
if you are harboring Jewish fugitives. There is a Jewish family
living in your attic. What are you morally obligated to do?
"While Comey has emphasized that it is still unclear whether any of the new
information will be of any significance, FBI officials have confirmed that the
investigation will not be completed before election day on November 8th, thereby
leaving voters in the dark about the potential ramifications of the investigation.
Trump has exploited the uncertainty caused by the revelation, telling the public
that the announcement is an indication that an indictment is imminent. Recent
polling analysis from Nate Silver at FiveThirtyEight indicates that Trump’s statistical
chances of winning have almost doubled since Comey’s announcement. Once
praised for refusing to let politics sway his integrity as an investigator—(as a lifelong
Republican he prosecuted many members of his own party)—Comey is now being
accused by many of his former supporters of gross negligence and reckless
endangerment of the democratic process.”
Polling from 538 suggested that people were confused by
the FBI's announcement, and that this confusion made
an impact on voting decisions.
CHALLENGE:
2. Turn the tables: How could one argue that Comey would have
been justified in withholding the information while still
satisfying the Formula of Universal Law?
Formula of Humanity: “Act in such a way that you treat humanity, whether in your
own person or in any other person, never merely as a means, but always at the same
time as an end in itself.”
CHALLENGE
2. Turn the tables: How could one argue that Comey would have
been justified in withholding the information from the public while
still upholding the Formula of Humanity?
THE RIGHT TO LIFE AND THE
RIGHT TO SELF-DEFENSE
KANTIAN ETHICS
AND
GUN RIGHTS
The Right to Life
In the wake of a series of grisly mass shootings, America has
and The Right become more divided than ever on the subject of gun control.
to Bear Arms: Some argue that we ought to prohibit civilian gun ownership
entirely , claiming that the evidence overwhelming demonstrates
that countries that have prohibited guns have dramatically
ESTABLISHING lower rates of gun-related fatalities. Such advocates argue that
the recreational benefits of gun ownership, as well as any
CONTEXT marginal effectiveness of gun ownership in deterring crimes, are
far outweighed by the harms of a gun owning society.
POLL:
SCENARIO1
A killer breaks into a house, where two people—“the victim” and “the accomplice”—
are staying. (The “accomplice” need have no prior interaction with the killer.) As the
The Right to Life killer enters the bedroom where the victim is hiding, the unwitting accomplice enters
through another door and proceeds, for no reason at all, to hold the victim down. The
and The Right killer then stabs the victim to death.
Same as in example 1, except that the victim has a gun by the bed, which he would,
if able, use to defend himself from the killer. As the killer enters the bedroom, the
victim reaches for the gun. The accomplice grabs the gun and runs away, with the
result that the killer then stabs his victim to death.
THINK: (i) In your view, is there a morally relevant similarity between example 1
and example 2? If the action depicted in 1 is wrong, do you think the action in 2
is wrong for similar reasons?
The Right to Life Scenario 3: Citizen wants to own a gun for self-defense. State
and The Right forcibly prevents Citizen from having a gun (or confiscates
Citizen's gun). Citizen is then victimized by a criminal.
to Bear Arms
What is the moral status of the State's gun prohibition?
The Right to Life
and The Right to
Bear Arms:
The debate over gun prohibition turns upon a more
fundamental philosophical question: Is it morally
RAISE A
acceptable to curtail an individual’s freedom in
DISRUPTING order to prevent bad things from happening?
"SO WHAT?"
QUESTION
Michael Huemer (2003) argues that the harms of gun ownership
would have to be far greater than the evidence suggests in
order to override our right to own a gun. Central to Huemer’s
The Right to Life account is a distinction between derivative rights and
fundamental rights. A derivative right is a right that derives its
and The Right force from other rights; A fundamental right is a right whose
to Bear Arms force is independent of other rights. Huemer argues that we
have a derivative right to own a gun insofar as we have a
fundamental right to life (and thus to self-defense). Appealing to
the examples we just discussed, Huemer claims that preventing
one's ability to defend themselves “is about as serious a wrong
as killing.”
To the extent that gun prohibition would impede the ability
The Right to Life of individuals to protect themselves, Huemer concludes that
and The Right “The analogy between the accomplice’s action in this case and a
to Bear Arms general firearms prohibition should be clear...If the accomplice’s
action in example 2 is a major violation of the right of self-
defense, then gun prohibition seems to be about equally serious
as a violation of the right of self-defense.”
Huemer’s argument, in outline form, is as follows:
1. It is wrong to murder a person, even to prevent several other killings. (premise)
2. A violation of a person or group’s right of self-defense, predictably resulting in the death of one of the victims, is
morally comparable to murder. (premise)
3. If it is wrong to commit a murder to prevent several killings, then it is wrong to commit a rights-violation comparable to
murder to prevent several killings.
4. Therefore, it is wrong to violate a person or group’s right of self-defense, predictably resulting in the death of one of
the victims, even to prevent several killings. (from 1, 2, 3)
5. Therefore, it is wrong to violate a group of people’s right of self-defense, predictably resulting in the deaths of many
of the victims, even to prevent several times as many killings. (from 4)
6. Gun prohibition would violate a group of people’s right of self-defense, predictably resulting in the deaths of many of
the victims.
CONCLUSION: Therefore, gun prohibition is wrong, even if it would prevent several times as many killings as it contributed
to. (5, 6)
The Categorical Imperative determines how all
rational beings would necessarily act in all cases.
The Formula
of Universal The Formula of Universal Law (FUL):
“Act only on that maxim by which you can at
Law the same time will that it should become a
universal law.”
• Consider a time in your life where you believe you showed respect
for another person.
"Suppose, then, that the mind of this philanthropist were overclouded by his own grief, which
extinguished all sympathy with the fate of the others, and that while he still had the means to
benefit others in distress their troubles did not move him because he had enough to do with his
own; and suppose that now, when no longer incited to it by any inclination, he nevertheless tears
himself out of this deadly insensibility and does the action without any inclination, simply from
duty."
KANT'S RATIONALIST MORAL PSYCHOLOGY
Kant then asks if we should not consider that the begrudging philanthropist action would have
a greater moral worth if nature had designed him to feel pleasure at the idea of helping
others.
For Kant, it is the very reluctance of his act that allows us to see that it was done from duty and
not from some self-serving inclination:
“By all means! It is just then that the worth of character comes out, which is moral and
incomparably the highest, namely, that he is beneficent not from inclination but from duty.” (G:
AA 4: 399).
KANT'S RATIONALIST MORAL PSYCHOLOGY
“If the determination of the will occurs in accordance with the moral law but only
by means of a feeling of any kind whatsoever, which must be presupposed in
order that the law may become a determining ground of the will, and if the
action thus occurs not for the sake of the law, it has legality but not morality”
(Pr. R 5:72)
Intellectualist Model
Andrews Reath: “If the moral law determines choice by exerting a force that is
stronger than the alternatives, moral conduct will result from the balance of
whatever psychological forces are acting on the will […] Morality would then
become an empirically explainable natural phenomenon; and one would lose the
notion that pure reason is practical, since one could account for moral conduct
entirely in terms of natural desires.”
THE INTELLECTUALIST MODEL
Challenge for Intellectualist: Why is feeling necessary for Kant?
KEY PASSAGE: "[A]ll inclination rests on feeling, so that what infringes upon all the
inclinations...has, just by this, a necessary influence on feeling.”
OVERCOMING THE PATHOLOGICAL SELF:
HUMILIATION
Kant calls the negative effect on feeling associated with the frustration of our pathological
desires 'Humiliation':
KEY PASSAGE: "Now, what in our own judgment infringes upon self-conceit humiliates. Hence
the moral law unavoidably humiliates every human being when he compares with it the
sensible propensity of his nature."
"Hence, as submission to a law, i.e., as a command (proclaiming constraint for the sensibly
affected subject), this feeling contains within itself no pleasure, but rather—to this extent—
displeasure, in the action."
OVERCOMING THE PATHOLOGICAL SELF:
HUMILIATION
Kant calls the negative effect on feeling associated with the frustration of our pathological
desires 'Humiliation':
KEY PASSAGE: "Now, what in our own judgment infringes upon self-conceit humiliates. Hence
the moral law unavoidably humiliates every human being when he compares with it the
sensible propensity of his nature."
"Hence, as submission to a law, i.e., as a command (proclaiming constraint for the sensibly
affected subject), this feeling contains within itself no pleasure, but rather—to this extent—
displeasure, in the action."
THE NECESSITY OF FEELING: THE "EPIPHENOMENALIST"
SOLUTION
Call this the epiphenomenalist account of the status of feeling in moral motivation. On this view,
moral feeling is to be seen as motivationally inefficacious side-effect of an self-contained and
purely intellectual motivational process—that is to say, the feeling of respect is understood to
be epiphenomenal to the recognition and execution of dutiful action.
The necessity of feeling on this account is external to moral motivation itself: it is necessary only
as a by-product.
Strictly speaking, then, insofar as the purely intellectual apprehension of the law is sufficient
to generate moral action, Reath concludes that “moral motivation does not require, or
occur, through any feeling” (Reath 2006: 12).
THE NECESSITY OF FEELING: THE "EPIPHENOMENALIST"
SOLUTION
THE NECESSITY OF FEELING: THE 'EPIPHENOMENALIST' SOLUTION
THINK: Setting aside matters of interpretive accuracy, do you think the epiphonomenalist
model provides a plausible account of moral action?
SHORTCOMINGS OF THE INTELLECTUALIST READING:
THE POSITIVE SIDE OF THE FEELING OF RESPECT
Kant also describes a positive side to the feeling of respect that appears to do heavy
lifting in the generation of moral deeds:
"[T]he subjective effect on feeling, inasmuch as pure practical reason is the sole cause of it, can
thus be called self-approval with reference to pure practical reason" (CrPr 5:81).
Affectivist Model
Richard McCarty: “The strongest reason intellectualists deny the causal role of
moral feelings in Kantian moral motivation lies in their conviction that such
"deterministic" affective mechanisms are incompatible with the presumed
freedom of rational agency."
[...] However, Kant considers freedom itself a kind of causality, and so would find
no absurdity in identifying the determining cause of a free action. And if the
"intellectual causality" of freedom employs affective mechanisms in generating
action, then motivating moral feelings are entirely compatible with [rational]
freedom"
DESIRE, PLEASURE, AND FREEDOM:
KANT'S ACCOUNT OF AGENCY
According to Kant, our capacity to perform any action is grounded in our capacity to actualize
our ideas – Kant calls this capacity the faculty of desire:
“The faculty of desire is the faculty to be by means of one’s representations the cause of the
objects of these representations” (MM 6:211).
DESIRE, PLEASURE, AND FREEDOM:
KANT'S ACCOUNT OF AGENCY
In other words, the faculty of desire refers to the mind’s ability to actualize the objects
of certain representations—specifically, Kant tells us, the objects
of pleasurable representations. As Kant tells us in a lecture on metaphysics:
"The faculty of desire rests on the principle: I desire nothing but what pleases, and avoid
nothing but what displeases...But representations cannot be the cause of an object where we
have no pleasure or displeasure in it. This is therefore the subjective condition by which alone a
representation can become the cause of an object (LM 29:894).
DESIRE, PLEASURE, AND FREEDOM:
KANT'S ACCOUNT OF AGENCY
Kant appears to be claiming that desires and feelings of pleasure are present in all actions,
including non-moral acts and moral deeds alike.
“If the determination of the will occurs in accordance with the moral law but only by means
of a feeling of any kind whatsoever, which must be presupposed in order that the law
may become a determining ground of the will, and if the action thus occurs not for the sake of
the law, it has legality but not morality”
(Pr. R 5:72)
DESIRE, PLEASURE, AND FREEDOM:
KANT'S ACCOUNT OF AGENCY
1. The will proper [Wille], understood as the purely intellectual faculty of recognizing practical
laws
2. The executive faculty of choice [Willkür] in accordance with such laws, through which the
sensibly-affected subject implements the deliverances of the will into action.
The 'Election' Model:
Another Intellectualist Strategy
Some Intellectualists accept that the Kantian moral agent can only choose to actualize a
pleasurable idea, but reject the balance of forces model insofar as it is thought to
undermine rational autonomy.
Election Model: I can only choose to actualize a pleasurable idea of action. The idea of doing
some non-moral act X happens to cause me pleasure. The idea of doing something out of duty,
however, also causes me pleasure. Reflecting on my candidate options for pleasure according
to rational principles, I freely elect to pursue the pleasurable choice associated with the idea
of acting for the sake of duty, which in turn causes me to move to actualize this duty. Since the
choice was ultimately determined by reason, the fact that pleasure was necessary does not
compromise moral agency.
ACTION, DESIRE, AND PLEASURE:
KANT'S ACCOUNT OF ACTION
Kant tells us that when the faculty of desireis mediated by way of a subject’s faculty of
reason—that is, insofar as the subject represents by means of concepts—then the faculty of
desire is called “choice” [Willkür]. As “the faculty of doing as one pleases,” Kant claims that
choice is “the capacity for desiring according to concepts, insofar as the ground determining it
lies in itself and not in its object” (MM 6:213). As a species of desiring in general, then, choice
is always grounded in and initiated by a pleasurable representation:
" [T]he determining ground of choice consists in the conception of an object in relation to the
subject, whereby the faculty of desire is determined to realize the object. Such a relation to the
subject is called pleasure in the reality of an object (CrPr 5:21).
KANT'S ACCOUNT OF AGENCY
McCarty agrees with Reath that in order for actions to be chosen for the sake of duty, the
moral law must command the rational assent of the Wille immediately and without the
contribution of any sensible influence. But according to McCarty, this is only the beginning of
the motivational process for Kant. For in addition to one's legislative recognition of the moral
law as the all-sufficient reason for action, the actual execution of a corresponding moral deed
always depends upon a subsequent Choice. It is here in the operation of choice, McCarty
claims, that affective mechanisms are necessary in order to execute the dictates of the Wille.
For the Sake of Duty
For Kant, we always enter the moral scene as beings with selfish desires that conflict with
duty:
"[W]e find our nature as sensible beings so constituted that the matter of the faculty of desire
(objects of inclination, whether of hope or fear) first forces itself upon us, and we find our
pathologically determinable self, even though it is quite unfit to give universal law through its
maxims, nevertheless striving antecedently to make its claims primary and originally valid, just
as if it constituted our entire self" (CrPr 5:74).
The Corruption of the Will:
"Sensible Inclination"
A Good Will for Kant is one that acts according to maxims that are determined purely by one’s
intellectual recognition of the moral law – that is, by our faculty of Reason.
By contrast, a motive of the will that is determined by empirical contingencies, such as contingent
desires, impulses, instincts - or what Kant refers to collectively as Sensible Inclination - would not
have genuine moral worth. For this would make the will determined by a force that is alien to
one’s recognition of duty.
KANT'S RATIONALIST MORAL PSYCHOLOGY
Rational Self-Determination Thesis - The condition of the possibility of morality is one's capacity
to determine one's actions according to self-legislated rational laws and “independent of any
determination of alien causes.” Indeed, for Kant: “Autonomy of the will is the sole principle
of all moral laws and of duties in keeping with them.”
THE "HYPER-RATIONALIST" CARICATURE OF KANT
Andrews Reath: Because all human beings have pathological desires that must be thwarted
when we act out of duty, then “the determination of the will by moral law will always be
accompanied by an affect” (Reath 2006: 12).
E.G. Lightning will always be accompanied by thunder, but this does not mean that lightning is
caused by thunder
In the same way, Reath argues that “while an affect is produced when the moral law
determines the will, it is not this affect that motivates” (Reath 2006: 12).
'MORAL FEELING' AS CAUSALLY EFFICACIOUS
KEY PASSAGE: “Every determination of choice proceeds from the representation of the
possible action, through the feeling of pleasure or displeasure in taking an interest in the action
or in its effect, to the deed; And here the sensitive condition [...] is either a pathological or a
moral feeling. [A pathological feeling] is that feeling which precedes the representation of the
law; [A moral feeling] is that which can only follow the representation of the law.”
The moral integrity of the motivational process only turns upon how the mechanistic forces enter
into the motivational process. Provided that the choice-determining feelings are somehow
dependent upon one's prior recognition of the moral law, the resulting action can be seen as
the product of a rational cause, and thus as a legitimate moral deed.
Affectivist Model
By virtue of the affective mechanisms standing in a suitable causal relationship with the
representation of the moral law, the autonomy of reason as an intellectual causality can be
made consistent with the necessity of affective forces.
As such, McCarty concludes contra Reath that “there is no reason to assume, as many
intellectualists have, that introducing an affective mechanism into Kantian moral motivation
threatens the freedom of moral agency.”
Since the causal sequence begins with the purely rational recognition of
duty“affectivists need not deny that Kantian moral motivation initially arises from
an intellectual recognition of the moral law.”
APPLYING THE AFFECTIVIST MODEL: How might an affectivist explain the difference in
moral status between Anton's action and the other two cases?
Beast of the Field A silverback gorilla forms a mental representation of killing the offspring
of his competitors. Insofar as actualizing this "idea" poses strategic benefits, the gorilla has
been conditioned by adaptive mechanisms to feel pleasure at this idea. This feeling of
pleasure moves the gorilla to kill his competitor's offspring.
Anton's Respect for Humanity The thought of buying the shoes fills Anton with pleasure. on
inquiring about the shoes, Anton discovers that they are a brand name manufactured by a
corporation known for operating exploitative child sweatshops. The idea of not buying the
shoes in order to respect the dignity of exploited people’s causes him to feel pleasure. This
feeling moves him to not buy the shoes.
The Life of Joy Joy forms an idea of helping a lost child stranded on the side of the
freeway. This idea causes Joy to feel pleasure. This feeling moves Joy to help the child.
The 'Balance of Forces' Model
Balance of Forces: The idea of doing some non-moral act X happens to cause me pleasure.
This pleasure exerts a certain amount of force on my faculty of choice. The idea of doing
something out of duty, however, causes me to feel pleasure that happens to exert a greater
amount of force. The overriding strength of this pleasure in turn determines my choice, and
causes me to move to actualize this duty.
THINK: Why might one argue that the balance of forces model fails to preserve human
freedom and the autonomy of reason?
THINK: Why might one argue that the balance of forces model makes it impossible to hold
someone morally blameworthy for actions that violate the moral law?
Rational Freedom as the Locus of Moral
Responsibility
Kant: "Freedom is independence from inclinations...as determining our faculty of choice"
We tend to think that people are only morally responsible for their actions if their actions were
self-determined through their own rational agency.
First Lemma: We are only morally responsible insofar we are free rational agents
Second Lemma: To exercise rational freedom just is to be determined by the moral law
Implication: No morally responsible agent can commit an evil action; Evil is never imputable to
a morally responsible agent
Kant and the Problem of Evil
First Lemma: Moral Responsibility Requires Rational Freedom
If Anton chooses to buy the shoes, knowing their origins, on account of the fact
that they fill him with pleasure, then his action would be determined by sensible
inclination, and not by pure practical reason.
KEY PASSAGE: "[I]f one had insight into the possibility of freedom...one would also have insight
into not merely the possibility but even the necessity of the moral law as the supreme practical
law of rational beings...for, the two concepts are so inseparably connected that one could even
define practical freedom as independence of the will from anything other than the moral law
alone."
Kant and the Problem of Evil
Second Lemma: Rational Freedom Just Is Moral Action
KEY PASSAGES: "F]reedom can never be located in the fact that the rational subject is able to
make a choice in opposition to his (legislative) reason"
"Only freedom in relation to the internal legislation of reason is properly a capacity; the
possibility of deviating from it is an incapacity"
"Freedom is the capacity to actively will that which is known to be good and is in our power;
but to [freedom] does not necessarily belong the capacity to will that which is known to be evil
and whose avoidance is in our power. This [latter] is not actually a capacity, but rather the
possibility of a passivity." (3868)
Kant and the Problem of Evil
THE PROBLEM: Free transgression of the moral law is impossible; Transgression of the
moral law can only be a result of the lack of freedom
C.f. Karl Leonard Reinhold: "If the moral law announces to us no other freedom than that
which consists in the self-activity of reason, then the capacity [for a morally responsible agent]
to act immorally is not only an incapacity, but is simply impossible."
"[The categorical imperative]....can therefore never be transgressed. Its not having been
followed cannot be a transgression. It is, rather, a necessary result of the circumstance that
human choice, in certain cases, has no negative freedom, no independence of sensible
incentives—is no human choice—and that positive freedom in these cases is not effective,
practical reason is not [free]."
Kant and the Problem of Evil
THE PROBLEM:
First Lemma: We are only morally responsible insofar we are free rational agents
Second Lemma: We are only free rational agents insofar as we follow the moral law;
Rationally free agents always act according to the moral law.
Implication: No morally responsible agent can commit an evil action; We are never
responsible for moral wrongdoing
The Negative Account:
Evil as the Lack of Rationality
ONE PROPOSED SOLUTION: THE 'NEGATIVE' ACCOUNT OF EVIL
1. Accept that 'imputable' evil is impossible; Evil is never the result of rational freedom
Michelle Kosch sums up this account as follows: "If practical reason is the source of moral
goodness, for Kant, then it seems moral evil can be dealt with quickly: it is a failure to achieve
maximal practical rationality due to some cognitive or voluntative limitations of finite agents,
never a genuinely free choice. "
Kant and the Problem of Evil
THE 'NEGATIVE' ACCOUNT OF EVIL
On 'negative' readings of the place of evil within the Kantian framework, evil is never a
result of a free choice; It is a failure of practical reasoning that can be traced to some
cognitive limitation or defect in one's capacities to act according to reason.
Likewise, on the Kantian picture, evil would result from the failure to deploy one's
rational faculties; Evil is a result of practical irrationality.
CONTRA KANT: How might this suggest that rationality is not the primary locus for morality?
PRO KANT: How might it only underscore that reason can become corrupted by non-rational
influences?
Eichmann's Fall from Kant: The Cog Theory
ARENDT: "He then proceeded to explain that from the moment he was charged with carrying
out the Final Solution he had ceased to live according to Kantian principles, that he had known
it, and that he had consoled himself with the thought that he no longer "was master of his own
deeds," that he was unable "to change anything."
Negative Solution 1:
Evil as Lack of Practical Rationality
The Cog Theory Eichmann's evil was the result of an absence of practical reason, as his actions
are determined by external forces – like a cog in a machine. This is in line with Eichmann's own
description of his actions as originating in an "obedience of corpses"
THINK: Why might one think this model provides an inaccurate account of Eichmann's actions?
Eichmann's Distorted Kant: The Führer as Moral
Law
ARENDT: "What he failed to point out in court was that in this "period of crimes legalized
by the state," as he himself now called it, he had not simply dismissed the Kantian formula as no
longer applicable, he had distorted it to read: Act as if the principle of your actions were the
same as that of the legislator or of the law of the land.'
"Or, in Hans Frank's formulation of "the categorical imperative in the Third Reich," which
Eichmann might have known: "Act in such a way that the Führer, if he knew your action, would
approve it."
CHALLENGE FOR THE COG THEORY: The ability to construct a rival moral law suggests the
presence of rational capacities. So, in what sense can Eichmann's evil be said to result from the
absence of practical reason?
Negative Solution 2:
Inclination as Corrupting Temptation
PROPOSED SOLUTION: Eichmann has 'online' rational faculties, recognizes the moral law, but
is subsequently 'corrupted' by the 'temptation' of countervailing pathological feelings and
inclinations – e.g. the desire to feel validated by his community, the desire for self-
preservation, etc.
Thus, Eichmann's distorted 'moral law' was the result of something other than the exercise of
rationality – namely, feeling and inclination.
DEBATE: Do you think this model provides an accurate account of Eichmann's actions? Or does
it only scapegoat feelings? Do you think reason plays a greater role in evil than this account
suggests?
LAWFUL EVIL? THE POSITIVE USE OF REASON IN EVIL ACTION:
ARENDT: "Just as the law in civilized countries assumes that the voice of
conscience tells everybody "Thou shalt not kill," even though man's natural
desires and inclinations may at times be murderous, so the law of Hitler's land
demanded that the voice of conscience tell everybody: "Thou shalt kill," although
the organizers of the massacres knew full well that murder is against the normal
desires and inclinations of most people."
RATIONALIZATION AND EVIL:
THE POSITIVE USE OF REASON IN EVIL ACTION:
ARENDT: "Evil in the Third Reich had lost the quality by which most people recognize it -
the quality of temptation."
"Many Germans and many Nazis, probably an overwhelming majority of them, must
have been tempted not to murder, not to rob, not to let their neighbors go off to their
doom...and not to become accomplices in all these crimes by benefiting from them. But, God
knows, they had learned how to resist temptation."
The Trial of Adolf Eichmann:
Rationality and the Problem of Evil
LAWFUL EVIL? THE POSITIVE USE OF REASON IN EVIL ACTION:
These passages suggest that:
(I) Evil is not a mere absence of moral conscience, but a positive 'inversion' of moral conscience,
whereby moral transgression itself becomes law and the feeling of respect
becomes the corrupting temptation
(II) As opposed to Evil being a matter of passive determination by forces external to one's
rationality, such that reason is simply bypassed in the generation of evil, reason itself makes
an active contribution in carrying out this moral inversion.
Kant and 'Positive' Evil
Kant himself appeared to hold a 'positive' conception of evil, according to which evil is
not a 'negative' absence of rational agency, but the result of some 'positive' exercise of
our agency that is distinct from dutiful action:
"Nothing is … morally (i.e. imputably) evil but that which is our own deed."
"‘Evil can have originated only from moral evil (not just from the limitations of our nature)’"
"[T]he lack of the agreement of the power of choice (Willkür) with [the moral law] is possible
only as a consequence of a real and opposite determination of the power (p.45) of choice, i.e.
of a resistance on its part … or again, it is only possible through an evil power of choice (eine
böse Willkür)"
RECONSTRUCTIVE PAPER TOPIC
Kant and the Problem of Evil:
An Inconsistent Triad?
CONTRA KANT: How might this suggest that rationality is not the primary locus for morality?
PRO KANT: How might it only underscore that reason can become corrupted by non-rational
influences?