Springer Studia Logica: An International Journal For Symbolic Logic
Springer Studia Logica: An International Journal For Symbolic Logic
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/40210800?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Studia Logica: An
International Journal for Symbolic Logic
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
P. Agliano Basic Hoops: an Algebraic
I. M.A. Ferreirim Study
F. MONTAGNA
of Continuous t-norms
Abstract. A continuous t-norm is a continuous map * from [0, 1]2 into [0, 1] suc
([0, 1], *, 1) is a commutative totally ordered monoid. Since the natural ordering o
is a complete lattice ordering, each continuous t-norm induces naturally a residu
- > and ([0, 1], *, - >, 1) becomes a commutative naturally ordered residuated mono
called a hoop. The variety of basic hoops is precisely the variety generated by all a
([0, 1], *, - >, 1), where * is a continuous t-norm. In this paper we investigate the st
of the variety of basic hoops and some of its subvarieties. In particular we prov
complete description of the finite subdirectly irreducible basic hoops, and we show
the variety of basic hoops is generated as a quasivariety by its finite algebras. We
these results to Hajek's BL-algebras, and we give an alternative proof of the fact
the variety of BL-algebras is generated by all algebras arising from continuous t-no
[0, 1] and their residua. The last part of the paper is devoted to the investigation
subreducts of BL-algebras, of Godel algebras and of product algebras.
A continuous t-norm is a continuous map * from [0, 1]2 into [0, 1] suc
([0, 1], *, 1) is a commutative totally ordered monoid. There are thre
damental continuous t-norms: the Lukasiewicz t-norm defined by x *
max(x + y - 1, 0), the Godel (or lattice) norm x *g y = x A y and the prod
norm x*pj/ = xy. Indeed it is known ([24, 35]) that, up to isomorph
every continuous t-norm behaves locally as one of the above.
Since the natural ordering on [0, 1] is a complete lattice ordering,
t-norm induces naturally a residuation, or an implication in more l
terms, by x - > y = sup{z : z * x < y}. The implications associated
three fundamental norms are:
x-^l!/ = min(y - x + 1, 1)
if x < y
y otherwise
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
74 P. Agliano, I. M.A. Ferreirim and F. Montagna
fl ifx<y
and x ^P y = < . .
\y/x otherwise .
x - » x = 1
a; -+1 = 1
1 -> rr = x
x - » y = 1 and y - ► x = 1 imply x = y.
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Basic Hoops: an Algebraic Study of Continuous t-norms 75
Bosbach's work seems to have been the main source of inspiration for Biichi
and Owens' research on commutative complemented monoids, which they
called hoops. They prepared a manuscript entitled "Complemented Monoids
and Hoops" in the middle seventies but, mainly because the manuscript
was never published, their ideas caught on slowly. Blok and Pigozzi in
[10] applied these ideas in the study of hoops with dual normal operators,
which are a generalization of Boolean algebras with operators, but the first
systematic study of the structural properties of hoops appeared in Ferreirim's
thesis [19]. Some of the results obtained there can be found in two joint
papers with Blok [5] and [6]; in particular the description of subdirectly
irreducible hoops ([6, Theorem 2.9]) will play a crucial role in this paper.
Since the ordering induced by the residual of any continuous t-norm is the
natural ordering on [0, 1], any algebra of the form ([0, 1], *, - ►, 0, 1) is a hoop
that is also bounded, i.e., has a smallest element 0. Hence all the varieties we
have considered so far are varieties of (bounded) hoops. This suggests the
possibility that the structure theory of hoops can be used to achieve a better
understanding of these varieties (and of the logics involved); conversely the
class of varieties arising from these logics might shed more light on the be-
havior of other classes of hoops (and their implicative subreducts). The aim
of this paper is to show that this enterprise can be successful. In Section 1
we investigate the variety of basic hoops, i.e., the variety of hoops naturally
associated with basic logic; we clarify its relationship with the variety of
basic BL-algebras and we characterize completely its finite subdirectly irre-
ducible members in terms of ordinal sums of hoops. Then we do the same for
its implicative subreducts. In Sections 2 and 3 we proceed to show that the
variety of basic hoops is generated as a quasivariety by its finite algebras and
the same holds for its implicative subreducts. As a by-product we are able
to give a new proof and a slight improvement of the completeness result in
[14]. In Section 4 we point out that the variety of G-hoops, naturally associ-
ated with Godel logic, consists of well-known objects and we characterize its
implicative subreducts. Sections 5 and 6 are devoted to product hoops, i.e.,
hoops coming from the product t-norm. In Section 5 we study the structure
of product hoops and their implicative subreducts, while in Section 6 we
describe completely the lattice of subvarieties of product hoops.
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
76 P. Agliano, I. M.A. Ferreirim and F. Montagna
1. x-*x = l
2. x(x -► y) = y{y -► x)
3. x -► (y -+ z) = xy -► z.
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Basic Hoops: an Algebraic Study of Continuous t-norms 77
We now tu
known tha
BCK-algeb
Meredith's
form a qua
is any vari
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
78 P. Agliano, I. M.A. Ferreirim and F. Montagna
(((X _+ y) -+ y) _+ X) _+ X « (((y ^ X) -+ X)
(x ^ y) -+ (x -* z) « (y ^ x) -+ (y -^ z) (H)
[5, 20]. A syntactic derivation of (J) from axioms for BCK-algebras tog
with (H) may be found in [34].
It is known that for BCK-algebras identity (T) implies (J). Theref
(T) defines a subvariety of WSeOC, the variety L'hQX of Lukasiewicz
algebras. Lukasiewicz BCK-algebras were introduced by Komori [32],
the name C algebras, to study the implicative fragment of Lukasiewicz ma
valued logic. The variety L'BQX coincides with the variety of implic
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Basic Hoops: an Algebraic Study of Continuous t-norms 79
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
80 P. Agliano, I. M.A. Feneirim and F. Montagna
(x^y)^z<((y-+x)-+z)-+ z. (B)
1The equivalence between (ii) and (iii) has been considered by Palasinski in [38], with
respect to BCK-algebras.
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Basic Hoops: an Algebraic Study of Continuous t-norms 81
(x->y)->z<((y^x)-^z)-+ z. (B)
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
82 P. Agliano, I. M.A. Ferrekim and F. Montagna
A^Cni0.-.0Cnfc,
as claimed. ■
Since every
see that the
the same as th
bounded hoop
correspond to
to BL-algebra
It follows fr
hoop subredu
isfying (B). T
BL-algebras, l
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Basic Hoops: an Algebraic Study of Continuous t-norms 83
In this section we shall show that both "BJi and ££ are generated as qua-
sivarieties by their finite algebras. As a by-product we will obtain a new
proof and a slight improvement of the completeness result [14] mentioned
in the introduction. The results obtained in this section are a refinement
for the varieties £ % and ££ of similar results obtained for a large class of
varieties of hoops - see [6, section 3]. An algebra A in a class % has the
finite embeddability property (FEP) with respect to X if for any finite partial
subalgebra A; of A there exists a finite algebra B € % such that A' is em-
beddable in B. A class X has the FEP if each of its members has the FEP
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
84 P. Agliano, L M.A. Ferreirim and F. Montagna
Since it is clear
a totally ordered
proof goes throu
Corollary 2.2. T
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Basic Hoops: an Algebraic Study of Continuous t-norms 85
Corollary 2.4. The quasi- equational theories of'B'K and'BH are decidable.
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
86 P. Agliano, I. M.A. Ferreirim and F. Montagna
a->bL=<
L fl ifa<6
^max{l - a, 6} otherwise
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Basic Hoops: an Algebraic Study of Continuous t-norms 87
Note that - > is the residual of the nilpotent minimum t-norm [21], de
by
_ J min{a, b} if a > 1 - b
yO otherwise
Thus, A is the implicative reduct of a commutative integral residuated lat-
tice, hence a BCK-algebra. However A does not satisfy (H). This can be
seen by taking x = 2/3, y = 1/3 and z = 0. It follows that A is a (totally
ordered) BCK-algebra that is not a subreduct of any hoop, hence does not
belong to SSeOC.
Using [32, Theorem 3.13] and [5, Theorem 4.3] we can characterize the
finite subdirectly irreducible HBCK-algebras satisfying (B). Here the build-
ing blocks are the implicative reducts of the hoops Cn, which will be denoted
henceforth by Ln.
A^Lnie--.0Lnfc.
Our next goal is to show that the variety BBC9C is generated by its finite
algebras. Since every subdirectly irreducible basic BCK-algebra is a tota
ordered HBCK-algebra, it suffices to show that the class of totally order
HBCK-algebras has the FEP; using [5, Theorem 4.3], the proof of Theor
2.1 will go through for totally ordered HBCK-algebras. It is only necessa
to show that the class of totally ordered Lukasiewicz BCK-algebras has t
FEP, so we proceed to prove it.
Proposition 3
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
88 P. Agliano, I. M.A. Ferreirim and F. Montagna
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Basic Hoops: an Algebraic Study of Continuous t-norms 89
xAnx = 0 (PAl)
-i-* -> {{xz -> yz) ->(*-+ y)) = 1. (PA2)
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
90 P. Agliano, I. M.A. Ferreirim and F. Montagna
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Basic Hoops: an Algebraic Study of Continuous t-norms 91
Proof. The second claim is easily proved by inspection, using the above
description of finite Wajsberg chains. Let A be a totally ordered Wajsberg
hoop and a,b,c€ A with c < ab. Then ab £ c and by residuation a£b - ► c.
Since A is totally ordered, 6 - ► c < a. By a repeated use of equation (T) we
get
a = a V (b -> c)
= (a->(6-c))->(6->c)
= (ab - ♦ c) - > (b - > c)
= b - > ((ab -> c) -* c)
= 6->(a&Vc)
= 6 -► aft. m
Lemma 5.5. Let A be a subdirectly irreducible basic hoop satisfying the equa-
tion
(x-+y)->y<((y->z)-+ ((y -> x) -> x)) -> ((y -+ x) -> x). (PB)
Then either A is a Wajsberg hoop or A = 2 ©B for some Wajsberg hoop B.
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
92 P. Agliano, I. M.A. Ferreirim and F. Montagna
Theorem 5.6.2 The variety 3*K consists exactly of basic hoops satisfying
(V^z)V((y^xy)-*x) = l. (PH)
The descr
1.9 is har
rectly irr
uct hoops
Corollary
if it is th
irreducib
subdirectl
Moreover
subdirect
2This axiom
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Basic Hoops: an Algebraic Study of Continuous t-norms 93
xy = x + y
x->y = 0V(y-x)
lp(G) = 0g-
It is easily seen that P(G) is cancellative. The converse is true as well [6,
Theorem 1.17]: if A is a cancellative hoop then there is an abelian ^-group
G such that A^P(G).
Lemma 5.8. Any Lukasiewicz BCK-algebra is isomorphic to a subreduct of
a cancellative hoop; hence S^(G) = L^QX.
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
94 P. Agliand, I. M.A. Ferreirim and F. Montagna
where:
xy = u A (x + y)
x->y = OV(y-:r)
U = 0G
Oa = u.
Theorem 5.9. Th
satisfying the eq
The link between abelian ^-groups, cancellative hoops and product algebras
has been explored in [6] and [15]. A similar result holds for product hoops.
It is well-known [4] that the variety C of cancellative hoops is generated
as a quasivariety by the cancellative hoop C^ = (C^, - >, •, 1) (i.e. 6 =
SPPU{CU)), where Cu = {an : n £ uj} is the free monogenerated monoid
and
anam = an+m an -► am = amax(m"n'°) .
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Basic Hoops: an Algebraic Study of Continuous t-norms 95
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
96 P. Agliano, I. M.A. Ferreirim and F. Montagna
s\>e T
l = (a->0)->0=(0->a)->a=l-»a = a
References
[1] Adillon, R.J., and V. Verdu, 'On product logic', Soft Computing 2 (19
146.
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Basic Hoops: an Algebraic Study of Continuous t-norms 97
[9] Blok, W.J., and D. Pigozzi, 'Algebraizable logics', vol. 77 (396), Mem. A
Math. Soc, Providence, 1989.
[10] Blok, W.J., and D. Pigozzi, 'On the structure of varieties with equationally d
able principal congruences III , Algebra Universalis 32 (1994), 545-608.
[11] Blok, W.J., and J. Raftery, 'Varieties of commutative residuated inte
pomonoids and their residuation subreducts', J. Algebra 190 (1997), 280-328.
[12] BOSBACH, B., 'Komplementare Halbgruppen. Axiomatik und Arithmetik',
Math. 64 (1969), 257-287.
[13] Chang, C.C., 'Algebraic analysis of many valued logics', Trans. Amer. Mat
88 (1958), 467-490.
[14] ClGNOLl, R., F. Esteva, L. Godo, and A. TORRENS, 'Basic fuzzy logic is th
of continuous t-norms and their residua', Soft Computing 4 (2000), 106-112.
[15] Cignoli, R., and A. Torrens, 'An algebraic analysis of product logic', Mult-Val
Log. 5 (2000), 45-65.
[16] Cornish, W.H., 'A large variety of BCK-algebras', Math. Japon. 26 (1981), 339
[17] Dummett, M., 'A propositional calculus with denumerable matrix', J. Symb.
24 (1959), 97-106.
[18] Evans, T., 'Some connections between residual finiteness, finite embeddabilit
the word problem', J. London Math. Soc. 1 (1969), 399-403.
[19] Ferreirim, I.M.A., On varieties and quasivarieties of hoops and their reducts,
thesis, University of Illinois at Chicago, 1992.
[20] Ferreirim, I.M.A., 'On a conjecture by Andrzej Wronski for BCK-algebr
subreducts of hoops', Sci. Math. Jpn. 53 (2001).
[21] Fodor, J. C, 'Nilpotent minimum and related connectives for fuzzy logic', Pr
IEEE International Conference on Fuzzy Systems 4 (1995), 2077-2082.
[22] Font, J.M., A.J. Rodriguez, and A. Torrens, 'Wajsberg algebras', Stochas
(1984), 5-31.
[23] Gumm H.P., and A. Ursini, 'Ideals in universal algebra', Algebra Universalis 19
(1984), 45-54.
[24] Hajek, P., Metamathematics of fuzzy logic, Trends in Logic- Studia Logica Library,
no. 4, Kluwer Academic Publ., Dordrecht/ Boston/ London, 1998.
[25] Hajek, P., L. Godo, and F. Esteva, 'A complete many- valued logic with product
conjunction', Arch. Math. Logic 35 (1996), 191-208.
[26] Harrop, R., 'On the existence of finite models and decision procedures for proposi-
tional calculi', Proc. Cambridge Philos. Soc. 58 (1958), 1-13.
[27] Hecht, T., and T. Katrinak, 'Equational classes of relative Stone algebras', Notre
Dame J. Formal Logic 13 (1972), 248-254.
[28] HiGGS, D., 'Dually residuated commutative monoids with identity element do not
form an equational class', Math. Japon. 29 (1984), 69-75.
[29] HORN, A., 'The separation theorem of Intuicionistic Propositional Calculus', J. Symb.
Log. 27 (1962), 391-399.
[30] Iseki, K., 'An algebra related with a propositional calculus', Proc. Japan Acad. 42
(1966), 26-29.
[31] Kohler, P., 'Brouweriansemilattices', Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 268 (1981), 103-126.
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
98 P. Agliano, I. M.A. Ferreirim and F. Montagna
[34] Kowalski, T., 'A syntactic proof of a conjecture of Andrzej Wronski', Rep. Math.
Logic 28 (1994), 81-86.
[35] Mostert, P.S., and A.L. Shields, 'On the structure of semigroups on a compact
manifold with boundary', Ann. of Math. 65 (1957), 117-143.
[36] Mundici, D., 'Interpretation of AFC* -algebras in Lukasiewicz sentential calculus',
J. Functional Analysis 65 (1986), 15-63.
[37] Nemitz, W., 'Semi-boolean lattices', Notre Dame J. Formal Logic 10 (1969), 235-
238.
[38] Palasinski, M., 'Some remarks on BCK-algebras', Math. Seminar Notes, Kobe Univ.
8 (1980), 137-144.
[39] Palasinski, M., 'Ideals in BCK-algebras which are lower semilattices', Math. Japon.
26 (1981), 245-250.
[40] Raftery, J.G., On ideals, congruences and extensions of BCK-algebras, Ph.D. the-
sis, University of Natal, Durban, 1987.
[41] Raftery, J.G., and T. Sturm, 'On ideal and congruence lattices of BCK-
semilattices', Math. Japon. 32 (1987), 465-474.
[42] Wronski, A., 'BCK-algebras do not form a variety', Math. Japon. 28 (1983), 211-
213.
P. Agliano
Dipartimento di Matematica
Via del Capitano 15
53100 Siena, Italy
aglianoQunisi . it
I.M.A. Ferreirim
Departamento de Matemdtica
FCUL
Campo Grande, Ed. C6, Piso 2
1749-016 Lisboa, Portugal
mimaf erQptmat .fc.ul.pt
F. Montagna
Dipartimento di Matematica
Via del Capitano 15
53100 Siena, Italy
montagnaQunisi . it
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Wed, 17 Aug 2016 03:13:34 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms