Graham Harman: Utonomous Bjects
Graham Harman: Utonomous Bjects
Graham Harman: Utonomous Bjects
Graham Harman
Jane Bennett, Vibrant Matter: a political ecology of things, Durham, North
Carolina, Duke University Press, 2010; 200pp, £14.99 paperback.
Jane Bennett’s Vibrant Matter is an admirable book for at least three reasons.
First, it is wonderfully written in a comfortable personal style, which is rare
enough for academic books. Second, Bennett makes an explicit break with
the timeworn dogmas of postmodernist academia. She bids farewell to the
continental platitudes of recent decades: the social construction of the real,
and a dominant human subject cloaked in the alibi of language. In place
of these tattered garments she gives us ‘thing-power’, and from this new
autonomy of things much follows. Better yet, Bennett repeatedly avoids the
half-measure of saying that things ‘resist us with their recalcitrance’, that
disappointing manoeuvre which leaves humans in command while merely
haunting them with a vague letter X beyond their grasp. The third point
that makes this book admirable is Bennett’s professional position: Chair of
Political Science at Johns Hopkins University. That someone in a Political
Science department at an important university could write as candid a work
of metaphysics as Vibrant Matter is an encouraging sign. Perhaps philosophical
speculation on fundamental topics is poised for a comeback throughout the
humanities.
Bennett’s twelve-page preface has a certain freshness to it, and serves as a
fine overture to the chapters that follow. What she seeks is a ‘vital materiality’
or ‘material vitalism’ sharing more in common with childhood naiveté than
with the aloof critique that one normally adopts as a basic intellectual stance.
This leads her to oppose a Hegel-Marx-Adorno axis of ‘historical materialism’
that tends to ‘follow the trail of power to expose social hegemonies’ (pxiii).
Instead, Bennett empowers the non-human world, dropping the tedious
opposition between active humans and inanimate things. This leads her
to endorse an alternate materialist axis of Democritus-Epicurus-Spinoza-
Diderot-Deleuze. This may seem too close for comfort to Deleuze’s own
pantheon of favoured thinkers (I will return to this issue later). Nonetheless,
Bennett’s preface contains a flurry of insights. The usual tool of the intellectual
is demystification, and for Bennett it must be used with caution, since
‘demystification assumes that at the heart of any event or process lies a human
agency that has illicitly been projected into things’ (pxiv). Things do not just
obstruct human action, but have an inherent liveliness that allows them to act
in the world at large, not just on us. And finally, in a stirring declaration: ‘I
will emphasize, even overemphasize, the agentic contributions of nonhuman
forces.... in an attempt to counter the narcissistic reflex of human language
Reviews 127
powerful claim that the inhuman has a life of its own and does not exist only
to obstruct human will (p62), Bennett turns to the vitalist theories of Henri
Bergson and Hans Driesch (p63). It is not a matter of naively collecting
false allies: Bennett openly notes that Bergson and Driesch both agree that
matter is lifeless and mechanistic (p69), while she does not agree at all:
‘[This] association of matter with passivity still haunts us today ... weakening
our discernment of the force of things’ (p65). Bennett’s boldness in walking
alone is displayed further in her willingness to challenge Kant, that giant of
modern philosophy. For Kant the vital principle in the Critique of Judgment is
merely regulative and can never be directly encountered (p66); for Bennett,
however, mechanism is no less inscrutable (p67). For Kant there is a quantum
leap in reality from nature to humans; for Bennett, the world is made up
of fine gradations of experience (p68), a claim linking her with Whitehead.
Here, a Latourian sensitivity to the emptiness of the human-world duality
is combined with a Heideggerian vision of reality withdrawing from human
grasp. This should only be celebrated. But Bennett proceeds to a further
deduction that I find less compelling. Namely, she approvingly cites Bergson’s
view that ‘a world of fixed entities’ is a ‘distortion.... necessary and useful
because humans must use the world instrumentally if they are to survive in it’,
and laments that we ‘view the world as if it consisted not of an ever-changing
flow of time but of a calculable set of things’ (p77). In a related point, Bennett
celebrates the Bergsonian élan vital for being a source of surprise beneath
all the specific bodies it organizes. Now as before, this is aimed against the
notion of individual things as having causal agency: ‘the means available
to élan vital do not preexist.... the moment of their deployment, but rather
emerge in tandem with their effects’ (p78). And further: ‘as self-dispensing,
élan vital is profoundly at odds with itself ’ (pp79-80). In short, Bennett’s initial
enemies are (a) the robotic human-world gap of modern philosophy and (b)
the pairing of an inscrutable vital principle with calculable bland matter. But
she then pivots into an attack on (c) the very viability of individual things
and (d) the notion of discrete causal agents. The problem is that points (c)
and (d) need not result from points (a) and (b). In my view this is the wrong
choice on Bennett’s part, as will be argued at the close of this review.
Chapter Six, ‘Stem Cells and the Culture of Life’, applies the results of
Chapter Five to recent political events. Bennett makes the interesting claim
that the ‘culture of life’ represented by Catholics and evangelicals, and by
politicians such as George W. Bush and Tom DeLay, is in fact a kind of vitalism
in which the divine spark of life is opposed to bland inert matter. With this
form of vitalism she contrasts Driesch’s and her own: ‘unlike that evangelical
vitalism, the “critical,” “modern,” or “scientific” vitalism of Driesch pairs
an affirmation of non-material agencies (entelechies) at work in nature with
an agnosticism about the existence of any supernatural agency’ (p84). This
identification of the tacit evangelical metaphysics is interesting enough.
What makes it even more interesting is the parallel consideration, unstated
Reviews 129
Substance remains too static a notion, despite Spinoza’s different use of the
term, since nature ‘operates not in the service of a pre-given end but for the
sake of itself as process’ (p118). Anything that acts ‘has already entered an
agentic assemblage’ (p121). In referring to her own prose, Bennett stresses her
need to choose the appropriate verbs (p119), as if she were less interested in
nouns and their ‘static’ tendencies. With a wonderfully irreverent flourish, she
ends the book with a four-sentence ‘Nicene Creed,’ whose first two sentences
give a sufficient flavour of the whole: ‘I believe in one matter-energy, the
maker of things seen and unseen. I believe that this pluriverse is traversed
by heterogeneities that are continually doing things’ (p122).
We may be at a turning point in continental philosophy: a moment when
the increasingly sterile human-world couplet is losing legitimacy as the pillar
of our discipline. In nearly every case where key issues are touched upon
in Vibrant Matter, Bennett makes a fresh choice. We have seen that Bennett
avoids the typical, futile half-measure of saying that the human subject is not
all-powerful but meets with resistance from the world. Instead, she proposes
that philosophy treat the relations between things as no different in kind from
those between human and thing, and in this way she tacitly encroaches on
the terrain of the natural sciences. The old correlation of ‘man and world’ is
dissolved, as all human and inhuman actors are placed on the same footing:
atoms and stones are no less inscrutable than élan vital or the death drive.
And here one can only applaud. Yet it is less clear why dissolving the artificial
gap between human and world as kinds of beings entails that we need to
challenge the existence of individual things altogether. Instead of simply
placing flowers, armies, Italians, Chinese, radios, and hurricanes on the same
ontological footing by dissolving the rift between people and things, Bennett
also wants to dissolve the rift that divides any given thing from any other.
Ultimately, what is real in her new Nicene Creed is a pluriverse not of many
things, but of ‘one matter-energy’ that is ‘traversed by heterogeneities’. The
danger for Bennett, as for Deleuze and Deleuze’s Spinoza, is that objects are
liberated from slavery to the human gaze only to fall into a new slavery to a
single ‘matter-energy’ that allows for no strife between autonomous individual
things. Although it is true that Deleuze rescued us in the mid-1990s from
an endless repetition of text-centred philosophies, it is less clear in 2011
whether he remains the liberator we need. For this reader at least, Bennett
resembles DeLanda in being most interesting when she departs from Deleuze
most markedly.
Rainer Emig
Friedrich Kittler, Optical Media: Berlin Lectures 1999, Anthony Enns
(trans), Cambridge and Malden, MA, Polity Press, 2009, 250 pp, £17.99
paperback.
Reviews 133
Precarious, Pointillist
Deborah Staines
Judith Butler, Frames of War: When Is Life Grievable?, London and New
York, Verso, 2009.
In 2006, Judith Butler visited Sydney, and gave a public lecture in a modern
recital hall strikingly panelled with blonde Australian timber and gold leaf.
The street address - Angel Place - added a delicious irony, as did the gift of
dripping red flowers, and altogether the sense of occasion expressed the high
esteem in which Butler is held worldwide. There, Butler chose not to recap
her popular and influential philosophies of gender, as she might easily have
done and instead spoke intently about being an American citizen during the
Abu Ghraib abuses. Butler’s increasingly direct contribution to international
affairs seemed then to mark the passing of so many of the late twentieth
century’s major thinkers - Derrida, Deleuze, Lyotard, Said - whose intellectual
company she had kept, and who had written in resistance to the offences of
political violence. With her homeland launching an apparently limitless war
on Others, Butler has responded with critiques of statist political culture.
Following Precarious Life (2004), Frames of War reflects this commitment,
bringing together five essays written and revised between 2004-08.
Appropriately, Butler notes that she is writing in response to the contemporary
situation - Frames is neither treatise nor transhistorical narrative. However, it is
concerned with epistemological and ontological problems that are more than
incidental. The ‘frames’ under consideration are Western cultural structures
of recognition and of knowledge. Butler demonstrates how such frames shape
the representation of war, circumscribe war’s meaning, and efface violence’s
affect. Further, she links these epistemological issues to post-structuralist
understandings of socially constructed ontologies, to conclude that in these
wars, Others become ‘ungrievable’ casualties. This paradigm is also explored
across a number of other topics including abortion, sexuality, torture, and
religion. Thus, the book elaborates an existential politic that Butler locates
in the ‘precarity’ of life. The immediate context is the US-initiated conflicts
in Iraq and Afghanistan, but Butler aims to contribute an insight applicable
to many debates about violence and the human.
Certainly, Butler brings an unimpeachable degree of ethics to writing
on war. Her position of responsiveness is reclaimed from its current military
overuse, and brought back to Foucault’s reflexive ethos, to self conduct amidst
cultures of domination and atrocity. War’s destructiveness has a compelling
gravity that attracts and challenges the writer, but its pitiless light also
exposes weakness. Butler does not wield the eloquence of Simone Weil or the
practicality of Mary Kaldor, for comparison. At times, Butler’s approach is a
Reviews 135
In Our Time Of Dying
David W. Hill
Slavoj Žižek, Living in the End Times, London, Verso, 2010, 415 pp; £20
cloth.
The publication of Slavoj Žižek’s Living in the End Times was something of a
media event in Britain. An interview with the philosopher and psychoanalyst
appeared in the Observer whilst (an increasingly frustrated) Gavin Esler made
a commendable attempt at a conversation with the motor-brained thinker
on the BBC’s Newsnight program. All of which suggests that the book is one
of Žižek’s more populist offerings. ‘Serious’ Žižek produces work of such
philosophical insight that they cannot be ignored; ‘popular’ Žižek offers
laughs and film references - but without ever obscuring the vital ideas within.
This latest offering is no exception to the latter, a wonderful mix of jokes,
provocations, popular culture - and a serious message about a series of
impending crises being brought about by global capitalism.
The premise of the book is that the global capitalist system is facing a
fatal catastrophe occasioned by the ecological crisis, the biogenetic revolution,
the imbalances of the system itself (e.g. struggles over scarce resources), and
the rapid growth of social divisions and exclusions (e.g. gated communities,
slums). The book is organised into five chapters, each corresponding to
Elisabeth Kübler-Ross’ famous stages of coming to terms with death: denial,
anger, bargaining, depression, and acceptance. Žižek’s hypothesis is that we
can see these five stages in the way we (as a society) attempt to deal with the
coming apocalypse.
Denial: the way ideology works to mask the fundamental disorder. The
first chapter begins with an excellent analysis of the burqa/niqab debate in
France that briskly introduces the reader to Žižek’s account of denial. We are
taught, he says, that racism is a product of intolerance; if only we were more
tolerant, the world would be a better place. This is to forget the ‘background
noise’ (p6), an ideological move that would have us ignore the violence
that sustains the system. Racism is not the product of intolerance, it is the
product of injustice and inequality; tolerance is not the cure - emancipation
and political struggle is. The same ideological move, tuning-out background
noise, can be seen with recycling: ‘we are bombarded from all sides with
injunctions to recycle personal waste, placing bottles, newspapers, etc., in the
appropriate bins. In this way, guilt and responsibility are personalized - it is not
the entire organization of the economy which is to blame, but our subjective
attitude which needs to change’ (p22). This chapter is easily the strongest;
it carries a clear message applicable to a range of supposedly ethical actions
Reviews 137
With the discussion of depression, it begins to feel as if the five-stage format
is strained. Whilst the account of how we perceive the deleterious effects of
global capitalism is merited, lengthy and technical discussion of hard-to-pin-
down pathologies is somewhat dazzling - the risk here being that the message
is lost in translation (from ‘Lacanese’).
Acceptance: seeing the situation as a chance for a new beginning rather
than as a threat. After going in search of communist culture (in Kafka,
Platonov, Sturgeon, Vertov, and Satie) Žižek discusses subversion through
sheer brutality, using the German rock band Rammstein as a launch-pad.
Observing that Blair could be re-elected despite massive unpopularity, that
Berlusconi could hold a majority despite his clownishness, Žižek remarks
that ‘some form of violence will clearly have to be rehabilitated’ if the
Left is to ‘awaken’ the people (p390). However it is vital to note that Žižek
is not advocating a program of total violence. Once we accept that the
catastrophe we are heading towards is not an ‘uncontrollable quasi-natural
power’ (p387), which is to say, once we confront the abstract violence of
the system and give up on bargaining, another way becomes possible. What
should we do? Nothing? Some violent revolutionary act? Local pragmatic
interventions? Here Žižek advises that there is no need to choose, any one
of these strategies being appropriate at different times - even doing nothing
can, when appropriate, be a radical act. If these are the routes then what is
the destination? For Žižek, it is, of course, the dictatorship of the proletariat.
This shift from commentary and diagnosis to political response shows Žižek
for what he is: an excellent theorist and psychoanalyst, not a political figure.
It is not easy to ascertain what form resistance should really take (how do
we choose between violence, pragmatism, nothing?) and the organisation
of the dictatorship of the proletariat is opaque. In what way does it differ
from that in Marx? If it does not, then how would that work?
Between chapters are diverting interludes, with discussions on such topics
as Josef Fritzl, Silvio Berlusconi, and the animated film Kung Fu Panda. An
interlude on architecture is notable for exemplifying Žižek’s scenic routes
through topics: ‘So, back to postmodern architecture’ (p261) he writes, after
getting side-tracked by the phenomenological experience of shit in a section
that also includes the author’s musings on Sarah Palin as a failed feminist
icon (‘drill, baby, drill!’ (p270)).
There are comments on Emmanuel Levinas at several points in the
1. For example, book that echo those made often in Žižek’s other work.1 For example, in his
in Slavoj Žižek,
Violence: Six Sideways discussion of the burqa he writes:
Reflections, London,
Profile, 2008.
why does the encounter with a face covered by a burqa trigger such
anxiety? Is it that a face so covered is no longer the Levinasian face: that
Otherness from which the unconditional ethical call emanates? But what
if the opposite is the case? From a Freudian perspective, the face is the
ultimate mask that conceals the horror of the Neighbor-Thing: the face is
Žižek notes that if the face is covered then it reveals the abyss of the other,
causing anxiety. I do not disagree with this but I find the reading of Levinas
uncharitable. The Levinasian other is a source of anxiety. Unknowable -
forever ‘the stranger in the neighbour’2 - the other is a source of ontological 2. Emmanuel
Levinas, Otherwise
insecurity: we cannot know what there is with the other. Further, the infinite Than Being, or Beyond
demands that are placed on the ‘I’ in encounter with the other are surely Essence, A. Lingis
(trans), Pittsburgh,
a source of further ill-ease, responsibility initiated against the will as the ‘I’ Duquesne University
is ‘ordered toward the face of the other’.3 The Levinasian ethical encounter Press, 2008, p123.
Reviews 139