(Great Medieval Thinkers) Stephen Edmund Lahey - John Wyclif-Oxford University Press, USA (2008) PDF
(Great Medieval Thinkers) Stephen Edmund Lahey - John Wyclif-Oxford University Press, USA (2008) PDF
(Great Medieval Thinkers) Stephen Edmund Lahey - John Wyclif-Oxford University Press, USA (2008) PDF
Series Editor
Brian Davies
Fordham University
duns scotus
Richard Cross
bernard of clairvaux
Gillian R. Evans
robert grosseteste
James McEvoy
boethius
John Marenbon
peter lombard
Philipp W. Rosemann
bonaventure
Christopher M. Cullen
al-kindī
Peter Adamson
john buridan
Gyula Klima
anselm
Sandra Visser and Thomas Williams
john wyclif
Stephen E. Lahey
john
wyclif
Stephen E. Lahey
1 2009
1
Oxford University Press, Inc., publishes works that further
Oxford University’s objective of excellence
in research, scholarship, and education.
With offices in
Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece
Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore
South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam
www.oup.com
Lahey, Stephen E.
John Wyclif / by Stephen E. Lahey.
p. cm. — (Great medieval thinkers)
Includes bibliographical references (p. ) and index.
ISBN 978-0-19-518331-3; 978-0-19-518332-0 (pbk.)
1. Wycliffe, John, d. 1384. I. Title.
BX4905.L34 2008
270.5092—dc22 2008013774
1 3 5 7 9 8 6 4 2
Printed in the United States of America
on acid-free paper
series foreword
Many people would be surprised to be told that there were any great medi-
eval thinkers. If a great thinker is one from whom we can learn today, and
if “medieval” serves as an adjective for describing anything which existed
from (roughly) ad 600 to 1500, then, so it is often supposed, medieval think-
ers cannot be called “great.”
Why not? One answer often given appeals to ways in which medieval
authors with a taste for argument and speculation tend to invoke authori-
ties, especially religious ones. Such invocations of authority are not the stuff
of which great thought is made—so it is often said today. It is also fre-
quently said that greatness is not to be found in the thinking of those who
lived before the rise of modern science, modern philosophy, and theology.
Students of science are nowadays hardly ever referred to literature earlier
than the seventeenth century. Students of philosophy in the twentieth cen-
tury were often taught nothing about the history of ideas between Aristotle
(384–322 bc) and Descartes (1596–1650). Modern students of theology have
often been frequently encouraged to believe that significant theological
thinking is a product of the nineteenth century.
Yet the origins of modern science lie in the conviction that the world is
open to rational investigation and is orderly rather than chaotic—a con-
viction which came fully to birth, and was systematically explored and
v
vi series foreword
And they do so on the assumption that these authors are as worth reading
today as they were when they wrote. Students of medieval literature (e.g.,
the writings of Chaucer) are currently well supplied (if not oversupplied)
with secondary works to aid them when reading the objects of their con-
cern. But those with an interest in medieval philosophy and theology are by
no means so fortunate when it comes to reliable and accessible volumes to
help them. The Great Medieval Thinkers series therefore aspires to remedy
that deficiency by concentrating on medieval philosophers and theologians
and by offering solid overviews of their lives and thought coupled with
contemporary reflections on what they had to say. Taken individually, vol-
umes in the series provide valuable treatments of single thinkers, many of
whom are not currently covered by any comparable books. Taken together,
they constitute a rich and distinguished history and discussion of medieval
philosophy and theology considered as a whole. With an eye on college
and university students, and with an eye on the general reader, authors of
volumes in the series strive to write in a clear and accessible manner so that
each of the thinkers can be investigated by those who have no previous
knowledge about them. But each contributor to the series also intends to
inform, engage, and generally entertain even those with specialist knowl-
edge when it comes to medieval thinking. So, as well as surveying and
introducing, the volumes in the series seek to advance the state of medieval
studies at both the historical and the speculative levels.
The subject of the present volume belongs to the period of late scholasti-
cism. Wyclif was the most prominent English philosopher of the second
half of the fourteenth century. He wrote voluminously on topics such as
logic, language, epistemology, and politics. Yet he was also a very distin-
guished theologian. He had things to say about, for example, God’s exis-
tence and nature, the Bible, grace, the sacraments, and ecclesiology.
Condemned as a heretic after his death, Wyclif stressed the authority
of scripture, attacked the notion of transubstantiation, and was a vigorous
critic of several aspects of the church as he took it to be in his lifetime. So
he has often been regarded as a forerunner (or the major forerunner) of
sixteenth-century Reformation thinkers. But was Wyclif really that? To
answer this question, we need to know how his philosophical and theo-
logical conclusions compare and contrast with those of his predecessors,
and this is something that Stephen Lahey explains in some detail. In addi-
tion, Professor Lahey provides us with a comprehensive introduction to
viii series foreword
—Brian Davies
preface
ix
x preface
Wyclif devoted to attacking the papacy and the friars. Those with a taste
for Wyclif ’s antipapal and antifraternal polemics should turn to the studies
I list in the notes for chapter 6. Likewise, I have made no more than passing
reference to the phenomena of Lollardy and the Hussites. In the first case,
readers are advised to look to the relative wealth of studies of Lollardy that
have followed on the groundbreaking work of Anne Hudson. In the sec-
ond, readers unfamiliar with Czech have considerably fewer alternatives
beyond the pioneering work of Thomas A. Fudge, Howard Kaminsky,
and Matthew Spinka. The best bibliographic resource is at http://lollard
society.org.
I am indebted to Lesley Ann Dyer for making available to me her dis-
covery of the Wyclif Society’s handwritten manuscripts of De Ydeis and
De Tempore, which had been left in a drawer in Trinity College library.
Similarly, I am indebted to Michael Dunne, Rega Wood, Aidan Breen,
Dallas Denery, Laurent Cesalli, Christina van Nolcken, Michael Treschow,
and Paul Streveler, each of whom have made their scholarship available to
me as I researched this book. I am particularly grateful to the late Norman
Kretzman, who kindly gave me his collected notes on and translations of
Wyclif ’s atomism, and wished me luck in studying a heretic in a field in
which such a thing still matters. I am also grateful to Stella Wilks who,
with the help of Diana Wood, made the collected papers of the late Michael
Wilks available to me. Ian Levy, Ruth Nisse, and Anne Hudson have read
and commented on sections of this book, and Brian Davies, Merryl Sloan,
Patrick Hornbeck, Fiona Somerset, and Julia McQuillan have read the
whole of it; to each, I am very grateful for saving me from having made
unfortunate mistakes. Those that remain are my own. Ian Levy has helped
immeasurably in many conversations and e-mail exchanges, and his scholar-
ship has contributed much to what follows. Finally, I am particularly grate-
ful to A. S. “Steve” McGrade, my dissertation advisor and mentor, who,
when I said I thought that Wyclif might be a good candidate for Oxford’s
Great Medieval Thinkers series, heartily encouraged me. I hope this book
will serve as a token of thanks for the friendly guidance he has provided
me over the years.
This page intentionally left blank
contents
Epilogue 222
Notes 245
Bibliography 271
Index 287
xiii
This page intentionally left blank
john wyclif
This page intentionally left blank
1
3
4 john wyclif
are suggested as his birthplace, and historians generally recognize the latter
as most likely.2 This tiny village is not far from Richmond castle, a northern
stronghold in a time when Bannockburn and Scots raiders haunted living
memory. J. M. W. Turner’s romantic depictions of Richmond castle and
Wycliffe near Rokeby show a thickly wooded landscape of towering hills
and secluded glens. While appealing to us, in Wyclif ’s time, this was fron-
tier territory, the beauty of which may have been lost on its inhabitants. We
know that Wyclif ’s family was of lesser nobility and that his parents were
married in 1319. Many priests of the age were younger sons deprived by
primogeniture of landholding, so it is probable that Wyclif, likely a younger
son, was born sometime in the 1320s; the accepted date is 1328. Of his early
life, nothing is known, save that his first teacher was one John de Clervaux,
the rector of Wycliffe Church until his death in 1362. Extant records sug-
gest that Wyclif became lord of the manor around 1360, thereby assum-
ing responsibility for supplying Wycliffe Church with its rector. This office
was occupied by William Wyclif, a cousin of John and a fellow student at
Oxford, and later by other members of his family. More important, the
small landholding’s overlord was the Duke of Lancaster, John of Gaunt,
which may account for the genesis of Wyclif ’s later political affiliation.
While we know little about the actual appearance of many medieval
figures, we have an idea of Wyclif ’s physical presence. A contemporary
source describes him as having a distinctly charismatic aura and a frail, per-
haps birdlike physique, while an illumination in a 1410 Prague manuscript
depicts a bearded, faintly scowling scholar. Certainly, Wyclif ’s writings give
evidence of a contentious, acerbic personality who evolved from a philoso-
pher with a quicksilver wit to a churchman unswervingly dedicated to the
pastoral responsibilities of preaching and writing. Also, we can be sure that
Wyclif ’s native tongue was what we now call Middle English, the version of
English most often encountered by students reading Chaucer’s Canterbury
Tales. Despite the historically widespread belief that Wyclif wrote volumi-
nously in English for the spiritual edification of the laity, there is no extant
text that can be attributed to him with certainty. That Wyclif spoke, prob-
ably wrote, and very likely thought in his native tongue is relevant to under-
standing his Latin works, though. Wyclif ’s Latin is difficult to understand
at its best, and sensitivity to the speech patterns and vocabulary of Middle
English can help to clarify at least some of the difficult areas in it.
Wyclif likely began studying at Queen’s College, Oxford, in the 1340s,
perhaps with an eye on a career in the law, and we know that he graduated
wyclif’s life and work 5
Merton College. He spent the next four years pursuing a master’s degree
at Balliol College, during which period he was also elected to be Balliol’s
third master. In gaining this distinction, Wyclif had to receive the concur-
rence of numerous other officials at Oxford, notably Uthred of Boldon, a
Benedictine scholar who was to become one of his first intellectual oppo-
nents. Upon receiving his master of arts degree, Wyclif was installed as a
parish priest in Fillingham, Lincolnshire, on 14 May 1361. The next year,
he formally asked the pope for a canonry in Yorkshire, somewhat closer to
home, but instead was granted another parish in Bristol, Aust at Westbury-
on-Trym, which he held in addition to the one in Fillingham. Wyclif was
at best an infrequent figure at Westbury. Instead, he requested permission
to return to Oxford, which was granted on 29 August 1363. Holding sev-
eral livings in different parishes was quite common, and had Wyclif been
any other scholarly priest, this pluralism would have been unremarkable.
Given Wyclif ’s later vehement excoriation of the practice, it is difficult to
understand why he engaged in it throughout his Oxford career.
In the autumn of 1363, Wyclif began his theological training, which
would involve four years of lectures and several more years of experience in
formal disputation. Following this demanding curriculum, the theologian
in training was required to begin studying and constructing a commentary
on Peter Lombard’s Sentences. Should he finish this, he would receive a doc-
torate in theology.4 All the while, Wyclif was expected to remain respon-
sible for his parish in Fillingham and his prebend at Aust, although he
exchanged Fillingham for Ludgershall, Buckinghamshire, in November
1368. Wyclif achieved a bachelor’s of theology in March 1369, and a doctor-
ate in late 1372; the three-year period between the two was full of signifi-
cance for his later career.
Archbishop Simon Islip of Canterbury had founded Canterbury Col-
lege at Oxford in 1361 and, perhaps remembering the promising young
cleric from Thoresby’s diocese, selected Wyclif to be its warden in December
1365. The college was founded to include a mixture of monks and secular,
nonmonastic students, which in those times could be a volatile combina-
tion. Quarreling between the two factions had driven out the first warden,
a monk named Woodhull, and the monks had little interest in the super-
vision of a secular priest like Wyclif. Islip supported Wyclif for a year in
the face of this tension, but died and was succeeded by John Langham, who
had been a Benedictine abbot before becoming archbishop of Canterbury.
Langham immediately ordered Wyclif from Canterbury’s wardenship, but
wyclif’s life and work 7
Wyclif would not submit to this sort of politics and appealed the case to
Pope Urban V at Avignon. Urban had little love for Langham, who had
earlier thwarted Avignon’s attempts to exact tribute from England. Five
uncomfortable years passed at Canterbury College before Urban finally
decided against Wyclif. During that period, Wyclif occasionally ran afoul
of the “regulars,” the scholars who as monks and friars had sworn to live
according to a rule.
Summa de Ente
I.1. De Ente in Communi
I.2. De Ente Primo in Communi
I.3. Purgans Errores circa Veritates in Communi
I.4. Purgans Errores circa Universalia in Communi
I.5. De Universalibus
I.6. De Tempore
I.7. De Ente Predicamentali
II.1. De Intellectione Dei
II.2. De Sciencia Dei
II.3. De Volucione Dei
II.4. De Trinitate
II.5. De Ydeis
II.6. De Potencia Productiva Dei ad extra
Others are predicable of both divine and created nature, though only analo-
gously. These are goodness, knowing, power, understanding, and volition.
Wyclif begins with these in the second book of the Summa de Ente, devot-
ing individual treatises to God’s knowing, understanding, and willing. The
contents of God’s knowledge, the divine ideas, are the subject of De Ydeis,
while De Trinitate addresses the relation of the three persons of the Trinity.
We will consider these in our summary of Wyclif ’s conception of God’s
nature in chapter 3.
Wyclif ’s expressly philosophical works also include a discussion of
Aristotelian hylomorphism in light of his realism, De Materia et Forma,
and an exploration of the relation of body to soul in human beings, De
Composicione Hominis. These treatises, while not part of the Summa de Ente,
are important to Wyclif ’s later philosophy because the relation of soul to
body, he explains, causally prefigures the relation of lord to master, which
he views as the fundamental human relation in creation.12 This is also a
significant element of De Benedicta Incarnacione, Wyclif ’s analysis of the
relation of divine and human natures in the incarnation. Here, he empha-
sizes that Christ’s life as described in scripture embodies the intertwined
relation of servanthood and lordship that holds between Christ’s divinity
and humanity. As with his conception of God’s nature and the Trinity, his
Christology is characterized by emphasis on the primary causative reality
of the divine ideas and universals.
Throughout this book, reference will be made to “the moderni,” a term
frequently interpreted as synonymous with followers of Ockham. While
this may be acceptable in contemporary historical studies, it is not accurate
for fourteenth-century Oxford usage. In Wyclif ’s day, the term was gen-
erally used to refer to anybody active from the time of Aquinas onward.
Wyclif himself uses the term with profligacy, sometimes referring to theo-
logians like Henry of Ghent or Thomas Bradwardine, with whom he
generally agrees. More often, his reference has a derisory tone, as when
he charges the moderni with ignoring the universal “humanity’s” place in
Christ’s assumption of created substantial form, which he holds as tanta-
mount to closing one’s eyes to the incarnation’s majesty. This antagonism
toward the Ockhamist rejection of realism runs throughout these early
works, as does a concurrent frustration with Thomist and Scotist attempts
at moderating Augustine’s realism. It would be inaccurate to hold that
Wyclif rejects Ockhamism as a whole, just as it would be shortsighted to
ignore the influence of the Aristotelian syntheses of Thomas and Scotus
14 john wyclif
By November 1372, Wyclif had entered into the service of John of Gaunt,
the Duke of Lancaster. Gaunt was the most powerful, and the most
unpopular, individual in England in the 1370s. The third surviving son
of Edward III was also the only member of the king’s immediate family
with a future, such as it was. The aging Edward suffered from dementia,
while the heir apparent, Edward the Black Prince, was slowly dying of
an infection contracted while campaigning on the Continent. The Black
Prince had arranged that his younger brother John should have sufficient
power to protect the dynastic line for his own son Richard, but had sowed
discord among other nobles and prelates against his brother to keep John
from making an attempt on the crown for himself. So John of Gaunt had
custody of royal power, but no sovereignty. He had need of academic minds
in his retinue, and his selection of Wyclif is not surprising. Wyclif had an
agile mind, was a younger son of the lesser nobility, and was familiar with
ecclesiastical politics. That the Duke of Lancaster was engaged in conflict
with powerful bishops likely had nothing to do with the invitation, for
16 john wyclif
Wyclif had not yet manifested the anticlericalism that would identify his
later works.
One of Wyclif ’s first responsibilities, after receiving the living associated
with the parish of Lutterworth in Lincolnshire, was to serve at a meet-
ing between representatives of the Crown and the pope at Bruges in July
1374. The conference was ostensibly an attempt to iron out past differences
on the subject of papal provisions, but in fact was meant to facilitate the
flow of funds from the English church to the Crown. Wyclif ’s presence was
unnecessary, and he returned to England that September. In the late sum-
mer, he had begun to develop his theory of dominium, explaining that “it is
time to devote my energies as much to practical as to theoretical affairs, for
as much time as God has given me.”17 His dominium treatises, in which he
explains the relation of God’s creation and subsequent lordship over cre-
ation to all instances of human lordship and servitude, mark a significant
turning point in Wyclif ’s writing career. While he would refer regularly
to metaphysical subjects in his writings, he would only address them in
something resembling a sustained fashion once more, in Trialogus, a summa
summe, in 1383. Now his attention was directed to producing the Summa
Theologie, a collection of treatises on the foundation of all human law in
God’s law and its implications for secular politics, ecclesiology, scriptural
interpretation, and crimes against God’s commands. Just before beginning
the work that would become his second Summa, Wyclif wrote De Dominio
Divino (1373), a treatise in three books that examines the nature of God’s
lordship over creation. Given Wyclif ’s metaphysical realism, it is difficult
to avoid concluding that he viewed God’s lordship relation as having a pri-
mary causal bearing on human lordship relations, in the manner of a uni-
versal to particulars.18
The opening treatises of the Summa Theologie were the cause of Wyclif ’s
first significant clashes with the church hierarchy. On the face of it, trea-
tises on the foundation of just human law in the Ten Commandments
(De Mandatis Divinis, 1375) and the ideal human state in Eden (De Statu
Innocencie, 1376) seem innocent enough. In the former, there is already evi-
dence for Wyclif ’s suspicion of the church’s inordinate concern for tempo-
ralia, but Wyclif ’s contention that property ownership follows from original
sin, which is outlined in these treatises, is consonant with Augustinian the-
ology. The treatise on civil lordship that was to follow changed everything.
De Civili Dominio (1376–1377) argued for a total royal divestment of all
ecclesiastical property on this Augustinian foundation. Wyclif ’s argument
wyclif’s life and work 17
included claims about the evils of property ownership that had been made
by radical Franciscans during the poverty controversy, arguments for cleri-
cal submission to secular justice, the renunciation of papal authority, and
the assertions that the damned are no part of the church and that no one
in mortal sin can function as a priest. As we will see, these positions follow
logically from his earlier treatises, but their effect, given Wyclif ’s promi-
nence in the service of the noble most at odds with Canterbury and the
papacy, was dramatic.
On 19 February 1377, Wyclif answered a summons to appear before
Archbishop Sudbury, Bishop William Courtenay of London, and several
other notables at St. Paul’s to account for his heretical ideas. He did not
appear alone, though; John of Gaunt, his associate Henry Percy, and vari-
ous other nobles of the duke’s retinue accompanied him to the arraignment,
much to the interest of the gathering crowd of Londoners. The proceed-
ings resembled a stereotypical press conference before a championship
bout. John of Gaunt’s appearance guaranteed that little of substance would
occur, given his well-known energetic antipathy for England’s ecclesiastical
establishment, and little did occur beyond some name calling, grumbled
threats, and acrimonious posturing. Upon hearing the duke threaten to
drag Courtenay out of the chapel by his hair, the crowd erupted in clamor-
ous rage against the nobles, and the arraignment dissolved into confusion.
Had it not been for the duke’s soldiers, a full-scale riot would have fol-
lowed. As it was, Wyclif and his protectors escaped to safety elsewhere,
while the mob spent the next day tearing London apart in search for the
hated duke.
It is unlikely that the duke had paid much attention to the substance of
Wyclif ’s arguments. The arraignment at St. Paul’s had been an opportunity
for him to humiliate his enemies, and the angry Londoners had interceded
too quickly for his purposes. John would bide his time and wait for a new
chance to attack the bishops. Wyclif, perhaps sensing that he had been used
by his patron, attempted to address criticisms of De Civili Dominio made by
his Franciscan colleague William Woodford, hoping that his many argu-
ments taken from canon law, patristic authority, and especially from scrip-
ture would help to win over his erring fellow clerics. The result, the second
and third books of the treatise, introduces many of the topics that would
later occupy Wyclif ’s full attention, including the church’s need for pastoral
reform, the problems inherent in devoting one’s life to a monastic or frater-
nal rule, the nature of heresy, and the place of scripture in a life of faith.19
18 john wyclif
The English bishops were not the only church authorities alarmed
by De Civili Dominio. The pope, who had until very recently been based
in Avignon, had moved to Rome. Unaware of the theatrics at St. Paul’s,
Gregory XI issued a series of five bulls on 22 May 1377, demanding that
Sudbury and Courtenay address the problem by extracting a confession
from Wyclif and imprisoning him to await judgment from Rome. Should
Wyclif go into hiding, Gregory continued, he should be ferreted out.
Judgment from Rome would have been contingent on the Crown’s reac-
tion to Wyclif ’s seizure. Gregory had been trying to reconcile England with
France, and may have had Wyclif ’s disposition in mind as a means of per-
suading Edward to reconsider his antipathy toward the French. Certainly,
the language Gregory used made it clear that he expected Edward to recog-
nize the danger that Wyclif posed to England’s well-being:
her younger brother-in-law John of Gaunt employed her revered name for
his purposes. Given the royal council’s earlier orders that Wyclif desist his
troublemaking, though, it appears that the duke was beginning to weary
of his servant’s zeal. The zealous and cultured Sir Lewis Clifford would
later be among the seven highly placed knights accused of having Lollard
sympathies in the early days of the movement.
Wyclif ’s usefulness to the duke ended later that year. Two English sol-
diers, Robert Hauley and John Shakyl, had captured a Spanish nobleman
while on campaign with the Black Prince eleven years previously, and had
been holding him for ransom, as was common in medieval warfare. In 1377,
the Crown had decided that it would profit more from holding the noble-
man directly and ordered the two soldiers to surrender their hostage. They
refused and were thrown into prison. The next summer, they managed to
escape and received sanctuary at Westminster Abbey. On 11 August, the
duke’s soldiers broke into the abbey during mass and tricked Shakyl into
fleeing to the steeple, which did not count as sanctuary. Meanwhile, Hauley
had run to hide at the altar, where he was caught and butchered by the
soldiers, who also murdered one of the priests celebrating the Eucharist.
Walsingham reports that the soldiers took Hauley’s corpse by the ankles and
heaved it outside, “bespattering everything with his blood and brains.”
Canterbury’s reaction was outrage, although the cautious Archbishop
Sudbury waited three days before formally excommunicating the soldiers
involved. That October, when Parliament met at Gloucester, the archbishop
made formal demands that those responsible, namely, John of Gaunt,
be held accountable for polluting Westminster and violating sanctuary.
Wyclif had been asked to represent the duke, who presumably expected
his servant to have learned about diplomacy from the Lambeth incident.
His arguments showed that he had learned little: sanctuary was in no
wise permissible when the royal authority was so flagrantly threatened, he
argued, and while the violence was regrettable, it had been brought on by
Hauley’s aggressive behavior. Parliament tabled discussion of the incident,
but Wyclif ’s unsuitability as a public spokesman for the Crown was by now
painfully obvious to the duke.21
Royal service must have been disagreeably confusing to Wyclif, who
had been used to the intellectual duels of Oxford. Why would his lord ask
him for arguments, which he could craft with such incisive skill and theo-
logical purity, only to back away from them as being too likely to upset his
opponents? Was that not the whole point? He had been engaged for some
wyclif’s life and work 21
years in running debate with the eminent lawyer and Mertonian logician
Ralph Strode, who disagreed forcefully with Wyclif ’s determinism and its
implications for a church of the predestinate. Strode argued that Wyclif ’s
ideas led to a dozen distinct problems linked to predestination and pre-
sented a host of objections about the dangers of total church reform.22 A
lawyer of some renown, Strode had not quailed before Wyclif ’s intellec-
tual onslaught; he had responded in kind. On the other hand, the prelates
responsible for the church’s welfare hid behind the questionable authority
of their office and of the power of the pope of Rome. Could the duke not
see that this gave evidence of their own guilt?
When Gregory XI died in March 1378, Bartolomeo Prignano, well
known for his probity and devotion to the ideal of apostolic poverty, became
Pope Urban VI. Hoping that this election signaled a new beginning for an
ailing church, and suspecting that Gregory had harbored personal animus
against him, Wyclif wrote to Urban to explain the orthodoxy of his thought.
He never lost hope that Urban would live up to his judicious reputation,
as is clear from an extant 1384 letter to that pope.23 Unfortunately, Urban
rarely gave evidence of his earlier sagacity. Shortly after his election, he
displayed a pugnacity that contributed to the French cardinals’ decision to
elect Robert of Geneva to the papacy instead. With the election of Cle-
ment VII, the Western schism had begun, and prospects for serious, sober
dialogue with the papacy on reform had vanished.
During these years, Wyclif wrote many of the treatises for which he is
now best known, including De Veritate Sacrae Scripturae (1377–1378), De
Ecclesia (1378–1379), De Officio Regis, De Officio Pastoralis, and De Potestate
Pape (all 1379). In addition, throughout the 1370s, Wyclif maintained a
heavy schedule of preaching and biblical scholarship, producing several
hundred sermons and commentaries on the Bible, including Postilla super
totam Bibliam and Opus Evangelicum. As we consider the arguments of the
works of the late 1370s in later chapters, we should remember that their
author made weekly appearances in London to preach and was probably
involved in pastoral responsibilities at Oxford. When he left Oxford in the
summer of 1381, he went to serve as the parish priest for the Leicestershire
village of Lutterworth, where he continued his scholarly projects as he cared
for the needs of the villagers. While reading his polemical outbursts against
the abuses he perceived throughout England and his sustained arguments
for a renewed church, it is easy to forget that Wyclif was all along actively
engaged in cura animarum, the care of souls.
22 john wyclif
Wyclif ’s last year in Oxford was one of controversy, in which ongoing argu-
ments that he and his disciples had with various opponents escalated into
hostile conflict. His followers were primarily younger, secular scholars eager
to defend their master’s views against their more conservative opponents,
who tended to be monks or friars. Among these followers, three stand out
because of their later roles in the genesis of Lollardy: Philip Repingdon,
Nicholas Hereford, and John Purvey. Repingdon was held in high regard
among his fellows at Oxford, and his extant writings give evidence of a
broad, seasoned theological mind. His sensitivity to theological error led
him to disavow his Wycliffite leanings early on, shortly after Wyclif him-
self left Oxford, forever vilifying himself to his former associates and their
Lollard disciples.24 Repingdon went on to become the bishop of Lincoln
and personal confessor to Henry IV. He would even receive a cardinal’s
hat, but from Gregory XII, whose papal authority would ultimately be nul-
lified. Despite almost joining the princes of the church, though, Repingdon
never abandoned his belief in the need for clerical reform; however, unlike
the Wycliffites, he believed such reform to be possible from within the hier-
archy of the church.25
Hereford and Purvey remained within the Wycliffite fold longer, one
at least until shortly after his master’s death and the other for the rest of his
life. Hereford, a zealous preacher, was condemned along with Repingdon
by Archbishop Courtenay in May 1382. Rather than bow to local ecclesiasti-
cal authority, as Repingdon would do, Hereford chose to travel to Rome to
appeal personally to Urban VI. He was immediately imprisoned, but man-
aged to escape somehow and return to England. There, he continued lead-
ing Lollards until 1391, when he was forced to recant in Nottingham. Ever
the zealot, he became a vigorous prosecutor of Wycliffism and continued
for the rest of his days to serve his new masters as enthusiastically as he had
Wyclif. Purvey, known as the librarian of Lollardy, was made to recant in
1401 and was given a benefice near Archbishop Arundel’s castle, where he
struggled to restrain himself from heresy for three years. Finally, he could
stand no more and returned to Lollardy for the rest of his life.26
The debates at Oxford shifted from intellectual duels to theological
combat following Wyclif ’s volte-face regarding the Eucharist. As we will
see in a later chapter, Wyclif ’s position evolved from orthodoxy to heresy.
In 1376, he had embraced transubstantiation, in which the bread and wine
wyclif’s life and work 23
become the true body and blood of Christ in substance while retaining the
physical properties of bread and wine, but he would come to reject this
as metaphysically impossible several years later. William Berton, a secular
scholar from Merton College and the new chancellor of Oxford, sensed
a shift in the political wind when the Crown attempted to mollify the
church after the Hauley-Shakyl incident. Likely hoping that this signaled
the end of Wyclif ’s political protection, he summoned a formal council of
twelve scholars—eight regular and four secular—to weigh the orthodoxy
of Wyclif ’s views on the Eucharist. Given Berton’s leeway in selecting the
members of the council, it is surprising that any of its members were dis-
posed to entertain the prospect of Wyclif ’s innocence, but four eventually
concluded that he was orthodox. The remaining eight (one apparently
abstained) were convinced that he was a heretic, and they published a list
of twelve conclusions that included the demand that Wyclif ’s teaching be
banned at Oxford. This document was formally promulgated by a public
reading, at which Wyclif was present. Having had no knowledge of the
chancellor’s actions, Wyclif was thunderstruck and responded, “Neither the
chancellor, nor any of his accomplices, can cast aspersions on what I say!”27
Rather than register an appeal in the approved academic courts, Wyclif
immediately asked John of Gaunt for help. Mindful of his responsibility,
the duke complied, advising his charge to be silent henceforth. Wyclif
was incapable of this and published a formal response on 10 May 1381, his
Confessio (see appendix). Here, he declaims his fidelity to the spirit of the
church fathers and doctors and accuses his opponents of sliding into inno-
vations that sully the sacrament and the church itself: “Woe to this genera-
tion of adulterers, who puts more belief in the testimony of an Innocent or
a Raymond than the sense of the gospel . . . who moulds the later church
in ways contrary to the earlier!”28 Blistering responses came from the
Franciscan John Tissington, the Augustinian Thomas Winterton, and sev-
eral Benedictines, but Wyclif seems to have ignored them. There is an anec-
dote from this period that could account for this. Wyclif, sick to the point of
death, is lying in bed, surrounded by friars intent on rescuing him from his
heresy. Wyclif rallies, rising up and crying, “I shall not die, but shall live and
declare the works of the Lord!”29 Whatever the state of Wyclif ’s health, this
was his last season at Oxford; he left for Lutterworth in the fateful summer
of 1381, when rebellion was in the air.
During this period, Wyclif was involved in the project for which pos-
terity remembers him best, the translation of the Bible from the Vulgate
24 john wyclif
Latin into English. By the fourteenth century, scripture was still largely
beyond the reach of English folk unable to read Latin. Several much earlier
Old English translations existed, ascribed to Alfred the Great, Bede, and
Aelfric, and there were French versions as well, one completed as recently
as 1355. Richard Rolle, the Yorkshire mystic, had translated the Psalms into
English earlier in the fourteenth century, and there were other translated
books and sections available in scattered locations, but no complete vernac-
ular scripture existed. As a young priest, Wyclif had likely been inspired by
Archbishop Thoresby’s translation of the catechism; by now, it had become
clear to him that this was not enough. The church’s present state demanded
a wide-scale return to the truths most clearly expressed in scripture itself, and
Wyclif determined that a translation project was the best means of achieving
that end.
It is easy to confuse this with what was to follow in the Reformation,
but Wyclif was not intent on a scriptura sola theology. As we shall see in a
later chapter, Wyclif ’s theology of scripture did not involve the idea that the
reader needed nothing but faith to read the Bible. Nor, in fact, was Wyclif
himself actively engaged in the actual translation. Scholarship indicates that
work on the Old and New Testaments was undertaken by John Purvey,
among others, at first in Oxford, then in Lutterworth and elsewhere, into
the 1390s. There are 250 manuscripts of the Wycliffite Bible that survive, of
which 21 contain the entirety of both testaments. This is the largest num-
ber of copies known for any medieval English text; in comparison, only 64
copies of Chaucer’s Canterbury Tales exist, none complete. Of these Bibles,
there appear to be two versions, one stiffly literal, the other more natural
and less Latinate. Tradition holds that Hereford was responsible for most
of the literal version, and Purvey for most of the latter, with Wyclif serving
as the inspiration and guide for one, if not both. More recent scholarship
suggests otherwise; the scope of this project and the variation in transla-
tion styles suggests a host of anonymous hands at work, thereby forestalling
attempts to trace individual personalities behind the translations.30
The summer of 1381 was a tumultuous one throughout southern En-
gland. Early June saw a popular rising against taxes in Essex, which spread
within a fortnight through Kent, Middlesex, Hertfordshire, Cambridgeshire,
Norfolk, and Suffolk to London. Its leaders, Wat Tyler and a vagrant priest
named John Ball, rallied a huge mob against injustices they perceived in
both secular and sacred rule, and for a brief period, both church and Crown
were in serious danger. Riots and burning in London and its outskirts led to
wyclif’s life and work 25
the capture and murder of Archbishop Simon Sudbury, among other nota-
bles. While the mob also burned John of Gaunt’s Savoy palace, the duke
himself was in Scotland, where he remained for a time. The weekend of
15–17 June saw similar violence throughout southern England, with crowds
hurling documents that provided legal structure to the feudal machinery
into bonfires. The young Richard II, in what would turn out to be the high-
point of his reign, managed to quell the rebellion outside London by sheer
force of his youthful character, and Tyler and Ball were hastily executed.
Thereafter, the revolt fizzled out, although its clamor echoed in the minds
of ecclesiastical and royal authorities for the next quarter-century. That so
much rage had been directed against the church, and that it had come to a
head so quickly, led many among the clergy to connect Wyclif ’s preaching
and writings to the uprising. Had Wyclif restricted his activities to Oxford,
these accusations would be easily dismissed, but his disciples were active in
the world outside of academe.
Wyclif’s disdain for the friars was founded on his anger that their orders
were defined by manmade sets of rules, but not on their dedication to a life
of apostolic purity. If we live the apostle’s life as imitators of the rule that
Jesus the man exemplified, he reasoned, we are but “Jesusans,” followers of
a man. If grace inspires us to a life in faithful service to God, which is likely
to result in a life of apostolic poverty, we are “Christians,” followers of the
Christ.31 To outward appearances, the results are the same, but Wyclif was
convinced that it was the mediation of another man’s interpretation of
scriptural truth that made monks or friars prone to error. Why rely on the
teaching of Francis, or Benedict, or Dominic when one can learn to read
scripture for oneself? The result was that Wyclif ’s disciples took on the cast
of a mendicant order of preachers whose mission was to bring scripture’s
truth to everyone. Preaching this truth involved exposing the present evils
of political ambition and greed afflicting the church hierarchy, which illus-
trated the divergence between scripture’s ideal and ecclesiastical reality.
Contemporary chronicles describe Wyclif ’s “poor preachers” wander-
ing the countryside in russet robes, enthusiastically fomenting discord in
an already disaffected populace. One chronicler, Thomas Walsingham, is
unequivocal in connecting these preachers with the revolt of June 1381,
decrying Wyclif ’s teachings as the cause of the fire and death of rebellion.
Scholars today are less likely to equate the two phenomena of Wyclif ’s
preachers and the rebellion, although many agree that some crossover was
likely. John Ball, the vagrant priest and rebel, claimed Wycliffite sympathies,
26 john wyclif
For as there are held in the bowels of the earth the air and spirit of
infection, and which escape by means of some earthquake, by means
of which the earth is purified not without great violence, so there were
previously buried in the hearts of the reprobate many heresies of which
the realm has been cleansed after their condemnation, but not without
travail and great effort.34
grew out of Wyclif ’s ideas in the fifteenth century. In England, the phenom-
enon of Lollardy, which evolved into a vehicle for vernacular theology and
political ideology, would come to be equated with treason during the reign
of Henry IV and would be the cause for the introduction of burning at the
stake into England in 1401. Despite this dire punishment, Lollardy lasted
into the sixteenth century in some quarters, although its ties to Protestant
Reform in England are tenuous at best. In Bohemia, Wycliffism catalyzed
the Czech nationalist movement and quickly became the framework on
which Hus and Jerome of Prague constructed their own reform movement.
Wycliffism came to Prague through academic connections that had arisen
from Richard II’s marriage to Anne of Bohemia, and the force of its philo-
sophical realism appealed to Czechs resentful of the moderni Germans who
exercised control at Charles University. Wycliffism soon became an ideol-
ogy for revolution and led to open conflict with the Holy Roman Empire.
Jan Hus, the gifted preacher and leader of the movement, explicitly denied
following Wyclif into any of his heretical positions regarding the Eucharist
or Donatism, but was nonetheless made to suffer and die at the Council of
Constance in 1415. The war that broke out shortly after Hus’s martyrdom
would tear apart Central Europe for decades to come. Wyclif ’s ideas were
known through early publication of Trialogus in 1525, but played no sig-
nificant role in Reformation thought. His place in history grew in import
as scholarship began to view the medieval as worthy of serious study in the
nineteenth century, with a series of nineteenth-century biographies endors-
ing a view of Wyclif as the “morning star of the Reformation.”
The work of the Wyclif Society, which flourished from the 1880s to
the 1920s, made Wyclif ’s Latin works available in then state-of-the-art
editions to libraries throughout the Anglophone world. His reputation
evolved during the twentieth century from a proto-Reformer to a philoso-
pher and theologian of his age as contemporary academics learned how to
read fourteenth-century thought. Recently, the earlier view of Wyclif as
an Augustinian “ultrarealist” braving a forlorn hope against the forces of
Ockhamism has been replaced by a nuanced understanding of philosophi-
cal theology in fourteenth-century Oxford. The great growth of interest
in late medieval English literature, both of Lollards and of more ortho-
dox writers, has sparked real interest in Wyclif ’s ideas as indicative of the
fourteenth-century English theological milieu, and Wyclif now seems able
to be understood as something more than heretic, or proto-Reformer, or
lone intellectual holdout facing the Ockhamist tide of change. Hume’s
wyclif’s life and work 31
In late August 1909, Charles Doolittle Walcott was prospecting for fossils
on the Burgess ridge in what is now Yoho National Park, in the Canadian
Rockies of British Columbia. He found a section of rock embedded in the
mountainside that contained the richest and strangest collection of fossils
ever discovered, which today we call the Burgess shale. Walcott struggled
to classify these tiny animals from the Middle Cambrian period, 530 million
years ago, because they just didn’t fit the expectations of early twentieth-
century paleontology. So he described them as he felt they should have been,
interpreting the fossil evidence to fit into the accepted scientific expectations
of what lived in the warm sea beds of the early Paleozoic era. In the 1970s,
when paleontologists at Cambridge recognized Walcott’s error, they began
to explore the fascinating possibilities of almost twenty unknown phyla.
Today, there are some thirty-two distinct phyla in the animal kingdom; the
Burgess shale shows us almost twenty directions that evolution could have
taken, but didn’t, thus giving paleontologists and evolutionary biologists a
tremendous opportunity to explore possibilities that would otherwise never
have been imagined.
Our understanding of the period in which Wyclif developed as a theo-
logian has changed in the same way that our understanding of the Burgess
shale has changed. What looked like a degenerate, inbred version of high
medieval theology to scholars as recently as the mid-twentieth century now
32
the oxford context of wyclif’s thought 33
Grosseteste. But this was not the case; among Ockham’s most active oppo-
nents at Oxford was Walter Chatton (d. 1343), a fellow Franciscan, while
Henry Harclay, Oxford’s chancellor during the latter part of Ockham’s stay
there, whose ontology was quite similar to Ockham’s, was a secular. Despite
the great impact that Scotus had in Paris, Scotism at Oxford was a paltry thing,
and Thomism was not the authoritative approach among Oxford Dominicans
that it might have been. The emphasis on science and logic that character-
ized Oxford thought led away from broad, all-encompassing metaphysical
approaches and tended to foster a more individualistic, analytic brand of
theology than the phrase “school of thought” might allow.
Adam Wodeham (d. 1358), Ockham’s student and friend, attacked the
arguments of his fellow Franciscan Walter Chatton with notable vigor.
Chatton had argued, as Wyclif would, that a return to the safety of theo-
logical tradition and scriptural foundation would best serve the needs of
the day.6 Wodeham argued against using natural reasoning to broaden our
understanding of the divine, rejecting Chatton’s attempts at natural theol-
ogy to emphasize this impossibility. While one scientific conclusion may
seem applicable in another field, it would be foolhardy to assume that this
holds across all science. We may presume that two diverse lines of argu-
ment lead to the same conclusion, as in the famous five ways that Aquinas
uses to demonstrate God’s existence, but “diverse sciences do not prove
formally the same conclusion through the same medium, unless by men-
dacity.”7 Scientific reasoning’s ability, for example, to construct arguments
demonstrating the existence of an infinite being may entice one to suppose
that it can demonstrate God’s existence, but the God it constructs is ulti-
mately nothing in comparison to the God of theology. There is no possibil-
ity of reason establishing the falsity of the apparently valid syllogism “this
thing is the Father; this same thing is the Son; therefore the Father is the
same as the Son,” for by Aristotle’s rules, the conclusion follows neatly from
the premises. “And thus unless through our faith it were known that one
thing is three things, we would believe firmly the aforesaid sophism to have
been well argued.”8
Further emphasizing the problems that come with trying to fit these theolo-
gians into neatly defined groups is the thought of the calculators, a group of
38 john wyclif
secular scholars at Oxford’s Merton College. Like Ockham and his follow-
ers, the calculators were philosophers with a keen interest in logical dispu-
tation and the complexities of mathematics and theoretical physics to which
they could lead. Being a calculator was certainly not the same as being an
Ockhamist. One of the foremost calculators, Thomas Bradwardine, vigor-
ously opposed Ockhamist theology. Disputations de sophismatibus were the
standard genre of argument in which undergraduate students learned to
engage one another in intellectual dispute in medieval universities. The
students used ambiguously worded sentences like “Socrates twice sees every
man besides Plato” to analyze how terms functioned within propositions.
In most cases, the analysis focused on syncategorematic terms, which lack
independent signification outside of their use in sentences. In the example,
the term “besides” has an ambiguous reference, and resolving the ambigu-
ity would involve addressing the larger question of how exceptive terms
function in the distribution of meaning within a proposition. While, at first
sight, sophismata may appear to be a recondite academic exercise, the pur-
pose of the genre was to sensitize students to the relation of language use
and reasoning by exploring the problems that come from assuming things
about meaning that have not been established. As is the case now with
courses in logic or programming, formulating texts whereby the rules for
this level of analysis could be established was a very specialized affair, and
the logicians at Merton College were tasked with this responsibility.
Merton College had been founded in 1264 and was reserved for those
studying for higher degrees. Both Scotus and Ockham had studied there,
and many of the foremost figures in fourteenth-century Oxford were asso-
ciated with the college. Here, a movement arose among the logical theorists
intent on regulating sophismata in which physics and theoretical mathe-
matics began to figure importantly. Take a proposition like “Socrates is
whiter than Plato begins to be white.” This sophisma, the first in Richard
Kilvington’s collection from the 1320s, tests the extent to which we can
understand a degree of a quality, whiteness, and its ratio to a lesser degree of
whiteness.9 Kilvington’s sentences, with their problems involving degrees
of quantity or quality, or traversing distances, find their resolution in logical
analyses of the terms, but as the genre developed, mathematical and physical
speculation became increasingly complex. Walter Burley, a Mertonian from
1305 to 1309, had investigated the physics of a substance beginning to be and
ceasing nonexistence in his quodlibetal question De primo et ultimo instanti,
and he introduced analyses of problems of natural philosophy into the
the oxford context of wyclif’s thought 39
at some point the rate of resistance will be greater than the rate of force.
The problem lies in the axiom of velocity being proportionate to the ratio
of force to resistance; as the rate of velocity decreases in proportion to the
increase of resistance, there will still be a rate of velocity assignable at the
point that resistance is greater than force. This would mean that there is
a measurable, albeit tiny, rate of velocity assignable to a stationary object.
Better, Bradwardine argued, to recognize that velocities vary arithmetically,
while the ratios of force to resistance vary geometrically.10
In the two decades that followed, the calculator tradition at Oxford
would flourish. Foremost among the calculators was William Heytesbury,
who would become chancellor of the university in 1370. Heytesbury’s inter-
est was in infinite divisibility and the nature of continua, and he was a pio-
neer in analyzing the logic of quantitative statements about heat and color.
His Regulae Solvendi Sophismata, one of the textbooks for undergraduates
that was the initial aim of the calculators, illustrates the reciprocity of logic
and mathematical physics that characterized the movement. In it, problems
of physics and mathematics are examined as logical constructs, with the
application of physical and mathematical principles mixed into the seman-
tical analysis. Another important figure, Richard Swineshead (pronounced
Swinnis-et), elevated the abstraction in the mathematical analysis of physi-
cal propositions to new levels of intricacy. His Liber calculationum considers
how to parse propositions concerning the measurement of the intensity or
absence of qualities. Does one understand a quality’s intensity by proximity
to the highest degree of a quality, or by distance from the absolute absence
of the quality? Further, is it possible to analyze the distribution of intensi-
ties of a quality across a given substance? What of the intensity of light?
And building on Bradwardine’s understanding of motion, if we consider
an object falling through the center of the earth, does the part of the object
that has already passed the center resist the descent of the parts that have
yet to reach the center? The practical, physical applicability of these ques-
tions is beside the point. Swineshead, like all of the calculators, was more
interested in the complexity of mathematical analysis that the logically
formulable problems demand.11 Leibniz would later praise Swineshead as
the individual who introduced mathematics into philosophy, and Robert
Burton, author of the encyclopedic Anatomy of Melancholy, described him
as exceeding the bounds of human genius, but later humanists would gen-
erally reject the calculator tradition as typifying the subtleties that had com-
plicated scholasticism to the point of irrelevance. From the standpoint of
the oxford context of wyclif’s thought 41
or to believe things to be true that are not true, then all that seems evi-
dent to human reason runs the risk of being dubitable. When discussing
the history of skepticism in Western thought, the usual course is to pro-
ceed from the academics of ancient Greece and Rome to the use of sys-
tematic doubt as the basis for modern thought in Descartes’ Meditations,
on the assumption that Christian dogmatism forbade its use in scholastic
thought, or that Aristotelian thought provided sufficient material to stave
off skeptical tendencies. The great figures in skepticism include Pyrrho,
Carneades, and Sextus Empiricus in antiquity, and Descartes, Bayle, and
Hume in early modernity. Augustine had rejected skepticism as a useful
philosophical method in Contra Academicos ( 386 ce) and had argued in De
Utiliate Credendi (392 ce) that, since few men were sufficiently wise as to
understand the truth, it is better to believe and avoid sin than to doubt
and risk damnation. And until the fourteenth century, skepticism had a
bad reputation; to accuse one’s opponent of having a position that led to
skepticism, as Scotus did to Henry of Ghent, was as good as rendering it
untenable.12 Etienne Gilson set the terms for twentieth-century consider-
ation of skepticism in scholastic thought by identifying it with Ockhamism,
describing Ockham’s thought as an apprentice sorcerer unleashing forces
that would overturn the classical scholasticism of the thirteenth century.
Because Ockham was ontologically a “nominalist,” it became the norm to
equate Ockham’s ontological approach with a skeptical distrust of natural
theology and a correspondent fideism.13 But the reality of later medieval
skepticism is much more complex. Not every fourteenth-century theolo-
gian with a healthy respect for the limits of human reasoning was a skeptic.
Still, burgeoning interest in the absolute power of God and its relation to
human knowledge, an important aspect of Ockham’s thought, led many
to explore the philosophical uses of epistemic skepticism.
For centuries, scholastic thinkers had Aristotelian reasoning as their
firm foundation, and by the end of the thirteenth century, theologians had
used syllogistic reasoning to articulate ideas of great subtlety about the
divine nature. In his Summa Logica III, 16, Ockham argued that great care
should be taken with the terms in an expository syllogism, the building
block of scholastic reasoning. It could not have as its subject a term that is
ambiguous in number. For instance, “homo est Socrates, homo est Plato,
ergo Socrates est Plato” may be true, and it may be false, depending on
how the term “man” refers. If the term stands for a singular thing, a man,
then the syllogism would prove that Socrates and Plato are two names for
the oxford context of wyclif’s thought 43
the same person. This is either the truth, or it is not. If the term stands for
a plural, then the conclusion would be impossible if Socrates and Plato are
two different people. So the ambiguity of the term “man” means that the
syllogism doesn’t really tell us anything. The subject of a syllogism must
be either recognizably singular or recognizably plural to prevent the syl-
logism from being useless. The problem for theology arises in discussing
God’s triune nature. “This essence is the Father, this essence is the Son,
therefore the Son is the Father” is useless as an expository syllogism because
of the ambiguity of the term “essence” when describing God. Does it refer
to one thing or to more than one? If essence describes one thing, then the
syllogism is saying something about the identity of the persons of the Son
and the Father within the essence. If it describes several things, then its
meaning is confusing: do the different persons themselves have essences?
Or is the syllogism just falsely conceived, since the faith holds that there
can only be one essence and several persons? The syllogism is not wrong
in itself; in Quodlibet III, q.3, Ockham explains that if we could enjoy the
vision that those in heaven have of God, the ambiguity of the term would
vanish and the syllogism would clearly and unequivocally describe the real-
ity we perceive. But the unbeliever, for whom the term “God” refers to a
fictional entity, will not recognize the truth of any syllogism in which there
is reasoning about the divine nature as something real. Ought we then to
conclude that philosophy is of no help whatever to theology? In Quodlibet V,
q.1, Ockham explains that delineating the way that terms in statements
refer, whereby he has established that a theological truth cannot be proven
scientifically, is itself a philosophical activity. Hence, philosophy is of tre-
mendous utility for the theological project. The result of this general line
of reasoning, though, is that theology is distinct from other sciences, and
philosophy, theology’s erstwhile handmaiden, becomes the de facto queen
of the sciences.
Peter Aureol (1280–1322), a contemporary of Ockham’s in Paris, had
warned strenuously against assuming that “whatever appears, exists” in his
analysis of human cognition, indicating that the appearances of things per-
ceived serve as the basis for our knowledge of things in the world. In the next
generation of Parisian theologians, Nicholas of Autrecourt (c. 1295–1369)
stunned his colleagues by arguing that, aside from the certainties of faith, all
that we have to rely on in our reasoning is the principle of noncontradiction.
This means that basic principles of cause and effect, and metaphysical fun-
damentals like “accidents require substances for their existence” are ruled
44 john wyclif
out as the bases for knowledge, because doubting them does not entail a
contradiction. While we may never have experienced an accident without
a substance, or smoke without fire, it would not involve a contradiction
of terms to imagine them, in the way that one imagines a square circle
or a married bachelor. This seriously endangers the certainties of science,
broadly understood to include all descriptions about the world around us.
Nicholas was famously censured at Avignon in 1346. Although his skepti-
cal tendencies do not amount to classical skepticism, they are indicative of
a tendency toward skeptical reasoning in fourteenth-century theology that
was quite active in Oxford.14
Some Oxford theologians were willing to question the tenets of causality
to test the extent to which we are capable of certain empirical knowledge,
even if only to sharpen their students’ wits. One, a Benedictine known only
as Monachus Niger, or the Black Monk, who wrote between 1337 and 1341,
suggested that we cannot know substances by natural knowledge:
[B]ecause then it could be known in the Sacrament of the Altar [i.e., the
Eucharist] when it would be bread there, and when not. From this it
follows that it is not pure philosophy to hold a substance to exist in the
nature of things. I prove this because nothing holds naturally unless the
knowing of it naturally comes, and the knowledge of substance cannot
come naturally, as demonstrated with the Sacrament of the Altar . . . so
there can be no experience had of a substance.
being does not exist. This is what Aston calls his “Achilles argument,” and
it is obviously based on an assumed real relation holding between true state-
ments and things. A skeptic holding that true statements only accidentally
reflect reality would never agree to this variation on Anselm’s famous argu-
ment from Proslogion 2–4, and a follower of Ockham, for whom the refer-
ence of terms within propositions is dependent upon the concepts we derive
from what we perceive, would reject Aston’s semantic realism. Further,
since God is the only necessary being, any true answer to the question “why
is this the way things are?” must find its basis in God’s being. This includes
every case of human willing, whether good or evil, although Aston shies
away from what he sees as an excessive determinism in Bradwardine. Because
his approach is semantically oriented, grounded in a propositional realism
in which true statements are made true by their correspondence to a prop-
ositionally structured truth in God’s being, it would be a mistake to call
Aston a skeptic. It is difficult to avoid the powerful skeptical overtones in
his description of the contingency of human understanding, though.
The case is similar for Robert Holcot (d. 1349), whose arguments are
easily interpreted as skeptical but are better understood in their theologi-
cal context. Holcot was a Dominican known both for his incisive logical
mind and his remarkable gifts as a preacher. He was active at Oxford from
1330, but by 1337 may have left to join Richard de Bury in Durham, where
we will see him in our discussion of the de Bury circle in chapter 3, on
Wyclif ’s realism. By 1342, he was active as a pastor in Salisbury, and later
in Northampton, where he died of plague. He was best known during the
centuries after his death for his remarkable Commentary on Wisdom, an
encyclopedic scripture commentary on the apocryphal Book of Wisdom,
which contains pastoral advice about the path of one’s life, just political rule,
married life, and many social issues. At present, this fascinating work is all
but forgotten; those few familiar with his thought today recognize him as
an important, original response to Ockham. In his Sentences commentary,
Holcot addressed the incompatibility of Aristotelian logic and the nature
of the Trinity typified by this syllogism: “the divine essence is the Father,
the divine essence is the Son, therefore the Father is the Son,” the premises
of which are true, which lead to a valid but false conclusion. While earlier
theologians had addressed this by qualifying how the divine essence “is” the
person, Holcot denied the validity of using a distinction to avoid the doc-
trinally problematic conclusion. This led him to decide that the demands of
the faith so contrasted with the rules of logic that there must be two systems
48 john wyclif
This is not fideism, for Holcot does not evoke an individual faith, but
the security and stability of ecclesiastical authority. Those entrusted with
this authority must hold more truths of the faith through belief than those
without it, because their duty is to understand and teach the faith. This
does not mean that a separate faith exists for the clergy—every statement
held true by scripture or the church must be conceded by every Catholic—
but that some of the relations of the truths of the faith are the concern of
the magisterium alone.
We are left, then, with a sampling of theologians who were writing when
the cohesive theological systematizing of figures like Thomas Aquinas
and Scotus was no longer an option. While theological problems like the
determinism–human freedom issue commanded great interest, the shift of
attention from primarily ontological issues to problems involving language
and logic made epistemology the field in which theological innovation was
necessary. Bradwardine’s De Causa Dei contains little that addresses the dif-
ficult questions of how we gain understanding and how we use it as a basis
for theological certainty. Those thinkers who do face down this problem are
haunted by the specter of skepticism, and, for Wyclif, their results seemed
inadequate to address theology’s needs. So his approach was to engage in
questions like “what is knowing?” “what is mind?” and “what is the basis
for theological science?” to shore up Bradwardine’s approach with reliable,
philosophical underpinnings.
Wyclif ’s Epistemology:
The Mind and the Eye
and are divisible into direct, reflective, and refractive subspecies, Wyclif is
deliberately papering over some very complex issues.25
In his discussion of how human intellectual faculties are deducible from
analyses of intuitive and abstractive cognition, John Rodington, O.F.M.
(d. 1348) had expressed an interest in the functioning of the eye, especially
in whether the visual power is located on the eye’s surface, as Bacon had
suggested, or inside the eye, in the optic nerve, as Scotus had thought.
Rodington pursued the matter carefully, comprehensively analyzing the
theories of vision available to fourteenth-century science. Wyclif ’s brief
account of the anatomy of the eye, describing the aqueous and vitreous
humors, the path of the optic nerves, the dura and pia mater protecting
the brain, and the connective web of veins and arteries that “bear life and
spirit from the heart, and nutrition from the liver” suggests familiarity with
Rodington’s interest in the connection of anatomy and perception. Medieval
scientists were not certain that the eye actively sends out rays of perception
(as Aristotle had suggested) that meet up with the species being emitted
by perceptible objects. Rodington struggled with this question. Alhazen
(Ibn al-Haitham c. 965–1039), the Persian scientist whose Kitâb al-Manâzir,
known to medievals as De Aspectibus or Perspectiva, was the primary source
for optics, thought that “extramission” was nonsense, as would the influ-
ential thirteenth-century Polish scientist Witelo, whose Liber Perspectivae
would be an important text for fourteenth-century Mertonians. Bacon and
Pecham advocated a combination of extramission and intromission, as did
Rodington. Wyclif, too, suggests that vision involves both the eye sending
something out to contact the object perceived and the eye’s reception of spe-
cies emitted by the perceived object.26
In Wyclif ’s Trialogus, a later work written for the instruction of the edu-
cated laity, he argues that an understanding of brain anatomy reveals the
different areas in which sense perception is interpreted into thought. In
the first ventricle, at the front of the brain, the sensus communis flourishes,
where sense data from all of the sense organs are sorted and interpreted
into a common sensory language that is interpreted by the higher powers.
Here also is where imagination is based, where we construct the illusory
stuff of dreams. The estimative and fantastic powers occupy the middle
ventricle, where we make judgments about the physical world and, like
other animals, “syllogize about particulars,” as when a fox stalks its prey.
In the rear ventricle, memory and locomotive power are located, “through
nerves in junctures in the back of the spine it is diverted to the other parts
the oxford context of wyclif’s thought 53
of the body.”27 Defects in the eye, such as cataracts or trauma to the eye or
optic nerve, cause distortion in the objects as they are perceived. Changes in
the media through which perception occurs bring about changes in percep-
tion itself, as when a torch, when waved in a rapid circular motion at night,
appears to be a ring of fire. Wyclif ’s gross anatomy of the brain is in keeping
with the understanding of his contemporaries; William Crathorn, whose
unique epistemology particularly incensed Wyclif, gives a similar account
in his Sentences commentary I, q.2, conclusion 4, although he uses cellula
where Wyclif uses ventricula.
Why does Wyclif wander into an anatomical explanation of the eye in
explaining knowledge? Wyclif ’s approach is to follow the lead of a Polish
theologian and scientist, Erazmo Witelo (c. 1230–c. 1300), whose thought
provides a ready source of heuristic devices throughout Wyclif ’s Latin
works. Witelo’s Perspectivae is a ten-volume analysis of the science of optics
as applied mathematics, and its impact on Western scientific thought was
remarkable. For centuries, scientific theorists would make considerable use
of Witelo’s approach in their own attempts to mathematize the understand-
ing of physical phenomena. Wyclif ’s Parisian contemporary Nicole Oresme
(1323–1382) made considerable use of it in his own scientific thought, as did
later theorists from Regiomontanus and da Vinci, Galileo and Tycho Brahe,
to Descartes. Kepler’s work Ad Vitellionem paralipomena (1604) marks the
end of Witelo’s tenure as a scientific authority. More recently, Witelo has
been interpreted as being an advocate of the theological light metaphysics
best articulated by Grosseteste in De Luce, but this is an overstatement;
his interest was in systematizing Alhazen, the great Persian optic theo-
rist, along the lines of Euclidean demonstration.28 Witelo was not a great
mathematician, although he was the first to introduce ideas of Eutochius
and Apollonius of Pergia into European thought, thanks to the translat-
ing work of his contemporary William of Moerbeke. His importance rests
in his systematic presentation and application of theory to applied math-
ematics; Perspectivae appears to have been a particularly important text for
Mertonian instruction. Wyclif ’s description of the eye in Logica Continuacio
is a precis of Witelo’s Perspectivae, book 3. His account of how the species
follows a perpendicular line from the object to a point in the core of the eye
is that of Witelo, who describes very carefully the function of the aqueous
and vitreous humors in the act of perception. Hence, for Wyclif as for other
Oxford theorists, optics provided a useful means of modeling and analyz-
ing our understanding of ideas. But what is involved in knowing ideas?
54 john wyclif
Early in his career, Wyclif addressed the nature of the mental act of know-
ing in De Actibus Anime. He devotes a large portion of the treatise to refut-
ing the position of an unnamed predecessor who believed that mental acts
are absolute things capable of per se existence, the way bodies are. Instead,
Wyclif argues that the acts of the mind are accidents of the genus action, and
not beings distinct from the mind that forms them. The usual assumption
that Wyclif is addressing Ockham or his followers is groundless, because
neither Ockham nor most of the philosophers who wrote in response to
him thought of mental acts as really different from the mind.
Ockham’s innovation was to dismiss the need for species in the act of
understanding. Earlier epistemic models, like that of Aquinas, held that we
arrive at judgments about extramental objects through an involved process.
First, our senses take in the perceptible appearance of some object that is
transmitted from the object through the air and received in the senses as
“sensible species.” Next, another part of the cognitive apparatus takes these
raw sensible species and turns them into mentally encoded “phantasms,”
which become the mental image of the object perceived when cognized
by the mind. The mind does not yet recognize the object of which it has
a mental image, though; the understanding is simultaneously abstracting
from the raw sensible species a higher, more comprehensive form of the
object perceived by the senses, which Aquinas calls the “intelligible spe-
cies.” This intelligible species is what Aquinas believes to be the univer-
sal, which is converted into a concept, and it is this concept that is used to
interpret the mental image. None of these beings by which we comprehend
extramental objects, these species or phantasms, can exist on their own; each
is an act of the mind the purpose of which is to facilitate understanding.
Ockham rejected the existence of species in our act of understanding some-
thing extramental, in part because of doubts he had about the reliability
of the species’ representation of their object. Instead, we directly perceive
the object through “intuitive cognition,” from which the understanding
abstracts in a distinct action called “abstractive cognition.”
At an early point in his career, Ockham was willing to concede that
the product of abstractive cognition, namely, a concept, might have a kind
of being of its own. This being, which he called “objective being” and
which today’s philosophers might call “intentional being,” is but a ghost
the oxford context of wyclif’s thought 55
Few or none would disagree that there are acts of the soul. Nobody doubts
that at some time [the soul] can sense, understand, wish or eschew, and
other particular acts. And it is impossible thus to have one’s self, unless
there were a being indicating itself to be in this way; therefore such a
being is recognized as such.32
After a little unpacking of the language, the sense of the last sentence
should be familiar. Even if one doubts that there are acts of the soul, one
cannot doubt that there is something there doing the doubting. This truth,
generally connected with the Meditations of Descartes, was well known by
the scholastics and had been mentioned by Augustine in De Civitate Dei
11.26 and De Trinitate XI. Scotus and Henry of Ghent made reference to
it in arguing against skepticism, while Nicholas of Autrecourt argued that
it did not provide sufficient epistemic certainty. In the 1330s, Fitzralph
referred to it as reliable evidence that some things can be known with cer-
tainty, and Crathorn did as well: “If someone doubts a proposition like this
one, ‘I exist,’ it follows that he exists, because this follows: ‘I doubt that
I exist; therefore, I exist.’ For anyone who does not exist does not doubt.
Therefore no one can doubt this proposition: ‘I exist.’ ”33
Wyclif includes another approach among his arguments for mental acts
as qualities. Acts of the mind, he begins, have attributes that no thing exist-
ing on its own could have, which means that they would have to be acci-
dents, beings reliant on the existence of another. Imagine assuming that
the statement “every man understands himself to be a non-understanding
being” is true. Call the statement A. It is possible to imagine assuming this,
the oxford context of wyclif’s thought 57
In the questions of what knowledge involves, and what the act of knowing
is, Wyclif ’s approach is to turn to logic to clear up problems that threaten
to swamp the project of theology. Wyclif ’s conception of what knowledge
involves will influence his argument that theology, which involves faith,
counts as a science. His discussion in Logice Continuacio is part of a larger
analysis of the kinds of terms that need special treatment when parsing the
meaning of propositions. The assertion of knowing, or of doubt, within a
proposition points to the nature of knowledge itself. If we have knowledge,
we have something present to us the certainty of which can be measured.
If what we know is certain because anytime we test it, it turns out to be the
truth, we have knowledge of a universally holding statement. Knowing
that “every fire is hot” is an example of this kind of knowing. Knowing a
first principle is even more certain. Once every part of such a statement is
understood, the truth of the statement is given. Knowing that “nothing at
once is and is not” is like this, since its truth is evident from the very nature
of the terms. Finally, knowing a deductively clear truth is the best sort of
knowing, Wyclif argues, because such a truth tells us more about the world
than the first two. Such a truth, which arises from the conjoining of two
simpler statements in syllogistic reasoning, is the basis for deductive science.
Here, Wyclif has deductive systems like Euclidean geometry in mind.
But there are more kinds of knowledge than these. Acts of knowing
either proceed from these habitually present things known, or they pro-
ceed from what is evident to the senses, or from evidence of what could
be perceived, if the knower were locally or temporally situated. That is, I
might recognize a triangle that I happen upon in architecture or in a paint-
ing as being a right triangle, and so know both from what is evident to
my senses and from what I have in my head about right triangles. Or
I might know that Paris is a beautiful city, even though I’ve never been there.
Actual knowing, Wyclif explains, is ultimately belief in the truth of some-
thing, without fear of the contrary being true. My actual knowing might
be either of a universal, as in knowing what “humanity” is, or it might
be of a particular person. Knowing the universal allows me to recognize
the particular. Knowing that this recognition is a dependable result, in that
I will usually recognize people to be human beings, given my knowledge of
humanity, allows me to know with a general certainty that when I meet the
the oxford context of wyclif’s thought 59
next person, I’ll recognize her as being a person. But an element of doubt
has crept in. There is always the possibility that I might not recognize the
next person I meet as a human being, so I can’t say with certainty that
I know that I will recognize her.
Actual knowing, which always includes belief, functions on a par with
habitual knowing, the term Wyclif uses for the first kind of more certain
knowing. If yesterday I saw the pope standing before me, I knew him to be
alive at that time, but because I do not now see him, my knowledge of him
being alive involves belief that nothing has since happened to him. Strictly
speaking, my knowledge about him now is not really knowing: it is believ-
ing that counts as knowing. Now, when I saw him standing before me yes-
terday, there was certainly a degree of belief involved. I believed my senses,
and I believed that the man before me was indeed the person he presented
himself as being. But now, belief is more of an issue, because while certainty
that the pope still lives is high, it is not absolute.
Ordinarily, people don’t make this kind of distinction. We don’t usu-
ally measure what we know based on the percentage of slippage caused by
the possibility of doubt: “So the laity, who do not doubt or argue about the
media that verify the thing believed, frequently know, while the literate,
and especially the philosophers, are ignorant.”35 Philosophers can easily let
this need for belief lead to problems with skepticism. The right approach
to measuring knowing, Wyclif argues, is not to wander in skeptical specu-
lation, but to focus attention on how the language we use about knowing
shows what is present to our minds. At a very basic level, a proposition Fx
either signifies (a) that you know that there is a given proposition, Fx, or
(b) that you know that the proposition Fx signifies a state of affairs about
x and F, or (c) that the proposed state of affairs Fx is the truth. Without speci-
fying which way of signifying we have in mind, Fx is something that can
be both known and not known at the same time. We can know Fx in the
first and the second senses, without knowing whether Fx is really true, in
the third sense.
Imagine that you are told that you know a sentence A. Sentence A could
be one of two sentences: “God exists” or “a man is an ass.” Now we know
at the outset that the first is necessarily true, while the second is impossible.
Still, you must admit to the truth of knowing the sentence A, with A’s con-
tent being indeterminate. If by indeterminate, we mean “either of the two”
(altera istorum), all is well. Even if A most likely stands for the impossible
proposition, there is always the chance, since “either of the two” admits
60 john wyclif
of both, that the other, necessary sentence is what A stands for. But if by
indeterminate, we mean “only one of the two” ( alterum istorum), then of
course there will be a problem, because the leeway that “either of the two”
provides is gone. You commit yourself to either knowing that something is
necessarily true, or knowing something that you cannot know. “Either of
the two” provides a middle ground, while “only one of the two” does not.
The point of this example is to show that how we conceive of the names
of the things that are given in a proposition that we claim to know has
everything to do with whether we really know what we think we know.
By now, the grounds for Wyclif ’s argument that theology should indeed
be counted among the sciences are clear. He has argued that all knowledge
outside of the limited sphere of habitual knowledge of indubitable truths,
first principles, and deductively certain conclusions involves an element of
belief. Given that belief is the foundation for theological reasoning as well,
it follows that theology is a science like any other. Wyclif makes the case
for this in De Trinitate, a treatise included in the Summa de Ente, which
he appears to have written around 1370. Despite its title, which suggests
Augustine’s magisterial work on the Trinity, De Trinitate focuses on sev-
eral particular problems that had become set pieces for theologians in the
mid-fourteenth century. The complexity of the reasoning that had evolved
from theologians’ commentaries on book I of Peter Lombard’s Sentences
had become breathtaking.
If God the Father (G[f ]) generates God the Son (G[s]), meaning that
God generates God, God would have to be distinct from God insofar as
the Son and the Father differ. Otherwise, insofar as G(f ) is not the same
as G(s), then God is not God. One way of interpreting this would be to say
that “God is different from God.” This could mean that God is not the
same as G(f ), G(s), and G(hg), which would mean that the Trinity is other
than God. Or if G(f ) is not the same as G(s), then God the Trinity differs
from G(insert a person here). If God is not the same as God, then the differ-
ence either lies in number within God, or somehow outside of God, with a
distinct God. The former, that there is a difference in number within God,
the oxford context of wyclif’s thought 61
In predication according to essence the singular and its universal are dis-
tinct, since the singular is one, as the universal another individual. It
does not follow, “these are distinct things, so to these we assign number”
because through most general and most singular demonstrating of its
supposit, any things distinct are these, yet they are not held numerable,
since one of them remains. Thus they are distinct formally, but not for-
mally distinct things. Nor are they formally “these two” [indicating this
universal and this singular] but they are this, and so the differences are to
this sense, that these differ, but not through numerical difference; because
only by difference formally or according to reason are they “these.”36
divine truths woven into creation, but in each case the faith must serve as
foundation. “This is generally said,” Wyclif continues, “that no one can
assent to this deduction [of the threefold divine nature from perceived
created trinities] without faith, and so it is not merely natural, and is not
demonstrated in the natural light.”41 But if faith is the foundation, is dem-
onstration through natural reasoning impossible? All reasoning demands
some sort of nonrational assent, Wyclif argues, either before or outside
of the reasoning process, to conditions that serve as evidence for the rea-
soning to take place. Learning to read or to speak requires a degree of
faith in the teacher. The absence of the light of faith infused in the mind
allows one to give assent to many ideas, but in each case, the mind craves
evidence of some kind. The testimony of authority counts as such even in
matters otherwise neutral, so assent can be given in these matters from
the authority of scripture or teaching that will be, in light of divine reality,
rationally clear to all.
Later in his life, Wyclif made a similar argument in Trialogus, where
his foil, Pseustis, argues a simplified version of the Ockhamist position.
His champion, Phronesis, responds:
Their position was that every act of understanding entails the divine illu-
mination of the mind, a participation in the light of Truth every time we
apprehend the truth. Aquinas and Scotus limited the need for this illu-
mination to the sphere of revelation, arguing that the unassisted human
reason is capable of accurately perceiving the truth about things in this
world without the need of divine assistance. Faith factors into this question
when truths understood by pagans such as Aristotle must be explained;
Aristotle lacked the Christian faith, yet reasoned out the truth of things in
the world. This led Aquinas to conclude that one could not have faith and
knowledge about the same thing. Faith requires assent without evidence,
while knowledge entails having that evidence. Henry of Ghent (d. 1293)
is the last widely studied philosopher to have argued the need for divine
illumination before Nicholas of Cusa in the fifteenth century. By the shape
of Wyclif ’s arguments here, it is difficult to avoid concluding that he fol-
lowed Henry, Bonaventure, and Grosseteste in arguing the need for divine
illumination. “For it is impossible for a creature to know anything unless
it knows it through grounding from the authority of God teaching and
moving to assent.”43
All that we understand, then, requires some faithful assent of the human
mind, some acquiescence to evidence that might be doubted. In the case of
understanding objects we perceive, our intuition of sense data entails faith,
which kindles the growth of knowledge as our experiences increase and
leads to acts of judgment about the world. Faith has a natural place in all
of our acts of understanding, great and small, and if we can claim to have
an accurate explanation for even the least act of understanding the simplest
thing, we should also admit to the possibility that great truths of faith, like
the Trinity, may be explored and understood by human reason. If the arti-
cles of faith were demonstrable scientifically, philosophers would already
have done so, without the need for revelation. But the articles of faith are
subtle, hidden from natural light. The merit that comes from faith consists
in voluntarily and humbly submitting the sensibility to the authority of the
Catholic church and the articles of faith, against which rebellion is a sin. So
to view faith and reason as incompatible is premature. Faith is at once an
act of believing, a habit, an assent to a truth; since what is known is believed
as well, faith and knowing are not really incompatible.
3
wyclif in oxford
Logic, Metaphysics
Two English thinkers define later medieval Oxford philosophy and the-
ology: Robert Grosseteste (1170–1273) and William Ockham (1287–1347).
Each attracted students who would further their intellectual vision and
profoundly influenced thought in fourteenth-century Oxford. It would
be premature to view their differing approaches as inherently antitheti-
cal to one another, though. Both were willing to countenance Aristotelian
thought as the basis for understanding the created universe, and both have
been described as philosophical mathematizers, in reference to their inter-
est in taking an analytical approach to problems. The differences between
them lie more in how they thought Aristotle’s philosophy could articulate
the traditional Augustinian Christian ideal.1
A handy means of distinguishing them is their answer to the question
of what there is in the universe. Do individual members of a species have
their special identities through their relations to an unchanging universal,
or are individuals of a species related to one another without reference to
an additional universal? That is, is there a universal “dog” by virtue of
which all animals that have a canine nature are defined, or are all canine
animals members of the species dog without reference to some immutable,
65
66 john wyclif
Of the many important thinkers who figured in the theological and scien-
tific debates at Oxford between 1315 and 1349, several tower over the rest.
Not by coincidence, these theologians also play an important role in Wyclif ’s
thought. Walter Burley, Thomas Bradwardine, and Richard Fitzralph are
each mentioned by Wyclif as authoritative in the arguments that underlie
his own theological vision: Burley in metaphysics, Bradwardine in formal
theology, and Fitzralph in his theory of dominion. Robert Holcot’s name, on
the other hand, does not appear in Wyclif ’s works, but his presence looms
68 john wyclif
Bury’s words suggest that Oxford scholars saw their university as the
new Athens, where the rich heritage of classical antiquity, notably the works
of Aristotle, could enrich Christian doctrine and discourse. The members of
Bury’s circle of scholars included most of the important Oxonians of the mid-
dle decades of the fourteenth century: in addition to Burley, Bradwardine,
Fitzralph, and Holcot, Bury included a number of other scientists and theo-
logians, including Richard Kilvington and Walter Chatton, in his entou-
rage. Scholars continue to suspect that the long-standing view that Holcot
helped in the writing of Philobiblon is the truth, suggesting a general under-
standing among the theology faculty that Oxford had established itself as
a worthy successor to the academic mantle that Paris claimed. The ideal
of recovering the riches of classical antiquity for the benefits of contempo-
rary society, which is usually associated with Renaissance humanism, is very
much in evidence in the writings of Bury’s circle, suggesting that only the
horrors of the plague staved off a humanist florescence at Oxford.4
Walter Burley was renowned at both Oxford and Paris as a logician, phi-
losopher, and theologian, and in his early years at Merton College, he was
likely to have been a student of Scotus and a contemporary of Ockham.
When Burley had moved to Paris to lecture on the Sentences in 1318,
Ockham was teaching his austere ontology at Oxford. The two seem to have
been well acquainted by this point. Burley energetically opposed Ockham’s
logic and metaphysics, and Ockham made use of Burley’s thought both
to formulate his own philosophy and to respond to Burley’s challenges.
The cliché that Ockham’s logical and semantic analytic approach neces-
sarily entails a rejection of metaphysical realism is undone with a reading
of Burley’s philosophy. He was an important innovator in several logical
genres, including the theory of the logical disputations called obligationes,
the theory of reference called supposition theory, and other questions in the
semantic analysis of the language of written terms and concepts. While his
ontology rates as the most realist regarding the existence of universals, his
understanding of the importance of linguistic and logical analysis of how
terms function in arguments rivals Ockham’s. The realists who were to
follow at Oxford throughout the fourteenth century were heavily indebted
70 john wyclif
gives Socrates his individual identity, but since there are differences in his
various parts, in that his bones are different from his muscles, there must be
forms by which parts of the matter of Socrates are differentiated into mus-
cle and other parts into bone. Thus far, Burley’s account is similar to that
of Aquinas described above, in that one substantial form gives identity to a
substance, while lesser forms coexist within it. Burley’s departure lies in his
assertion that there are other general forms or natures in a given substance
that can be shared with other substances, forms like humanity and ani-
mality, substantiality and rationality. Earlier, he had argued that these are
component parts of a substance, but his later position was to rule out these
general forms being constitutive of an individual. This does not mean that
humanity is not part of the makeup of Socrates. When we cognize Socrates,
our intellective soul actualizes the potential of the universal humanity that
is naturally present to it as an organizing force, which makes the universal
essential to Socrates, but not actively constitutive of his being. The intellec-
tive soul relies on these universals, making them quidditative parts, but this
reliance does not make them component parts of Socrates.
These universals do not exist apart from the individuals to which they
give identity, but their identity is not the same kind as the identity that they
give. “This name ‘man’ signifies a thing outside the soul yet this thing is not
one in number, but one according to species, nor is every thing outside the
soul one thing in number.”8 Burley calls the identity of a universal “specific
or generic identity,” while the identity of a substance is “numerical iden-
tity.” Beings with specific or generic identity are not limited by the rule
that a thing cannot be two places at the same time, simply because they do
not have the numerical identity that would make this rule apply. Burley is
not simply using an invented identity distinction to define universals into
existence. He is following Aristotle’s division of the categories of being,
where a secondary substance is described as being different from a primary
substance. A primary substance is something that can exist on its own, with
its own essence, capable of accidents or properties, while a secondary sub-
stance is dependent on individual primary substances for their own exis-
tence. Burley understands Aristotle as describing secondary substances as
universal types, of which primary substances are the individual tokens. The
identity of the individual depends on the universal, but the being of the
type rests on the being of the tokens.
This is the strongest sort of realism about universals that there was in
fourteenth-century Aristotelian metaphysics, but Burley appears to have
74 john wyclif
emerged as the benchmark for realism only in the 1360s. Most in Oxford
recognized Adam Wodeham as the chief exponent of Ockhamism, and it
would be logical to expect him to have argued energetically against Burley.
But Wodeham rarely mentions him, leading William Courtenay to sus-
pect that Walter Chatton’s realism was more widely discussed at the time.9
Chatton was vigorously attacked by Wodeham for espousing an ontol-
ogy similar to Burley’s around 1330, long after Burley had left Oxford.
By the time Burley was in Bury’s circle in Durham, he would likely have
been familiar with Wodeham’s arguments. It was during this period that
he wrote the Commentaries on Porphyry and Aristotle that express most
fully his belief that universals have real being apart from particulars. In the
meantime, Chatton was in the company of Walsingham, Ralph Pigaz, and
Kilvington, although none of these were to present as forceful and extended
an argument for realism as Burley did. By the 1340s, Richard Kilvington
had joined Bury in Durham, Walter Chatton had moved to Avignon, and
we have no evidence for Ralph Pigaz beyond 1329.
William Crathorn
matter demands being clear about what singular and universal terms are.
Aristotle had said in Physics that universals are the place where we begin
with our understanding of things in the world. Crathorn explains that there
are five ways that a universal term may be understood. First, the term may
refer to something having causal power over all or many things, as God has
over creation, or as a heavenly body has over beings inferior to it. Another
way something is said to be universal is through its perfection, as God is
perfect in anything that can be said of him, and each thing that can be said
is equivalent to all the rest within the unity of God’s perfection. Then again,
universality can be predicated of something similar to many other things. A
fourth way is when something represents other things either naturally, as
with smoke signifying combustion, or artificially, as when a given word,
like “dog,” stands for anything canine. Finally, Crathorn concludes by say-
ing that something could be universal according to essence or existence, “in
the way that Aristotle explains about what Plato believed to be universal.”
In this brief catalog of the uses of the term “universal,” Crathorn dis-
plays a decidedly Ockhamist position: there are no real, extramental, uni-
versal entities listed, nor is there room for the introduction of concepts that
naturally signify natures or essences having universal identity. Things are
similar to one another, and words stand for concepts and things by human
convention. A thing may naturally stand for another thing all of the time,
as with the relation of smoke and fire, but by no means are we to think
that there is some supervening universal relation involved. His final com-
ment about what Aristotle attributes to Plato intimates that he understands
Aristotle effectively to have refuted Plato’s ontology. In short, the only thing
that is universal is a term, which may be mental or written. It is important
to ask where Crathorn came up with his list of variant uses of the term
universal, though; his arrangement is by no means novel. His listing sug-
gests familiarity with the kinds of universal truths that Grosseteste lists in
his Commentary on the Posterior Analytics. Wyclif may have had Crathorn’s
list in mind in his recounting of Grosseteste’s list in De Universalibus 2, since
he comments that all of the respectable authors he can recall having read
understand Aristotle only to have argued against the divine ideas being
included among the universals.
Crathorn figured in the previous chapter as having advocated the odd
position that, since there are no mental acts, when we know something like
a white cat, we have a white feline-ness in our minds. In eliminating men-
tal acts and formulating the outlandish idea that our minds take on the
76 john wyclif
arguing for universals outside the mind, with attention to the propositional
structure of language, while others, like Ockham, have been described as
rejecting extramental universals as extraneous to a more simplified ontol-
ogy of things and accidents. In both cases, the positions represent ontological
extremes without much attention to the logical and epistemological com-
plexity that was the hallmark of fourteenth-century philosophical debate.
Some attention to that complexity will help us to understand why Wyclif
took the position that he did.
Adam Wodeham’s Sentences commentary provides a convenient start-
ing point for our exploration of the relation of logic and epistemology to
ontology. Wodeham enjoyed great prominence at Oxford as Ockham’s
foremost disciple, and was active there from 1322 to his death in 1358,
except for a short stay in Norwich in the mid-1320s and a trip to Basel in
1339. Lombard’s Sentences begins with Augustine’s dictum that all teaching
is either of things, or of signs.12 Wodeham takes this opportunity to contrast
the approaches of two of his senior colleagues, Walter Chatton and William
Ockham. Chatton, he explains, had argued that the objects of scientific
knowledge are things outside the mind, which are mind-independent
realities that we translate into the terms that make up mental propositions.
Ockham, on the other hand, held that the object of knowing is the men-
tal proposition we formulate about the things we perceive. Both views are
admissible, Wodeham admits, but taken separately, each falls short.
On the face of it, Chatton and Ockham may not appear to be in too much
disagreement. Chatton holds that we understand things outside the mind,
make judgments about them, and translate that understanding into mental
propositions, while Ockham argues that we perceive things outside the mind
and immediately translate those perceptions into mental propositions, which
are what we understand and about which we make judgments. Either way,
our understanding tracks directly onto extramental reality and is naturally
structured in our minds according to the propositional structure of subjects
and predicates. But Chatton’s position dispenses with the mediation of prop-
ositions, while Ockham’s emphasizes this. Chatton argued:
Assent to a proposition itself necessarily presupposes assent to the thing
signified by the proposition, because I assent that “thus it is in reality
as is signified by the proposition” before I assent that the proposition is
true. Hence the first assent which the intellect has in forming the propo-
sition does not have the proposition itself for an object but [instead] the
thing or things signified by means of [the proposition].13
78 john wyclif
Ockham, on the other hand, argued that the first assent our intellect
gives in an act of knowledge is to a proposition naturally formed about
what we perceive:
Chatton’s was only one voice among the many critics of Ockham’s
approach in fourteenth-century Oxford, but his was a critical one because
it led to Wodeham’s idea that, in making judgments about things in the
world, we take more into consideration than the bare particulars under
discussion. Wodeham agreed with Chatton that we make judgments about
the perceived thing, and not about the mental proposition we form about
it. Science is not about sentences, after all, but about things. But scientific
knowledge involves time-relative truths that are glossed over by Chatton’s
approach. If all that is needed is a thing to serve as a statement’s reference,
then so long as there is an angel, the statements “there was an angel” or
“there will be an angel” are not just true, but functionally identical. This
seems wrong. Hence, Wodeham argued that our knowledge is not just
about bare particulars, things in themselves, but about how things are in
the world. Wodeham calls this thing known quoddam significabile per com-
plexum, something signifiable through a complex (proposition), or a com-
plexly significable. What Wodeham believes that we understand and make
judgments about is how things are in the world when the world conforms
to the mode of signifying that is characteristic of the proposition formed by
the mind. That is, Wodeham’s complexly significable theory proposition-
alizes the world. Put another way, complexly significables are “modes of
things rather than things, answers to questions about how things are rather
than what they are.”15
In 1918, Bertrand Russell gave a series of lectures entitled “The Philos-
ophy of Logical Atomism” in which he argued that true statements describe
facts, but that facts are not particular things in the world. While facts are a
part of the natural world, they are not real things apart from, or in addition
to, the objects to which they refer. They arise from objects in the world as we
make statements about the world. We use symbols, words, numbers, and so
wyclif in oxford 79
value? Another problem would be, how can a thing “say itself ” if it has no
language, or no mouth? Another problem would be, what is the relation
between the being of a thing and the being of the proposition that it “says”?
Are they the same? How can there be anything “propositional” in the being
of a stone lying on the ground? There may be a propositional structure to
my recognition of the stone lying on the ground, but why should that sug-
gest anything about the being of the stone?
Wyclif begins explaining this seemingly bizarre assertion by distin-
guishing between natural and artificial signification:
Philosophy of Being
Wyclif ’s Summa de Ente, which he wrote between 1365 and 1372, contains
many of the treatises that articulate his metaphysics. Our understanding
of fourteenth-century philosophy can easily be colored by the interests of
past historians of thought. The primacy of universals over particulars in
Wyclif ’s thought has led to extended focus on his realism, and the relatively
recent (1985) edition and translation of the Tractatus de Universalibus has
kept scholarly attention squarely on the role that universals play in his phil-
osophical program. But even though he rashly exclaims that error about
universals is at the base of all that is wrong in society, realism about univer-
sals is only one aspect of his metaphysics.22 The Summa de Ente is made up
of two books, the first (I) with seven treatises about being and how it relates
wyclif in oxford 83
to man, and the second (II) with six concerning formal theology (the divine
nature, its attributes, divine ideas, and the Trinity). The fifth treatises in
each of the two books (I.5 and II.5) appear to relate to one another from
the standpoint of the other. In the first book, concerning being and how we
can understand it, I.5 is De Universalibus, while in the second, concerning
the divine being, II.5 is De Ydeis, which explores the philosophical possi-
bilities of how God’s ideas relate to one another and to things in creation.
Taken together, I.5 and II.5 might provide a useful means of moving back
and forth between the metaphysics of created being and the metaphysics
of divine being. Given the depth and breadth of the subject matter of the
Summa de Ente, what follows will do little more than suggest the philosoph-
ical richness of Wyclif ’s metaphysics, which deserves much further study.
Aristotle begins Physics by explaining that scientific knowledge about
anything involves, first, gaining acquaintance with the more general, and
then moving in analysis toward the particular. When considering any class
of beings, we begin by asking whether the principle or element that ulti-
mately constitutes it is one or many. Since everything that we might con-
sider would fall under the category “being,” Aristotle explores whether
Parmenides was right to hold that it is one or more than one, and points
out the many problems consequent for the scientist involved in taking
Parmenides seriously. Wyclif comments that Aristotle has made “being”
and “what is” interchangeable in this, and concludes that it would be con-
tradictory, then, for someone “actually or habitudinally to know something
to be, unless he cognizes proportionately Being to be.”23
In one sense, this is consonant with the linguistic approach that has
defined twentieth-century Anglo-American philosophy. When we say
something about a subject, like “the apple is red,” we are really saying two
things: first, there is such a thing as the apple, and, second, it is red. There
is an “existential predication,” or an existence claim, inherent in any state-
ment we make about something, whether true, false, or ambiguous.24 But
in another sense, to claim that there is a correlative “being,” in which the
subject that has been identified as existing participates, is something else
entirely. Most philosophers, at least since Kant, reject the idea that exis-
tence is a property that a thing can or cannot have. Nor can it fairly be said
that Aristotle himself believed there to be such a thing as “being” really or
possibly distinct from individual beings.
Aquinas’s description of the two possible concepts of being is a good place
to begin. At a very basic cognitive level, he says, “what comes first to our
84 john wyclif
On Being in Common
Wyclif does not really expect us to believe that nonhuman animals think
about being. First, he admits that this would suggest that they might also
love God, and so turn away from loving God and thus sin. Probably their
idea of something general is nothing at all like our idea of the transcen-
dent. After all, they don’t have a language. But then, neither are the ideas
of the moderni about general things anything like Wyclif ’s conception of
the transcendent; they reject transcendentals and lay all their metaphysical
explanations on individual things and terms about them. So, the doctors of
signs would attribute to human beings no higher a level of comprehension
of truth than is available to beasts. Here is the real point of Wyclif ’s intro-
duction of nonhuman judgment: given that animals make decisions with-
out understanding transcendental truths, and given that his opponents hold
that there are no such truths available to metaphysicians, it follows in his
eyes that his opponents make us into nothing more than animals that have
a language. We would have no knowledge whatever of the eternal, if all
of our knowledge was composed of terms about things in the world. If the
first truth is the cause of knowing what is true, and if we are able to reason
back to this, as Aristotle has suggested, it must be that we are able to use
our words to refer to the transcendental reality of the existence of being.
We are able to sort how we perceive things from how things are by rec-
ognizing that our perceptions of individual, material things lead us to recog-
nize universals, which have ontological priority to the things we perceive. It
does not follow that, because our perceptions of things precedes our recog-
nizing general truths, these general truths only have their bases in individual
things. Our fallen nature keeps us from seeing things as they are in the natu-
ral order, causing a division between the order of knowing, which is ascend-
ing, and the order of being, which is descending. In our analysis of Wyclif ’s
conception of the relation of God’s knowledge of our actions and the free-
dom of our will, this will be particularly important. Here, everything rests
on the distinction between the hypothetical necessity of God’s knowledge
and the freedom with which we will and act. It will appear that God’s neces-
sary knowledge of what we do is dependent upon our willing and acting,
which preserves human freedom, but this is only the result of our inability to
reconcile the order of knowing with the order of being. Wyclif ’s condemna-
tion for a fatalistic determinism rested, in his view at least, on a confusion
between the two orders. This will occupy our attention in chapter 6.
Those who would hold that Aristotle meant for us to suppose that a prop-
osition like “man is an animal” is about terms that refer only to individual
wyclif in oxford 87
beings, men, need to reconsider to what the embedded proposition “man is”
refers. Any singular man, the referent of this embedded proposition, is in
fact a metaphysical proposition: wherever any man is, there is “man is.” But
we need to distinguish between “this man is” and “man is.” Here, Wyclif
suggests that we recognize that Aristotle distinguished between two types
of substances in the Categories: a primary substance, which is articulated
by “this man is,” and a secondary substance, which is directly connected to
the primary substance of this man, but is signified by “man is.”
The doctors of signs who deny that “man is” signifies anything beyond
individual men are guilty of more than misunderstanding Aristotle, though;
they make understanding the ontology expressed in scripture impossible:
Indeed I often wonder now how anyone could so churlishly explain the
philosophical sense of a philosophical text. But even more, I wonder how
an advanced theologian would dare this, because of the danger to the
soul in interpreting the words of Scripture about universals to be only
about signs.29
The Bible often refers to creatures according to their kinds; are we to think
that these kinds have no referent? When we read in Genesis that God said,
“Let the earth put forth vegetation: plants yielding seed, and fruit trees of
every kind on earth that bear fruit with the seed in it,” are we to suppose
that the “excellent philosopher Moses brought from [his] clear vision of
God on the mountain the sense that the earth would make seed according
to a concept” that was extrapolated from mere particular things? When
we read that God created man shortly afterward, what is the referent of
“man” (hominem)? Just the individual Adam, “this man,” or the entire kind,
“man”? According to Aristotle, “For in definition, universals are prior, in
relation to perception, individuals [are].” One might well mistake how we
perceive things to be prior, Wyclif explains, but ontologically the kind is
prior to the individual, meaning that, in the passage relating the creation of
man, the term “man” means primarily the universal, and only secondarily
the particular, Adam.30
Divine Ideas
Walter Chatton edges carefully around the issue, arguing against Ockham
and Aureol without making any commitment to ontological reality in any
way.37
Wyclif begins his analysis by bringing the problem back to the pre-
Ockhamist approach: the very term “idea” signifies an eternal, rational
exemplar by which God creates, a medium between the being of the crea-
ture and God’s act of knowing. The host of problems accompanying the
doctrine, which have led to so much erroneous speculation, arises from
confusion about the nature and extent of the ideas. Assuming that they
have reality, the questions become, how much reality, and how many of
them can there be? Wyclif ’s attention lies with the latter problem first:
can there be ideas for impossibles? What about unactualized possibles, or
counterfactuals? These questions in themselves should suggest Wyclif ’s
realism; they would not long interest someone thinking that the ideas
arise out of the fact of creation. Thus, it is likely that Wyclif has a more
developed picture than Aquinas, whom Scotus and Aureol had accused of
hypostasizing. At the very outset, then, Wyclif is ready to argue for ideas of
actual beings, if ideas for impossibles and counterfactuals are on the table.
Wyclif dismisses ideas for impossibles and counterfactuals quickly, if
for no other reason than because scripture rules them out. “In Him are all
things that were made” ( John 1:3) is also evidence suitable for arguing in
favor of ideas for all actualized creatures. Dionysius the Areopagite argued
that the goodness of all things preexists in God’s understanding, having
their origin in his unity and their formal identity in the actuality of form,
just as the human soul provides the basis for all of our organic powers,
92 john wyclif
assume that Aristotle implicitly assumed divine ideas, even if at times this
is difficult to ascertain. To suppose otherwise would make scripture incom-
prehensible: “I preach to the laity that every creature was alive eternally in
God, but because of my limits, I am subtle about it. Nor do I know how to
express the sense of Scripture, if not in this way.”38
Aquinas and Grosseteste suggest that an idea is best understood as a
relation of reason, Wyclif continues, but this cannot be right. Any relation
other than an identity relation must have relata, but what would be the
second term of the relation, if not the creature understood? If it were the
creature, the idea would presuppose itself, since God knows what comes
into being through the ideas. Hence, Aquinas’s belief that ideas fall out of
God’s creative relation to creation cannot be accurate, either:
After unraveling the tortured syntax, we can see that the statement allows
Wyclif to avoid hypostasizing the ideas as known by God. The “creature
as understood by God” is the cause for the creature’s production without
having anything like substantial being. It is a “body through which,” intel-
ligible as actualized in creation, yet eternal and complete in God’s mind.
With this conception of ideas, we need not concern ourselves with ideas
of ideas, or other problematic issues.
Universals
The extent of Wyclif ’s realism has been exaggerated, at least from the
time of Thomas Netter, and certainly in contemporary scholarship. In
J. A. Robson’s Wyclif and the Oxford Schools, he is described as “ultrareal-
ist” in an otherwise excellent treatment of his Summa de Ente. As we gain
a more developed picture of fourteenth-century Oxford’s metaphysics, it is
clear that Wyclif ’s understanding of universals was much more moderate
than was Burley’s, whose position Wyclif had expressly hoped to modify.40
Wyclif makes comments throughout the treatises of the Summa de Ente that
94 john wyclif
lead one to believe that he thought there were any number of kinds of uni-
versals: “Here we must say that there are only five universals, and that there
are only ten universals, and that there are any number of universals that
you want; because numbers, as things counted, vary in accordance with the
size of the units chosen.”41 It is easy to envision him smiling while making a
comment like this in a lecture, as his students scratch their heads in frustra-
tion. In fact, he argued for only three: universals by causation, universals by
community, and universals by signification. Both in De Ente in Communi,
the first treatise of the first half of the Summa, and in De Universalibus, this
is Wyclif ’s list. The differing medieval approaches to universals suggest
his reasoning for this list. The traditional, ontologically oriented approach,
founded in Boethius’s second Commentary on Porphyry’s Isagoge, under-
stands a universal to be one something common to many, with each par-
ticular containing the whole universal in itself. Thus, the universal man
is fully in Socrates, and in Plato, and in any other male human being as
well. Further, the universal man “constitutes and forms the substance of the
[men] to which it is common.” Peter Abelard’s approach was different. He
explained universals by concentrating on predication, shifting the explana-
tion from ontological to a more logically oriented account. Universals are
predicated in many things, but what sorts of things are “capable of being
predicated of many”? The statements “Socrates is a man” and “Plato is a
man” use the predicate “is a man.” These statements reflect how things
are in the world, for their subjects are things in the world. So the question
is whether “is a man” is also something in the world; if it is, what is it?
Abelard’s approach allowed philosophers to argue about whether predica-
tion could be a relation applied to nonlinguistic things, and while Wyclif
is committed to the Boethian approach, he is also an enthusiastic advocate
of framing metaphysical accounts in terms of predication. Both sorts of uni-
versals fit into his system.42
He is also very sensitive to Ockham’s critique of realism and recognizes
that we can easily suppose that something real lies behind linguistic signs
or concepts, when frequently there is nothing there. When we say that the
universal man is argued by one philosopher to be a real thing, part of every
male animal with a human form, while it is explained away by another phi-
losopher as but a puff of air, or marks on paper, or a concept used to stand
for something similar in the nature of every male animal with human form,
what is the status of the terms we use? Is there some universal term “man”
that gives meaning to each use of the term in a sentence? And is there a
wyclif in oxford 95
membership relation holding between that and the universal term “ani-
mal” that is similar to the membership relation holding between the uni-
versal man and the universal animal? What would be the relation between
the universal term “man” and the universal man? Wyclif ’s universals by
representation are the terms we use to account for the other two kinds of
universals, but he says that they are only equivocally universal, as when we
see a picture of Abraham Lincoln and say, “That’s Lincoln.”43
Wyclif ’s universal by community, which he describes as a thing shared by
many supposits, corresponds to the Boethian universal. General and specific
natures, like animal and human, fit this bill. Albert the Great and Aquinas
had thought that genus and species are the products of our intellects’ actu-
alization of potential commonalities of common forms, but Wyclif was
frustrated with their denial of these universals having extramental real-
ity. He understands them as being faced with a problem, namely, how can
a universal man exist in several other, particular human beings, without
being divided up between them? Their answer was to emphasize the com-
monality of the form of the human beings, which commonality is realized
as a universal man in our understanding of the things. His answer was
to distinguish between man’s existence in God’s mind and man’s existence
in creation, a distinction between first- and second-intention universals. A
first-intention term is a concept we derive from a real thing: when I hold a
red apple, I can consider the redness of that apple. That concept is a first-
intention concept of the apple’s redness. I can then reflect back on all of
the other red apples I’ve encountered, and compare this apple’s redness
with them. This reflection back is itself a concept, derived from earlier con-
cepts, and is a second-intention concept. Similarly, universals by commu-
nity have existence as objects of God’s mind, or divine ideas, and they also
have existence in the being of things. When we encounter an individual
apple, we recognize the universal “fruit” as it exists in the essential nature
of the apple as a universal of the first intention. This gives us a foundation
for understanding the universal’s primary being, which is to have being as
a second-intention idea in God’s mind. Since the divine ideas are eternal,
while universals are created, this means that second-intention universals
have ontological primacy over first-intention universals.
This does not mean that God’s knowledge is reliant on the being of
creatures. Wyclif ’s use of first- and second-intention universals should not
confuse us into thinking that the created order is the basis for divine real-
ity. Logically, we consider universals from their particulars back to their
96 john wyclif
correlates in the divine ideas, but metaphysically, the idea is the basis for the
being of all the particulars. The being of man as a divine idea is the ground
for the existence of all individual people. The being of man in Socrates is
not different from the being of Socrates; it is only formally distinct from the
being of Socrates. Put another way, the universal man is each of its particu-
lars, but with differing supposits, or different individual referents. Still, it is
nothing more than its particulars. In this way, Wyclif sees himself as avoid-
ing Platonism, which he thinks Burley has not avoided, without sacrific-
ing the reality of universals, as the Thomists, Scotists, and the Ockhamists
have done.44 In Wyclif ’s Christology, his conception of the universal man is
central to the metaphysics of the incarnation. On becoming a man, Christ
incorporated the universal man into the identity of the second person of
the Trinity. Since the universal man is each of its particulars, by Wyclif ’s
description, Christ became Everyman.
Universals by commonality, the familiar Boethian universals, are joined
by universals by causality, because everything in creation that is, was, or
will be exists in a certain way in its causes at the beginning of time. The
most universal cause is God, and all secondary causes that act in creation
have their structure and being from the divine nature. So when God made
the first human being, all of his progeny, the entire human race, was within
Adam. When Adam sinned, then all sinned. This is not part of the created
human nature, though, because the universal man was created free of the
stain of sin. Universals by commonality do not explain how we came to be
the way we are, so the causal agency of the first human being’s sin, which
affects all subsequent human beings, functions as a universal in this sense.
This universal by causality is the reason that I have been brought into being
by my father, by Adam, and ultimately, by God’s creation of man. Because
the universal by causality has its primary being in God’s creation, it fol-
lows that God’s causal knowledge is the most primary kind of universal by
causality. If this is so, God’s causal knowledge of my coming into existence
is the primary cause of my being, and my father’s efficient causality is only
a mediate cause, determined by God’s knowing from eternity. In our dis-
cussion of determinism in a later chapter, it will be clear that this causal
account is made more complex by understanding the reciprocity that holds
between created action and divine knowledge.
Efficient causality is not the only kind of causal relation Wyclif has in
mind for universals by causality. Every relation describable by Aristotle’s
categorical structure is founded in universals by causality because the
wyclif in oxford 97
the universal by causality of the being of his formal cause, which was first
instantiated in Adam. Simply, while universals by commonality give the
basis for what a thing is, universals by causality provide the reason for how
that thing has come into being.
But it would be a mistake to interpret this as leading to the belief that
universals by commonality simply account for essences, and universals by
causality account for the actual being of the essential nature. The relation
between essence and existence was a matter of some disagreement among the
later scholastics. Aquinas and Giles of Rome had argued for a real distinc-
tion between essence and existence in the composition of a substantial being,
which Ockham, Henry of Ghent, and Scotus rejected. Perhaps influenced
by Henry of Ghent’s attention to the different kinds of being of an essence,
Wyclif insisted that there is no real distinction between being and essence,
that the essence of a given substance does not precede its being in creation.
He explains:
[An essence is t]he matter, the form, and the union of these. There is no
matter, unless [it is] able to exist or be informed by the absolute essence,
and there is no form unless [it is] actually existing or informing the same
essence, and there is no union of these unless the same essence is one from
this: that formally it is this, that it is to its potency, and all this is the essence.
From which it is clear that any essence exists perpetually, because it can-
not be brought to an end, save through annihilation. But nothing can be
annihilated. . . . For prime matter is not corrupted because of generations
of different kinds of forms; but it remains constant underneath, with
various forms at different times; therefore so with essence, which exists
with this matter, since matter predicates, beyond the essence, a relation
to form in common.45
This is confusing, in that it seems to say that essence is both limited to
the duration of the union of a particular form with some particular mat-
ter, and unlimited in that it holds across all time in the relation of prime
matter to form in common. There are, in fact, two kinds of essence. The
individual being of a substance in time and space is defined by its singu-
lar essence, while the type that this individual instantiates is its universal
essence. Being, too, is manifold: Wyclif describes creatures as having four
kinds in the same discussion. First, there is the eternal mental being of
ideas in God. From eternity, for example, God has understood the idea of
a “rose.” Next, there is the being that a creature has in its causes. This can
either be being in a universal cause, like a species, or in a particular cause,
wyclif in oxford 99
For just as a thing is an entity before it is any kind of thing, since the
question “Is there such a thing?” presupposes the question “What kind
of thing is it?,” and a man is an entity before he is a substance, so too
it seems that essence, the putting of the bare question “Is there such a
thing?” precedes the quiddity which adds genus to being. In such cases
therefore there is a mental distinction.47
This mental distinction, or distinctio rationis, allows him to assert the real-
ity of universals by commonality and by causality without bringing free-
floating universals into the discussion, as Burley did, and without relegating
universals to being only creatures of the understanding, brought about by
100 john wyclif
analysis of how terms refer to the persons within the Trinity. The Calabrian
claimed that Lombard’s description of a Trinity that neither begets nor is
begotten entailed a fourth entity in addition to the three divine persons.
Lombard had emphasized the impossibility of attributing particular actions
of the divine persons to the divine essence, and caused Joachim conster-
nation by having used the term “essence” to mean something other than
“person.” Joachim was rebuked by the Fourth Lateran Council for con-
ceiving of the divine unity as a collective, or group of individual persons.50
He erred, Wyclif explains, by confusing the reference of terms predicated
of the divine essence and terms predicated of persons. The absolute nature
of the divine essence precludes generating or being generated, so the pres-
ence of this generating, which holds between Father and Son, cannot be
essential to God. Yet to hold that the essence is something beyond the gener-
ating and the being generated of the persons seems to lead to positing a
quaternity that includes a fourth divine being beyond the generating, the
generated, and the spirated persons. The divine Trinity, he argues, is an
aggregate of the three persons, Father, Son, and Spirit. While the Father
begets, the Son is begotten, and the Spirit is spirated from the Father and
Son together, the aggregate godhead neither begets nor is begotten. The
Trinity is a universal, of which the divine persons are the instantiates. But
this aggregate of the three persons is more than just a universal, because
universals only give being to their particulars, while the godhead is both
subsistent being and the source of being to all creatures. So this aggregate
must have reality of some kind, beyond that of a universal. If Wyclif ’s trini-
tarian thought is the basis for his belief that any ordered pair of creatures
gives rise to an aggregate third, apart from any universal the two might
have in common in their natures, then it would seem that here his meta-
physics is, at least in part, an outgrowth of theology. The same cannot be
said for his understanding of the Eucharist. There, his conviction of the
impossibility of annihilation, along with spatiotemporal atomism, leads to
his argument that transubstantiation is impossible.
4
denying transubstantiation
Physics, Eucharist, and Apostasy
When the mass of cardinals, archbishops, abbots, bishops, and other clergy
met in ecclesiastical council at Constance in the fall of 1414, much needed
to be done. Five years earlier, they had met in Pisa hoping to resolve the
schism that had divided Western Christendom in 1378, when the elec-
tion of Urban VI in Rome had prompted French cardinals to name
Clement VII in Avignon. The result had been a third pope, John XXIII,
who proved anything but unifying in his dealings with the other church-
men. Sigismund of Luxembourg had managed to force John to decree the
council at Constance, and hopes were high among the conciliarists that a
watershed in Christian history was at hand. The conciliarists, political the-
orists who advocated an Aristotelian polity rather than a papal monarchy
within the church, were determined to use the crisis to eliminate the basis
for any pope to exercise absolute power over the cardinals and bishops. The
drama that would play out over the coming three years saw the ultimate
triumph of the papacy and the conciliarists’ defeat. But this was only after
the drama of a decree declaring the pope’s duty to obey the council, the
resignation of Gregory XII (who had succeeded Innocent VII, Urban’s
successor), the deposing of Benedict XIII (Clement’s successor), and the
trial and deposing of the slippery John XXIII.
In the midst of all this, Bohemia was headed toward open rebellion
against both the church and the empire. The conciliarists could ill afford
102
denying transubstantiation 103
to show weakness when quelling heresy, and they brought the full weight
of their corrective power against Jan Hus and Jerome of Prague, both of
whom had been inspired by Wyclif ’s theological vision. In the course of
this, the council also formally condemned 45 propositions directly associ-
ated with Wyclif ’s thought, and 260 others more indirectly relevant. Of all
of these, Wyclif ’s eucharistic errors topped the list, but among the proposi-
tions that drew the council’s ire, several seem less predictably inflamma-
tory: “It is impossible for two corporeal substances to be co-extensive, the
one continuously at rest in a place and the other continuously penetrating
the body of Christ at rest.” Further, “[a]ny continuous mathematical line is
composed of two, three or four contiguous points, or of only a simply finite
number of points; and time is, was and will be composed of contiguous
instants.”1 What these assertions about physics have to do with Wyclif ’s
heresies is by no means immediately obvious, and it is difficult to imagine
the beleaguered churchmen fulminating for very long about the assertion
that time and space are composed of indivisible atoms. Yet, in Wyclif ’s analy-
sis of the Thomist doctrine of transubstantiation, this innocuous position
features prominently. In this dense section of De Eucharistia, Wyclif seems
to suggest that error about the makeup of spatiotemporal continua leads to
believing that transubstantiation somehow makes sense. This connection
is by no means an easy one to make, but if it is tenable, it might help us to
understand why Wyclif seemed driven to deny a doctrine that was cen-
tral to the medieval world. Philosophers generally like to have alternatives
ready when they disprove long-held beliefs, and one wants to read that a
clever philosopher like Wyclif came up with some sort of tenable eucharis-
tic theory to replace transubstantiation. Unfortunately, aside from insisting
that Christ is really present in the consecrated host, Wyclif did not pre-
sent a philosophically developed alternative to what he angrily dismissed as
“accidents without a subject.” In fairness to him, Wyclif might have replied
that such an alternative was unnecessary; the words of scripture and the
teachings of the fathers should be sufficient. A response like this would
be consonant with the Confessio, which is translated as an appendix in this
work. We will be forced to jump from sacramental theology to spatiotem-
poral physical theory in what follows, if we are to understand why Wyclif
felt that the prevalent explanations of transubstantiation were insufficient.
So, following a discussion of the development of eucharistic theology, we
will explore Wyclif ’s theory of indivisible instants of time and space and
his arguments against the possibility of annihilation.
104 john wyclif
During the meal Jesus shared with his disciples on the evening before his
arrest, the Gospels tell us that he took bread and said, “Take; this is my
body.” Next, he took a cup of wine and told them to drink from it, saying,
“This is my blood of the covenant, which is poured out for many” (Mark
14:22–25; Matthew 26:26–29; Luke 22:19–21). Throughout the medieval
period, the words Jesus used, called the words of “institution,” were the basis
for the central liturgical office of the faith, the Eucharist. Of the sacraments
recognized to be outward signs of inward grace, the liturgical celebration
of Eucharist in the Mass was regarded as the supreme sacrament, in which
the entire salvation of the world is embodied. The attempt to understand
exactly what occurs in the Eucharist was an important part of medieval the-
ology from the ninth century onward. Extensive theological dialogue was
devoted to understanding exactly what Jesus meant by “this is my body.”
After all, anyone could see that it was bread he was holding. Today, many
Christians, particularly Protestants, are content to approach the Eucharist
as a communal activity in which believers participate. Whether the ele-
ments undergo some sort of mystic change is of much less importance than
the accompanying grace that moves within the participants. In antiquity,
Augustine’s interests were similarly directed, although it would be an over-
statement to say that he had no interest in the reality of Christ’s presence in
the elements.2
The great rebirth of scientific interest in the ninth century was accom-
panied by serious efforts to shore up liturgical practice, and two monks
from the French monastery of Corbie defined the beginning of medieval
eucharistic thought. Paschasius Radbertus (c. 790–865) argued that the ele-
ments of bread and wine change into Christ’s body and blood at the conse-
cration. They may not change in appearance, but in a spiritual sense, they
really do become parts of the risen Christ. Ratramnus (d. 868) agreed that
Christ’s spiritual presence in the elements is real, but objected to what he
perceived to be a lack of sensitivity regarding the means through which the
consecrated elements “are” the body and blood. He distinguished between
“figure” and “reality” in the being of Christ in the elements. If Christ were
“in reality” in the elements, he would be empirically present, but if he were
there “in figure,” he would not be perceptibly present but “proclaimed
inwardly to the minds of the faithful.” A very useful way of understanding
denying transubstantiation 105
label refers not to the handle, but to the water that comes from the faucet.
In the same way, the visible sacrament is not Christ, but it signifies the
invisible body of Christ one receives when eating it.
Lanfranc’s criticism of Berengar was bolstered by his use of a more com-
plex notion of substance than Berengar seems to have envisioned. He was
the first to formulate the essential change of bread into body by using the
framework of the Categories, which allows for the exchange of one sub-
stantial platform for another, without a change in the perceptible qualities
resting upon them. The stage was set for the introduction of the concept
of transubstantiation. This term was being used by 1140 to distinguish
between the usual sort of change we see in bodies, when qualities or proper-
ties change, while the underlying nature remains constant, and the mystical
change of the Eucharist, when the opposite occurs. Of the many theologians
who addressed the metaphysics of the Eucharist in the late twelfth century,
Lothario of Segni stands out. Lothario’s approach was not novel, nor were
his explanations that much more compelling than those of his fellows. He
distilled the best of the explanations then prevalent in his own mind, and
on becoming Innocent III, he convened the Fourth Lateran Council, where
transubstantiation became the established term for explaining the real pres-
ence of Christ. Lateran IV’s codification of transubstantiation was not the
end of eucharistic speculation; three distinct means by which the miracle
occurs attracted their own admirers, and each was judged to be a valid
explanation. First, the substance of the bread might remain along with the
substance of Christ’s body, which is consubstantiation. Where once there
was one thing, bread, now there are two, for the body of Christ is now in
the same place. Second, the substance of the bread might be annihilated and
replaced by the substance of Christ’s body. Third, the substance of the bread
itself might change, becoming the substance of Christ’s body, without pass-
ing out of existence. Here, the substance itself converts, from “being bread”
to “being body” without a change in the underlying subject.5
While the advent of commentary on Lombard’s Sentences afforded
some structure, it wasn’t until 1234, with the publication of the Decretales
by Gregory IX, that canon law provided firm boundaries to define late
medieval eucharistic theology. While many theologians in the ensuing two
centuries assayed explanations of the real presence, the limits of space in
this volume prevent us from doing more than mentioning the three land-
mark theologians’ approaches. For Aquinas, the Eucharist is “the summit
of spiritual life, and all the sacraments are ordered to it.” Its centrality to the
denying transubstantiation 107
sense in which the conversion involves Christ being in two places at once,
with one being in place remaining unchanging, and the other beginning to
be at the moment of consecration. His approach is to look at what is involved
in being in a place, and he thinks of it as relation based. That is, “being in
a place” is like “having a relation.” Just as someone can have one relation
to one person, and another to another, so God could arrange it that Christ’s
body is in one place and that it can begin to be in another place at the same
time. Hence, God can make Christ’s body present in many separate loca-
tions without a change in Christ. But if Christ can begin to be on an altar,
and be unchangeable in heaven, what about the being of the bread? Does
it undergo a commensurate ceasing to be at the same time? Scotus seemed
to envision the bread as losing its “being here” without losing its “being as
such,” avoiding annihilation, but only barely. In general, Scotus was willing
to support conversion on the force of his adherence to church teachings, even
if he could imagine that consubstantiation might fit more to the structure
of our reasoning than does transubstantiation by conversion.7
Ockham’s approach seems to be the last important variation before
Wyclif ’s rejection of transubstantiation. Like Scotus, Ockham was willing
to countenance consubstantiation as a reasonable possibility. If two bodies
can exist in the same place, which is certainly within God’s power to effect,
then Christ’s body can exist alongside the substance of the elements. Like
Scotus again, Ockham addressed being in a place as central to explaining
how Christ’s body can be both in heaven and on a thousand altars across
Christendom. While consubstantiation is a reasonable possibility, transub-
stantiation is the church’s preferred approach, and Ockham abided by this
in his eucharistic theology. Ockham’s innovation was to distinguish between
being in a place and being in part of a place. When a given substance is
whole in one place and exists in part in a correspondent part of that place,
this is circumspective place, the way that extended bodies normally exist in
space. But a thing might exist whole in a given place, and whole in every
part of the given place; this would be an indivisible being, and it would
have definitive place. Our experience tells us that no material substance can
occupy a place in this way, although Christ’s body and blood exist in defini-
tive place in the consecrated elements. So at least one material substance
must have definitive place, for Christ’s ascended body remains extended,
material substance. And this is also the way the intellectual soul exists in the
body: whole in the body and whole in each of its parts. But Ockham was not
simply inventing a distinction to explain dogma. God could cause Christ’s
denying transubstantiation 109
For example, Augustine and Boethius both note the widespread accep-
tance of the story of Circe, who turned the comrades of Ulysses into beasts,
and the story about the Arcadians, who swam across a pool and turned
into wolves. Scripture itself tells us of Lot’s wife being turned into a pil-
lar of salt; the transubstantiation of bread into the body of Christ is not
denying transubstantiation 113
Indivisibles
position that time and space are divisible into atomic units. At one point in
his attempts to overcome the prevalent rejection of indivisiblism, he admits,
“And I do not yet know how to disprove any of these three replies effec-
tively.”14 Walter Burley had weighed in against indivisiblists, but he did
not reject the possibility of the existence of indivisibles in continua. Not all
parts of a given continuum actually exist, but God sees all the atoms on a
continuum as potentially existing, and the intervals between them as well.
Logic demands that there be indivisibles in time. Two contradictory sen-
tences about a given time cannot both be true, but if they are about a unit
of time that is divisible, like an hour or a minute, they could both be true, if
one is about the first part and the other is about the second part. Of course,
these would not be real contradictories; two truly contradictory sentences
about a given unit of time would require that the unit be indivisible. Since
there are such sets of contradictories, there must also, Burley reasoned, be
indivisibles in time.15
It is possible that Wyclif ’s approach is related to Burley’s reasoning as
a consequence of his propositional realism. Kretzman describes Wyclif ’s
indivisiblism in terms of his use of Mertonian methodology to disprove the
calculators’ rejection of indivisiblism. As described in chapter 2, the cal-
culators were skilled in using the analysis of sophismata to reason out the
physical laws of mechanics. Wyclif, a product of Merton College, was cer-
tainly adept at this method, and he appears to have developed one sophisma
to show the untenability of the infinite divisibility of time. Unlike Zeno’s
paradox of complete divisibility, which Aristotle described as having com-
pelled the ancient atomists to advocate indivisibles, this puzzle is meant
solely to show a problem with how we understand the truth of a statement
like “Socrates begins to move east.” This puzzle, known as the “vacillating
man,” asks that we imagine a period of time, say, an hour, with a marked
midpoint, and divided such that each half on either side of the midpoint is
respectively divided in half, and then in half again, and so on. The number
of divisions, according to the continuist, can be infinite. Consider one of
the halves, say, the first half hour. It is divided in an infinitely diminish-
ing number of halves, so that each division consists of half of the previ-
ous quantity and an infinitely divided other half. Give each half a number.
Now, imagine Socrates moving in this period of time, so that he moves
east during the odd-numbered periods of time, and west during the even-
numbered periods. Never mind that, at a certain point, this will be physically
denying transubstantiation 117
impossible; the point is that, at the midpoint, Socrates would be both begin-
ning to move and beginning to be at rest:
And yet immediately after this, he will begin to move, and the same
holds regarding rest. Indeed, now he is not moving, and immediately
after this he will not be moving, and immediately before this he was not
moving; and yet he begins to move, and he ceases not moving—just as
immediately before this he ceased not moving, and immediately after
this he will cease not moving.16
The result of this thought experiment is, for Wyclif, forcing the continuist
to acknowledge that beginning to move is not instantaneous but successive,
so that there will always be contradictories true of any given case of some-
thing beginning to move:
But those who claim that a continuum is composed of indivisibles—e.g.,
Time composed of instants, a line composed of points, a surface composed
of lines, a body composed of surfaces, a motion composed of mutata esse,
and so on . . . say that it is impossible that any entity begin or cease to be
except in virtue of the introduction of the present.
This means that any sentence involving “begin” or “cease” must involve a
uniform unit of indivisible time.17 Wyclif ’s indivisiblism is not enthusiastic,
though; he recognizes that reason throws up as many arguments against
spatiotemporal indivisibles as it presents supports:
Leaving the deeper investigation of all these matters to the subtle logi-
cians and natural philosophers, I ask those who read through this chap-
ter not to condemn or deride the things that have been said here . . . for
I know that these things are rejected by many authorities, and that they
demolish the Calculators’ arguments [along with] many doctrines and
fanciful examples put forward by the moderns.18
The problem with this, though, is that this reasoning in obedience to author-
ity is what compelled Holcot to accept transubstantiation in the face of the
welter of reasons to the contrary. One might well respond that Holcot’s
acceptance of transubstantiation on faith is something altogether different
from Wyclif ’s acceptance of atomism on faith, were it not for the connec-
tion that had been established in Ockham’s argument against Aquinas’s
version of transubstantiation.
Temporal Atomism
unified; so, too, must any of its instantiations in act be unified. Hence, time
is measured by the indivisible mass, or point, that instantiates the magni-
tude of time. There is a one-to-one correspondence of body to instant, then,
in which the body’s continuity persists from instant to instant, because the
body’s form is anterior to its material extension. For moving bodies, the
movement is itself composed of indivisible instants, and these correspond
directly with temporal instants.26
What Wyclif has in mind is a picture of time structured in the way we
watch movies. Each frame of the movie is in itself unified, a moment frozen
in time. From one frame to the next, the subject portrayed seems to move,
but in fact there is no movement distinct from the time in which it occurs,
or the succession of frames. On this analogy, God is the great director, view-
ing all created being through the medium of time, knowing each occur-
rence and each individual through its placement in individual frames of
the movie. This structure, Wyclif suggests, is more coherent than the one
in which there is no one-to-one correspondence of body to instant, for
there we are expected to believe that some accident of a substance might
have a greater reality than the substance itself. Wyclif throws this com-
ment off quickly, and moves back to the virtues of his own position, but this
statement bears closer examination. In the context, Wyclif appears to be
referring to an understanding of time and movement in which there are no
indivisibles, and a body moves continuously through two infinitely divisible
media. Here, the substance moving is finite, but it is moving across infi-
nitely divisible time and space. In holding this, “I have denied substance to
be equal to its duration and consequently some accident of a subject is great
which does not have a subject equally great, but equally lasting.” In itself,
the criticism points to a disparity in the Aristotelian scheme wherein the
accidents depend for their being on a substance. In a later chapter, Wyclif
is discussing the nature of indivisibles, and the question of persons arises.
Are persons indivisible? It does not lead to a contradiction to suppose that
several natures might be contained in one person, he reasons, given that
Christ had both a divine and a human nature, “but it is contradictory for
the same to be communicated as [the] same nature to many supposits, as is
clear elsewhere.” By “the same,” does Wyclif mean Christ? Thomson notes
in his catalog of Wyclif ’s Latin works that Wyclif seems to have had the
Eucharist on his mind in this work; these two comments can be construed
as supporting his thesis.27
denying transubstantiation 121
Annihilation
[B]ut it remains one body serving as subject to the accidents of the bread,
which I call an abstract mathematical body. Just as a substance is first
not a being more than it is a something, so the bread first in its nature
is a body more than it is bread. . . . And thus the same being, which
first is bread, remains a body under this degree of general quiddity, but
it does not remain purely the body of Christ, nor pure bread, but the
bread is converted into the body of Christ, because the bread remains
the body of Christ sacramentally, existing under those accidents under
which formally it was bread.33
Better to continue by talking about how two things can be in the same
place at the same time; a thing that is at once corporeal and spiritual is said
to be located equivocally. As Grosseteste said, the soul is more truly with
that of which it is desirous than where it provides form, and in this way,
Wyclif continues, we speak about visual abilities. When the sensible species
of something appears in a medium that causes it to be multiplied through-
out the medium, as when something appears in a mirror, and is reflected
again in another mirror, the image of the thing reflected can be said to be
present to the vision of one seeing the thing in the mirror. When I look
at my back in a mirror in a clothing store, I do not see my back; I see an
image of my back with clarity, and I see the color and shape of the mirror
confusedly. Characteristically, Wyclif returns to the example that haunts
him: “In this sensible way is the body of Christ in the Eucharist, but not
extensively. And so it is not right that the same [body of Christ] be moved,
but that it be multiplied, as it is here [in the mirror example].”
That Christ is present in the Eucharist as an image is in a mirror is as
near to a positive assertion of how Wyclif understands the sacrament as
we are likely to get. Heather Phillips has argued that we ought not under-
estimate this imagery from a philosopher given to enthusiastic use of the
science of optics in his philosophical reasoning.34 She points out that he
gives exactly the same explanation several times throughout De Eucharistia,
as here in chapter 5:
[T]he pious philosopher says that a body has intentional being through
a medium which receives its species, spiritual being in the soul through
the consideration of the soul, without being moved there. Why can it not
be thus of the sacramental being which the body of Christ has in the host
by virtue imparted to the host, without being moved there locally?35
Indeed, in his Postilla, Wyclif says much the same thing in his comments
on 1 Corinthians 10:
It could be said, then, if it pleases the satraps, that the bread and wine
remain, and every particle of the body of Christ is sacramentally mul-
tiplied to every one of their points. Nor is this inconvenient for God,
because according to another perspective the sensible body is multiplied
through every distance, where it is perceived, therefore the body of
Christ has a certain being under the sacrament, but not a dimensional
one, nor is it perceptibly there as a quantum or quality, nor is it there
a non-quantum, but it is there a non-quantum there.36
126 john wyclif
So the body of Christ is to every point of the world, since the power of
this body perfects any part of the world more than a terrestrial king
can perfect any part of his kingdom. Nevertheless it is believed, that the
body of Christ is in another way largely in the consecrated host, since it
would be habitudinally the same as the host, and by reason of [its] power
and of virtual existence it is otherwise to any of its points. And it is clear
that according to this two-fold reason the body of Christ is in the place
of the consecrated host.37
One could be forgiven for supposing that Wyclif has formulated a clear
philosophical explanation for the Eucharist to counter transubstantiation;
after all, he uses this mirror analogy repeatedly throughout his career. But
making an analogy is one thing, and constructing a philosophical account is
quite another. One could as easily dismiss any thorny problem in Christian
theology with a handy analogy. The real heavy lifting comes in explaining
the analogy. If Christ is to bread as an image is to mirror, what is to stop
us from freezing that image on the glass, as in a daguerreotype, and mak-
ing the claim that just as Christ is really present in the bread, so Abraham
Lincoln is really present in the picture I have of him on the wall? Of course,
Wyclif recognized this, and while he continued to use the example until he
died, he seems to have realized that he needed substantially more early on,
at least by Easter Sunday 1378, when he preached on Mark 16:2.
Beginning from a discussion of the appearance of the risen Christ, he
distinguishes between our perception of Christ in the host with our vision
and with our mind, and asserts that the Christian perceives “by faith that
the fullness of the body of Christ, and the blood and the soul, is from its
integrity to every point of this sacrament.” But how this takes place has
given rise to erroneous theorizing, “some supposing that the bread is the
body of Christ, some that the bread becomes and will be the body of Christ,
some that the bread is converted into the body of Christ through the drain-
ing away of the bread in some of its parts.” All of this should be swept away
as useless theorizing: “It is enough that a Christian believe that the body
of Christ is in some spiritual, sacramental way present to every point of
the consecrated host.” In the mirror of the world, Christ appears to every
point as a full likeness, which one sees in one place, and another somewhere
else: “If a created nature can make itself or its likeness to be multiplied,
denying transubstantiation 127
Denying Transubstantiation
by Process of Elimination
Wyclif ’s De Eucharistia is most notable for its critical analysis of the extant
theories of transubstantiation of Scotus, Aquinas, and, in a different con-
text, Ockham. His rejection of Ockham’s position is based primarily in
his refutation of the possibility of annihilation. Wyclif addresses Scotus by
exploring how one says that the soul and the body of Christ are, at the same
time, in many places at once. The Scotist approach, based as it is on the
assertion that a thing can be whole in several places at once, would allow us
to conclude that God could make it possible that someone other than Christ
be multiplied across time and space. Importing God’s absolute power into
creation to allow for the multiplication of Christ effectively undercuts all
laws of God’s ordinate command, Wyclif argues, and can as easily be used
to allow that two contraries coexist. Does the need for transubstantiation to
be true go so far as to violate the idea that God’s absolute power would not
surpass the laws of logic? Further, multiplying any being, even a point of
space, would eliminate the coherence of time and space, the dependability
of the senses in accurately measuring the world, and the way we use terms
to explain reality:
Every man would be dizzy, not knowing how to discern sensible things—
and all of this error was born in the lying story of the sacrament of the
altar! . . . there are a thousand such instances disturbing the church, all of
which are dependent upon, or are based in, the most impossible fantasy
and occasion of heresy introduced by the sacrament of the Eucharist.42
The key here seems to lie in Wyclif ’s conception that all continua are com-
posed of indivisibles, because if there are infinitely many possible places
between any two given places, as Scotus would have asserted, there would
be room for the insertion of something new without destroying the cohe-
sion of time and space. Wyclif ’s atomism compels him to declare Scotus’s
theory of conversio guilty of the introduction of skepticism; but with infi-
nitely divisible continua, there is room for change without the peril of illu-
sion causing us to doubt our every step.
Aquinas’s conception of transubstantiation requires an understanding of
change over time, and seems to be the place where atomism plays the most
important role in Wyclif ’s eucharistic thought. If time really is divided in
discrete units, continuous motion seems impossible, while if our senses are
denying transubstantiation 129
correct, and continuous motion is real, time must also be similarly continu-
ous, and infinitely divisible. But because time is naturally prior to motion,
Wyclif reasons, there is no need to justify time to continuous motion by
admitting it to be continuous. Wyclif is making use of an innovation of
Scotus here; Scotus had argued for the priority of time to motion in a signifi-
cant break with Aristotelian physics, likely reacting to the 1277 condemna-
tion of the proposition “if heaven stood still, fire would not burn flax, because
time would not exist.” He is likewise in direct opposition to Ockham, for
whom time and movement are directly related, such that movement is what
allows us to define time. Wyclif reads Aquinas’s Sentences Commentary IIa,
d.3, q.25, as recognizing the possibility of indivisibles in time, thereby sup-
porting a model of time made up of indivisibles in the midst of an otherwise
infinitely divisible continuum, rather like pebbles caught in concrete. But
why have both? “God could annihilate every continuum of this sensible
world while preserving every one of its [indivisible] points . . . and it is clear
that there would be a temporal continuum just as there is a permanent spa-
tial continuum, yet time would be composed of instants.”43 Simply, if God
could ensure motion across time defined by indivisibles, why hold onto the
idea of an infinitely divisible temporal continuum? Wyclif concludes that
Aquinas gave in to the laws of man here and bent his theory of time to suit
the desires of his ecclesiastical superiors: “Who would believe this of such
a man?” It looks very much as if Wyclif is hinting that Aquinas would
have been more favorably inclined toward atomism than his followers had
wanted him to be. Wyclif is probably goading later Thomists, whom he
appears to have believed were using Aquinas for their own purposes.44
Piecing together Wyclif ’s temporal atomism and its relation to his rejec-
tion of the Thomistic version of transubstantiation will require a full
understanding of the contents of De Tempore, which he wrote twelve years
prior. The best we can do here is reason through the problem. Let us follow
Aristotle in holding that the accidents we perceive depend on some under-
lying substantial being. Up to time 1, that substantial being is bread. At
time 2, that substantial being is Christ. The use of “x” is a temporal place-
holder, and contains no ontological assumptions beyond what is given.
with a pure and spotless religion; God the Son, who, since he is the virtue
and wisdom of God, is daily blasphemed . . . God the Holy Spirit, who,
although by his great benevolence he wisely establishes a peaceful order
in his house, is thwarted by simoniacal corruption contrary to his plan.46
When he is not careful, Wyclif allows himself to slide from serious argu-
ment into ridicule, giving some sense of what it must have been like to
listen to him lecture when he was in high spirits. For example, later in
De Apostasia, while engaged in a catalog of theological authorities whose
thought would unweave the web of authority supporting transubstantia-
tion, he wanders into a discussion of papal authority. Many popes are too
quick to allow themselves to use their power for their own ends, he com-
plains, and they may even veer into madness:
The pope could fall into such a madness as to believe that the entire rest
of the world depends on his willing, in temporal as much as in spiritual
things . . . so that the church cannot be governed without it, so that not
only all sublunar corporeal bodies, but even all spiritual gifts, like grace
and the virtues, depend on him. This is as blasphemous as to believe
that the body of Christ is, in its nature, as imperfect as rat feces. The rat
is a melancholic animal, and the madness of philosophers grows from
melancholy; Magog is read in Genesis as having been the son of Joseph,
whose generation is said to have occupied the western territory, where
melancholy reigns.48
Comments like these certainly lead the reader to regard his continual avow-
als of willingness to be corrected by ecclesiastical authority with skepticism.
Given that the doctrine of transubstantiation is about Christ’s presence
in created being, it would be natural to expect the book assigned to sins
against God the Son to be devoted to more of the same. De Blasphemia
has a wider scope than De Apostasia, though; blasphemy is a detraction
from the honor due to God, in particular, when we attribute honor to
creatures which are due to God alone. Adoring the host is one aspect of
blasphemy, but so is honoring a man as one ought to submit oneself to
God. All are part of too great an allegiance to temporal, mutable things and
too little thought given to the spiritual. The triumph of Satan has turned
men’s minds from their spiritual welfare and toward fascination with the
mundane. His daughters, hypocrisy and tyranny, have enchanted men:
“And just as the thorny briar and the poisonous herb grows out of the earth
and perchance flourishes, despite many attempts to root them out, so it is
with the words of hypocrisy and tyranny.”49 The ecclesiastical hierarchy,
from pope down to verger, is as likely to be infected with this tendency as
any secular organization. And thus the treatise launches into the indict-
ment of clerical corruption, the misuse of office, and the priestly neglect of
134 john wyclif
the spiritual needs of the people that characterizes many of Wyclif ’s later
works. In De Blasphemia, foisting off bread as the body of the Savior is but
one of the ploys that clergymen use in furthering their worldly aims, albeit
one of the more pernicious ones.
Wyclif reiterated his eucharistic theology during the remaining six
years of his life, attacking transubstantiation in De Fide Sacramenti (a por-
tion of which was translated into English perhaps a year after its composi-
tion), in Trialogus, and finally in the section of Opus Evangelicum entitled
De Antichristo.50 The Opus Evangelicum is an extended commentary on
three selections from the Gospels; the first, Matthew 5–7, on the Sermon
on the Mount, is followed by De Antichristo, an exegesis on Matthew 23–25
and John 13–17. His criticism of transubstantiation here is a summary of his
earlier arguments against the doctrine, interlarded with vituperative com-
ments like “if these lying disciples of Antichrist would have us believe that
they annihilate substance when they bless it, perhaps we should ask rather
that they curse us at the benediction.”51 Still, he does not shy away from
discussions of the need for distinctions in kinds of identity and predication
in understanding the force of “this is my body,” repeatedly reminding his
reader of the arguments he made in De Eucharistia and De Apostasia.
Scholars have long argued about the relation of Wyclif ’s eucharistic
theology and his metaphysics, some holding that there is an important tie
between the two, others denying one. In arguing against this connection,
Maurice Keen has suggested that Wyclif was angrier with the clerical abuse
of a sacrament than with the ontological twisting the abuse involved, and
that he was angriest of all about how the “followers of Antichrist” misused
scripture to their own ends. In arguing for a connection, Gordon Leff has
held that Wyclif ’s realist system was the beginning point for an unavoid-
able collision with the ontologies that admitted transubstantiation. While
the intent of this chapter has been to show the tie between Wyclif ’s atom-
ism and his eucharistic theology, his overall position on the subject involves
scriptural hermeneutics as much as philosophy, and granting pride of place
to either “theology” or “philosophy” misdirects the force of Wyclif ’s thought.
Throughout his writings, he insisted that “the logic of Christ” is the proper
instrument with which to read scripture and to understand any theological
position. In this case of the Christ being asserted to be present in the elements
of a sacrament, the eternal word’s presence to those taking the sacrament
is at issue, and in Christ there is no room for an either-or relation between
theology and philosophy.52
5
135
136 john wyclif
Even before engaging in the reasoning that Holcot used to separate out
what is tenable to the human mind lacking faith from what is theologically
grounded, Wyclif argues, one must proceed on the assumption that all of
our reasoning has its basis in the authority of Christ. This is Augustine’s
approach, and Wyclif ’s admiration for it is as enthusiastic as is his antipathy
toward those who would sidestep its dedication to scripture’s centrality in
all reasoning: “In every case I am in conformity with both the logic and the
metaphysics of Augustine, which are all the more excellent for belonging to
Holy Scripture, the very first rule of all human perfection.”8 Anselm, Hugh
of St. Victor, Bernard, and Grosseteste are his authorities, and, he con-
tinues, they would certainly have agreed. Scripture is the source of every
valid system of logic and the eternal source of truth in creation. To under-
stand it, one must recognize that it has its own all-encompassing logic, and
devote oneself to learning it. And if there is a real connection between Holy
Scripture and the Christ himself, this logic of scripture must be tied to the
nature of the incarnation somehow. So, in this chapter, we will pursue this
connection between hermeneutics and incarnational theology.
would Wyclif make such a case for equating Christ’s nature with the Bible?
By 1378, when he was at work on DVSS, he suggests that the case has been
made: “I have often said that the entire Holy Scripture is the one word of
God, and that every one of its parts should be condensed into the totality
of that Word in whom the blessed in heaven see the multitude of truths
spoken by God.”9 He had argued this way at least as early as 1372 in De
Benedicta Incarnacione, when he considered the unlikelihood of a dissolu-
tion of the union of God and man in Christ. Following John 10:35–36 (as
it appears in the Vulgate: “ ‘Scripture,’ He said, ‘cannot be dissolved, which
the Father blessed and sent into the world’ ”), Wyclif reasoned that Christ
cannot mean the physical books themselves, because they can be destroyed
just like anything else. What the Father has blessed and sent into the world is
the incarnate word, and Christ’s words are self-referential.10 He carried this
relation between Bibles and Christ further, explaining that Bibles are sugges-
tive of a hypostatic union themselves. They are a union of the divine word
and parchment, just as Christ was the word made flesh. This does not mean
that we should worship Bibles, though. The material book is no more scrip-
ture than Jesus’ body was the Christ when it lay dead in the tomb.
Robert Grosseteste’s influence on Wyclif resonates in the idea that
Christ’s centrality to the very being of the Bible emerges as we trace the
evolution of God’s covenant with humanity. Grosseteste had written two
treatises central to his formal theology in the 1230s. In De Decem Mandatis,
Grosseteste gives a pastoral analysis of the Ten Commandments, with a
central focus on the implicit command to love God and our neighbors. The
accompanying, longer De Cessatione Legalium contains his account of the
evolution of the divine law given to man, from the Mosaic code of cer-
emony and behavior to the law of Christ, through which salvation is possible.
In both treatises, the development of law from commands given to subjects
to a code of love depends on the incarnation, in particular the passion and
resurrection. So, if scripture is the record containing this evolution of law,
Christ occupies the foremost position. Grosseteste explains in De Decem
Mandatis that love lies at the heart of all the teachings and laws of scripture,
citing Matthew 7:12 (“All things therefore whatsoever you would that men
should do to you, do you also to them. For this is the law and the prophets”):
“In these brief words the Lord gave the law of love, from which alone hang
all the laws and commands of the prophets.”11 In De Cessatione, Grosseteste
describes Christ’s primacy as lawgiver to all of humanity, as both the living
word of God and the perfect exemplar of the law of love: “So then with all
140 john wyclif
works of the good the Word is the eternal principle, just as was written [in
the prologue to De Decem Mandatis]: the foundation of all works [is] the
Word. For the life and the form of everything exterior to the Word that
proceeds by ordained, loving cognition, is the eternal Word of the Father
Jesus Christ.”12 Here, he distinguishes himself by arguing that the incarna-
tion would have occurred even without sin. As he had explained in his
Hexamaeron, his commentary on the creation, it was the necessary conclu-
sion to creation, completing the Neoplatonic return of all being to God:
“But when God became a human being, the God-man shared in a nature
with the rational creature in a univocal way, and the making of the circle
was perfect, and the circular return to God was joined up.”13 With this,
Grosseteste shifts the Christological emphasis on redemption from sin to
cosmological completion, allowing him to emphasize the “law of love” as
what binds the elements of creation. This motif lies at the center of Wyclif ’s
prolonged study of the law of scripture as the purpose for a revealed body
of truth.
Wyclif wrote De Mandatis Divinis, a treatise grounded firmly in these
two works of Grosseteste, in early 1376. Here, he takes this theme of Christ’s
loving command as the basis for all of the laws and teachings of scripture
and develops it as the basis for understanding his relation of Christ to scrip-
ture. Contained within every word of scripture, Wyclif argues, is an under-
lying truth that was known before the Fall. Now, because of our damaged
faculties, it must be written: love of God is our first and final duty, which
when carried out, will unite all creatures in harmonious concord. The
core of De Mandatis Divinis is five chapters that he calls “the more pleasant
treatise on love,” a development of Grosseteste’s discussion of love in De
Decem Mandatis. Wyclif argues that the command to love God with all your
heart, soul, mind, and strength of Deuteronomy 6:5–9, echoed in Matthew
22:37–40, is the primary rule for all created being, the foundational precept
for all human endeavor, and the chief scriptural truth. All of the virtues
that Aristotle describes, as well as the theological virtues, have the com-
mand to love God as their necessary condition. Without this absolute sub-
mission of the self to God, a right ordering to the rest of created being is
impossible. Our first urge, he explains, is to know that which we are created
to love, so more than anything, we need knowledge of God. God may be
comprehended, and so loved, in three ways. The blessed receive intuitive
awareness in paradise, philosophers achieve a discursive awareness through
philosophical reasoning, and the simple Christian gains God through simple
the logic of scripture 141
faith. The infidel, who balks at elevating the mind to a love of that which
surpasses empirical evidence, cannot hope to lead a properly ordered life.
His virtuous behavior is accidental at best.
Naturally, Wyclif takes this opportunity for a riposte at the moderni,
who reject the possibility of theological knowledge of God grounded in cre-
ated being, and at the Thomists and Scotists, who reject illuminatio as the
basis for understanding God. Regarding the latter, who think that theology
is possible from the created order, Wyclif suggests that their way, taken in
itself, has limited value:
But since nothing is loved unless known, it is clear that the true order
of knowing God leads the reason into His love, and although from
creatures they take philosophically evident knowledge of God . . . the
way is more compendious and more certain in which, following the
exemplary reasons or the intelligible being of creatures, it ascends
to God.14
Regarding the moderni, who imagine that knowledge of the sensible order
of created being is grounded in empirical evidence, Wyclif is less forgiving.
To gain knowledge of a thing simply for the sake of having knowledge of
that thing is intellectual fornication, or using a means as an end unto itself.
We are to know creatures as a means to know, and love, God. In words
certainly meant to evoke Romans 13:13, and so the climactic moment of
Augustine’s Confessions, he equates moderni empiricism with wanton cham-
bering: “Not in contemplating the tumultuous cares of the world, nor the
subject spirit’s collisions with fantasmata, to which the imagination is led
hurriedly here and there, nor indeed to the passions of the body, but by
quiet speculation is the highest good contemplated.”15
We should begin our knowledge, and love, of God, in the way Anselm
had suggested in Proslogion 5. Reasoning from the idea of a being greater
than which cannot be conceived to recognition of its necessary existence
outside the mind leads us to recognize God as the “most useful, most beau-
tiful, and most delectable” being, the supreme good. Plunging from this
pinnacle of being down to created being is madness. When we recognize
the absolute nature of God, our first instinct should be to seek the reasons
of things in the world in the divine. Rather than try to understand the con-
tents of God’s mind from things as they exist in the world, we should use
our reason to touch the divine ideas, which are “so necessary [to created
being] that without knowledge of them, no one would be wise, nor as a
142 john wyclif
Many viators should carefully study the Gospel in that language in which
the sentences of the evangelists are most clear, because from faith all the
faithful should follow the lord Jesus Christ, and however many will have
followed Him, that many and more love Him meritoriously. Since, then,
the story of Christ is even more fully expressed than His doctrine, it is
clear how carefully the faithful ought [to] study this book.16
The story of Christ’s life, the center of scripture for medieval exegetes,
is as important to the viator as are his teachings. Christ gave his law, the
most perfect vehicle for loving God available to us, in the manner of his life
as well as in his teachings. This gift does not dissolve the law of the Jews,
Wyclif says, following Grosseteste’s De Cessatione. It completes it. He gives
two examples, one from the world of objects, and the other from the world
of words. Imagine a house the foundation of which is the eternal truths of
God’s mind. The stones of its walls are the laws of Moses, and the mor-
tar binding them together is love and grace. This is the law of Christ, he
explains, a house that will stand for as long as time endure. Now consider
the letter i (iota). In its form, it is the simplest of letters, without twist, bend,
or break. In the same way, the chief commandment to love God is the most
brief and direct, without possibility of misinterpretation. The dot on the
letter, the simplest of all written marks, is equivalent to all letters figura-
tively, and so denotes all of the other laws of God in the figurative sense.
One needs the industry of a bee to study scripture, and an understanding of
the logic of scripture 143
In the first, the word clothed himself with human nature as a man wears
a cloak. This is the habitus theory, suggested by Augustine. In the sec-
ond, a man composed of body and soul was assumed by the word so that
he became identical with the word. This is the assumptus homo theory,
endorsed by Hugh of St. Victor and Anselm. In the third, Christ begins
to be composed of divinity, along with body and soul, in a subsistence
relation. This appears to have been Lombard’s approximation of the posi-
tion of Gilbert of Poitiers.18 Aquinas understood both the habitus and the
assumptus homo position to have been condemned by Alexander III in
1170 and 1177, and he supposed that any theory in which Christ’s human-
ity is described as accident was heretical. In the second general group,
including Bonaventure, Giles of Rome, Henry of Ghent, and Scotus, the
theologians used a substance-accident model, where Christ’s humanity is
related to the word as an accident or property is related to its substance.
Ockham’s ontology, where “humanity” is a concept naturally referring
to a concrete individual or individuals, denies any further reality to what
his predecessors called universals. In his pared-down ontology, Ockham
rejected the existence of a common nature like humanity apart from indi-
vidual people. But this easily leads to understanding him to have held
that in Christ was an individual human person in addition to the divine
nature, making up either a two-person person (that is, the human person
Jesus and, with the added word, the person of the Christ), or a Christ in
which a human person and the divine person of the word are not united
by anything into a third composite. Both suggest the Nestorian heresy,
and despite his arguments, many opponents of Ockham interpret him as
a Nestorian.19
After Ockham, both Holcot and Adam Wodeham wrote on incarna-
tional theology. Wodeham’s Oxford Lectures of 1332 and several of Holcot’s
Quodlibeta suggest a sustained interest in Christology among the moderni.
These works are not yet edited, and may prove to be a gold mine for post-
Ockham incarnational theology at Oxford. Wyclif ’s contemporary Nicholas
Aston, who was by no means Ockhamist in his theology, also lectured on
Christological questions, but what survives of Aston’s work in this vein is
unedited as well. The major secular figures among Wyclif ’s predecessors,
Walter Burley and Thomas Bradwardine, leave no record of contributing
to the debate. Burley’s Sentences commentary, if he produced one, has never
been identified, while what remains of Bradwardine’s does not touch sig-
nificantly on the incarnation’s metaphysics.20 Of the Franciscans, Walter
the logic of scripture 145
It appears more likely that “this man” communicates more than “this
body and this animal” for it communicates “this spirit,” which remains
[a] human spirit existing as such, even when it no longer remains a body
or an animal. It is not the case that these two [spirit and body] are the
same animal or the same body in number, for the prior corporeal nature
is a body and yet is not thereby an animal. Since man is all three [body,
soul, and integrated body + soul], he exists, after his body is dead, by vir-
tue of the prior corporeal nature, and he is a composite, prior to being an
animal, according to his corporeal nature and the soul.21
[F]or the person or for the substance, which is any of these three natures
or things, or indeed all beings contracted [together], which is each of
them, and in this way the faith speaks from Scripture that this Man, who
created heaven and earth, was born of a virgin, conversed with men,
suffered, died, and was buried, descended to hell, and ascended, etc. Not
according to the assumed nature did He create the kingdom, nor accord-
ing to Deity did He suffer, nor according to His soul was He dead and
buried, nor according to His body or other integrated nature did He
descend to hell, but since the same person was all these, according to one
of these He did one, and according to another He did the rest, just as it
was best suitable.22
becoming the integrated whole (word + humanity) and each of its parts.
The number of parts varies, depending on how you count the elements
and the composites that arise from them, which in Wyclif ’s account, can
be dizzying in their complexity. Many of the difficulties that arise in the
Christologically oriented study of scripture can be avoided by remember-
ing that “there are three incommunicable natures in Christ: deity, body, and
soul. This is clear in this way. Christ is God and perfect man, as supported
by the faith: God is wholly deity, and the perfect man is wholly as much
body as soul.”24 While any individual member of the species is body, soul,
and the aggregate (body + soul), Christ differs through the addition of deity
to these three components, although this in no way affects the truly human
nature of Christ. The word assumed not a human nature, but humanity
as such. Perhaps the right approach is to imagine that deity, the universal
divine nature shared by the persons of the Trinity, needs something more
than a human nature to offset its magnitude in the Christ: the balance is
achieved by the word’s assuming humanity as such.
In the medieval play Everyman, Death causes the eponymous character
to go from carefree ignorance of his place in creation to an awareness of
his need for good deeds and the sacraments. Death says, “Every man I will
beset that liveth beastly / Out of God’s laws, and dreadeth not folly. . . . Lo,
yonder I see Everyman walking; / Full little he thinketh on my coming.”25
Wyclif makes a jump similar to the one Death has just made. He argues that,
if every man would be Everyman, then Everyman would only be one man,
and if Christ assumes humanity, then Christ, too, would be Everyman.26
It cannot be that Christ is every man, of course, nor that Christ is more
than one man, nor can the universal humanity itself be a man capable of
receiving accidents like individual men. What Wyclif means is that Christ
has the same kind of body and soul as all other men have. In assuming the
universal, he did not become the being of the universal by which all of its
particulars have their being. There need be no posited haecceity by which
individualization occurs for Wyclif, and there need be no additional indi-
viduating element added to the hypostatic union of the word and human-
ity. In assuming humanity, Christ did not assume every relation that holds
between the universal and its particulars.
Wyclif proceeds from the being of Christ into creation by means of the
truth he defines. In De Veritate Sacrae Scripturae, he describes five grada-
tions, or equivocations, by which we can understand the identity of Christ
with scripture. First is the Book of Life, described in Revelation 20:12,
148 john wyclif
who realizes this ideal, just as they define the Lord’s Prayer, which Christ
teaches in Matthew 6:
Familiar concerns soon surface. With Matthew 5:13, “You are the salt
of the earth,” we see Wyclif returning to the threats facing the church. He
begins by taking Bede’s approach, with a discussion of salt’s formation from
“sand and water and the heat of the air, compacted by blowing air,” and
its properties of desiccating and flavoring food. This signifies good priests,
who at one time may have come from shifting sand, but have been trans-
formed by the waters of baptism and the fires of divine ardor, and whitened
in purity. When this salt is mixed with the earth, the earth becomes sterile.
In the same way, when priests come into contact with mundane evil, their
purity nullifies its powers. As salt desiccates meat, keeping it from putre-
faction, so too the priest can keep his flock from the corrosion of sin, the
stink of defamation, and the corruption of the devouring worm. But if the
salt should lose its taste, if the priest should be caught up in the very tem-
poral desires he is meant to overcome, then he becomes useless and is best
trampled underfoot. The clergymen who turn to avarice or lust hasten the
spread of sin throughout the church. The best course is to fight the threat
by relieving priests and bishops of any source of temptation: “It would be
meritorious for someone to lovingly relieve our clerics from temporal dig-
nities, so that, made spiritual, they could regard the law of God.”35
The unmistakable form of Aristotelian philosophy gives shape to Wyclif ’s
account of Christ’s teachings throughout. The virtues by which one realizes
happiness both in this life and in the next define the normative commands of
Jesus. Not for Wyclif the mystic elevation from scholastic reason, nor the
ineffable encounter with the godhead, nor even the prospect of a journey of
the mind to God through love of the visible creatures of the world. Despite
being an advocate of the illumination theory of understanding and a devoted
adherent of the connection of every created particular to its divine idea, the
Bonaventuran spiritual approach is foreign to Wyclif. His Beatitudes are the
means by which the virtues are perfectly realized, by which body and soul
are placed into the balance for which they were created, and ultimately by
the logic of scripture 153
which the church can best function on earth. Benrath comments that, for
Wyclif, the Golden Rule is the rational basis for all Christian morality. Love
should be sought not because the loving soul realizes Christ’s ongoing rela-
tion to creation, but because it best aligns every soul with the purposes for
which they were created: “What the Square of Opposition is to logic, thus
the Golden Rule is to ethics.”36 For Wyclif, the New Testament does indeed
provide a road map for the soul’s journey to God, but it is a map defined by
justice and reasoned truths for communal use, not one by which the soul
necessarily enters into the holy otherness of the divine.
Is this a fair judgment? After all, one rarely finds the spiritual path to
mystic union with God from a concise scripture summary, which is only a
tool for preachers and scholars. Benrath’s assessment is accurate, though, as
a reliable guide through Wyclif ’s exegetical works. A good instance is the
brief, later work De Amore (1383). Here, in an apparent response to a request
for an explanation of the nature of love, Wyclif delivers a terse, reasoned
response. True love, he explains, is a movement of the will toward a given
subject, the ideal of which is God. Hence, only those for whom God is the
object of the will experience true love. Lovingly studying the law of God
lies at the base of such a life, and the laws of Christ lie at the base of a loving
understanding of the ideal object of the will. All of the teachings of the Old
and New Law are summed up in Christ’s teachings, interconnected and
made into a perfect whole to be realized by diligent study. But which state of
life is most proper for a man to love God? This depends on whether one is a
priest, a soldier, or a laborer. Ideally, the states most suitable are those of the
virgin and of the priest, as was Jesus, but “for some men, one state is right,
for others, another is right.” The important thing is that every man should
study the gospel “in that tongue in which the reasonings of the evangelist
are most clear, because all the faithful should follow their Lord Jesus Christ
from faith, and insofar as they are able to follow Him in a like manner, thus
the more meritoriously will they love Him.” Perhaps the best expression of
this love is martyrdom, a total giving of the self to God, but for those for
whom this is not an option, a communal life in Christ is the best choice.37
Opus Evangelicum
While Wyclif believed that the Gospels comprise the perfect clothing for
the soul of the Christian, he felt some parts to be more important than
154 john wyclif
organization, and finally, the work ends with some parting words for theo-
logians, perhaps written within a week of his death:
It is necessary that a theologian be instructed in right logic, philosophy and
metaphysics, and that he have these five pieces of armor at hand: first that
he know universals apart from things, through which he can know the
words Moses spoke of genus and species. . . . Second he should know the
teachings of Christ according to right metaphysics of the nature of time and
other accidents, how they do not exist unless as formal and accidentally
inherent dispositions of their subject. And through this he can under-
stand the distinction of the nine kinds of accident and how Augustine
rightly teaches that from his youth he had taught that it is not possible
for an accident to be without a subject. And this confounds the heresy
that consecrated host could be accident without underlying subject, or
a nothing. Third that he knows that with God and the creating spirit
everything that was or will be are present to Him in the greatness of
time. . . . Fourth, that he know that a creature has in God ideal eternal
being existing in its kind antecedently. . . . And fifth that he know the
natural essence to be perpetual and not composed of quanta, and mate-
rial forms to be its dispositions, although they would be quiddities of the
species and the genus. And through this it can be known how God sees
everything that He [has] made and they [are] very good, how one ele-
ment will remain, although substantial form[s] which are material acci-
dents would be renewed. Through these five with their appendices the
subtle logician can theologically defend the catholic text of Scriptures.38
Wyclif ’s sources are the core of his treatment of the Sermon on the
Mount and, given their authors, warrant some attention. Woven into the
Beatitudes are the guiding words of Augustine and Chrysostom, two pillars
of right exegetical and preaching practice. But aside from Augustine and
his De Sermone Domini in Monte, Wyclif ’s sources turn out to be people very
different from these models of orthodoxy. Chrysostom’s Opus Imperfectum,
a collection of sermons on Matthew cited at length throughout Wyclif ’s
exposition of the Sermon on the Mount, would seem a logical choice for
an exegesis of the Gospel of Matthew. The Opus Imperfectum was a widely
used source for later medieval exegetes, as is clear by the wealth of manu-
scripts remaining, but by the time it was included in Migne’s collection of
Chrysostom’s works in the Patrologia Graeca, it was clear that it could not
have come from Chrysostom’s hand. It has turned out to be a sermon col-
lection written by an anonymous Arian cleric of the fifth century, likely
156 john wyclif
from the region of the southern Danube. Its Arianism is negligible in the
selections Wyclif cites, and any medievalist knows that spurious sources
like these were common. Because Lollards were very glad to make use of
sources that Wyclif favored, particularly in Opus Evangelicum, citations
from the Opus Imperfectum were relatively common in their sermons.39
Much more interesting is an odd piece that Wyclif attributes to Augustine,
entitled De Duodecem Abusivis Saeculii (De XII ), the centerpiece for his han-
dling of the Beatitudes. The bulk of Wyclif ’s efforts are devoted to correlat-
ing the nine groups Christ lists as “blessed” with the twelve threats to the
Christian kingdom described in De XII. The treatise is a catalog of the moral
evils that plague humanity. Six of these affect the lives of every Christian,
including clerical hypocrisy, the immoral behavior of social leaders, rebel-
lious youth, widespread avarice, sexual prurience, and incompetent nobles.
The remaining abuses target specific evils in the body politic: strife among
Christians, rebellious peasants, wicked kings, negligent bishops, schismatic
sects, and people who have turned away from religion. The list seems ide-
ally crafted for fourteenth-century England, and Wyclif likely treasured the
text for its seemingly perfect intersection of Augustinian authority and the
social and ecclesiastical diagnoses at which he himself had arrived. So appo-
site are its critiques to Wyclif ’s own thought that one wonders why De XII
plays no part in his other works. Its hefty authority and pungent phrases
might have added just the right force to his critiques of the papacy, the fri-
ars, the bishops, and the unraveling social order. However, De XII might not
have been available to Wyclif until 1383, since its general structure would
have fit very nicely with the twelve torments of the church described in De
Blasphemia, written shortly after the Peasants’ Revolt of 1381.
Perhaps Wyclif suspected the truth about the treatise. It is not Augustine’s
work, as anyone familiar with his polished Latin style would recognize
instantly. De XII was written by someone with a much more primitive style,
and was attributed as much to Cyprian as to Augustine. It was an extremely
popular work, mined by preachers throughout the Middle Ages for pithy
images and succinct indictments of a failed social order. Manuscripts have
been found with the text in Old and Middle English, Castilian Spanish,
Latin, and Irish, from Scandinavia to Byzantium. While its author remains
anonymous, scholars agree that it likely dates to seventh-century Ireland
and is perhaps the work of a Benedictine well read in Isidore of Seville and
Jerome, among many others. Its prevalence in Irish manuscripts lent it to be
attributed to St. Patrick, but this is very unlikely.40
the logic of scripture 157
It is clear in practice how one pope curses the other with the utmost
severity, which is a sign that the pope who curses the other more lightly
is less cursed by God. Both reveal themselves in doing this, and infi-
nitely many other things, not to be vicars of Christ but chief vicars of
antichrist.41
Beatitudes express the essence of lex Christi: “Since the whole Christian
religion is founded in this love, it is clear how it is the work of any believer
to learn this art of loving, in which the whole salvation of man rests, and
[which is] the reason of every good thing.”43
“Christ’s law would in itself suffice to regulate the entire church militant
better than it is ruled through artificed human tradition. . . . the Sermon
on the Mount should suffice to rule viators perfectly without any human
tradition.”44 While Benrath’s assessment is of the Postilla, it applies equally
to the much more detailed Opus Evangelicum. Along with the philosophical
reduction of Christ’s teachings to the fundamental, rationally self-evident
precept of the Golden Rule, to which Wyclif repeatedly reduces the contents
of Matthew 5–7, we also find stern injunctions to root out those social evils
that keep us from realizing this. Christ gave us a renewed natural domin-
ion through his victory over death, yet his church continues to embrace
sin and death, Wyclif declares. Taking the salt that has lost its flavor and
trampling it underfoot is not an empty metaphor, it is a call to action. The
church must be cleansed of its impurities, divested of the cares that keep it
from realizing the ongoing perfection of lex Christi, and secular lords are
the ones to do the work.
Our brief description of one part of Wyclif ’s extensive exegesis has bor-
rowed heavily from the tone of all of his exegetical works. The threats that
Wyclif devoted himself to uncovering—the unruly cleric, the immoral
noble, the dissolute bishop, and the schismatic sect—are never far from his
mind as he explicates the reasonableness of Christian morality. Neither is
his conviction that no part of scripture is greater than the rest in embody-
ing God’s word. A study of Wyclif the exegete, a very welcome addition to
scholarship, will involve both the theoretical elements of De Veritate Sacrae
Scripturae and the applied exegesis of De Mandatis Divinis, the (still largely
unedited) Postilla, and the Opus Evangelicum.
and are divisible into two distinct groups. The larger collection makes
up the first three volumes, which were likely compiled during Wyclif ’s
last years in Lutterworth, perhaps as a homiletic manual for the band of
preachers he seems to have been organizing. They certainly do not seem to
have the popular appeal one would expect from a preacher sensitive to the
needs of ordinary listeners, as they contain arguments for predestination
and the true nature of the church, frequent interjections of pastoral the-
ology, and vituperative indictments of academic practices. It is likely that
this collection, with 120 sermons on the Gospels and 58 on epistolary read-
ings, was meant as the practical application of Wyclif ’s pastoral program
as described in De Veritate Sacrae Scripturae, De Officio Pastoralis, and Opus
Evangelicum.47 Wyclif himself described this collection as the product of his
last years:
And so that the teaching of God be more distinct and his servant bet-
ter exempted from uselessness, it appears that in this quiet in which we
are at leisure from scholastic affairs, we are roused, in the end of our
days, into the building of a portion for the church, to collecting simple
sermons for the people, so that things they might recognize in the right
teaching of Christ be better known, and things be avoided by which will
have slid away from the catholic truth.48
succumbing to the temptation to return evil for evil. Mallard notes that this
injunction to patient acquiescence to temporal evil also entails a willingness
to engage in fraternal correction. A good and faithful Christian will not
shrink from admonishing a fellow for moral lapses for fear of a reputation
for being difficult. If all Christians are equal heirs of a restored natural
dominion, no one can shirk in upholding lex Christi, whatever their earthly
station. It is one thing to suffer the injustice of a powerful temporal lord,
but quite another to ignore priestly tyranny.
All of this suggests that Wyclif had the same audience in mind for both
sets of sermons. Sprinkled throughout the Forty Sermons are reminders
that preaching the word lies at the heart of the priest’s life. Preaching well
requires not simply a sound understanding of scripture, but a sober demeanor,
forceful delivery, and awareness of the needs of the audience.49 Just as in the
parable of the sower, seed carelessly strewn onto rocky soil, or to the crows,
will fail to grow, no matter its great potential, and so it is with sowing the
word of God. This familiar parable from Luke warrants two disparate ser-
mons in this collection. The first, Sermon 30, is a sober consideration of the
preacher’s need to steer away from sin in his own life and to fearlessly face it
down in the lives of his flock. The sin lying at the base of every other is pride,
and Wyclif devotes the bulk of his message to warning against its insidi-
ous way of sneaking into one’s thoughts, slipping in among praiseworthy
ideas and emotions and planting the seeds that sprout quickly into thorns
that choke out the word of God. Reading it, one cannot help but suspect
that Wyclif had some familiarity with this vice. The next sermon is a tour
de force of Wyclif ’s preaching abilities, beginning with a survey of the lev-
els of meaning possible in the parable and fixing quickly on the connection
between sowing the divine seed and preaching the gospel. Preachers today,
Wyclif exclaims, have taken on the loathsome habits of the vainglorious dis-
play of learning, clever rhythmic schemes and metrical novelties, and a tire-
some reliance on silly stories. No wonder that the word does not have the
force it once had; its preachers have killed it with their worldly sophistica-
tion and gross popularizing. What once leaped and danced gracefully as the
simple, sweet word of God has become a ponderous beast, or worse, is now
like a reanimated cadaver, lurching out of the grave to wreak havoc among
the living. Readers who sigh at Wyclif ’s tendentious and dusty prose in his
theological and political works would do well to investigate his sermons.
His voice remains the same, but freed of the constraints and formal require-
ments of the schools, his sermons can be zestful, even entertaining.50
the logic of scripture 163
holiness of the pastor and the wholesomeness of his teaching.” Friars who
seek money, priests and bishops concerned with temporal status, and prel-
ates enamored of political authority, from priests to popes, are all incapable
of perceiving their own cupiditas, their own inability to live as shepherds of
Christ’s flock. A good pastor does not shrink from telling his flock about
this danger and should expect his flock to be vigilant accordingly: “The
faithful conclude that when a curate is notoriously negligent in his office,
they as subjects should, yea ought, to withdraw offerings and tithes from
him and whatever might be the occasion for fostering such wickedness.”53
This warning, which recurs throughout Wyclif ’s writings, lies at the base
of the accusations of Donatism against him, which we will consider in the
next chapter.
The friars are usually the object of Wyclif ’s criticism in his homiletic
teachings. Time and again, if he inveighs against some bad preaching habit,
it’s likely to be a hallmark of fraternal preaching. They school their preach-
ers to develop an entertaining delivery and to put minimal emphasis on
the need for penitence. They manipulate their preaching venues to garner
the largest offerings from their audiences and avoid those where funds are
scarce. Such a preacher happily tells his audience what they want to hear,
all the while handing around the collection plate, bilking the very souls for
whom he pretends to care. Wyclif comments that the friars’ habit of using
frivolous stories in preaching appears to come from a deliberate refusal to
take Christ’s sewing advice in Matthew 9:16. They are willing to attach
themselves to their sect, which is a patch ready to unravel at the seams
from the fabric of the church, and so delight in their “unseemly” stories.54
While an honest preacher goes no further than scripture for his meter and
rhythm, the friars consistently indulge in ornament and deride those who
do not as fools:
And thus with clamor and ornate words they overcome the faithful who
would speak the sense of God, and where God wills to have helpers for
the simple, and mild speaking, as the Apostle says with “We are God’s
servants,” they regard this with disdain, asking against the rule of love
for money, doing the devil’s work with frivolous tales and sophistication,
rather than the simple truth of the gospel.55
friars’ departure from lex Christi: “They use their preaching office to incite
the people to spill their blood in misguided crusades, like the fiasco led by
Bishop Spencer in Flanders, and this more for the money they can hope to
gain from the plunder!”56
looking at the evidence. Is there reason to believe that he was involved either
in the production of the eponymous Bible or with the storied russet-robed
preachers? As to Wyclif ’s having translated the Bible from Jerome’s Latin
into Middle English, an idea reported as commonly understood by Hus in
1411: this was laid to rest in Margaret Deansley’s The Lollard Bible in 1920.
Wyclif ’s disciples, chiefly Nicholas Hereford, were given the credit.
The second question has been more controversial. Workman’s 1926 biog-
raphy is dramatic:
Clad in russet robes of undressed wool reaching to their feet (a garb which
Wyclif had assumed at Canterbury), without sandals, purse, or scrip, a
long staff in their hand, dependent for food and shelter on the good will
of their neighbors, their only possession a few pages of Wyclif ’s Bible
(especially the gospel and the epistles for the day), his tracts and sermons,
moving constantly from place to place like the early Methodist preachers
on their “circuits”—for Wyclif feared as Wesley feared lest they should
become “possessioners,” tied to one place like a dog—given not “to fre-
quenting taverns, hunting or to chess,” but “to the duties which befit the
priesthood, studious acquaintance with God’s law, plain preaching of
the word of God, and devout thankfulness,” Wyclif ’s poor priests, like
the friars before them, soon became a power in the land.59
Workman’s depiction harks back to Thomas Walsingham’s description
of Wyclif ’s Oxford comrades wearing russet robes to demonstrate their
superiority, going barefoot to trample popular errors underfoot. But
Walsingham’s description lacks the approving tone of Workman; the
famous chronicler was a monk at St. Alban’s, and he thought that Wyclif ’s
teachings were venomous poison seeping into the body of Christ, espe-
cially given the violence of the Peasants’ Uprising in the summer of 1381.
Walsingham’s narration of the chaos spreading across the land attributes at
least some of the blame to Wyclif, given the reputation of one of the rebel-
lion’s leaders, the priest John Ball: “He taught the perverse doctrine of the
perfidious John Wiclyf, and the opinions that he held, and the insane lies,
and many other things it would take long to recite.”60 Wyclif ’s horrified
reaction to the uprising notwithstanding, the story of the russet-robed poor
preachers sent out to promulgate his reforming agenda would stand as long
as writers connected Wycliffite ideology with the Peasants’ Revolt. Thus,
mid-twentieth-century scholars found themselves searching for firmer evi-
dence than the assumptions made in biased contemporary sources and the
passing references in English works once thought to be Wyclif ’s. While
the logic of scripture 167
The myth had its foundation in more than just the frets of chroniclers,
though. Michael Wilks noticed that Wyclif ’s writings are filled with refer-
ences to the small number of his associates who saw the awful truth of the
church’s need for renewal and reform. While Wyclif certainly had the ten-
dency to view himself as a lonely, prophetic figure, his gestures toward “the
simple few who speak the truth,” the “unknown true priests in the world,”
as well as the fact that his sermons are unmistakably designed to instruct an
educated elite group of preachers, make certain the reality of a small num-
ber of “poor preachers.” Whether Wyclif hand-picked his disciples during
his years at Oxford, preparing them for evangelizing throughout the coun-
try, or whether it was a self-selecting group of Oxford scholars, given ben-
efices by their colleges in parishes across England, is beside the point.62 The
fact remains that an educated corps of preachers, likely also responsible for
the Wyclif Bible, did champion his ideas throughout England in the 1380s.
In one of Wyclif ’s sermons on the parable of the sower, he devotes consider-
able attention to the need for preachers to pay close attention to the ground
on which their words are cast, and his references to “my brothers” certainly
suggest that these earlier sermons could be evidence that Wyclif was con-
sciously organizing a band of educated preachers while still at Oxford. In
this sermon, dating to February 1376, Wyclif also refers to “your frater-
nity,” which was an unusual form for him to use. This is a common address
for papal rescripts, letters in which the pope answers specific requests with
the force of ecclesiastical law.63 Wyclif also uses this form in Sermons 37 and
38 from the same, earlier collection. Leaving aside, for now, the question of
tone in his use of a form of address normally reserved for popes, his audi-
ence must have had a degree of internal coherence to deserve being called a
fraternity. Whether this was simply because of collegiate ties, or something
more, remains open to speculation.
168 john wyclif
So, answering the second question remains a problem. On the one hand,
as Anne Hudson has commented, given that a fair number of educated
men set out from Oxford before or shortly after Wyclif ’s departure in 1381,
“it would seem perverse to maintain that Wyclif himself had nothing to do
with their activities.” On the other hand, as Gillian Evans has observed,
we have no texts explicitly outlining plans for organizing a band of poor
preachers written by Wyclif himself. All we have is the basis for an induc-
tive conclusion. If Wyclif had purposively organized a band of preachers,
there are numerous references throughout his works that would apply
well to them. For example, embedded in several of his sermons is what
appears to be a treatise describing the six yokes that bind people together
in the service of Christ. It is reasonable to assume that the sermons are
intended for an educated audience preparing to engage in their own hom-
iletics, not least because of the frequent excursions into homiletic theory
they contain. Here, Wyclif actually provides a handy outline for the extem-
poraneous preacher in need of a structure for a series of sermons outlining
the Christian life: “Since these six yokes are, by their lightness and smooth-
ness, able to be grounded in Scripture, evangelists animated by God ought
preach this order with zest and strength.”64 Still, his antipathy for what
he called “private religions,” which he viewed as nothing more than sects
founded on the charismatic force of a saintly personality, suggests some-
thing other than the founding of an order of preachers.65 A thorough study
of the content of Sermones will likely provide the best means of tackling this
question, which for now must remain unresolved.
6
Of the four major orders of mendicant friars in the medieval period, the
Carmelites laid claim to the earliest origins. The Dominicans, Franciscans,
and Augustinians (or “Austyns”) originated in the thirteenth century, as do
the first records of the Carmelites, but these earliest records point to a com-
munity of hermits on Mount Carmel in Israel dating to the time of Elijah.
John the Baptist, say the Carmelites, was a member of this ancient and
honored community, and St. Anne, mother of the Virgin, had sought their
advice. There had been Carmelites at Pentecost, and they had worn their
white cloaks with pride, until Muslims conquered the holy lands, when
they had to shift to a black-and-white-striped habit. This mythic history
seems to have been well received, since the number of Carmelite houses
in England increased from six to twenty-seven in the second half of the
thirteenth century.1 Not only were they daring in making historical claims
questionable even to sympathetic popes, they were relentless in their criti-
cism of Wyclif ’s views of the church and its ordering. One of the earliest
records of the tempestuous events of Wyclif ’s career was given the pro-
vocative title Fasciculi Zizianorum Vuiclevi, or The Bundle of Wyclif ’s Weeds.
Following the parable in Matthew 13:36–43, where Jesus likens evildoers to
the weeds that will be separated out at the harvest and cast into the fire, the
English Carmelite friars began gathering up records of Wyclif ’s arguments
169
170 john wyclif
to permit universal agreement with the proposition that “all that is in scrip-
ture is truth”?
Kenningham argued, as do most twenty-first-century scripture scholars,
that sensitivity to the human hands behind the Gospels is a central part of
appreciating biblical truth, while Wyclif stoutly defends the self-evidence
of its truth by reason of its divine authorship.3 Lying behind their debate
was Kenningham’s great distaste for Wyclif ’s contention that all that is,
was, or will be is immediate to God’s understanding. The absolute necessity
of God’s knowledge of all created events, Wyclif believed, involved every-
thing being immediately present to God’s cognition. This rules out the pos-
sibility of counterfactuals that lead one to conclude that “it might have been
otherwise,” objected Kenningham, who pushed for nuance in describing
God’s understanding. Better to say that things in time are present to God
subjectively, as something is present in a mode of time, rather than in the
immediate clarity of objective understanding. This prevents us from rea-
soning that “A is known by God, therefore A is,” which, at the least, endan-
gers human freedom. The appeal of the idea for Wyclif, though, lies in the
ties possible between eternal divine ideas, the universals to which they cor-
respond in creation, and created particulars, on the one hand, and the Book
of Life (another way of referring to the divine ideas), scripture, and truth in
creation, on the other. If all created truth is tied directly to scripture, as we
noted in chapter 5, and scripture is a particular of the Book of Life, a certain
degree of determinism will be unavoidable.
While Kenningham’s objections are more to what follows from Wyclif ’s
hard-headed hermeneutic than to the implications of his determinism, he
felt that Wyclif ’s readiness to transcend temporal limitation in interpreting
scripture was impracticable in the church. Even more problematic were its
implications for understanding sentences like “Now you are the body of
Christ and individually members of it” (1 Corinthians 12:27). By Wyclif ’s
reasoning, God knows to whom “you” refers, and to whom it does not,
down to the last member. This makes defining the church as the elect,
those eternally foreknown to merit salvation, and no one else, a natural
conclusion. Wyclif is clear about this: “Although the church is mentioned
many times in scripture, I suppose that it can be taken most famously by
the proposition, the congregation of the faithful.”4 This definition, with its
roots in Augustine’s thought, was foundational to the medieval church.
Wyclif ’s position, as it will be articulated in this chapter, turns out to be
an attempt at mediating between the fatalistic determinism he perceives in
172 john wyclif
so God knows that it contingently will be, for if He knows it, He can not
know that it will be.” Ockham was aware that what he was suggesting,
while certainly preserving the freedom of human willing and action, could
easily be understood to restrict the range of God’s knowledge, and he admit-
ted, “it is impossible to express clearly the way in which God knows future
contingents; nevertheless, it must be held that He does, but contingently.”6
Ockham’s resolution of the puzzle was not necessarily a departure from
earlier thinkers like Grosseteste or Peter Lombard, but in his delicately
nuanced treatment of the relation of God’s eternal knowledge and the contin-
gency of action in time, it seemed that we might be able to earn salvation on
our own merit, without grace. In short, it was possible to interpret Ockham’s
approach as countenancing elements of Pelagianism. Bradwardine describes
it this way:
When I was applying myself to the study of philosophy, I was foolish and
empty of the knowledge of God, and was seduced into error. When I
heard theologians discuss this matter, the part of the Pelagians appeared
more true to me. In the schools of the philosophers, I rarely heard any
talk of grace, unless perchance through equivocation, but all the time I
heard that we ourselves are the lords of our actions, and that it is in our
power to do good and evil, to have virtue and vices, and many simi-
lar things. And if, in church, I ever heard a reading from the Apostle
explaining grace, as in Romans 9, “Not on [human] willing or exertion,
but on the mercy of God,” and such like, it grated on me mightily. With
the Manichees I believed the Apostle in his humanity to have deviated
from the path of truth, just as anyone might have done.7
Bradwardine appears to have come to this realization as he began his
theological studies in the late 1320s. His first approach to the question
of God’s foreknowledge and future contingents can be found in some
recently discovered Sentences commentaries, dating to 1332–1334, and in
the more developed De Futuris Contingentibus, which was written several
years later. Bradwardine’s interest in the subject developed, and after he
had become a member of de Bury’s circle, he compiled De Causa Dei, a
labyrinthine refutation of “the Pelagians.” This massive work is not con-
structed along a recognizably scholastic model, but appears instead to be
a summa encompassing all that Bradwardine understood to be involved in
explaining grace, merit, human salvation, and God’s knowing and will-
ing. Unlike Aquinas’s Summa, Bradwardine’s does not proceed methodi-
cally and logically; instead, each topic Bradwardine addresses finds its way
predestination and the church 175
back to God’s unmediated causal influence over creation. Topics that do not
interest him, particularly metaphysical questions of ontology or epistemol-
ogy, rarely arise. He appears to have had no interest whatsoever in the ques-
tion of universals, for example, and questions of how terms or propositions
express created or divine truths do not arise. Earlier readers have supposed
that Bradwardine’s departure from the logico-semantic approach of the
Ockhamists represents a reactionary Augustinianism, but this fails to take
into consideration his earlier, mathematically oriented thought, including
his fully developed theory of signification in his treatise on insolubles of
1324. The more freely flowing theological arguments of De Causa Dei sug-
gest a polemicized summa, in which the reader is able to recover the nature
of more informal—but still extraordinarily complex—arguments in which
Bradwardine engaged during his years in Durham.8
At the heart of Bradwardine’s theology is the fundamental truth that
God’s causal power over creation is absolute; nothing occurs that is not
willed by God. On the face of it, this seems so deterministic as to be fatal-
istic. If all that happens is in accord with God’s will, then the revealed
certainty that some will be damned and others saved amounts to double
predestination, the ancient heresy in which God has consigned some to hell
and others to heaven from eternity. Later theologians with a predilection
for determinism, particularly Luther, the Calvinists, and the Jansenists,
interpreted Augustine’s thought in this manner, and some philosophers
like Descartes and Nicolas Malebranche even espoused occasionalism, the
position that God directly causes every created occurrence, without created
agency playing any role. Bradwardine’s position was not so extreme. Even
if God is a co-agent in every created action, including the evil that men
do, he is neither responsible for evil nor is his foreknowledge the cause
of men’s damnation. Those who would warn theologians away from the
murky depths of this problem for fear of causing despair and abandonment
of the faith should know that only the shortsighted will suffer:
On the basis of such preaching a predestinate person grows in a use-
ful way; for he can know on the basis of it that if he is predestinate he
will be saved, and so he has more material for praising God than if
he were not to know the eternity of predestination and the eternity of
reprobation. . . . But all the same, it can allowably be left out [of preach-
ing] because of the simplicity of most men, since they can easily fall into
heresies by thinking a great deal on the difficult subject of whether they
are reprobate or elect.9
176 john wyclif
Augustine had argued that, just as our memory does not force the past to
have happened, so God’s knowledge does not force the future to happen, at
least as far as human sin is concerned. A problem arose with understand-
ing the prophets’ foretelling of Christ’s coming and his death, though. Was
Christ’s suffering and death necessary eternally by reason of something
that occurred in time, namely, human sin? Anselm explained that “there
is a necessity which precedes, being the cause for an actuality’s existence,
and there is a necessity which is consequent, being caused by an actual-
ity.”10 That is, there is a difference between saying “it is necessary that
Socrates sits,” meaning that Socrates cannot help but sit, and saying the
predestination and the church 177
same thing simply because Socrates has already taken a seat. The first rules
out Socrates choosing to sit, while the second simply describes what already
is true. Likewise, Anselm believed that God knows our sinning by conse-
quent necessity, the kind that follows from what already is true, and not by
the former, compulsive kind, called antecedent necessity.
Peter Lombard popularized a further distinction, between kinds of con-
sequent necessity. If it is necessarily true that “if God knows that man will
sin, then man will sin,” it follows that “if God knows that man will sin,
then man’s sinning is necessary” is also necessarily true. Aquinas would
argue that the first conditional statement, “if God knows that man will
sin, then man sins,” is true by “necessity of the consequent” (necessitas con-
sequentiae), but the second conditional statement, “if God knows that man
will sin, then man’s sinning is necessary,” is necessary conditionally (necessi-
tas consequentis). Human freedom is preserved, Aquinas argued, in the first
statement, because man’s sinning is not necessitated by God’s knowing. In
the second, freedom is compromised since the consequence follows neces-
sarily from the antecedent, and so instead of saying that the will of God has
a necessary relation to man’s sinning, it is better to say that it is necessary
by supposition. Aquinas introduced this kind of necessity in distinguish-
ing between the necessity by which a bachelor is an unmarried male, or
man is a rational animal, and the necessity by which Socrates sits. In the
latter, so long as he is sitting, he must necessarily be sitting, but he certainly
needn’t be sitting.11 This makes “if God knows that man will sin, then man
sins” true because the necessity in “man sins” is not inescapable, and not
brought about by God’s knowing, but entirely reliant upon the fact that,
so long as he is sinning, he must necessarily be sinning. Another way that
Aquinas clarifies the difference between kinds of consequent necessity, one
that Wyclif would favor, is by describing the freedom-threatening neces-
sity of “if God knows that man will sin, then man’s sinning is necessary”
as absolute necessity, and the necessity of the freedom-preserving “if God
knows that man will sin, then man sins” as necessity by supposition. So
long as man’s sinning is not necessitated by God’s knowing, but only by
man’s choice, the consequent necessity by which man sins is necessary by
supposition.
Unlike Aquinas, Bradwardine felt that necessitas consequentis, or abso-
lute necessity, is commensurate with God’s foreknowledge without leading
to a fatalistic determinism. Talk of God knowing a thing before it hap-
pens, or of a thing being necessary because God knows it ahead of time, is
178 john wyclif
Wyclif described, because losing track can too easily lead one to suspect that
he obscured the question of determinism with an ink cloud of distinctions.
He described necessity in four places: Logice continuacio I.11, De Logica
III.10, De Actibus Anime 1, and De Universalibus 14. Wyclif was not overly
consistent in his terminology in his catalog of types of necessity in these four
works, much to the frustration of anyone trying to formulate a coherent
Wycliffian modal philosophy. In the chapters in De Logica, he began by
distinguishing between what cannot not be by virtue of itself, or “primary
per se necessity” (i.e., God’s being) (A); that which cannot not be by virtue of
something outside itself, or “secondary per se necessity” (B); and things that
are necessary, but could have been otherwise, or “accidental necessity” (C).
In De Actibus Anime, he called the necessity of God’s being “simple, absolute
necessity” (A.1), and seems willing to include the world’s being, which by
Logice continuacio.11 would be secondary per se necessity (B), under the
heading “created absolute necessity,” suggesting a close tie between A and B.
(Here, he described the secondary per se necessity as “a created truth with-
out which God could not be,” the meaning of which he does not pursue.)
For our purposes, A and B seem to point to the kind of absolute necessity
that earlier philosophers had posited as distinct from necessity by supposi-
tion. What he described in. Logice continuacio11 as “necessary secundum
quid” appears to be the same as necessary by supposition in De Logica III.10
and in De Actibus Anime, and likely would correspond to accidental neces-
sity (C).14 In this category, Wyclif described antecedent (C.1), consequent
(C.2), and concomitant necessity (C.3) by supposition in the two sections of
De Logica and De Actibus Anime. In De Universalibus, suppositional neces-
sity is divided into “nonvolitional natural necessity,” “volition-dependent
natural necessity,” “agent compulsive natural necessity,” and “free neces-
sity.” Where did “natural” necessity come from? It seems to refer to C.1. In
Logice continuacio.11, Wyclif divided antecedent suppositional necessity
into “necessity of volition” (C.1.a), a willing that brings something about by
necessity; “necessity of nature” (C.1.b), as with fire burning anything com-
bustible; and “necessity of coercion” (C.1.c), when a force elicits a response
that rules out freedom. “Free necessity” (C.1.d) seems to point to an ante-
cedent necessity by supposition that lacks a defining force like a will or a
law, “free either in the sense of freedom between alternatives or of freedom
from compulsion.” Anthony Kenny described nine kinds of necessity in
his catalog of Wyclif ’s modal thought, but Wyclif himself suggested that
180 john wyclif
this could be the tip of the iceberg: “There are many other similar, non-
exclusive notional distinctions.”15
Consider the following argument:
1. If God eternally knows that Peter sins today, then Peter sins today.
2. God eternally knows that Peter sins today.
3. Therefore, Peter sins today.
Statement 1 is eternally true, and would be logically unavoidable, no mat-
ter what. This is an instance of absolute necessity because it is connected to
the necessity of divine omniscience (A.1). Likewise, the argument formed
by combining 1 and 2 leads directly to the conclusion according to modus
ponens. This argument is both valid and true by absolute necessity from
eternity, according to Wyclif ’s understanding of the nature of logic. All
logical, mathematical, and geometric truths are absolutely necessary (A.2).
Suppositional necessity is so called because everything depends on the
relation of the truth of one part of a proposition to another. An if-then
statement might not be an instance of relative necessity for a host of rea-
sons; both antecedent and consequent might be impossible, or contin-
gent, or even absolutely necessarily true. But the world is structured so
that many things that are necessarily true are so because of the truth of
something prior. Wyclif envisions a complex modal system to describe the
many sorts of necessary truths that derive their necessity from the relation
of one truth to another. Any given modal proposition, he explains, must
be dissected carefully prior to seeing how the whole statement works.
There is a world of difference between the assertion “Peter necessarily
sins” and “necessarily, Peter sins,” and this realm of suppositional neces-
sity is where this kind of care is needed. With antecedent suppositional
necessity (C.1), once the truth of the situation described as antecedent
is met, the consequent will necessarily come about; as with “God wills
Socrates to exist,” the truth of “Socrates exists” will necessarily follow. As
just mentioned, there are three species of antecedent necessity by supposi-
tion. The first, volitional, involves a willing that brings something about
by necessity, as with “God wills Socrates to exist” (C.1.a). Wyclif believes
this to be the critical issue in the problem of free will and determinism.
That God’s willing brings about Socrates’ existing is necessary, but that
Socrates might not have existed is also a real contingency. Likewise,
that God knows that Peter sins today may be necessary, but Peter’s sin is
not thereby inescapable. The necessity of the truth of statement 2 in our
predestination and the church 181
Once I had imagined it madness to speak this way, because I was bur-
dened by a young mind, and smitten with the mutability of corporeal
fantasmata, not conceiving of the priority and the coexistence of eternity
with time. . . . Error in this logic causes many to err in the matter of the
necessity of futures. Some suppose that every future is absolutely neces-
sary, perhaps because of foreknowledge, foreordination, or the determi-
nation of God. But this does not follow, since it can always be that God
did not know it thus; and as it is contingent for the world not to be, or
not to have been, it is as contingent for this soul not to be in the future,
indicating whatever that soul produces.17
J. A. Robson rightly points out that Wyclif charted his position on neces-
sity and contingency by tacking between Bradwardine’s De Causa Dei and
Fitzralph’s De Quaestionibus Armenorum. Fitzralph’s antipredestinarian
position appears to have been well established by the time he was called
upon to summarize the points of disagreement between the Western
church and the Armenian church in the early 1340s. Here, he articulates a
position akin to Bradwardine’s, but emphasizes the infallibility of scripture,
which gives him a moderating position between the profound doctor and
the moderni. In fact, his emphasis on scripture’s centrality to theological
argument would later inspire the Lollards to list him among their guiding
lights. In De Dominio Divino I.14–18, Wyclif relates Fitzralph as arguing
that Christ’s knowledge of futures was imperfect during his time on earth,
so that he could have preached inaccurately about the future. In effect, Peter
predestination and the church 183
might have gotten through that famous Thursday night without denying
Jesus, had he really tried. The temporally oriented Christ might have been
wrong about Peter’s denial, because otherwise Peter would have been fatally
compelled to sin. This nuanced understanding of prophetic statements and
Christ’s predictions, like the one made about Peter’s denial, gave Wyclif a
reason to implement the results of his modal theory in describing the rela-
tion of God’s knowledge and willing to human action.18 Of the treatises in
which Wyclif most fully articulates this position, De Intellectione Dei, De
Sciencia Dei, and De Volucione Dei (Summa de Ente II.1–3), only two have
been edited and published, and these from the poorer of the two extant
manuscripts. In the case of De Volucione Dei, the present edition is missing
chapter 12 and most of chapter 13. It is easy to get the sense that Wyclif ’s
zeal for explaining it all was beginning to flag by the time he was to weave
the elements of his philosophical theology into a coherent picture of God’s
dominion. As he begins his explanation of how our actions have causal
power over divine ideas, he grumbles, “I am certain that nobody may dis-
cover another solution of the argument of the necessity of futures, even if
he were to study diligently through a life as long as Methuselah’s.”19
If created action has a causative effect on God’s knowing, is it true also
to say that created willing might affect God’s willing? Wyclif is prepared to
argue that one can cause God’s willing, without imagining that God’s will
is within human power. The relation of God’s knowing and willing is so
close as to demand care to avoid both the fatalism of Bradwardine and the
voluntarism of the moderni. If God eternally knows that Peter denies Jesus,
in what sense does he will this? Wyclif explains that God’s will is a conse-
quence of Peter’s denial in the same way that the divine knowledge is: that
God will something about Peter’s denial is absolutely necessary, but that he
will that Peter denies Jesus is hypothetically necessary, and could have been
otherwise, had Peter not denied Jesus. There is a strong reciprocity holding
between God and creation, then. The creature has its being through the
divine idea that exists eternally. God has this eternal idea by virtue of the
temporal being that is realized as the creature lives in time:
Thus the logician concedes that for the instant of eternity, there is such
contingent willing completely caused, since in this measure it lacks the
creature’s [moving] causing. And this is consonant with the popular and
philosophical way of speaking in which it is truly said that God’s willing
is not satisfied before what He intends occurs.20
184 john wyclif
Behold, I fortify you from all evil, and suggest that under pain of certain
damnation, you shun it, since I have given you assistance through grace
by which to avoid Satanic temptation. Yet a condition of your liberty
is that you have free power to accomplish whatever you might wish,
whether good or evil. I will not incite you nor stir you to something, nor
permit anything evil, save the punishment of sin.21
While it is madness to imagine that God approves of our sinning, it does not
follow that God does not will sin. In fact, the main thrust of De Volucione
Dei is that God does will sin, but that he does not will the sinner to sin.
This runs against the scriptural assurance that God wills the salvation of
all mankind (1 Timothy 2:4), but there are many ways of construing such
a blanket statement. Paul might have meant all classes of men, rich and
poor alike, or he might have meant that God wills that all men ought to
be saved. Wyclif thinks the possibility that God wills all men’s salvation
insofar as each human being wills his or her own salvation is the most
likely. It also challenges the assumption that God’s will would not be per-
fectly free if it were in some way caused by something outside it, which is
Bradwardine’s position. In most cases, it is probably wiser to be quiet about
this around most people: “It seems expedient to me to be silent about such
things with the ill-educated and the common people, as much because they
are not disposed to addressing scripture’s subtlety as because of the sense
in which they might err heretically by supposing that God unduly or cul-
pably ordains things.”22 Should such questions arise, it is helpful to have
Paul’s analogy of a potter in mind (Romans 9:21). A pot cannot censure
a potter, if it is made to hold urine, even if it is made from the same lump
from which a wine jug is made. Likewise, a man cannot censure God,
even if created insufficient in his nature, because God created the mass of
humanity from nothing.
predestination and the church 185
Christ has remained the head of this church throughout its history, from
the beginning down to the present. Sadly, as the church has grown and
aged, it has become weaker than it once was:
Once the Elect so fully filled the Church Militant that few weeds could
mix in. . . . but after these, those who followed were much more thinly
dispersed, so that you would survey many a wayfarer before you would
find one of the Elect, as one after harvest seeking to find a cornstalk, with
one here, and another far away. From the blindness of stupidity, they
accept wayfarers who are thistles and other poisonous weeds as branches
of the Mother Church, when they really deserve to be eradicated as
members of the devil.27
This sentiment appears repeatedly throughout his writings, usually in
equally explicit language. Along those lines, those who would imagine
themselves to be safely among the elect do themselves a serious disservice:
From the faith of the Scripture it is clear that nobody can cease to be
a member of the holy mother church, or [cease to] be condemned in
perpetuity, and from this, those wayfarers unfamiliar with the revela-
tion of the apostles, who were told that they should not idly anticipate
that they are the head of the church or its members, do whatever they
would, and thereby contradict [their membership] with their life and
presumption.28
Acting as if scriptural injunctions against hypocrisy, greed, and selfishness
do not apply in every moral decision, even if apparently on behalf of the
church, is definitive of sin. The result is that those who do behave this way,
whether lay or ordained, are eternally known to be damned—but we can-
not lay claim to this kind of knowledge:
And it is clear how the prayers of the predestinate are infinitely better
than the prayers of the foreknown, since God, who cannot err in His
judgement, accepts the first to be infinitely better than the second. And
this we piously believe to be the reason why God willed the Elect and
the damned to be hidden from us in this life, so that we may escape the
urge to buy a priest’s prayers. If the ministering priest is of the Elect, or
this curate, priest or prelate is damned, the prayer and the merit of the
ministering priest is infinitely more valid than is the merit or prayer of
the other kind of priest. Who is so prudent as to buy with certainty?29
This is the kind of statement that led many to identify Wyclif with the
Protestantism that would evolve over a century after his death, or even with
predestination and the church 189
the ancient Donatist heresy. The very existence of the priestly office appears
up for questioning. If we cannot know who is damned, and who is saved,
why rely on a clerical class for sacraments? Indeed, why have any sacra-
ments at all, if one’s fate is eternally foreknown? And if these are valid
questions, then why even go to the trouble of reforming the earthly church,
when its true membership is unknowable? Yet for all the seeming ecclesi-
astical anarchy that results from his criticisms, we also find frequent indict-
ments of any attempts to revolutionize the social structure. At the time,
critics invariably connected his ideas with the uproar of the 1381 Peasants’
Revolt. His defense of the social status quo, with its division into nobility,
clergy, and peasantry, is an important aspect of his ecclesiology. While he
did not actively condemn the Peasants’ Revolt, his social ideals were far
from incendiary:
It is fitting that in this household [of Christ] there be three kinds of min-
isters reciprocally helping one another, so that the clergy, who should be
the highest and most worthy of God, but not attending to earthly honors
or wealth, should expect a whole faith of the retribution to come in the
Church triumphant. The second, middle part should be the knights and
secular lords; the third, lowest part, defending the house as above should
be the community of commoners, as cultivators of fields and other arti-
sans. And from all those three parts come the martyrs and the glori-
ous of the Church triumphant. . . . it is clear that anyone of these three
estates will have suffered meritoriously and [be] among those accepted
of the Lord.30
Apocalypse or Reform?
pope’s seemingly endless wealth of lands, armies, and secular authority had
fostered the expansion of canon law to encompass all worldly affairs. The
time was coming for a change, Wyclif concluded, and with it a completion
of the cycle of history. If the incarnation were the midpoint, then the end
would come at the close of the third age.31
But if the end times were at hand, why bother reforming the church?
To understand Wyclif ’s brand of apocalypticism, it is necessary to gain per-
spective on the range of orthodox and heterodox apocalyptic ideas prev-
alent in his era. Two figures define later medieval apocalyptic literature,
Hildegard of Bingen and Joachim of Fiore. Of the two, Joachim’s influence
on the Franciscans warrants our attention, especially because of Wyclif ’s
use of Franciscan conceptions of poverty and property. Joachim of Fiore
(c. 1135–1222) had founded an offshoot of the Cistercian order and had
become one of the great prophetic voices of the period. Joachim’s approach
to scripture was similar to Wyclif ’s in that both believed it to contain the
whole of created truth. The two differed significantly about what to take
out of scriptural study. Joachim read the Bible to understand the whole of
human history and devised a complex schema using numerology and pro-
phetic imagery to tease out God’s plan for Christendom. The result was
that Joachim’s thought was taken to endorse a prophetic approach to his-
tory, and kings like Richard I of England and Emperor Henry VI came to
him for advice about their crusading ventures. By one reading, Joachim’s
moments of mystic revelation opened the curtains to show the biblical
forces at work in contemporary events, and central to this mechanism was
the coming new age. The Old Testament was the age of the Father, and
the New Testament heralded the age of the Son, but the future was the
domain of the Spirit proceeding from Father and Son. The age of the Son
replaced law with grace, but the age of the Spirit would replace both with
love. Hence, the incarnation was not the completion of God’s creation, but
only a milestone. By another reading, Joachim believed the incarnation to
be the crucial dividing point in created history, and the age of the Spirit was
to be understood as arising from the ages of the Father and the Son, just
as the Spirit proceeds from the first two persons of the Trinity.32 The two
readings go together for Joachim, but many who would take up his cause
were not as subtle in their prophetic understanding.
Of the many who would embrace Joachism, perhaps the most notori-
ous were the spiritual Franciscans, who eagerly placed St. Francis at the
inauguration of the age of the Spirit. Most dramatic was Gerard de Borgo
192 john wyclif
the day of judgment.34 Wyclif explains that Christ wisely keeps three things
hidden from us, namely, the hour of our death, the nature of our election
or damnation, and the exact time of the apocalypse. Preachers who pretend
knowledge of such things only confuse the faithful: “preaching to the people
of the future should be moderated prudently. . . . By narrating the events of
the day of judgement and the future from prognosticating by the constella-
tions they often deceive themselves and others.”35 A presumptuous care to
discover things that God means us not to know only detracts from the more
important business of saving souls.
While Wyclif had no patience with Joachism, his entire ecclesiology
depends on awareness that the end was soon to come. His commentary on
the “little apocalypse” in Matthew 24 illustrates this well. Rather than pars-
ing scripture to eke out hints about historical warnings of the end times,
we ought to take Jesus at his word and accept that no one knows the day
and hour of the coming end. He speaks of those in Judea who flee to the
mountains, and of one on the house top, and another in the field (Matthew
24:16–18). These tell us of the three classes of society that will have to face
the end times, namely, the priests, who should flee to the example of the
early church; the secular lords, who ought to keep to their civic duties and
guard society against the depredations of Antichrist; and the common peo-
ple, whose duty it is to labor for the good of all: “And if these three parts
of the Church are constantly instructed in this catholic faith, it would be
a sufficient medium for removing the perfidy of Antichrist.”36 The tradi-
tional temptations each class will face, whether it be secular authority for
priests, a life of ease for lords, or material goods for peasants, are the chief
means by which Antichrist will keep the church militant from its end. Any
movement from within the church that fosters these temptations can only
be meant to forestall the completion of history.
Two dark forces swirl through the shadows of the twilight of history,
namely, the papacy and the friars. While Wyclif ’s program for reform of
the church is as vague on details as his eucharistic theology, it is quite spe-
cific in its rejection of a papal hierarchy and the proliferation of fraternal
orders. Before the imperial papacy and the four sects were introduced, the
church blossomed, but afterward, its blooms withered and its branches
194 john wyclif
corporeal and spiritual power, but there is a notable difference in how God
wills these to be organized in human affairs. While God gives all a degree
of secular power by which they can direct themselves and their goods, civil
lords have been ordained to direct more generally. It is similar with spiritual
power, a degree of which is entrusted to all, and another degree of which is
given to the clerical order. The mistake lies in the clergy’s assumption that
their power is analogous to that of civil lords. God gives kings authority to
make material judgments about subjects, but popes and bishops can never
lay claim to a similar spiritual authority over the laity. Further, kings may
delegate to lesser lords power over material goods, but spiritual lords have
no basis for delegating their power to clerical authority. There is no simple
basis for comparing the spiritual to the material in allocating and quantify-
ing power, because the two kinds lack a commonly shared property, other
than being itself.
Here, Wyclif ’s metaphysics provides the ground for his assessment of
power. His conviction that the order and structure of created being lies in
universals and, even more fundamentally, in the divine ideas, leads him to
concentrate more power in God’s direct control the higher up the chain of
being we inquire. Material goods are lower than spiritual ones and have a
lower degree of correspondent being. Hence, while all that occurs materi-
ally is directly subject to God, our rational, spiritual power allows us some
control over material goods. The same is not true for spiritual goods. Grace,
by which God sustains and nurtures the universe, is the basis for all spiritual
goods’ distribution in creation. While material goods are also distributed
by grace, the higher nature of spiritual goods places them more directly
under divine control. In the case of spiritual goods in the purview of spiri-
tual lords, which is the term Wyclif frequently uses for the clergy, grace
is always the means by which preaching and the sacraments are directly
distributed. Priests are only human vehicles for their promulgation and dis-
tribution.39 But Wyclif ’s theology of the priesthood is so heavily weighted
toward preaching as to require attention to the specifics of a priest’s role in
creation. God ordained the priestly office to protect Christ’s body on earth
from external evils and to foster its growth and life in lex Christi. To that
end, priests must instruct the members of the body both by personal exam-
ple and by the specific duties of their office. The actions and words of the
individual priest’s life have a more immediate force than do the sacraments,
because they are more evident to the faithful. Hence, “preaching the gospel
exceeds prayer and administration of the sacraments to an infinite degree.”
196 john wyclif
(c. 1379), he argued that the church militant needs a pope, but that the pope
ought to be wary of assuming that he is, by the fact of exercising papal office,
necessarily among the elect. De Potestate Pape followed within the year, and
he took up papalist theories with great enthusiasm. What Bradwardine’s
De Causa Dei is to Pelagianism, De Potestate Pape is to papal triumpha-
lism, both in structure and approach. Wyclif refuted any and all arguments
for any papal responsibility or power beyond continual prayer on behalf of
the faithful without reference to contemporary papal theorists like Giles of
Rome or Augustinus Triumphus, but also without the structure and rea-
soned approach of John of Paris. At the center was Wyclif ’s admission that
if the church must have a pope, he should meet the thirty-four rigorous
standards that Bernard set in his Letter to Eugenius.42 Arguments intimat-
ing the need for papal rule as a basis for sacraments, bishops, or other eccle-
siastical necessities are specious at best, and are evidence of Antichrist’s use
of clerical weakness in the face of material temptation. Excommunication,
a favorite weapon in the pope’s bag of dirty tricks, has no theological jus-
tification whatever, given the close connection between divine and human
will. If someone excommunicates himself from Christ’s body on earth, God
knows of this eternally, and no papal pronouncement will make the slight-
est difference one way or the other.43
While the friars lacked a treatise of their own, Wyclif ’s attacks against
them appeared throughout his works. His attitude against them was adver-
sarial in Oxford, but developed into real antifraternalism as organized eccle-
siastical opposition against him mounted. Wyclif ’s antifraternalism was of
a piece with the attitude of many secular clergy of his age, who resented the
friars for a host of reasons. They were accused of hypocrisy; abusing their
vow of poverty; slick, crowd-pleasing preaching; and stealing the rights of
secular priests and bishops. Any reader of Chaucer or Langland will recall
the portraits of nefarious, seedy friars preying on the ignorant laity. As far
as Wyclif was concerned, the best that might be expected for these artificial
churches within the church would be for them to be dissolved and their
members absorbed into Christ’s body. But the odds of this happening are
as good for the Saracen or the Jew, Wyclif continued, so it would be best
simply to cleanse the church of the friars, root and branch.44 If any among
the friars could lay claim to the apostolic ideal of the church, though, it was
the Franciscan spirituals. Wyclif noted that Ockham had worked “along
with other faithful friars” in an attempt to lift his order from the sorry state
to which it had sunk. If only all the Franciscans were like their founder, he
198 john wyclif
commented, they would serve as an ideal for the Christian life, rather than
its antithesis.45 As we will see in the next chapter, Wyclif ’s opinion on the
Franciscan dedication to poverty and his view of the apostolic ideal that had
inspired the friars were by no means the same. The friars’ claim to poverty
is grounded in the rule of St. Francis, a human invention, while the pure
apostolic communalism of the early church is a recovered Edenic state.
7
dominium as foundation
of wyclif’s political
and ecclesiological vision
199
200 john wyclif
subjects serve one another in love, the latter obeying while the former take
thought for all.”5 There is really only one true lord in creation, God; mas-
tery of one man over another is the result of original sin and is unnatural,
save in the case of paternity, which is founded in the parent’s love for the
child. Among members of the city of God, the relation of prince and sub-
ject is not a political one as understood in the city of man, and it does not
entail mastery, but rather service and sacrifice, as exemplified in parental
relations.
Property ownership has become associated with mastery in the city of
man because of original sin, when man turned away from God and mistak-
enly believed that he could make claims of exclusive ownership of created
beings. This is not to say that Augustine thought that all private property
relations are wrong; indeed, he is famous for having argued that all things
belong to the just.6 People who own things are not de facto just. Those
for whom ownership is not an end in itself but a means by which to do
God’s will are freed from the bondage of selfishness imposed by the Fall.
They easily recognize the truth of the dictum “[o]ne should abstain from
the possession of private things, or if one cannot abstain from possession,
then from the love of property.”7
These brief summaries show that Augustine’s thought on the relation
of ownership to political authority is open to interpretation. One can easily
read Augustine as having argued that the church, as the body of Christ and
the earthly instantiation of the city of God, can best exemplify love-centered
lord-subject relations in its hierarchical clerical structure, thereby justifying
a top-down papal monarchy. Likewise, one can interpret him as having so
totally separated secular political authority from the rule of love as to rule
out all similarity between political and ecclesiastical jurisdictive authority.
Again, one can interpret Augustine’s “all things belong to the just” as mean-
ing that the church is the arbiter of all property ownership by virtue of its
being the body of Christ and the seat of all created justice. Or, one could
argue that the church should abandon all claims to property ownership,
just as the apostles abstained from the possession of private things. This
openness to interpretation was the source of several competing theories that
led to Wyclif ’s position.
In 1301, during the conflict between Philip IV of France and Pope
Boniface VIII, an Augustinian friar named Giles of Rome wrote De
Ecclesiastica Potestate, a treatise designed to establish the absolute secular
superiority of the papacy. Earlier, Giles had written a less papally centered,
dominium as foundation of wyclif’s vision 203
it follows that the friars are bound to obey ecclesiastical authority. Thus,
friars’ claims to be unaffected by ecclesiastical authority—at the papal, dioc-
esan, or parochial level—are unfounded.11
For our purposes, Fitzralph’s position is important because it argues that
grace alone is the justification for any instance of dominium in creation, and
that all just dominium ultimately relies on God’s dominium; both serve as the
cornerstones of Wyclif ’s position. All species of man’s exercising authority
involve, at their base, divine dominium, he explains. Fitzralph’s interest is
directed primarily toward ownership, and much less so toward political
jurisdiction, but his catalog of the many species of private and communal
ownership, possession, and rights of use occasionally lead him to address
the legitimacy of political authority and its relation to ecclesiastical author-
ity. God’s dominium over creation is a natural consequence of the act of
creating, and with it comes divine governance and conservation of created
being. The rational beings in creation, angels and men, enjoy the loan of
elements of God’s created universe, but this communicative giving is not a
divine abdication of ultimate authority, because everything is still directly
subject to divine dominium.
When the nature of the dominium loaned to Adam changed with the Fall,
the peaceful coexistence of Eden and the love embodying the grace of our
natural dominium was damaged, but not eradicated. Man devised political
dominium to restrict and regulate the property relations that were no longer
guaranteed to be pure by grace. Original sin clouds our eyes, keeping us
from naturally recognizing the loaned nature of any dominium in creation,
but it does not preclude there being grace-justified property ownership. In
some cases, God infuses the artificial property relations that we call domi-
nium with sufficient grace to make them almost as pure as prelapsarian
dominium. These grace-favored cases of human dominium cannot claim the
authority of God’s dominium, but can be so pure as to exhibit the caritas,
or love, that characterizes God’s dominium. Unfortunately, Fitzralph is not
particularly clear about determining which of our dominium relations are
favored by grace, and which are phantoms, thereby restricting the applica-
bility of his argument to theological investigation about the friars’ claims
to be free from ecclesiastical authority.
Thus, from Augustine’s position that all things belong to the just comes
Giles’s position that all property ownership and all secular lordship are
grounded in ecclesiastical authority, as well as Franciscan arguments that
expressly reject connections between property ownership and the apostolic
206 john wyclif
Dominium’s Foundation:
De Dominio Divino
God’s dominium has six aspects, three identifiable with lordship’s rul-
ing element (creation, sustenance, and governance), and three that define
lordship’s proprietary nature (giving, receiving, and lending).13 Wyclif
argues that the necessary precondition for an act of dominium is the first
act, creation, of which no created being is capable. This makes God’s domi-
nium the only true instance of dominium, the source from which all created
instances of dominium originate. Because the divine ideas and their created
correlates, the universals, are prior in being to particular created beings,
God’s dominium over universals is prior to his dominium over particulars.
This means that God creates, sustains, and governs the species humanity
prior to ruling—and knowing—individual people. Without the carefully
crafted modal theory lying at the base of his understanding of how God
knows and wills human actions, Wyclif ’s position could be crippled by
fatalism. This is why a significant portion of the first book of De Dominio
Divino involves his recapitulation of the position described in the previous
chapter of this volume.
The second set of acts that defines dominium—giving, receiving, and
lending—provides the foundation for his arguments that all created domi-
nium necessarily requires grace. God’s act of giving the divine essence in
order to realize creation is the truest form of giving because God is giving
of himself through himself, which no created being can do. Nor can any
created being receive as God receives. God truly receives only from himself
through his giving. God gives up nothing in his giving, and acquires noth-
ing in his receiving; creation is God’s self-expression in which the divine
essence is neither decreased nor increased. The crucial act from the created
standpoint is God’s lending, for here there is real interaction between the
Lord and his subjects. What human beings, as rationally aware participants
in God’s lending relation, can claim as their own is loaned to them by divine
authority, and they enjoy it through grace.
People can confuse giving with lending, because a lord who has been
“loaned” a gift of God for use during his lifetime appears to have been “given”
that gift. God’s giving is communicative, not translative. For us, most giv-
ing is translative, in that it involves the giver’s surrender of every connec-
tion to the gift, making it natural for us to suppose that God renounces his
authority over what he gives to us. In fact, God’s giving is communicative,
which does not involve surrender of the gift. His gifts to people are meant
to be enjoyed in common, and the more commonly enjoyed, the more the
giver is enriched. On the broadest level, God’s gift to creatures is being,
208 john wyclif
given through the Holy Spirit, which is differentiated through the divine
ideas into created substance. Two aspects of that gift, Wyclif explains, are
necessarily connected: caritas and dominium. Rational creatures are given
participation in divine dominium through the Holy Spirit, and are thereby
responsible to God for that gift, which, when enjoyed commonly, engen-
ders true caritas, God’s caring love, in creation, thereby enriching both the
creature and the Creator.14
Because all that God gives to creation will ultimately return to him, it
makes more sense to speak of God’s giving as lending. With any instance
of lending, Wyclif explains, the lender seeks assurance that the borrower
truly deserves what is to be loaned. Rational beings’ desert of the dominium
they are loaned is a matter of some complexity involving examination of the
relation of deserving to grace, which is particularly clear in the distinction
between congruent and condign grace. When a temporal lord lends to his
subject according to the subject’s worthiness, the subject’s merit is on a mea-
surable level to the lord’s merit, and the mutual agreement that defines the
loan is made according to the respective merit of each party. The merit that
allows the subject desert of consideration for the loan is condign, grounded
in the dignitas shared by lender and subject. Condign merit implies that
the meritorious truly deserves the reward, requiring the giver to give the
merited as something due, as when an Olympic athlete earns a gold medal
by besting all opponents. Such a loan is impossible between the Creator
and creature, because there is no way of comparing a creature’s merit with
God’s perfect nature; all that is the creature’s, including its worth, is from
outside itself, from God, while God’s perfection is from within. There is
no way in which a creature can be considered to “deserve” anything from
God in such a relation. Congruent merit is when the meritorious does not
have the power to require of the giver. In instances of congruent merit, the
goodness of the act does not require the giver to reward the agent, but it
provides sufficient cause for the reward to be given, as when one receives
an Academy Award. While many of the audience members may deserve an
Oscar, the recipient receives one because something about her performance
was somehow pleasing to the academy. Yet Wyclif believes that it must
make some sense to talk of deserving grace: “It is the invariable law of God
that nobody is awarded blessedness unless they first deserve it.”15 Merit, he
says, requires the motion of an object, the deliberation of the mind, and
finally voluntary adherence, which does not happen instantaneously. We
can move our wills to the good, and from this, Wyclif says, grace may—but
dominium as foundation of wyclif’s vision 209
lord both master and servant; from the divine perspective, the lord is God’s
servant, but from the viewpoint of the subject, he is master. Wyclif is tire-
less in his emphasis on the illusory nature of this mastery. Grace allows the
human lord to recognize that he is, in fact, his subjects’ servant, ministering
to them as a nurturing steward, not lording over them as would a powerful
sovereign.
De Civili Dominio begins with the motto “Civil justice presupposes divine
justice; civil dominium presupposes natural dominium.” Wyclif means his
readers to be aware that his discourse on human dominium is already in
full swing as he begins his explication of how the grace-favored civil lord is
obligated to take control of the church. Critics who have dismissed Wyclif ’s
political thought as an iteration of Marsilius of Padua, as did Pope Gregory XI
in 1377, or as written largely as a vehicle for John of Gaunt’s anticlerical
leanings, as has K. B. McFarlane, should take Wyclif at his word. Man’s
dominium is threefold—natural, civil, and evangelical—but comprehensi-
ble only in terms of its instantiation of the justice of God’s dominium. As he
moved into his general analysis of human dominium, his thoughts turned
to the most fundamental instance of God’s loving governance, the scrip-
tural commandments. The foundation of all that is right (ius) in creation,
he explains, is the justice (iustitia) of God’s eternal righteousness, which
means that we cannot begin to understand right and wrong in creation
without understanding God’s uncreated right. This is a significant depar-
ture from the Aristotelian position that unaided human reason is capable of
justice, and Wyclif explicitly rejects any conception of justice that does not
rely on uncreated right.18 The basis for justice in creation is not necessarily
evident to human eyes, because the Fall has made humans prone to value
natural, material goods above spiritual ones: “Because the human commu-
nity appreciates greatly these goods, of course it says that this law [founded
in material goods] is most useful, and the law of the Gospel which is of the
virtues and in general against the vices they call useless.”19
The laws of scripture are the purest expression of uncreated right avail-
able to human eyes, he explains, and are most clearly expressed in the Ten
Commandments of Exodus 20 and again in Matthew 22:37–40. Wyclif ’s
analysis of Christ’s law of love and of the Ten Commandments proceeds
dominium as foundation of wyclif’s vision 211
necessary for apostolic poverty. The church, Christ’s body on earth, ought to
preserve this apostolic poverty with a purity exceeding any manmade insti-
tution, because it is based in the true justice of Christ’s evangelical law, not
the illusory justice of human law: “For the law of Christ teaches about the
glory of tribulations and condemns fame, prosperity, and the riches of the
world, advising the relinquishment of proprietary lordship; civil law seems
to command the opposites of all these.”27 Because the church is founded not
on the materially based laws of man, but on the spiritually grounded lex
Christi, it must be absolutely free of any property ownership, the better to
realize the ideal of spiritual purity required by apostolic poverty. That the
church must be characterized by a total absence of ownership is central to
Wyclif ’s understanding of the ecclesiastical implementation of Christ’s law.
Any material riches that the church comes upon as “goods of fortune” must
be distributed as alms for the poor, which was the practice of Christ, the dis-
ciples, and the apostolic church. This alms giving must not be motivated by
worldly aspirations to appear “charitable,” for that is nothing more than the
kind of giving common to civil dominium. A kindly civil lord may give the
use of some good to a poor subject while still retaining ultimate dominium
over that good, but true giving according to the evangelical law entails rec-
ognition that the church—and no man—has the dominium necessary to
make this kind of gift. Hence, what goods come to the church ought auto-
matically to be bestowed upon those in need as a matter of course, without
the church’s having anything to do with civil dominium.
This is the ideal for which the church was ordered by Christ, and some
of the harshest invective in Wyclif ’s prose is against the church’s inability
even to desire to return to this apostolic state. For example, in Dialogus
sive Speculum Ecclesie Militantis (The Dialogue; or, A Mirror of the Church
Militant, 1379), he attributes all of the clergy’s shortcomings to their captiva-
tion with property: “And so as the devil perverts [the church’s] priests from
Christ’s poverty to secular lordship, thus he turns them away from humil-
ity, from evangelical preaching and from every other duty for which Christ
anointed them.”28 The turning point in church history was the Donation of
Constantine, the basis from which the church claims to have the civil domi-
nium of a Caesar. Wyclif was vigorous in his condemnation of the Donation
and would likely have been pleased, had he lived into the early fifteenth
century, when Nicholas of Cusa, Lorenzo Valla, and Reginald Pecock
argued persuasively that the document in which Constantine conferred
considerable temporal privileges to the papacy was a ninth-century forgery.
216 john wyclif
Not only was such a gift impossible, according to the right understanding
of civil dominium—for, as we will see, a just civil lord cannot grant any gift
in perpetuity—but the Donation opened wide the floodgates that had been
protecting the church from the evils of the world, the flesh, and the devil.
Now that the pope and the bishops were allowed to be temporal lords, they
were polluted with the same cares and fears that haunt the machinery of
secular human dominium. The result is not a class of evangelical lords who,
through the power of grace, are better able to guide the secular world, for
civil dominium is an onerous, degrading business that soils anyone involved.
The Donation has resulted in a church riddled with tumorous growths
of civil dominium that strangle its chances of embodying Christ’s law of
caritas.
Given the obviously poisonous influence that civil dominium has had
on the evangelical dominium of Christ’s law, it is difficult to imagine how
Wyclif would set aside some civil lords as capable of instantiating divine
justice. But apostolic poverty is not identical to an absence of property owner-
ship; it is having with caritas. While the clergy as spiritual lords ought to
follow Christ’s example of material poverty, this does not mean that all
ownership precludes caritas. Recall that Wyclif had argued that all grace-
favored human lords who instantiate divine dominium are able to recognize
their true place as stewards. Those civil lords made able through grace to
recognize this truth are as much capable of apostolic poverty, he reasons,
as are any of the postlapsarian meritorious. But this does not mean that
Wyclif endorses the feudal structure of fourteenth-century Europe. We
will see that he rejects hereditary succession and servitude, two practices
that defined the lordship of his age.
Wyclif envisions the just civil lord or king as the means by which the
church is relieved of its accumulated burden of property ownership. So
long as the church exists in postlapsarian society, it must be protected from
the avarice of thieves, the errors of heresy, and the depredations of infi-
dels. Certainly, priests ought not to be concerned with such matters, given
their higher responsibility for the welfare of Christian souls. As a result,
the church needs a worldly protector, a guardian to ward off enemies while
caring for the church’s physical health and administering its alms on behalf
of the poor. This allows Wyclif to describe just, grace-favored civil domi-
nium as different in kind from the civil lordship predicated on materialistic
human concerns: “It is right for God to have two vicars in His church,
namely a king in temporal affairs, and a priest in spiritual. The king should
dominium as foundation of wyclif’s vision 217
strongly check rebellion, as did God in the Old Testament, while priests
ought minister the precepts mildly . . . as did Christ, who was at once priest
and king.”29 In saying this, he calls to mind an argument made by an anony-
mous Norman political theorist in the twelfth century, in which the king is
an image of God, the almighty Lord, while the priest is an image of Christ
the spiritual counselor. While it is unlikely that Wyclif had access to the
writings of “Norman Anonymous,” and while Wyclif ’s conception of king-
ship was not theocratic, it is interesting to note that both argued for the
church’s need for the guiding hand of secular rule.
When Wyclif discusses civil dominium and kingship, which terms he
generally uses synonymously, his interest is in explaining their function in
God’s dominium, especially as paladins of Christ’s body on earth:
tyranny; after all, a tyrannical civil lord can only do damage to one’s mate-
rial well-being, but a tyrannical priest can endanger one’s very soul.
The guardian against priestly tyranny must be the civil lord, whose
responsibility to the church requires him to monitor the clergy’s execution
of its spiritual duties. This responsibility is his by virtue of the responsibil-
ity he has to God to protect the church from dangers without and within.
Those who argue that a civil lord has no business interfering with spiritual
concerns overlook the fundamental relation that holds between just civil
law and divine law; because the civil lord’s responsibility is to God, his first
concern must be to ensure that nothing any man may do can block obedi-
ence to divine law. The cumbersome apparatus of canon law that has built
up over the centuries like barnacles on a ship’s hull is held up as the means
by which the church regulates spiritual affairs, but this, Wyclif explains, is
a superfluous creation of priests, ultimately hindering the church by intro-
ducing material structure to what should be a spiritual enterprise. This is
not to say that the king should take on the spiritual authority of a pope, for
as we will discuss, such a concentration of spiritual authority is antithetical
to Wyclif ’s vision of ecclesiastical structure.
The means by which a king ought to monitor the spiritual offices of
priests are bishops, who exist to correct the errant and to reward the excel-
lent clergy. Bishops, he explains, were the early church’s means by which
its priests were protected from error, and the king should use them as his
deputies to protect the church from the dangers of simony, pluralism,
absenteeism, and heresy. The bishops ought also to act as royal theologi-
cal advisors, helping the civil lord to understand how lex Christi is best
implemented in his own legislation. Post-Reformation readers of Wyclif
may be surprised by this apparent reliance on a hierarchy of the spiritual
lords, given Wyclif ’s generally dim view of the church being organized
according to the needs of secular society. Yet a bishop’s power is analogous
to a civil lord’s. Just as a civil lord is God’s steward and a servant to his sub-
jects, a bishop is not superior to the laity or the priests, but a steward whose
responsibility is to God and the divine law, which ordains subservience to
the grace-favored civil lord.
Wyclif continued to argue for the centrality of the episcopal office
throughout his life, despite his troubles with the bishop of London and
the archbishop of Canterbury. While a church untroubled by the material
world may need only priests as spiritual shepherds, he argues in Trialogus
dominium as foundation of wyclif’s vision 221
IV.15 in early 1383, in this age it needs bishops to provide supervisory and
regulatory guidance in the service of a just civil lord.
This, then, is Wyclif ’s conception of how human lords ought to serve as
instantiations of God’s dominium in postlapsarian society. A civil lord must
recognize that his jurisdictive and proprietary authority are based not in his
own worth, but are founded in grace given for the purpose of serving God’s
will in human society. Kings must hold all material power as stewards in
service of the divine Lord and are bound especially to protect the church,
Christ’s body on earth, from the world, the flesh, and the devil. While evan-
gelical lords may believe themselves to wield secular authority justly, theirs
is a higher, purer sphere of influence, and the civil lord’s responsibility is
to help them to realize this. Given the ecclesiastical status quo of the late
fourteenth century, this would involve the radical divestment of all church
property ownership and a strict regulation of clerical behavior. The place
of the human lord—whether natural, evangelical, or civil—in Wyclif ’s
thought is ultimately that of a guardian, not a philosopher-king, a means
by which creation’s true Lord realizes perfect justice.
epilogue
Wyclif ’s legacy has long been a matter for partisan debate. The theological
cataclysm that broke over sixteenth-century Europe dramatically polarized
opinions about a thinker whose ideas appeared to presage those of Luther.
His monarchism seemed to foresee the Tudor state, his emphasis on scrip-
ture as the divine standard of truth evoked Protestant bibliolatry, and his
vigorous antipapalism rivaled all but the most vehement of Reformers. It is
no wonder that modern assessments of Wyclif ’s thought have ranged from
vigorous Catholic condemnation to adulatory Protestant encomia, with
almost nothing in between.
Even before the Reformation, polarization over Wyclif had been com-
mon. In England, his Oxford-trained preachers had instigated a program
of preaching and teaching according to his ideals, which continued after his
death in 1384. The first fruit was the Wyclif Bible, a complete translation
of Jerome’s Vulgate into English. While parts of scripture had been avail-
able in translation as far back as King Alfred the Great, the Wyclif Bible
warrants attention as the first complete English Bible in the history of the
language. This Bible, and the energetic preaching that became associated
with its proponents, gave rise to the Lollard movement, the lay piety phe-
nomenon that, because of Lancastrian politics, would soon be associated
with treason. The Lancastrian crusade against Wycliffism brought burn-
ing at the stake to England in 1401, and scores would perish in this way
222
epilogue 223
for their association with the writings of a man for whom rebellion against
the social order was unthinkable. Defining Lollardy became very much a
matter of circumstance, though; by the middle of the fifteenth century, an
accusation of Lollardy might be made for any number of reasons. Some
were accused of questioning the ecclesiastical monopoly on scripture inter-
pretation, others for their complaints about what they perceived as idolatry,
while still others were questioned for expressing doubts about the sacra-
ments. Our understanding of the Lollards continues to develop as scholars
continue to study fifteenth-century England, and the phenomenon appears
to have been much more complex than it was previously understood to be.
The absence of the formal organization of the Protestant movements that
scholars first used as paradigms to explain Lollardy does not demonstrate a
correspondent theological simplicity. Something linked to Wyclif ’s teach-
ings certainly compelled Bishop Reginald Pecock (c. 1390–1461) to launch
a one-man crusade against scripturally founded anticlericalism, using rea-
soned argument, rather than the more standard threats of imprisonment
and burning. The result was what may be the first genuine philosophi-
cal literature in the English language. Pecock’s unpleasant personality and
his willingness to count church doctrine as secondary to reason led to his
own conviction for heresy, and rather than face the fate of the Lollards, he
recanted. Pecock’s campaign ended two decades before the end of medieval
England on Bosworth field, suggesting that there were “fellow travelers,”
if not actual Lollards, into the first decades of the Tudor era. Most scholars
agree that Lollardy had little to do with the genesis of Anglicanism. John
Foxe (1517–1587), author of the widely read Actes and Monuments (1563),
introduced Wyclif into the sixteenth-century mix from his encounters
with his manuscripts on the Continent, and contributed significantly to the
Protestant myth of Wyclif and Lollardy as proto-Protestantism. The same
is true of John Bale (1495–1563), an ex-Carmelite who embraced Wyclif ’s
memory, coining the epithet “morning star of the Reformation.”
The established church, on the other hand, had long followed the lead
of the Earthquake Council and refused to admit that Wyclif or his writings
had described Catholic truth. Wyclif ’s ideas had attracted some attention
among the lesser English nobility in the 1380s, prompting Richard II to join
forces with Archbishop Courtenay in an active program dedicated to elimi-
nating Wycliffism. A minor uprising against Henry V, led by a Lollard
knight, Sir John Oldcastle, in 1414, made Wycliffism synonymous with
treason. Henry’s confessor, the Carmelite Thomas Netter, penned the most
224 john wyclif
226
wyclif’s confessio 227
a title associated with his earlier days or one written during his final years,
has been subjected to his editorial hand.
sign, since in Luke 2:34 it is said that “He is given for the falling and rising
of many, and in His sign is He opposed.”
And the second part of the conclusion is clear because the way of being
a sign of the body of Christ is one thing, and the way of true and real being
by the power of the words of our Lord Jesus Christ is another. It is conceded
that these two ways are conjoined inseparably. Yet this infinite sign is more
present than the sign of the body of Christ in the Old Law, or the images in
the New Law, since it is at the same time the truth and a figure.
Moreover, I understand what I have said in this matter according to the
logic of Scripture, and indeed, according to the logic of the ancient doc-
tors and the decrees of the Roman church, according to which I declare
myself prudently to have spoken. It is not right, though, to cause a scandal
in the whole Roman church when the bread and wine are said to be, after
consecration, the body and blood of Jesus Christ, and, when not impeded
by the glossators’ error, this faith remains constant in the church, especially
among the laity. Since the faithful do not desire corporeally to eat the body
of Christ, but spiritually, it is clear that the All-Knowing prepared this
spiritual way of the being of His body in the host according to which He
should be eaten by the faithful. Any other mode of being, since it would
be superfluous, He has excluded.
So those without faith murmur, either with those who have cast [this
teaching] away from them, saying “This teaching is hard,” when the body
of Christ would be corporeally eaten, or with those legal observers of the
Old Law, who do not imagine there to be a more immediate degree or
mode of being of Christ in the sign of the Eucharist than there was in the
Old Law, or than there is in the humanly instituted signs. And they imag-
ine that an accident can be made of the body Christ, and that Christ would
better and more plainly have said, “This accident without a subject signifies
my body.” Both of these sects are, through their faithlessness, the poorer
from their ignorance in the gradations of signs.
So we hold that, by the power of Christ’s words, the bread becomes
miraculously the body of Christ, beyond the possibility of a humanly insti-
tuted sign. Nevertheless, this unity, whether a union or a joining, does not
achieve the identical, numerical, or hypostatic unity, but it is believed that
it would be unmediated after this, and so the corporeal accidents of the
body of Christ, such as quantity, the corporeal quality of the body of Christ
do not appear to be multiplied concomitantly to the body of Christ in the
host, and through this, no other respective accidents which are based in
230 appendix
this, because all of these accidents have already gone on to be corporeal with
their subject, wherever they were. So that if here is “seven feet tall,” or
“colour,” or “corporeal glory of the Lord,” then it is here that the body of
Christ is seven feet tall, coloured, and corporeally glorified, and so Christ
has corporeal existence here. Since this is false, such a multiplication of acci-
dents concomitant to the body of Christ was denied, according to material
conditions in the consecrated host.
The quantitative parts of the body of Christ have a spiritual being in the
host, indeed they have the same sacramental being, since, in a certain way,
they are any quantitative part of this host. And the soul of Christ is much
more greatly multiplied through the host, according to a certain spiritual
being, than is that being that the body of Christ has in heaven. And the
cause of this multiplication of the soul of Christ is that it is more founda-
tional in the person of the Word than is His body. The immaterial quali-
ties which have the soul of Christ as a subject are multiplied with it in the
host, such as knowledge, justice, and the other powers of the soul of Christ,
which do not require a preexisting body, wherever they have been. These
same powers were with Him, because with His spirit, in Hell. So just as
Christ is powerful throughout the entire host, so the power of Christ is
throughout it. So the author of On the Divine Office 3 believes that because
of the spiritual body of Christ in the host, there is a concomitance of the
angels. Because this oblation can be complicated by defects in the power
of faith, and of the words of the priest, many of the religious adore this
host conditionally, and they are unmistakenly at rest in the body of Christ,
which is substantially, and ineffably, raised up, and is walking in heaven.
But the ignorant continue to grumble, asking how the body is this holy
bread, since it is not [holy] according to substance or nature. But it is right
for them to learn about the incarnation, how two substances or natures,
very distinct from one another, are the same suppositum, and yet are not
the same, because both of them are Christ, and then they can ascend, by a
posteriori reasoning, to cognizing this miraculous union; conserving both
natures, not made identical, in the Word of God. But it is right that they
bear in mind a gradation of signs, and put away the baseless blasphemy of
the miraculous coming-into-being of accidents, and believe the power
of the words of Christ, and then they can know how this bread is truly,
miraculously, really, and powerfully, and sacramentally the body of Christ.
But many are not contented by this way, and demand that this bread, or
at least through this bread, is substantially and corporeally the body of
wyclif’s confessio 231
Christ. So they want to eat Christ with the zeal of blasphemers, but they
cannot.
There is a witness for this in Hugh of St. Victor, On the Sacraments II,
8.7, “In whatever way this species is distinguished, the thing or substance
of which is not believed to be here; so the thing is believed truly and sub-
stantially to be here present, the species of which is not distinct.” Regarding
this doctor, it is clear what he subtly mixes into the above-said Catholic
reasoning. He wants [to argue] that the species are perceived sensibly here,
and that these same species are essentially bread and wine, which are dis-
tinguished, although through the accidents [alone]. So he often calls them
bread and wine, the which are usually foods, and principally the substance
of food, as is clear in the chapter mentioned, and in those following. He says
that the same bread having the substance by which it is perceived, is not
here distinguished, since it is the body of Christ.
But for this adverb, “substantially,” it should be known that whenever
it is taken simply for the mode of substance, [it is] such that the same thing
would be the body of Christ present there substantially, and being there
in the substantial way. And this is how Hugh spoke. In due time, he adds
“reduplicative” by reason of body, insofar as [it is] such a substance. And
so I properly understand this adverb in this way. So in the same chapter it
is said that, we take Christ at the altar corporeally, according to the power
of the body and blood of Christ. It is fitting that it be understood that we
spiritually take the body of Christ at the altar. And this is the true mode of
the body, although it is not a mode in which “body” is understood as body,
because [in] John 6:63, Christ says, “[It is the spirit that gives life;] the flesh
is useless,” since He is brought forth neither by corporeal assumption nor
by the corporeal eating of the body of the Lord. For it is taken invisibly
insofar as the form of His body, as the doctor [Hugh] says in chapter 3 of the
same work, but visibly insofar as the substance of the sacrament. So such
equivocation was made adverbially, for the declaration of the excellence
of the Eucharist beyond the figure of the Old Law. Our words are appro-
priate because otherwise it would be right to concede that to be substantially
would be to be accidentally, and to be corporeally would be to be spiritually,
and to be carnally would be to be virtually, and to be dimensively would
be to be multiplicatively, and ways of making distinction would cease.
So, then, it is conceded that the body of Christ is held in symbol, or in
the host, and it is perceived; and yet it is not moved thus, because [it is] not
according to the nature of the body of Christ or insofar as [it is] the same
232 appendix
body; thus it is conceded that the body of Christ is in the host in the acci-
dental mode of substance, because the spiritual way and the sacramental
presupposing three other ways [are] more real ways for the same body [to]
exist causatively. So it was not in the figure of the Old Law, nor [was it] in
the sign of our laws humanly instituted. And so before the fact, the ways
can be distinguished by which [the body of Christ] is in heaven, and after
the fact [the ways] by which it is in the sacrament.
So we differ in three ways from the sect of signs.
First, we hold that the venerable sacrament of the altar is bread and
wine in nature, but the body and blood of Christ sacramentally. But the
opposing sect imagines the same sacrament to be unknown accidents with-
out substantial subject.
And [second,] from this erroneous root a wide variety of errors grows.
For our sect adores the sacrament not as the substance of bread and wine,
but as the body and blood of Christ. But the sect of the cult of accidents, as
I believe, adores this sacrament not as it is accidents without a subject, but
as it is the sacramental sign of the body and blood of Christ. The signs of
their cult show that they adore this sacrament, since they adore the cross
and other images of the church, which have less a reason for adoration than
does this venerable sacrament. For God is more really in any created sub-
stance and more substantially, than the body of Christ is in the consecrated
host. So unless the same makes His body by power of the words of Christ,
there is no reason for such excellence of adoring.
Third, our sect would take up the arguments of our adversaries through
the detection of equivocation and of other fallacies, so that some things are
said of the sacrament as it is bread, and others speak of it not as identical
with the body of Christ, but sacramentally. But the sects of our adversaries
introduce useless difficulties, imagining miracles about the operations of
accidents.
For our reasoning there is the definition of the Highest Judge [Summa
Judicis from Decreta Summi Pontificis V], our Lord Jesus Christ, who at
table on the night he was betrayed, took bread in His hands, blessed it
and broke it, and instructed that they eat of it, saying, “This is my body.”
When the bread had been indicated, which He had referred to with the
demonstrative pronoun [“this”], then, according to He who does not lie,
the complete rest of the proposition signifies that the same is His body. So
it is manifest from the authority and the words of Christ that this bread
was and is sacramentally His body.
wyclif’s confessio 233
Seven witnesses are added onto this to testify to the judgment of the
church about this reasoning.4
The first is the Blessed Ignatius, contemporaneous to the apostles, who
from them and with them received the sense from the Lord. And Lincolni-
ensis cites him in On the Ecclesiastical Hierarchy 3. “The sacrament,” he says,
“or the Eucharist is the body of Christ.”
The second witness is the Blessed Cyprianus in his letter of the body of
Christ. “Taking the cup on the day of the passion, He blessed it and gave it
to His disciples, saying, ‘Take and drink of this all of you, this is the blood of
the new covenant, which is spilled for many for the remission of sins. Verily
I say to you, I will not drink again of this fruit of the vine until the day when
I drink it new with you in my Father’s kingdom.’ ” “By which in part,”
says the saint, “we have discovered the mixed chalice to have been what He
offered, and the wine to have been what He called His blood.”
The third witness is Blessed Ambrose in his book on the sacraments,
and he is placed in the canon on Consecration, d.2, “The bread is on the
altar.” “What the bread was,” he said, “before the consecration, the same is
the body of Christ after the consecration.”
The fourth witness is Blessed Augustine in a certain sermon explain-
ing Luke 24:35, “They knew Him in the breaking of the bread.” “Not all
bread,” he said, “but in taking the bread with the blessing of Christ was it
the body of Christ.” And this is held in the canon mentioned above.
The fifth witness is the Blessed Jerome in the letter to Elvidam. “We
understand the bread which the Lord broke and gave to His disciples to be
the body of our Lord Saviour, Himself saying to them, ‘Take and eat, this
is my body.’ ”
The sixth witness is the decretum of the Roman church in which Nicho-
las II, with 114 bishops, dictated prudently under right reasoning, which
was taken for the entire church, that the bread and wine that are placed on
the altar are, after consecration, not only sacramentally but truly the body
and blood of our Lord Jesus Christ, as is clear in the canon given above.
The seventh witness is the use of the church, in the canon according to
which the Mass is held, [which] says that this oblation becomes for us the
body and blood of our Lord Jesus Christ. This oblation the church calls
earthly substance, just as is clear in the secreto mediae of the mass of the
nativity of the Lord.
The glossators poison these witnesses, so that they say tacitly all such
words of the saints ought [to] be understood through what is contrary to
234 appendix
them, and so [should] in the end be denied, with Scripture. The faithful
should consider whether it is sound to make heresy, or to cause scandal, in
this way, of these witnesses and many similar. He should consider secondly
how he could extend honor to the body of Christ, or [how he could direct]
the devotion of the people, with this same most worthy body being acci-
dents without subject, which Augustine says is not able to be, or if it is, it is
one nothing or something most abject in its nature. Then, I say, Augustine
would be largely consonant with a heretic, when he writes in Epistle XIV
to Boniface of the faith of the Church: “If a sacrament did not have a certain
similitude to the things of which they are sacraments, there would not be
any sacraments. They take their names from these similitudes and from
the fullness of strength in these things. Just as according to a certain sacra-
mental way the body of Christ is corporeally Christ, and the sacrament of
the blood is Christ’s blood.”5 Here it is plain that it is said of the sacrament
that the accidents are imagined without a subject. But in what, I ask, is its
similitude to the body of Christ? Really the fruit of this madness would be
to blaspheme God, to bring scandal to the saints, and to ridicule the church
through lies about accidents. To this, certain testimonies of the saints are
subverted by glossators, so that by thinking in an equivocal sense, anything
that is said, even scripturally, is not shameless to the faith.
Hilary writes, as is repeated in On Consecration d.2, “The body of Christ
which is taken on the altar is the figure, while it appears bread and wine
externally, the truth is believed on the inside, with the body and blood of
Christ.” See how plainly this sacrament is the bread and wine, as in the
decretum Ego Berengarius. So for the uncovering of equivocations in this
matter, it is written according to Jerome, “Of this particular host, through
which a commemoration of Christ is miraculously made, one may eat”
[Jerome’s commentary On Leviticus]. Here it is plain that what is discussed
is corporeal eating, and he distinguishes between these two hosts according
to their substances or natures; granted that this bread would be according to
another reason as sacramentally the same body as Jerome says in his letter
to Elvidam, as listed above.
And it is clear how difficult the cultivators of signs are in this matter
of heresy, not to say because they impose a heresy upon the faithful when
they elucidate this faith; and an accusation of heresy obligates a punishment
in retaliation, because they deny and falsify our Lord Jesus Christ. For we
ought [to] believe nothing according to faith in the gospel of Jesus Christ if
He did not assert that the bread that He held in His hand and broke was
wyclif’s confessio 235
His body, just as Augustine says about Psalm 66, “If I were to have said any-
thing, I do not will that you believe it thereby, but if Christ speaks, woe to
he who does not believe.” Nor should we believe something to be the sense
of the Gospels, if it is not so.
So woe to the adulterous generation, who believes more the testimony
of Innocent or Raymond, than the sense of the Gospels taken from the wit-
nesses just given. This would indeed bring scandal to them, and impose
the heresy through the perversion of Scripture. Particularly again, woe
to the perverse mouth of the apostate accumulating lies about the Roman
church, who imagines that the later church has corrected the faith of the
early church through opposing it, that this sacrament would be accident
without a subject, and not true bread and wine, as the Gospels say with
the decretum. For by Augustine’s witness, priests cannot confect such acci-
dents without a subject. And yet the priests of Baal prize this above all, lying
without a doubt, just as they have been instructed by their father, about the
consecration of accidents, so that they count other masses to have been heard
unworthily, or those who dissent from their position to be unfit for a position
anywhere.
But I believe that, in the end, the truth will overcome them.6
From the understanding that every adverb determines its verb in com-
parison to the subject, with this proposition “The body of Christ is substan-
tially in the sacrament of the altar,” this sense should be held, i.e., the body
of Christ is in the sacrament of the altar in substantial mode. But it remains
that it is not there in an incorporeal, substantial mode, therefore it is there
in a corporeal, substantial mode, and hence, dimensively. Again, the body of
Christ is not otherwise in the sacrament of the altar than it is [when] eaten
by the faithful; but it is not eaten by the faithful substantially, therefore it is
not in the sacrament of the altar substantially. The minor is clear from the
blessed Augustine and is posited in the decretal, where it says this, “The
body of Christ may not be ground down by faithful teeth.” Again, Christ
is not in the sacrament of the altar in some way other than the way He is
there sacramentally. But nothing being Christ is essentially its sacramental
being, therefore Christ is not in the sacrament of the altar essentially. The
minor is clear, that He is only there sacramentally, just as is clear through
the exponents, therefore, etc. Again, thus truly is Christ in the soul of the
just in the same way as He is in the sacrament of the altar, but He is not
in the soul of the just essentially substantially. Therefore He is not in the
sacrament of the altar, and this can be proven as such with Anselm. And
236 appendix
the major is proven [in that] where Christ has perfect and real being, there
He is perfectly and really, but in the soul of the just He has a being more
perfect and real than in the sacrament of the altar, therefore, etc. And many
doubt what is denoted by the word “this” when “this is my body” is said.
A certain decretist as ordinary glossator [John of God] holds that noth-
ing is denoted by the name “this” since the same and the whole oration is
taken materially just as spoken by Christ; which if it were true in signify-
ing everything the whole oration and the good subject it denotes, it would
indicate nothing on the inside. How would these words of Christ be an
effective sacrament of the altar in us, or bread miraculously convertible?
Thus others say that through this pronoun is denoted the body abso-
lutely simply, but these fools soil the faith, since according to them Christ
would not intend more save that His body is His body, which was true
beginning with His birth. Thus the reasoning of the blessed Jerome in his
letter to Hedibiam was held, “We should hear the bread which the Lord
broke and gave to His disciples to eat to be the body of the Lord Savior,
Himself saying, ‘This is my body.’ ” Where it is clear that this saint, who
more understood the sense of Scripture than all the lying postillators from
the time of Innocent III to today, acknowledges as a certitude of the faith
that in this proposition, bread is denoted sacramentally as substance rather than
Christ, just as its speaker had accepted it in His hands before, and from this
repeatedly the Apostle in this treatise chapters 10 and 11 pronounces this
sacrament to be bread. And the same is clear in the four evangelists (Luke
24 and Acts 2). Nor do I doubt but that the authors of Scripture understood
the bread to be not a nothing, or unknown accidents, but the true bread
which the priest transubstantiates by virtue of the sacramental words into
the body of the Lord; and truly this holy doctor [Jerome] with others in
the age of Christ clearly and deeply perceives the sense of Scripture, and
especially the propositions of the faith, better than every pope or postillator
succeeding from the time in which the devil was loosed. This same saint
manifestly says that this bread that the priest takes in consecrating hands
is the body of the Lord; which proves through this that He who cannot lie
says, “This is my body” when without doubt he denotes this bread. But
from the time in which the Church was divided through the introduction
of apostasy, the faith about the sacrament of the Eucharist was divided,
indicating an ulterior division between popes and such and the simple reli-
gion of the Christian, since nevertheless the Apostle says that there should
be one faith. But all the friars or others from private religions do not know
wyclif’s confessio 237
what is denoted by the pronoun, or what in its nature would be the percep-
tible sacrament discernible to the eye, secondly divided into three parts, and
third devoured by chewing teeth. The instant one of the faithful asks this
question of the satraps, they flee in ignorance, insanely simulating weight
with extensive subterfuge. He cannot convince the faithful that this is the
faith before he could disclose this matter of the faith. I often have asked the
friars in what sense the sacrament that is frequently called bread should
be understood, but they have not dared to express their position, as if they
were innocents not knowing the faith.
But these ignorant ones argue against our reasonings and the sense of
the Lord first, paralogistically, which they call an expository syllogism,
claiming that they prove that the entire body of Christ, united and in each
individual part, may cruelly be broken by us, decay, and be devoured by
vile beasts, because this bread has been treated thus by many, and this bread
according to us is the body of Christ, therefore the body of Christ is thus
treated.
But, as I have often said, these ignorant people should first learn by logic
and the faith of the Church how this does not follow expositorily if this
divine nature is communicated to these three supposits, and thus of a thou-
sand examples in the matter of the Trinity. The second example is in the
matter of Incarnation, where it does not follow: This Christ is the assumed
humanity, and this Christ is deity, therefore the assumed humanity is deity;
indeed, through this same argument they argue and hold with other infi-
dels that deity had been laid open and died, because Christ, who is this
deity, underwent this. The third example is in the matter of universals,
through which an example of the ignorant faith is brought into service in
the matter: if A is the common man [i.e., humanity], it is not right if this
A were Socrates and this same A [because] since the common man is every
man, that the pope would be Socrates. Therefore, as they say reasoning
properly, only when the middle term [i.e., humanity] exists, is this neces-
sitated through the force of an expository syllogism for the extreme terms
[i.e., Socrates and the pope], of which one is as such conjoined through the
common, because this way, if Socrates dies, and he is as such the human
species, then the whole species dies. The minor is false, since Socrates is an
individual according to his personal propriety; but a man is the human spe-
cies according to the commonality that is communicated to any individual
of the species, and you will run into such wasteful reasoning whenever such
a paralogism is called expository syllogism.
238 appendix
But third a certain puppy argues principally in this manner: If the sacra-
ment of the altar were material bread, it follows, that every viator would be
thus perfected in his nature, such that the final form of any man would
be accidentally more perfect; the final form of this sacrament would be
accidental, since the same would be a sacrament accidentally. But the fox
has often grumbled about this argument, first about the conclusion of the
first proposition, since every dog contrary to the faith of the sacrament
perceives that the same would be more imperfect in its nature than what
could be allotted to another substance. In this way, then, this puppy holds
as unsuitable that a man in whose grace the sacrament is eaten would be
more perfect than the sacrament on its own. I am astounded at the form of
this dog’s argument. For if this argument were to describe the faith, then
any created substance would be more imperfect than what might be allot-
ted to another.
Fourth, it is not created substance, although it were informed with acci-
dents. In dismissing these arguments I concede that this sacrament would
be in its nature more imperfect than the paschal lamb prefigured in the
old testament, but it is sacramentally far more perfect, because [it is the]
created body of Christ. And I wish that the faithful, or the heretical if they
dare, would place their faith on the quiddity of this venerable sacrament.
Nor do I doubt but that everyone pertinaciously opposed to this reasoning
are the heretics, whether pope, or bishop, or member of a private religion.
For according to the saints in the age of Christ, and especially in the ancient
faith preserving the laity, this sacrament is the body of Christ in the form of
bread. But these obtusely defend the contrary, so according to the definition
of heresy, these are manifestly heretics, which if they will have denied Holy
Scripture to assert this, they fall apart through the testimony of the saints
and arguments of the watchful about how the words of Truth that cannot
lie should be understood: “This is my body.” They ought not believe the
false fables of the false brothers, that this sacrament is nothing or accidents,
but (as the Scripture faith often says) the substance of true bread. Just as
Christ is two natures, namely humanity and divinity united in [one] person,
such that any of these is the person of Christ, so in the same manner this sac-
rament is true bread naturally and sacramentally the body of Christ. And
in this union of titles the hypostatic union is most fully. It is right, though,
for the faithful theologian to know triple predication for detecting sophis-
tic arguments of the devil in this matter, namely formal predication, essen-
tial predication, and habitual predication. Whoever is ignorant of these
240 appendix
of Scripture, though, says that the same sacrament is the bread that is
broken, and it is certain that this bread is not identical to the body of Christ,
nor [is it] the accidents obscure to the faithful, nor [is it] nothing. And so
I deny that this bread in its nature is prior [to] the bread a horse might
eat, nor to any other material substance as poison. So in such arguments
I look closely at heretics seeking the way of Christ from these things that
they themselves perceive of the quiddity and the passions of this venerable
sacrament.
Returning to the text, [which is] often put forth as the reasoning of Christ
alluding to our reasoning, where He says, “Do this in remembrance of me.”
For Christ wished the bread and wine to be sacramentally consumed as
a memorial for His faithful. In doing this, the text says the chalice there is
“a new testament” in the blood of Christ [which] is fully indicated through
predication of habitus, since the new testament has been understood to be
identical with neither the chalice nor the wine it contains. It is treachery to
disbelieve that the Word of God, who is eternal wisdom, alternates with
His words indifferently in this, but productively and with comprehensive
reasoning. He does not say this wine is my blood, but “this cup is the new
testament” in my blood, where it is clear that according to metonymy He
understands through this chalice, the wine to be contained in the chalice,
and through this is taught that in the prior proposition, “this is my body,” is
uniformly demonstrated through the pronoun that sacrament, since there
would not be an imaginable reason why in the following proposition “this
cup is the new testament” the liquor perceptibly contained in the cup is
demonstrated, but that through the same in the prior proposition would
be demonstrated the bread that He holds in His hands.
Second it is known how Christ through the second word says in different
ways “this cup” not “to be” His blood but “a new testament in His blood,”
so that thus He would teach His church such predication to be habitual,
and not identical. Thus the postillators, who say that from the order of
words before and after it is clear that this is not figurative locution without
foundation, in fact deceive themselves and their followers.
But third it is clear that, just as the sprinkling of the blood of a calf
remotely figured the confirmation of the old testament, thus the wine of
this cup figures the nearness of the new testament, and it is in accordance
with the realization of the testament itself, and is not contradictory. Indeed
the Holy Spirit at once says both, although differently and equivocally,
that “This is the cup of my blood of the new and eternal testament,” and
242 appendix
“This cup is the new testament” in my blood, because on both sides, the
same reasoning is thus expressed.
And a grammarian would be ashamed by the baseless rudeness with
which they say that this pronoun “this” refers only to an insensible thing.
For the Holy Spirit shows in the grammar a thing commonly perceptible,
as is clear in this proposition from the end of Ecclesiastes, “Fear God and
keep His commandment, this is all man” [Ecclesiastes 12:13]. And this at
the end of Mark, “And these signs shall follow them that believe” [Mark
16:17]. “For as often,” it says, “as you shall eat this bread and drink this
cup, you shall show the death of the Lord, until He comes” [1 Corinthians
11:26]. A certain body is to that end made sacramental and whence to the
day of judgment the viator may memorialize the death of the Lord. But
from this to arriving at clear knowledge of the presence of the body of
Christ in accidents through experience would be a waste of this kind of
sacrament. Thus, “Whoever will have eaten the bread and drunk this cup
of the Lord unworthily will be answerable for the body and blood of the
Lord” [perhaps a variant of 1 Corinthians 11:27], for just as a lying traitor
impiously kissing, he simulates the sacramental and fruitful memory, and
like another Judas, he lies beneath the cup pointlessly pretending.
For “let a man prove himself ” [1 Corinthians 11:28] and thus the world
may be saved from crime, and in the right intention to fruitful remember-
ing through these parts of the Lord, as much in the body as in the soul. “He
who eats and drinks unworthily, eats and drinks in judgment of himself ”
[1 Corinthians 11:29] since falsity presents an appearance contrary to the
judgment of the truth; in which way, therefore, “he discerns,” that is, in dis-
tinguishing in his memory the end from which he judges with the reason of
which such a corporeal meal is eaten; the end of which God would intend
of such thoughtless judgment of a traitor of this kind has been frustrated.
If, on the other hand, without such eating a man would drink the fruitful
memory from the body and blood of Christ, he spiritually eats the body
of Christ and drinks His blood [as] well. And by this quadruple recita-
tion by which the sacrament is said to be “bread” is the faithful awakened
to defending the reasoning and words of Paul, even though he had been
baselessly dreaming during the words and the extraneous reasoning. What,
then, would Saint Paul understand by bread and wine?
But if it is objected that according to this reasoning the sacrament is
violated, it may be said to the adversary of the faith that they themselves
object even as they are idolatrously raising up perceptible creatures in their
wyclif’s confessio 243
faithless worship of God; thus indeed the ignorant carry on, who, unaware
of the proper voices, lack understanding of what the sacrament is. But they
know, just as they falsely imagine, that it [the sacrament] would be more
imperfect than any other material substance signified, and through this
they seduce the people that this sacrament is not honorable in its nature, but
deserves honor because it is really, if imperceptibly, the body of Christ. We,
however, say that this sacrament is honorable in its nature and much less in
its nature, but the same really is, as the faithful people believe, the body of
Christ. The faithful are stimulated in their faith by this faithless reasoning,
for they believe in concord, and they adore in effect, this sensible thing just
as they would Christ, and by lifting up some little piece of wood there is in
it the blessed Trinity, since necessarily it would be both, and consequently a
more perfect body of Christ, in which indeed there is commonly the same
body of Christ, since it has itself spiritually in any part of His kingdom.
By this the adversary of the faith would dishonor through evil ignorance
the body of Christ inasmuch as it is in the sacrament. And thus this little
treatise is ended.
This page intentionally left blank
notes
abbreviations
CCSLC Corpus Christianorum Series Latina Clavis
CHLMP Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy
DCD De Civili Dominio
DCH De Composicione Hominis
DD De Dominio Divino
De XII De Duodecem Abusivis Saeculii
DI De Incarnacione
DMD De Mandatis Divinis
DOR De Officio Regis
DT De Trinitate
DU De Universalibus
DVSS De Veritate Sacrae Scripturae
EETS Early English Text Society journal
FZ Fasciculi Zizianorum
OP Opera Polemica
PG Patrologia Graeca
WS Wyclif Society
chapter 1
1. William James, The Varieties of Religious Experience (Viking Penguin,
1982), “Lecture I: Religion and Neurology,” 24.
245
246 notes to pages 4– 9
chapter 2
1. See R. L. Poole’s introduction to DD, xxi. The groundbreaking
survey of the philosophy and theology of the period remains The Cambridge
History of Later Medieval Philosophy, ed. Norman Kretzman, Anthony Kenny,
and Jan Pinborg (Cambridge, 1982). Accompanying this is The Cambridge
Translations of Medieval Philosophical Texts, a set of anthologies exemplifying
250 notes to pages 33–42
the development and breadth of later medieval thought. See volume 1, Logic
and the Philosophy of Language, ed. Norman Kretzman and Eleonore Stump
(1988); volume 2, Ethics and Politics, ed. A. S. McGrade, John Kilcullen,
and Matthew Kempshall (2001); volume 3, Mind and Knowledge, ed. Robert
Pasnau (2002). Volume 2 contains Kilcullen’s translation of the first ten chap-
ters of Wyclif ’s DCD I.
2. See Marilyn McCord Adams, William Ockham (Notre Dame, Ind., 1988),
2 vols.; Paul Vincent Spade, A Cambridge Companion to Ockham (Cambridge,
1999). For an overview of Oxford’s “golden age,” see William Courtenay,
Schools and Scholars in Fourteenth Century England (Princeton, N.J., 1987).
3. Hester Gelber, It Could Have Been Otherwise: Contingency and Necessity
in Dominican Theology at Oxford 1300–1350 (Leiden, 2004), 313n9; reference is
to Scotus’s Ordinatio I, d.44, in Opera Omnia, ed. Charles Balic (Vatican City,
1963), 6, 363.17–364.10.
4. William Ockham, Quodlibetal Questions, trans. Alfred Freddosso (New
Haven, Conn., 1991), vol. 2, 491.
5. See William Courtenay, Capacity and Volition (Bergamo, Italy, 1990).
6. See ibid., 265–266; also Gracia 674–675. The influence of Chatton on
Wyclif deserves much fuller consideration than is possible here, where Wyclif ’s
more immediate opponents are of interest. See Girard Etzkorn and Joseph
Wey, eds., Reportatio in I Sent. Dist. 1–9 and Dist. 10–48 (Toronto, 2002), 2 vols.
7. Adam de Wodeham, Lectura Secunda in Librum Primum Sentatiarum,
ed. Rega Wood and Gedeon Gàl (St. Bonaventure, N.Y., 1990). “Et ideo ad
variationem mediorum secundum speciem variatur actus sciendi secundum
speciem, et diversae scientiae non probant formaliter eandem conclusionem
per idem medium, nisi mendicando” (d.1, q.3.12, 247).
8. Ibid., vol. 2, “Et ideo nisi per fidem nobis innotuisset quod una res est
tres res, credidissemus firmiter sophismata praedicta bona fuissa argumenta”
(d.2, q.1.13, 25).
9. See Norman Kretzman and Barbara Ensign Kretzman, The Sophismata
of Richard Kilvington (Cambridge, 1990); Edith Dudley Sylla, “The Oxford
Calculators,” in Kretzman, Kenny, and Pinborg 1982, 540–563.
10. John E. Murdoch, “Mathesis in Philosophiam Scholasticam Introducta:
The Rise and Development of the Application of Mathematics in Fourteenth
Century Philosophy and Theology,” in Arts Libéraux et Philosophie au Moyen
Age (Montreal and Paris, 1969), 215–254.
11. Curtis Wilson, William Heytesbury: Medieval Logic and the Rise of
Mathematical Physics (Madison, Wisc., 1956); Marshall Clagett, The Science of
Mechanics in the Middle Ages (Madison, Wisc., 1959).
12. See Opus oxoniense I, d.III, q.4, in Philosophical Writings, trans. Allan
Wolter (Hackett, 1987), 97–132, esp. 106–115.
notes to pages 42–48 251
21. Quodlibet 87, Utrum haec est concedenda: Deus est Pater et Filius et Spiritus
Sanctus, in Hester Gelber, Exploring the Boundaries of Reason: Three Questions
on the Nature of God by Robert Holcot, OP (Toronto, 1983), 34–36.
22. Robert Holcot, Super Libros Sapientiae (Hagenau, 1494; rpt., Frankfurt,
1974), lect. 155, translated by Beryl Smalley in English Friars and Antiquity in
the Early Fourteenth Century (Oxford, 1960), 185.
23. It is still too soon to declare certain treatises to have been included
in Wyclif ’s Sentences commentary. This line of reasoning was introduced by
J. A. Robson in Wyclif and the Oxford Schools (Cambridge, 1961); I explore it more in
“Wyclif ’s Trinitarian and Christological Theology,” in A Companion to John Wyclif,
ed. Ian Levy (Leiden, 2006), 127–198, but further documentary research is needed.
24. See also De Trinitate, chap. 10, 110.
25. See Katherine Tachau, Vision and Certitude in the Age of Ockham: Optics,
Epistemology and the Foundations of Semantics 1250–1345 (Leiden, 1988), for a
definitive history of the complexities of early fourteenth-century epistemology.
For Peter Aureol, see Scriptum proem I, 204–205 (Aureol’s Sentences Commentary
in its second version), in E. Buytaert, ed., Petri Aureoli Scriptum super primum
Sententiarum, prooemium-dist. 8, 2 vols. (St. Bonaventure, N.Y., 1953–1956);
Tachau 85–112. For Scotus on intuitive cognition, see Sebastian Day, Intuitive
Cognition: A Key to the Significance of the Later Scholastics (St. Bonaventure, N.Y.,
1947); Allan Wolter, “Duns Scotus on Intuition, Memory, and Our Knowledge
of Individuals,” in The Philosophical Theology of John Duns Scotus, ed. Marilyn
McCord Adams (Ithaca, N.Y., 1990).
26. For Rodington, see Tachau 216–236; for Bacon, Pecham, and Witelo on
optics, see David C. Linberg, “Lines of Influence in Thirteenth-Century Optics:
Bacon, Witelo, and Pecham,” Speculum 46: 66–83; for Witelo, see Sabetai
Unguru, “Witelonis Perspectivae Liber Primus,” Studia Copernicana 15 (1977).
27. Trialogus II.6.
28. See Unguru 12–40.
29. See Eleonore Stump, “The Mechanisms of Cognition: Ockham on
Mediating Species,” in Spade 1999, 168–203.
30. Translated by Robert Pasnau, in The Cambridge Translations of Medieval
Philosophical Texts: vol. 3, Mind and Knowledge (Cambridge, 2003), 255.
31. For Crathorn, see Quaestiones super librum sententiarum, in Questionen
Zum ersten Sentenzenbuch, ed. F. Hoffmann (Münster, 1988); also Sent. I, q.1, trans.
Pasnau; Tachau 255–274; Robert Aurélien, “William Crathorn,” in Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, available at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/crat
horn/#8b.
32. De Actibus Anime I, 1.1–10.
33. Pasnau 298–299. See also Adams, William Ockham, vol. 1, 552–571, for
Henry of Ghent’s position, and William Frank and Allan Wolter, Duns Scotus,
notes to pages 57–70 253
Metaphysician, 125, 167. See Julius Weinberg, Nicholas of Autrecourt (Princeton, N.J.,
1948), and Constantin Michalski, Le Criticisme et le Scepticisme dans la Philosophie
du XIVe Siècle (Cracow, 1926), reprinted in La Philosophie au XIVe Siècle: Six
Etudes (Frankfurt, 1969), 100. On the differences between Descartes’ use of this
argument and Augustine’s, see Gareth Matthews, “Si fallor, sum,” in Augustine:
A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. R. A. Markus (New York, 1972), 151–167.
34. Insolubilia literature is extensive in medieval logic. See Paul V. Spade,
“Insolubilia,” in CHLMP 246–253, and also online at The Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy. See Johannis Wyclif: Summa Insolubilium, ed. Paul V. Spade and
Gordon Wilson (Binghamton, N.Y., 1986).
35. De Logica, vol. 1, 181.
36. Purgans Errores circa Universalia in Communi, De Ente I, Tractatus IV,
chap. 5, in Johannis Wyclif De Ente Librorum Duorum (WS 1909), 47.7–22.
37. See Gordon Leff, Richard Fitzralph: Commentator on the Sentences
(Manchester, 1963), 52–55. My thanks are due to Michael Dunne, who kindly
provided me with a draft of his edition of Fitzralph’s discussion in I, q.5, a.6.
38. Zénon Kaluza, “L’ouevre théologique de Richard Brinkley, OFM,”
Archives d’Histoire Doctrinale et Littéraire du Moyen Age 56: 169–273.
39. Summa de Ente, Libri Primi: Tractatus primus et secundus, ed. S. Harrison
Thomson (Oxford, 1930), xxv (translation by Thomson).
40. Trialogus I, i.
41. DT, chap. 1, 3: “Hic dicitur communiter, quod nemo potest sine fide
prima assentire isti deduccioni, et ideo non est mere naturalis, et sic non demon-
stratur in lumine naturali.”
42. Trialogus I.6, 55.
43. DT, chap. 2, 19.
chapter 3
1. James McEvoy, Robert Grosseteste (Oxford, 2000); and Marilyn McCord
Adams, William Ockham (Notre Dame, Ind., 1987).
2. See Marilyn McCord Adams, “Universals in the Early Fourteenth
Century,” in CHLMP 411–439.
3. The Philobiblon of Richard de Bury, trans. E. C. Thomas (London, 1888),
chap. 9. See www.philobiblon.com/philobiblon.htm.
4. See Beryl Smalley, English Friars and Antiquity in the Early Fourteenth
Century (Oxford, 1960), for development of the idea that Oxford friars were
moving toward humanism.
5. Jennifer Ottman and Rega Wood, “Walter of Burley: His Life and
Works,” Vivarium 37.1 (1999): 1–23. This edition of Vivarium is devoted entirely
to Burley and provides the most up-to-date introduction available.
254 notes to pages 71–79
6. For Aquinas, see Sententia super Posteriora Analytica II.20.14. For Burley,
see n. 7. See also Alessandro Conti, “Walter Burley,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy, online at http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fa112004/entries/burley.
Also see his “Ontology in Walter Burley’s Last Commentary on the Ars Vetus,”
Franciscan Studies 50 (1990): 121–176; and Elizabeth Karger, “Walter Burley’s
Realism,” Vivarium 37.1 (1999): 24–40.
7. See Walter Burley, Super artem veterem Porphirii et Aristotles, trans. Paul
Vincent Spade, in Readings in Medieval Philosophy, ed. Andrew Schoedinger
(Oxford, 1996), 619–646. Reference here is to Metaphysics VII.
8. Stephen F. Brown, “Walter Burley’s Quaestiones in Librum Periher-
meneias,” Franciscan Studies 34 (1974): 213 (1.82). See Elizabeth Karger’s discus-
sion in Karger 1999, 34–36.
9. William Courtenay, Adam Wodeham (Leiden, 1978), 59–60.
10. Tachau 269n81. See 255–274 for a more complete discussion than is
possible here.
11. Robert Holcot, Conferentiae, ed. Fritz Hoffman, in Die “Conferentiae” des
Robert Holcot O.P. und die Akademischen Auseinandersetzungen an der Univerität
Oxford 1330–1332 (Münster, 1993), 73–82.
12. Peter Lombard, Sententiae I, d.1, chap. 1; reference is to Augustine, De
Doctrina Christiana I.2.
13. Walter Chatton, Lectura, prologue, q.1, translated in Tachau 205.
14. William Ockham, Exposition super librum Perihermenias, translated in
Philosophical Writings, ed. Philotheus Boehner and Stephen Brown, 44.
15. Adam de Wodeham, Lectura Secunda in Librum Primum Sententiarum,
ed. Rega Wood and Gedeon Gàl (St. Bonaventure, N.Y., 1990), I, d.1, q.1,
180–208; see also Jack Zupko, John Buridan: Portrait of a Fourteenth-Century
Arts Master (Notre Dame, Ind., 2003), 126; and Gabriel Nuchelmans, “Adam
Wodeham on the Meaning of Declarative Sentences,” Historiographia Linguistica 7
(1980): 177–187.
16. Bertrand Russell, “The Philosophy of Logical Atomism: 1. Facts and
Propositions,” in Logic and Knowledge, ed. Robert Charles Marsh (London,
1956, 1989), 185.
17. See Laurent Cesalli, “Le ‘pan-propositionalisme’ de Jean Wyclif,”
Vivarium 43.1: 124–155. See also his “Some Fourteenth-Century Realist Theories
of the Proposition: A Historical and Speculative Study,” in Signification in
Language and Culture, ed. H. S. Gill (Shimla, 2002), 83–118, and his Le réal-
isme propositionnel: Sémantique et ontologie des propositions chez Jean Duns Scot,
Gauthier Burley, Richard Brinkley et Jean Wyclif (Paris, 2007).
18. De Logica, vol. 1, chap. 5, 14.1–4. Recall that this first treatise of De
Logica is Wyclif ’s primer written for students hungry to understand the logic
of scripture through the lens of formal academic logic.
notes to pages 80 –89 255
the bibliography. Professor Wilem Herold and Dr. Ivan Mueller are in the fin-
ishing stages of a complete edition of De Ideis, which will certainly supersede
the incomplete version I’ve used.
34. De Veritate, q.3, a.1, ad.5; Summa Theologica Ia, q.15, aa.1–2. For a
comparison of theories of divine ideas, see M. J. F. M. Hoenen, Marsilius of
Inghen (Leiden, 1993), 121–156; Alessandro Conti, “Divine Ideas and Exemplar
Causality in Auriol,” Vivarium 38 (2000): 99–116.
35. For Henry of Ghent, see Quodlibeta VIII, q.1 and q.8; IX, q.2. For Scotus,
see Lectura I, d.35. For a discussion of the relation of Henry and Scotus, see
William Frank and Allan Wolter, Duns Scotus, Metaphysician (West Lafayette,
Ind., 1995), 165–166. For Peter Aureol, see Commentariorum in primum librum
Sententiarum Pars prima, d.35.
36. Ordinatio I, d.35, q.5, in Opera Theologica IV, 483, ed. Etzkorn and Kelly
(St. Bonaventure, N.Y., 1979).
37. See Adams, William Ockham, 1033–1063; Thomas Bradwardine, De
Causa Dei I.xvii, 219; Walter Chatton, Reportatio super Sententias I, d.35, q.2,
316–317.
38. De Ideis, chap. 3
39. De Ideis, chap. 4.
40. See Robson 1961, 141–171. For a recent plea for moderation regard-
ing Wyclif ’s realism, see Paul V. Spade, “Universals and Wyclif ’s Alleged
‘Ultrarealism,’ ” Vivarium 43.1 (2004): 111–123. See this also for a complete bib-
liography of recent scholarly assessments of Wyclif ’s thought on universals.
41. DU, trans. Kenny, chap. 9, 402–405.
42. For Boethius, see Second Commentary on Porphyry’s Isagoge, in P. V. Spade,
ed., Five Texts on the Mediaeval Problem of Universals (Hackett, 1994), 20–26;
for Abelard, see “Glosses on Porphyry,” in Logica “ingredientibus,” ibid.,
26–56.
43. This explanation of Wyclif ’s types of universals is more fully presented
in Paul V. Spade’s “Introduction” to Kenny’s DU translation. For an excellent
introduction to the medieval discourse on universals, see Spade’s Five Texts on
the Mediaeval Problem of Universals.
44. This is more fully discussed in my Philosophy and Politics in the Thought
of John Wyclif (Cambridge, 2003), 73–75. See also De Logica III, chap. 2, 35.
11–33; Purgans Errores, chap. 4, 41.14–30; DU, chap. 4, 28.
45. De Ente Predicamentali, chap. 5, 43.9–27. For a more complete discus-
sion of Wyclif ’s conception of essence and being, see A. D. Conti, “Logica
intensionale e metafisica dell’essenza in John Wyclif,” Bullettino dell’Instituto
Storico Italiano per il Medioevo e Archivio Muratoriano 99.1 (1993): 159–219;
Conti, “Wyclif ’s Logic and Metaphysics,” in Levy 2006; Conti, “Wyclif,” in
The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, available at http://plato.stanford.
notes to pages 99 –109 257
chapter 4
1. H. von der Hardt, Magnum oecumenicum Constantiense concilium, 6 vols.
(Frankfurt and Leipzig, 1696–1700), vol. 4, 406. See John Murdoch, “Infinity
and Continuity,” in CHLMP 576n36. For a translation of much of the council’s
condemnation of Wyclif, see http://www.dailycatholic.org/history/16ecume1.
htm.
2. Augustine, De Sacramentis IV, 14–15; Tractatus in Iohannis Evangelium
XXVI, 11; De Doctrina Christiana 55.
3. Levy 135; Gary Macy, The Theologies of the Eucharist in Early Medieval
Europe (Oxford, 1984). See Paschasius Radbertus, De Corpore et Sanguine
Domini; Ratramnus Corbie, De Corpore et Sanguine Domini.
4. Quoted in Levy 140. Cited in Lanfranc of Bec, Liber de Corpore et
Sanguine Domini. For Berengar, see De Sacra Coena Adversus Lanfrancum.
5. Lotario de Segni, De Sacro Altaris Mysterio.
6. See Summa Theologica IIIa, q.77, a.1–7.
7. See David Burr, “Scotus and Transubstantiation,” Mediaeval Studies
34 (1972): 336–360. See Duns Scotus, Quaestiones in Librum Sententiarum IV,
d.10–11; Ordinatio Liber Primus, d.11.
8. William Ockham, Reportatio IV, 8; Tractatus de Quantitate; Tractatus
de Corpore Christi. An edition of the latter two, entitled De Sacramento Altaris,
ed. T. Bruce Birch (Burlington, Iowa, 1930), has been superseded by the Opera
258 notes to pages 110–118
Theologica published by the Franciscan Institute. See also Quodlibeta II, 19;
IV, 13.
9. Bartolme Maria Xiberta y Roqueta, De Scriptoribus Scholasticis Saeculis
XIV ex Ordine Carmelitarum (Louvain, 1931).
10. I am indebted to Rega Wood, who provided me with a draft of a trans-
lation of Ordinatio Liber Primus IV, q.5, which is being prepared by Professor
Wood and Father Gedeon Gàl. See also Adam de Wodeham, Tractatus de
Indivisibilibus, ed. Rega Wood (Dordrecht, 1988).
11. See Levy 280–281; Dallas G. Denery II, “From Sacred Mystery to
Divine Deception: Robert Holkot, John Wyclif and the Transformation of
Fourteenth-Century Eucharistic Discourse,” Journal of Religious History 29.2
( June 2005): 129–144. All quotations from Holcot are from In Quatuor Libros
Sententiarum Quaestiones IV, q.3.
12. See John Murdoch, “Infinity and Continuity,” in CHLMP 564–591.
13. This translation is from Murdoch’s edition published in CHLMP
576n36. Note Bradwardine’s willingness to include Grosseteste among the ato-
mists. For a lucid survey of Bradwardine’s theory of time and rejection of atom-
ism, see Edith Wilks Dolnikowski, Thomas Bradwardine: A View of Time and a
Vision of Eternity in Fourteenth-Century Thought (Leiden, 1995).
14. Norman Kretzman, “Continua, Indivisibles, and Change in Wyclif ’s
Logic of Scripture,” in Kenny 1986, 31–65; here, see n. 78. I am very grateful
to the late Professor Kretzman for having given me his extensive notes and the
translations of De Logica that he used in preparing this article.
15. See Calvin Normore, “Walter Burley on Continuity,” in Infinity and
Continuity, ed. Norman Kretzman (Ithaca, N.Y., 1982), 258–269.
16. Kretzman, 57–58, translating Logice continuatio, chap. 14, 194.36–195.2.
Note that the Oxford schools were well aware of Zeno’s arguments thanks to
Aristotle’s records of them. Wyclif refers once in passing to Zeno in De Logica,
but Wodeham explores his arguments in Tractatus de Indivisibilibus, q.3.
17. Kretzman, 61–62, translation of Logice continuatio 197.3–6.
18. Kretzman, 63, translation of Logice continuatio III, 132.25–32.
19. Trialogus II, chap. 3.
20. See Robson’s (1966) discussion at 156–161. De Tempore has been made
available to me in the version prepared under the supervision of M. H. Dzwiecki
for the Wyclif Society a century ago, thanks to its discovery by Lesley Ann
Dyer in the spring of 2005. The text is being prepared in a critical edition by
Wlodzimierz Zega.
21. See Simo Knutilla, Modalities in Medieval Philosophy (London, 1993),
138–150. For critique of Knutilla’s position, see Nicole Wyatt, “Did Duns Scotus
Invent Possible Worlds Semantics?” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 78.2
( June 2000): 196–212.
notes to pages 119 –129 259
chapter 5
1. These honorific titles lack the imprimatur of official sanction, despite
their widespread use. In fact, the Catholic designation “doctor of the church,”
which has been bestowed upon Aquinas, Bonaventure, and Albertus Magnus,
each of whom have his own medieval “doctor” cognomen, was first instituted
by Boniface VIII in 1925. Hence, Anthony of Padua (1195–1231, proclaimed
doctor of the church in 1946) is officially known as doctor evangelicus, while
Wyclif ’s name is not included among the officially celebrated doctors.
2. See Beryl Smalley, The Study of the Bible in the Middle Ages (Notre
Dame, Ind., 1964), for the classic narrative of the development of this tradi-
tion. For theological analysis, as well as a sustained argument for its continued
relevance, see Henri de Lubac, Scripture in the Tradition (New York, 1968). This
work is compiled from his four-volume Exégèse Médiévale, which is being pub-
lished in translation by Eerdmans.
3. See Heiko Oberman, “Facientibus Quod in se est Deus non Denegat
Gratiam: Robert Holcot, O.P., and the Beginnings of Luther’s Theology,” in
Oberman, The Dawn of the Reformation (Grand Rapids, Mich., 1992), 84–103.
For a fuller treatment of this in the context of the development of late medieval
theology, see Oberman, The Harvest of Late Medieval Theology (Harvard, 1963).
notes to pages 137–146 261
23. This question is the subject of Sentences III, d.12, c.1, and it appears that
what follows here is Wyclif ’s discussion of Lombard’s position.
24. DI, chap. 1, 3.6–11.
25. Everyman in Medieval English Literature, ed. J. B. Trapp (Oxford,
1973), 390–391.
26. DI, 216.13–16. For a more developed analysis of Wyclif ’s Christology,
see my “Wyclif ’s Trinitarian and Christological Theology,” in Wyclif Handbook,
ed. Ian C. Levy (Leiden, 2006).
27. DVSS I, 6; see Levy 2001, 97–112. By 1382, Wyclif had reduced the
number of levels to three; see Trialogus III, 31.
28. See Beryl Smalley, The Study of the Bible in the Middle Ages (Notre
Dame, Ind., 1964); Philip Krey and Lesley Smith, Nicholas of Lyra: The Senses
of Scripture (Leiden, 2000).
29. DVSS I, 12, 276.1–4.
30. Alistair Minnis, “ ‘Authorial Intention’ and ‘Literal Sense’ in the Exe-
getical Theories of Richard Fitzralph and John Wyclif: An Essay in the Medie-
val History of Biblical Hermeneutics,” Proceedings of the Royal Irish Academy
(Section C) 75.1 (1975): 1–30.
31. Beryl Smalley, “John Wyclif ’s Postilla Super Totam Bibliam,” Bodleian
Library Record 4.3 (April 1953): 186–205; Smalley, “Wyclif ’s Postilla on the Old
Testament and His Principium,” in Oxford Studies Presented to Daniel Callus,
O.P. (Oxford, 1964), 256.
32. De Apostasia, chap. 3, 49.17–25.
33. Opus Evangelicum II, 368.22–24.
34. Benrath 115n3.
35. Benrath 353. Benrath’s study contains twelve edited sections from
Wyclif ’s Postilla.
36. Benrath 119.
37. De Amore (ad Quinque Questiones), in Opera Minora, ed. J. Loserth (WS
1913), 8–10.
38. Opus Evangelicum IV, chap. 12, 325.17–326.30. W. Thomson suggests
that the passage’s appearance at the end of the manuscript may give evidence of
its composition on the last day of Wyclif ’s life. While the possibility exists that
he had written it earlier and that it was inserted by a later hand, it is satisfying
to imagine Wyclif seeing his coming end and attempting one last summation of
his guiding principles. See W. Thomson 1983, 221.
39. See J. van Banning, S.J., ed., Opus Imperfectum in Matthaeum (Praefatio)
(Turnhout, Belgium, 1988), 87B, esp. 276–277. The complete edition has yet
to appear, and the reader must be content with Migne’s 1859 PG, vol. 56,
611–916.
notes to pages 156 –164 263
40. Siegmund Hellman, ed., De Duodecem Abusivis Saeculi: Texte und Unter-
suchungen zur Geschichte der Altchristlichen Literatur (Leipzig, 1910). See Aidan
Breen, “Pseudo-Cyprian De Duodecim Abusivis Saeculi and the Bible,” in Irland
und die Christenheit (1987); and his “De XII Abusivis: Text and Transmission,” in
Ireland and Europe in the Early Middle Ages: Texts and Transmission, ed. Próinséas
Ní Chatháin and Michael Richter (Four Courts, 2002), 78–94. I am grateful to
Dr. Breen for having kindly provided me with his edition and translation of
this text.
41. Opus Evangelicum I, chap. 6, 18.19–25.
42. Postilla Matt. 5:8; DMD, chap. 12, 115.32; cited in Benrath 114n102.
43. De Mandatis Divinis, chap. 12, 93.8–11. See chapters 11–15 for the entire
“Treatise on Love.”
44. Opus Evangelicum II, chap. 33, 367.30–368.24. See Benrath, esp. 110–
122, “Das Gesetz Christi.”
45. See Siegfried Wenzel, Latin Sermon Collections from Later Medieval
England: Orthodox Preaching in the Age of Wyclif (Cambridge, 2005); Smalley
1960.
46. See English Wycliffite Sermons, ed. Anne Hudson and Pamela Gradon
(Oxford, 1983–1996), 5 vols.
47. Edith Wilks Dolnikowski, “Preaching at Oxford: Academic and Pastoral
Themes in Wyclif ’s Latin Sermon Cycle,” in Medieval Sermons and Society, ed.
J. Hamesse et al. (Louvain-la-Neuve, 1998), 371–386.
48. Praefatio, in Sermones, vol. 1, 1.7–14.
49. See William Mallard, “Clarity and Dilemma: The Forty Sermons of
John Wyclif,” in Contemporary Reflections on the Medieval Christian Tradition,
ed. G. H. Shriver et al. (Durham, N.C., 1974), 19–38.
50. See Sermones, vol. 4, 256–275.
51. DVSS II, 21, trans. Levy 287. For Wyclif on preaching, see Ian Levy,
“Wyclif and the Christian Life,” in A Companion to John Wyclif, ed. Ian Levy
(Leiden, 2006), 302–316.
52. De Officio Pastoralis, ed. G. Lechler (Leipzig, 1863), II.1, 32. Abridged
translation by Ford Lewis Battles in Advocates of Reform, ed. M. Spinka
(Philadelphia, 1953), 32–60. See also Sermones I, 110, 377.
53. De Officio Pastoralis I.1, ed. Spinka 32; I.8, ed. Spinka 38. See also
Sermones I, 244; DVSS III.25; Levy 306–310; DOR, chap. 7, 165–166.
54. De Ordinatione Fratrum, in Polemical Works in Latin, ed. R. Buddensieg
(WS 1883), vol. 1, 96.15–20. The Latin has panni rudis for the untreated patch,
and Wyclif also uses rudis to refer to their crude stories.
55. De Diabolo et Membrus Eius, in OP, vol. 1, 372. Reference is to 1 Corin-
thians 3:9.
264 notes to pages 165–171
chapter 6
1. Richard Copsey, O.C., The Hermits from Mount Carmel, vol. 3 of Carmel
in Britain (Kent, 2004).
2. See De Volucione Dei 117.20–21; Sermones I, 12; see also W. Thomson
1983, 100n8, citing at least fourteen other instances
3. See Ian Levy, “Defining the Responsibility of the Late Medieval Theo-
logian: The Debate between John Kynnyngham and John Wyclif,” Carmelus 19
notes to pages 171–182 265
(2002): fasc. 1, 5–29; Martin Hoenen, “Theology and Metaphysics: The Debate
between John Wyclif and John Kenningham on the Principles of Reading
the Scriptures,” in John Wyclif: Logica, Politica, Teologia, ed. Fumagalli and
Simonetta (Florence, 2003), 23–56.
4. De Ecclesia, chap. 1, 2.25. See Augustine, De Civitate Dei XVIII, 49; De
Praedestinatione Sanctorum, chap. 11.
5. De Ideis, chap. 3, see n. 21.
6. William Ockham, Predestination, God’s Foreknowledge, and Future
Contingents, ed. Marilyn McCord Adams and Norman Kretzman (Hackett,
1983), q.2, art. 4, pt. 1, 67. See also Tractatus de Principiis Theologiae I.5, and
Calvin Normore, “Future Contingents,” in CHLMP.
7. De Causa Dei I.35, 308c– d.
8. A complete study of Bradwardine would take both his mathematically
grounded physics and his theology into consideration, across the whole of his
career. The nearest to this is Edith Wilks Dolnikowski, Thomas Bradwardine: A
View of Time and a Vision of Eternity (Leiden, 1995). For his earlier theological
works, see Jean-Francois Genest, ed., “Le De futuris contingentibus de Thomas
Bradwardine,” Recherches Augustiniennes 14 (1979): 249–336; “Les premiers
écrits théologiques de Bradwardine: Textes inédits et découvertes récentes,” in
G. R. Evans, Mediaeval Commentaries on the Sentences of Peter Lombard (Leiden,
2002), vol. 1, 395–421.
9. De Futuris Contingentibus, trans. Norman Kretzman, unpublished draft,
1981; also see Genest 317.
10. Anselm, Cur Deus Homo II.17.
11. Summa Contra Gentiles I.67; Summa Theologica Ia, q.19, a.3. For Brad-
wardine’s deviation from Aquinas, see Oberman 1957, 71–76.
12. See Calvin Normore, “Future Contingents,” in CHLMP 374–377; see
also Bartolomew De La Torre, Thomas Buckingham and the Contingency of
Futures (Notre Dame, Ind., 1987).
13. De Ente Libri II, Tractatus iii (De Volucione Dei), 2, in De Ente Librorum
Duorum, ed. M. H. Dziewicki (WS 1909), 136.16–24.
14. Kenny translates this as “hypothetical” necessity; Conti refers to it as
“relational” necessity; to show Wyclif ’s ties to Aquinas in this discussion, I will
use necessity “by supposition.”
15. DU, chap. 14, 64–68. See Kenny 1985, 31–41; Kenny, “Realism and
Determinism in the Early Wyclif,” in Hudson and Wilks 165–178; Alessandro
Conti, “Wyclif ’s Logic and Metaphysics,” in Levy 2006, 67–126. See also Logice
continuacio I, xi, 157–161; De Logica III, x, 179.17–196.32; De Actibus Anime I,
71.23–76.20; DU, chap. 14.
16. De Actibus Anime I, 72.20.
17. DU, chap. 14, 162.336–339; De Logica III, x, 181.10–25.
266 notes to pages 183–193
18. See Robson 88–96; Walsh 1981, 129–181; K. Walsh, “Die Rezeption
der Schriften des Richard FitzRalph (Armachanus) in lollardisch-hussitischen
Kreisen,” in Das Publikum politischer Theorie im 14. Jahrhundert, ed. J. Miethke
(1992), 237–253. An edition of the Summa de Quaestionibus Armenorum is sorely
needed; the only extant edition is that of Johannis Sudoris (Paris, 1511).
19. De Dominio Divino (DD) I, 14, 130.23–25. See Ian Levy, “Grace and
Freedom in the Soteriology of John Wyclif,” Traditio 60 (2005): 279–337, for a
thorough analysis of the extent of Wyclif ’s theological determinism.
20. DD I, 18, 165.
21. An abridgment of DD I, 16, 121.17–30.
22. De Volucione Dei, chap. 2, 131.18–24.
23. De Volucione Dei, chap. 6, 176.33–35 (see Hebrews 6:13), 180.28–30.
24. Gordon Leff, Heresy in the Later Middle Ages (Manchester, 1967),
516–545.
25. De Civitate Dei XVIII, chap. 51, for a complete overview of recent
literature.
26. De Ecclesia, chap. 1, 1–5; Sermones 50, vol. 3, 434.
27. Sermones 50, vol. 3, 435.8–436.3.
28. Sermones 5, vol. 4, 45.7–12.
29. Sermones 9, vol. 4, 76.3–14.
30. Sermones 49, vol. 2, 354.24.
31. Michael Wilks, “Wyclif and the Wheel of Time,” reprinted in Wyclif:
Political Ideas and Practice, ed. Anne Hudson (Oxbow, 2000), 205–221. I am
grateful to Professor Wilks for providing me with his thoughts on Wyclif ’s
understanding of the church in additional correspondence.
32. See Marjorie Reeves, The Influence of Prophecy in the Later Middle Ages
(Oxford, 1969), 16–27; Reeves, Joachim of Fiore and the Prophetic Future (London,
1976), 1–58; E. Randolph Daniel, “The Double Procession of the Holy Spirit in
Joachim of Fiore’s Understanding of History,” Speculum 53 (1980): 469–483.
33. See Malcolm Lambert, Franciscan Poverty (St. Bonaventure, N.Y., 1998);
Christopher Cullen, Bonaventure (Oxford, 2006), 177–187; G. C. Coulton, From
St. Francis to Dante: Translations from the Chronicle of the Franciscan Salimbene
(Philadelphia, 1907).
34. Kathryn Kerby-Fulton, Books under Suspicion: Censorship and Tolerance
of Revelatory Writing in Late Medieval England (Notre Dame, Ind., 2006), 45–
188. See Tractatus de Universalibus, chap. 11, 108, 119; Opus Evangelicum III,
chap. 58, 216.35–38. For more of Wyclif ’s derisory comments about Joachim,
see Thomson’s list in W. Thomson 1983, 14n4.
35. De Antichristo, chap. 28, 102.18–25, which is contained in Opus
Evangelicum II.
36. De Antichristo, chap. 49, 181.6.
notes to pages 194–202 267
37. De Antichristo, chap. 24, 125.36. For the ties between Wyclif ’s eschatol-
ogy and his antifraternalism, see Penn Szittya, The Antifraternal Tradition in
Medieval Literature (Princeton, N.J., 1986), 152–182.
38. See Margaret Aston, “ ‘Caim’s Castles’: Poverty, Politics, and Disendow-
ment,” in The Church, Politics, and Patronage in the Fifteenth Century, ed. Barrie
Dobson (Gloucester, 1984), 45–81.
39. De Potestate Pape, chap. 1, 10–17; DD II.
40. De Officio Pastoralis, ed. G. Lechler (Leipzig, 1863); see a translation by
Ford Lewis Battles in Advocates of Reform, ed. Matthew Spinka (Philadelphia,
1953), 32–60.
41. De Ecclesia, chap. 19, 448–449; De Antichristo, chap. 48, 175–176. For
a full discussion, see Ian Levy, “Was John Wyclif ’s Theology of the Eucharist
Donatistic?” Scottish Journal of Theology 53 (2000): 137–153; Levy 2003,
305–307.
42. De Potestate Pape, chap. 11; see Gillian Evans, Bernard of Clairvaux (Oxford,
2000), 158–165.
43. DCD I, chap. 38, 275.3; DOR, chap. 7, 166–175; De Blasphemia, chap. 7,
97–110.
44. De Oratione et Ecclesiae Purgatione, in OP I, 343–354; De Fundacione
Sectarum (OP I), 13–80.
45. De Ordinatione Fratrum (OP I), 92.2.
chapter 7
1. DD I, 1, 1.6.
2. Earlier scholars of medieval political theory expended a lot of energy to
establish overarching theories that would predict a philosopher’s political position
given his metaphysics. The most famous instance of this is Martin Grabmann’s
Studien über den Einfluss der aristotelischen Philosophie auf die mittelalterlichen
Theorien über das Verhältniss von Kirche und Staat (Munich, 1934). Much of the
scholarship of the past fifty years has demonstrated that such theorizing is pre-
mature; particularly influential has been A. S. McGrade’s The Political Thought
of William Ockham (Cambridge, 1974), which demonstrated that Ockham’s
political thought cannot be connected to his conceptualist ontology.
3. See Janet Coleman, “Property and Poverty,” in The Cambridge History
of Medieval Political Thought c. 350– c. 1450, ed. J. H. Burns (Cambridge 1988),
607–648.
4. Summa Theologica Ia–IIae, q.56, a.5; q.58, a.2. See also J. H. Burns,
Lordship, Kingship, and Empire (Oxford, 1992).
5. Augustine, On the City of God, bk. 14, chap. 28; Basic Writings of
St. Augustine, ed. Whitney Oates (New York, 1948), vol. 2, 451.
268 notes to pages 202–211
6. Augustine, Epistola 93, chap. 12; Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, 1st ser.,
vol. 1, 400.
7. Enarratio in Psalmam 132.4; Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, 1st ser.,
vol. 8, 617.
8. Giles of Rome, On Ecclesiastical Power: The De Ecclesiastica Potestate of
Aegidius Romanus, ed. and trans. R. W. Dyson (Drew, N.H., 1986), III, 2, 4.
9. D. L. Burr, Olivi and Franciscan Poverty (Philadelphia, 1989), and
M. D. Lambert, Franciscan Poverty (St. Bonaventure, N.Y., 1998).
10. For details of the controversy between John XXII and Ockham, see
William Ockham, A Letter to the Friars Minor and Other Writings, ed. and trans.
A. S. McGrade and John Kilcullen (Cambridge, 1995). See also McGrade 1974.
11. Fitzralph’s arguments concerning the Franciscans await a thorough
scholarly study. The first four books of De Pauperie Salvatoris were included in
the Wyclif Society’s 1890 edition of Wyclif ’s DD, while Richard Brock edited
the latter books of the treatise in “An Edition of Richard Fitzralph’s ‘De Pauperie
Salvatoris’ Books V, VI, and VII,” Ph.D. diss., University of Colorado, 1954.
See Katherine Walsh, A Fourteenth-Century Scholar and Primate: Richard Fitzralph
of Oxford, Avignon, and Armagh (Oxford, 1981); and James Doyne Dawson,
“Richard Fitzralph and the Fourteenth Century Poverty Controversies,” Journal
of Ecclesiastical History 34 (1983).
12. DD I, 3, 16.18–22.
13. DD III, 1, 198.9. Although Wyclif gives a list of sixteen characteris-
tics, he proceeds to discuss only these six. This has prompted some scholars to
suppose that his discussion of the remaining ten has been lost, leaving us with
only a fragment of the original treatise. I suspect that Wyclif recognized these
six acts to be sufficient for his argument and abandoned the remaining ten as
superfluous.
14. DD III, 2, 207–210. See also my discussion of God’s giving and receiving
in Metaphysics and Politics in John Wyclif (Cambridge, 2003), 97–105.
15. DD III, 4, 229.18.
16. This is the sense of DD III, 5–7, which corresponds to Trialogus III, 7,
written in 1383.
17. DD III, 6, 250.25–29.
18. Compare Wyclif ’s discussion of justice and right in DMD, chap. 3,
to Aquinas’s in Summa Theologica Iia–IIae, q.57, aa.1–4, and q.58, aa.1–12.
Aquinas argues that, while right is the object of justice, natural reason is capa-
ble of ascertaining justice without an understanding of God’s uncreated right.
See also my “Wyclif on Rights,” Journal of the History of Ideas 58 (1997): 1–20.
19. DMD, chap. 4, 32.24–27.
20. De Statu Innocencie 8, 34–37. Note that Wyclif uses caritatem for the
standard dilectionem in John 15:13; this is likely because Wyclif is quoting from
notes to pages 212–227 269
memory. Ian Levy has kindly pointed out to me that Wyclif makes this same
substitution in DCD I, 24, 175; DVSS II, 40; and De Antichristo 289.
21. De Statu Innocencie 6, 508.7–9. For Wyclif ’s conception of the nature
of original sin as an ongoing inherited separation from justice, see Trialogus III,
26.
22. DCD III, 11, 178.9–17. For a translation of DCD I, 1–10, see A. S.
McGrade, John Kilcullen, and Matthew Kempshall, eds., The Cambridge Trans-
lations of Medieval Philosophical Texts: vol. 2, Ethics and Politics (Cambridge,
2001), 587–654.
23. DCD III, 4, 51.17–24.
24. DCD I, 9, 62.9.
25. DCD III, 8, 119–120.
26. DCD III, 2, 15.5–23. For Woodford’s criticism, see Eric Doyle, O.F.M.,
“William Woodford, O.F.M., His Life and Works,” Franciscan Studies 43 (1983):
17–187; Doyle, “William Woodford’s De Dominio Civili Clericorum against
John Wyclif,” Archivum Franciscanum Historicum 66 (1973): 49–109.
27. DCD II, 16, 209.13–18.
28. Dialogus 35, 83.25–29. See also Michael Wilks, “Thesaurus Ecclesiae,”
reprinted in Wyclif: Political Ideas and Practice, ed. Anne Hudson (Oxbow,
2000), 147–177.
29. DOR, chap. 1, 13.4–8.
30. DCD I, 26, 188.14–24.
31. DCD I, 22, 231.18–30.
32. DOR, chap. 5, 96.9–27. For a fuller discussion of Wyclif ’s conceptions
of royal responsibility to the realm, see chap. 6 of Lahey 2003. See also William
Farr, Wyclif as Legal Reformer (Leiden, 1974), for a consideration of Wyclif ’s
use of English law in his vision of the reform of the church.
33. DCD I, 30, 215.10–12.
34. DCD I, 18, 130.6.
epilogue
1. See Zénon Kaluza, “Late Medieval Philosophy 1350–1500,” in Routledge
History of Philosophy: vol. 3, Late Medieval Philosophy, ed. John Marenbon (New
York, 1998), 426–451.
2. William James, The Varieties of Religious Experience (Viking Penguin,
1982), 25.
appendix
1. Wyclif cites Augustine, Tractatus in Johannem 25, “Why preparest thou
the teeth and the belly? Believe and thou hast eaten.”
270 notes to pages 228 –235
2. The text beginning with “But many grumble” through to the paragraph
ending “as this same saint says in the letter to Elbidiam” is reproduced without
substantial alteration in De Apostasia, chap. 16, 222.40–229.37.
3. William Durandus (1237–1296), Rationale divinorum officiorum IV,
chap. 1, who probably took the remark from Gregory, in whose “Paschal Homily”
it occurs.
4. Wyclif appears to have Gratian’s Decretum III De Consecratione open before
him as he writes; aside from Ignatius, which he likely took from Grosseteste,
Super Ecclesiastica Hierarchia, chap. 3, the sources are all cited in Gratian. See
Cyprianus Carthaginensis, Epistulae, ep. 63, c.9 (Corpus Christianorum Series
Latina Clavis [CCSLC] 0050); Ambrosius (dubia), De Sacramentis (CCSLC
0154); Augustinus, Sermones 234 (CCSLC 0284); Hieronymus, Epistulae 120
(CCSLC 0620); Augustinus, Epistulae 98 (CCSLC 0262).
5. The completion of the text in Augustine’s letter is “, thus the sacrament
of the faith is the faith.” This is not included in Wyclif ’s citation.
6. Here, the FZ version ends; what follows appears in the Bohemian manu-
scripts. After the first paragraph, this is also the text of Sermon 34 in vol. 3 of
Sermones, with only minor variants.
bibliography
primary sources
Unpublished Works
De Ydeis, unpublished WS edition of: Praha, UK, IV.H.9 (773) ff. 114r–130v;
Praha, UK, VIII.F.1 (1955) ff. 73va–87rb; Stockholm Lat.A.164, ff. 244ra–
258va; Trinity B.16.2, ff. 131ra–137va.
De Tempore, unpublished WS edition.
271
272 bibliography
De Ente Librorum Duorum. Excerpta: Libri I Tractatus III & IV; Libri II Tractatus I
& III; et Fragmentum de Annihilatione. Ed. M. H. Dziewicki. WS 1909.
De Ente Praedicamentali, Quaestiones XIII Logicae et Philosophiae. Ed. Rudolf
Beer. WS 1891.
De Eucharistia Tractatus Maior: Accedit Tractatus de Eucharistia et Poenitentia sive
De Confessione. Ed. J. Loserth. WS 1892.
De Logica. 3 vols. Ed. M. H. Dziewicki. WS 1893–1899.
De Mandatis Divinis. Ed. Johann Loserth and F. D. Matthew. WS 1922.
De Officio Pastoralis. Ed. G. V. Lechler. Leipzig, 1863.
De Officio Regis. Ed. Alfred W. Pollard and Charles Sayle. WS 1887.
De Potestate Pape. Ed. J. Loserth. WS 1907.
De Simonia. Ed. Herzberg-Frankel and M. H. Dziewicki. WS 1898.
De Statu Innocencie, published in De Mandatis Divinis. WS 1922.
De Trinitate. Ed. Allen duPont Breck. Boulder: University of Colorado Press, 1962.
De Veritate Sacrae Scripturae. 3 vols. Ed. Rudolf Buddensieg. WS 1905, 1906, 1907.
Dialogus sive Speculum Ecclesie Militantis. Ed. Alfred W. Pollard. WS 1886.
Johannis Wyclif: Summa Insolubilium. Ed. P. V. Spade and G. A. Wilson. Binghamton,
N.Y., 1986.
“A ‘Lost’ Chapter of Wyclif’s Summa de Ente.” Ed. S. Harrison Thomson. Speculum
4 (1929): 339–346.
Miscellanea Philosophica. 2 vols. Ed. M. H. Dziewicki. WS 1902–1905.
Opera Minora. Ed. J. Loserth. WS 1913.
Opus Evangelicum. 2 vols. Ed. Johann Loserth. WS 1895, 1896.
Polemical Works in Latin. 2 vols. Ed. R. Buddenseig. WS 1883.
Sermones. 4 vols. Ed. J. Loserth. WS 1886–1889.
Tractatus de Benedicta Incarnacione. Ed. Edward Harris. WS 1886.
Tractatus de Universalibus. Ed. Ivan J. Mueller. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1985.
Trialogus. Published as Io. Wiclefi viri undiquaque piis. dialogorum libri quattuor.
Ed. Johann Froben. Basel, 1525.
———. Published as Ioannis Wiclefi viri undiquaque piissimi Dialogorum Libri
Quatuor. Ed. L. P. Wirth. Leipzig, 1753.
———. Published as Johannis Wiclif Trialogus cum Supplemento Trialogi. Ed.
Gotthard Lechler. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1869.
“An Unpublished Fragment of Wyclif ’s Confessio.” Ed. I. H. Stein. Speculum
8 (1933): 503–510.
———, Reportatio super Sententias. 4 vols. Ed. Joseph Wey and Girard Etzkorn.
Toronto: Pontifical Institute, 2002–2005.
William Crathorn, Quaestiones super librum sententiarum. In F. Hoffmann, ed.,
Questionen Zum ersten Sentenzenbuch. Münster: Aschendorff, 1988.
William Ockham, A Letter to the Friars Minor and Other Writings. Ed. and Trans.
A. S. McGrade and John Kilcullen. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1995.
———, Opera Philosophica. 7 vols. Ed. Philotheus Boehner, Gedeon Gàl, et al.
St. Bonaventure, N.Y.: Franciscan Institute, 1974–1988.
———, Predestination, God’s Foreknowledge, and Future Contingents. Ed.
Marilyn McCord Adams and Norman Kretzman. Indianapolis, Ind.:
Hackett, 1983.
———, Tractatus de Principiis Theologiae. Trans. Julian Davies. Published as
A Compendium of Ockham’s Teachings. St. Bonaventure, N.Y.: Franciscan
Institute, 1998.
secondary sources
Adams, Marilyn McCord, William Ockham. 2 vols. Notre Dame, Ind.: University
of Notre Dame Press, 1988.
Aston, Margaret, “ ‘Caim’s Castles’: Poverty, Politics, and Disendowment.” In
Barrie Dobson, ed., The Church, Politics, and Patronage in the Fifteenth
Century (Gloucester, 1984), 45–81. Reprinted in Aston, Faith and Fire,
95–132.
———, Lollards and Reformers: Images and Literacy in Late Medieval Religion.
London: Hambledon, 1984.
Benrath, Gustav, Wyclif ’s Bibelkommentar. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1966.
Beonio-Brocchieri Fumigalli, M. T., and M. Parodi, Storia della Filosophia
Medievale: Da Boezio a Wyclif. Rome: Editori Laterza, 1988.
Biller, Peter, and Anne Hudson, eds., Heresy and Literacy, 1000–1530.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994.
Breck, Allan DuPont, “John Wyclyf on Time.” In W. Yourgrau and Allen d. Breck,
eds., Cosmology, History, and Theology, 211–218. New York: Plenum, 1977.
———, “The Manuscripts of Wyclif ’s De Trinitate.” Medievalia et Humanistica,
o.s. 7 (1952): 56–70.
Breen, Aidan, “Pseudo-Cyprian De Duodecim Abusivis Saeculi and the Bible.”
In Irland und die Christenheit, 1987.
Burns, J. H., ed., The Cambridge History of Medieval Political Thought c. 350–
c. 1450. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988.
Burr, David, Olivi and Franciscan Poverty. Philadelphia: University of
Pennsylvania Press, 1989.
276 bibliography
Dahmus, Joseph, The Prosecution of John Wyclyf. New Haven, Conn.: Yale
University Press, 1952.
Daly, Lowrie J., The Political Theory of John Wyclif. Chicago: Loyola University
Press, 1962.
Dawson, James Doyne, “Richard Fitzralph and the Fourteenth-Century
Poverty Controversies.” Journal of Ecclesiastical History 34 (1983).
Deanesly, Margaret, The Lollard Bible and Other Medieval Biblical Versions.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1920. Rpt., Eugene, Ore.: Wipf
and Stock, 2002.
Denery, Dallas, “From Sacred Mystery to Divine Deception: Robert Holkot,
John Wyclif and the Transformation of Fourteenth-Century Eucharistic
Discourse.” Journal of Religious History 29.2 ( June 2005): 129–144.
Dipple, Geoffrey L., “Uthred and the Friars: Apostolic Poverty and Clerical
Dominion between Fitzralph and Wyclif.” Traditio 49 (1994): 235–358.
Dolnikowski, Edith, “The Encouragement of Lay Preaching as an Ecclesiastical
Critique in Wyclif ’s Latin Sermons.” In Beverly M. Kinzie et al., eds.,
Models of Holiness in Medieval Sermons, 193–209. Louvain-la-Neuve:
Fédération Internationale des Institutes d’Etudes Médiévales, 1996.
———, “Preaching at Oxford: Academic and Pastoral Themes in Wyclif ’s
Latin Sermon Cycle.” In J. Hamesse et al., eds., Medieval Sermons and
Society: Cloister, City, University, 371–386. Louvain-la-Neuve: Fédération
Internationale des Institutes d’Etudes Médiévales, 1998.
Doyle, Eric, O.F.M., “William Woodford, O.F.M., His Life and Works.”
Franciscan Studies 43 (1983): 17–187.
———, “William Woodford’s De Dominio Civili Clericorum against John
Wyclif.” Archivum Franciscanum Historicum 66 (1973): 49–109.
Evans, G. R., John Wyclif: Myth and Reality. Lion Hudson, 2005.
———, Mediaeval Commentaries on the Sentences of Peter Lombard, vol. 1.
Leiden: Brill, 2002.
———, “Wyclif on Literal and Metaphorical.” In Hudson and Wilks 259–266.
Farr, William, Wyclif as Legal Reformer. Leiden: Brill, 1974.
Fletcher, John M., “Inter-Faculty Disputes in Late Medieval Oxford.” In
Hudson and Wilks 331–342.
Fumigalli, Maria Theresa, and Stefano Simonetta, eds., John Wyclif: Logica,
Politica, Teologia. Florence: Sismel, 2003.
Gelber, Hester, Exploring the Boundaries of Reason: Three Questions on the Nature
of God by Robert Holcot, OP. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1983.
———, It Could Have Been Otherwise: Contingency and Necessity in Dominican
Theology at Oxford 1300–1350. Leiden: Brill, 2004.
Ghosh, Kantik, The Wycliffite Heresy: Authority and the Interpretation of Texts.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002.
278 bibliography
Grabmann, Martin, Studien über den Einfluss der aristotelischen Philosophie auf
die mittelalterlichen Theorien über das Verhältniss von Kirche und Staat.
Munich, 1934.
Gwynn, Aubrey, The English Austin Friars in the Time of Wyclif. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1940.
Harvey, Margaret, “Adam Easton and the Condemnation of John Wyclif.”
English Historical Review 113 (April 1998): 321–335.
Henry, Desmond P., Medieval Mereology. Amsterdam: Grüner, 1991.
———, “Wyclif ’s Deviant Mereology.” In Olaf Pluta, ed., Die Philosophie im
14. Und 15. Jahrhundert, 1–17. Amsterdam, 1988.
Herold, Vilém, “Platonic Ideas and ‘Hussite’ Philosophy.” In David R. Holeton,
ed., The Bohemian Reformation and Religious Practice: vol. 1, Papers from the
17th World Congress of the Czechoslovak Society of Arts and Sciences, 13–18.
Prague: Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic, Main Library, 1994.
Hoenen, Martin, “Theology and Metaphysics: The Debate between John Wyclif
and John Kenningham on the Principles of Reading the Scriptures.” In
Fumagalli and Simonetta 23–56.
Hoffmann, Fritz, Die “Conferentiae” des Robert Holcot O.P. und die Akademischen
Auseinandersetzungen an der Univerität Oxford 1330–1332. Münster, 1993.
Hudson, Anne, “Accessus ad auctorem: The Case of John Wyclif.” Viator 30
(1999): 323–344.
———, “Aspects of the ‘Publication’ of Wyclif ’s Latin Sermons.” In Minnis,
Late Medieval Religious Texts, 121–129.
———, “Cross-Referencing in Wyclif ’s Latin Works.” In Peter Biller and
Barrie Dobson, eds., The Medieval Church: University, Heresy, and the Reli-
gious Life (1999), 193–216.
———, “From Oxford to Prague: The Writings of John Wyclif and His
English Followers in Bohemia.” Slavonic and East European Review 75
(October 1997): 642–658.
———, Lollards and Their Books. London: Hambledon, 1985.
———, “The Mouse in the Pyx: Popular Heresy and the Eucharist.” Trivium
26 (1991): 40–53.
———, “Poor Preachers, Poor Men: Views of Poverty in Wyclif and His
Followers.” In Šmahel and Müller-Luckner 41–54.
———, The Premature Reformation: Wycliffite Texts and Lollard History. Oxford:
Clarendon, 1988.
———, “Wyclif and the English Language.” In Kenny 85–103.
———, “Wycliffism in Oxford 1381–1411.” In Kenny 67–84.
———, “Wyclif ’s Latin Sermons: Questions of Form, Date and Audience.”
Archives d’Histoire Doctrinale et Littéraire du Moyen Âge 68 (2001): 223–248.
bibliography 279
Hudson, Anne, and M. Wilks, eds., From Ockham to Wyclif. Oxford: Blackwell,
1987.
Hurley, Michael, “ ‘Scriptura Sola’: Wyclif and His Critics.” Traditio 16 (1960):
275–352.
Jurkowski, Maureen, “Heresy and Factionalism at Merton College in the Early
Fifteenth Century.” Journal of Ecclesiastical History 48 (October 1997):
658–681.
Justice, Steven, Writing and Rebellion: England in 1381. Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1994.
Kaluza, Zénon, “Late Medieval Philosophy, 1350–1500.” In John Marenbon,
ed., Routledge History of Philosophy: vol. 3, Late Medieval Philosophy, 426–
451. New York: Routledge, 1998.
————, “L’ouevre théologique de Richard Brinkley, OFM.” Archives
d’Histoire Doctrinale et Littéraire du Moyen Age 56:169–273.
Kaminsky, Howard, “Wyclifism as Ideology of Revolution.” Church History 32
(1963): 57–74.
Keen, Maurice, England in the Later Middle Ages: A Political History. London:
Methuen, 1973.
———, “The Influence of Wyclif.” In Kenny 127–145.
———, “Wyclif, the Bible, and Transubstantiation.” In Kenny 1–17.
Kennedy, Leonard A., “Late-Fourteenth-Century Philosophical Scepticism at
Oxford.” Vivarium 23.2 (1985): 124–151.
———, “Philosophical Scepticism in England in the Mid-Fourteenth Century.”
Vivarium 21.1 (1983): 43–44.
———, The Philosophy of Robert Holcot: A Fourteenth-Century Skeptic.
Lewiston, Maine: Mellen, 1993.
Kenny, Anthony, “Realism and Determinism in the Early Wyclif.” In Hudson
and Wilks 165–178.
———, Wyclif. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985.
Kenny, Anthony, ed., Wyclif in His Times. Oxford: Clarendon, 1986.
Kerby-Fulton, Kathryn, Books under Suspicion: Censorship and Tolerance of
Revelatory Writing in Late Medieval England. Notre Dame, Ind.: Notre
Dame University Press, 2006.
Knowles, David, “The Censured Opinions of Uthred of Boldon.” In D. Knowles,
ed., The Historian and Character and Other Essays, 129–170. Cambridge:
University of Cambridge Press, 1963.
———, The Religious Orders in England. 3 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1961.
Kretzman, Norman, “Continua, Indivisibles, and Change in Wyclif ’s Logic of
Scripture.” In Kenny 31–65.
280 bibliography
Sergeant, Lewis, John Wyclif: Last of the Schoolmen and First of the English
Reformers. New York, 1893. Rpt., New York: AMS, 1978.
Shogimen, Takashi, “Wyclif ’s Ecclesiology and Political Thought” In Levy
199–240.
Simonetta, Stefano, “The Concept of Two Churches in the Religious Philosophy
of the English Reformer, John Wyclif.” Studi Medievali 40 (1999): 119–137.
———, “John Wyclif between Utopia and Plan.” In Sophie Wlodek, ed.,
Société et Église: Textes et discussions dans les universités de l’Europe centrale
pendant le moyen âge tardif, 65–86. Turnhout, Belgium: Brepols, 1995.
———, “La maturazione del progetto riformatore di Giovanni Wyclif: Dal De
Civili Dominio al De Officio Regis.” Medioevo 22 (1996): 225–258.
———, “Una riforma prematura? Realizzabilita del progetto di Wyclif.”
Pensiero Politico: Rivista di Storia della Idee Politiche e Sociali 29.3 (1996):
343–373.
———, “Una singolare alleanza: Wyclif e Lancaster [A Singular Alliance:
John Wyclif and the Duke of Lancaster: A Study of Ecclesial Politics in
the Fourteenth-Century English Church].” Studi Medievali 36.2 (1995):
797–837.
———, “Two Parallel Trains of Anti-Hierocratic Thought in the Fourteenth
Century: Marsilius of Padua and John Wyclif.” Rivista Di Storia Della
Philosophia 52.1 (1997): 91–110.
Smalley, Beryl, “The Bible and Eternity: John Wyclif ’s Dilemma.” Journal of
the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes 27 (1964): 73–89. Reprinted in Beryl
Smalley, ed., Studies in Medieval Thought and Learning from Abelard to
Wyclif, 399–415. London: Hambledon, 1981.
———, English Friars and Antiquity in the Early Fourteenth Century. Oxford:
Blackwell, 1960.
———, “John Wyclif ’s Postilla Super Totam Bibliam.” Bodleian Library Record
5 (1953): 186–205.
———, “Problems of Exegesis in the Fourteenth Century.” In Paul Wilpert,
ed., Antike und Orient im Mittelalter, 266–274. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1962.
———, The Study of the Bible in the Middle Ages. Notre Dame, Ind.: University
of Notre Dame Press, 1964.
Somerset, Fiona, Clerical Discourse and Lay Audience in Late Medieval England.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
Spade, Paul V., A Cambridge Companion to Ockham. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1999.
———, “Universals and Wyclif ’s Alleged ‘Ultrarealism.’ ” Vivarium 43.1 (2004):
111–123.
Stein, I. H., “Another ‘Lost’ Chapter of Wyclif ’s Summa de Ente.” Speculum 3
(1928): 254–255.
284 bibliography
Wood, Rega, and Gedeon Gàl, “Richard Brinkley and His Summa Logica.”
Franciscan Studies 40 (1980): 59–102.
Workman, Herbert B., John Wyclif: A Study of the English Medieval Church. 2
vols. Oxford: Clarendon, 1926.
internet resources
Aurélien, Robert, “William Crathorn.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Available at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/crathorn/#Oth.
Gelber, Hester, “Robert Holcot.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available
at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/holkot.
index
287
288 index
Wyclif, John (continued) De Veritate Sacrae Scripturae, 21, 132, 136 –143
errors about universals, 11, 82 De Volucione Dei, 173, 182–186
Eucharist, theory of, 22, 122–131 De Ydeis, 13, 83, 172
“Everything that occurs, occurs of necessity,” 170 Dialogus, 215
excommunication, belief in the impossibility Logice Continuacio, 9, 50, 53, 58, 179
of, 197 Opus Evangelicum, 21, 28, 134, 136, 148,
formal distinction, use of, 61 153–158
hermeneutics, scriptural, theory of, 24 Postilla super totam Bibliam, 21, 125, 136, 148
illumination, theory of, 63– 64, 141 Purgans Errores circa Universalia in Communi, 61
knowledge, kinds of, 58 Purgans Errores circa Veritates in Communi, 88
Latin works of Responsio, 19
Confessio, 23, 103, 123, 131 Sermones, 160 –165, 196
De Actibus Anime, 10, 50, 55, 74, 179 Summa de Ente divisions of, 11–12, 82– 83
De Amore sive ad Quinque quaestiones, 142, 153 Summa Theologie divisions of, 16, 131
De Antichristo (Opus Evangelicum III–IV ), 28, Trialogus, 16, 28, 30, 52, 62, 63, 117, 123, 126,
134, 148, 154 134, 154
De Apostasia, 131–132 Lollardy, relation to, 165
De Blasphemia, 131, 133, 156 Lord’s Prayer, commentary on, 152
De Civili Dominio, 16, 19, 194, 199 mental acts, on, 10, 50, 54
De Composiciione Hominis, 13, 49, 145 mereology of, 100
De Dominio Divino, 16, 63, 182, 199, 206 –210 modal theory of, 86, 176 –186
De Ecclesia, 7, 173, 186 –189 modern conceptions of, 29 –30
De Ente in Communi, 94 Ockham, opinion of, 197
De Eucharistia, 103, 122, 128, 131 Oxford career of, 4–24
De Eucharistia Conclusiones Duodecim, 123 papal authority, critiques of, 133, 190, 194–197
De Fide Sacramenti, 134 pluralism of, 6
De Incarnacione, De Benedicta Incarnacione, post-mortem career of, 29
De Verbi Incarnacione, 8, 13, 49, 139, 145 preaching, views on, 158 –165
De Insolubilia, 9, 57 predication, kinds of, 81– 82
De Intellectione Dei, 173, 183, 184 priesthood, theology of, 195–196
De Logica, 8, 50 propositional realism of, 79 – 82, 97
De Logica Tratatus Tercius, 8, 9, 50, 121, 179 realism
De Mandatis Divinis, 16, 140, 150, 157, 199, 211 kinds of universals, 95– 96
De Materia et Forma, 13 ultrarealism or realism?, 30, 93– 94
De Officio Pastoralis, 21 universal-particular relation, 12, 62, 82
De Officio Regis, 21, 194 relations, theory of, 97– 98
De Potentia Productiva Dei ad Extra, 121 Sermon on the Mount, commentary on, 151–158
De Potestate Pape, 21, 194, 197 signification, natural vs. artificial, 80
De Sciencia Dei, 173, 183 skepticism, arguments against, 92
De Simonia, 131 theologians, instruction of, 155
De Statu Innocencie, 16, 150, 199, 211 theology as a science, 60 – 64
De Tempore, 118, 129 Trinity, description of, 100 –101
De Trinitate, 13, 49, 60, 100 vision, theory of as heuristic for epistemology, 51
De Universalibus, 11, 74, 75, 81, 83, 94, Retirement to Lutterworth, 21, 27
100, 179 Wyclif Bible, 222