A Look at Informal Logic PDF
A Look at Informal Logic PDF
Iryna Khomenko1
The challenges of the global time require new solutions and up-to-date ways of thinking and
communication. These challenges call for the ability to use critical thinking to face the ever-changing
world and the ability to maintain a dialog based on the effective skills of communication. Studies in the
fields of logic and argumentation theory are of particular importance in this regard. Nowadays they can
be presented as a mix of theoretical and practical approaches.
In this paper, I will present my reflections on informal logic, which was formed in the late 1970s.
Unfortunately, in spite of numerous papers, books, and text-books published over the last forty years,
consensus on many issues in this field has not been achieved so far. Therefore, it is difficult to treat
informal logic as one of the well-defined approaches to argumentation. The goal of this paper is to take
a look at the place of informal logic in state-of-the art study of argumentation by clarifying its subject
matter and figuring out the realm to which informal logic belongs.
Keywords: logic, informal logic, formal logic, theory of argumentation, epistemology, cognitive
science, real argument
Introduction
The challenges of the globalized world require new solutions and fresh ways of thinking
and communication. These challenges call for the ability to study new issues and quick change
your mind, the ability to use critical thinking to face the ever-changing world and to maintain
a dialog based on the effective communication skills. Studies in the fields of logic and theory
of argumentation are of particular importance in this regard.
It should be stated that until the middle of the 20th century, the dominant approach to the
study of argumentation was logical, or rather formal-logical one. “Logic was for millennia
seen as the skeleton of argument” [Hample, 2006: 2].
© Khomenko, Iryna, 2018
Logic is primarily concerned with reasoning and we can find in numerous text books on
logic its definition as the science of reasoning. In order to summarize the traditional view of
logic let’s look at such quote: “For over two millennia, since the days of Aristotle and Euclid,
the notion of formal logic has figured centrally in conceptions of human reasoning, rationality,
and adaptiveness. To be adaptive, the story goes, we must be rational about ends and means,
truth and evidence. To be rational, we must reason about what means suit what ends, what
evidence supports what conclusions. And to so reason, we must respect the canons of logic”
[Perkins, 2002: 187].
However, as it turned out, the canons of standard logic had not been sufficient for the analysis
of various situations from real life. That is why, in the late 20th century informal treatments
appeared in argumentation area. The key reason of their development was the criticism of
the possibilities of formal logic. First of all among neoclassical theoretical approaches to
argumentation it is necessary to point out Toulmin’s concept of the ‘working logic’ [Toulmin,
1958] and Perelman’s treatment of the ‘new rhetoric’ [Perelman & Olbrechts-Tyteca, 1958].
Stephen Toulmin believed that the key problem of formal deductive logic is that it reduces
arguments, used in different situation, to universal standards even though the procedure must
depend on the realm of knowledge in which they are used. In his opinion, it is necessary
to create a new logic similar to epistemology, which has broader subject matter including
argumentative process in various spheres of human life and primarily in law. In this respect,
he identified formal logic as the ‘ideal logic’ while informal one is the logic which operates or
the ‘working logic.’
Chaim Perelman believed that rapid development of mathematical logic became the reason
why logicians developed mainly the theories of mathematical proof and did not pay attention
to the problem of proof in liberal arts. Natural sciences deal with the obvious statements or
statements which may be deduced from their combinations. Unlike them, arts deal with the
values. Thus, we cannot use the same proof scheme in natural science and liberal arts. In order
to highlight this distinction, Perelman used ‘proof’ for natural science and ‘argument’ — for
humanities. He held the position that formal logic is the ‘logic of proof’ and informal logic is
the ‘logic of argument.’
As a result, Stephen Toulmin and Chaim Perelman concluded that most areas of intellectual
and practical activities cannot be limited to formal-logical thinking and require a new logic as
a theory of argumentation. Following this idea, Stephen Toulmin came up with ‘working logic’
while Chaim Perelman developed ‘new rhetoric.’
The approaches, discussed above, have inspired new interesting developments. It should
be stated that nowadays informal studies of argumentation are topic within the scientific
community. During the late 20th century and almost the past two decades of the 21th century
their results are being actively discussed at the conferences, symposiums, and workshops.1
Today a number of different streams can be identified as informal: American tradition of
communication studies and rhetoric, linguistic approaches, pragma-dialectics, informal logic,
pragmatic approach etc2.
1
Among them are well known International Symposium on Informal Logic (Canada); International
Conference on Argumentation (Netherlands), European Conference of Argumentation (ECA) and others.
2
It should be noted that more recently formal approaches in argumentation theory have been further
developed too. As examples are formal dialectics and promising connections between approaches in
fields of argumentation theory and artificial intelligence.
For my present purposes it is particularly important to take a look at informal logic. It was
formed by group of Canadian scholars in the late 1970s, who then called themselves informal
logicians. J. Anthony Blair and Ralph H. Johnson from the University of Windsor, Ontario,
Canada were first and foremost among them. They “contributed the institutional conditions for
the establishment of informal logic as a field of research.” [Eemeren et al., 2015: 373].
Unfortunately, in spite of numerous papers, books, and text-books on informal logic,
published over the last forty years, consensus on many issues has not been achieved so far.
In this regard it is difficult to consider informal logic as one of the well-defined vision of
argumentation. Not coincidentally, in Handbook of Argumentation Theory, published in 2015,
it was pointed out that the term informal logic cannot refer to one well-delineated approach.
“It rather refers to a collection of attempts to develop and theoretically justify a method for
the analysis and evaluation of natural language arguments in different context of use that is an
alternative to formal logic.” [Eemeren et al., 2015, 2015: 374].
In this paper I would like to introduce my vision of informal logic by clarifying its subject
matter and figuring out the realm to which informal logic belongs to.
In order to clarify this problem I am going to compare formal and informal logic. The
results we can see in the Table 1.
All these points are coming together in the following way. Informal logic can be considered
as an applied epistemology in a sense that it is an application of epistemological findings to
the evaluation of arguments. It means that epistemological nature of informal logic is directly
connected to the problem of argument evaluation.
In this respect, my next step would be to reflect on a question about determining what
constitutes a good argument in logic. Unfortunately, no consensus has been reached so far in
terms of defining the notion of such argument. Generally, it can be distinguished as two key
approaches to the evaluation of the argument: fallacies approach and criteria approach.
Outsiders often link informal logic with the study of informal fallacies, which are not
covered by formal logic. However, a lot of informal logicians feel skeptical towards such
fallacies approach to the evaluation of arguments. The traditional fallacies (primarily including
ad hominem) describe theses argument as perfectly reasonable. In this respect, many informal
logicians try to clarify what makes an argumentative move legitimate as well as the conditions
under which it is fallacious.
Now let’s look at criteria approaches. We covered various way to separate a good argument
from a bad one. For instance, speaking of traditional criteria we can talk about ‘soundness’ and
‘validity.’
An argument is good if and only if it is formally valid and its premises are true. It should be
noted that ‘validity’ is a purely logical criterion because we can identify validity of argument
by the logical methods. Meanwhile, it is not possible to establish whether its premises and
conclusion are true or not.
The fact that by following these criteria all good arguments are being reduced to deductive
proves how strong they are. There are obvious counter-examples to the hypothesis that an
argument is good if and only if it is sound in this technical sense. We can see that some arguments
which we take to be good are not sound by reflecting on examples of perfectly acceptable
arguments whose premises are not all true, or whose inferential step is not deductively valid. In
this regard the point of view highlighting inadequacy of formal logic to be the tool for evaluating
natural-language arguments is wide spread and recognized within informal logic.
In order to avoid such restriction researchers offered another approach to argument
evaluation. For example, Charles Leonard Hamblin distinguishes alethic, epistemic, and
dialectical criteria for good argument [Hamblin, 1970: 224-252]. Unfortunately, it should be
noted that although given points were identified clear definition of good argument has not been
provided.
Informal logicians have developed other criteria for assessing arguments. For instance, a
triad of acceptability, relevance, and sufficiency is often used as a popular set of criteria in this
regard. In order to be considered good premises of an argument must be acceptable, relevant
to the conclusion and sufficient to support it. Let’s consider these criteria in more details. The
main question in this regard is whether informal criteria should be considered as logical or
epistemological.
From my point of view, these criteria bring argument appraisal much closer to
epistemological approach than to formal logical one. Firstly all of these criteria are explicated
via epistemological concepts such as belief, knowledge, common knowledge, justification,
and others. For example, one of the standard tests for premises acceptability is whether a
premise satisfies the common knowledge condition.
Secondly, informal researchers hold that these criteria are best conceived in a relation to
a particular person in at a particular time and in a particular epistemological situation. For
For the purposes of this paper I propose to examine the experimental results called “The
Suppression Task”. The author of this experiment is Ruth M. Byrne and her results were
published in the paper “Suppressing Valid Inferences with Conditionals” [Burne, 1989].
Everybody who has at least some sort of knowledge about formal logic knows one of the
most recognizable inference rules — modus ponens. It is often defined as: if A implies B and
A holds, we can conclude that B holds.
This poses a question whether this logical inference rule can be mental inference rule at the
same time for personal usage in reasoning with conditional sentence?
Ruth M. Byrne begins with reasoning that has the form of modus ponens (Example 1).
Premise 1: If she has an essay to write then she will study late in the library.
Premise 2: She has an essay to write.
Conclusion: She will study late in the library.
As a result, 96% of subjects conclude that she will study late in the library.
Then Ruth M. Byrne replicated these results by presenting a second condition containing
an alternative for the same consequent (Example 2).
Premise 1: If she has an essay to write then she will study late in the library.
Premise 2: She has an essay to write.
Premise 3: If she has a textbook to read she will study late in the library.
Conclusion: She will study late in the library.
She gets the same result. 96% of subjects chose the conclusion: She will study late in the
library.
Further Ruth M. Byrne extends the experiment by introducing a second condition with an
additional requirement that must also hold (Example 3).
Premise 1: If she has an essay to write then she will study late in the library.
Premise 2: She has an essay to write.
Premise 3: If the library stays open she will study late in the library.
Conclusion: She will study late in the library.
Now only 38% of subjects made modus ponens inferences, compared to 96% when a
simple conditional or two conditionals with alternative conditions were presented.
Ruth M. Byrne concludes that either there are no mental rules for the valid inferences, or
that “…suppression by itself tells us nothing about the existence or non-existence of rules of
inference in the mind.” [Byrne, 1989: 76]
She admits that the results can still be explained in terms of mental rules if one assumes that
the joint representation of both sentences makes the application of inference rules impossible.
Her proposal is that: “Formal theories, therefore, need to be supplemented with a detailed
account of the process of interpretation, because premises of the same apparent logical form
are represented in different ways depending on their meaning.” [Byrne, 1989: 77]
Later on, she rejects mental rules in favor of the mental model theory.
Based the aforesaid, I believe that the study of mental (informal) schemes of reasoning that
isn’t based on the deductive logical forms and rules, but mental presentation or mental picture
of world may be a relevant task for informal logicians.
For example, according to Blair and Johnson, real argument is an “actual natural language
arguments used in public discourse, clothed in their native ambiguity, vagueness and
incompleteness. […] arguments that have actually been used to try to persuade people, the sorts
of arguments the student will encounter outside the classroom.” [Johnson & Blair 1994: 6].
Leo Groarke thinks that real arguments are “the arguments found in discussion, debate and
disagreement as they manifest themselves in daily life.” [Groarke, 2017].
With regard to clarifying this term I consider it as a complex kind of reasoning, which is
used in argumentation as a form of dialogical interaction, where arguers aim is to resolve a
conflict of opinions expressed by verbal means.
In my view, we can highlight the key features of such arguments and it can be described in
the following way.
(1) Unlike formal logic, which uses artificial language, real argument is expressed by
natural language.
(2) Real argument is a dialogical argument. Arguing requires at least two arguers. They
express to divergent points of view on certain question and at the same time should keep in
mind objections, which they may have.
(3) Real argument relates to everyday communication. In this regard the artificial
reasoning from logic textbooks are not relevant to real arguments.
(4) Real argument mostly is a defeasible argument. We can see that some arguments,
which we consider to be good, are not sound by reflecting on examples of perfectly acceptable
arguments whose premises are not all true, or whose inferential step is not deductively valid.
(5) One of the key features of real argument is its incompleteness. Arguers often do
not use all premises and conclusions in such arguments. Some of them do it on purpose to
confusing the opponents, but sometimes this case occurs when arguers do not have sufficient
skills to express their thoughts clearly.
(6) Real argument depends on the context of utterance.
In addition, I would like to emphasize that informal logic cannot be viewed only as a
branch of logic. From my point of view, it would be more reasonable to define it as a discipline
that sits on the borderline between the interests of logic, epistemology, and cognitive science.
Three perspectives in study of real argument within informal logic can be suggested:
logical, epistemic, and cognitive. The first relates to the normative standards, criteria, and
procedures of real arguments interpretation. The issues concerning with construction and
reconstruction, schemes and forms, unexpressed premises of real argument and others could
be considered there.
The epistemic perspective focuses on studying the assessment of a real argument. The
cognitive perspective concentrates on a descriptive study of argument, because empirical
investigations are important as theoretical ones are in this area. Of the latter, survey data
collection is especially noteworthy.
Thus, in my opinion, informal logic should be considered as a normative and descriptive
discipline sitting on the borderline between the interests of logic, epistemology, and cognitive
science, with a task to study the real arguments through the development of certain standards,
criteria, and procedures for its interpretation and evaluation.
Conclusions
In this paper I try to present my reflections on informal logic as one of the informal streams
in state-of-the art study of argumentation. In conclusion, I would like to summarize the main
points of my paper.
The appearance of informal investigations in argumentation field was preceded by the
publication of two books: The Uses of argument [Toulmin, 1958] and Traité de L’argumentation:
La Nouvelle Rhétorique [Perelman & Olbrechts-Tyteca, 1958]. In my view Toulmin’s concept
of the “working logic” and Perelman’s concept of the “new rhetoric” can be identified as the
preconditions of informal research in modern theory of argumentation.
By considering various approaches I set the goal to identify the place of informal logic
in state-of-the art study of argumentation. In this way I want to create an adequate basis for
providing a precise definition of informal logic. In my view, a suitable definition clarifying a
subject matter of informal logic and identifying the realm to which informal logic belongs.
To answer the first question, real argument is the subject matter of informal logic. It is as a
complex kind of reasoning, which is used in argumentation as a form of dialogical interaction,
where arguers aim is to resolve a conflict of opinions expressed by verbal means.
Next, it is important to highlight, the key features of such argument: (i) it is expressed in
natural language; (ii) it is a dialogical argument; (iii) it relates to everyday communication; (iv)
it mostly is a defeasible argument; (v) incompleteness remains one of the key features of a real
argument; (vi) it depends on the context of utterance.
Furthermore, I emphasize that a real argument can be studied within informal logic from
various perspectives: logical, epistemic and cognitive. The first relates to the normative
standards, criteria, and procedures of interpreting real arguments. The second focuses on
the problem of real argument assessment. The third concentrates on a descriptive study of
argument. On my mind, informal logic involves appeals not only to the theoretical studies.
Empirical research is important in this area as well.
Recapitulating, I can now propose a definition of informal logic, which is based on the one
proposed by Ralf H. Johnson and J. Antony Blair [Johnson & Blair, 2000]3. It clarifies and
broadens our vision of informal logic and its place in contemporary study of argumentation.
Here it is: informal logic can be viewed as a normative and descriptive discipline, sitting on
the borderline between the interests of logic, epistemology, and cognitive science, with a task
to study the real arguments through development of certain standards, criteria, and procedures
for its interpretation and evaluation.
References
Battersby, Mark E. Applied Epistemology and Argumentation Epidemiology. Informal Logic,
26(1), 2006: 41-62.
Battersby, Mark E. Critical Thinking as Applied Epistemology: Relocating Critical Thinking
in the Philosophical Landscape. Informal Logic, 11(2), 1989: 91-100.
Byrne, Ruth M..Suppressing valid inferences with conditionals. Cognition, 31,1989: 61-83.
Declerck, Renaat., & Reed, Susan. Conditionals: a comprehensive empirical analysis. Mouton
de Gruyter, 2001.
3
“Informal logic designates that branch of logic whose task is to develop non-formal2 standards,
criteria, procedures for analysis, interpretation, evaluation, critique and construction of argumentation in
everyday language.” [Johnson & Blair, 2000: 102]
Eemeren, Frans Hendrik van. The Study of Argumentation. The SAGE Handbook of Rhetorical
Studies. SAGE, 2009: 109-24.
Eemeren,Frans. Hendrik van, Garssen, Bart, Krabbe, Erik C. W., Snoeck Henkemans,
Francisca A., Verheij, Bart,
Wagemans, Jean H. M. eds. Handbook of argumentation theory. Dordrecht: Springer
Reference, 2015.
Evans, Jonathan. Matching bias in conditional reasoning: Do we understand it after 25 years?
Thinking and Reasoning, 4, 1998: 45–82.
Fiddick, Laurence., Cosmides, Leda, and Tooby, John. No interpretation without representation:
the role of domain-specific representations and inferences in the Wason selection task.
Cognition, 77, 2000: 1–79.
Ford, Mark. Two modes of mental representation and problem solution in syllogistic reasoning,
Cognition, 54, 1995: 1–71.
Freeman, James B. The Place of Informal Logic in Logic. New Essays in Informal Logic.
Winsdor, Ontario, Canada: Informal Logic, 1994: 36-47.
Freeman, James B. The Place of Informal Logic in Philosophy. Informal Logic 20 (2),
2000:117-28.
Govier, Trudy. Problems in argument analysis and evaluation. Dordrecht-Holland: Foris
Publications, 1987.
Groarke, Leo. Informal logic. In Stanford Encyclopedia on Philosophy, 2017. http://plato.
stanford.edu/ entries/logic-informal/ [accessed 2nd January 2017].
Hamblin, Charles Leonard. Fallacies. New York: Methuen, 1970.
Hample, David. Arguing: Exchanging reasons face to face, Routledge, 2006.
Hitchcock, David. Informal Logic and Concept of Argument. Handbook of the Philosophy of
Science. Vol. 5. Philosophy of Logic. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 2007.
Hintikka, Jaakko. True and False Logics of Scientific Discovery. Selected Papers. Vol. 5.
Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer, 1999: 115-196.
Johnson, Ralf H. Manifest Rationality. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum and Associates, 2000.
Johnson, Ralf H., and Blair, J. Antony Informal logic. An Overview. Informal Logic, 20 (2),
2000: 93-107.
Johnson, Ralf H., and Blair, J. Antony. Informal logic: past and present. New essays in informal
logic. Winsdor, Ontario, Canada: Informal Logic, 1994: 1-19.
Perelman, Chaim and Lucy Olbrechts-Tyteca. Traité De L’argumentation: La Nouvelle
Rhétorique. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France La Nouvelle Rhetorique, 1958.
Pinto, Robert C. (1994) Logic, Epistemology and Argumeny Appraisal. New Essays in Informal
Logic. Winsdor, Ontario, Canada:Informal Logic, 1994:116-124.
Perkins, David N. Standard Logic as a Model of Reasoning: The Empirical Critique. Handbook
of the Logic of Argument and Inference. The Turn Towards the Practical. Amsterdam:
Elsevier, 2002: 187-224.
Siegel, Harvey. Educating Reason: Rationality, Critical Thinking and Education. New York:
Routledge, 1988.
Siegal, Harvey. (1994b). Justification by Balance and the Epistemology of Informal Logic. New
Essays in Informal Logic. Winsdor, Ontario, Canada:Informal Logic, 1994:125-139.
Toulmin, Stephen E. The Uses of Argument. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1958.
Weinstein, Mark. Informal Logic and Applied Epistemology. New Essays in Informal Logic.
Winsdor, Ontario, Canada: Informal Logic, 1994:140-161.