1 1 PDF
1 1 PDF
0521861241c01 CB996/Velleman October 19, 2005 23:46 0 521 86124 1 Char Count= 0
1
Sentential Logic
P or Q.
not Q.
Therefore, P.
It is this form, and not the subject matter, that makes these arguments valid.
You can see that argument 1 has this form by thinking of the letter P as standing
for the statement “It will rain tomorrow,” and Q as standing for “It will snow
tomorrow.” For argument 3, P would be “I will go to work tomorrow,” and Q
would be “I will go to work today.”
Replacing certain statements in each argument with letters, as we have in
stating the form of arguments 1 and 3, has two advantages. First, it keeps us
from being distracted by aspects of the arguments that don’t affect their validity.
You don’t need to know anything about weather forecasting or work habits to
recognize that arguments 1 and 3 are valid. That’s because both arguments have
the form shown earlier, and you can tell that this argument form is valid without
P1: PIG/
0521861241c01 CB996/Velleman October 19, 2005 23:46 0 521 86124 1 Char Count= 0
10 Sentential Logic
even knowing what P and Q stand for. If you don’t believe this, consider the
following argument:
Either the framger widget is misfiring, or the wrompal mechanism is out of
alignment.
I’ve checked the alignment of the wrompal mechanism, and it’s fine.
Therefore, the framger widget is misfiring.
If a mechanic gave this explanation after examining your car, you might still
be mystified about why the car won’t start, but you’d have no trouble following
his logic!
Perhaps more important, our analysis of the forms of arguments 1 and 3
makes clear what is important in determining their validity: the words or and
not. In most deductive reasoning, and in particular in mathematical reasoning,
the meanings of just a few words give us the key to understanding what makes
a piece of reasoning valid or invalid. (Which are the important words in ar-
gument 2 in Example 1.1.1?) The first few chapters of this book are devoted
to studying those words and how they are used in mathematical writing and
reasoning.
In this chapter, we’ll concentrate on words used to combine statements to
form more complex statements. We’ll continue to use letters to stand for state-
ments, but only for unambiguous statements that are either true or false. Ques-
tions, exclamations, and vague statements will not be allowed. It will also be
useful to use symbols, sometimes called connective symbols, to stand for some
of the words used to combine statements. Here are our first three connective
symbols and the words they stand for:
Symbol Meaning
∨ or
∧ and
¬ not
Thus, if P and Q stand for two statements, then we’ll write P ∨ Q to stand
for the statement “P or Q,” P ∧ Q for “P and Q,” and ¬P for “not P” or
“P is false.” The statement P ∨ Q is sometimes called the disjunction of P
and Q, P ∧ Q is called the conjunction of P and Q, and ¬P is called the
negation of P.
1. (¬S ∧ L) ∨ S, where S stands for “John is stupid” and L stands for “John is
lazy.”
2. ¬S ∧ (L ∨ S), where S and L have the same meanings as before.
3. ¬(S ∧ L) ∨ S, with S and L still as before.
P1: PIG/
0521861241c01 CB996/Velleman October 19, 2005 23:46 0 521 86124 1 Char Count= 0
12 Sentential Logic
Solutions
1. Either John isn’t stupid and he is lazy, or he’s stupid.
2. John isn’t stupid, and either he’s lazy or he’s stupid. Notice how the place-
ment of the word either in English changes according to where the paren-
theses are.
3. Either John isn’t both stupid and lazy, or John is stupid. The word
both in English also helps distinguish the different possible positions of
parentheses.
Exercises
∗
1. Analyze the logical forms of the following statements:
(a) We’ll have either a reading assignment or homework problems, but we
won’t have both homework problems and a test.
(b) You
√ won’t go skiing, or you will and there won’t be any snow.
(c) 7 ≤ 2.
2. Analyze the logical forms of the following statements:
(a) Either John and Bill are both telling the truth, or neither of them is.
(b) I’ll have either fish or chicken, but I won’t have both fish and mashed
potatoes.
(c) 3 is a common divisor of 6, 9, and 15.
3. Analyze the logical forms of the following statements:
(a) Alice and Bob are not both in the room.
(b) Alice and Bob are both not in the room.
(c) Either Alice or Bob is not in the room.
(d) Neither Alice nor Bob is in the room.
4. Which of the following expressions are well-formed formulas?
(a) ¬(¬P ∨ ¬¬R).
(b) ¬(P, Q, ∧R).
(c) P ∧ ¬P.
(d) (P ∧ Q)(P ∨ R).
P1: PIG/
0521861241c01 CB996/Velleman October 19, 2005 23:46 0 521 86124 1 Char Count= 0
14 Sentential Logic
∗
5. Let P stand for the statement “I will buy the pants” and S for the statement
“I will buy the shirt.” What English sentences are represented by the fol-
lowing expressions?
(a) ¬(P ∧ ¬S).
(b) ¬P ∧ ¬S.
(c) ¬P ∨ ¬S.
6. Let S stand for the statement “Steve is happy” and G for “George is happy.”
What English sentences are represented by the following expressions?
(a) (S ∨ G) ∧ (¬S ∨ ¬G).
(b) [S ∨ (G ∧ ¬S)] ∨ ¬G.
(c) S ∨ [G ∧ (¬S ∨ ¬G)].
7. Identify the premises and conclusions of the following deductive argu-
ments and analyze their logical forms. Do you think the reasoning is valid?
(Although you will have only your intuition to guide you in answering
this last question, in the next section we will develop some techniques for
determining the validity of arguments.)
(a) Jane and Pete won’t both win the math prize. Pete will win either
the math prize or the chemistry prize. Jane will win the math prize.
Therefore, Pete will win the chemistry prize.
(b) The main course will be either beef or fish. The vegetable will be either
peas or corn. We will not have both fish as a main course and corn as a
vegetable. Therefore, we will not have both beef as a main course and
peas as a vegetable.
(c) Either John or Bill is telling the truth. Either Sam or Bill is lying.
Therefore, either John is telling the truth or Sam is lying.
(d) Either sales will go up and the boss will be happy, or expenses will go
up and the boss won’t be happy. Therefore, sales and expenses will not
both go up.
We saw in Section 1.1 that an argument is valid if the premises cannot all be
true without the conclusion being true as well. Thus, to understand how words
such as and, or, and not affect the validity of arguments, we must see how they
contribute to the truth or falsity of statements containing them.
When we evaluate the truth or falsity of a statement, we assign to it one of
the labels true or false, and this label is called its truth value. It is clear how the
word and contributes to the truth value of a statement containing it. A statement
of the form P ∧ Q can only be true if both P and Q are true; if either P or Q
is false, then P ∧ Q will be false too. Because we have assumed that P and