Lecture 3 Prospect Theory PDF
Lecture 3 Prospect Theory PDF
1/41
Outline
2/41
EUT and Ecient Markets
E(re ) is the risk premium for this company, and reects the
(systematic) risk of the company and investors preference
toward risk.
3/41
Decisions Under Risk
4/41
Expected Utility Theory
5/41
Expected Utility Theory
6/41
EUT Application
7/41
Shape of utility function
9/41
Lets look at some decision problems
10/41
Expected Utility Theory: Violations
Choose between A1 and A2 :
A1 : (£1M, 1)
A2 : (£5M, 0.1; £1M, 0.89; 0, 0.01)
11/41
Expected Utility Theory: Violations
Choose between A1 and A2 : Now choose between A3 and A4 :
A1 : (£1M, 1) A3 : (£5M, 0.1; £0, 0.9)
A2 : (£5M, 0.1; £1M, 0.89; 0, 0.01) A4 : (£1M, 0.11; £0M, 0.89)
11/41
Expected Utility Theory: Violations
Choose between A1 and A2 : Now choose between A3 and A4 :
A1 : (£1M, 1) A3 : (£5M, 0.1; £0, 0.9)
A2 : (£5M, 0.1; £1M, 0.89; 0, 0.01) A4 : (£1M, 0.11; £0M, 0.89)
Most people in experimental studies choose A1 and then A3 , which
violates the independence axiom → the Allaix Paradox.
A1 A2 A4 A3
¿ p ¿ p ¿ p ¿ p
12/41
Expected Utility Theory: Violations
12/41
Expected Utility Theory: Violations
13/41
Expected Utility Theory: Violations
13/41
Expected Utility Theory: Violations
Imagine you are 20K richer and you have two options:
A1: get 5K for sure
A2: get 50% chance to win 10K and 50% chance to win 0.
14/41
Expected Utility Theory: Violations
Imagine you are 20K richer and you have two options:
A1: get 5K for sure
A2: get 50% chance to win 10K and 50% chance to win 0.
Imagine you are richer by 30K and you have two options:
B1: Lose 5K for sure
B2: 50% chance of losing 10K and 50% of losing 0.
14/41
Expected Utility Theory: Violations
Imagine you are 20K richer and you have two options:
A1: get 5K for sure
A2: get 50% chance to win 10K and 50% chance to win 0.
Imagine you are richer by 30K and you have two options:
B1: Lose 5K for sure
B2: 50% chance of losing 10K and 50% of losing 0.
People commonly feel that the two problems are dierent, one with
losses and the other gains,choosing A1 and then B2.
This relativity eect violates an important rule of rational decision
making- that the two problems are identical when formulated in
terms of nal states of wealth.
14/41
Expected Utility Theory: Violations
18/41
PT:The Probability Weighting Function
19/41
PT
20/41
EUT vs. PT
21/41
PT and stock market anomalies
22/41
The Equity Premium Puzzle
23/41
The Equity Premium Puzzle
24/41
Benartzi and Thaler 1995
Benartzi and Thaler (1995) (BT) resolve this puzzle using two
(very plausible) behavioral phenomena
1 Investors are loss averse, so very concerned about the
probability of loss (PT preferences).
2 Investors are myopic when calculating probability of losses, so
consider only recent history.
25/41
Pr(losses) with 1-year evaluation periods
26/41
Pr(losses) with 20-year evaluation periods
27/41
Benartzi and Thaler 1995
28/41
Implied equity premium with myopic PT investors
29/41
Implied equity premium with myopic PT investors
30/41
PT and risk taking
31/41
PT and the Disposition Eect
32/41
Disposition Eect, Odean 1998
Table I
PGR and PLR for the Entire Data Set
This table compares the aggregate Proportion of Gains Realized ~PGR! to the aggregate Pro-
portion of Losses Realized ~PLR!, where PGR is the number of realized gains divided by the
number of realized gains plus the number of paper ~unrealized! gains, and PLR is the number
of realized losses divided by the number of realized losses plus the number of paper ~unrealized!
losses. Realized gains, paper gains, losses, and paper losses are aggregated over time ~1987–
1993! and across all accounts in the data set. PGR and PLR are reported for the entire year, for
December only, and for January through November. For the entire year there are 13,883 real-
ized gains, 79,658 paper gains, 11,930 realized losses, and 110,348 paper losses. For December
there are 866 realized gains, 7,131 paper gains, 1,555 realized losses, and 10,604 paper losses.
The t-statistics test the null hypotheses that the differences in proportions are equal to zero
assuming that all realized gains, paper gains, realized losses, and paper losses result from
independent decisions.
33/41
PT and Sophisticated Investors
34/41
PT and Sophisticated Investors
Traders
Thiswith
figure morning losses averages
plots the time-series are more of 236likely to take above
daily cross-sectional average risk in
semi-parametric
the afternoon
regressions of afternoon total dollar risk on morning profit percentile. The regressions are
35/41
Loss aversion and the cross section of stocks
36/41
Loss aversion and the cross section of stocks
1.2
1.0
0.8
0.6
0.4
0.2
0.0
Low-1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 High-10
-0.2
-0.4
EW-TK
Low
0.6 PT-value stocks out-perform high PT-value stocks by 1.4% per
month
37/41
Loss aversion and the cross section of stocks
38/41
PT and the Pricing of Skewness
39/41
PT and the Pricing of Skewness
40/41
Readings
Essential Readings:
Barberis, N., Mukherjee, A., & Wang, B. (2016). Prospect theory
and stock returns: an empirical test. The Review of Financial
Studies, 29(11), 3068-3107.
Kahneman D. and Tversky A. (1979), Prospect Theory: An Analysis
of Decision under Risk, Econometrica, 47(2),pp. 263-291
Benartzi, Shlomo, and Richard H. Thaler, 1995, "Myopic loss
aversion and the equity premium puzzle." The Quarterly Journal of
Economics, 73-92.
Odean, T., (1998), Are investors reluctant to realize their losses?
Journal of Finance 53, 1775-1798
Additional Reading:
Barberis, N., 2012, "Thirty Years of Prospect Theory in Economics: A Review and Assessment",
Journal of Economic Perspectives.
Grinblatt, Mark, and Bing Han. "Prospect theory, mental accounting, and momentum." Journal
of Financial Economics 78.2 (2005): 311-339.
Frazzini, Andrea. "The disposition eect and underreaction to news." The Journal of Finance
61.4 (2006): 2017-2046.
41/41