Lon L. Fuller - The Morality of Law-Yale University Press (1969)
Lon L. Fuller - The Morality of Law-Yale University Press (1969)
Lon L. Fuller - The Morality of Law-Yale University Press (1969)
Revised edition
BY LON L. FULLER
BookCrafters, Inc.,
Fredericksburg, Virginia.
35 34 33 32 31 30 29 28
PREFACE TO
THE SECOND EDITION
In this new edition of The Morality of Law the first four chapters
have been reprinted from the type as it was originally set, with
only a minor correction or two. The only change of substance
consists, therefore, in the addition of a fifth and final chapter
entitled "A Reply to Critics."
The fact that the first four chapters remain virtually unchanged
does not imply complete satisfaction with either the form or the
substance of the presentation achieved in them. It means simply
that I have not proceeded far enough in my rethinking of the
problems involved to undertake any substantial reformulation
of the views I first expressed in lectures delivered in 1963. It
VI
PREFACE TO
THE FIRST EDITION
vii
PREFACE
but for granting an extension of time so that I might more nearly
L.L.F.
vui
5
3
1
CONTENTS
y
Preface to the Second Edition v
ix
CONTENTS
Constancy of the Law through Time 79
Congruence between Official Action and Declared Rule 81
Legality as a Practical Art 91
XI
THE MORALITY OF LAW
THE TWO
I
MORALITIES
s
Sin, v.i. 1. To depart voluntarily from the path of duty prescribed by God
to man. —Webster's New International Dictionary
Die Siinde ist ein Versinken in das Nichts. 1
Sir
something I read long ago. Friends learned in theology have been unable
to identify its source. They inform me that its thought is Augustinian and
that there is a closely parallel passage in Karl Barth: "Die Siinde ist ein
Versinken in das Bodenlose." However, "das Bodenlose" implies a loss of
limits or boundaries and therefore suggests a transgression of duty. What
I have sought is an expression of the concept of sin as viewed by a morality
—
of aspiration sin as a failure in the effort to achieve a realization of the
human quality itself.
THE MORALITY OF LAW
compared with morality, it seems to be assumed that everyone
knows what the second term of the comparison embraces.
Thomas Reed Powell used to say that if you can think about
something that is related to something else without thinking
about the thing to which it is related, then you have the legal
mind. In the present case, it has seemed to me, the legal mind
generally exhausts itself in thinking about law and is content to
leave unexamined the thing to which law is being related and
from which it is being distinguished.
In my first chapter an effort is made to redress this balance.
This is done by emphasizing a distinction between what
chiefly
I call the morality of aspiration and the morality of duty. A failure
to make this distinction has, I think, been the cause of much ob-
scurity in discussions of the relation between law and morals.
The other major dissatisfaction underlying these lectures arises
from a neglect of what the title of my second chapter calls, "The
Morality That Makes Law Possible." Insofar as the existing litera-
ture deals with the chief subject of this second chapter which I —
call "the internal morality of law" — it is usually to dismiss it with
a few remarks about "legal justice," this conception of justice
being equated with a purely formal requirement that like cases be
given like treatment. There is little recognition that the problem
thus adumbrated is only one aspect of a much larger problem,
that of clarifying the directions of human effort essential to main-
tainany system of law, even one whose ultimate objectives may
be regarded as mistaken or evil.
The third and fourth chapters constitute a further development
and application of the analysis presented in the first two. The
third, entitled"The Concept of Law," attempts to bring this
analysis into relation with the various schools of legal philosophy
generally. The fourth, "The Substantive Aims of Law," seeks to
demonstrate how a proper respect for the internal morality of law
limits the kinds of substantive aims that may be achieved through
legal rules. The chapter closes with an examination of the extent
to which something like a substantive "natural law" may be de-
rived from the morality of aspiration.
THE TWO MORALITIES
and ask how the two moralities might proceed to pass judgment
on it. I have chosen the example of gambling. In using this term
I do not have in mind anything like a friendly game of penny ante,
^
it
all creative effort and that it is right and good that a man engaged
>l
v" /VjXin creative acts should not only accept the risks of his role, but
cd^ rejoice in them. The gambler, on the other hand, cultivates risk
>^y for own sake. Unable to face the broader responsibilities of
its
There isno way by which the law can compel a man to live up
to the excellences of which he is capable. For workable standards
of judgment the law must turn to its blood cousin, the morality
of duty. There, if anywhere, it will find help in deciding whether
gambling ought to be legally prohibited.
But what the morality of aspiration loses in direct relevance
for the law, it gains in the pervasiveness of its implications. In one
aspect our whole legal system represents a complex of rules de-
signed to rescue man from the blind play of chance and to put
him safely on the road to purposeful and creative activity. When
in transacting affairs with another a man pays money under a
mistake of fact, the law of quasi contract compels a return. The
law of contracts declares void agreements entered under a mutual
misapprehension of the relevant facts. Under the law of torts a
man may become answer for injuries
active without having to
that are the fortuitous by-product of his actions, except where
he enters upon some enterprise causing foreseeable risks that may
be reckoned as an actuarial cost of his undertaking and thus
subjected to rational calculation in advance. In the early stages
of the law, none of these principles was recognized. Their accep-
tance today represents the fruit of a centuries-old struggle to
reduce the role of the irrational in human affairs.
10
THE TWO MORALITIES
tivity of moral judgments.One side argues as follows: It is a fact
of experience that we can know and agree on what is bad. It
must follow that we have in the back of our minds some shared
picture of what is perfectly good. The task of moral philosophy is
therefore to bring to articulation something we already know
and agree upon. This is by the Platonic Socrates.
the route taken
The opposing party reasons as follows: It is obvious that men do
not agree on what is perfectly good. But since meaningful judg-
ments as to what is bad are impossible without an agreement on
—
what is perfectly good an agreement that plainly does not exist
— it must follow that our apparent agreement on what is bad is
11
THE MORALITY OF LAW
penter's hammer serves adequately over a large but indefinite
range of uses, revealing its deficiencies only when we try to use
it to drive very small tacks or heavy tent stakes. If a working
companion asks me for a hammer, or the nearest thing to it
available to me, I know at once, without knowing precisely what
operation he is undertaking, that many tools will be useless to
him. do not pass him a screwdriver or a length of rope. I can,
I
12
THE TWO MORALITIES
portant. But this does not mean that the social bond is ever
broken in that ascent. The classic statement of the morality of
aspiration was Greek philosophers. They took it for
that of the
granted that man had to find the good life
as a political animal
in a life shared with others. If we were cut off from our social
inheritance of language, thought, and art, none of us could aspire
to anything much above a purely animal existence. One of the
highest responsibilities of the morality of aspiration is to preserve
and enrich this social inheritance.
13
—
14
THE TWO MORALITIES
have been clarified, but confused, if he had said, "First, I shall
demonstrate what the good life is like so that you may understand
it and discern what kind of man you would become if you led it.
Then I shall advance reasons why you ought to lead such a life."
The Socratic identification of virtue with knowledge itself il-
uneasy way our ethical vocabulary has of migrating
lustrates the ^h
back and forth between the two moralities. With us the word >\P
"virtue" has become thoroughly identified with the morality of
J*
„UjV
L
duty. For moderns the word has largely lost its original sense of
~
/x
A
power, efficacy, skill, and courage, a set of connotations that once \
^ . L/yjJ*
put it plainly within the morality of aspiration. The word "sin" p4^>L4
has undergone a similar migration. With us to sin is to violate a JW
duty. Yet the words translated in the Bible as "sin" contained *\/Qp
originally the metaphor of "missing the mark." Something of ty
this original figure remained among the early Christians, for they )^\)
listed among the deadly sins, not only Avarice and Unchastity, but
15
THE MORALITY OF LAW
kinds of problems that are the special concern of the economist.
Beyond that the reader is left to decide for himself just what it is
he is studying. 11
There are, however, a few serious attempts to come to grips
with the problem of properly defining economic science. 12 In
these, two general views emerge. One is that economics has to do
with relationships of exchange. The other is that the heart of
economics lies in the principle of marginal utility, the principle by
which we make the most effective allocation of the resources at
our command in achieving whatever objectives we have set for
ourselves. The standard figure employed for distinguishing be-
tween these views is, of course, that of Robinson Crusoe. Until
the arrival of Friday, at least, there was no one with whom Crusoe
could exchange anything, except in the metaphorical sense in
which one may be said to trade one's solitary labor against the
fruits of nature. If economics is identified with exchanges between
—
Paul A. Samuelson's treatise, Economics An Introductory Analy-
11.
sis, is one of the most widely used college textbooks ever written.
said to be
In the second edition (1951, pp. 14-16) there appeared a discussion of the
"Boundaries and Limits to Economics," in which the view was advanced
that economics is concerned exclusively with means and has no compe-
tence to deal with ends. In the fifth edition (1961) this attempt to delimit
the competence of the subject has disappeared and in its place there is
simply a listing of the kinds of subjects with which economics deals
(pp. 5-6). An interesting demonstration that economic science is charac-
terized by a particular kind of end, and is incompetent to answer questions
when that end is excluded from consideration, will be found in R. F. Har-
rod, Scope and Method of Economics (1938), reprinted in Clemence,
Readings in Economic Analysis, 1 (1950), 1-30.
The most widely read treatment of the subject is that of Lionel
12.
Robbins, An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science
(2d ed. 1935).
16
THE TWO MORALITIES
sense Crusoe not only had economic problems, but very serious
ones.
Now there is, I believe, a striking parallel between these two
conceptions of economics and the two views of morality that are
the subject of this chapter. The economics of exchange has a close
affinity with the morality of duty. The economics of marginal
utility is, as it were, the economic counterpart of the morality of
aspiration. Let me begin with this second relationship.
The morality of aspiration has to do with our efforts to make
the best use of our short lives. Marginal utility economics deals
with our efforts to make the best use of our limited economic
resources. The two are not only alike in what they seek to do, but
also in their limitations. It is said that the morality of aspiration
necessarily implies some conception of the highest good of man,
though it fails to tell us what this is. Exactly the same criticism,
p^\$S
with the same force, can be directed against the marginal utility y
principle. The consumer is viewed by marginal utility economics \yKp\ .
as seeking to equalize the return for each dollar he spends. When\V(y a(V
he has spent so many dollars for books that the return from this d^
particular expenditure begins to diminish perceptibly, he may
expenditures to some other direction, say, for a richer and
shift his
—
more satisfying diet. In this shift in the very idea that one can}
compare and equalize expenditures for radically different things
— there seems to be implied some ultimate criterion that stands
above books, food, clothing, and all the other things and services
for which men may spend their money. The marginal utility
economist cannot describe what this criterion is, though, unlike,
the moralist of aspiration, he has a word to cover his ignorance.
That word is, of course, "utility." When the utility derived from
a dollar's worth of Commodity A declines to a point where it is
lower than the utility derived from a dollar's worth of Commodity l s
good. It is with this word "utility" that the economist draws a veil V f
over his failure to discern some economic good that stands above
all particular goods and serves to guide choice among them. The Y\\
17
THE MORALITY OF LAW
of the moralist who purports to show men the way to the Good
Life, without defining what the highest aim of life is or should
be. 13
Bentham's attempt to substitute for the goal of excellence that
of pleasure was in effect simply to introduce into morality the
same covert default that is inveterate in economics. It is impossible
to maintain the assertion that all human striving is directed toward
pleasure unless we are willing to expand the notion of pleasure to
the point becomes, like utility in economics, an empty
where it
13. It may be objected that the comparison in the text confuses descrip-
tion with prescription. Unlike the moral philosopher, the economist, it
may be said, is indifferent to the question what the consumer ought to
want; he merely describes a process of evaluation and finds the term
"utility" useful in this description. But this view dodges the difficulties
involved in trying to describe in wholly non-evaluative terms a process
that is itself evaluative. (These difficulties were the occasion for an ex-
change between myself and Professor Ernest Nagel; see 3 Natural Law
Forum 68-104 [1958]; 4 id. 26-43 [1959].) The economist may not care
what the consumer wants, but he cannot be indifferent to the process by
which the consumer reaches his decision as to what he wants. If he is to
understand that process, the economist must be capable of participating
in it vicariously and have an understanding of its terms.
18
THE TWO MORALITIES
it follows that we would not act at all, in any direction, if we were
not guided by some highest end. 14 Whatever one may think of
this paradoxical reasoning, there is nothing banal about Aris-
totle's conception of the just mean. This mean is not to be con- ,
A
fused with^he modern notion of "the middle way." For moderns ^\a 5$
the middle way is, the easy way, involving a minimum of commit-
mefer^or_Axist6tle the mean was the hard way, the way from,
which the and unskilled were most likely to fall. In this
slothful
respect it made the same demands on insight and intelligence that
sound economic management does. ^
Reciprocity and the Morality of Duty
example, that the citizen has a moral duty to vote, and to inform
himself sufficiently to vote intelligently, without implying that this
duty rests on a bargain between him and his government or be-
tween him and his fellow citizens.
To establish the affinity between duty and exchange we require
a third member, a mediating principle. This is to be found, I
think, in the relationship of reciprocity. Exchange is, after all,
19
THE MORALITY OF LAW
Even in the midst of the exalted appeals of the Sermon on the
Mount there is a repeated note of sober reciprocity. "Judge not,
that ye be not judged. For with what judgment ye judge, ye shall
be judged; and with what measure ye mete, it shall be measured
15. Matthew 7:1 and 12. Cf. Deuteronomy 7:11-12, "Thou shalt there-
fore keep the commandments, and the statutes, and the judgments, which
I command thee this day, to do them. Wherefore it shall come to pass, if ye
hearken to these judgments, and keep, and do them, that the lord thy God
shall keep unto thee the covenant and the mercy which he sware unto thy
fathers."
20
a
of an original compact.
This argument underestimates, I believe, the extent to which
the principle of reciprocity has roots not only in our professions
but in our practices as well. The rephrasing of the Golden Rule I
presented a short while ago was an obvious perversion of its
-£>>
'r X
it represents a kind of "fail-safe" point. Men are certain to be ofj^T
different minds as to just when this point is reached. But there are'
obvious cases where no dispute is possible. So when I urge on a
fellow citizen that he has a duty to go to the polls, my appeal will
certainly lose its force if he knows quite well there is no likelihood
that his ballot will be counted.
The duty to vote is not absolute, but depends upon the fulfill-
ment of certain expectations concerning the actions of others.
This would be true even of a citizen who might vote knowing his
ballot would not be counted where his object was to make a test
case of certain election abuses. If all the world remains indifferent
and unmoved by his action —does come forward with some
not
reaction to it —then it remains utterly pointless.
In this broad sense there is a notion of reciprocity implicit in
the very notion of duty — at least in the case of every duty that
runs toward society or toward another responsible human being.
One can imagine a social bond that knows nothing of duties.
Such a bond might exist between a couple deeply in love, or
among a small band of men united by some emergency making —
—
THE MORALITY OF LAW
let us say, a stand against an encircling enemy. In such a
last
situation therewould be no thought of measuring contributions.
The appropriate organizing principle would be "one for all and
all for one." But so soon as contributions are designated and
—
measured which means so soon as there are duties there must —
—
be some standard however rough and approximate it may be
by which the kind and the extent of the expected contribution is
determined. This standard must be derived from the pattern of
a social fabric that unites strands of individual action. A sufficient
rupture in this fabric must — if we are to judge the matter with
any rationality at all — release men from those duties that had
as their only reason for being, maintaining a pattern of social
interaction that has now been destroyed.
In the argument just presented there is implicit the notion of
a sort of anonymous collaboration among men by which their
activities are channeled through the institutions and procedures
of an organized society. This conception seems a long way from
that of a simple exchange of economic values. But we should
recall that even the direct and explicit relationship of reciprocity
is by no means confined to anything like a horse trade. Suppose,
for example, that two men exchange promises to give equal sums
to the same charity. Here the usual self-serving motives of ex-
change are absent, as is also the notion of performances running
between the parties to the exchange. Yet in this case we certainly
have a relation of reciprocity and, assuming no rights of the
charity have intervened, the repudiation of his promise by one
of the parties ought in fairness to excuse the other. The duties of
both arise from and depend upon a relation of reciprocity that is
not different in kind from that which unites the members of a
society in more complex ways.
If it is true that duties generally can be traced to the principle
of reciprocity, it is also true that the reciprocity out of which a
given duty arises can be visible, as it were, in varying degrees.
At times it is obvious to those affected by it; at others it traces a
more subtle and obscure course through the institutions and
practices of society. This suggests the question: Under what cir-
22
THE TWO MORALITIES
cumstances does a duty, legal or moral, become most understand-
able and most acceptable to those affected by it? I think we may
discern three conditions for the optimum efficacy of the notion
of duty. First, the relationship of reciprocity out of which the
duty arises must result from a voluntary agreement between the
parties immediately affected; they themselves "create" the duty.
Second, the reciprocal performances of the parties must in some
sense be equal in value. Though the notion of voluntary assump-
tion itselfmakes a strong appeal to the sense of justice, that appeal
is reinforced when the element of equivalence is added to it. We
cannot here speak of an exact identity, for it makes no sense at
all to exchange, say, a book or idea in return for exactly the
same book or idea. The bond of reciprocity unites men, not simply
in spite of their differences, but because of their differences. When,
therefore, we seek equality in a relation of reciprocity what we
require is some measure of value that can be applied to things
that are different in kind. Third, the relationships within the so-
ciety must be sufficiently fluid so that the same duty you owe me
today, I may owe you tomorrow — in other words, the relation-
ship of dutymust in theory and in practice be reversible. Without
symmetry we are likely to be stumped by Rousseau's question,
this
What is the reason that I, being myself, should act as if I were
the other person, when I am virtually certain that I shall never
be found in his situation? 16
These, then, are the three conditions for an optimum realiza-
tion of the notion of duty, the conditions that make a duty most
16. The passage from Rousseau occurs in Emile, Book IV, and is here
quoted from Del Vecchio, Justice (1952), p. 96. Rousseau intends his ques-
tion, of course, as a refutation of utilitarian theories of duty. Del Vecchio
himself makes much of reciprocity in his analysis of justice. In distinguish-
ing a mere demand from a claim of right, Del Vecchio points out that the
latter presupposes a general principle, according to which if the positions
of the parties were reversed, the same duty would be imposed in the oppo-
site direction. This abstract reciprocity loses much of its appeal, however,
if the reversal of positions cannot in fact occur. It is not much consolation
to the slave, for example, to be told that if he had been born a master and
his master, a slave, then it would have been his right to command what
he must now render.
23
THE MORALITY OF LAW
understandable and most palatable to the man who owes it. When
we what kind of society are these conditions most apt to
ask, "In
be met?" the answer is a surprising one: in a society of economic
traders. By definition the members of such a society enter direct
and voluntary relationships of exchange. As for equality it is
only with the aid of something like a free market that it is possible
to develop anything like an exact measure for the value of dis-
parate goods. 17 Without such a measure, the notion of equality
loses substance and descends to the level of a kind of metaphor.
Finally, economic traders frequently change roles, now selling,
now buying. The duties that arise out of their exchanges are
therefore reversible, not only in theory but in practice. The re-
versibility of role that thus characterizes a trading society exists
nowhere else in the same degree, as becomes apparent when we
consider the duties running between parent and child, husband
and wife, citizen and government. Hayek sees the rule of law itself
as dependent on a condition of society such that men may meet
today to legislate their duties not knowing tomorrow whether
they will owe these duties or be their beneficiaries. Understand-
ably, Hayek identifies such a society with one organized on the
market principle, and predicts a collapse of the rule of law for
any society which abandons the market principle. 18
This analysis suggests the somewhat startling conclusion that
it is only under capitalism that the notion of the moral and legal
duty can reach its full development. This was in fact the conclu-
sion reached by a once famous Soviet writer, Eugene Pashukanis,
perhaps the only Soviet thinker who can be said to have made a
distinctive contribution to social philosophy. 19
17. It should be recalled, however, that there are proposals (which have
been put into at least partial operation within the Soviet bloc) for managing
a socialist economy by market principles. See, for example, Oskar Lange,
On the Economic Theory of Socialism (1936-37), reprinted in a volume
with the same title, edited by Benjamin E. Lippincott (1938), pp. 55-129.
18. Chapter VI, "Planning and the Rule of Law," The Road to Serf-
dom (1944), pp. 72-87.
19. See Vol. V, 20th Century Legal Philosophy Series, Soviet Legal
Philosophy, trans. Babb (1951), "The General Theory of Law and Marx-
24
THE TWO MORALITIES
Pashukanis' theory became known as the Commodity Ex-
change Theory of Law, though it might better have been called
the Commodity Exchange Theory of Legal and Moral Duty. The
theory was built on two pillars of Marxist thought: first, in the
organization of society the economic factor is paramount; legal
and moral principles and institutions therefore constitute a kind c,
x
o^
,
exchange. It follows therefore that the legal and political institu- \fi)
tions of such a society will be permeated with notions derived
from exchange. So in bourgeois criminal law we find a table of
crimes with a schedule of appropriate punishments or expiations
—a kind of price list for misbehavior. In private law the dominant
figure is that of the legal subject who owes duties, possesses rights,
and is granted the legal power to settle his disputes with others by \)^ v
^
Aj^
agreement. The legal subject is thus the legal counterpart of the
economic With communism economic exchange will be
trader.
abolished, as will all the legal and political conceptions that
derive from it. In particular communism will know nothing of
legal rights and duties.
The same analysis was extended to the field of morals. With
achieved communism, morality as it is usually understood (that
is, as the morality of duty) will cease to perform any function.
How far Pashukanis carried his theory may be seen in his attitude
toward Kant. Kant's view that we should treat our fellow man as
an end, and not merely as a means, is usually regarded as one of
the noblest expressions of his philosophy. For Pashukanis it was
merely the reflection of a market economy, for it is only by enter-
25
THE MORALITY OF LAW
serve our ends at the same time we serve theirs. Indeed, any kind
of reciprocity, however circuitously it may operate through social
forms, casts men in a dual role, as ends in themselves and as means
to the ends of others. Since there is no clear stop or breaking point
between implicit reciprocity and explicit exchange, Pashukanis
^
\ends with the conclusion that when communism is finally achieved
allmoral duties will disappear.
These views proved too strong (or at least too inconvenient)
for Pashukanis' contemporaries in Stalinist Russia, and he was
VJCfiquidated in 1937. In justice to his memory it should be said that
r &/ his theories have strong roots in the teachings of the communist
>\V\ forefathers. They obviously derive support from the twin doc-
u v ^Nlrines of the superstructure and of the future withering away of
kj ^n]\ state and law. They also have a remarkable emotional affinity with
the whole tenor of Marx's thought, especially as revealed in the
youthful "alienation theme." Marx seemed to have had a strong
distaste for any principle or arrangement that could make one
v man serve the ends of another, though this compulsion is not only
""
implicit in exchange but in any kind of formal social organization.
This distaste reveals itself implicitly in his lifelong antipathy to
the very notion of a formal division of labor, an antipathy all the
more curious since it must have been plain to Marx that the eco-
nomic production sought by communism would be impossible
without the gains resulting from a specialization of function. This
fundamental aversion to interdependence comes to most articulate
expression in an early passage in which Marx describes life in
bourgeois society — that is, in a trading society — as one in which
man "treats others as means, reduces himself to the role of a
means, and becomes the plaything of alien forces." 20
With the bitter mood of this passage from Marx we may con-
trast the description of economic exchange given by Philip Wick-
steed, a Unitarian minister turned economist:
26
THE TWO MORALITIES
furthering the immediate purposes of others than by the
direct method of pursuing our own . . . We enter into busi-
ness relations with others, not because our purposes are
selfish, but because those with whom we deal are relatively
indifferent to them, but are (like us) keenly interested in
purposes of their own, to which we in our turn are relatively
indifferent There is surely nothing degrading or revolting
. . .
mood, the world might today bear a very different aspect for all
of us.
27
—
28
THE TWO MORALITIES
perfection, including that which seeks maximum economic ef-
at p. 355 (1908).
29
THE MORALITY OF LAW
notion of "defeasible concepts." 25 To say that a man has entered
a contract is not just to tip the scales of justice indeterminately
toward the conclusion that he may possibly have incurred an
obligation. It is to say that he is obligated unless some specific
ground of excuse, such as incapacity or duress, can be established.
One may suggest that what is manifested here is an impulse of
the morality of duty, expressing itself within the law, to maintain
the integrity of its domain and to protect that domain from the
erosions threatened by a view that attempts to solve too many
simultaneous equations at once.
30
THE TWO MORALITIES
industry, agriculture, and sports. Wherever distinctions are
granted or deprivations imposed it is natural to select some um-
pire or committee to make the decision, and, no matter whether
the issue be that of penalty or award, the deciding agency is
31
—
THE MORALITY OF LAW
Generally we are content with informal methods of decision
often screened from the public —when selections are made for
honorary degrees, military decorations, hero medals, literary and
scientific prizes, foundation awards, and testimonial dinners. One
outstanding exception to this laxness may seem to be presented
by the elaborately formal procedure of beatification in the Roman
Catholic Church. But this procedure does not in fact constitute
an exception. Its object is not to honor a saint, but to authorize
a cult. In the language of administrative law, it is a certification
procedure. The required performance — including as does the
—
it
32
THE MORALITY
II
THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
[A] law which a man cannot obey, nor act according to it, is void and no
law: and it is impossible to obey contradictions, or act according to them.
— Vaughan, C. J. in Thomas v. Sorrell, 1677
gave them a lawless unlimited power, and at their pleasure to walk con-
trary to their own laws and ordinances before they have repealed them?
— Lilburne, England's Birth-Right Justified, 1645
33
THE MORALITY OF LAW
the rules of law spoke in the archaic tongue of another age, justice
was expensive, the judges were slovenly and sometimes corrupt.
Rex was resolved to remedy all this and to make his name in
history as a great lawgiver. It was his unhappy fate to fail in this
ambition. Indeed, he failed spectacularly, since not only did he
not succeed in introducing the needed reforms, but he never even
succeeded in creating any law at good or bad.
all,
34
—
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
labor, succeeded in preparing a fairly lengthy document. He was
still not confident, however, that he had fully overcome his pre-
vious defects. Accordingly, he announced to his subjects that he
had written out a code and would henceforth be governed by it
in deciding cases, but that for an indefinite future the contents of
had taught him one clear lesson, namely, that it is easier to decide
things with the aid of hindsight than it is to attempt to foresee
and control the Not only did hindsight make it easier to
future.
decide cases, but —
and this was of supreme importance to Rex
it made it easier to give reasons. Deciding to capitalize on this
judgments with the rules applied by him, thus meeting the chief
objection to the old plan. Rex's subjects received this announce-
ment in silence, then quietly explained through their leaders that
when they said they needed to know the rules, they meant they
needed to know them in advance so they could act on them. Rex
muttered something to the effect that they might have made that
point a little clearer, but said he would see what could be done.
Rex now realized that there was no escape from a published
code declaring the rules to be applied in future disputes. Con-
tinuing his lessons in generalization, Rex worked diligently on a
35
THE MORALITY OF LAW
revised code, and finally announced that it would shortly be pub-
lished. This announcement was received with universal gratifica-
tion. The dismay of Rex's subjects was all the more intense,
therefore, when his code became available and it was discovered
that it was truly a masterpiece of obscurity. Legal experts who
studied it declared that there was not a single sentence in it that
could be understood either by an ordinary citizen or by a trained
lawyer. Indignation became general and soon a picket appeared
before the royal palace carrying a sign that read, "How can any-
body follow a rule that nobody can understand?"
The code was quickly withdrawn. Recognizing for the first
time that he needed assistance, Rex put a staff of experts to work
on a revision. He instructed them to leave the substance un-
touched, but to clarify the expression throughout. The resulting
code was a model of clarity, but as it was studied itbecame ap-
parent that its new clarity had merely brought to light that it was
honeycombed with contradictions. It was reliably reported that
there was not a single provision in the code that was not nullified
by another provision inconsistent with it. A picket again appeared
before the royal residence carrying a sign that read, "This time
the king —
made himself clear in both directions."
Once again the code was withdrawn for revision. By now,
however, Rex had lost his patience with his subjects and the nega-
tive attitude they seemed to adopt toward everything he tried to
do for them. He decided to teach them a lesson and put an end
to their carping. He instructed his experts to purge the code of
contradictions, but at the same time to stiffen drastically every
requirement contained and to add a long list of new crimes.
in it
Thus, where before the citizen summoned to the throne was given
ten days in which to report, in the revision the time was cut to ten
seconds. It was made a crime, punishable by ten years' imprison-
ment, to cough, sneeze, hiccough, faint or fall down in the pres-
ence of the king. It was made treason not to understand, believe
in, and correctly profess the doctrine of evolutionary, democratic
redemption.
When the new code was published a near revolution resulted.
36
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
Leading citizens declared their intention to flout its provisions.
Someone discovered in an ancient author a passage that seemed
apt: "To command what cannot be done is not to make law; it
is to unmake law, for a command that cannot be obeyed serves
no end but confusion, fear and chaos." Soon this passage was
being quoted in a hundred petitions to the king.
The code was again withdrawn and a staff of experts charged
with the task of revision. Rex's instructions to the experts were
that whenever they encountered a rule requiring an impossibility,
it make compliance possible. It turned out
should be revised to
that to accomplish this result every provision in the code had
to be substantially rewritten. The final result was, however, a
triumph of draftsmanship. It was clear, consistent with itself, and
demanded nothing of the subject that did not lie easily within
was printed and distributed free of charge on every
his powers. It
street corner.
However, before the effective date for the new code had ar-
rived, it was discovered that so much time had been spent in
37
THE MORALITY OF LAW
suming the judicial power in his own way he could
person. In this
directly control the application of the new code and insure his
country against another crisis. He began to spend practically all
of his time hearing and deciding cases arising under the new code.
As the king proceeded with this task, it seemed to bring to a
belated blossoming his long dormant powers of generalization.
His opinions began, indeed, to reveal a confident and almost
exuberant virtuosity as he deftly distinguished his own previous
decisions, exposed the principles on which he acted, and laid
down guide lines for the disposition of future controversies. For
Rex's subjects a new day seemed about to dawn when they could
finally conform their conduct to a coherent body of rules.
This hope was, however, soon shattered. As the bound volumes
of Rex's judgments became available and were subjected to closer
study, his subjects were appalled to discover that there existed
no discernible relation between those judgments and the code
they purported to apply. Insofar as it found expression in the
actual disposition of controversies, the new code might just as
well not have existed at all. Yet in virtually every one of his
decisions Rex declared and redeclared the code to be the basic
law of his kingdom.
Leading citizens began to hold private meetings to discuss
what measures, short of open revolt, could be taken to get the
king away from the bench and back on the throne. While these
discussions were going on Rex suddenly died, old before his time
and deeply disillusioned with his subjects.
The first act of his successor, Rex II, was to announce that he
was taking the powers of government away from the lawyers and
placing them in the hands of psychiatrists and experts in public
relations. This way, he explained, people could be made happy
without rules.
38
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
carry in at least eight ways; there are in this enterprise, if you
lies ina failure to achieve rules at all, so that every issue must
be decided on an ad hoc basis. The other routes are: (2) a failure | ;jj\|^
.
\£
to publicize, or at least to make available to the affected party, \*@JX
the rules he is expected to observe; (3) the abuse of retroactive
legislation, which not only cannot itself guide action, but under-
39
THE MORALITY OF LAW
effect, "These are the rules we expect you to follow. If you follow
them, you have our assurance that they are the rules that will be
applied to your conduct." When this bond of reciprocity is finally
40
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
that of the voter who knows that the odds are against his ballot
being counted at all, and that if is counted, there is a good
it
0^
chance that it be counted for the^side against which he actual-
will ip^
ly voted. A citizen in this predicament has to decide for himself #^v
whether to stay with the system and cast his ballot as a kind of A0- J>L
^ a\t
-
v
than there can be such a principle for testing his right to engage \\ \
41
—
THE MORALITY OF LAW
Nevertheless it does suggest eight distinct standards by which
excellence in legality may be tested.
In expounding in my first chapter the distinction between the
morality of duty and that of aspiration, I spoke of an imaginary
scale that starts at the bottom with the most obvious and essential
moral duties and ascends upward to the highest achievements
open to man. I also spoke of an invisible pointer as marking the
dividing line where the pressure of duty leaves off and the chal-
lenge of excellence begins. The inner morality of law, it should
now be clear, presents all of these aspects. It too embraces a
morality of duty and a morality of aspiration. It too confronts
us with the problem of knowing where to draw the boundary
below which men will be condemned for failure, but can expect
no praise for success, and above which they will be admired for
success and at worst pitied for the lack of it.
In applying the analysis of the first chapter to our present
subject, it becomes essential to consider certain distinctive quali-
ties of the inner morality of law. In what may be called the basic
not defame, and the like. Such duties lend themselves with a
minimum of difficulty to formalized definition. That is to say,
whether we are concerned with legal or moral duties, we are able
to develop standards which designate with some precision
—
though it is never complete the kind of conduct that is to be
avoided.
The demands of the inner morality of the law, however, though
they concern a relationship with persons generally, demand more
than forbearances; they are, as we loosely say, affirmative in na-
ture: make the law known, make it coherent and clear, see that
your decisions as an official are guided by it, etc. To meet these
demands human energies must be directed toward specific kinds
of achievement and not merely warned away from harmful acts.
Because of the affirmative and creative quality of its demands,
42
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
the inner morality of law lends itself badly to realization through **V^
duties, whether they be moral or legal. No matter how desirable CrAig/
a direction of human effort may appear to be, if we assert there p<\P.
is a duty to pursue it, we shall confront the responsibility of de- X^fXN •
fining at what point been violated. It is easy to as-
that duty has V rfy
sert that the legislator has a moral duty to make his laws clear \$r £{J*
less we are prepared to define the degree of clarity he must at- fe-
^ qC?
tain in order to discharge his duty. The notion of subjecting n, (J^O
clarity to quantitative measure presents obvious difficulties. WeC/^
may content ourselves, of course, by saying that the legislator
has at least a moral duty to try to be clear. But this only post-
pones the difficulty, for in some situations nothing can be more
baffling than to attempt to measure how vigorously a man in-
tended to do that which he has failed to do. In the morality of
law, in any event, good intentions are of little avail, as King Rex
amply demonstrated. All of this adds up to the conclusion that
the inner morality of law is condemned to remain largely a
morality of aspiration and not of duty. Its primary appeal must
be to a sense of trusteeship and to the pride of the craftsman.
To these observations there is one important exception. This
relates to the desideratum of making the laws known, or at least
making them available to those affected by them. Here we have
a demand that lends itself with unusual readiness to formaliza-
tion. A written constitution may prescribe that no statute shall
become law until it has been given a specified form of publica-
tion. If the courts have power to effectuate this provision, we
may speak of a legal requirement for the making of law. But a
moral duty with respect to publication is also readily imaginable.
A custom, for example, might define what kind of promulgation
of laws is expected, at the same time leaving unclear what con-
sequences attend a departure from the accepted mode of publica-
tion. A formalization of the desideratum of publicity has obvious
advantages over uncanalized efforts, even when they are intel-
and conscientiously pursued. A formalized standard of
ligently
promulgation not only tells the lawmaker where to publish his
43
THE MORALITY OF LAW
laws; it also lets the subject — or a lawyer representing his in-
terests —know where to go to learn what the law is.
One might suppose that the principle condemning retroactive
laws could also be very readily formalized in a simple rule that
no such law should ever be passed, or should be valid if en-
Pv acted. Such a rule would, however, disserve the cause of legality.
Curiously, one of the most obvious seeming demands of legality
— that a rule passed today should govern what happens to-
—
morrow, not what happened yesterday turns out to present some
of the most difficult problems of the whole internal morality of
law.
With respect to the demands of legality other than promulga-
tion, then, themost we can expect of constitutions and courts is
that they save us from the abyss; they cannot be expected to lay
out very many compulsory steps toward truly significant accom-
plishment.
44
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
wavering middle course between too frequent change and no
change at all, sustained by the conviction, not that the course
chosen is the only right one, but that we must in all events keep
clear of the shoals of disaster that lie on either side.
It is much less obvious, I suspect, that antinomies may arise
within the internal morality of law Yet it is easy to demon-
itself.
45
THE MORALITY OF LAW
road that leads from the abyss of total failure to the heights of
human excellence.
It is now time to pass in an extended review each of the eight
demands of the law's inner morality. This review will deal with
certain difficulties hitherto passed over, particularly those touch-
ing the relation between the internal and external moralities of
law. It will also include some remarks on the ways in which
problems of the law's inner morality have actually arisen in
history.
46
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
The complaint registered against these agencies is not so much
that their rules are unfair, but that they have failed to develop
any significant rules at all. This distinction is important because
any person of age." (Article VI §25, as amended to Nov. 4, 1952.) The same
Article, however, contains a general prohibition of special or local laws
"in all cases where a general law can be made applicable." This has pro-
duced a veritable donnybrook of litigation.
47
THE MORALITY OF LAW
lating general rules; if he does, he may not succeed in conveying
them employer succeeds in bringing
to the employee, etc. If the
into existence a functioning system of rules, he will discover that
this success has been bought at a certain cost to himself. He must
not only invest some effort and intelligence in the enterprise, but
its very success limits his own freedom of action. If in distrib-
uting praise and censure, he habitually disregards his own rules,
he may find his system of law disintegrating, and without any
open revolt, it may cease to produce for him what he sought to
obtain through it.
48
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
literature since his time has scarcely recovered from this original
misdirection. 6
Perhaps the basic defect of Austin's analysis lay in his failure
Promulgation
49
THE MORALITY OF LAW
The need for this education will, of course, depend upon how
far the requirements of law depart from generally shared views
of right and wrong. Over much of its history the common law
has been largely engaged in working out the implications of
conceptions that were generally held in the society of the time.
This large measure of coincidence between moral and legal de-
mands reduced greatly the force of the objection that the rules of
the common law were, in contrast with those of a code, difficult
of access.
The problem of promulgation is complicated by the question,
"Just what counts as law for purposes of this requirement?" De-
ciding agencies, especially administrative tribunals, often take
the view that, though the rules they apply to controversies ought
to be published, a like requirement does not attach to the rules
and practices governing their internal procedures. Yet every ex-
perienced attorney knows that to predict the outcome of cases
it is often essential to know, not only the formal rules governing
them, but the internal procedures of deliberation and consulta-
tion by which these rules are in fact applied. Perhaps it is in
recognition of this that the otherwise bizarre seeming require-
ment has developed in Switzerland and Mexico that certain courts
must hold their deliberations in public.
The man whom Thurman Arnold sometimes calls the "mere
realist" (when he is not reserving that role for himself) 9 might be
tempted to say something like this of the requirement of promul-
gation: "After all, we have thousands of laws, only the smallest
fraction of which are known, directly or indirectly, to the ordi-
50
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
nary citizen. Why all this fuss about publishing them? Without
reading the criminal code, the citizen knows he shouldn't murder
and steal. As for the more esoteric laws, the full text of them
might be distributed on every street corner and not one man
in a hundred would ever read it." To this a number of responses
must be made. Even if only one man in a hundred takes the pains
to inform himself concerning, say, the laws applicable to the
practice of his calling, this is enough to justify the trouble taken
to make the laws generally available. This citizen at least is en-
titled to know, and he cannot be identified in advance. Further-
more, in many activities men observe the law, not because they
know it directly, but because they follow the pattern set by others
whom they know to be better informed than themselves. In this
way knowledge of the law by a few often influences indirectly
the actions of many. The laws should also be given adequate
publication so that they may be subject to public criticism, in-
cluding the criticism that they are the kind of laws that ought
not to be enacted unless their content can be effectively conveyed
to those subject to them. It is also plain that if the laws are not
made readily available, there no check against a disregard of
is
Retroactive Laws
In this country the problem of retroactive laws is explicitly dealt
with in certain provisions of the United States Constitution 10
10. The third paragraph of Article I, Section IX, provides, "No bill of
attainder or ex post facto law shall be passed" by the Congress. Despite
the breadth of its language, the provision concerning ex post facto laws has
been construed to apply only to criminal statutes. (See the articles cited in
51
.
ignorance of law does not excuse, and hence a law may properly be ap-
plied to one who did not know of it, the retroactive statute only carries this
a bit further by applying a law to one who could not possibly have known
of it. General Theory of Law and State (1945), pp. 43-44, 73, 146, 149. For
52
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
Taken by itself, and in abstraction from its possible function
in a system of laws that are largely prospective, a retroactive
law is truly a monstrosity. Law has to do with the governance
of human conduct by rules. To speak of governing or directing
conduct today by rules that will be enacted tomorrow is to talk
in blank prose. To ask how we should appraise an imaginary
legal system consisting exclusively of laws that are retroactive,
and retroactive only, is like asking how much air pressure there
is in a perfect vacuum.
53
THE MORALITY OF LAW
Though the statute is duly promulgated, it is little publicized, and
the method by which it would ordinarily become known, by word
of mouth among those who perform marriages, fails because the
stamps are not distributed. Many marriages take place between
persons who know nothing of the law, and often before a minister
who also knows nothing of it. This occurs after the legislature has
adjourned. When it is back into session, the legislature
called
enacts a statute conferring validity on marriages which by the
terms of the previous statute were declared void. Though taken
by itself, the retrospective effect of the second statute impairs
the principle of legality, it alleviates the effect of a previous
failure to realize two other desiderata of legality: that the laws
should be made known to those affected by them and that they
should be capable of being obeyed. 14
One might be tempted to derive from this illustration the les-
54
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
ings were attended by a mere irregularity of form which con-
sisted in the fact that he held in his hand a pistol rather than
the staff of justice. 15 And, on this view of the matter, he might
even have quoted the language of our Supreme Court in up-
holding an enactment which it called "a curative statute aptly
designed to remedy . . . defects in the administration of govern-
ment."^
A second aspect of retrospective lawmaking relates not so
much to any positive contribution it may on occasion make to
the internal morality of the law, but rather to the circumstance
that it unavoidably attaches in some measure to the office of
judge. It is important to note that a system for governing human
conduct by formally enacted rules does not of necessity require
courts or any other institutional procedure for deciding disputes
about the meaning of rules. In a small and friendly society,
governed by relatively simple rules, such disputes may not arise.
If they do, they may be settled by a voluntary accommodation
of interests. Even if they are not so resolved, a certain number
of continuing controversies on the periphery may not seriously
impair the efficacy of the system as a whole.
I emphasize this point because it is so often taken for granted
that courts are simply a reflection of the fundamental purpose
of law, which assumed to be that of settling disputes. The need
is
for rules —
so it seems to be thought —
arises wholly out of man's
selfish, quarrelsome, and disputatious nature. In a society of angels
55
THE MORALITY OF LAW
by some then they need law as law is viewed
explicit decision,
in these essays. A
King Rex called in to govern them and to
establish rules for their conduct would lose no opportunity to
bungle his job simply because his subjects were angels. One
might object that at least the problem of maintaining congruence
between official action and enacted rule would not arise; but
this is not true, for Rex might easily fall into the pit of addressing
particular requests to his angelic subjects that conflicted with the
general rules he had laid down for their conduct. This practice
might produce a state of confusion in which the general rules
would lose their directive force.
In a complex and numerous political society courts perform
—
an essential function. No system of law whether it be judge-
made or legislatively enacted —can be so perfectly drafted as
to leave no room for dispute. When a dispute arises concerning
the meaning of a particular rule, some provision for a resolution
of the dispute is necessary. The most apt way to achieve this
resolution lies in some form of judicial proceeding.
Suppose, then, a dispute arises between A and B concerning the
meaning of a statutory rule by which their respective rights are
determined. Their dispute is submitted to a court. After weigh-
ing all the arguments carefully the judge may consider that they
are about evenly balanced between the position taken by A and
that taken by B. In that sense the statute really gives him no clear
standard for deciding the case. Yet the principles relevant to its
decision lie in this statute, the requirements of which would in
nine cases out of ten raise no problem at all. If the judge fails
to render a decision, he fails in his duty to settle disputes arising
out of an existing body of law. If he decides the case, he in-
evitably engages in an act of retrospective legislation.
Obviously the judge must decide the case. If every time doubt
arose as to the meaning of a rule, the judge were to declare the
existence of a legal vacuum, the efficacy of the whole system of
prospective rules would be seriously impaired. To act on rules
confidently, men must not only have a chance to learn what the
rules are, but must also be assured that in case of a dispute about
56
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
their meaning there is available some method for resolving the
dispute.
In the case just supposed the argument for a retrospective de-
cision is very strong. Suppose, however, that the court acts not
to clarify a doubt about the law, but to overrule one of its own
precedents. Following the case of A v. B, for example, the same
dispute arises between C and D. C refuses to settle the dispute
on the basis of the decision rendered in A v. B, and instead takes
the case to court. C convinces the court that its decision in A v. B
was mistaken and should be overruled. If this overruling is made
retrospective, then D loses out though he relied on a legal de-
cision that was clearly in his favor. On the other hand, if the
decision in A v. B was wrong and ought to have been overruled,
then C has performed a public service in refusing to accept it
and in taking it to court to be reexamined. It is surely ironic
if the only reward C receives for this service is to have a now
17. See the note in the Yale Law Journal cited in n. 12, supra.
18. See reference of last note.
57
THE MORALITY OF LAW
ruling decision were projected retrospectively, then men would
be branded as criminals who acted in reliance on a judicial
interpretation of the law.
It has been supposed that different considerations apply to
cases where the court settles previously unresolved uncertainties
in the application of a criminal statute and that such cases are to
be treated just like the civil case of A v. B discussed above. This
view is, I believe, mistaken. It is true that there are certain safe-
guards here that mitigate what appears to be the gross injustice
of retrospectively making criminal what was previously not clear-
ly so. If the criminal statute as a whole is uncertain of applica-
tion it may be declared unconstitutionally vague. Furthermore,
58
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
There remains for examination the most difficult problem of
all, that of knowing when an enactment should properly be re-
pass today a tax law that determines the levy to be imposed onj
the basis of events occurring in the past.
To the ordinary citizen the argument just advanced would
probably appear as the merest quibble. He would be likely to
say that just as a man may do an act because he knows it to be
legal under the existing criminal law, so he may enter a trans-
action because he knows that under the existing law the gain it
yields is not subject to tax. If the ex post facto criminal law is
59
—
THE MORALITY OF LAW
The answer to this argument would call attention to the con-
sequences that would follow if its implications were fully ac-
cepted. Laws of all kinds, and not merely tax laws, enter into
men's calculations and decisions. A man may decide to study
for a particular profession, to get married, to limit or increase
the size of his family, to make a final disposition of his estate
all with reference to an existing body of law, which includes not
only tax laws, but the laws of property and contract, and per-
haps, even, election laws which bring about a particular distri-
bution of political power. If every time a man relied on existing
law in arranging his affairs, he were made secure against any
change in legal rules, the whole body of our law would be ossified
forever.
To
this argument a reply could be made along the following
lines:Tax laws are not just like other laws. For one thing, they
enter more directly into the planning of one's affairs. Moreover
« ^ ^-\\ —
and much more importantly their principal object is often not
merely to raise revenue, but to shape human conduct in ways
thought desirable by the legislator. In this respect they are close
N ry^ cousins to the criminal law. The laws of property and contract
neither prescribe nor recommend any particular course of ac-
tion; their object is merely to protect acquisitions resulting from
unspecified activities. Tax laws, on the other hand, coax men
into, or dissuade them from, certain kinds of behavior and this
is often precisely their objective. When they thus become a kind
of surrogate for the criminal law, they lose, as it were, their
primitive innocence. In the case with which this discussion began
(where the law originally imposed no tax on certain kinds of
gains) the purpose of the law may have been to induce men to
enter transactions of the kind that would yield these very gains.
When a tax is later imposed on gains arising from these trans-
actions, men are in effect penalized for doing what the law itself
60
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
tracts, for example, might be said to have the purpose of in-
ducing men to organize their affairs through "private enterprise."
If business operations are planned in part by taking into account
the existing law of contracts, is that law to be forever immune
from change? Suppose a man unable to read or write becomes
a real estate broker at a time when oral brokerage contracts are
enforceable. Is he to be protected against a later law that might
require such contracts to be evidenced by a signed writing? As
for the argument that tax laws often have the explicit purpose
of attracting men into, or deterring them from, certain activities,
who can say what the precise function of a tax is, except that
it raises revenue? One. legislator may have favored a tax for one
61
THE MORALITY OF LAW
felt they had a right to depose him. The notion that a revolution
may be by a breach of contract by the government is,
justified
United States. 20
20. Tot v. United States, 319 U.S. 463 (1942). The Court also struck
down another presumption contained in the Act. This provided that pos-
62
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
vision which itself impairs legality. Water from a tainted spring vj ftjij
l
unintelligible statute. But it does not appear in his discussion. The neglect
of this subject by positivistic writers is, however, quite understandable. A
recognition that laws may vary in clarity would entail a further recognition
that laws can have varying degrees of efficacy, that the unclear statute is,
n
in a real sense, less a law than the clear one. But this would be to accept a
proposition that runs counter to the basic assumptions of positivism.
In this country it has been urged that, quite without reference to any
standards impliedly imposed by constitutions, the courts should refuse to
make any attempt to apply statutes drastically lacking in clarity. Aigler,
#
"Legislation in Vague or General Terms," 21 Michigan Law Review 831—
51 (1922). As the law has developed, however, the requirement of clarity
has been incorporated in a doctrine of unconstitutional vagueness, the
application of this doctrine being almost entirely confined to criminal cases.
See the extensive note, "The Void-for- Vagueness Doctrine in the Supreme
Court," 109 University of Pennsylvania Law Review 67-116 (1960).
63
THE MORALITY OF LAW
can sometimes be purified, but only at the cost of making it
something other than it was. Being at the top of the chain of
i command does not exempt the legislature from its responsibility
Ho respect the demands of the internal morality of law; indeed, it
"fair" or "reasonable":
64
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
vague formulas into legislation and jurisdiction, 22 and of
the increasing arbitrariness and uncertainty of, and the con-
sequent disrespect for, the law and the judicature. 23
65
THE MORALITY OF LAW
owner to install new license plates on January first; the other
makes it a crime to perform any labor on that date. Here there
seems to be a violation of the law of identity; an act cannot be
both forbidden and commanded same time. But is there
at the
66
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
are bound by promises under oath, and then by undoing its de-
cree, the court would remind the promisee of what his overreach-
ing had cost him.
Assuming that the court confronted with the New Year's Day
statute would see no value in convicting the defendant and then
remitting his fine, it might adopt one of two interpretations of
the statute: (1) that the section making work on New Year's Day
a crime overrides the provision concerning license plates, so that
the automobile owner may lawfully postpone installing his plates
until January second; or (2) that the provision concerning license
plates overrides the work prohibition, so that the owner must
install his plates on the first, but commits no crime in doing so.
A less obvious, but much better solution would be to combine
these interpretations, so that the owner who installs his plates on
the first violates no law, while the owner who postpones providing
his car with new plates until the second is equally within the law.
This solution would recognize that the basic problem presented °*
67
—
68
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
applied where contradictions arise within the frame of a single
statute, that is, by effecting a reciprocal adjustment between the
two statutes, interpreting each in the light of the other. This
solution would, however, involve its own difficulties. One would
be to know where to stop, for the courts might easily find them-
selvesembarked on the perilous adventure of attempting to re-
make the entire body of our statutory law into a more coherent
whole. The reinterpretation of old statutes in the light of new
would also present embarrassing problems of retrospective legis-
lation. I shall not attempt to pursue these issues. Enough has
been intimated, however, to convey one clear lesson: legislative
carelessness about the jibe of statutes with one another can be
very hurtful to legality and there is no simple rule by which to
undo the damage.
It has been suggested that instead of speaking of "contradic-
tions" in legal and moral argument we ought to speak of "in-
compatibilities," 28 —
of things that do not go together or do not go
together well. Another term, a great favorite in the history of the
common law, is useful here. This is the word "repugnant." It is
/ 69
THE MORALITY OF LAW
dictory simply because we assume there is no way open to him
to take the ground along with him in his leap. The context that
must be taken into account in determining the issue of incompati-
bility is, of course, not merely or even chiefly technological, for
it includes the whole institutional setting of the problem — legal,
moral, political, economic, and sociological. To test this asser-
tion one may suppose that the New Year's Day statute required
the installation of license plates, on that day, but in another sec-
an excise tax of one dollar on any person performing
tion levied
work on that day. It would be instructive to reflect how one
would go about demonstrating that these provisions are "repug-
nant" and that their inclusion in a single statute must have been
the result of legislative oversight.
29. The question may be raised at this point whether most of the other
desiderata that make up the internal morality of the law are not also ul-
timately concerned with the possibility of obedience. There is no question
that the matter may be viewed in this light. Just as it is impossible to obey
a law that requires one to become ten feet tall, so it is also impossible to
obey a law that cannot be known, that is unintelligible, that has not yet
been enacted, etc. But in justification for the separation effected in the text
it should be observed that my concern is not to engage in an exercise in
70
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
less unlimited power" by its very absurdity; its brutal pointless-
ness may let the subject know that there is. nothing that may not
be demanded of him and that he should keep himself ieady to
jump in any direction.
The technique of demanding the impossible is subject to more
subtle and sometimes even to beneficent exploitation. The good
teacher often demands of his pupils more than he thinks they
are capable of giving. He does this with the quite laudable motive
of stretching their capacities. Unfortunately in many human con-
texts the line can become blurred between vigorous exhortation
and imposed duty. The legislator is thus easily misled into be-
lieving his role is like that of the teacher. He forgets that the
teacher whose pupils fail what he asked of them can,
to achieve
without insincerity or self-contradiction, congratulate them on
what they did in fact accomplish. In a similar situation the
government official faces the alternative of doing serious injustice
or of diluting respect for law by himself winking at a departure
from its demands.
The principle that the law should not demand the impossible
of the subject may be pressed toward a quixotic extreme in which
it ends by demanding the impossible of the legislator. It is some-
71
THE MORALITY OF LAW
run the risk of imposing on him requirements he is incapable of
meeting, for his education and native capacities may not bring
this standard within his reach. Ifwe take the opposite course
and attempt to ask whether the man before us, with all his indi-
vidual limitations and quirks, fell short of what he ought to have
achieved, we enter upon a hazardous inquiry in which all capacity
for objective judgment may be lost. This inquiry requires a sym-
pathetic identification with the life of another. Obviously differ-
ences of class, race, religion, age, and culture may obstruct or
distort that identification. The result is that though an aloof
justice bound at times to be harsh, an intimate justice, seeking
is
punishing a man for doing an act which may on its face have
seemed quite innocent. From my own observation it is often
a question whether in this case the cure is not worse than the
disease. The required intent is so little susceptible of definite proof
or disproof that the trier of fact is almost inevitably driven to
asking, "Does he look like the kind who would stick by the rules
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
or one who would cheat on them when he saw a chance?" This
question, unfortunately, leads easily into another, "Does he look
like my kind?"3°
These, then, are the difficulties encountered when, in order
to keep the law within the citizen's capacity for obedience, his
liability is limited to cases where fault or wrongful intent can be
a wrongful act.
73
THE MORALITY OF LAW
pacity to comprehend the nature of their acts. Some of this law
explicitly assigned to quasi contracts; the rest of makes its
— —
is it
74
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
where legal liability arises without fault or intent. There exists,
75
THE MORALITY OF LAW
#
bear the cost of the injuries resulting from their operation is
^^ P art m * e
v
v\^
aw *
'
^^
\ \
we can be reasonably
c
I think sure that no such future lies
«
ahead of us. If strict liability were to attend, not certain specified
\\ f6hns of activity, but all activities, the conception of a causal
connection between the act and the resulting injury would be
,
^M&m?
only that the plaintiff's loss or injury should "arise out of" the
defendant's conduct. 1/ .hf
..IV. \rf
76
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
The account just given of the problem of strict civil liability
is by no means exhaustive. Some forms of such liability exist
77
THE MORALITY OF LAW
no mystery about the reason for their continued and perhaps
expanding appearance in modern legislation: they serve mightily
the convenience of the prosecutor. Their apparent injustice, he
is likely to assure us, is removed by "selective enforcement."
(ji Though theoretically such laws are a trap for the innocent, it is
only the real villains who are pursued in practice. As for them,
their being brought to justice is greatly facilitated because the
government in making out its case is relieved from having to
prove intent or fault, a particularly difficult task when compli-
cated regulatory measures are involved. When absolute liability
is coupled with drastic penalties — as it often is —the position of
the prosecutor is further improved. Usually he will not have to
take the case to trial at all; the threat of imprisonment or a heavy
fine is enough to induce a plea of guilty, or—where this is au-
thorized —a settlement out of court. Drastic penalties also en-
hance the public relations of the agencies of enforcement. The
innocent stumbler who knows that he could have been found
guilty is deeply grateful when he is let off and therefore saved
from being branded as a criminal. He promises in all sincerity to
be more intelligently cooperative in the future.
The conveniences of what has been called "jawbone enforce-
ment"— might be less charitably called "enforcement by black-
mail"—became widely known during
it
World
the hectic days of
War when overworked administrators of complex economic
II,
33. Hall, General Principles of Criminal Law (2d ed. 1960), Chapter X,
pp. 325-59; Hart, "The Aims of Criminal Law," 23 Law & Contemporary
Problems 401-41 (1958); The American Law Institute, Model Penal Code,
V Proposed Official Draft (1962), Sections 1.04(5), 2.01-2.13.
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
Before leaving the subject of laws commanding the impossible,
two further observations need to be made. One is simply and
obviously to the effect that no hard and fast line can be drawn
between extreme difficulty and impossibility. A rule that asks
somewhat too much can be harsh and unfair, but it need not
contradict the basic purpose of a legal order, as does a rule that
demands what is patently impossible. Between the two is an
indeterminate area in which the internal and external moralities
of law meet.
My final observation is that our notions of what is in fact im-
possible may be determined by presuppositions about the nature
of man and the universe, presuppositions that are subject to his-
torical change. Today opposition to laws purporting to compel
religious or political beliefs is rested on the ground that such
laws constitute an unwarranted interference with individual
liberty. Thomas Jefferson took a different view. In the original
draft of the Preamble to the Virginia Statute of Religious Free-
dom he condemned such laws as attempting to compel the im-
possible:
One may raise the question whether there is not in this con-
ception a profounder respect both for truth and for human powers
than there is in our own.
79
THE MORALITY OF LAW
changed more often than, say, once a year. Restrictions on retro-
active legislation, on the other hand, have been a favorite among
constitution makers. 85 Yet there is a close affinity between the
harms done by retrospective legislation and those resulting from
too frequent changes in the law. Both follow from what may be
called legislative inconstancy. It is interesting to note that Madi-
son, when he sought to defend the provisions in the Constitution
prohibiting ex post facto laws and laws impairing the obligation
of contract, used language more apt for describing the evil of
frequent change than that resulting from retroactive laws:
80
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
still remains for the commencement of an action before the
bar takes effect. 37
37. Ochoa v. Hernandez y Morales, 230 U.S. !39, at pp. 161-^2 (1913). X?
*>\\Un
—
THE MORALITY OF LAW
relatively ineffective in controlling lawless conduct by the police,
this evil being in fact compounded by the tendency of lower
courts to identify their mission with that of maintaining the
morale of the police force. For an effective control of police law-
lessness much can be said for some overseeing agency, like the
Scandinavian ombudsman, capable of acting promptly and flexi-
bly on informal complaints.
is judge-made it may be said that,
In those areas where the law
though the essential congruence between law and official action
can be impaired by lower courts, it cannot be impaired by the
supreme court since it makes the law. The supreme court of a
jurisdiction, it may seem, cannot be out of step since it calls the
tune. But the tune called may be quite undanceable by anyone,
including the tune-caller. All of the influences that can produce
a lack of congruence between judicial action and statutory law
can, when the itself makes the law, produce equally damag-
court
ing departures from other principles of legality: a failure to articu-
late reasonably clear general rules and an inconstancy in decision
manifesting itself in contradictory rulings, frequent changes of
direction, and retrospective changes in the law.
The most subtle element in the task of maintaining congruence
between law and official action lies, of course, in the problem of
interpretation. Legality requires that judges and other officials
apply statutory law, not according to their fancy or with crabbed
literalness, but in accordance with principles of interpretation
that are appropriate to their position in the whole legal order.
What are those principles? The best short answer I know dates
back to 1584 when the Barons of the Exchequer met to consider
- a difficult problem of interpretation in Hey don's Case:
And it was resolved by them, that for the sure and true
interpretation of all statutes in general (be they penal or
beneficial, restrictive or enlarging of the common law,) four
things are to be discerned and considered:
1st. What was the common law before the making of the
r
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
2nd. What was the mischief and defect for which the
common law did not provide.
3rd. What remedy the Parliament hath resolved and ap-
pointed to cure the disease of the commonwealth.
And, 4th. The true reason of the remedy; and then the
office of all the Judges is always to make such construction
as shall suppress the mischief, and advance the remedy. 38
38. 3 Co. Rep. 7a. It is apparent that in the passage quoted the word
"mischief" used in a sense no longer current. As used in Heydon's Case
is
it was in fact a close cousin to two other words that were then great favor-
83
THE MORALITY OF LAW
arise when the Legislature has had no meaning at all; when
the question which is raised on the statute never occurred
to it . . . [In such cases] when the judges are professing to
declare what the Legislature meant, they are in truth, them-
selves legislating to fill up casus omissi.™
39. The Nature and Sources of the Law (2d ed. 1921), pp. 172-73.
40. The "atomistic" view of intention described in the text is related to,
and may be regarded as an expression of, philosophic nominalism. I have
dealt with the influence of this view on the movement known as legal
realism in my article, "American Legal Realism," 82 University of Pennsyl-
vania Law Review 429, 443-47 (1934).
84
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
of useful household devices dies leaving the pencil sketch of an
invention on which he was working at the time of his death. On
his deathbed he requests his son to continue work on the inven-
tion, though he dies without having had a chance to tell the son
what purpose the invention was to serve or anything about his
own plans for completing it. In carrying out his father's wish the
son's first would be to decide what the purpose of the pro-
step
jected invention was, what defect or insufficiency of existing de-
vices it was intended to remedy. He would then try to grasp the
underlying principle of the projected invention, the "true reason
of theremedy" in the language of Heydon's Case. With these
problems solved he would then proceed to work out what was
essential to complete the design for the projected device.
Let us now ask of the son's action questions of the sort com-
monly asked concerning the interpretation of statutes. Was the
son faithful to his father's intention? If we mean, "Did he carry
out an intention the father had actually formed concerning the
manner of completing the design?" why, of course, the question
is quite unanswerable forwe do not know whether the father had
any such intention, and if so, what it was. If we mean, "Did he
remain within the framework set by the father, accepting the
father's conception of a need for the projected device and his
father's general approach to the problem of supplying that need?"
then the answer, on the facts supposed, is yes. If the son were
able to call on his father's spirit for help, the chances are that
this help would take the form of collaborating with the son in
the solution of a problem the father had left unsolved. So it is
usually with difficult problems of interpretation. If the draftsman
of a statute were called into direct consultation, he would normal-
ly have to proceed in the same manner as the judge by asking
such questions as the following: Does this case fall within the
mischief which the statute sought to remedy? Does it fall within
the "true reason of theremedy" appointed by the statute, that is,
is remedy apt for dealing with this particular
the prescribed
manifestation of the general mischief at which the statute was
aimed?
85
THE MORALITY OF LAW
The analogy of the incomplete invention may also be helpful
in clarifying an obscurity that runs through the vocabulary of
interpretation. We tend to think of intention as a phenomenon of
individual psychology, though what we are interpreting is a cor-
porate act. Thus we ask after the intention of "the legislator,"
though we know there no such being. At other times we speak
is
86
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
the son's task. So in speaking of legislative intention I think it
87
THE MORALITY OF LAW
mischief sought to be remedied by a statute can be tolerated. But
if this obscurity exceeds a certain crucial point, then no virtuos-
ity in draftsmanship nor skill in interpretation can make a mean-
ingful thing of a statute afflicted with it. Again, some looseness
of thought about the connection between the remedy and the
defect it is appointed to cure does not inevitably vitiate a statute.
But if this connection is fundamentally misconceived, then all
88
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
trust to the memory of witnesses for a longer time than one
year."-**
Difficulty arose because the draftsmen had simply not thought
through the relation between the mischief and the remedy they
appointed to cure it. In the first place it is clear that there is no
direct relation between the time when a witness will be called
to testify and the time required to perform the contract; a con-
tract might be scheduled for completion within one month and
yet first come into proof in court two years later. Furthermore,
the draftsmen failed to ask themselves what the courts should
do with the very common case of contracts as to which it is im-
possible to say in advance how much time their performance
will require, such as contracts to employ a man for life or to pay
a monthly sum to him until he is cured of an illness. By imagining
unexpected events that accelerate or postpone performance this
class of contracts can be greatly expanded. In a case coming up
for decision shortly after the Statutewas passed it was suggested
that the validity of the contract should depend on the actual
course of events. 44 If it turned out that performance came due
within a year, the oral contract was valid; if not, then the con-
tract was unenforceable. But this solution was never accepted
and could not be. Parties need to know from the outset, or at
least as soon as trouble develops, whether or not they have a
contract. To make the existence of a binding contract depend
upon later events would invite all kinds of jockeying for position
and produce the greatest imaginable confusion. In short, the
courts were confronted with a statute which simply could not be
applied in a way to carry out the loosely conceived intention of
its draftsmen. The British finally found in 1954 the only cure for
89
—
THE MORALITY OF LAW
in any clear terms just what mischief it was intended to cure.
With the repeal of prohibition Americans highly resolved "to
prevent the return of the old saloon." What did this mean? The
old saloon was a complex thing, combining architectural, atmo-
spheric, artistic, commercial, legal, and sociological aspects. It
was highly improbable that it would, or even could, return in
its old form after an absence of fifteen years during which funda-
buy food before he could be served a drink. Let the legal require-
ment be, then, that the new saloon be prepared to serve food to
any who may order it, however few they may be among its
patrons.
The primary responsibility for administering this allopathic
concoction of rules was of course vested, not with the prosecutor,
but with the licensing authority.Can anyone imagine deriving
any sense of useful social function from serving on such an
authority? Is it any wonder that this area of regulation is no-
torious for inefficiencyand corruption? Even if a conscientious
bureaucrat could be found who would consider his life filled with
mission if he were simply allowed to enforce rules, however
senseless, the problem would still not be solved. There would re-
main insoluble problems of interpretation, in deciding, for ex-
90
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
ample, what constitutes being adequately prepared to serve a
meal to a diner who never comes.
At this point our discussion of the problem of interpretation
must be broken off. It is too richly textured a subject to be ex-
hausted by any one analogy or metaphor. Its demands depend so
much on context that illustrative cases can serve only to disclose
general principles, but cannot convey the nuances that attend
the application of those principles to particular branches of the
law. With all its subtleties, the problem of interpretation occupies
a sensitive, central position in the internal morality of the law.
It reveals, as no other problem can, the cooperative nature of
91
THE MORALITY OF LAW
secret. Such a case might arise where a legislative appropriation
was made to finance research into some new military weapon.
It is always unfortunate when any act of government must be
concealed from the public and thus shielded from public criticism.
But there are times when we must bow to grim necessity. The
Constitution itself in Article V provides that each "house shall
keep a journal of its proceedings, and from time to time publish
the same, excepting such parts as may in their judgment require
secrecy." All of this has very relevance, however, to the
little
laws that are the subject under discussion. 45 I can conceive, for
example, of no emergency that would justify withholding from
the public knowledge of a law creating a new crime or changing
the requirements for making a valid will.
Secondly, infringements of legal morality tend to become
cumulative. A neglect of clarity, consistency, or publicity may
beget the necessity for retroactive laws. Too frequent changes
in the law may nullify the benefits of formal, but slow-moving
procedures for making the law known. Carelessness about keep-
ing the laws possible of obedience may engender the need for a
discretionary enforcement which in turn impairs the congruence
between official action and enacted rule.
Thirdly, to the extent that the law merely brings to explicit
92
THE MORALITY THAT MAKES LAW POSSIBLE
parties to do directly what they had previously been compelled
to achieve by indirection.
Fourthly, the stringency with which the eight desiderata as a
whole should be applied, as well as their priority of ranking among
themselves, will be affected by the branch of law in question, as
well as by the kinds of legal rules that are under consideration.
Thus, it is generally more important that a man have a clear
warning of his legal duties than that he should know precisely
what unpleasantness will attend a breach; a retroactive statute
creating a new crime is thoroughly objectionable, a similar statute
lengthening the term of imprisonment for an existing crime is
less so. A familiar distinction between rules of law is that which
distinguishes rules imposing duties from rules conferring legal
capacities. Both sorts of rules are affected in some measure by
all eight of the demands of legal morality. At the same time, rules
granting and defining legal powers seldom have any counterpart
in the practices of everyday life —shaking hands on a deal has
never been accepted as an adequate legal formality. Hence as
to rules defining legal powers the requirements of publicity and
clarity are apt to be especially demanding. Contrariwise, con-
ferring retroactive validity on what was under existing law a
vain attempt to exercise a legal power will often be seen as ad-
vancing the cause of legality by preventing a confusion of legal
rights.
93
THE MORALITY OF LAW
difficult may be illumined by a figure from Aristotle. In his
Ethics Aristotle raises the question whether it is easy to deal
justly with others. He observes that it might seem that it would
be, for there are certain established rules of just dealing that can
be learned without difficulty. The application of a simple rule
ought itself to be simple. But this is not so, Aristotle says, in-
voking at this point a favorite analogy, that of medicine: "It is
94
•v
THE CONCEPT
III
OF LAW
As ideas of what law is for are so largely implicit in ideas of what law is,
a brief survey of ideas of the nature of law will be useful.
. . . Roscoe —
Pound
Das Vergessen der Absichten ist die hdufigste Dummheit, die gemacht
wird. —Friedrich Nietzsche
95
THE MORALITY OF LAW
trenched in the vocabulary and thought of one's subject is an
essential part of exposition.
Though these natural laws touch one of the most vital of hu-
man activities they obviously do not exhaust the whole of man's
moral life. They have nothing
to say on such topics as polygamy,
the study of Marx, the worship of God, the progressive income
tax, or the subjugation of women. If the question be raised
whether any of these subjects, or others like them, should be
taken as objects of legislation, that question relates to what I have
called the external morality of law.
As a convenient (though not wholly satisfactory) way of de-
scribing the distinction being taken we may speak of a pro-
cedural, as distinguished from a substantive natural law. What
I have called the internal morality of law is in this sense a pro-
cedural version of natural law, though to avoid misunderstanding
96
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
theword "procedural" should be assigned a special and expanded
sense so thatit would include, for example, a substantive accord
2. See note
3. ibid.
6,
T
Chapter 2, p. 49.
re
"Es kann somit bloss ein Rechtsinhaltsprinzip sein, das die riick-
4.
wirkende Kraft von Rechtsnormen ausschliesst, nicht ein Voraussetzungs- >
prinzip." Juristische Grundlehre (2d ed. 1927), p. 302. See'alSO note 13,
Chapter 2, supra p. 52. \ .
97
THE MORALITY OF LAW
With respect to thinkers associated with the natural law tradi-
tion it is none of them would display the casual-
safe to say that
ness of a Gray or Somlo toward the demands of legal morality.
On the other hand, their chief concern is with what I have called
substantive natural law, with the proper ends to be sought through
legal rules. When they treat of the demands of legal morality it
not far to seek. Men do not generally see any need to explain
or to justify the obvious. It is likely that nearly every legal phi-
losopher of any consequence in the history of ideas has had oc-
casion to declare that laws ought to be published so that those
subject to them can know what they are. Few have felt called
upon expand the argument for this proposition or to bring
to
it within the cover of any more inclusive theory.
6. Ibid., Art. 3.
98
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
Yet, as I have tried to show, in some situations the principle
against contradiction can become one of the most difficult to
apply of those which make up the internal morality of the law. 7
To the generalization that in the history of political and legal
thought the principles of legality have received a casual and
incidental treatment —such as befits the self-evident — there is
99
THE MORALITY OF LAW
In the course of Coke's judgment upholding Bonham's cause,
this famous passage appears:
100
—
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
judgment of his own case. Then came the King and Parliament
sticking an ugly, incongruous finger into this effort, creating a
"court" of physicians for judging infringements of their own
monopoly and collecting half the fines for themselves. When
Coke associated this legislative indecency with repugnancy he
was not simply expressing his distaste for it; he meant that it
contradicted essential purposive efforts moving in an opposite
direction.
The view, common among modern scholars, that in the quoted
passage Coke betrays a naive faith in natural law, tells us little
101
THE MORALITY OF LAW
this rule being derived not "from any positive law, but from the
nature and reason of the thing." 11
A continuing debate in this country relates to the question
whether in interpreting the Constitution the courts should be
influenced by considerations drawn from "natural law." 12 I sug-
gest that this debate might contribute more to a clarification of
issues if a distinction were taken between a natural law of sub-
stantive ends and a natural law concerned with procedures and
should be confessed, however, that the term "nat-
institutions. It
ural law" has been so misused on all sides that it is difficult to
recapture a dispassionate attitude toward it.
What is perfectly clear is that many of the provisions of the
Constitution have the quality have described as that of being
I
102
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
description of the act it prohibits. 14 When one reflects on the
problems of drafting a constitution the justification for this hold-
ing becomes obvious. If an express provision directed against
vague laws were included in the Constitution, some standard,
explicit or tacit, would have to determine what degree of ob-
scurity should vitiate. This standard would have to run in quite
general terms. Starting with the premise that law governs and
judges men's actions by general rules, any criminal statute ought
to be sufficiently clear to serve the double purpose of giving to
the citizen an adequate warning of the nature of the act pro-
hibited and of providing adequate guidelines for adjudication in
accordance with law. If one wished to summarize all this in a
becomes plain that the same objection that applies to laws re-
ducing the obligations of existing contracts may equally apply
to laws enlarging those obligations. In assuming the risks in-
herent in a contractual engagement, a man may properly take
into account what the existing law prescribes as his obligation in
case of default. If that law is then radically changed to his dis-
favor, the legislature has broken faith with him.
In these last remarks I may seem to be assigning contradictory
103
THE MORALITY OF LAW
qualities to the internal morality of the law. I have suggested that
this morality lends itself awkwardly to formulation in a written
constitution. I have at the same time asserted that in dealing
with questions touching the internal morality of the law judicial
interpretation can proceed with an unusual degree of confidence
in its objectivity, and this despite the fragmentary and inadequate
constitutional expressions on which it must build. How can a
task so difficult for the draftsman that he must leave his job
half-done be thought to provide relatively firm guidelines for
judicial interpretation?
^
The answer to this question has, I think, already been given,
thoughin somewhat unfamiliar terms. I have described the in-
ternal morality of law as being chiefly a morality of aspiration,
rather than of duty. 16 Though this morality may be viewed as
made up of separate —
demands or "desiderata" I have discerned
eight —these do not lend themselves to anything like separate and
categorical statement. 17 All of them are means toward a single
end, and under varying circumstances the optimum marshalling
of these means may change. Thus an inadvertent departure from
one desideratum may require a compensating departure from
another; this is the case where a failure to give adequate publicity
to a new requirement of form may demand for its cure a retro-
spective statute. 18 At other times, a neglect of one desideratum
may throw an added burden on another; thus, where laws change
frequently, the requirement of publicity becomes increasingly
stringent. In other words, under varying circumstances the ele-
ments of legality must be combined and recombined in accord-
ance with something like an economic calculation that will suit
them to the instant case.
These considerations seem to me to lead to the conclusion that
it is within the constitutional area I have designated as that of the
104
—
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
reasonably open to it, the court ought to remain within this area.
and unusual one had to take into account the nature of the of-
fense for which it was imposed. Thus the Court needlessly took
on its shoulders a general responsibility — surely oppressive, even
if it has been described as sublime — for making the punishment
fit the crime.
This excursion into substantive justice was, I submit, quite
unnecessary. We
have an express constitutional prohibition of
ex post facto criminal laws, and a well-established rule of con-
stitutional law that a statutory definition of crime must meet
certain minimum
standards of clarity. Both of these restraints
on freedom proceed on the assumption that the crimi-
legislative
nal law ought to be presented to the citizen in such a form that he
can mold his conduct by it, that he can, in short, obe.y it. Being
innocently in a state or condition of drug addiction cannot be
construed as an act, and certainly not as an act of disobedience.
Bringing the decision in Robinson v. California within the tra-
ditional confines of due process would certainly have presented
no greater difficulty than would be presented by a case, say,
where a criminal statute was kept secret by the legislature until
105
THE MORALITY OF LAW
an indictment was brought under it. (It should be recalled that
our Constitution has no express requirement that laws be pub-
lished.)
Our next task is to bring the view of law implicit in these chapters
into proper relation with current definitions of positive law.
its
in fact, we must ask what they are trying to do. We must indeed
go further and participate vicariously in the whole purposive ef-
20. "The Path of the Law," 10 Harvard Law Review 457-78, at p. 461
(1897).
106
.
hauled into court for things we don't mean to cover at all. But
how long must I go on rewriting it?"
107
THE MORALITY OF LAW
Most theories of law either explicitly assert, or tacitly assume,
\\
that a distinguishingmark of law consists in the use of coercion
or force. That distinguishing mark is not recognized in this
volume. In this respect the concept of law I have defended con-
tradicts the following definition, proposed by an anthropologist
seeking to identify the distinctive "legal" element among the
various forms of social order that make up a primitive society:
J
*?
108
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
law with force. It is precisely when the legal system itself takes
up weapons of violence that we impose on it the most stringent
requirements of due process. In civilized nations it is in criminal 1
u
cases that we are most exigent in the demand for guarantees that
the law remain faithful to itself. Thus, that branch of law most
closely identified with force is which we associate most
also that
closely with formality, ritual, and solemn due process. This
identification has a particular relevance to primitive society, where
the first steps toward a legal order are likely to be directed
toward preventing or healing outbreaks of private violence.
These considerations explain, but do not justify, the modern
tendency to see physical force as the identifying mark of law.
Let us test this identification with a hypothetical case. A nation
admits foreign traders within its borders only on condition that
they deposit a substantial sum of money in the national bank
guaranteeing their observance of a body of law specially ap-
plicable to their activities. This body of law is administered with
integrity and, in case of dispute, is interpreted and applied by
special courts. If an infraction is established the state pursuant
to court order levies a fine in the form of a deduction from the
trader's deposit. No force, but a mere bookkeeping operation, is
required to accomplish this deduction; no force is available to
the trader that could preventit. Surely ITwouTd be perverse to
robed judges were a mere facade for what was in fact a lawless
act of confiscation.
The considerations implicit in this illustration relieve us, I
109
THE MORALITY OF LAW
achieve some minimum efficacy in practical affairs, whatever the
basis of that efficacy — a proposition both unobjectionable and
quite unexciting.
In most theories of law the element of force is closely associ-
ated with the notion of a formal hierarchy of command or au-
thority. In the passage quoted from Hoebel this association was
absent because, as an anthropologist, Hoebel was concerned with
primitive law, where any clearly defined hierarchic ordering of
authority is generally lacking. Since the emergence of the na-
tional state,however, a long line of legal philosophers running
from Hobbes through Austin to Kelsen and Somlo have seen the
essence of law in a pyramidal structure of state power. This view
abstracts from the purposive activity necessary to create and
maintain a system of legal rules, contenting itself with a descrip-
tion of the institutional framework within which this activity is
110
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
less vague and, I believe, jusier answer would be to say that it
expresses a concern with the problem of resolving conflicts within
the legal system. Indeed, one may say that it converts one princi-
ple of the internal morality of law — that condemning contradic-
tory laws — into an absolute to the neglect of all others. With
24. See Kelsen, General Theory of Law and State (1945), pp. 401-04 and
index entry "Non-contradiction, principle of"; Somlo, Juristische Grund-
lehre (2d ed. 1927), index entry "Widerspriiche des Rechts."
Ill
THE MORALITY OF LAW
impossible to assert both 'A ought to be' and 'A ought not to
"
be' 25 —
a proposition certainly not likely to help a judge strug-
gling with a statute that inone section seems to say Mr. A ought
to pay a tax and in another that heis exempt from it. Nor would
112
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
formal provision is made in anticipation of this possibility; when
the parties cannot agree on an arbitrator the American Arbitra-
tion Association may, for example, be authorized to nominate
him. But such a provision is neither indispensable to success, nor
28. Pashukanis, The General Theory of Law and Marxism (1927), trans.
Babb in Soviet Legal Philosophy, 20th Century Legal Philosophy Series, 5
(1951), 11 1-225, at p. 154.
113
THE MORALITY OF LAW
Parliamentary sovereignty can, of course, be supported entirely
by an argument of political prudence to the effect that it is always
desirable to have a reserve of lawmaking power ready to meet
unforeseen circumstances. Explicit limitations on the power of the
legislature that seem wise and beneficial when adopted may later
serve to block measures necessary to deal with drastically changed
conditions. If the pressure of circumstance mounts too high, the
restraint may be circumvented by dodges and fictions that them-
selves carry a high cost in the distortions they introduce into the
moral atmosphere of government and even into its institutional
structure. These points can be illustrated hypothetically by a
reference to the most stringent restraint contained in our own
Constitution. This is the provision that no state shall, without
its consent, "be deprived of its equal suffrage in the Senate." 29
This is the only constitutional restraint now operative that is re-
moved even from the effect of change by amendment of the Con-
stitution itself.
Now it is possible that there might occur —perhaps as the
result of some natural disaster — a radical reduction in the popula-
one third of the
tion of certain of the states, so that, let us say,
states would contain a population of only about one thousand
persons each. In such a situation equal representation in the
Senate might become a political absurdity. If the right to equal
representation is respected, the whole political life of the nation
might be mortally crippled. In such a situation the possibility of
some legal maneuver comes naturally to mind. Could we perhaps
use the amending power to reduce the role of the Senate to some-
thing like that of the House of Lords? Or abolish the Senate in
favor of a unicameral assembly? Or is public opinion sufficiently
behind us to make it enough simply to rename the Senate "The
Council of Elders" and then reallocate representation in it?
29. Art. V.
114
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
principle presents. Parliamentary sovereignty means, in effect,
that the parliament stands above the law in the sense that it can
change any law that is not to its liking. But, paradoxically, it a£
gains this position of being above the law only by subjecting it-
self to law —
the law of its own internal procedure.^or a corpo-
rate body to pass laws it must conform to laws that will determine
when a law has been passed. This body of laws is itself subject
to all the kinds of shipwreck that can visit any other legal system
— it can be too vague or contradictory to give sure guidance,
and, above all, its standards can be so disregarded in practice as
30. Dicey, The Law of the Constitution (10th ed., 1960), Intro., xl.
115
THE MORALITY OF LAW
he asserts that certain laws passed by Parliament constitute "the
highest exertion and crowning proof of sovereign power." 31
What are the enactments that possess these extraordinary
qualities? In Dicey's own words they are "Acts such as those
which declare valid marriages which, owing to some mistake of
form or otherwise, have not been properly celebrated," and
statutes "the object of which is to make legal transactions which
when they took place were illegal, or to free individuals to whom
the statute applies from having broken the law." 32
liability for
116
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
The tradition in discussing Parliament's legal omnipotence is
other laws of whatever kind were repealed; and (4) that the
Parliament be permanently dissolved. Surely it is difficult to imag-
ine any solicitor advising his client, after consulting Dicey, that
"as a matter of strict law" the rampaging and ravishing M.P.s
were within their legal rights and that the would have to
client
face for himself the moral issue whether to violate the law by
lifting his hand against them. At some point we take leave of the
gravitational field within which the distinction between law and
not-law makes sense. I suggest that that point is reached far
short of the situation I have described, and is indeed reached
when we begin to ask whether parliamentary suicide is possible,
or whether Parliament can formally assign all its powers to a
dictator, or whether Parliament can decide that all future laws
117
THE MORALITY OF LAW
ing its ends. In contrast, the theories I have rejected seem to me
to play about the fringe of that activity without ever concerning
themselves directly with its problems. Thus, law is defined as
"the existence of public order" without asking what kind of order
K' is meant or how it is brought about. Again, the distinguishing
mark of law lie in a means, namely "force," that is
is said to
typically employed to effectuate its aims. There is no recognition
that, except as it makes the stakes higher, the use or nonuse of
force leaves unchanged the essential problems of those who make
and administer the laws. Finally, there are theories that concen-
trate on the hierarchic structure that is commonly thought to
organize and direct the activity I have called law, though again
without recognizing that this structure is itself a product of the
activity it is thought to put in order.
At this point I am sure there will be those who, though agreeing
118
.
119
THE MORALITY OF LAW
Now it cannot be said that any of these views is false. It is
simply that none of them would start the lay citizen on his way
toward any real understanding of science and its problems. Nor
would they serve the scientist usefully who wanted to clarify for
himself the aims of science and the institutional arrangements
that would promote those aims.
Recently there has been a movement of reform in scientific
education, particularly in the teaching of general courses in sci-
ence intended for those who do not expect to become scientists.
120
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
the demands it has to meet, be a morality of aspiration, not of
duty. A single example will suffice, I think, to make clear why
this must be so.
A scientist believes that he has made a fundamental discovery
of the sort that may touch upon and advance the researches of
others. When should he publish? It is clear that if he has in fact
made an important discovery, he must make it known to the
scientific community even though, for example, he can foresee
that a rival scientist, building on it, may perhaps be enabled to
make a further discovery overshadowing his own. On the other
hand, he must be sure that he has in fact made the discovery he
believes he has, for by rushing into print he may waste the time
of others by giving a false lead to their researches.
It is questions of this sort that Polanyi has in mind when, bor-
121
THE MORALITY OF LAW
must remain unanswered in any philosophy of law that abstracts
from the nature of the activity we call law.
122
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
something like this: "Why, yes, their achievements in this field
are very fine," or "Well, yes, but only in a very rudimentary way."
So would be with science, literature, chess, obstetrics, conversa-
it
tion, and the mortuary art. Disputes might arise, to be sure, about
the proper standards for judging achievement, and of course,
any attempt at quantitative appraisal (such as "half-success)
would have to be considered as metaphorical. Nevertheless the
normal expectation would be of some performance falling be-
tween zero and a theoretical perfection.
Only with law is it different. It is truly astounding to what an
extent there runs through modern thinking in legal philosophy
the assumption that law is like a piece of inert matter — it is there
or not there. It is only such an assumption that could lead legal
scholars to assume, for example, that the "laws" enacted by the
Nazis in their closing years, considered as laws and in abstrac-
tion from their evil aims, were just as much laws as those of Eng-
land and Switzerland. An even more grotesque outcropping of
this assumption is the notion that the moral obligation of the
decent German citizen to obey these laws was in no way affected
by the fact that they were in part kept from his knowledge, that
some of them retroactively "cured" wholesale murder, that they
contained wide delegations of administrative discretion to redefine
the crimes they proscribed, and that, in any event, their actual
terms were largely disregarded when
suited the convenience of
it
123
THE MORALITY OF LAW
another regulating commercial relations and still a third govern-
ing what is left over, all three systems being separately adminis-
tered by special courts.
Multiple systems may give rise to difficulties both for theory
and for practice. Difficulties of the first sort can arise only if
theory has committed itself to the view that the concept of law
requires a neatly defined hierarchy of authority with a supreme
power at the top that is itself free from legal restraints.
legislative
One way of accommodating this theory to the facts of political
life is to say that although there may appear to be three systems,
A, B and C, actually B and C exist only by the legal tolerance
of A. Carrying this a step further it may be asserted that what
thesupreme legal power permits it impliedly commands, so that
what appears as three systems is actually one "in contempla- —
tion of law."
Practical difficulties can arise when there is a real rub between
systems because their boundaries of competence have not been
and perhaps cannot be clearly defined. One solution of this prob-
lem as it affects the division of competence between nation and
system is to subject disputes to judicial decision
state in a federal
under the terms of a written constitution. This device is useful,
but not in all cases indispensable. Historically dual and triple
systems have functioned without serious friction, and when con-
flicthas arisen it has often been solved by some kind of voluntary
accommodation. This happened in England when the common
law courts began to absorb into their own system many of the
rules developed by the courts of the law merchant, though the
end of this development was that the merchants' courts were
finally supplanted by those of the common law.
A possible third criticism points to the same basic objection as
the second, but sees it this time magnified many times over. If
law is considered as "the enterprise of subjecting human conduct
to the governance of rules," then this enterprise is being con-
ducted, not on two or three fronts, but on thousands. Engaged
in this enterprise are those who draft and administer rules gov-
124
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
erning the internal affairs of clubs, churches, schools, labor
unions, trade associations, agricultural fairs, and a hundred and
one other forms of human association. If, therefore, we are pre-
pared to apply with consistency the conception of law advanced
in these chapters, it must follow that there are in this country
125
THE MORALITY OF LAW
There abundant authority that the courts may and should take
is
126
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
intuitively realize that in cases like that I have been discussing
we are confronted with delicate issues of maintaining a proper
balance of institutional function within our society. That such
issues are at stake becomes apparent if the case brought for
judicial determination involves a student expelled from a school
run by a religious order because of heresy or from a private mili-
tary academy because "he is constitutionally incapable of accept-
ing military discipline in the proper spirit." When issues as deli-
cate as those here suggested are under consideration we hesitate
to throw into the balance a word as heavily loaded with implica-
tions of sheer power and established authority as is the word
"law."
One may approve the motives that prompt this restraint. I
127
THE MORALITY OF LAW
comings we should recall that the school expulsion cases con-
stitute only a small sampling drawn from a vast body of prece-
dent dealing with similar problems as they arise in labor unions,
churches, social clubs, and a whole host of other institutional
forms. As a device for dealing with this wide range of problems
the concept of contract defaults in several important respects.
For one thing, it points to remedies that are inappropriate to the
context. For another, it suggests that if the institution or associa-
tion sees fit to do so, it may contractually stipulate for an un-
restricted privilege of canceling membership. Most fundamental-
ly, the contract theory is inconsistent with the responsibility ac-
tually assumed by the courts in these cases. It is easy to say,
for example, that the parietal rules constitute a contract between
the college and the student, but how are we to explain the defer-
ence accorded by the courts to the interpretation put on those
rules by the college authorities in the process of applying them
to an alleged infraction? When what a con-
parties quarrel about
tract means we do not ordinarily defer to the interpretation made
by either of them but judge between the two impartially. These
difficulties, and others I have left unmentioned, can be cured by
128
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
grown up outside our written constitutions should not be a source
of concern. It would have been impossible for the draftsmen of
our first written constitutions to have anticipated the rich insti-
tutional growth that has occurred since their time. Furthermore,
the intellectual climate of the late eighteenth century was such
as to obscure a recognition of the centers of authority created
when men form voluntary associations. 44 In the light of these
considerations we should be no more disturbed to find that we
have a body of unwritten constitutional law than the British have
been to discover that since the Statute of Westminster of 1931
they have acquired the rudiments of a written constitution living
comfortably in the midst of their unwritten constitution.
A view that seeks to understand law in terms of the activity
that sustains it, instead of considering only the formal sources of
129
THE MORALITY OF LAW
I come now to the fourth —and so far as my own account can
go — final criticism that may be made of the view of law taken
here. This is that it does not sufficiently distinguish between law
130
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
one to serve as judge. Nothing, it seems to me, hinges upon the
particular manner in which the members of the society, or some
of them, are plunged into what I have called the "enterprise" of
law.
Though can be said that law and morality share certain
—
it
131
THE MORALITY OF LAW
tion, gambling, or the requisition of private property for public
use.
But the very same considerations that require an attitude of
neutrality with regard to the external aims of the law demand a
commitment by the judge to the law's internal morality. It would,
for example, be an abdication of the responsibilities of his office
if the judge were to take a neutral stand between an interpreta-
132
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
quite inconclusive on both sides, resting as it does on initial as-
133
THE MORALITY OF LAW
book and its chief contribution. In developing this concept Hart
begins with a distinction between rules imposing duties and rules
conferring legal powers. So far there can be no complaint. The
distinction is a familiar one, especially in this country where it
134
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
the beneficiary now has a legal duty to reimburse the trustee.
The fundamental principle is, however, the same in both cases,
135
THE MORALITY OF LAW
the power to create binding contracts orally; after the Statute was
enacted this power, as to certain kinds of contracts, was removed.
So runs an argument based on the Hohfeldian analysis. 51
This argument seems quite convincing until we reflect that in
cases like that of the machine the courts start with the assump-
tion that A ought to stop work, for by continuing he squanders
his and society's resources on something that no longer serves
any need. This is what the courts mean by saying A has a duty
to mitigate. There is no occasion for B to sue for a breach of this
duty; since he doesn't have to pay for the work done after his
repudiation, he is not personally injured by A's continued per-
formance. The Statute of Frauds, on the other hand, does not
say that men ought to put their contracts in writing; it simply
says that if certain contracts are left in oral form they will not be
legally enforced. Contracting parties, familiar with the terms of
the Statute, may in fact deliberately refrain from executing a
written memorandum so as to preserve for their contract the
status of a "gentlemen's agreement."
In the cases of the machine and the Statute, what has been
called "the sanction of nullity" is employed to effectuate quite
different ends. In the one case it is used to make A do what he
ought to do, by cutting off his pay, as it were; in the other, it is
136
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
tempts to put the Hohfeldian analysis to practical account. 52
On the other hand, if one attempts always to penetrate behind
legal forms to underlying intent, the distinction loses much of its
"a most powerful tool for the analysis of much that has puzzled
both the jurist and the political theorist." (The Concept of Law,
p. 95.)
These doubts approach something like a certitude when it
comes to Hart's "rule of recognition." Let me express what I
understand this rule to mean by the aid of an illustration of per-
haps grotesque simplicity. A small country is ruled by King Rex.
Within this country there is unanimous agreement that the high-
est legal power rests in Rex. To make this abundantly clear we
may suppose that every adult citizen signs, with cheerful sincerity,
a statement reading, "I recognize in Rex the sole and ultimate
source of law in my country."
Now it is is in his kingdom an accepted
apparent that there
rule according to which Rex has the final say as to what shall
be considered law. Hart proposes to call this "the rule of recogni-
tion." Certainly there can be no quarrel with this proposal. But
Hart goes further and insists that we apply to this rule the distinc-
tion between rules that confer powers and those that impose
duties. The rule of recognition, he declares, must be regarded as a
power-conferring rule. Again, this seems almost a truism.
But Hart seems to read into this characterization the further
notion that the rule cannot contain any express or tacit pro-
vision to the effect that the authority it confers can be withdrawn
for abuses of it. To one concerned to discourage tendencies
137
THE MORALITY OF LAW
toward anarchy something can be said for this and Hobbes in
fact had a great deal to say for it. But Hart seems to consider
that he is dealing with a necessity of logical thinking. If one is
intent on preserving a sharp distinction between rules imposing
duties and rules conferring powers, there are reasons for being
unhappy about any suggestion that it may be possible to with-
draw the lawmaking authority once it has been conferred by the
rule of recognition. If Rex began to keep his laws secret from
those legally bound to obey them, and had his crown taken away
from him for doing so, it would certainly seem foolish to ask
whether he was deposed because he violated an implied duty or
because, by exceeding the tacit limits of his power, he had worked
an automatic forfeiture of his office and thus became subject to
"the sanction of nullity." In other words, a rule that confers a
power and provides, expressly or by implication, that this power
may be revoked
*
for abuses, presents in its proviso a stipulation
that straddles ambiguously the distinction between duty-imposing
rules and those that grant powers.
It follows then thatif Hart is to preserve his key distinction he
138
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
cerned with that question as she would with the one Wittgenstein
himself raises: Can she truthfully say, "I did not mean that kind
of game," when she never thought of the possibility of such a
game being taught to her children? There are some outcomes in
human relations too absurd to rise to the level of conscious ex-
clusion. So it would be, in modern times at least, if a parliament
should forget that its accepted function is, after all, to make laws
and should begin to act as if it had been given the power to save
souls or to declare scientific truth. And if the expectations and
acceptances that underlie a parliament's power confine it to law-
making, does not this tacitly entail further limitations? Is it not
assumed, for example, that the parliament will not hold a drink-
ing bout with the understanding that those members still on their
feet at midnight shall have the power to make the laws? And is
it going much further— or even as far — to say that it is tacitly
understood that the parliament will not withhold its enactments
from the knowledge of those bound to obey them or express its
y
life," it is certainly expected that if I give him my money, he will Vp^
139
—
THE MORALITY OF LAW
standing and general orders that may be published, but do not
constitute a directcommunication between lawgiver and subject.
Acting through general rules is "the standard way in which law
functions, if only because no society could support the number
of officials necessary to secure that every member of the society
was and separately informed of every act which he was
officially
required to do" (p. 21). Every step in the analysis seems almost
as if it were designed to exclude the notion that there could be
any rightful expectation on the part of the citizen that could be
violated by the lawgiver.
I shall not attempt to trace in detail Hart's application of the
rule of recognition to a complex, constitutional democracy. Suf-
fice it to say he concedes that in this case there is not one rule
of recognition, but a whole complex of rules, practices, and con-
ventions that determine how lawmakers are elected, what the
qualifications and jurisdiction of judges shall be, and all the re-
lated matters that affect the determination in a given case of what
shall count as law and what not (pp. 59, 75, 242, et passim).
He also concedes "that a great proportion of ordinary citizens
perhaps a majority —have
no general conception of the legal
structure or of its he con-
criteria of validity" (p. 111). Finally,
cedes that it is not always possible to draw a sharp line of dis-
tinction between ordinary rules of law and those rules that grant
lawmaking powers (p. 144). Yet he seems to insist that, despite
all these concessions, the rule of recognition that ascribes legal
sovereignty to the Queen in Parliament can in some way sum-
marize and absorb all the little rules that enable lawyers to
recognize law in a hundred different special contexts. He seems
further to assert that this view of the matter is not a juristic con-
struction imposed from without, nor an expression of confidence
in the political power of Parliament to resolve any conceivable
conflicts that may arise within the system, but rather something
provable empirically in the daily practices of his government.
I have difficulty in seeing how this can be. "Parliament" is,
after all, only a name for an institution that has changed its na-
ture drastically over the centuries. The memory of one such
140
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
change is preserved i the gracious fiction that even today speaks,
not of lawmaking by the Parliament, but by "the Queen in Parlia-
ment." To speak of one rule of recognition as pointing to some-
thing constantly changing is, it seems to me, almost like saying
that in a given country the rule of recognition has always ac-
corded the supreme lawmaking power to The Great X, where X
in one decade meant an elected official, in the next, the eldest son
of the last X, and in a third, a triumvirate selected by lot from
the Army, the Clergy, and the Laborers' Union.
It thus appears in Hart's account that the pointing finger which
the rule of recognition directs toward the source of law can move
through a wide arc without losing its target. How wide can that
arc become? It is perhaps a matter of political wisdom not to
ask for too precise an answer to this question. It is well in survey-
ing the past of one's country to see continuities even where con-
temporaries saw revolutions. But when the rule of recognition is
141
THE MORALITY OF LAW
Hart's explanation of this fact of experience is to say that the
rule of recognition points not to the man, but to the office, and
includes within itself the rules of lawful succession. In a similar
way we are in a position to explain, Hart suggests, why a law en-
acted by Parliament in 1735 can still be law in 1944.
But suppose that in our hypothetical case Rex IV is succeeded
not by his son, Rex V, but by Brutus I, who ousts Rex IV from
the throne without the slightest pretense of title and in open
how and when a primitive society makes its "step from the pre-
legal into the legal world" (p. 41). A society living in the pre-legal
world knows only primary rules of obligation, that is, duty-
imposing rules (p. 89). Such a system of rules is defective in a
number of respects: it provides no machinery for resolving doubts
and contradictions, or for effecting deliberate change; its rules
142
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
depend for their effectiveness on diffuse social pressures (pp. 90-
91). A transition to the "legal world" occurs when a society first
conceives and applies to its affairs the notion that a rule may con-
fera power to make or change rules of duty (p. 61). This dis-
covery "is a step forward as important to society as the invention
of the wheel" (p. 41).
Now it seems to me that this essentially Austinian conception
represents, again, a misapplication of juristic distinctions to a
context that will not support them. For one thing, in a society
where there is a pervasive belief in magic, and where nature is
invoked by a formula, it is apparent that there can be no clear
distinction between "natural" and "legal" powers. The charis-
matic lawgiver is not authorized by any man-made rule of recog-
nition to make the law. Rather, the authority he enjoys in society
derives from a belief that he possesses a special capacity to dis-
cern and declare the law. 54 If we can speak of the emergence of
something like an explicit rule of recognition, this took place over
centuries and involved a gradual shift from the notion of powers
as an attribute of the person to powers conferred by an assigned
social role. Before this transition is complete, we have long since
left behind anything that could be called a primitive state of
society. Indeed, it may be said that this transition is never secure
against a relapse into more primitive notions. The cult of per-
sonality remains in some measure with us always.
It is furthermore doubtful whether primitive society was domi-
nated by anything like the modern conception of duty. It is at
54. See Weber, Law in Economy and Society, trans. Shils and Rhein
stein (1954), pp. 73-82. The distinction taken in Chinese philosophy be-
tween a government by men and a government by laws is also worthy of
note, since it can serve to counteract somewhat Weber's insistence on the
nonrational character of "charisma." See Escarra, Le droit chinois (1936),
pp. 7-57.
143
THE MORALITY OF LAW
munity of an uncleanliness. A similar purging was accomplished
through the generous use of ostracism. Instead of a generalized
notion of duty we encounter acts that are allowed and disallowed,
proper and improper, fas et nefas. The first legal procedures often
took the form, not of a judicial determination of guilt, but of a
ritualistic self-help. Every misdeed tended to demand for its cure
a distinctive, and specially designed remedy. A generalized con-
ception of duty may perhaps be said to emerge only when we have
several remedies for the breach of a single duty, or several duties
that may be enforced by a single remedy. So long as the con-
sequences of a misdeed are identified with the formal steps neces-
sary to cure it, it would seem we are confronted with a notion of
power, rather than of duty.
It willbe useful to test Hart's hypothesis concerning the
world" against the actual experience of a
transition to "the legal
primitive people making that transition in quite modern times.
The experience in question is that of the Manus people of the
Admiralty Islands as reported by Margaret Mead. 55
After World War II the Manus people learned from their
Australian governors that there was a way of dealing with dis-
putes of which they had no previous knowledge. This was the
procedure of adjudication. Their own methods of settling disputes
had been most unsatisfactory, consisting as they did of "feuds,
raids, and subsequent ephemeral peace-making ceremonies often
with payments in expiation." Now they came to see that a dispute
could be decided and settled by a submission of it to an impartial
arbiter. There followed a veritable fad for adjudication, their own
elders being assigned or assuming a quite unfamiliar social role,
that of judge. Curiously the justice thus dispensed was a kind of
black market commodity since the "judges" who decided their
disputes lacked any legal standing with the Australian govern-
ment; their powers were quite unsupported by any rule of recog-
nition except a very informal and shifting one among the Manus
people themselves.
55. New Lives for Old (1956). The quotations in the text are taken from
pp. 306 and 307.
144
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
The attitude of the indigenous people toward this innovation
is thus described by Miss Mead:
145
THE MORALITY OF LAW
has a proper role to play in the interpretation of individual legal
enactments. A statute is obviously a purposive thing, serving
some end or congeries of related ends. What is objected to is not
the assignment of purposes to particular laws, but to law as a
whole.
Any view that ascribes some purpose or end to a whole insti-
56. Boorstin, The Lost World of Thomas Jefferson (1948), pp. 45^*7.
146
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
I have shown in my second chapter, far from being either self-
evident or unimportant.
Before denying ourselves the modest indulgence in teleology
I have proposed, we should consider carefully the cost entailed
in this denial. The most significant element of that cost lies in
the fact that we lose wholly any standard for defining legality. If
law is simply a manifested fact of authority or social power, then,
though we can still talk about the substantive justice or injustice
of particular enactments, we can no longer talk about the degree
to which a legal system as a whole achieves the ideal of legality;
if we are consistent with our premises we cannot, for example,
assert that the legal system of Country X achieves a greater mea-
sure of legality than that of Country Y. We can talk about con-
tradictions in the law, but we have no standard for defining what
a contradiction is. We may bemoan some kinds of retroactive
laws, but we cannot even explain what would be wrong with a
system of laws that were wholly retroactive. If we observe that
the power of law normally expresses itself in the application of
general rules, we can think of no better explanation for this than
to say that the supreme legal power can hardly afford to post
a subordinate at every street corner to tell people what to do.
In short, we can neither formulate nor answer the problems to
which my second chapter was devoted.
It may be said that if in truth these problems cannot be formu-
147
THE MORALITY OF LAW
an established lawmaking authority. What this authority deter-
mines to be law is law. There is in this determination no question
of degree; one cannot apply to it the adjectives "successful" or
"unsuccessful." This, it seems to me, is the gist of the theory
which opposes that underlying these chapters.
Now this theory can seem tenable, I submit, only if we sys-
tematically strike from view two elements in the reality it pur-
ports to describe. The first of these lies in the fact that the
established authority which tells us what is law is itself the
product of law. 57 In modern society law is typically created by
corporate action. Corporate action —by a parliament, for example
— is possible only by adopting and following rules of procedure
that will enable a body of men to speak legally with one voice.
These rules of procedure may meet shipwreck in all of the eight
ways open to any system of law. So when we assert that in the
United Kingdom Parliament has the final say as to what law is,
we are tacitly assuming some measure of success in at least one
legal enterprise, that directed toward giving Parliament the cor-
porate power to "say" things. This assumption of success is nor-
mally quite justified in countries with a long parliamentary tradi-
tion. But if we are faithful to the reality we purport to describe,
we shall recognize that a parliament's ability to enact law is itself
an achievement of purposive effort, and not simply a datum of
nature.
The second falsification of reality consists in ignoring the fact
that a formal structure of authority is itself usually dependent on
human effort that is not required by any law or command. Weber
points out that all formal social structures —whether embodied
in a tradition or a written constitution — are likely to have gaps
that do not appear as such because they are filled by appropriate
actions taken, often, without any awareness that an alternative is
148
—
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
that would defeat the whole undertaking in which they are en-
gaged, even though the formal directions under which they
operate permit these absurdities.
Agood example of a gap in formal structure is to be found
in the Constitution of the United States. That laws should be a a j\(
promulgated is probably the most obvious demand of legality.
It is also the demand that is most readily reduced to a formal
149
—
THE MORALITY OF LAW
of formal authority and excludes from its operations the possible
influence of human judgment and insight.
The heavy emphasis theory tends to place on an exact defini-
tion of the highest legal power expresses, no doubt, a concern
that obscurity on this point may cause the legal system as a whole
to disintegrate. Again, it is forgotten that no set of directions
emanating from above can ever dispense with the need for intel-
ligent action guided by a sense of purpose. Even the lowly
justice of the peace, who cannot make head or tail of the language
by which his jurisdiction is limited, will usually have the insight
to see that his powers derive from an office forming part of a
larger system. He will at least have the judgment to proceed
150
THE CONCEPT OF LAW
of its own, that it imposes demands that must be met (sometimes
with considerable inconvenience) if its objectives are to be at-
tained. It is because men generally in some measure perceive
these demands and respect them, that legal systems display a
certain likeness in societies otherwise quite diverse.
It is, then, precisely because law is a purposeful enterprise
that it displays structural constancies which the legal theorist can
discover and treat as uniformities in the factually given. If he
realized on what he built his theory, he might be less inclined
151
THE SUBSTANTIVE AIMS
IV
OF LAW
152
THE SUBSTANTIVE AIMS OF LAW
secondary importance. The two principal distinctions upon which
the discussion has so far been built are,it will be recalled, the
also clear that a legal system might maintain its internal integrity
whether its rules were designed to prohibit or to encourage
contraception.
But a recognition that the internal morality of law may support
and give efficacy to a wide variety of substantive aims should
not mislead us into believing that any substantive aim may be
adopted without compromise of legality. Even the adoption of
an objective like the legal suppression of contraception may,
under some circumstances, impair legal morality. If, as sometimes
seems to be the case, laws prohibiting the sale of contraceptives
are kept on the books as a kind of symbolic act, with the knowl-
edge that they will not and cannot be enforced, legal morality is
seriously affected. There is no way to quarantine this contagion
against a spread to other parts of the legal system. It is unfortu-
nately a familiar political technique to placate one interest by
passing a statute, and to appease an opposing interest by leaving
the statute largely unenforced.
One of the tasks of the present chapter is to analyze in general
terms the manner in which the internal and external moralities
of law interact. Before presenting this analysis it will be useful
to oppose against it the view expressed by H. L. A. Hart in
153
THE MORALITY OF LAW
The Concept of Law. 2 In his chapter on "Law and Morals" Hart
writes:
Certainly one could not wish for a more explicit denial of any
possible interaction between the internal and external moralities
of law than that contained in this last sentence. must confess
I
2. This book has been previously discussed at some length; see pp. 133—
45, supra.
3. Ibid., p. 202. The unidentified "critic of positivism" mentioned in
the quoted passage is myself.
154
THE SUBSTANTIVE AIMS OF LAW
itself solely in have quoted. It permeates his
the few sentences I
155
THE MORALITY OF LAW
phans' asylum, and that it will be a better asylum if he is a skill-
ful craftsman equipped with tools that have been used with care
and kept in proper condition.
If we had no
carpenters at all it would be plain that our first
need would be, not to draft blueprints for hospitals and asylums
or to argue about the principles of good design, but to recruit
and train carpenters. It is in this sense that much of the world
today needs law more than it does good law.
It is worth recalling that in the indictment set forth in the
156
THE SUBSTANTIVE AIMS OF LAW
Hart's treatment (pp. 114-20) of "The Pathology of a Legal
System." All the situations he discusses under that heading in-
volve either a conflict of ultimate authority or "the simple break-
down of ordered legal control in the face of anarchy or banditry
without political pretensions to govern." Here, as elsewhere in
Hart's book, law is conceived entirely in terms of its formal source
rather than as a complex undertaking capable of various degrees
of success. There is no recognition that there may be a con-
tinued public acceptance of a single source of legal power and
yet that power may be so ineptly or corruptly exercised that an
effective legal system is not achieved. Nor is there any recognition
that some degree of "pathology" attends all legal systems, in-
cluding the most exemplary. Even if one is interested only in
shifts from one formal source of legal power to another, no
One deep affinity between legality and justice has often been re-
marked and is in fact explicitly recognized by Hart himself
(p. lies in a quality shared by both, namely, that they
202). This
act by known rule. The internal morality of the law demands
that there be rules, that they be made known, and that they be
observed in practice by those charged with their administration.
These demands may seem ethically neutral so far as the external
aims of law are concerned. Yet, just as law is a precondition for
good law, so acting by known rule is a precondition for any
meaningful appraisal of the justice of law. "A lawless unlimited
power" expressing itself solely in unpredictable and patternless
157
THE MORALITY OF LAW
interventions in human affairs could be said to be unjust only in
the sense that it does not act by known rule. It would be hard
to call it unjust in any more specific sense until one discovered
what hidden principle, if any, guided its interventions. It is the
virtue of a legal order conscientiously constructed and adminis-
tered that it exposes to public scrutiny the rules by which it acts.
It is now generally forgotten by what dodges the Nazis avoided
that public disclosure. During their regime there appeared in
many German shop windows a sign reading "JUdisches Geschaft."
No law was ever passed requiring the display of such signs. They
were installed at the "request" of Party members who went about
distributing them to the stores where their display was thought
appropriate. The explanation of this procedure current among
the German citizenry was that the Nazis knew that a formal and
published legal enactment would invite foreign criticism. This
ruse was in fact partly successful. At times when an influx of
foreigners was expected, say, during a commercial fair, the signs
were, again at the request of the Party, temporarily removed. In
Berlin, where a great many foreign visitors were coming and
going at all times, signs were not used at all. Instead stores of
Jewish ownership were "requested" by the Party to use a distinc-
tive paint around the frames of their display windows. The casual
foreign visitor would be likely to observe the frequency with
which this color was used, but generally remained ignorant of
its significance and that it had been used in compliance with a
158
THE SUBSTANTIVE AIMS OF LAW
Signing such a paper is a condition of his discharge from custody.
No doubt many a police officer, quite unreflective about this
practice, has applied it with a sense of conscientiously observing
standard operating procedure. It is hard to imagine any law-
maker who would be willing to authorize such a procedure by a
published rule.
So far I have spoken as if the affinity between legality and
justice consisted simply in the fact that a rule articulated and
made known permits the public to judge of its fairness. The
affinity has, however, deeper roots. Even if a man is answerable
only to his own
conscience, he will answer more responsibly if
he is compelled to articulate the principles on which he acts.
Many persons occupying positions of power betray in their rela-
tions with subordinates uniformities of behavior that may be said
to constitute unwritten rules. It is not always clear that those who
express these rules in their actions are themselves aware of them.
It has been said that most of the world's injustices are inflicted,
Even the South African judge who in his private life shares
the prejudices that have shaped the law he is bound to interpret
and apply, must, if he respects the ethos of his calling, feel a deep
distaste for the arbitrary manipulations this legislation demands
of him.
160
THE SUBSTANTIVE AIMS OF LAW
It should not be supposed it is only in South Africa that statutes
attaching legal consequences to differences in race have given
rise to serious difficulties of interpretation. In 1948 in Perez v.
7. 32Cal.2d711.
8. USCA,Tit.8, §1422.
9. 260 U.S. 178(1922).
10. United States v. Thind, 261 U.S. 204 (1923).
161
THE MORALITY OF LAW
for another The words of familiar speech, which were used
. . .
a Jew. The Court conceded that this was true, but said that the
question was not one of religious law but of the secular law of
Israel. By that law he was no longer a Jew because he had em-
braced the Christian religion. 11
162
THE SUBSTANTIVE AIMS OF LAW
morality loses its reason for being. To judge his actions by un-
published or retrospective laws is no longer an affront, for there
is nothing left to affront — indeed, even the verb "to judge" be-
comes itself incongruous in this context; we no longer judge a
man, we act upon him.
Today a whole complex of attitudes, practices, and theories
seems to drive us toward a view which denies that man is, or
can meaningfully strive to become, a responsible, self-determin-
ing center of action. The causes of this development are of the
most varied sort; in their motivation they seem to run the gamut
from the basest to the most noble.
One stream of influence comes from science, and more par-
ticularly from certain doctrinaire schools of thought in the social
sciences. Let me allow the eminent psychologist B. F. Skinner
at this point to speak for himself:
163
—
THE MORALITY OF LAW
church or remaining in church while coughing. But there
are variables which are responsible for whispering as well as
coughing, and these may be just as inexorable. When we
recognize this, we are likely to drop the notion of responsi-
bility altogether and with it the doctrine of free will as an
inner causal agent. This may make a great difference in our
practices. The doctrine of personal responsibility is associ-
ated with certain techniques of controlling behavior
techniques which generate "a sense of responsibility" or
point out "an obligation to society." These techniques are
^relatively ill-adapted to their purpose. 12
12. Science and Human Behavior (1953); the quotations in the text are
taken from pp. 6-7, 10, 115-16.
13. Two themes that run through Skinner's thinking are: (1) that pur-
pose must be excluded from scientific explanation, since it involves a con-
ceived future state as governing the present, whereas it is an accepted
tenet of science that the past controls the present; (2) human behavior
must, so far as possible, be explained in terms of causes "outside" the
organism, rather than operative "within" it.
164
THE SUBSTANTIVE AIMS OF LAW
overworked prosecutor who seeks to simplify his job through v^
laws that will make criminal responsibility independent of any
proof of fault or intent.
I have spoken of "noble" impulses as having played a part in
confusing the concept of responsibility. An outstanding example
lies in abuses of the rehabilitative ideal in the criminal law. As
Francis Allen has demonstrated, 14 misapplied this ideal can
brutalize the criminal law it sought to make more humane. When,
for example, rehabilitation is taken as the exclusive aim of the
criminal law, all concern about due process and a clear definition
of what is criminal may be lost. If the worst that can happen to
the defendant is that he should be given a chance to have him-
self improved at public expense, why all the worry about a fair
trial?
ask himself what, after all, is the difference between a tax and
a fine? His mood of quiet desperation is not likely to be improved
166
THE SUBSTANTIVE AIMS OF LAW
if he is unfortunate enough to learn that a famous justice of the
Supreme Court of the United States used to insist that there is
no difference.
I shall not dwell longer on these incongruities of the modern
Jr?^
legal order. I should like instead to recall what we would lose
s >J\^
if the concept of responsibility ever disappeared completely from ^v >/
the law. The whole body of the law is permeated by two recurring
standards of decision: fault and intent. Philosophic discussion of )(X)
J$^
^
these notions has largely concentrated on their role in the criminal
law, where they have given rise to the most abstruse arguments,
including that concerning freedom of the will. But these twin
standards play an equally important role in the law of contracts,
torts, and property. Examined closely they turn out to be difficult
and elusive conceptions in whatever area of the law they appear.
Yet without them we would have no thread to guide us through
the labyrinth. When one of them fails, we are apt to reach for
the closest approximation of it. When there is no clearly deter-
mined intent, we ask what intention the parties would have had
had they foreseen the situation that has arisen. When neither
party seems chargeable directly with fault, we ask which of them
—
had the best chance to prevent the harm which, in other words,
was closest to being at fault.
Notice what happens when these two tests, and their near
relatives, fail completely. This occurs in the law of contracts
when performance of an agreement is hampered or its significance
is changed by some external event, such as the cancellation of a
167
THE MORALITY OF LAW
ki Is made
finally, the specific
to express blind Tiatreds mrough legal rules , ancPtfiat,
morality of law articulates and holds before
us a view of man's nature that is indispensable to law and morality
alike.
168
—
169
THE MORALITY OF LAW
about to discuss, in Pound's famous phrase, "the limits of effec-
tive legal action," one is not sure whether the subject will be the
attempted legal suppression of homosexuality or the failure of
the government to convert the power of the tides into electricity
at Passamaquoddy.
170
THE SUBSTANTIVE AIMS OF LAW
with creating and enforcing legal duties. The internal morality
of law, in other words, is not and cannot be a morality appropri-
ate for every kind of governmental action. The Army is a creature
of law and its officers are, in a sense, officials of the government.
Yet certainly it does not follow that every exercise of military
command must subject itself to the restraints appropriate, for
example, to a discharge of the judicial function.
It is chiefly in the economic field that truisms like those just
171
THE MORALITY OF LAW
nature adjudication must act through openly declared rule or
principle, and the grounds on which it acts must display some
continuity through time. Without this, joinder of argument be-
comes impossible and all the conventional safeguards that sur-
round decision (such as that proscribing private conferences be-
tween the litigant and the arbiter of the dispute) forfeit their
meaning.
To act wisely, the economic manager must take into account
every circumstance relevant to his decision and must himself
assume the what circumstances are rele-
initiative in discovering
vant. His decisions must be subject to reversal or change as con-
ditions alter. The judge, on the other hand, acts upon those facts
that are in advance deemed relevant under declared principles of
decision. His decision does not simply direct resources and ener-
gies; it declares rights, and rights to be meaningful must in some
measure stand firm through changing circumstances. When,
therefore, we attempt to discharge tasks of economic manage-
ment through adjudicative forms there is a serious mismatch be-
tween the procedure adopted and the problem to be solved.
Nowhere is this thought more effectively conveyed than in an
illustration suggested by Henry J. Friendly in his Holmes Lec-
tures, The Federal Administrative Agencies: The Need for Better
Definition of Standards. 19 Judge Friendly speaks of "the frustrat-
ing nature" of the task assigned by Congress to the Federal Com-
munications Commission. He continues:
172
THE SUBSTANTIVE AIMS OF LAW
it to any of the other qualified applicants; prohibit the board
173
THE MORALITY OF LAW
will be found throughout Judge Friendly's lectures that praise
and blame trace a path closely adhering to the distinction be-
tween allocative and nonallocative functions. Both praise and
blame are, however, largely misplaced when they are directed at
individuals; they ought instead to be directed to the aptness of
the institutional design of the agency to perform the task assigned
to it.
174
THE SUBSTANTIVE AIMS OF LAW
agency whether to close down or to subsidize the continued
operation of a losing mine. An intelligent determination of that
question could only be made after an investigation into alterna-
tive uses for the manpower released by the shutdown and into
other opportunities for the use of the subsidy.
In stressing the special significance of the allocative function,
I do not wish to imply, of course, that there are no gradations in
the distinction between allocative and nonallocative tasks. Even
a judicial decision declaring a tax unconstitutional may operate
to draw investment into the area previously affected by the tax.
This allocative side effect is in theory disregarded as irrelevant
to the decision. Similarly an administrative tribunal may proceed
on standards that ignore the allocative effects of its decisions.
This is done by a rate-making agency where it takes as its stan-
dard the principle of an adequate return on a particular invest-
ment. If, on the other hand, the agency takes as its standard
setting a rate that will induce a sufficient flow of capital into the
regulated industry as a whole, its allocative function becomes
more explicit, but can be muted by an assumption that the in-
dustry requires a "normal" inflow of investment, though a wider
view of the economy might falsify this assumption. Tasks that
were once only incidentally allocative may become more directly
so with a change in circumstances. This happened to the Inter-
state Commerce Commission when the railways came under
competition from the truck and the airplane. It is interesting to
note that Judge Friendly praises some of the earlier decisions of
the ICC (pp. 27-35) and condemns more recent decisions for a
lack of "clear standards" (pp. 106-40).
The problem of finding the most apt institutional design for
governmental control over the economy has been acute for a long
time. In the future this problem is, I think, bound to become
more pressing and pervasive. Indispensable facilities, like certain
of our railways, will have to be rescued in one way or another
from their economic plight, a plight which, in the case of the
railways, has in part been brought about by the allocative effects
(for which no one assumes explicit responsibility) of subsidies
175
—
THE MORALITY OF LAW
granted to competing forms of transportation. In the labor field,
176
THE SUBSTANTIVE AIMS OF LAW
against abuse we need not confine ourselves to adjudicative pro-
cedures in the strict sense, but may also consider the models
suggested by the French Conseil d'fitat, the Scandinavian
ombudsman, the British Council on Tribunals, and the boards of
censors once established by several American states, censors
whose function it was not to supervise private morals, but to be
alert to detect abuses and deficiencies in government.
177
THE MORALITY OF LAW
choice. This procedure normally involves a series of accommoda-
tions and compromises among those to be affected by the final
decision.
The architectural design of legal institutions and procedures
obviously cannot be drawn by adjudicative decision. It is for
this reason that the Supreme Court has wisely regarded as beyond
its competence the enforcement of the constitutional provision
guaranteeing to the states a republican form of government. A
court acting as such can neither write a constitution nor under-
take a general managerial supervision of its administration.
The decision in Carr 23 represents a gamble that
Baker v.
and prudence.
At the risk of laboring the obvious, let me illustrate the point
178
THE SUBSTANTIVE AIMS OF LAW
pupils are denied promotion and are compelled to repeat a grade.
The parents' dissatisfaction is twofold: (1) they are not certain
that decisions on this matter are correctly made there have, in—
fact, been rumors of favoritism and of carelessness in the study
of records; (2) the parents think that in any event too much is
the decision.
Now it is apparent that this program combines elements be-
tween which there is a very considerable incompatibility. Skill
and tact in administering the program can reduce this clash, but
it will still remain generally true that the more effective the pro-
cedural guarantees against mistake and favoritism are, the more
unambiguously the finger of shame will point to the pupil not
promoted. A public trial may protect him against injustice, but
it will do so at the cost of depriving him of the consolation of be-
lieving that those who held him back did not know what they
were doing.
Similar problems of weighing costs run throughout our legal
and political life. For example, if the question be asked, "How
much effort should be expended to make certain that no innocent
man is ever convicted of crime?," the answer is apt to run toward
the absolute, and the suggestion may even be made that where
fundamental human rights are at stake a question so indecently
calculative should not even be raised. Yet when we reflect that
in order to make sure that a decision is right we must consume
the scarce commodity of time, and that a right decision too long
179
THE MORALITY OF LAW
delayed may do more damage to the accused himself than a mis-
taken decision promptly rendered, the matter assumes a differ-
ent aspect. We then perceive that even in this case we are com-
make a calculation that is in the broad sense "economic"
pelled to
even though money costs are completely left out of account.
It is a great mistake to treat questions of the design and ad-
ministration of our institutions as if the problem were merely
180
THE SUBSTANTIVE AIMS OF LAW
outlined, that these problems of the proper design and coordina-
tion of our legal institutions are certain to become more pressing
in the years ahead. Their solution will require an earnest col-
laborative effort among those competent to understand them.
Something like the spirit of the Federalist Papers will become
essential —a once inquiring and constructive.
spirit at
regard those who disagree with them, not merely as being mis-
taken, but as being unprincipled and immoral.
Fortunately, the lines of controversy are not quite so grimly
drawn as the account just given might suggest. One hopes that
the future will bring a further bridging of extremes, for the capac-
ity todevise institutions and procedures adequate to its problems
is perhaps the chief mark of a civilized society. That capacity is
in any event the chief instrument by which civilization can hope
to survive in a radically changing world.
181
THE MORALITY OF LAW
This is a problem that has bothered all moral philosophers.
Within a functioning community, held together by bonds of mu-
tual interest, the task of drafting a moral code is not difficult.
my neighbor?"
On this occasion Jesus does not answer, "Your neighbor is
everyone; you are bound to love all men everywhere, even your
Good Samaritan. 25
enemies." Instead he relates the parable of the
A certain man had been struck down by thieves and left half
dead. Two of his community brothers passed him by without
offering aid. Then one of the despised Samaritans — definitely a
member of the out-group —bound up his wounds and took him
into care. Jesus ends with the question: "Which now of these
182
THE SUBSTANTIVE AIMS OF LAW
three, thinkest thou, was neighbor unto him that fell among the
thieves?"
The meaning of this parable is, I believe, not that we should
include everyone in the moral community, but that we should ^y,
aspire to enlarge that community at every o^por4tmtty--asd to ^\C>
183
THE MORALITY OF LAW
biological tag line to our own title, then we deny the human
quality to ourselves in an effort to justify denying it to others.
184
THE SUBSTANTIVE AIMS OF LAW
kinds of reasons. One amounts to saying that survival is a neces-
sary condition for every other human achievement and satisfac-
185
THE MORALITY OF LAW
tures, often more powerful than he and sometimes gifted with
keener senses, man has so far been the victor. His victory has
come about because he can acquire and transmit knowledge and
because he can consciously and deliberately effect a coordination
of effort with other human beings. If in the future man succeeds
in surviving his own powers of self-destruction, it will be because
he can communicate and reach understanding with his fellows.
Finally, I doubt if most of us would regard as desirable survival
into a kind of vegetable existence in which we could make no
meaningful contact with other human beings.
Communication something more than a means of staying
is
186
A REPLY
V
TO CRITICS
187
THE MORALITY OF LAW
completely mistaken his critics are. In general, efforts at self
justification are apt to be painful for all concerned; there is, in-
deed, a saying in my profession that a lawyer never appears to
worse advantage than when pleading his own cause.
In the case at hand there was also the consideration that any
Reply to Critics would mark the continuation of a debate between
H. L. A. Hart and myself that has already gone on for more than a
decade. It began when Professor Hart published the Holmes Lec-
ture delivered at the Harvard Law School in April 1957. 1 In that
lecture he undertook to defend legal positivism against criticisms
made by myself and others. The first attempt at counterthrust
was my critical commentary on this lecture. 2 Round three was
marked by the publication of Hart's The Concept of Law; round
four occurred when the first edition of the present work was pub-
lished; round five took place when Hart published his review. 3
One has the feeling that at some point such an exchange must
terminate. Interest reipublicae ut sit finis litium. As Ernest Nagel
remarked in the fourth and final round of a debate we had in
1958 and 1959, "There is, in general, little intellectual nourish-
ment to be found in rebuttals to rejoinders to replies." 4
A final deterrent lay in the sheer number of reviews and the
diversity of opinion expressed in them, 5 not to speak of the con-
tributions to a symposium held on April 2, 1965, 6 or of incidental
188
—
A REPLY TO CRITICS
book seem to me
from the same single source.
to spring
The author has all his life been in love with the notion of
purpose and this passion, like any other can both inspire
and blind a man. I have tried to show how it has done both
189
THE MORALITY OF LAW
to the author. The inspiration is so considerable that I would
not wish him to terminate his longstanding union with this
idee maitresse. But I wish that the high romance would
settle down to some cooler form of regard. When this hap-
pens, the author's many readers will feel the drop in tem-
perature; but they will be amply compensated by an increase
in light. 8
8. Supra n. 3, at 1295-96.
Summers, 'The New Analytical
9. Jurists," 41 New York University
Law Review 861-96 (1966).
190
A REPLY TO CRITICS
can in what follows identify those starting points more clearly than
the New Analytical Jurists themselves have been able to do.
191
THE MORALITY OF LAW
the positivist position. Confining myself, then, to the basic "start-
ing points" that shape the positivist creed, I would discern five
of these.
law as a one-way projection
First, the analytical positivist sees
of authority, emanating from an authorized source and imposing
itself on the citizen. It does not discern as an essential element
192
A REPLY TO CRITICS
I think I need not labor the point that the four elements of the
positivist creed just outlined are interdependent; each in a sense
implies the others. They may all be summed up in the observation
that the positivist recognizes in the functioning of a legal system
nothing that can truly be called a social dimension. The positivist
sees the law at the point of its dispatch by the lawgiver and again
at the point of its impact on the legal subject. He does not see the
lawgiver and the citizen in interaction with one another, and by
virtue of that failure he fails to see that the creation of an effective
interaction between them is an essential ingredient of the law
itself.
So far I have left out the fifth and most central article of faith
193
—
THE MORALITY OF LAW
stance toward reality becomes most difficult to maintain. In con-
trast, whenever human action can plausibly be viewed as unilater-
ally projected, the embarrassments of a commitment to positivism
^ he thinks the other seeks and in part also by what he thinks the
other thinks he seeks. Here there emerges from the parties' inter-
actions no hard factual datum that can be set off against the
purposes that brought it into existence. The quality and terms of
194
A REPLY TO CRITICS
195
THE MORALITY OF LAW
found, there seems to be a kind of presumption that they will
prove valid and useful and that once they have been fully
articulated there is no need to go further. An exemplification
of the method is offered by Hart's intense interest in the distinc-
tion between "being obliged" and "having an obligation." Some
useful insights have been derived through this method; there is
indeed a lot of tacit and subtle wisdom concealed in the in-
terstices of everyday speech. But the tendency of the practitioners
of this method has been to regard as an end in itself what ought
to be viewed as a useful adjunct to philosophic thought. As Stuart
Hampshire has observed, there seems to be an assumption among
linguistic philosophers that distinctions disentangled from or-
dinary speech have a utility that is independent of the context
of any particular problem and that these distinctions can be
transferred freely from one problem to another. 13 I agree with
Hampshire that this is a serious mistake.
I shall call attention later to some instances in which the as-
sumptions of ordinary-language have, in my opinion, misled cer-
tain of my critics. For the time being let me just note one illustra-
tive outcropping of the spirit of this philosophy. On pages 124-29
I suggested that the problems involved in maintaining the in-
tegrity of a legal system were characteristic not only of state and
national law, but affected also the creation and administration of
the internal law of such association^ forms as churches, clubs,
universities, and labor unions. I declared therefore that for
purposes of my analysis the internal regulations of these bodies
were "law." Hart calls this assertion "unashamed," 14 while
Summers was so unnerved by it he could find nothing better to
say than that it was another instance of what he regards as my
life-long intellectual dedication, that is, to an activity he calls
196
A REPLY TO CRITICS
197
THE MORALITY OF LAW
sort is correct." 17 Dworkin puts it this way: "I accept Fuller's
conclusion that some degree of compliance with his eight canons
of law is necessary to produce (or equally as important, to apply)
any law, even bad law." 18 Summers is more cautious: "at least
some of [Fuller's] opponents would not deny that if we are to have
law at all, we must have some compliance with [his] 'principles of
legality.'
"*»
198
—
A REPLY TO CRITICS
199
THE MORALITY OF LAW
dictates of ordinary language nor the insistences of the New
Analytical Jurisprudence need cause any serious inconvenience;
ifone wishes to avoid saying that the law of Country A is more
truly law than that of Country B, one can simply affirm that the
government of A displays a greater respect for the principles of
legality than does the government of B. If one is addressing an
audience that has had its tolerance for metaphor and oxymoron
reduced through exposure to ordinary-language philosophy, the
course of prudence will be to choose the second and more routine
form of expression.
200
A REPLY TO CRITICS
201
THE MORALITY OF LAW
That something is here involved more basic than any mere
202
—
A REPLY TO CRITICS
203
THE MORALITY OF LAW
ficacy to morality; certainly nothing is attained that justifies treat-
ing the use of the word "morality" in this connection as an exer-
cise in obfuscation. In truth, the appeal of "efficacy" does not lie
in any definiteness of meaning, but in the tough-sounding,
its
204
A REPLY TO CRITICS
meager, being confined chiefly to the observation that legal rules
long established tend, through a kind of cultural conditioning, to
be regarded as morally right.
against all. To live the good life requires something more than
good intentions, even if they are generally shared; it requires the
support of firm base lines for human interaction, something that
— in modern society at least —only a sound legal system can
supply.
"Do not take what belongs to another" is about as trite an
example of a moral precept as can be found in the books. But
how do we decide what belongs to another? To answer that
question we resort not to morals but to law. In some contexts
we can, of course, talk meaningfully of a person's being morally
entitled tosome object of property. For example, an ailing
mother has two daughters. One of them foregoes marriage and
devotes herself for many years to looking after the invalid parent;
the other selfishly refuses to go near her mother or to contribute
anything to her care. On the mother's death it is found that she
left no will; under the law the two daughters succeed equally to
their mother's meager estate. Here we may say that the faithful
daughter morally entitled to the whole estate, even though the
is
sert." So it is that the moral precept, "Do not take what belongs
to another," must of necessity rest on standards borrowed from
the law; without that support it could not achieve reality in the
conduct of human affairs.
205
THE MORALITY OF LAW
Again, all would agree, I suppose, that the institution of
marriage has moral implications — indeed, many of them. But
this institution can scarcely function —morally or legally — with-
out some fairly definite rule that will enable us to know when
the marital state exists. An illustration drawn from Hoebel's
chapter, "The Eskimo: Rudimentary Law in a Primitive An-
archy," may be instructive here. 26 It appears that among the
Eskimos the concept of marriage exists, but there are lacking
clear signposts "which might demarcate the beginning and the
end of a marital relationship." The result is that what one man
views as a fair contest for the lady's favors, the other may see as an
adulterous invasion of his home; in Hoebers words there are "no
cultural devices signalizing marriage in such a way as to keep out
trespassers." In consequence Eskimo society is beset by an in-
ordinate number of violent quarrels arising out of sexual jealousy
and these quarrels in turn produce a high rate of homicide. Plainly
the remedy here is not to be found in preaching, but in some
explicit legislative measure that will define and set visible bound-
aries around the marital relation. The Eskimos simply lack the
social machinery needed to accomplish this task; the consequent
non-existence of needed law may be said to impoverish seriously
the quality of their lives.
So when we speak of "the moral neutrality of law" we cannot
mean that the existence and conscientious administration of a
legal system are unrelated to a realization of moral objectives
in the affairs of life. If respect for the principles of legality is
206
A REPLY TO CRITICS
207
THE MORALITY OF LAW
citizens and only in a collateral manner his relations with the
seat of authority from which the rules proceed. (Though we
sometimes think of the criminal law as defining the citizen's
duties toward his government, its primary function is to provide
a sound and stable framework for the interactions of citizens with
one another.)
The account just given could stand much expansion and quali-
fication; the two forms of social ordering present themselves in
actual life in many mixed, ambiguous, and distorted forms. For
our present purposes, however, we shall attempt to clarify the
essential difference between them by presupposing what may be
called "ideal types." We shall proceed by inquiring what implica-
tions the eight principles of legality (or analogues thereof) have
for a system of managerial direction as compared with their im-
plications for a legal order.
Now five of the eight principles are quite at home in a man-
agerial context. If the superior is what he wants through
to secure
the instrumentality of the subordinate he must, first of all, com-
municate his wishes, or "promulgate" them by giving the sub-
ordinate a chance to know what they are, for example, by posting
them on a bulletin board. His directives must also be reasonabl}
clear, free from contradiction, possible of execution and noi
changed so often as to frustrate the efforts of the subordinate tc
act on them. Carelessness in these matters may seriously irr
pair the "efficacy" of the managerial enterprise.
What of the other three principles? With respect to the require-
ment of generality, this becomes, in a managerial context, simpl)
a matter of expediency. In actual practice managerial control i?
208
A REPLY TO CRITICS
209
THE MORALITY OF LAW
followed by the citizen and as being determinative of his rights
and duties. If the Rule of Law does not mean this, it means
nothing. Applying rules faithfully implies, in turn, that rules will
take the form of general declarations; it would make little sense,
for example, if the government were today to enact a special law
whereby Jones should be put in jail and then tomorrow were
"faithfully" to follow this "rule" by actually putting him in jail.
Furthermore, if the law is intended to permit a man to conduct
his own an obligation to observe certain re-
affairs subject to
210
j
A REPLY TO CRITICS
we need to recall that under the Rule of Law control over the
citizen's actions is accomplished, not by specific directions, but
seriously infringed, and the only cure (at best involving a choice
of evils) may lie in retrospective legislation. 27 Plainly problems
27. In Anatomy of the Law (1968), pp. 14-15, 1 have given an historical
example of retroactive (and "special") legislation designed to cure a
judicial departure from legality.
211
THE MORALITY OF LAW
of this sort cannot arise in a managerial context, since managerial
directionis not in principle required to act by general rule and has
212
A REPLY TO CRITICS
a rule to violate. This does not mean, however, that the rule has to
be free from obscurity, or widely publicized, or consistently en-
forced. Indeed, any of these conditions may curtail the discretion
of the man in control —a discretion from which he may derive not
only a sense of personal power but also a sense, perhaps not
wholly perverse, of serving well the enterprise of which he is a
part.
It may seem that in the broader, more impersonal processes of
a national or state legal system there would be lacking any im-
pulse toward deformations or accommodations of the sort just
suggested. This is far from being the case. It should be remem-
bered, for example, that in drafting almost any statute, par-
ticularly in the fields of criminal law and economic regulation,
there is likely to occur a struggle between those who want to
preserve for government a broad freedom of action and those
whose primary concern is to let the citizen know in advance where
he stands. In confronting this kind of problem there is room in
213
THE MORALITY OF LAW
close cases for honest differences of opinion, but there can also
arise acute problems of conscience touching the basic integrity
of legal processes.Over wide areas of governmental action a
still more fundamental question can be raised: whether there is
214
A REPLY TO CRITICS
215
THE MORALITY OF LAW
consistent with the view that law is a one-way projection of au-
thority. This does not mean, of course, that the lawgiver can
bring a legal system into existence by himself; like the manager
he requires the acquiescence and cooperation of those subject to
his direction. This is recognized quite explicitly and with his
usual aptness of phrasing by Hart himself:
216
A REPLY TO CRITICS
217
THE MORALITY OF LAW
intendments. This is the passage in which Lilburae demands to
know "whether ever the Commonwealth, when they chose the
Parliament, gave them a lawless and unlimited power, and at their
pleasure to walk contrary to their own laws and ordinances before
they have repealed them?" Lilburae is suggesting that underlying
the institution of parliamentary government there is an intend-
ment — that is, a generally shared tacit expectation — that parlia-
ment will act toward the citizen in accordance with its own laws
so long as those laws remain unrepealed. A tacit commitment by
parliament to that effect is so taken for granted that, except when
things go wrong, there is no occasion to talk or even to think about
it.
218
A REPLY TO CRITICS
commitment men tend to read into the acts of those having au-
thority over them.
A similar struggle over the meaning to be attributed to exer-
cises of authority is a familiar accompaniment of the managerial
allocation of duties among subordinates. An employer, for ex-
ample, directs A to perform certain tasks, at the same time assign-
ing a different set of tasks to B. If this division of labor con-
tinues for some time any reallocation of functions may arouse
resentment and a sense of injury. An employee may resist the
point if the man subject to them knows that the rulemaker will not
himself pay any attention to his own enactments. The converse
of this proposition must also be kept in mind, namely, that the
rulemaker any incentive to accept for himself the re-
will lack
straints of the Rule of Law if he knows that his subjects have no
disposition, or lack the capacity, to abide by his rules; it would
serve little purpose, for example, to attempt a juristic ordering of
relations among the inmates of a lunatic asylum. It is in this sense
that the functioning of a legal system depends upon a cooperative
effort —an effective —
and responsible interaction between law-
giver and subject.
A complete failure in this interaction is so remote from ordi-
nary experience that the significance of the interaction itself tends
to be lost from our intellectual perspective. Yet in numberless
instances, all about us, we can perceive the ways in which the
219
THE MORALITY OF LAW
success of law depends on a voluntary collaboration between the
citizen and government, as well as upon a coordination of
his
effort among the various agencies of government concerned with
the making and enforcing of law.
In the regulation of traffic the dependence of law on voluntary
cooperation often becomes painfully visible. The example I am
about to give is by no means entirely hypothetical. In a university
city located on the Atlantic seaboard traffic congestion has during
the last thirty years presented an increasing problem; at one
street intersection in particular the situation has for some time
approached a state of crisis. At were until
this intersection there
220
A REPLY TO CRITICS
only safe course for him was to join a phalanx of stalwart law-
breakers, instead of waiting timidly for the signal legalizing a
crossing he would have to negotiate alone, unprotected, and per-
haps against a flood of delayed motorists seizing their first oppor-
tunity to cross.
When a system of legal controls has suffered this degree of
breakdown it is often difficult to allocate blame or to discern what
curative measures will be effective. Each human element involved
will contend that any mending of its own ways would be rendered
pointless by a failure in the performance of complementary roles.
221
THE MORALITY OF LAW
tion that legal moralityembraces a principle against contradic-
tory laws: "A an overlooked
legislature adopts a statute with
inconsistency so fundamental as to make the statute an empty
form. Where is the immorality, or lapse of moral ideal?" 31
Now in the first place even to imagine a case such as Dworkin
supposes requires a fantastic set of assumptions. Suppose, for
example, a statute is passed affecting the validity of foreign di-
vorces; as applied to a particular situation of the fact the statute
seems in one paragraph to say that A is married to Y, while by
the terms of another provision it would appear that he is still
222
A REPLY TO CRITICS
men guide their actions toward one another are sufficiently tam-
pered with, those that remain intact will lose their meaning and
issue stem from a basic disagreement about law itself. This dis-
agreement I have attempted to express by contrasting a view of
law that sees it as an interactional process and one that sees in it
only a unidirectional exercise of authority. My reviewers have, of
course, criticized a number on specific issues taken in
of positions
my book that I have left unmentioned and undefended here. I
believe that most, though not all, of these disagreements on sub-
sidiary matters have their origin in the same fundamental di-
vergence in starting points that I have just examined at length.
This is particularly true of my critics' rejection of the suggestion
that governmental respect for the internal morality of law will
generally be conducive toward a respect for what may be called
32. "The Relations between State and Federal Law," 54 Columbia Law
Review 489, 490 (1954).
223
THE MORALITY OF LAW
the substantive or external morality of law. The interested reader
will find a defense of my position on this issue in a paper I pre-
sented in April 1965. 33
224
A REPLY TO CRITICS
of tacit assumptions that do not appear in the explicit rules at all. Gottlieb's
book has some valuable observations on this point in Chapter IV, "The
Facts," particularly on pages 56-57, where he remarks that "non-legal
standards are infused at a crucial step [that is, in defining the relevant facts]
in the process of applying legal rules."
35. Supra n. 1, pp. 606-15.
225
.
226
A REPLY TO CRITICS
mises that serve to define the problem. I suggest that the difficulty
arises because all of the writers whose views have just been
summarized start with the assumption that law must be regarded
as a one-way projection of authority, instead of being conceived
as a collaborative enterprise. If we discern, as a basic element of
law, a commitment by government to abide by its own law in
judging the acts of its subjects, then interpretation will occupy in
theory the central place it has always occupied in our everyday
thinking about law. This emphatically does not mean that the
problem become simple; on the contrary its hidden com-
will
were using the same words, and what you would suppose I would
227
THE MORALITY OF LAW
be likely to mean by them in the context of our relationship — not
to speak of even more complex lines of reciprocating expecta-
tions.
Writers in the positivist mood have generally sought escape
from complexities of the sort just intimated by adopting a sim-
plistic view of language which I have described (page 84) as "a
228
A REPLY TO CRITICS
229
THE MORALITY OF LAW
provide a workable guide to action, are all essential for a proper
decision.
In my second chapter I dealt at some length with the "anti-
nomies" that may confront those responsible for maintaining
legality, frequently some miscarriage in the legal enterprise will
create a situation in which it is impossible to escape some com-
promise of legality, so that the essential task is to reduce the
dimensions of that compromise. The most obvious example of this
predicament is presented by situations in which a resort to retro-
spective legislation will seem the lesser of two evils.
In subtle ways interpretation is permeated with problems of
this sort. Suppose, for example, that a statute is passed for the
purpose of putting in better order some area of human relations.
On its face, we may suppose, the enactment is reasonably clear,
but it suffers from the fundamental defect that it is based on a
misconception of the situation it is intended to correct, the legis-
lature being in this respect like a physician who prescribes a
course of treatment for one disease when the patient is in fact
suffering from another. By what standards should a court con-
strue such a statute? A tolerably literal application of its terms
may be said to carry out the legislative intent as it actually was,
though not as it would have been had the legislature known what
230
A REPLY TO CRITICS
with other laws already on the books, or if it had realized that the
supreme court was about to reverse a relevant precedent these —
and other like questions can remind us that there is something
more to the task of interpreting statutes than simply "carrying out
the intention of the legislature."
The remarks just concluded may seem to suggest that what is
231
THE MORALITY OF LAW
tion not of Federal but of Massachusetts law. Several precedents
of the Massachusetts Supreme Judicial Court were in point, and
the question was whether that court, if the controversy were
before it, would qualify the language of its precedents and make
232
A REPLY TO CRITICS
posite tack of reshaping these two forms of law so that they can be
accommodated to his theory, though at the cost of so distorting
their premises that the subjects themselves become largely un-
recognizable.
Plainly the conception of law as a unidirectional assertion of
control over human behavior is not a view that can easily be ap-
plied to customary and international law. These two manifesta-
tions of law have been described as horizontal forms of order,
while the law that a state imposes on its citizens we tend to think
of as having only a vertical dimension. Stated in another way, the
difficulty of conceiving of customary and international law as
being properly law arises from the notion that the concept of law
involves at the very minimum three elements: a lawgiver and at
least two subjects whose relations are put in order by rules im-
posed on them by the law-making authority. The question that
gives trouble is, How can a person, a family, a tribe, or a nation
impose law on itself that will control its relations with other per-
sons, families, tribes, or nations? Unlike morality, law cannot be
a thing self-imposed; it must proceed from some higher authority.
Now I suggest that all these questions would require radical
redefinition if we were to recognize one simple, basic reality,
namely, that enacted law itself presupposes a commitment by
the governing authority to abide by its own rules in dealing with
its subjects. There is, in this sense, a horizontal element in what
233
THE MORALITY OF LAW
ment so that the essential distinction between law and morality is
fatally compromised.
If, however, we disregard these conceptual tangles and allow
our minds to participate vicariously in the responsibilities involved
in maintaining the Rule of Law within a modern state, we shall
234
A REPLY TO CRITICS
235
THE MORALITY OF LAW
merely different sides of the same coin. Every state institu-
236
A REPLY TO CRITICS
national law and customary law without calling attention to a re-
cent book by Michael Barkun, Law without Sanctions: Order in
Primitive Societies and the World Community (1968). Barkun
has many perceptive things to say about the damage done to
thinking in the fields of his concern by simplistic theories about
law in general. He calls particular attention to the dangers in-
volved when and anthropologists base their defini-
sociologists
tions of law on those that have become current in dealing with
domestic law:
237
THE MORALITY OF LAW
the eight principles of legality. These principles should be valued,
Hart asserts, "so far only as they contribute to human happiness
and other substantive moral aims of the law." 45 In the same pas-
sage he indicates that retroactive laws are generally to be con-
demned simply because they "make no contribution to human
happiness" and, if they result in punishment, "inflict useless
not to say, of course, that such laws might not be passed for
reasons that would make them immoral or that a situation
inadvertently created might not be abused in an immoral
way. 46
238
A REPLY TO CRITICS
condition of legal uncertainty that may give someone else an
opportunity to do the entrapping.
Dorothy Emmet has done a great service to ethical philosophy
in her book, Rules, Roles and Relations (1966), by reintroducing
in a cogently argued and perceptive way the ancient concept of
social role. Role morality is patently a morality of interaction.
But the modes of analysis appropriate to problems of role morality
are also relevant to moral problems which do not involve the per-
formance of roles that have been recognized as such. It is for this
reason that I believe a study of the complex demands of the in-
ternal morality of law would deepen our insight into moral prob-
lems generally.
In particular, a close study of the problems encountered in try-
ing to achieve and maintain legality would confront us in an un-
mistakable way with the problem I have referred to as that of
"antinomies," that is, with the sort of dilemma we face when it
is necessary to depart from one principle of legal morality to save
another. In my my illustrations of this phenome-
second chapter
non have do with cases where the correction of some
chiefly to
mishap or oversight requires a departure from the normal prac-
tices of legality, as by demanding curative legislation which is by
necessity retrospective.
That ethical philosophers are not universally prepared to deal
with this kind of dilemma shown when Cohen raises the ques-
is
239
THE MORALITY OF LAW
intended victim is hiding —while in the other case the social con-
text is complex and the interactions involved are indirect and in-
conspicuous.
If Cohen has difficulty with my "admission" that retrospective
statutes curing past departures from legality may, on net balance,
be beneficial, he has even more difficulty in absorbing the notion
that antinomies among the principles of legal morality may be
encountered in the design of legal institutions. After dealing with
the "admission" involved in my comments on curative statutes,
Cohen continues:
hissound claim that unless the judge decides such cases "he
duty to settle disputes arising out of an existing
fails in his
body of law." 4 »
The statement just quoted could hardly come from one able
to visualize a context in which two litigants, in an argument over
the significance of a statute for their respective rights, take then-
dispute to a judge and ask him to resolve it. Would Cohen have
the judge say, "You gentlemen have performed a public service
in calling attention to a serious ambiguity in this statute. Though
the arguments are about equally balanced, I hereby resolve your
dispute about the meaning of the statute in favor of the contention
made by A . Since, however, I do not wish to make retrospective
law, this interpretation shall be effective only for situations that
may arise in the future. As for the specific controversy between
you two, I leave that undecided." A soliloquizing ethics will, of
course, have little occasion to recognize or deal with problems of
this sort; a morality concerned with social interaction will in-
evitably confront them and solve them as best it can, which means
that it will often be forced to weigh the advantages and disadvan-
49. Ibid.
240
A REPLY TO CRITICS
50. In Anatomy of the Law (1968), pp. 84-1 12, 1 have attempted a com-
parison in these terms between the Anglo-American common law and
systems based on comprehensive codifications.
51. Supra n. 34.
241
THE MORALITY OF LAW
tradition of natural law. Yet as one writer has recently pointed
out, 52 Aquinas in some measure recognized and dealt with all
eight of the principles of legality discussed in my second chapter.
I know of no writer in the positivist vein who has concerned him-
self in more than a perfunctory way with the general problem of
52. Lewis, "The High Court: Final ... but Fallible," 19 Western Re-
serve Law Review 528-643, at p. 565 (1968). (It may be stretching things
a bit to say that Aquinas recognized the principle of congruity between
official action and declared rule.)
242
.
243
THE MORALITY OF LAW
Grunbaum, Church & State 473-75 (1966?).
Hanft, 43 North Carolina Law Review 238-44 (1964).
Hart, 78 Harvard Law Review 1281-96 (1965).
Hosking, 40 California State Bar Journal 90-94 ( 1 965).
Hughes, 17 Stanford Law Review 547-59 (1965).
Jacobs, F. G., 10 N.S., Juridical Review 92-93 (Edinburgh,
1965).
Jacobs, Francis, 75 N.S. Mind 605-07 (1966).
Johnson, 33 Tennessee Law Review 563-65 (1966).
129 Justice of the Peace and Local Government Review 44 (Lon-
don, Jan. 16, 1965).
Kurczewski, Studia Filozoficzne 274-80 (Warsaw, 1967).
235 Law Times 502 (London, Sept. 4, 1964).
Lewis, 17 Western Reserve Law Review 349-57 (1965).
McDowell, 44 Boston University Law Review 587-90 (1964).
Mandelbaum, 10 New York Law Forum 648-50 (1964).
Meyer, 10 McGill Law Journal 380-83 (1964).
Montrose, 1 6 University of Toronto Law Journal 45 1-55 (1966).
Morison, 5 Sydney Law Review 181-85 (1965).
Perelman, 10 Natural Law Forum 242-45 (1965).
Review of Metaphysics, p. 367 (December 1966).
Rose, 39 Tulane Law Review 387-95 (1965).
Savarese, 53 Georgetown Law Journal 250-58 (1964).
Schwartz, 359 Annals of the American Academy of Political and
Social Sciences 190 (1965).
Selznick, 30 American Sociological Review 947-48 (1965).
Summers, 1 8 Journal of Legal Education 1-27 (1965).
Tucker, 40 Indiana Law Journal 270-79 (1965).
Tunc, 3 Revue Internationale de Droit Compare 519-21 (1965).
Wasserstrom, 19 Rutgers Law Review 581-86 (1965).
Woozley, 16 Philosophical Quarterly 89-90 (St. Andrews Univ.,
1966).
Wroblewski, Ruch Prawniczy, Ekonomiczny i Socjologiczny 224-
30(Poznan,1966).
244
APPENDIX: THE PROBLEM OF
THE GRUDGE INFORMER
245
APPENDIX
many people away from the polls who would have voted against
the party.
When power they took no steps to
the Purple Shirts arrived in
repeal the ancient Constitution or any of its provisions. They also
left intact the Civil and Criminal Codes and the Code of Pro-
246
THE GRUDGE INFORMER
still influenced by prerevolutionary conceptions, wanted to ac-
complish this by a statute declaring their goods forfeited for
criminal acts. Another wanted to do by compelling the owners
it
247
APPENDIX
to conference. At the conference the five Deputies speak in turn
as follows:
248
THE GRUDGE INFORMER
to repeal them. If we now seek to unscramble the acts of the
Purple Shirt regime, declaring this judgment invalid, that statute
void, this sentence excessive, we shall be doing exactly the thing
we most condemn in them. I recognize that it will take courage
249
APPENDIX
this whole dark, lawless chapter of our history behind us like
ideology. The legal questions that arose in this area were handled
by the courts much as they had been formerly and much as they
are being handled today. It would invite an intolerable chaos if
we were to declare everything that happened under the Purple
Shirts to be without legal basis. On the other hand, we certainly
cannot say that the murders committed by members
in the streets
of the party acting under orders from the Headman were lawful
simply because the party had achieved control of the government
and its chief had become President of the Republic. If we must
250
THE GRUDGE INFORMER
condemn its members, it would
the criminal acts of the party and
seem absurd uphold every act which happened to be canalized
to
through the apparatus of a government that had become, in effect,
the alter ego of the Purple Shirt Party. We must therefore, in this
situation, as in most human affairs, discriminate. Where the
Purple Shirt philosophy intruded and perverted the ad-
itself
in fact, Purple Shirtism itself, pure and simple. We like this law,
251
APPENDIX
so let us enforce it. We like this judgment, let it stand. This law
we don't like, therefore it never was a law at all. This govern-
mental act we disapprove, be deemed a nullity. If we pro-
let it
ceed this way, we take toward the laws and acts of the Purple
Shirt government precisely the unprincipled attitude they took
toward the laws and acts of the government they supplanted. We
shall have chaos, with every judge and every prosecuting attorney
a law unto himself. Instead of ending the abuses of the Purple
Shirt regime, my would perpetuate them.
colleague's proposal
There is only one way problem that is com-
of dealing with this
patible with our philosophy of law and government and that is
to deal with it by duly enacted law, I mean, by a special statute
directed toward it. Let us study this whole problem of the grudge
informer, get all the relevant facts, and draft a comprehensive
law dealing with it. We shall not then be twisting old laws to pur-
poses for which they were never intended. We shall furthermore
provide penalties appropriate to the offense and not treat every
informer as a murderer simply because the one he informed
against was ultimately executed. I admit that we shall encounter
some difficult problems of draftsmanship. Among other things,
we shall have to assign a definite legal meaning to 'grudge' and
that will not be easy. We should not be deterred by these diffi-
culties, however, from adopting the only course that will lead
us out of a condition of lawless, personal rule."
252
THE GRUDGE INFORMER
would this statute provide? One of my colleagues speaks of some-
one who had failed for five days to report a loss of his identifica-
tion papers. My colleague implies that the judicial sentence im-
posed for that offense, namely death, was so utterly disproportion-
ate as to be clearly wrong. But we must remember that at that
time the underground movement against the Purple Shirts was
mounting in intensity and that the Purple Shirts were being ha-
rassed constantly by people with false identification papers. From
their point of view they had a real problem, and the only objec-
tion we can make to their solution of it (other than the fact that
we didn't want them to solve was that they acted with some-
it)
what more rigor than the occasion seemed to demand. How will
my colleague deal with this case in his statute, and with all of
its cousins and second cousins? Will he deny the existence of any
need for law and order under the Purple Shirt regime? I will not
go further into the difficulties involved in drafting this proposed
statute, since they are evident enough to anyone who reflects. I
shall instead turn to my own solution. It has been said on very
respectable authority that the main purpose of the criminal law
is to give an outlet to the human instinct for revenge. There are
253
INDEX
Absolute liability. See Strict liability judicial review, 125-29; law con-
Adams, Brooks, 73 n. cerning such review a branch of
Adamson v. California, 102 n. constitutional law, 128-29
Adjudication: not indispensable to a Attainder, bills of, 52 n.
legal system, 55-56; legal system Auden, W. H., 152
may take its start in, 130-31, Austin, J. L., 195-97
144-45: not suited to allocative Austin, John, 48-49, 53 n., 63 n.,
tasks, 46,171-75; not suited to 97, 110, 192, 215-16 n., 225-26
problems of institutional design,
177-81 Baker v. Carr, 178
255
INDEX
Bonham's Case, 99-101 morality of law, 102-06; judicial
Boorstin, D. J., 146 n. review of disciplinary action in
Brandt, R. B., 5 n. private associations as a branch
Bridgman, P. W., 119 of, 128-29
Brown, Jethro, 49 n. Constitutions, virtues and defects of
written, 114-15
Caligula, 93 Contraception and the law, 153
Campbell, Lord, 86 n. Contradictions in the law, 36, 65-
Censors, boards of, in early Ameri- 70,92,99, 101-02, 111-13, 115,
can history, 177 130; between institutions, 100-
Chafee, Zechariah, 129 01; as affecting managerial or-
Civil Aeronautics Board, 46, 171- ders, 208; whether presenting
75 moral issue, 238
Clarity of laws, 36, 43, 45, 63-65, Cook, W. W., 137 n.
92, 102-03, 107, 115; as affecting Corbin, A. L., 134 n., 136 n.
managerial direction, 208; as pre- Council on Tribunals, 177
senting moral issue in adminis- Criminal law: and retroactivity, 59;
tration of a legal system, 212-14 strict liability under, 77-78; and
Clark, Tom, 165 human responsibility, 163-67;
Cohen, Marshall, 191, 197, 201, abuses of rehabilitative ideal in,
256
INDEX
Duty, concept of, among Greeks, 5; 193-95; as affecting managerial
in primitive society, 143-44. See direction, 209; as essential to
also Morality of duty Rule of Law, 209-10
Dworkin, Ronald, 189, 190, 192, George III, 156
198-99, 201, 221-22, 224 n., Golden Rule, 20-21
238-39, 241 Good Samaritan, 182-83
Gottlieb, Gidon, 224 n.
Economics: definitions of, 15-17; Gough, J. W., 99
parallels with morality, 17-30; Graham v. Goodcell, 55 n.
adjudication an inept means for Gray, J. C, 49 n., 52 n., 83-84, 97,
solving task of, 170-76. See also 112,226
Exchange; Marginal Utility; Greeks, conception of morality
Reciprocity among, 5, 13-15
Ellesmere, Lord, 68 n.
Emmet, Dorothy, 239 Hale, R. L., 52 n., 103 n.
Escarra, Jean, 143 n. Hall, 78 n.
J.,
257
INDEX
54-55, 62, 107, 123, 155, 158 97; special attention during 17th
Hochman, C. B., 52 n. century, 99-101; as clarifying re-
Hoebel, A., 108, 206 lation of law and morality, 131-
Hohfeldian analysis, 134, 136-37 32; meaningless when law is ab-
Holmes, O. W., 29, 106, 1 19, 152 stracted from any general pur-
Holt, Lord, 88-89 pose, 147-48; interaction with
Honors. See Rewards substantive aims, 153-67; rela-
Hughes, Graham, 189 n., 224 n. tion to efficacy of law, 155-57;
relation to substantive justice,
Impossibility, laws commanding an, 157-59; necessarily infringed by
36-37, 45, 53-54, 70-79; liability laws directed toward undefinable
founded on fault, 71-72; liability evils, 159-62; requires view of
founded on a wrongful intent, man as responsible agent, 162-
72-73; liability based on unjust 67; whether entitled to be called
enrichment, 73-74; strict civil "morality," 200-23; as affecting
liability, 75-77; strict criminal managerial direction, 208-09.
liability, 77-78; not always dis- See also Clarity of laws; Con-
tinguishable from laws imposing gruence of official action with de-
severe hardship, 79; laws requir- clared rule; Constancy of the law
ing political or religious belief, through time; Contradictions in
79, 92, 99, 100; impossibility of the law; Generality of law; Im-
obedience as affecting managerial laws commanding an;
possibility,
orders, 208 Promulgation; Retroactive laws
Intention of laws, to whom Internal morality of science, 120-
ascribed, 86-87 21
Interaction, as an element in law, International law, 232-34, 236-37
39^0, 191, 193-95, 220-24, Interpretation:as an aspect of
233-34 maintaining congruence between
Internal morality of law: primarily official action and declared rule,
a morality of aspiration, 41-44; 82-91; as demanding creative
whether reducible to fewer than role of the judge, 87; of the
eight principles, 70 n.; as applied
Statute of Frauds, 88-89; of
to secret legislative orders, 91-
laws designed to prevent a "re-
92; departures from, tend to be-
turn of the old saloon," 89-91;
come cumulative, 92; its demands
theories of, implied in dispute
relaxed when laws correspond to
common views of right and with critics, 224-32; of custom,
wrong, 50, 92-93; demands vary 228-29; as affected by antinomies
with branch of law, 93; includes among principles of legality,
258
INDEX
expectations within legal system, hierarchic ordering of command,
231-32 110-13, 118, 148-49
Interstate Commerce Commission, Legal morality. See Internal mor-
175 ality of law
Israeli Law of Return, 162 Legality, principles of, some respect
for essential for existence of law,
Jefferson, Thomas, 79, 146 197-200. See also Internal moral-
Jhering, Rudolph von, 66 n. ity of law
Jones, J. W., 5 n. Lewan, Kenneth M., 189 n.
Judge-made law, problem of main- Lewis, Ovid, 242 n.
taining congruence with declared Lilburne, John, 33, 70, 217-18
rule, 82.See also Adjudication Lindsay, A. D., 5 n.
Judicial office,law does not in all Liquor laws, 89-91
cases require, 55-56. See also Ad- Llewellyn, Karl, 192
judication Lloyd, D., 127 n.
Jurisdiction over jobs in industrial
management, 219 Macbeath, A., 5 n.
259
INDEX
260
1
INDEX
261
INDEX
262