Reading The Visual by Mark Thorsby
Reading The Visual by Mark Thorsby
Reading The Visual by Mark Thorsby
Abstract
To speak of visual literacies is to invoke an analogy between the signs of a
language and the domain of the visual. And while a close parallel between
these two fields of perceptive activity is certainly comprehensible, there are
peculiar logical differences between linguistic and visual literacies that must
be conceptually delineated prior to the task of ‘reading’ the visual. This
paper examines and articulates the limits of the analog between these two
modes of perception and interpretation by drawing from the work of both
Ludwig Wittgenstein and Maurice Merleau-Ponty. By activating an
investigation into the phenomenological differences between seeing and
speaking, it becomes apparent that the body itself plays a crucial role in the
former that is not readily transmitted in a comparison with the later. Namely,
the interpretation of the visual is not simply a matter of ‘reading’ signs, but
also fundamentally evokes, involves, and references the activity of the body.
As such, sound interpretation requires more than just the recognition,
negotiation, or juxtaposition of cultural symbols; an acute awareness of the
bodily relation between the perceiver and ‘text’ is critical. Once this
conceptual differentiation is made, I then turn to and conclude with a
discussion on spatiality and its relation to visuacy in architecture. Every
architectural space contextualizes the body; thus adding, reorganizing, or
possibly transforming the texture, perception, and meaning of any visual
media. The museum, as an architectural motif, perfectly embodies the bodily
relation to the visual, although we might as easily speak of the hospital, the
cinema, the highway, or the garden. In essence, to be visually literate is to be
spatially aware.
*****
1. Introduction
At its core, philosophy can be understood as a worry and
puzzlement over the basic problems, possibilities, and manifestations of
meaning. The question I would like to entertain today, however related, is
to ask how exactly things that are perceived visually are meaningful. It is
2 Reading The Visual: Language, Body, & Space
______________________________________________________________
actually quite peculiar, for meaning and visual perception seem to occur
simultaneously. When one looks out over a landscape and sees a house in the
distance, they do not interpret what they see in a procedure of input-output
and, as it were, calculate that due to a certain pattern of sense datum that an
object called a house stands before them. No, not at all – one simply sees the
house; and this is to already understand a particular visual field. In a reverse
sense, we could consider the fact that art professors constantly must counsel
their novice students to paint what they see and not what they think they see.
What this reveals is that meaning and visual acuity are delivered together. So
if we are to ask what it means to be visually literate, then we will need to
offer an explanation that can make phenomenological sense of the fact that
meaning and visuacy are integrally interwoven.
To speak of visual literacy is to evoke an analogy between the signs
of a language and the domain of the visual. In A Primer of Visual Literacy,
Donis Dondis writes that “language is a means of expression and
communication and, therefore, is a parallel system to visual
communication.”1 But there are limitations to the parallel between visuacy
and the hermeneutics of a language. Certainly we might speak of the visual
field as a text to be read, but this sort of analog, taken alone, does not fully
encapsulate the phenomenology of visual understanding and could lead to a
false view about how meaning manifests itself in perception. What is at issue
here in the limit of the analog is the role of the body. As Gary Madison has
argued, “We must recognize the existence of a body-subject: we must view
the body as our living bond with the world and as the umbilical cord which
attaches us to it.”2 If we are to gain a fully satisfactory picture as to how
meaning and visual perceptions are integrally interwoven we will need to
supplement our account with a meditation on the role and centrality of the
body within visual perception. I argue that because the body is the locus of
spatial horizons for any thinking and perceiving human being upon which
visual perception is a priori dependant, we can say that to be visually literate
is to be spatially and bodily aware.
French phenomenologist Maurice Merleau-Ponty stands as the most
outstanding philosopher who has gone further than any other in situating the
centrality of the body within visual perception. By pulling from his
philosophical vernacular and phenomenological inquiry in his
Phenomenology of Perception we discover the enormous importance that the
body has for the very possibility of visual meaningfulness. At one section of
that text he writes:
3. Bodily Spatiality
When we take the phenomenology of the body seriously we discover that not
only is the body central to an understanding of visual literacy but that the
body itself is the criterion for spatiality. To be visually literate is to be at
home in a form of life in which the body's role is familiar within a series of
spatial involvements. In essence, to be visually literate is to be spatially
aware.
Notes
1
DA Dondis, A Primer of Visual Literacy, MIT Press, Cambridge, 1973, p. 182.
2
G Madison, The Phenomenology of Merleau-Ponty, Ohio University Press, Athens, 1973, p.21.
3
Ibid. p. 172.
4
L Wittgenstein, The Blue and Brown Books, Harper & Row, New York, 1958. p. 5.
5
Ibid.
6
G Free, “Language, Speech and Writing: Merleau-Ponty and Derrida on Saussure,” Human Studies, Vol. 13, No. 4,
Springer, Netherlands, 1990 p. 293.
7
Ibid. 297.
8
Ibid. p. 14.
9
S. Mollin, Merleau-Ponty's Philosophy, Yale University Press, New Haven, 1979. p. 12.
10
Madison, p. 21-22.
11
Merleau-Ponty, The Phenomenology of Perception. p. 369.
12
Ibid, p. 78.
13
Madison, p. 23, p. 29.
14
J Appleton, “Museums for 'The People'?” Museums and their Communities, Ed. Sheila Watson, Routledge, New York,
1997, p. 115-116.
15
Merleau-Ponty, “Indirect Language and the Voices of Silence.” p. 62.
16
An interesting example would be to think about The Museum of Natural History in New York, which houses
Peloponnesian totem poles. The totem pole in its home space would not have been housed at all and would likely imply an
idea of moving up into the heavens. But when the same artefact is enclosed in a space with a ceiling, the resonance of
meaning is likely to be lost for the thousands of visitors who visit the museum each month. The space of the museum
impacts and contextualizes the litany of ways in which one might be able to read that text.
17
M Lange, Merleau-Ponty's Phenomenology of Perception. Florida State UP, Tallahassee,1989. p. 47.
Bibliography
Appleton, J., “Museums for ‘The People’?” Museums and their Communities. Ed. Sheila Watson. Routledge, New York,
1997. pp. 114-126.
Cavel, S., “The Availability of Wittgenstein’s Later Philosophy.” The Philosphical Review. Vol. 71, No. 2. Duke
University Press, Durham, 1962. pp. 69-93.
Free, G. “Language, Speech and Writing: Merleau-Ponty and Derrida on Saussure.” Human Studies. Vol. 13, No. 4.
Springer, Netherlands, 2004. pp. 293-301.
Heidegger, M., Being and Time. Trans. John Macquarrie & Edward Robinson. Blackwell, New York, 1962.
Lang, M., Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology of Perception. Florida State UP, Tallahassee, 1989.
Madison, G., The Phenomenology of Merleau-Ponty. Ohio University Press, Athens, 1973.
Merleau-Ponty, M., “Indirect Language and the Voices of Silence.” Signs. Trans. Richard McCleary. Northwestern UP,
Chicago, 1964. pp. 39-83.
---, The Phenomenology of Perception. Trans. Colin Smith. Routledge, London, 2005.
Wittgenstein, L., The Blue and Brown Books. Harper & Row, New York, 1958.
---, Philosophical Investigations. Trans. GEM Anscombe. Macmillan Company, New York, 1953.