Judiciary Impeachment Process

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 55

Table of Contents

I. Introduction ............................................................................................................... 1
II. Summary of Principal Conclusions ...................................................................... 2
III. The Purpose of Impeachment ............................................................................... 6
IV. Impeachable Offenses .......................................................................................... 10
A. Lessons from British and Early American History .......................................... 11
B. Treason and Bribery ............................................................................................ 13
1. Impeachable Treason.......................................................................................... 14
2. Impeachable Bribery .......................................................................................... 14
C. Abuse, Betrayal & Corruption ........................................................................... 17
1. Abuse of Power .................................................................................................. 17
2. Betrayal of the National Interest Through Foreign Entanglements ................... 22
3. Corruption of Office or Elections....................................................................... 24
D. Conclusion ............................................................................................................ 28
V. The Criminality Issue .............................................................................................. 31
A. History ................................................................................................................... 31
B. Constitutional Text and Structure ..................................................................... 34
C. The Purpose of Impeachment ............................................................................. 36
D. The Limited Relevance of Criminality ............................................................... 38
VI. Addressing Fallacies About Impeachment ........................................................ 38
A. The Impeachment Process .................................................................................. 38
B. Evidentiary Considerations and Presidential Obstruction .............................. 41
C. Abuse of Presidential Power is Impeachable..................................................... 44
D. Presidential Pretexts Need Not Be Accepted at Face Value ............................. 47
E. Attempted Presidential Misconduct Is Impeachable ........................................ 49
F. Impeachment is Part of Democratic Governance ............................................. 51
VII. Conclusion ............................................................................................................ 52
Foreword by Mr. Nadler
I am pleased to make available a report prepared by the majority staff addressing
constitutional grounds for presidential impeachment. The staff of the Committee on the
Judiciary first produced a report addressing this topic in 1974, during the impeachment
inquiry into President Richard M. Nixon, and that report was updated by the majority and
minority staff in 1998, during the impeachment inquiry into President William Jefferson
Clinton. Over the past several decades, however, legal scholars and historians have
undertaken a substantial study of the subject. The earlier reports remain useful points of
reference, but no longer reflect the best available learning on questions relating to
presidential impeachment. Further, they do not address several issues of constitutional law
with particular relevance to the ongoing impeachment inquiry respecting President Donald
J. Trump. For that reason, the majority staff of the Committee have prepared this report for
the use of the Committee on the Judiciary.

The views and conclusions contained in the report are staff views and do not
necessarily reflect those of the Committee on the Judiciary or any of its members.

Amy Rutkin, Chief of Staff


Perry Apelbaum, Staff Director and Chief Counsel
Aaron Hiller, Deputy Chief Counsel and Chief Oversight Counsel
Barry Berke, Special Counsel
Norman Eisen, Special Counsel
Arya Hariharan, Deputy Chief Oversight Counsel
James Park, Chief Constitution Counsel
Joshua Matz, Counsel

Sophia Brill, Counsel


Charles Gayle, Counsel
Maggie Goodlander, Counsel
Sarah Istel, Counsel
Ted Kalo, Special Counsel
Matthew Morgan, Counsel
Matthew N. Robinson, Counsel
Kerry Tirrell, Counsel
Rachel Calanni, Professional Staff
William S. Emmons, Professional Staff
Priyanka Mara, Professional Staff
Madeline Strasser, Chief Clerk
Constitutional Grounds for Presidential Impeachment
Report by the Staff of the Committee on the Judiciary

I. Introduction

Our President holds the ultimate public trust. He is vested with powers so great that
they frightened the Framers of our Constitution; in exchange, he swears an oath to faithfully
execute the laws that hold those powers in check. This oath is no formality. The Framers
foresaw that a faithless President could destroy their experiment in democracy. As George
Mason warned at the Constitutional Convention, held in Philadelphia in 1787, “if we do
not provide against corruption, our government will soon be at an end.”1 Mason evoked a
well-known historical truth: when corrupt motives take root, they drive an endless thirst
for power and contempt for checks and balances. It is then only the smallest of steps toward
acts of oppression and assaults on free and fair elections. A President faithful only to
himself—who will sell out democracy and national security for his own personal
advantage—is a danger to every American. Indeed, he threatens America itself.

Impeachment is the Constitution’s final answer to a President who mistakes himself


for a monarch. Aware that power corrupts, our Framers built other guardrails against that
error. The Constitution thus separates governmental powers, imposes an oath of faithful
execution, prohibits profiting from office, and guarantees accountability through regular
elections. But the Framers were not naïve. They knew, and feared, that someday a corrupt
executive might claim he could do anything he wanted as President. Determined to protect
our democracy, the Framers built a safety valve into the Constitution: A President can be
removed from office if the House of Representatives approves articles of impeachment
charging him with “Treason, Bribery, or other high Crimes and Misdemeanors,” and if
two-thirds of the Senate votes to find the President guilty of such misconduct after a trial.2

As Justice Joseph Story recognized, “the power of impeachment is not one expected
in any government to be in constant or frequent exercise.”3 When faced with credible
evidence of extraordinary wrongdoing, however, it is incumbent on the House to
investigate and determine whether impeachment is warranted. On October 31, 2019, the
House approved H. Res. 660, which, among other things, confirmed the preexisting inquiry
“into whether sufficient grounds exist for the House of Representatives to exercise its
Constitutional power to impeach Donald John Trump, President of the United States of
America.”4

1
1 Max Farrand, ed., The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, 392 (1911) (hereinafter, “Records of
the Federal Convention”).
2
U.S. CONST. Art. II, § 4; id. Art. I, § 5, cl. 5; id. Art. I, § 3, cl. 6.
3
2 Joseph Story, Commentaries on the Constitution of the United States, 221 (1833).
4
H.Res. 660, 116th Cong. (2019).

1
The Judiciary Committee now faces questions of extraordinary importance. In prior
impeachment inquiries addressing allegations of Presidential misconduct, the staff of the
Judiciary Committee has prepared reports addressing relevant principles of constitutional
law.5 Consistent with that practice, and to assist the Committee and the House in working
toward a resolution of the questions before them, this staff report explores the meaning of
the words in the Constitution’s Impeachment Clause: “Treason, Bribery, or other high
Crimes and Misdemeanors.” It also describes the impeachment process and addresses
several mistaken claims about impeachment that have recently drawn public notice.

II. Summary of Principal Conclusions

Our principal conclusions are as follows.

The purpose of impeachment. As the Framers deliberated in Philadelphia, Mason


posed a profound question: “Shall any man be above justice?”6 By authorizing Congress
to remove Presidents for egregious misconduct, the Framers offered a resounding answer.
As Mason elaborated, “some mode of displacing an unfit magistrate is rendered
indispensable by the fallibility of those who choose, as well as by the corruptibility of the
man chosen.”7 Unlike Britain’s monarch, the President would answer personally—to
Congress and thus to the Nation—if he engaged in serious wrongdoing. Alexander
Hamilton explained that the President would have no more resemblance to the British king
than to “the Grand Seignior, to the khan of Tartary, [or] to the Man of the Seven
Mountains.”8 Whereas “the person of the king of Great Britain is sacred and inviolable,”
the President of the United States could be “impeached, tried, and upon conviction . . .
removed from office.”9 Critically, though, impeachment goes no further. It results only in
loss of political power. This speaks to the nature of impeachment: it exists not to inflict
punishment for past wrongdoing, but rather to save the Nation from misconduct that
endangers democracy and the rule of law. Thus, the ultimate question in an impeachment
is whether leaving the President in our highest office imperils the Constitution.10

Impeachable offenses. The Framers were careful students of history and knew that
threats to democracy can take many forms. They feared would-be monarchs, but also
warned against fake populists, charismatic demagogues, and corrupt kleptocrats. The
Framers thus intended impeachment to reach the full spectrum of Presidential misconduct
5
STAFF OF H. COMM. ON THE JUDICIARY, 93D CONG., CONSTITUTIONAL GROUNDS FOR PRESIDENTIAL
IMPEACHMENT 4 (Comm. Print 1974) (hereinafter “Constitutional Grounds for Presidential Impeachment
(1974)”); STAFF OF H. COMM. ON THE JUDICIARY, 105TH CONG., CONSTITUTIONAL GROUNDS FOR
PRESIDENTIAL IMPEACHMENT: MODERN PRECEDENTS (Comm. Print 1998) (hereinafter “Constitutional
Grounds for Presidential Impeachment: Modern Precedents (1998)”).
6
2 Farrand, Records of the Federal Convention, at 65.
7
1 Farrand, Records of the Federal Convention, at 86.
8
Alexander Hamilton, Federalist No. 69, 444 (Benjamin Fletcher Wright ed., 2004).
9
Id.
10
See Laurence H. Tribe, American Constitutional Law 155 (3d ed. 2000).

2
that menaced the Constitution. Because they could not anticipate and prohibit every threat
a President might someday pose, the Framers adopted a standard sufficiently general and
flexible to meet unknown future circumstances: “Treason, Bribery, or other high Crimes
and Misdemeanors.” This standard was proposed by Mason and was meant, in his words,
to capture all manner of “great and dangerous offenses” against the Constitution.11

Treason and bribery. Applying traditional tools of interpretation puts a sharper


point on this definition of “high Crimes and Misdemeanors.” For starters, it is useful to
consider the two impeachable offenses that the Framers identified for us. “Treason” is an
unforgiveable betrayal of the Nation and its security. A President who levies war against
the government, or lends aid and comfort to our enemies, cannot persist in office; a
President who betrays the Nation once will most certainly do so again. “Bribery,” in turn,
sounds in abuse of power. Impeachable bribery occurs when the President offers, solicits,
or accepts something of personal value to influence his own official actions. By rendering
such bribery impeachable, the Framers sought to ensure that the Nation could expel a leader
who would sell out the interests of “We the People” for his own personal gain.

In identifying “other high Crimes and Misdemeanors,” we are guided by the text
and structure of the Constitution, the records of the Constitutional Convention and state
ratifying debates, and the history of impeachment practice. These sources demonstrate that
the Framers principally intended impeachment for three overlapping forms of Presidential
wrongdoing: (1) abuse of power, (2) betrayal of the nation through foreign entanglements,
and (3) corruption of office and elections. Any one of these violations of the public trust
justifies impeachment; when combined in a single course of conduct, they state the
strongest possible case for impeachment and removal from office.

Abuse of power. There are at least as many ways to abuse power as there are powers
vested in the President. It would thus be an exercise in futility to attempt a list of every
abuse of power constituting “high Crimes and Misdemeanors.” That said, impeachable
abuse of power can be roughly divided into two categories: engaging in official acts
forbidden by law and engaging in official action with motives forbidden by law. As James
Iredell explained, “the president would be liable to impeachments [if] he had … acted from
some corrupt motive or other.”12 This warning echoed Edmund Randolph’s teaching that
impeachment must be allowed because “the Executive will have great opportunitys of
abusing his power.”13 President Richard Nixon’s conduct has come to exemplify
impeachable abuse of power: he acted with corrupt motives in obstructing justice and using
official power to target his political opponents, and his decision to unlawfully defy
subpoenas issued by the House impeachment inquiry was unconstitutional on its face.

11
2 Farrand, Records of the Federal Convention, at 550.
12
Quoted in Background and History of Impeachment: Hearing before the Subcomm. On the Constitution of
the H. Comm on the Judiciary, 105th Cong. 49 (1999) (hereinafter “1998 Background and History of
Impeachment Hearing”).
13
2 Farrand, Records of the Federal Convention at 67.

3
Betrayal involving foreign powers. As much as the Framers feared abuse, they
feared betrayal still more. That anxiety is shot through their discussion of impeachment—
and explains why “Treason” heads the Constitution’s list of impeachable offenses. James
Madison put it simply: the President “might betray his trust to foreign powers.”14 Although
the Framers did not intend impeachment for good faith disagreements on matters of
diplomacy, they were explicit that betrayal of the Nation through schemes with foreign
powers justified that remedy. Indeed, foreign interference in the American political system
was among the gravest dangers feared by the Founders of our Nation and the Framers of
our Constitution. In his farewell address, George Washington thus warned Americans “to
be constantly awake, since history and experience prove that foreign influence is one of the
most baneful foes of republican government.”15 And in a letter to Thomas Jefferson, John
Adams wrote: “You are apprehensive of foreign Interference, Intrigue, Influence. So am
I.—But, as often as Elections happen, the danger of foreign Influence recurs.”16

Corruption. Lurking beneath the Framers’ discussion of impeachment was the most
ancient and implacable foe of democracy: corruption. The Framers saw no shortage of
threats to the Republic, and sought to guard against them, “but the big fear underlying all
the small fears was whether they’d be able to control corruption.”17 As Madison put it,
corruption “might be fatal to the Republic.”18 This was not just a matter of thwarting bribes;
it was a far more expansive challenge. The Framers celebrated civic virtue and love of
country; they wrote rules to ensure officials would not use public power for private gain.

Impeachment was seen as especially necessary for Presidential conduct corrupting


our system of political self-government. That concern arose in multiple contexts as the
Framers debated the Constitution. The most important was the risk that Presidents would
place their personal interest in re-election above our bedrock national commitment to
democracy. The Framers knew that corrupt leaders concentrate power by manipulating
elections and undercutting adversaries. They despised King George III, who “resorted to
influencing the electoral process and the representatives in Parliament in order to gain [his]
treacherous ends.”19 That is why the Framers deemed electoral treachery a central ground
for impeachment. The very premise of the Constitution is that the American people govern
themselves, and choose their leaders, through free and fair elections. When the President
concludes that elections might threaten his grasp on power and abuses his office to sabotage
opponents or invite inference, he rejects democracy itself and must be removed.

14
Id., at 65-66.
15
George Washington Farewell Address (1796), George Washington Papers, Series 2, Letterbooks 1754-
1799: Letterbook 24, April 3, 1793 - March 3, 1797, Library of Congress.
16
To Thomas Jefferson from John Adams, 6 December 1787, National Archives, Founders Online.
17
Zephyr Teachout, Corruption in America: From Benjamin Franklin’s Snuff Box to Citizens United 57
(2014).
18
2 Farrand, Records of the Federal Convention, at 66.
19
Gordon S. Wood, The Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787 33 (1998).

4
Conclusions regarding the nature of impeachable offenses. In sum, history teaches
that “high Crimes and Misdemeanors” referred mainly to acts committed by public
officials, using their power or privileges, that inflicted grave harm on our political order.
Such great and dangerous offenses included treason, bribery, serious abuse of power,
betrayal of the national interest through foreign entanglements, and corruption of office and
elections. They were unified by a clear theme: officials who abused, abandoned, or sought
personal benefit from their public trust—and who threatened the rule of law if left in
power—faced impeachment. Each of these acts, moreover, should be plainly wrong to
reasonable officials and persons of honor. When a political official uses political power in
ways that substantially harm our political system, Congress can strip them of that power.

Within these parameters, and guided by fidelity to the Constitution, the House must
judge whether the President’s misconduct is grave enough to require impeachment. That
step must never be taken lightly. It is a momentous act, justified only when the President’s
full course of conduct, assessed without favor or prejudice, is “seriously incompatible with
either the constitutional form and principles of our government or the proper performance
of constitutional duties of the presidential office.”20 But when that high standard is met, the
Constitution calls the House to action—and the House, in turn, must rise to the occasion.
In such cases, a decision not to impeach can harm democracy and set an ominous precedent.

The criminality issue. It is occasionally suggested that Presidents can be impeached


only if they have committed crimes. That position was rejected in President Nixon’s case,
and then rejected again in President Clinton’s, and should be rejected once more. Offenses
against the Constitution are different than offenses against the criminal code. Some crimes,
like jaywalking, are not impeachable. And some forms of misconduct may offend both the
Constitution and the criminal law. Impeachment and criminality must therefore be assessed
separately—even though the President’s commission of indictable crimes may further
support a case for impeachment and removal. Ultimately, the House must judge whether a
President’s conduct offends and endangers the Constitution itself.

Fallacies about impeachment. In the final section of this Report, we briefly address
six falsehoods about impeachment that have recently drawn public notice.

First, contrary to mistaken claims otherwise, we demonstrate that the current


impeachment inquiry has complied in every respect with the Constitution, the Rules of the
House, and historic practice and precedent of the House.

Second, we address several evidentiary matters. The House impeachment inquiry


has compiled substantial direct and circumstantial evidence bearing on the issues at hand.
Nonetheless, President Trump has objected that some of the evidence gathered by the
House comes from witnesses lacking first-hand knowledge of his conduct. But in the same
breath, he has unlawfully ordered many witnesses with first-hand knowledge to defy House

20
REPORT OF THE COMMITTEE ON THE JUDICIARY, IMPEACHMENT OF RICHARD M. NIXON, PRESIDENT OF THE
UNITED STATES, H.R. REP. NO. 93-1305 8 (1974) (hereinafter “Committee Report on Nixon Articles of
Impeachment (1974)”).

5
subpoenas. As we show, President Trump’s assertions regarding the evidence before the
House are misplaced as a matter of constitutional law and common sense.

Third, we consider President Trump’s claim that his actions are protected because
of his right under Article II of the Constitution “to do whatever I want as president.”21 This
claim is wrong, and profoundly so, because our Constitution rejects pretensions to
monarchy and binds Presidents with law. That is true even of powers vested exclusively in
the chief executive. If those powers are invoked for corrupt reasons, or wielded in an
abusive manner harming the constitutional system, the President is subject to impeachment
for “high Crimes and Misdemeanors.” This is a core premise of the impeachment power.

Fourth, we address whether the House must accept at face value President Trump’s
claim that his motives were not corrupt. In short, no. When the House probes a President’s
state of mind, its mandate is to find the facts. That means evaluating the President’s account
of his motives to see if it rings true. The question is not whether the President’s conduct
could have resulted from permissible motives. It is whether the President’s real reasons,
the ones in his mind at the time, were legitimate. Where the House discovers persuasive
evidence of corrupt wrongdoing, it is entitled to rely upon that evidence to impeach.

Fifth, we explain that attempted Presidential wrongdoing is impeachable. Mason


himself said so at the Constitutional Convention, where he described “attempts to subvert
the Constitution” as a core example of “great and dangerous offenses.”22 Moreover, the
Judiciary Committee reached the same conclusion in President Nixon’s case. Historical
precedent thus confirms that ineptitude and insubordination do not afford the President a
defense to impeachment. A President cannot escape impeachment just because his scheme
to abuse power, betray the nation, or corrupt elections was discovered and abandoned.

Finally, we consider whether impeachment “nullifies” the last election or denies


voters their voice in the next one. The Framers themselves weighed this question. They
considered relying solely on elections—rather than impeachment—to remove wayward
Presidents. That position was firmly rejected. No President is entitled to persist in office
after committing “high Crimes and Misdemeanors,” and no one who voted for him in the
last election is entitled to expect he will do so. Where the President’s misconduct is aimed
at corrupting elections, relying on elections to solve the problem is no safeguard at all.

III. The Purpose of Impeachment

Freedom must not be taken for granted. It demands constant protection from leaders
whose taste of power sparks a voracious need for more. Time and again, republics have
fallen to officials who care little for the law and use the public trust for private gain.

21
Remarks by President Trump at Turning Point USA’s Teen Student Action Summit 2019, July 23, 2019,
THE WHITE HOUSE.
22
Cass R. Sunstein, Impeachment: A Citizen’s Guide 47 (2017).

6
The Framers of the Constitution knew this well. They saw corruption erode the
British constitution from within. They heard kings boast of their own excellence while
conspiring with foreign powers and consorting with shady figures. As talk of revolution
spread, they objected as King George III used favors and party politics to control
Parliament, aided by men who sold their souls and welcomed oppression.

The Framers risked their freedom, and their lives, to escape that monarchy. So did
their families and many of their friends. Together, they resolved to build a nation
committed to democracy and the rule of law—a beacon to the world in an age of
aristocracy. In the United States of America, “We the People” would be sovereign. We
would choose our own leaders and hold them accountable for how they exercised power.

As they designed our government at the Constitutional Convention, however, the


Framers faced a dilemma. On the one hand, many of them embraced the need for a powerful
chief executive. This had been cast into stark relief by the failure of the Nation’s very first
constitution, the Articles of Confederation, which put Congress in charge at the federal
level. The ensuing discord led James Madison to warn, “it is not possible that a government
can last long under these circumstances.”23 The Framers therefore created the Presidency.
A single official could lead the Nation with integrity, energy, and dispatch—and would be
held personally responsible for honoring that immense public trust.

Power, though, is a double-edged sword. “The power to do good meant also the
power to do harm, the power to serve the republic also meant the power to demean and
defile it.”24 The President would be vested with breathtaking authority. If corrupt motives
took root in his mind, displacing civic virtue and love of country, he could sabotage the
Constitution. That was clear to the Framers, who saw corruption as “the great force that
had undermined republics throughout history.”25 Obsessed with the fall of Rome, they
knew that corruption marked a leader’s path to abuse and betrayal. Mason thus emphasized,
“if we do not provide against corruption, our government will soon be at an end.” This
warning against corruption—echoed no fewer than 54 times by 15 delegates at the
Convention—extended far beyond bribes and presents. To the Framers, corruption was
fundamentally about the misuse of a position of public trust for any improper private
benefit. It thus went to the heart of their conception of public service. As a leading historian
recounts, “a corrupt political actor would either purposely ignore or forget the public good
as he used the reins of power.”26 Because men and women are not angels, corruption could
not be fully eradicated, even in virtuous officials, but “its power can be subdued with the
right combination of culture and political rules.”27

23
Quoted in id., at 27.
24
Arthur M. Schlesinger, Jr., The Imperial Presidency 415 (1973).
25
Elizabeth B. Wydra & Brianne J. Gorod, The First Magistrate in Foreign Pay, THE NEW REPUBLIC, Nov.
11 2019.
26
Teachout, Corruption in America, at 48.
27
Id., at 47.

7
The Framers therefore erected safeguards against Presidential abuse. Most
famously, they divided power among three branches of government that had the means and
motive to balance each other. “Ambition,” Madison reasoned, “must be made to counteract
ambition.”28 In addition, the Framers subjected the President to election every four years
and established the Electoral College (which, they hoped, would select virtuous, capable
leaders and refuse to re-elect corrupt or unpopular ones). Finally, the Framers imposed on
the President a duty to faithfully execute the laws—and required him to accept that duty in
a solemn oath.29 To the Framers, the concept of faithful execution was profoundly
important. It prohibited the President from taking official acts in bad faith or with corrupt
intent, as well as acts beyond what the law authorized.30

A few Framers would have stopped there. This minority feared vesting any branch
of government with the power to end a Presidency; as they saw it, even extreme Presidential
wrongdoing could be managed in the normal course (mainly by periodic elections).

That view was decisively rejected. As Professor Raoul Berger writes, “the Framers
were steeped in English history; the shades of despotic kings and conniving ministers
marched before them.”31 Haunted by those lessons, and convening in the shadow of
revolution, the Framers would not deny the Nation an escape from Presidents who deemed
themselves above the law. So they turned to a mighty constitutional power, one that offered
a peaceful and politically accountable method for ending an oppressive Presidency.

This was impeachment, a legal relic from the British past that over the preceding
century had found a new lease on life in the North American colonies. First deployed in
1376—and wielded in fits and starts over the following 400 years—impeachment allowed
Parliament to charge royal ministers with abuse, remove them from office, and imprison
them. Over time, impeachment helped Parliament shift power away from royal absolutism
and encouraged more politically accountable administration. In 1679, it was thus
proclaimed in the House of Commons that impeachment was “the chief institution for the
preservation of government.”32 That sentiment was echoed in the New World. Even as
Parliamentary impeachment fell into disuse by the early 1700s, colonists in Maryland,
Pennsylvania, and Massachusetts laid claim to this prerogative as part of their English
birthright. During the revolution, ten states ratified constitutions allowing the impeachment
of executive officials—and put that power to use in cases of corruption and abuse of

28
James Madison, Federalist No. 51, at 356.
29
U.S. CONST. Art. II, § 1, cl. 8.
30
See Andrew Kent, Ethan J. Leib & Jed Handelsman Shugerman, Faithful Execution and Article II, 132
HARV. L. REV. 2111- 2121 (2019).
31
Raoul Berger, Impeachment: The Constitutional Problems 4 (1974).
32
Id., at 1 n.2.

8
power.33 Unlike in Britain, though, American impeachment did not result in fines or
jailtime. It simply removed officials from political power when their conduct required it.

Familiar with the use of impeachment to address lawless officials, the Framers
offered a clear answer to Mason’s question at the Constitutional Convention, “Shall any
man be above justice”?34 As Mason himself explained, “some mode of displacing an unfit
magistrate is rendered indispensable by the fallibility of those who choose, as well as by
the corruptibility of the man chosen.”35 Future Vice President Elbridge Gerry agreed,
adding that impeachment repudiates the fallacy that our “chief magistrate could do no
wrong.”36 Benjamin Franklin, in turn, made the case that impeachment is “the best way”
to assess claims of serious wrongdoing by a President; without it, those accusations would
fester unresolved and invite enduring conflict over Presidential malfeasance.37

Unlike in Britain, the President would answer personally—to Congress and thus to
the Nation—for any serious wrongdoing. For that reason, as Hamilton later explained, the
President would have no more resemblance to the British king than to “the Grand Seignior,
to the khan of Tartary, [or] to the Man of the Seven Mountains.”38 Whereas “the person of
the king of Great Britain is sacred and inviolable,” the President could be “impeached,
tried, and upon conviction ... removed from office.”39

Of course, the decision to subject the President to impeachment was not the end of
the story. The Framers also had to specify how this would work in practice. After long and
searching debate they made three crucial decisions, each of which sheds light on their
understanding of impeachment’s proper role in our constitutional system.

First, they limited the consequences of impeachment to “removal from Office” and
“disqualification” from future officeholding.40 To the extent the President’s wrongful
conduct also breaks the law, the Constitution expressly reserves criminal punishment for
the ordinary processes of criminal law. In that respect, “the consequences of impeachment
and conviction go just far enough, and no further than, to remove the threat posed to the
Republic by an unfit official.”41 This speaks to the very nature of impeachment: it exists

33
Frank O. Bowman, III, High Crimes and Misdemeanors: A History of Impeachment for the Age of Trump
72 (2019).
34
2 Farrand, Records of the Federal Convention, at 65-67.
35
1 Farrand, Records of the Federal Convention, at 66.
36
2 Farrand, Records of the Federal Convention, at 66.
37
James Madison, Notes on Debates in the Federal Convention of 1787 332 (1987).
38
Alexander Hamilton, Federalist No. 69, at 444.
39
Id.
40
U.S. CONST. Art. I, § 43, cl. 7.
41
John O. McGinnis, Impeachment: The Structural Understanding, 67 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 650, 650 (1999).

9
not to inflict personal punishment for past wrongdoing, but rather to protect against future
Presidential misconduct that would endanger democracy and the rule of law.42

Second, the Framers vested the House with “the sole Power of Impeachment.”43
The House thus serves in a role analogous to a grand jury and prosecutor: it investigates
the President’s misconduct and decides whether to formally accuse him of impeachable
acts. As James Iredell explained during debates over whether to ratify the Constitution,
“this power is lodged in those who represent the great body of the people, because the
occasion for its exercise will arise from acts of great injury to the community.” 44 The
Senate, in turn, holds “the sole Power to try all Impeachments.”45 When the Senate sits as
a court of impeachment for the President, each Senator must swear a special oath, the Chief
Justice of the United States presides, and conviction requires “the concurrence of two thirds
of the Members present.”46 By designating Congress to accuse the President and conduct
his trial, the Framers confirmed—in Hamilton’s words—that impeachment concerns an
“abuse or violation of some public trust” with “injuries done immediately to the society
itself.”47 Impeachment is reserved for offenses against our political system. It is therefore
prosecuted and judged by Congress, speaking for the Nation.

Last, but not least, the Framers imposed a rule of wrongdoing. The President cannot
be removed based on poor management, general incompetence, or unpopular policies.
Instead, the question in any impeachment inquiry is whether the President has engaged in
misconduct justifying an early end to his term in office: “Treason, Bribery, or other high
Crimes and Misdemeanors.”48 This phrase had a particular legal meaning to the Framers.
It is to that understanding, and to its application in prior Presidential impeachments, that
we now turn.

IV. Impeachable Offenses

As careful students of history, the Framers knew that threats to democracy can take
many forms. They feared would-be monarchs, but also warned against fake populists,
charismatic demagogues, and corrupt kleptocrats. In describing the kind of leader who
might menace the Nation, Hamilton offered an especially striking portrait:

When a man unprincipled in private life[,] desperate in his fortune, bold in


his temper . . . known to have scoffed in private at the principles of liberty

42
See Tribe, American Constitutional Law, at 155.
43
U.S. CONST. Art. I, § 2, cl. 5.
44
4 Jonathan Elliot, ed., The Debates in the Several State Conventions on the Adoption of the Federal
Constitution 113 (1861) (hereinafter “Debates in the Several State Conventions”).
45
U.S. CONST. Art. I, § 3, cl. 6.
46
Id.
47
Alexander Hamilton, Federalist No. 65, at 426.
48
U.S. CONST. Art. II, § 4.

10
— when such a man is seen to mount the hobby horse of popularity — to
join in the cry of danger to liberty — to take every opportunity of
embarrassing the General Government & bringing it under suspicion — to
flatter and fall in with all the non sense [sic] of the zealots of the day — It
may justly be suspected that his object is to throw things into confusion that
he may ride the storm and direct the whirlwind.49

This prophesy echoed Hamilton’s warning, in Federalist No. 1, that “of those men who
have overturned the liberties of republics, the greatest number have begun their career by
paying an obsequious court to the people; commencing demagogues, and ending tyrants.”50

The Framers thus intended impeachment to reach the full spectrum of Presidential
misconduct that threatened the Constitution. They also intended our Constitution to endure
for the ages. Because they could not anticipate and specifically prohibit every threat a
President might someday pose, the Framers adopted a standard sufficiently general and
flexible to meet unknown future circumstances. This standard was meant—as Mason put
it—to capture all manner of “great and dangerous offenses” incompatible with the
Constitution. When the President uses the powers of his high office to benefit himself,
while injuring or ignoring the American people he is oath-bound to serve, he has committed
an impeachable offense.

Applying the tools of legal interpretation, as we do below, puts a sharper point on


this definition of “high Crimes and Misdemeanors.” It also confirms that the Framers
principally aimed the impeachment power at a few core evils, each grounded in a unifying
fear that a President might abandon his duty to faithfully execute the laws. Where the
President engages in serious abuse of power, betrays the national interest through foreign
entanglements, or corrupts his office or elections, he has undoubtedly committed “high
Crimes and Misdemeanors” as understood by the Framers. Any one of these violations of
the public trust is impeachable. When combined in a scheme to advance the President’s
personal interests while ignoring or injuring the Constitution, they state the strongest
possible case for impeachment and removal from office.

A. Lessons from British and Early American History

As Hamilton recounted, Britain afforded “[t]he model from which the idea of
[impeachment] has been borrowed.”51 That was manifestly true of the phrase “high Crimes
and Misdemeanors.” The Framers could have authorized impeachment for “crimes” or
“serious crimes.” Or they could have followed the practice of many American state

49
Alexander Hamilton, “Objections and Answers respecting the Administration of the Government,”
Founders Online, National Archives.
50
Alexander Hamilton, Federalist No. 1, at 91.
51
Alexander Hamilton, Federalist No. 65, at 427.

11
constitutions and permitted impeachment for “maladministration” or “malpractice.”52 But
they instead selected a “unique phrase used for centuries in English parliamentary
impeachments.”53 To understand their choice requires a quick tour through history.

That tour offers two lessons. The first is that the phrase “high Crimes and
Misdemeanors” was used only for parliamentary impeachments; it was never used in the
ordinary criminal law.54 Moreover, in the 400-year history of British impeachments, the
House of Commons impeached many officials on grounds that did not involve any
discernibly criminal conduct. Indeed, the House of Commons did so yet again just as the
Framers gathered in Philadelphia. That same month, Edmund Burke—the celebrated
champion of American liberty—brought twenty-two articles of impeachment against
Warren Hastings, the Governor General of India. Burke charged Hastings with offenses
including abuse of power, corruption, disregarding treaty obligations, and misconduct of
local wars. Historians have confirmed that “none of the charges could fairly be classed as
criminal conduct in any technical sense.”55 Aware of that fact, Burke accused Hastings of
“[c]rimes, not against forms, but against those eternal laws of justice, which are our rule
and our birthright: his offenses are not in formal, technical language, but in reality, in
substance and effect, High Crimes and High Misdemeanors.”56

Burke’s denunciation of Hastings points to the second lesson from British history:
“high Crimes and Misdemeanors” were understood as offenses against the constitutional
system itself. This is confirmed by use of the word “high,” as well as Parliamentary
practice. From 1376 to 1787, the House of Commons impeached officials on seven general
grounds: (1) abuse of power; (2) betrayal of the nation’s security and foreign policy; (3)
corruption; (4) armed rebellion [a.k.a. treason]; (5) bribery; (6) neglect of duty; and (7)
violating Parliament’s constitutional prerogatives.57 To the Framers and their
contemporaries learned in the law, the phrase “high Crimes and Misdemeanors” would
have called to mind these offenses against the body politic.

The same understanding prevailed on this side of the Atlantic. In the colonial period
and under newly-ratified state constitutions, most impeachments targeted abuse of power,
betrayal of the revolutionary cause, corruption, treason, and bribery.58 Many Framers at the
Constitutional Convention had participated in drafting their state constitutions, or in
colonial and state removal proceedings, and were steeped in this outlook on impeachment.
Further, the Framers knew well the Declaration of Independence, “whose bill of particulars

52
Bowman, High Crimes and Misdemeanors, at 65-72.
53
Constitutional Grounds for Presidential Impeachment (1974), at 4.
54
See id.
55
Bowman, High Crimes and Misdemeanors, at 41.
56
Id.
57
Id., at 46; Berger, Impeachment, at 70.
58
See Peter Charles Hoffer & N. E. H. Hull, Impeachment in America, 1635-1805 1-106 (1984).

12
against King George III modeled what [we would] now view as articles of impeachment.”59
That bill of particulars did not dwell on technicalities of criminal law, but rather charged
the king with a “long train of abuses and usurpations,” including misuse of power, efforts
to obstruct and undermine elections, and violating individual rights.60

History thus teaches that “high Crimes and Misdemeanors” referred mainly to acts
committed by public officials, using their power or privileges, that inflicted grave harm on
society itself. Such great and dangerous offenses included treason, bribery, abuse of power,
betrayal of the nation, and corruption of office. They were unified by a clear theme: officials
who abused, abandoned, or sought personal benefit from their public trust—and who
threatened the rule of law if left in power—faced impeachment and removal.

B. Treason and Bribery

For the briefest of moments at the Constitutional Convention, it appeared as though


Presidential impeachment might be restricted to “treason, or bribery.”61 But when this
suggestion reached the floor, Mason revolted. With undisguised alarm, he warned that such
limited grounds for impeachment would miss “attempts to subvert the Constitution,” as
well as “many great and dangerous offenses.”62 Here he invoked the charges pending in
Parliament against Hastings as a case warranting impeachment for reasons other than
treason. To “extend the power of impeachments,” Mason initially suggested adding “or
maladministration” after “treason, or bribery.”63 Madison, however, objected that “so
vague a term will be equivalent to a tenure during the pleasure of the Senate.”64 In response,
Mason substituted “other high Crimes and Misdemeanors.”65 Apparently pleased with
Mason’s compromise, the Convention accepted his proposal and moved on.

This discussion confirms that Presidential impeachment is warranted for all manner
of great and dangerous offenses that subvert the Constitution. It also sheds helpful light on
the nature of impeachable offenses: in identifying “other high Crimes and Misdemeanors,”
we can start with two that the Framers identified for us, “Treason” and “Bribery.”

59
Laurence H. Tribe & Joshua Matz, To End a Presidency: The Power of Impeachment 7 (2018).
60
The Declaration of Independence, Thomas Jefferson, et al, July 4, 1776, Copy of Declaration of
Independence, Library of Congress.
61
2 Farrand, Records of the Federal Convention, at 550.
62
Id.
63
Id.
64
Id.
65
Id.

13
1. Impeachable Treason

Under Article III of the Constitution, “treason against the United States, shall
consist only in levying War against them, or in adhering to their Enemies, giving them Aid
and Comfort.”66 In other words, a person commits treason if he uses armed force in an
attempt to overthrow the government, or if he knowingly gives aid and comfort to nations
(or organizations) with which the United States is in a state of declared or open war. At the
very heart of “Treason” is deliberate betrayal of the nation and its security. Such betrayal
would not only be unforgivable, but would also confirm that the President remains a threat
if allowed to remain in office. A President who has knowingly betrayed national security
is a President who will do so again. He endangers our lives and those of our allies.

2. Impeachable Bribery

The essence of impeachable bribery is a government official’s exploitation of his


or her public duties for personal gain. To the Framers, it was received wisdom that nothing
can be “a greater Temptation to Officers [than] to abuse their Power by Bribery and
Extortion.”67 To guard against that risk, the Framers authorized the impeachment of a
President who offers, solicits, or accepts something of personal value to influence his own
official actions. By rendering such “Bribery” impeachable, the Framers sought to ensure
that the Nation could expel a leader who would sell out the interests of “We the People” to
achieve his own personal gain.

Unlike “Treason,” which is defined in Article III, “Bribery” is not given an express
definition in the Constitution. But as Justice Joseph Story explained, a “proper exposition
of the nature and limits of this offense” can be found in the Anglo-American common law
tradition known well to our Framers.68 That understanding, in turn, can be refined by
reference to the Constitution’s text and the records of the Constitutional Convention.69

To start with common law: At the time of the Constitutional Convention, bribery
was well understood in Anglo-American law to encompass offering, soliciting, or
accepting bribes. In 1716, for example, William Hawkins defined bribery in an influential
treatise as “the receiving or offering of any undue reward, by or to any person whatsoever
… in order to incline him to do a thing against the known rules of honesty and integrity.”70

66
U.S. CONST. Art. III, § 3, cl. 1.
67
William Hawkins, A Treatise of Pleas to the Crown, ch. 67, § 3 (1716).
68
2 Story, Commentaries, at 263; see also H.R. REP. NO. 946, at 19 (1912).
69
For example, while the English common law tradition principally addressed itself to judicial bribery, the
Framers repeatedly made clear at the Constitutional Convention that they intended to subject the President
to impeachment for bribery. They confirmed this intention in the Impeachment Clause, which authorizes the
impeachment of “[t]he President, Vice President and all civil Officers of the United States” for “Treason,
Bribery, or other high Crimes and Misdemeanors.” U.S. CONST., Art. 2, § 4. It is therefore proper to draw
upon common law principles and to apply them to the office of the Presidency.
70
Hawkins, A Treatise of Pleas to the Crown, ch. 67, § 2 (1716).

14
This description of the offense was echoed many times over the following decades. In a
renowned bribery case involving the alleged solicitation of bribes, Lord Mansfield agreed
that “[w]herever it is a crime to take, it is a crime to give: they are reciprocal.”71 Two years
later, William Blackstone confirmed that “taking bribes is punished,” just as bribery is
punishable for “those who offer a bribe, though not taken.”72 Soliciting a bribe—even if it
is not accepted—thus qualified as bribery at common law. Indeed, it was clear under the
common law that “the attempt is a crime; it is complete on his side who offers it.”73

The Framers adopted that principle into the Constitution. As Judge John Noonan
explains, the drafting history of the Impeachment Clause demonstrates that “‘Bribery’ was
read both actively and passively, including the chief magistrate bribing someone and being
bribed.”74 Many scholars of Presidential impeachment have reached the same conclusion.75
Impeachable “Bribery” thus covers—inter alia—the offer, solicitation, or acceptance of
something of personal value by the President to influence his own official actions.

This conclusion draws still more support from a closely related part of the common
law. In the late-17th century, “bribery” was a relatively new offense, and was understood
as overlapping with the more ancient common law crime of “extortion.”76 “Extortion,” in
turn, was defined as the “abuse of public justice, which consists in any officer’s unlawfully
taking, by colour of his office, from any man, any money or thing of value, that is not due
to him, or more than is due, or before it is due.”77 Under this definition, both bribery and

71
Rex v. Vaughan, 98 Eng. Rep. 308, 311 (K.B. 1769).
72
William Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England, Vol. 2, Book 4, Ch. 10, § 17 (1771).
73
Rex v. Vaughan, 98 Eng. Rep. 308, 311 (K.B. 1769). American courts have subsequently repeated this
precise formulation. See, e.g., State v. Ellis, 33 N.J.L. 102, 104 (N.J. Sup. Ct. 1868) (“The offence is
complete when an offer or reward is made to influence the vote or action of the official.”); see also William
O. Russell, A Treatise on Crimes and Misdemeanors 239-240 (1st American Ed) (1824) (“The law abhors
the least tendency to corruption; and up on the principle which has been already mentioned, of an attempt to
commit even a misdemeanor, being itself a misdemeanor, (f) attempts to bribe, though unsuccessful, have in
several cases been held to be criminal.”).
74
John T. Noonan, Jr., Bribes: The Intellectual History of a Moral Idea, 430 (1984).
75
As Professor Bowman writes, bribery was “a common law crime that developed from a narrow beginning”
to reach “giving, and offering to give, [any] improper rewards.” Bowman, High Crimes & Misdemeanors, at
243; see also, e.g., Tribe & Matz, To End A Presidency, at 33 (“The corrupt exercise of power in exchange
for a personal benefit defines impeachable bribery. That’s self-evidently true whenever the president receives
bribes to act a certain way. But it’s also true when the president offers bribes to other officials—for example,
to a federal judge, a legislator, or a member of the Electoral College … In either case, the president is fully
complicit in a grave degradation of power, and he can never again be trusted to act as a faithful public
servant.”).
76
See James Lindgren, The Elusive Distinction Between Bribery and Extortion: From the Common Law to
the Hobbs Act, 35 UCLA L. REV. 815, 839 (1988).
77
Blackstone, Commentaries, Vol. 2, Book 4, Ch. 10, § 22 (1771) (citing 1 Hawk. P. C. 170); accord Giles
Jacob, A New Law-Dictionary 102 (1782) (defining “Extortion” as “an unlawful taking by an officer, &c. by
colour of his office, of any money, or valuable thing, from a person where none at all is due, or not so much
is due, or before it is due”).

15
extortion occurred when an official used his public position to obtain private benefits to
which he was not entitled. Conduct which qualified as bribery was therefore “routinely
punished as common law extortion.”78 To the Framers, who would have seen bribery and
extortion as virtually coextensive, when a President acted in his official capacity to offer,
solicit, or accept an improper personal benefit, he committed “Bribery.”79

Turning to the nature of the improper personal benefit: because officials can be
corrupted in many ways, the benefit at issue in a bribe can be anything of subjective
personal value to the President. This is not limited to money. Indeed, given their purposes,
it would have made no sense for the Framers to confine “Bribery” to the offer, solicitation,
or acceptance of money, and they expressed no desire to impose that restriction. To the
contrary, in guarding against foreign efforts to subvert American officials, they confirmed
their broad view of benefits that might cause corruption: a person who holds “any Office
of Profit or Trust,” such as the President, is forbidden from accepting “any present, Office
or Tile, of any kind whatever, from … a foreign State.”80 An equally pragmatic (and
capacious) view applies to the impeachable offense of “Bribery.” This view is further
anchored in the very same 17th and 18th century common law treatises that were well known
to the Framers. Those authorities used broad language in defining what qualifies as a “thing
of value” in the context of bribery: “any undue reward” or any “valuable consideration.”81

To summarize, impeachable “Bribery” occurs when a President offers, solicits, or


accepts something of personal value to influence his own official actions. Bribery is thus
an especially egregious and specific example of a President abusing his power for private
gain. As Blackstone explained, bribery is “the genius of despotic countries where the true
principles of government are never understood”—and where “it is imagined that there is
no obligation from the superior to the inferior, no relative duty owing from the governor to
the governed.”82 In our democracy, the Framers understood that there is no place for
Presidents who would abuse their power and betray the public trust through bribery.

Like “Treason,” the offense of “Bribery” is thus aimed at a President who is a


continuing threat to the Constitution. Someone who would willingly assist our enemies, or
trade public power for personal favors, is the kind of person likely to break the rules again
if they remain in office. But there is more: both “Treason” and “Bribery” are serious
offenses with the capacity to corrupt constitutional governance and harm the Nation itself;
both involve wrongdoing that reveals the President as a continuing threat if left in power;
and both offenses are “plainly wrong in themselves to a person of honor, or to a good

78
Lindgren, The Elusive Distinction, 35 UCLA L. REV. at 839.
79
For all the reasons given below in our discussion of the criminality issue, impeachable “Bribery” does not
refer to the meaning of bribery under modern federal criminal statutes. See also Bowman, High Crimes &
Misdemeanors, at 243-44; Tribe & Matz, To End A Presidency, at 31-33.
80
U.S. CONST, art. I, § 9, cl.8.
81
Hawkins, A Treatise of Pleas to the Crown, ch. 67, § 2 (1716).
82
Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England, Book 4, Ch. 10 “Of Offenses Against Public Justice”
(1765-1770).

16
citizen, regardless of words on the statute books.”83 Looking to the Constitution’s text and
history—including the British, colonial, and early American traditions discussed earlier—
these characteristics also define “other high Crimes and Misdemeanors.”

C. Abuse, Betrayal & Corruption

With that understanding in place, the records of the Constitutional Convention offer
even greater clarity. They demonstrate that the Framers principally intended impeachment
for three forms of Presidential wrongdoing: serious abuse of power, betrayal of the national
interest through foreign entanglements, and corruption of office and elections. When the
President engages in such misconduct, and does so in ways that are recognizably wrong
and injurious to our political system, impeachment is warranted. That is proven not only
by debates surrounding adoption of the Constitution, but also by the historical practice of
the House in exercising the impeachment power.

1. Abuse of Power

As Justice Robert Jackson wisely observed, “the purpose of the Constitution was
not only to grant power, but to keep it from getting out of hand.” 84 Nowhere is that truer
than in the Presidency. As the Framers created a formidable chief executive, they made
clear that impeachment is justified for serious abuse of power. Edmund Randolph was
explicit on this point. In explaining why the Constitution must authorize Presidential
impeachment, he warned that “the Executive will have great opportunitys of abusing his
power.”85 Madison, too, stated that impeachment is necessary because the President “might
pervert his administration into a scheme of … oppression.”86 This theme echoed through
the state ratifying conventions. Advocating that New York ratify the Constitution,
Hamilton set the standard for impeachment at an “abuse or violation of some public
trust.”87 In South Carolina, Charles Pinckney agreed that Presidents must be removed who
“behave amiss or betray their public trust.”88 In Massachusetts, Reverend Samuel Stillman
asked, “With such a prospect [of impeachment], who will dare to abuse the powers vested
in him by the people.”89 Time and again, Americans who wrote and ratified the
Constitution confirmed that Presidents may be impeached for abusing the power entrusted
to them.

There are at least as many ways to abuse power as there are powers vested in the
President. It would thus be an exercise in futility to attempt a list of every conceivable

83
Charles L. Black Jr. & Philip Bobbitt, Impeachment: A Handbook, New Edition 34 (2018).
84
Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 343 U.S. 579, 640 (Jackson, J., concurring).
85
2 Farrand, Records of the Federal Convention, at 67.
86
Id., at 65-66.
87
Alexander Hamilton, Federalist No. 65, at 426.
88
Berger, Impeachment, at 94.
89
2 Elliot, Debates in the Several State Conventions, at 169.

17
abuse constituting “high Crimes and Misdemeanors.” That said, abuse of power was no
vague notion to the Framers and their contemporaries. It had a very particular meaning to
them. Impeachable abuse of power can take two basic forms: (1) the exercise of official
power in a way that, on its very face, grossly exceeds the President’s constitutional
authority or violates legal limits on that authority; and (2) the exercise of official power to
obtain an improper personal benefit, while ignoring or injuring the national interest. In
other words, the President may commit an impeachable abuse of power in two different
ways: by engaging in forbidden acts, or by engaging in potentially permissible acts but for
forbidden reasons (e.g., with the corrupt motive of obtaining a personal political benefit).

The first category involves conduct that is inherently and sharply inconsistent with
the law—and that amounts to claims of monarchical prerogative. The generation that
rebelled against King George III knew what absolute power looked like. The Framers had
other ideas when they organized our government, and so they placed the chief executive
within the bounds of law. That means the President may exercise only the powers expressly
or impliedly vested in him by the Constitution, and he must also respect legal limits on the
exercise of those powers (including the rights of Americans citizens). A President who
refuses to abide these restrictions, thereby causing injury to society itself and engaging in
recognizably wrongful conduct, may be subjected to impeachment for abuse of power.

That principle also covers conduct grossly inconsistent with and subversive of the
separation of powers. The Framers knew that “[t]he accumulation of all powers, legislative,
executive, and judiciary, in the same hands, ... may justly be pronounced the very definition
of tyranny.”90 To protect liberty, they wrote a Constitution that creates a system of checks
and balances within the federal government. Some of those rules are expressly enumerated
in our founding charter; others are implied from its structure or from the history of inter-
branch relations.91 When a President wields executive power in ways that usurp and destroy
the prerogatives of Congress or the Judiciary, he exceeds the scope of his constitutional
authority and violates limits on permissible conduct. Such abuses of power are therefore
impeachable. That conclusion is further supported by the British origins of the phrase “high
Crimes and Misdemeanors”: Parliament repeatedly impeached ministers for “subvert[ing]
its conception of proper constitutional order in favor of the ‘arbitrary and tyrannical’
government of ambitious monarchs and their grasping minions.”92

The Supreme Court advanced similar logic in Ex Parte Grossman, which held the
President can pardon officials who defy judicial orders and are held in criminal contempt
of court.93 This holding raised an obvious concern: what if the President used “successive
pardons” to “deprive a court of power to enforce its orders”?94 That could fatally weaken

90
James Madison, Federalist No. 47, at 336.
91
See generally National Labor Relations Board v. Noel Canning, et al., 573 U.S. 513 (2014).
92
Bowman, High Crimes and Misdemeanors, at 109.
93
Ex Parte Grossman, 267 U.S. 87 (1925).
94
Id., at 121.

18
the Judiciary’s role under Article III of the Constitution. On behalf of a unanimous Court,
Chief Justice William Howard Taft—who had previously served as President—explained
that “exceptional cases like this … would suggest a resort to impeachment.”95

Two impeachment inquiries have involved claims that a President grossly violated
the Constitution’s separation of powers. The first was in 1868, when the House impeached
President Andrew Johnson, who had succeeded President Abraham Lincoln following his
assassination at Ford’s Theatre. There, the articles approved by the House charged
President Johnson with conduct forbidden by law: in firing the Secretary of War, he had
allegedly violated the Tenure of Office Act, which restricted the President’s power to
remove cabinet members during the term of the President who had appointed them.96
President Johnson was thus accused of a facial abuse of power. In the Senate, though, he
was acquitted by a single vote—largely because the Tenure of Office Act was viewed by
many Senators as likely unconstitutional (a conclusion later adopted by the Supreme Court
in an opinion by Chief Justice Taft, who described the Act as “invalid”97).

Just over 100 years later, this Committee accused a second chief executive of
abusing his power. In a departure from prior Presidential practice—and in contravention
of Article I of the Constitution—President Nixon had invoked specious claims of executive
privilege to defy Congressional subpoenas served as part of an impeachment inquiry. His
obstruction centered on tape recordings, papers, and memoranda relating to the Watergate
break-in and its aftermath. As the House Judiciary Committee found, he had interposed
“the powers of the presidency against the lawful subpoenas of the House of
Representatives, thereby assuming to himself functions and judgments necessary to
exercise the sole power of impeachment vested by the Constitution in the House of
Representatives.”98 Put simply, President Nixon purported to control the exercise of powers
that belonged solely to the House and not to him—including the power of inquiry that is
vital to any Congressional judgments about impeachment. In so doing, President Nixon
injured the constitutional plan: “Unless the defiance of the Committee’s subpoenas under
these circumstances is considered grounds for impeachment, it is difficult to conceive of
any President acknowledging that he obligated to supply the relevant evidence necessary
for Congress to exercise its constitutional responsibility in an impeachment proceeding.”99
The House Judiciary Committee therefore approved an article of impeachment against
President Nixon for abuse of power in obstructing the House impeachment inquiry.

But that was only part of President Nixon’s impeachable wrongdoing. The House
Judiciary Committee also approved two additional articles of impeachment against him for

95
Id.
96
Articles of Impeachment Exhibited By The House Of Representatives Against Andrew Johnson, President
of the United States, 40th Cong. (1868).
97
Myers v. United States, 272 U.S. 52, 108 (1926).
98
Committee Report on Nixon Articles of Impeachment (1974), at 188.
99
Id., at 213.

19
abuse of power, one for obstruction of justice and the other for using Presidential power to
target, harass, and surveil his political opponents. These articles demonstrate the second
way in which a President can abuse power: by acting with improper motives.

This understanding of impeachable abuse of power is rooted in the Constitution’s


text, which commands the President to “faithfully execute” the law. At minimum, that duty
requires Presidents “to exercise their power only when it is motivated in the public interest
rather than in their private self-interest.”100 A President can thus be removed for exercising
power with a corrupt purpose, even if his action would otherwise be permissible. As Iredell
explained at the North Carolina ratifying convention, “the president would be liable to
impeachments [if] he had … acted from some corrupt motive or other,” or if he was
“willfully abusing his trust.”101 Madison made a similar point at Virginia’s ratifying
convention. There, he observed that the President could be impeached for abuse of the
pardon power if there are “grounds to believe” he has used it to “shelter” persons with
whom he is connected “in any suspicious manner.”102 Such a pardon would technically be
within the President’s authority under Article II of the Constitution, but it would rank as
an impeachable abuse of power because it arose from the forbidden purpose of obstructing
justice. To the Framers, it was dangerous for officials to exceed their constitutional power,
or to transgress legal limits, but it was equally dangerous (perhaps more so) for officials to
conceal corrupt or illegitimate objectives behind superficially valid acts.

Again, President Nixon’s case is instructive. After individuals associated with his
campaign committee committed crimes to promote his reelection, he used the full powers
of his office as part of a scheme to obstruct justice. Among many other wrongful acts,
President Nixon dangled pardons to influence key witnesses, told a senior aide to have the
CIA stop an FBI investigation into Watergate, meddled with Justice Department immunity
decisions, and conveyed secret law enforcement information to suspects. Even if some of
this conduct was formally within the scope of President Nixon’s authority as head of the
Executive Branch, it was undertaken with illegitimate motives. The House Judiciary
Committee therefore included it within an article of impeachment charging him with
obstruction of justice. Indeed, following President Nixon’s resignation and the discovery
of additional evidence concerning obstruction, all eleven members of the Committee who
had originally voted against that article joined a statement affirming that “we were prepared
to vote for his impeachment on proposed Article I had he not resigned his office.” 103 Of
course, several decades later, obstruction of justice was also the basis for an article of
impeachment against President Clinton, though his conduct did not involve official acts.104

100
Kent et al., Faithful Execution, at 2120, 2179.
101
1998 Background and History of Impeachment Hearing, at 49.
102
3 Elliott, Debates in the Several State Conventions, at 497-98.
103
Committee Report on Nixon Articles of Impeachment (1974), at 361.
104
In President Clinton’s case, the House approved the article of impeachment for obstruction of justice.
There was virtually no disagreement in those proceedings over whether obstructing justice can be
impeachable; scholars, lawyers, and legislators on all sides of the dispute recognized that it can be. See Daniel
J. Hemel & Eric A. Posner, Presidential Obstruction of Justice, 106 CAL. L. REV 1277, 1305-1307 (2018).

20
Yet obstruction of justice did not exhaust President Nixon’s corrupt abuse of power.
He was also accused of manipulating federal agencies to injure his opponents, aid his
friends, gain personal political benefits, and violate the constitutional rights of American
citizens. For instance, President Nixon improperly attempted to cause income tax audits of
his perceived political adversaries; directed the FBI and Secret Service to engage in
targeted (and unlawful) surveillance; and formed a secret investigative unit within the
White House—financed with campaign contributions—that utilized CIA resources in its
illegal covert activities. In explaining this additional article of impeachment, the House
Judiciary Committee stated that President Nixon’s conduct was “undertaken for his
personal political advantage and not in furtherance of any valid national policy
objective.”105 His abuses of executive power were thus “seriously incompatible with our
system of constitutional government” and warranted removal from office.106

With the benefit of hindsight, the House’s decision to impeach President Johnson
is best understood in a similar frame. Scholars now largely agree that President Johnson’s
impeachment was motivated not by violations of the Tenure of Office Act, but on his
illegitimate use of power to undermine Reconstruction and subordinate African-Americans
following the Civil War.107 In that period, fundamental questions about the nature and
future of the Union stood unanswered. Congress therefore passed a series of laws to
“reconstruct the former Confederate states into political entities in which black Americans
enjoyed constitutional protections.”108 This program, however, faced an unyielding enemy
in President Johnson, who declared that “white men alone must manage the south.”109
Convinced that political control by African-Americans would cause a “relapse into
barbarism,” President Johnson vetoed civil rights laws; when Congress overrode him, he
refused to enforce those laws.110 The results were disastrous. As Annette Gordon-Reed
writes, “it would be impossible to exaggerate how devastating it was to have a man who
affirmatively hated black people in charge of the program that was designed to settle the
terms of their existence in post-Civil War America.”111 Congress tried to compromise with

Publicly available evidence does not suggest that the Senate’s acquittal of President Clinton was based on
the view that obstruction of justice is not impeachable. Rather, Senators who voted for acquittal appear to
have concluded that some of the factual charges were not supported and that, even if Presidential perjury and
obstruction of justice might in some cases justify removal, the nature and circumstances of the conduct at
issue (including its predominantly private character) rendered it insufficiently grave to warrant that remedy.
105
Committee Report on Nixon Articles of Impeachment (1974), at 139.
106
Id.
107
See generally Michael Les Benedict, The Impeachment and Trial of Andrew Johnson (1999).
108
Jeffrey A. Engel, Jon Meacham, Timothy Naftali, & Peter Baker, Impeachment: An American History 48
(2018).
109
Id. at 49.
110
Id.
111
See Annette Gordon-Reed, Andrew Johnson: The American Presidents Series: the 17th President, 1865-
1869 12 (2011).

21
the President, but to no avail. A majority of the House finally determined that President
Johnson posed a clear and present danger to the Nation if allowed to remain in office.

Rather than directly target President Johnson’s faithless execution of the laws, and
his illegitimate motives in wielding power, the House resorted to charges based on the
Tenure of Office Act. But in reality, “the shaky claims prosecuted by [the House] obscured
a far more compelling basis for removal: that Johnson’s virulent use of executive power to
sabotage Reconstruction posed a mortal threat to the nation—and to civil and political
rights—as reconstituted after the Civil War … [T]he country was in the throes of a second
founding. Yet Johnson abused the powers of his office and violated the Constitution to
preserve institutions and practices that had nearly killed the Union. He could not be allowed
to salt the earth as the Republic made itself anew.”112 Viewed from that perspective, the
case for impeaching President Johnson rested on his use of power with illegitimate motives.

Pulling this all together, the Framers repeatedly confirmed that Presidents can be
impeached for grave abuse of power. Where the President engages in acts forbidden by
law, or acts with an improper motive, he has committed an abuse of power under the
Constitution. Where those abuses inflict substantial harm on our political system and are
recognizably wrong, they warrant his impeachment and removal.113

2. Betrayal of the National Interest Through Foreign


Entanglements

It is not a coincidence that the Framers started with “Treason” in defining


impeachable offenses. Betrayal was no abstraction to them. They had recently waged a war
for independence in which some of their fellow citizens remained loyal to the enemy. The
infamous traitor, Benedict Arnold, had defected to Britain less than a decade earlier. As
they looked outward, the Framers saw kings scheming for power, promising fabulous
wealth to spies and deserters. The United States could be enmeshed in such conspiracies:
“Foreign powers,” warned Elbridge Gerry, “will intermeddle in our affairs, and spare no
expense to influence them.”114 The young Republic might not survive a President who
schemed with other nations, entangling himself in secret deals that harmed our democracy.

112
Tribe & Matz, To End a Presidency, at 55.
113
In President Clinton’s case, it was debated whether Presidents can be impeached for acts that do not
involve their official powers. See Constitutional Grounds for Presidential Impeachment: Modern Precedents
(1998), at 6-7; MINORITY STAFF OF H. COMM. ON THE JUDICIARY, 105TH CONG., CONSTITUTIONAL GROUNDS
FOR PRESIDENTIAL IMPEACHMENT: MODERN PRECEDENTS MINORITY V IEWS 3-4, 8-9, 13-16 (Comm. Print
1998. Many scholars have taken the view that such private conduct may be impeachable in extraordinary
circumstances, such as where it renders the President unviable as the leader of a democratic nation committed
to the rule of law. See, e.g., Tribe & Matz, To End A Presidency, at 10, 51; Black & Bobbitt, Impeachment,
at 35. It also bears mention that some authority supports the view that Presidents might be subject to
impeachment not for abusing their official powers, but by failing to use them and thus engaging in gross
dereliction of official duty. See, e.g., Tribe & Matz, To End A Presidency, at 50; Akhil Reed Amar, America’s
Constitution: A Biography 200 (2006); Black & Bobbitt, Impeachment, at 34.
114
Wydra & Gorod, The First Magistrate in Foreign Pay.

22
That reality loomed over the impeachment debate in Philadelphia. Explaining why
the Constitution required an impeachment option, Madison argued that a President “might
betray his trust to foreign powers.”115 Gouverneur Morris, who had initially opposed
allowing impeachment, was convinced: “no one would say that we ought to expose
ourselves to the danger of seeing the first Magistrate in foreign pay, without being able to
guard against it by displacing him.”116 In the same vein, Franklin noted “the case of the
Prince of Orange during the late war,” in which a Dutch prince reneged on a military treaty
with France.117 Because there was no impeachment power or other method of inquiry, the
prince’s motives were secret and untested, drastically destabilizing Dutch politics and
giving “birth to the most violent animosities and contentions.”118

Impeachment for betrayal of the Nation’s interest—and especially for betrayal of


national security and foreign policy—was hardly exotic to the Framers. “The history of
impeachment over the centuries shows an abiding awareness of how vulnerable the practice
of foreign policy is to the misconduct of its makers.”119 Indeed, “impeachments on this
ground were a constant of parliamentary practice,” and “a string of British ministers and
royal advisors were impeached for using their official powers contrary to the country’s
vital foreign interests.”120 Although the Framers did not intend impeachment for genuine,
good faith disagreements between the President and Congress over matters of diplomacy,
they were explicit that betrayal of the Nation through plots with foreign powers justified
removal.

In particular, foreign interference in the American political system was among the
gravest dangers feared by the Founders of our Nation and the Framers of our Constitution.
For example, in a letter to Thomas Jefferson, John Adams wrote: “You are apprehensive
of foreign Interference, Intrigue, Influence. So am I.—But, as often as Elections happen,
the danger of foreign Influence recurs.”121 And in Federalist No. 68, Hamilton cautioned
that the “most deadly adversaries of republican government” may come “chiefly from the
desire in foreign powers to gain an improper ascendant in our councils.122

The President’s important role in foreign affairs does not disable the House from
evaluating whether he committed impeachable offenses in that field. This conclusion
follows from the Impeachment Clause itself but is also supported by the Constitution’s
115
2 Farrand, Records of the Federal Convention, at 65.
116
Id., at 68.
117
Id., at 67-68.
118
Id.
119
Frank O. Bowman, III, Foreign Policy Has Always Been at the Heart of Impeachment, FOREIGN AFFAIRS
(Nov 2019).
120
Bowman, High Crimes & Misdemeanors, at 48, 106.
121
To Thomas Jefferson from John Adams, 6 December 1787, National Archives, Founders Online.
122
Alexander Hamilton, Federalist No. 68, at 441.

23
many grants of power to Congress addressing foreign affairs. Congress is empowered to
“declare War,” “regulate Commerce with foreign Nations,” “establish an uniform Rule of
Naturalization,” “define and punish Piracies and Felonies committed on the high Seas, and
Offences against the Law of Nations,” “grant Letters of Marque and Reprisal,” and “make
Rules for the Government and Regulation of the land and naval Forces.” 123 Congress also
has the power to set policy, define law, undertake oversight and investigations, create
executive departments, and authorize government funding for a slew of national security
matters.124 In addition, the President cannot make a treaty or appoint an ambassador
without the approval of the Senate.125 In those respects and many others, constitutional
authority over the “conduct of the foreign relations of our Government” is shared between
“the Executive and Legislative [branches].”126 Stated simply, “the Executive is not free
from the ordinary controls and checks of Congress merely because foreign affairs are at
issue.”127 In these realms, as in many others, the Constitution “enjoins upon its branches
separateness but interdependence, autonomy but reciprocity.”128

Accordingly, where the President uses his foreign affairs power in ways that betray
the national interest for his own benefit, or harm national security for equally corrupt
reasons, he is subject to impeachment by the House. Any claims to the contrary would
horrify the Framers. A President who perverts his role as chief diplomat to serve private
rather than public ends has unquestionably engaged in “high Crimes and Misdemeanors”—
especially if he invited, rather than opposed, foreign interference in our politics.

3. Corruption of Office or Elections

As should now be clear, the Framers feared corruption most of all, in its many and
shifting manifestations. It was corruption that led to abuse of power and betrayal of the
Nation. It was corruption that ruined empires, debased Britain, and menaced American
freedom. The Framers saw no shortage of threats to the Republic, and fought valiantly to
guard against them, “but the big fear underlying all the small fears was whether they’d be
able to control corruption.”129 This was not just a matter of thwarting bribes and extortion;
it was a far greater challenge. The Framers aimed to build a country in which officials
would not use public power for personal benefits, disregarding the public good in pursuit
of their own advancement. This virtuous principle applied with special force to the

123
U.S. CONST., Art. I, § 8.
124
See Lawrence Friedman & Victor Hansen, There Is No Constitutional Impediment to an Impeachment
Inquiry that Concerns National Security, JUST SECURITY, Oct. 1, 2019.
125
U.S. CONST., Art. II, §2, cl. 2.
126
Medellin v. Texas, 552 U.S. 491, 511 (2008).
127
Zivotofsky v. Kerry, 135 S. Ct. 2076 (2015).
128
Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 343 U.S. 579, 635 (1952) (Jackson, J., concurring).
129
Teachout, Corruption in America, at 57.

24
Presidency. As Madison emphasized, because the Presidency “was to be administered by
a single man,” his corruption “might be fatal to the Republic.”130

The Framers therefore sought to ensure that “corruption was more effectually
guarded against, in the manner this government was constituted, than in any other that had
ever been formed.”131 Impeachment was central to that plan. At one point the Convention
even provisionally adopted “treason, bribery, or corruption” as the standard for impeaching
a President. And no fewer than four delegates—Morris, Madison, Mason, and Randolph—
listed corruption as a reason why Presidents must be subject to removal. That understanding
followed from history: “One invariable theme in [centuries] of Anglo-American
impeachment practice has been corruption.”132 Treason posed a threat of swift national
extinction, but the steady rot of corruption could destroy us from within. Presidents who
succumbed to that instinct, serving themselves at the Nation’s expense, forfeited the public
trust.

Impeachment was seen as especially necessary for Presidential conduct corrupting


our system of political self-government. That concern arose in two contexts: the risk that
Presidents would be swayed to prioritize foreign over domestic interests, and the risk that
they would place their personal interest in re-election above our abiding commitment to
democracy. The need for impeachment peaks where both threats converge at once.

First was the risk that foreign royals would use wealth, power, and titles to seduce
American officials. This was not a hypothetical problem. Just a few years earlier, and
consistent with European custom, King Louis XVI of France had bestowed on Benjamin
Franklin (in his capacity as American emissary) a snuff box decorated with 408 diamonds
“of a beautiful water.”133 Magnificent gifts like this one could unconsciously shape how
American officials carried out their duties. To guard against that peril, the Framers adopted
the Foreign Emoluments Clause, which prohibits Presidents—among other federal
officials—from accepting “any present, Emolument, Office, or Title, of any kind whatever,
from any King, Prince, or foreign State” unless Congress affirmatively consents.134

The theory of the Foreign Emoluments Clause, based in history and the Framers’
lived experience, “is that a federal officeholder who receives something of value from a
foreign power can be imperceptibly induced to compromise what the Constitution insists
be his exclusive loyalty: the best interest of the United States of America.”135 Rather than

130
Jonathan Elliot ed., Debates on the Adoption of the Federal Constitution in the Convention Held at
Philadelphia, in 1787 341 (1861) (hereinafter “Debates on the Adoption of the Federal Constitution”).
131
4 Elliot, Debates in the Several State Conventions, at 302.
132
Bowman, High Crimes & Misdemeanors, at 277.
133
Teachout, Corruption in America, at 1.
134
U.S. CONST., Art. I, § 9, cl. 8.
135
Norman L. Eisen, Richard Painter & Laurence H. Tribe, The Emoluments Clause: Its Text, Meaning, And
Application To Donald J. Trump, BROOKINGS, Dec. 16, 2016.

25
scrutinize every exchange for potential bribery, the Framers simply banned officials from
receiving anything of value from foreign powers. Although this rule sweeps broadly, the
Framers deemed it central to American self-governance. Speaking in Philadelphia, Charles
Pinckney “urged the necessity of preserving foreign ministers, and other officers of the
United States, independent of external influence.”136 At Virginia’s convention, Randolph
elaborated that “[i]t was thought proper, in order to exclude corruption and foreign
influence, to prohibit any one in office from receiving or holding any emoluments from
foreign states.”137 Randolph added that if the President violated the Clause, “he may be
impeached.”138

The Framers also anticipated impeachment if a President placed his own interest in
retaining power above the national interest in free and fair elections. Several delegates were
explicit on this point when the topic arose at the Constitutional Convention. By then, the
Framers had created the Electoral College. They were “satisfied with it as a tool for picking
presidents but feared that individual electors might be intimidated or corrupted.”139
Impeachment was their answer. William Davie led off the discussion, warning that a
President who abused his office might seek to escape accountability by interfering with
elections, sparing “no efforts or means whatever to get himself re-elected.”140 Rendering
the President “impeachable whilst in office” was thus “an essential security for the good
behaviour of the Executive.”141 The Constitution thereby ensured that corrupt Presidents
could not avoid justice by subverting elections and remaining in office.

George Mason built on Davie’s position, directing attention to the Electoral


College: “One objection agst. Electors was the danger of their being corrupted by the
Candidates; & this furnished a peculiar reason in favor of impeachments whilst in office.
Shall the man who has practised corruption & by that means procured his appointment in
the first instance, be suffered to escape punishment, by repeating his guilt?”142 Mason’s
concern was straightforward. He feared that Presidents would win election by improperly
influencing members of the Electoral College (e.g., by offering them bribes). If evidence
of such wrongdoing came to light, it would be unthinkable to leave the President in office—
especially given that he might seek to avoid punishment by corrupting the next election. In
that circumstance, Mason concluded, the President should face impeachment and removal
under the Constitution. Notably, Mason was not alone in this view. Speaking just a short
while later, Gouverneur Morris emphatically agreed that “the Executive ought therefore to

136
Elliot, Debates on the Adoption of the Federal Constitution at 467.
137
3 Elliot, Debates in the Several State Conventions, at 465.
138
Id., at 201.
139
Tribe & Matz, To End A Presidency, at 4.
140
2 Farrand, Records of the Federal Convention, at 64.
141
Id.
142
Id., at 65.

26
be impeachable for … Corrupting his electors.”143 Although not articulated expressly, it is
reasonable to infer that the concerns raised by Davie, Mason, and Morris were especially
salient because the Constitution—until ratification of the Twenty-Second Amendment in
1951—did not limit the number of terms a President could serve in office.144 A President
who twisted or sabotaged the electoral process could rule for life, much like a king.

This commitment to impeaching Presidents who corruptly interfered with elections


was anchored in lessons from British rule. As historian Gordon Wood writes, “[t]hroughout
the eighteenth century the Crown had slyly avoided the blunt and clumsy instrument of
prerogative, and instead had resorted to influencing the electoral process and the
representatives in Parliament in order to gain its treacherous ends.”145 In his influential
Second Treatise on Civil Government, John Locke blasted such manipulation, warning that
it serves to “cut up the government by the roots, and poison the very fountain of public
security.”146 Channeling Locke, American revolutionaries vehemently objected to King
George III’s electoral shenanigans; ultimately, they listed several election-related charges
in the Declaration of Independence. Those who wrote our Constitution knew, and feared,
that the chief executive could threaten their plan of government by corrupting elections.

The true nature of this threat is its rejection of government by “We the People,”
who would “ordain and establish” the Constitution.147 The beating heart of the Framers’
project was a commitment to popular sovereignty. At a time when “democratic self-
government existed almost nowhere on earth,”148 the Framers imagined a society “where
the true principles of representation are understood and practised, and where all authority
flows from, and returns at stated periods to, the people.”149 That would be possible only if
“those entrusted with [power] should be kept in dependence on the people.”150 This is why
the President, and Members of Congress, must stand before the public for re-election on
fixed terms. It is through free and fair elections that the American people protect their right
to self-government, a right unforgivably denied to many as the Constitution was ratified in
1788 but now extended to all American citizens over the age of 18. When the President
concludes that elections threaten his continued grasp on power, and therefore seeks to
corrupt or interfere with them, he denies the very premise of our constitutional system. The
American people choose their leaders; a President who wields power to destroy opponents
or manipulate elections is a President who rejects democracy itself.

143
Id., at 69.
144
U.S. CONST. Amend. XXII.
145
Wood, The Creation of the American Republic, at 33.
146
John Locke, Second Treatise of Government 112 (C.B. Macpherson ed. 1980).
147
U.S. CONST. Pmbl.
148
Amar, America’s Constitution, at 8.
149
4 Elliot, Debates in the Several State Conventions, at 331; see also James Madison, Federalist No. 14.
150
James Madison, Federalist No. 37, at 268.

27
In sum, the Framers discussed the risk that Presidents would improperly conspire
with foreign nations; they also discussed the risk that Presidents would place their interest
in retaining power above the integrity of our elections. Both offenses, in their view, called
for impeachment. That is doubly true where a President conspires with a foreign power to
manipulate elections to his benefit—conduct that betrays American self-governance and
joins the Framers’ worst nightmares into a single impeachable offense.151

D. Conclusion

Writing in 1833, Justice Joseph Story remarked that impeachable offenses “are of
so various and complex a character” that it would be “almost absurd” to attempt a
comprehensive list.152 Consistent with Justice Story’s wisdom, “the House has never, in
any impeachment inquiry or proceeding, adopted either a comprehensive definition of
‘high Crimes and Misdemeanors’ or a catalog of offenses that are impeachable.”153 Rather
than engage in abstract, advisory or hypothetical debates about the precise nature of
conduct that calls for the exercise of its constitutional powers, the House has awaited a
“full development of the facts.”154 Only then has it weighed articles of impeachment.

In making such judgments, however, each Member of the House has sworn an oath
to follow the Constitution, which sets forth a legal standard governing when Presidential
conduct warrants impeachment. That standard has three main parts.

First, as Mason explained just before proposing “high Crimes and Misdemeanors”
as the basis for impeachment, the President’s conduct must constitute a “great and
dangerous offense” against the Nation. The Constitution itself offers us two examples:
“Treason” and “Bribery.” In identifying “other” offenses of the same kind, we are guided
by Parliamentary and early American practice, records from the Constitutional Convention
and state ratifying conventions, and insights from the Constitution’s text and structure.
These sources prove that “high Crimes and Misdemeanors” involve misconduct that
subverts and injures constitutional governance. Core instances of such misconduct by the
President are serious abuse of power, betrayal of the national interest through foreign
entanglements, and corruption of office and elections. The Framers included an

151
In fact, the Framers were so concerned about improper foreign influence in the Presidency that they
restricted that position to natural born citizens. U.S. CONST. Art. II, § 1. As one commentator observed,
“Considering the greatness of the trust, and that this department is the ultimately efficient power in
government, these restrictions will not appear altogether useless or unimportant. As the President is required
to be a native citizen of the United States, ambitious foreigners cannot intrigue for the office, and the
qualification of birth cuts off all those inducements from abroad to corruption, negotiation, and war, which
have frequently and fatally harassed the elective monarchies of Germany and Poland, as well as the
pontificate at Rome.” 1 James Kent, Commentaries on American Law 255 (1826).
152
2 Story, Commentaries, at 264.
153
1998 Background and History of Impeachment Hearing, at 2.
154
Constitutional Grounds for Presidential Impeachment (1974), at 2.

28
impeachment power in the Constitution specifically to protect the Nation against these
forms of wrongdoing.

Past practice of the House further illuminates the idea of a “great and dangerous
offense.” President Nixon’s case is most helpful. There, as explained above, the House
Judiciary Committee approved articles of impeachment on three grounds: (1) obstruction
of an ongoing law enforcement investigation into unlawful acts by his presidential re-
election campaign; (2) abuse of power in targeting his perceived political opponents; and
(3) improper obstruction of a Congressional impeachment inquiry into his obstruction of
justice and abuse of power. These articles of impeachment, moreover, were not confined
to discrete acts. Each of them accused President Nixon of undertaking a course of conduct
or scheme, and each of them supported that accusation with a list of discrete acts alleged
to comprise and demonstrate the overarching impeachable offense.155 Thus, where a
President engages in a course of conduct involving serious abuse of power, betrayal of the
national interest through foreign entanglements, or corruption of office and elections,
impeachment is justified.

Second, impeachable offenses involve wrongdoing that reveal the President as a


continuing threat to the constitutional system if he is allowed to remain in a position of
political power. As Iredell remarked, impeachment does not exist for a “mistake.”156 That
is why the Framers rejected “maladministration” as a basis for impeachment, and it is why
“high Crimes and Misdemeanors” are not simply unwise, unpopular, or unconsidered acts.
Like “Treason” and “Bribery,” they reflect decisions by the President to embark on a course
of conduct—or to act with motives—inconsistent with our plan of government. Where the
President makes such a decision, Congress may remove him to protect the Constitution,
especially if there is reason to think that he will commit additional offenses if left in office
(e.g., statements by the President that he did nothing wrong and would do it all again). This
forward-looking perspective follows from the limited consequences of impeachment. The
question is not whether to punish the President; that decision is left to the criminal justice
system. Instead, the ultimate question is whether to bring an early end to his four-year
electoral term. In his analysis of the Constitution, Alexis de Tocqueville thus saw
impeachment as “a preventive measure” which exists “to deprive the ill-disposed citizen
of an authority which he has used amiss, and to prevent him from ever acquiring it
again.”157 That is particularly true when the President injures the Nation’s interests as part
of a scheme to obtain personal benefits; someone so corrupt will again act corruptly.

155
Consistent with that understanding, one scholar remarks that it is the “repetition, pattern, [and] coherence”
of official misconduct that “tend to establish the requisite degree of seriousness warranting the removal of a
president from office.” John Labovitz, Presidential Impeachment 129-130 (1978); see also, e.g., McGinnis,
Impeachment, at 659 (“[I]t has been well understood that the official’s course of conduct as a whole should
be the subject of judgment.”); Debate On Articles Of Impeachment: Hearing before the H. Comm. On the
Judiciary, 93rd Cong. (1974) (hereinafter “Debate on Nixon Articles of Impeachment (1974)”) (addressing
the issue repeatedly from July 24, 1974 to July 30, 1974).
156
Sunstein, Impeachment, at 59.
157
Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America and Two Essays on America 124-30 (Gerald E. Bevan, tr.,
2003).

29
Finally, “high Crimes and Misdemeanors” involve conduct that is recognizably
wrong to a reasonable person. This principle resolves a potential tension in the
Constitution. On the one hand, the Framers adopted a standard for impeachment that could
stand the test of time. On the other hand, the structure of the Constitution—including its
prohibition on bills of attainder and the Ex Post Facto Clause—implies that impeachable
offenses should not come as a surprise.158 Impeachment is aimed at Presidents who believe
they are above the law, and who believe their own interests transcend those of the country
and Constitution. Of course, as President Nixon proved, Presidents who have committed
impeachable offenses may seek to confuse the public through manufactured ambiguity and
crafty pretexts. That does not shield their misconduct from impeachment. The principle of
a plainly wrong act is not about academic technicalities; it simply focuses impeachment on
conduct that any person of honor would recognize as wrong under the Constitution.

To summarize: Like “Treason” and “Bribery,” and consistent with the offenses
historically considered by Parliament to warrant impeachment, “high Crimes and
Misdemeanors” are great and dangerous offenses that injure the constitutional system.
Such offenses are defined mainly by abuse of power, betrayal of the national interest
through foreign entanglements, and corruption of office and elections. In addition,
impeachable offenses arise from wrongdoing that reveals the President as a continuing
threat to the constitutional system if allowed to remain in a position of power. Finally, they
involve conduct that reasonable officials would consider to be wrong in our democracy.

Within these parameters, and guided by fidelity to the Constitution, the House must
judge whether the President’s misconduct is grave enough to require impeachment. That
step must never be taken lightly. It is a momentous act, justified only when the President’s
full course of conduct, assessed without favor or prejudice, is “seriously incompatible with
either the constitutional form and principles of our government or the proper performance
of constitutional duties of the presidential office.”159 When that standard is met, however,
the Constitution calls the House to action. In such cases, a decision not to impeach has
grave consequences and sets an ominous precedent. As Representative William Cohen
remarked in President Nixon’s case, “It also has been said to me that even if Mr. Nixon did
commit these offenses, every other President … has engaged in some of the same conduct,
at least to some degree, but the answer I think is that democracy, that solid rock of our
system, may be eroded away by degree and its survival will be determined by the degree
to which we will tolerate those silent and subtle subversions that absorb it slowly into the
rule of a few.”160

158
See Black & Bobbitt, Impeachment, at 29-30.
159
Constitutional Grounds for Presidential Impeachment (1974), at 27.
160
Debate on Nixon Articles of Impeachment (1974), at 79.

30
V. The Criminality Issue

It is occasionally suggested that Presidents can be impeached only if they have


committed crimes. That position was rejected in President Nixon’s case, and then rejected
again in President Clinton’s, and should be rejected once more.161

Offenses against the Constitution are different in kind than offenses against the
criminal code. Some crimes, like jaywalking, are not impeachable. Some impeachable
offenses, like abuse of power, are not crimes. Some misconduct may offend both the
Constitution and the criminal law. Impeachment and criminality must therefore be assessed
separately—even though the commission of crimes may strengthen a case for removal.

A “great preponderance of authority” confirms that impeachable offenses are “not


confined to criminal conduct.”162 This authority includes nearly every legal scholar to have
studied the issue, as well as multiple Supreme Court justices who addressed it in public
remarks.163 More important, the House itself has long treated “high Crimes and
Misdemeanors” as distinct from crimes subject to indictment. That understanding follows
from the Constitution’s history, text, and structure, and reflects the absurdities and practical
difficulties that would result were the impeachment power confined to indictable crimes.

A. History

“If there is one point established by … Anglo-American impeachment practice, it


is that the phrase ‘high Crimes and Misdemeanors’ is not limited to indictable crimes.”164
As recounted above, impeachment was conceived in Parliament as a method for controlling
abusive royal ministers. Consistent with that purpose, it was not confined to accusations of
criminal wrongdoing. Instead, it was applied to “many offenses, not easily definable by
law,” such as abuse of power, betrayal of national security, corruption, neglect of duty, and

161
REPORT OF THE COMMITTEE ON THE JUDICIARY, HOUSE OF REPRESENTATIVES, TOGETHER WITH
ADDITIONAL, MINORITY, AND DISSENTING VIEWS TO ACCOMPANY H. RES. 611, IMPEACHMENT OF WILLIAM
JEFFERSON CLINTON, PRESIDENT OF THE UNITED STATES, H.R. REP. NO. 105-830 (1998) (hereinafter
“Committee Report on Clinton Articles of Impeachment (1998)”), at 64 (“Although, the actions of President
Clinton do not have to rise to the level of violating the federal statute regarding obstruction of justice in order
to justify impeachment.”). Constitutional Grounds for Presidential Impeachment (1974), at 22-26.
162
Berger, Impeachment, at 58.
163
See, e.g., Black & Bobbitt, Impeachment, at 33-37, 559-565; Bowman, High Crimes and Misdemeanors,
at 244-252; Tribe & Matz, To End A Presidency, at 43-53; Sunstein, Impeachment, at 117-134; Amar,
America’s Constitution, at 200-20; Charles J. Cooper, A Perjurer in the White House?: The Constitutional
Case for Perjury and Obstruction of Justice as High Crimes and Misdemeanors, 22 HARV. J. L. & PUB. POL’Y
619, 620 (1998-1999); Michael J. Gerhardt, The Federal Impeachment Process: A Constitutional and
Historical Analysis 105-113 (3rd ed. 2019); Berger, Impeachment, at 58 (collecting sources); Merrill Otis, A
Proposed Tribunal: Is It Constitutional?, 7 KAN. CITY. L. REV. 3, 22 (1938) (quoting Chief Justice Taft);
Charles E. Hughes, The Supreme Court of the United States 19 (1928) (Chief Justice Hughes); 2 Henry
Adams, History of the United States of America 223 (1962).
164
Bowman, High Crimes and Misdemeanors, at 44.

31
violating Parliament’s constitutional prerogatives.165 Many officials were impeached for
non-criminal wrongs against the British system of government; notable examples include
the Duke of Buckingham (1626), the Earl of Strafford (1640), the Lord Mayor of London
(1642), the Earl of Orford and others (1701), and Governor General Warren Hastings
(1787).166 Across centuries of use, the phrase “high Crimes and Misdemeanors” thus
assumed a “special historical meaning different from the ordinary meaning of the terms
‘crimes’ and ‘misdemeanors.’”167 It became a term of art confined to impeachments,
without “relation to whether an indictment would lie in the particular circumstances.”168

That understanding extended to North America. Here, the impeachment process


was used to address diverse misconduct by public officials, ranging from abuse of power
and corruption to bribery and betrayal of the revolutionary cause.169 As one scholar reports,
“American colonists before the Revolution, and American states after the Revolution but
before 1787, all impeached officials for non-criminal conduct.”170

At the Constitutional Convention itself, no delegate linked impeachment to the


technicalities of criminal law. On the contrary, the Framers invoked an array of broad,
adaptable terms as grounds for removal—and when the standard was temporarily narrowed
to “treason, or bribery,” Mason objected that it must reach “great and dangerous” offenses
against the Constitution. Here he cited Burke’s call to impeach Hastings, whose acts were
not crimes, but instead violated “those eternal laws of justice, which are our rule and our
birthright.”171 To the Framers, impeachment was about abuse of power, betrayal of nation,
and corruption of office and elections. It was meant to guard against these threats in every
manifestation—known and unknown—that might someday afflict the Republic.

That view appeared repeatedly in the state ratifying debates. Delegates opined that
the President could be impeached if he “deviates from his duty” or “dare[s] to abuse the
power vested in him by the people.”172 In North Carolina, Iredell noted that “the person
convicted [in an impeachment proceeding] is further liable to a trial at common law, and
may receive such common-law punishment … if it be punishable by that law” (emphasis
added).173 Similarly, in Virginia, George Nicholas declared that the President “will be
absolutely disqualified [by impeachment] to hold any place of profit, honor, or trust, and
liable to further punishment if he has committed such high crimes as are punishable at

165
2 Story, Commentaries, at 268.
166
See Bowman, High Crimes and Misdemeanors, at 44-47.
167
Constitutional Grounds for Presidential Impeachment (1974), at 22.
168
Berger, Impeachment, at 62.
169
Hoffer & Hull, Impeachment in America, at 1-95.
170
Bowman, High Crimes and Misdemeanors, at 244.
171
Edmund Burke, Reflections on the Revolution in France and Other Writings 409 (2015).
172
Quoted in Michael J. Gerhardt, Impeachment: What Everyone Needs to Know 60 (2018).
173
Constitutional Grounds for Presidential Impeachment (1974), at 23.

32
common law” (emphasis added).174 The premise underlying this statement—and
Iredell’s—is that some Presidential “high Crimes and Misdemeanors” were not punishable
by common law.

Leading minds echoed that position through the Nation’s early years. In Federalist
No. 65, Hamilton argued that impeachable offenses are defined by “the abuse or violation
of some public trust.”175 In that sense, he reasoned, “they are of a nature which may with
peculiar propriety be denominated POLITICAL, as they relate chiefly to injuries done
immediately to the society itself.”176 A few years later, Constitutional Convention delegate
James Wilson reiterated Hamilton’s point: “Impeachments, and offences and offenders
impeachable, come not ... within the sphere of ordinary jurisprudence. They are founded
on different principles, are governed by different maxims, and are directed to different
objects.”177 Writing in 1829, William Rawle described impeachment as reserved for “men
whose treachery to their country might be productive of the most serious disasters.”178 Four
years later, Justice Story emphasized that impeachable offenses ordinarily “must be
examined upon very broad and comprehensive principles of public policy and duty.”179

The American experience with impeachment confirms that lesson. A strong


majority of the impeachments voted by the House since 1789 have included “one or more
allegations that did not charge a violation of criminal law.”180 Several officials, moreover,
have subsequently been convicted on non-criminal articles of impeachment. For example,
Judge Robert Archbald was removed in 1912 for non-criminal speculation in coal
properties, and Judge Halsted Ritter was removed in 1936 for the non-criminal offense of
bringing his court “into scandal and disrepute.”181 As House Judiciary Committee
Chairman Hatton Sumners stated explicitly during Judge Ritter’s case, “We do not assume
the responsibility … of proving that the respondent is guilty of a crime as that term is
known to criminal jurisprudence.”182 The House has also applied that principle in
Presidential impeachments. Although President Nixon resigned before the House could
consider the articles of impeachment against him, the Judiciary Committee’s allegations
encompassed many non-criminal acts.183 And in President Clinton’s case, the Judiciary
Committee report accompanying articles of impeachment to the House floor stated that

174
Id.
175
Alexander Hamilton, Federalist No. 65, at 426.
176
Id.
177
James Wilson, Collected Works of James Wilson 736 (Kermit L. Hall and Mark David Hall ed. 2007).
178
William Rawle, A View of the Constitution of the United States of America 218 (1829).
179
2 Story, Commentaries, at 234.
180
Constitutional Grounds for Presidential Impeachment (1974), at 24.
181
REPORT OF THE COMMITTEE ON THE JUDICIARY, ROBERT W. ARCHBALD, JUDGE OF THE UNITED STATES
COMMERCE COURT, H.R. REP. NO. 62-946 (1912); H. Res. 422, 74th Cong. (1936) (enacted).
182
Berger, Impeachment, at 60.
183
See generally Committee Report on Nixon Articles of Impeachment (1974).

33
“the actions of President Clinton do not have to rise to the level of violating the federal
statute regarding obstruction of justice in order to justify impeachment.”184

History thus affords exceptionally clear and consistent evidence that impeachable
“high Crimes and Misdemeanors” are not limited to violations of the criminal code.

B. Constitutional Text and Structure

That historical conclusion is bolstered by the text and structure of the Constitution.
Starting with the text, we must assign weight to use of the word “high.” That is true not
only because “high Crimes and Misdemeanors” was a term of art with its own history, but
also because “high” connotes an offense against the State itself. Thus, “high” treason in
Britain was an offense against the Crown, whereas “petit” treason was the betrayal of a
superior by a subordinate. The Framers were aware of this when they incorporated “high”
as a limitation on impeachable offenses, signifying only constitutional wrongs.

That choice is particularly noteworthy because the Framers elsewhere referred to


“crimes,” “offenses,” and “punishment” without using this modifier—and so we know “the
Framers knew how to denote ordinary crimes when they wanted to do so.”185 For example,
the Fifth Amendment requires a grand jury indictment in cases of a “capital, or otherwise
infamous crime.”186 The Currency Clause, in turn, empowers Congress to “provide for the
Punishment of counterfeiting the Securities and current Coin of the United States.”187 The
Law of Nations Clause authorizes Congress to “define and punish Piracies and Felonies
committed on the high Seas, and Offenses against the Law of Nations.”188 And the
Interstate Extradition Clause provides that “[a] Person charged in any State with Treason,
Felony, or other Crime” who flees from one state to another shall be returned upon
request.189 Only in the Impeachment Clause did the Framers refer to “high” crimes. By
adding “high” in this one provision, while excluding it everywhere else, the Framers plainly
sought to capture a distinct category of offenses against the state.190

184
Committee Report on Clinton Articles of Impeachment (1998), at 66.
185
Tribe & Matz, To End a Presidency, at 40.
186
U.S. CONST. Amend. V, § 1.
187
U.S. CONST. Art. I, § 8, cl. 6.
188
U.S. CONST. Art. I, § 8, cl. 10.
189
U.S. CONST. Art. IV, § 2, cl. 2.
190
One might object that since “Treason” and “Bribery” are indictable crimes, the same must be true of “other
high Crimes and Misdemeanors.” But this argument would fail. Although it is true that “other high Crimes
and Misdemeanors” share certain characteristics with “Treason” and “Bribery,” the key question is which
characteristics unify them. And for all the reasons given here, it is wrong to conclude that criminality is the
unifying principle of impeachable offenses. Moreover, if the Framers’ goal was to limit impeachment to
violations of the criminal law, it is passing strange that the Impeachment Clause uses a term of art—“high
Crimes and Misdemeanors”—that appears neither in the criminal law itself nor anywhere else in the
Constitution (which does elsewhere refer both to “crimes” and “offenses”). It would have been easy to write
a provision limiting the impeachment power to serious crimes, and yet the Framers pointedly did not do so.

34
That interpretation is also most consistent with the structure of the Constitution.
This is true in three respects.

First, as explained above, the Impeachment Clause restricts the consequences of


impeachment to removal from office and disqualification from future federal officeholding.
That speaks to the fundamental character of impeachment. In Justice Story’s words, it is “a
proceeding purely of a political nature. It is not so much designed to punish an offender,
as to secure the state against gross official misdemeanors. It touches neither his person, nor
his property; but simply divests him of his political capacity.”191 Given that impeachment
exists to address threats to the political system, applies only to political officials, and
responds only by stripping political power, it makes sense to infer that “high Crimes and
Misdemeanors” are offenses against the political system rather than indictable crimes.

Second, if impeachment were restricted to crimes, impeachment proceedings would


be restricted to deciding whether the President had committed a specific crime. Such a view
would create tension between the Impeachment Clause and other provisions of the
Constitution. For example, the Double Jeopardy Clause protects against being tried twice
for the same crime. Yet the Impeachment Clause contemplates that an official, once
removed, can still face “Indictment, Trial, Judgment and Punishment, according to Law.”
It would be strange if the Framers forbade double jeopardy, yet allowed the President to be
tried in court for crimes after Congress convicted him in a proceeding that necessarily (and
exclusively) decided whether he was guilty of those very same crimes. 192 That oddity is
avoided only if impeachment proceedings are seen “in noncriminal terms,” which occurs
if impeachable offenses are understood as distinct from indictable crimes.193

Finally, the Constitution was originally understood as limiting Congress’s power


to create a federal law of crimes. It would therefore be strange if the Framers restricted
impeachment to criminal offenses, while denying Congress the ability to criminalize many
forms of Presidential wrongdoing that they repeatedly described as requiring impeachment.

To set this point in context, the Constitution expressly authorizes Congress to


criminalize only a handful of wrongful acts: “counterfeiting, piracy, ‘offenses against the
law of nations,’ and crimes that occur within the military.”194 Early Congresses did not
tread far beyond that core category of crimes, and the Supreme Court took a narrow view
of federal power to pass criminal statutes. It was not until much later—in the twentieth
century—that the Supreme Court came to recognize that Congress could enact a broader
criminal code. As a result, early federal criminal statutes “covered relatively few categories

191
2 Story, Commentaries, at 272.
192
See Berger, Impeachment, at 80.
193
Id.
194
William J. Stuntz, The Collapse of American Criminal Justice 99 (2011).

35
of offenses.”195 Many federal offenses were punishable only when committed “in special
places, and within peculiar jurisdictions, as, for instance, on the high seas, or in forts, navy-
yards, and arsenals ceded to the United States.”196

The Framers were not fools. They authorized impeachment for a reason, and that
reason would have been gutted if impeachment were limited to crimes. It is possible, of
course, that the Framers thought the common law, rather than federal statutes, would define
criminal offenses. That is undeniably true of “Bribery”: the Framers saw this impeachable
offense as defined by the common law of bribery as it was understood at the time. But it is
hard to believe that the Framers saw common law as the sole measure of impeachment. For
one thing, the common law did not address itself to many wrongs that could be committed
uniquely by the President in our republican system. The common law would thus have been
an extremely ineffective tool for achieving the Framers’ stated purposes in authorizing
impeachment. Moreover, the Supreme Court held in 1812 that there is no federal common
law of crimes.197 If the Framers thought only crimes could be impeachable offenses, and
hoped common law would describe the relevant crimes, then they made a tragic mistake—
and the Supreme Court’s 1812 decision ruined their plans for the impeachment power.198

Rather than assume the Framers wrote a Constitution full of empty words and
internal contradictions, it makes far more sense to agree with Hamilton that impeachment
is not about crimes. The better view, which the House itself has long embraced, confirms
that impeachment targets offenses against the Constitution that threaten democracy.199

C. The Purpose of Impeachment

The distinction between impeachable offenses and crimes also follows from the
fundamentally different purposes that impeachment and the criminal law serve. At bottom,
the impeachment power is “the first step in a remedial process—removal from office and
possible disqualification from holding future office.”200 It exists “primarily to maintain
constitutional government” and is addressed exclusively to abuses perpetrated by federal

195
Tribe & Matz, To End a Presidency, at 48.
196
2 Story, Commentaries, at 264.
197
United States v. Hudson and Goodwin, 11 U.S. 32 (1812).
198
In the alternative, one might say that “high Crimes and Misdemeanors” occur when the president violates
state criminal law. But that turns federalism upside down: invoking state criminal codes to supply the content
of the federal Impeachment Clause would grant states a bizarre and incongruous primacy in the constitutional
system. Especially given that impeachment is crucial to checks and balances within the federal government,
it would be nonsensical for states to effectively control when this power may be wielded by Congress.
Article III of the Constitution provides that “the Trial of all Crimes, except in Cases of Impeachment, shall
199

be by Jury.” Article III, §2. This provision recognizes that impeachable conduct may entail criminal
conduct—and clarifies that in such cases, the trial of an impeachment still occurs in the Senate, not by jury.
200
Constitutional Grounds for Presidential Impeachment (1974), at 24.

36
officeholders.201 It is through impeachment proceedings that “a President is called to
account for abusing powers that only a President possesses.”202 The criminal law, in
contrast, “sets a general standard of conduct that all must follow.”203 It applies to all persons
within its compass and ordinarily defines acts forbidden to everyone; in our legal tradition,
the criminal code “does not address itself [expressly] to the abuses of presidential
power.”204

Indeed, “the early Congresses—filled with Framers—didn’t even try to create a


body of criminal law addressing many of the specific abuses that motivated adoption of the
Impeachment Clause in the first place.”205 This partly reflects “a tacit judgment that it [did]
not deem such a code necessary.”206 But that is not the only explanation. The Constitution
vests “the sole Power of Impeachment” in the House; it is therefore doubtful that a statute
enacted by one Congress (and signed by the President) could bind the House at a later
date.207 Moreover, any such effort to define and criminalize all impeachable offenses would
quickly run aground. As Justice Story cautioned, impeachable offenses “are of so various
and complex a character, so utterly incapable of being defined, or classified, that the task
of positive legislation would be impracticable, if it were not almost absurd to attempt it.”208

There are also general characteristics of the criminal law that make criminality
inappropriate as an essential element of impeachable conduct. For example, criminal law
traditionally forbids acts, rather than failures to act, yet impeachable conduct “may include
the serious failure to discharge the affirmative duties imposed on the President by the
Constitution.”209 In addition, unlike a criminal case focused on very specific conduct and
nothing else, a Congressional impeachment proceeding may properly consider a broader
course of conduct or scheme that tends to subvert constitutional government.210 Finally,
the application of general criminal statutes to the President may raise constitutional issues
that have no bearing on an impeachment proceeding, the whole point of which is to assess
whether the President has abused power in ways requiring his removal from office.211

201
Id.
202
Id.
203
Id.
204
Id.
205
Tribe & Matz, To End a Presidency, at 48-49.
206
Berger, Impeachment, at 78.
207
Committee Report on Nixon Articles of Impeachment (1974), at 25.
208
2 Story, Commentaries, at 264.
209
Constitutional Grounds for Presidential Impeachment (1974), at 24
210
Id., at 24-25.
211
Robert S. Mueller, III, Report On The Investigation Into Russian Interference In The 2016 Presidential
Election, Vol. II at 170-181 (March 2019).

37
For all these reasons, “[a] requirement of criminality would be incompatible with
the intent of the framers to provide a mechanism broad enough to maintain the integrity of
constitutional government. Impeachment is a constitutional safety valve; to fulfill this
function, it must be flexible enough to cope with exigencies not now foreseeable.”212

D. The Limited Relevance of Criminality

As demonstrated, the President can commit “high Crimes and Misdemeanors”


without violating federal criminal law. “To conclude otherwise would be to ignore the
original meaning, purpose and history of the impeachment power; to subvert the
constitutional design of a system of checks and balances; and to leave the nation
unnecessarily vulnerable to abusive government officials.”213 Yet the criminal law is not
irrelevant. “Our criminal codes identify many terrible acts that would surely warrant
removal if committed by the chief executive.”214 Moreover, the President is sworn to
uphold the law. If he violates it while grossly abusing power, betraying the national interest
through foreign entanglements, or corrupting his office or elections, that weighs in favor
of impeaching him.

VI. Addressing Fallacies About Impeachment

Since the House began its impeachment inquiry, a number of inaccurate claims
have circulated about how impeachment works under the Constitution. To assist the
Committee in its deliberations, we address six issues of potential relevance: (1) the law that
governs House procedures for impeachment; (2) the law that governs the evaluation of
evidence, including where the President orders defiance of House subpoenas; (3) whether
the President can be impeached for the abuse of his executive powers; (4) whether the
President’s claims regarding his motives must be accepted at face value; (5) whether the
President is immune from impeachment if he attempts an impeachable offense but is caught
before he completes it; and (6) whether it is preferable to await the next election when a
President has sought to corrupt that very same election.

A. The Impeachment Process

It has been argued that the House has not followed proper procedure in its ongoing
impeachment inquiry. We have considered those arguments and find that they lack merit.

To start with first principles, the Constitution vests the House with the “sole Power
of Impeachment.”215 It also vests the House with the sole power to “determine the Rules

212
Constitutional Grounds for Presidential Impeachment (1974), at 25.
213
Keith E. Whittington, Must Impeachable Offenses Be Violations of the Criminal Code?, LAWFARE, Nov.
19, 2019.
214
Tribe & Matz, To End a Presidency, at 51.
215
U.S. CONST. Art. I, § 2, cl. 5.

38
of its Proceedings.”216 These provisions authorize the House to investigate potential “high
Crimes and Misdemeanors,” to draft and debate articles of impeachment, and to establish
whatever rules and procedures it deems proper for those proceedings.217

When the House wields its constitutional impeachment power, it functions like a
grand jury or prosecutor: its job is to figure out what the President did and why he did it,
and then to decide whether the President should be charged with impeachable offenses. If
the House approves any articles of impeachment, the President is entitled to present a full
defense at trial in the Senate. It is thus in the Senate, and not in the House, where the
President might properly raise certain protections associated with trials.218

Starting in May 2019, the Judiciary Committee undertook an inquiry to determine


whether to recommend articles of impeachment against President Trump. The Committee
subsequently confirmed, many times, that it was engaged in an impeachment investigation.
On June 11, 2019, the full House approved a resolution confirming that the Judiciary
Committee possessed “any and all necessary authority under Article I of the Constitution”
to continue its investigation; an accompanying Rules Committee Report emphasized that
the “purposes” of the inquiry included “whether to approve ‘articles of impeachment with
respect to the President.’”219 As the Judiciary Committee continued with its investigation,
evidence came to light that President Trump may have grossly abused the power of his
office in dealings with Ukraine. At that point, the House Permanent Select Committee on
Intelligence, and the House Oversight and Foreign Affairs Committees, began
investigating potential offenses relating to Ukraine. On September 24, 2019, House
Speaker Nancy Pelosi directed these committees, as well as the House Judiciary, Financial
Services and Ways and Means Committees, to “proceed with their investigations under
that umbrella of [an] impeachment inquiry.”220 Finally, on October 31, 2019, the full House
approved H. Res. 660, which directed the six committees “to continue their ongoing
investigations as part of the existing House of Representatives inquiry into whether
sufficient grounds exist for the House of Representatives to exercise its Constitutional
power to impeach Donald John Trump, President of the United States of America.”221

216
U.S. CONST. Art. I, § 5, cl. 2.
217
See David Pozen, Risk-Risk Tradeoffs in Presidential Impeachment, TAKE CARE, Jun. 6, 2018 (“Both
chambers of Congress enjoy vast discretion in how they run impeachment proceedings.”).
218
Contra Letter from Pat A. Cipollone, Counsel to the President, to Hon. Nancy Pelosi, Speaker of the
House, Hon. Adam B. Schiff, Chairman, H. Perm. Select Comm. on Intelligence, Hon. Eliot L. Engel,
Chairman, H. Foreign Affairs Comm., and Hon. Elijah E. Cummings, Chairman, H. Comm. on Oversight
and Reform (Oct. 8, 2019); Leader McCarthy Speech Against the Sham Impeachment Vote, Kevin McCarthy,
Republican Leader, Oct. 31, 2019.
219
H. Res. 430, 116th Cong. (2019); AUTHORIZING THE COMMITTEE ON THE JUDICIARY TO INITIATE OR
INTERVENE IN JUDICIAL PROCEEDINGS TO ENFORCE CERTAIN SUBPOENAS AND FOR OTHER PURPOSES TO
ACCOMPANY H. RES. 430, H.R. REP. 116-108, at 21 (2019).
220
Pelosi Remarks Announcing Impeachment Inquiry, Sep. 24 2019, NANCY PELOSI, SPEAKER OF THE HOUSE.
221
H. Res. 660, 116th Cong. (2019).

39
This approach to investigating potential impeachable offenses adheres to the
Constitution, the Rules of the House, and historical practice.222 House Committees have
frequently initiated and made substantial progress in impeachment inquiries before the full
House considered a resolution formalizing their efforts. That is what happened in the cases
of Presidents Johnson and Nixon, as well as in many judicial impeachments (which are
subject to the same constitutional provisions).223 Indeed, numerous judges have been
impeached without any prior vote of the full House authorizing a formal inquiry.224 It is
both customary and sensible for committees—particularly the Judiciary Committee—to
investigate evidence of serious wrongdoing before decisions are made by the full House.

In such investigations, the House’s initial task is to gather evidence. As is true of


virtually any competent investigation, whether governmental or private, the House has
historically conducted substantial parts of the initial fact-finding process out of public view
to ensure more accurate and complete testimony.225 In President Nixon’s case, for instance,
only the Judiciary Committee Chairman, Ranking Member, and Committee staff had
access to material gathered by the impeachment inquiry in its first several months.226 There
was no need for similar secrecy in President Clinton’s case, but only because the House
did not engage in a substantial investigation of its own; it largely adopted the facts set forth
in a report by Independent Counsel Kenneth Starr, who had spent years investigating
behind closed doors.227

When grand juries and prosecutors investigate wrongdoing by private citizens and
public officials, the person under investigation has no right to participate in the examination
of witnesses and evidence that precedes a decision on whether to file charges. That is black
letter law under the Constitution, even in serious criminal cases that threaten loss of life or
liberty. The same is true in impeachment proceedings, which threaten only loss of public
office. Accordingly, even if the full panoply of rights held by criminal defendants
hypothetically were to apply in the non-criminal setting of impeachment, the President has
no “due process right” to interfere with, or inject himself into, the House’s fact-finding
efforts. If the House ultimately approves articles of impeachment, any rights that the
President might hold are properly secured at trial in the Senate, where he may be afforded
an opportunity to present an evidentiary defense and test the strength of the House’s case.

222
See generally H.R. REP. NO. 116-108.
223
See 3 Hinds Ch. 75 § 2400 (President Johnson); 3 Deschler Ch. 14, § 15 (President Nixon); H.R. REP. NO.
101-36, at 13–16 (1988) (Judge Walter Nixon); H. R. Res. 320, 100th Cong. (Judge Alcee Hastings); H.R.
REP. NO. 99-688, at 3–7 (1986) (Judge Harry Claiborne); 3 Deschler Ch. 14 § 5 (Justice William O. Douglas).
224
See H. Res. 87, 101st Cong. (1989) (impeaching Judge Nixon); H. Res. 499, 100th Cong. (1988)
(impeaching Judge Hastings); H. Res. 461, 99th Cong. (1986) (impeaching Judge Claiborne).
225
See Tribe & Matz, To End A Presidency, at 92 (“Historically, the House and Senate have investigated
through their committees … Critically, although they may involve occasional public hearings, most in-
vestigatory activities must be kept secret until they have nearly reached an end.”).
226
Debate on Nixon Articles of Impeachment (1974), at 86.
227
Committee Report on Clinton Articles of Impeachment (1998), at 300.

40
Although under no constitutional or other legal obligation to do so, but consistent
with historical practice, the full House approved a resolution—H. Res. 660—that ensures
transparency, allows effective public hearings, and provides the President with
opportunities to participate. The privileges afforded under H. Res. 660 are even greater
than those provided to Presidents Nixon and Clinton. They allow the President or his
counsel to participate in House Judiciary Committee proceedings by presenting their case,
responding to evidence, submitting requests for additional evidence, attending hearings
(including non-public hearings), objecting to testimony, and cross-examining witnesses. In
addition, H. Res. 660 gave the minority the same rights to question witnesses that the
majority has, as has been true at every step of this impeachment proceeding.

The impeachment inquiry concerning President Trump has thus complied in every
respect with the Constitution, the Rules of the House, and historic practice of the House.

B. Evidentiary Considerations and Presidential Obstruction

The House impeachment inquiry has compiled substantial direct and circumstantial
evidence bearing on the question whether President Trump may have committed
impeachable offenses. President Trump has objected that some of this evidence comes from
witnesses lacking first-hand knowledge of his conduct. In the same breath, though, he has
ordered witnesses with first-hand knowledge to defy House subpoenas for testimony and
documents—and has done so in a categorical, unqualified manner. President Trump’s
evidentiary challenges are misplaced as a matter of constitutional law and common sense.

The Constitution does not prescribe rules of evidence for impeachment proceedings
in the House or Senate. Consistent with its sole powers to impeach and to determine the
rules of its proceedings, the House is constitutionally authorized to consider any evidence
that it believes may illuminate the issues before it. At this fact-finding stage, “no technical
‘rules of evidence’ apply,” and “[e]vidence may come from investigations by committee
staff, from grand jury matter made available to the committee, or from any other source.”228
The House may thus “subpoena documents, call witnesses, hold hearings, make legal de-
terminations, and undertake any other activities necessary to fulfill [its] mandate.”229 When
deciding whether to bring charges against the President, the House is not restricted by the
Constitution in deciding which evidence to consider or how much weight to afford it.

Indeed, were rules of evidence to apply anywhere, it would be in the Senate, where
impeachments are tried. Yet the Senate does not treat the law of evidence as controlling at
such trials.230 As one scholar explains, “rules of evidence were elaborated primarily to hold

228
Black & Bobbitt, Impeachment, at 9.
229
Tribe & Matz, To End a Presidency, at 129.
230
Gerhardt, The Federal Impeachment Process, at 42 (“[E]ven if the Senate could agree on such rules for
impeachment trials, they would not be enforceable against or binding on individual senators, each of whom
traditionally has had the discretion in an impeachment trial to follow any evidentiary standards he or she sees
fit.”).

41
juries within narrow limits. They have no place in the impeachment process. Both the
House and the Senate ought to hear and consider all evidence which seems relevant,
without regard to technical rules. Senators are in any case continually exposed to ‘hearsay’
evidence; they cannot be sequestered and kept away from newspapers, like a jury.”231

Instead of adopting abstract or inflexible rules, the House and Senate have long
relied on their common sense and good judgment to assess evidence in impeachments.
When evidence is relevant but there is reason to question its reliability, those considerations
affect how much weight the evidence is given, not whether it can be considered at all.

Here, the factual record is formidable and includes many forms of highly reliable
evidence. It goes without saying, however, that the record might be more expansive if the
House had full access to the documents and testimony it has lawfully subpoenaed from
government officials. The reason the House lacks such access is an unprecedented decision
by President Trump to order a total blockade of the House impeachment inquiry.

In contrast, the conduct of prior chief executives illustrates the lengths to which
they complied with impeachment inquiries. As President James Polk conceded, the “power
of the House” in cases of impeachment “would penetrate into the most secret recesses of
the Executive Departments,” and “could command the attendance of any and every agent
of the Government, and compel them to produce all papers, public or private, official or
unofficial, and to testify on oath to all facts within their knowledge.”232 Decades later, when
the House conducted an impeachment inquiry into President Johnson, it interviewed
cabinet officials and Presidential aides, obtained extensive records, and heard testimony
about conversations with Presidential advisors.233 Presidents Grover Cleveland, Ulysses S.
Grant, and Theodore Roosevelt each confirmed that Congress could obtain otherwise-
shielded executive branch documents in an impeachment inquiry.234 And in President
Nixon’s case—where the President’s refusal to turn over tapes led to an article of
impeachment—the House Judiciary Committee still heard testimony from his chief of staff
(H.R. Haldeman), special counsel (Charles Colson), personal attorney (Herbert Kalmbach),
and deputy assistant (Alexander Butterfield). Indeed, with respect to the Senate Watergate
investigation, President Nixon stated: “All members of the White House Staff will appear
voluntarily when requested by the committee. They will testify under oath, and they will

231
Black & Bobbitt, Impeachment, at 18. see also Gerhardt, The Federal Impeachment Process, at 117 (“Both
state and federal courts require special rules of evidence to make trials more efficient and fair or to keep
certain evidence away from a jury, whose members might not understand or appreciate its reliability,
credibility, or potentially prejudicial effect.”).
232
H.R. Jour., 29th Cong., 1st Sess., 693 (1846); 4 James D. Richardson ed., Messages and Papers of
Presidents 434-35 (1896).
233
See generally Reports of Committees, Impeachment Investigation, 40th Cong., 1st Sess. 183-578 (1867).
234
See Jonathan David Shaub, The Executive’s Privilege: Rethinking the President’s Power to Withhold
Information, LAWFARE (Oct. 31, 2019).

42
answer fully all proper questions.”235 President Trump’s categorical blockade of the House
impeachment inquiry has no analogue in the history of the Republic.236

As a matter of constitutional law, the House may properly conclude that a


President’s obstruction of Congress is relevant to assessing the evidentiary record in an
impeachment inquiry. For centuries, courts have recognized that “when a party has relevant
evidence within his control which he fails to produce, that failure gives rise to an inference
that the evidence is unfavorable to him.”237 Moreover, it is routine for courts to draw
adverse inferences where a party acts in bad faith to conceal or destroy evidence or preclude
witnesses from testifying.238 Although those judicial rules do not control here, they are
instructive in confirming that parties who interfere with fact-finding processes can suffer
an evidentiary sanction. Consistent with that commonsense principle, the House has
informed the administration that defiance of subpoenas at the direction or behest of the
President or the White House could justify an adverse inference against the President. In
light of President Trump’s unlawful and unqualified direction that governmental officials
violate their legal responsibilities to Congress, as well as his pattern of witness
intimidation, the House may reasonably infer that their testimony would be harmful to the
President—or at least not exculpatory. If this evidence were helpful to the President, he
would not break the law to keep it hidden, nor would he engage in public acts of harassment
to scare other witnesses who might consider coming forward.239

One noteworthy result of President Trump’s obstruction is that the House has been
improperly denied testimony by certain government officials who could have offered first-
hand accounts of relevant events. That does not leave the House at sea: there is still robust
evidence, both documentary and testimonial, bearing directly on his conduct and motives.

235
The President’s Remarks Announcing Developments and Procedures to be Followed in Connection with
the Investigation, THE WHITE HOUSE Apr. 17, 1973. President Nixon initially stated that members of his
“personal staff” would “decline a request for a formal appearance before a committee of the Congress,” but
reversed course approximately one month later., Statement by the President, Executive Privilege THE WHITE
HOUSE Mar. 12, 1973.
236
See Tribe & Matz, To End A Presidency, at 129 (“Congress’s investigatory powers are at their zenith in
the realm of impeachment. They should ordinarily overcome almost any claim of executive privilege asserted
by the president.”).
237
Int’l Union, United Auto., Aerospace & Agr. Implement Workers of Am. (UAW) v. N. L. R. B., 459 F.2d
1329, 1336 (D.C. Cir. 1972); see also Interstate Circuit v. United States, 306 U.S. 208, 225–26 (1939); Rossi
v. United States, 289 U.S. 89, 91–92 (1933); Mammoth Oil Co. v. United States, 275 U.S. 13, 51–53 (1927);
Burdine v. Johnson, 262 F.3d 336, 366 (5th Cir. 2001) (collecting cases); United States v. Pitts, 918 F.2d
197, 199 (D.C. Cir. 1990) (holding that, where a missing witness has “so much to offer that one would expect
[him] to take the stand,” and where “one of the parties had some special ability to produce him,” the law
allows an inference “that the missing witness would have given testimony damaging to that party”).
238
See, e.g., Bracey v. Grondin, 712 F.3d 1012, 1018 (7th Cir. 2013); Residential Funding Corp. v. DeGeorge
Fin. Corp., 306 F.3d 99, 107 (2d Cir. 2002); Nation-Wide Check Corp. v. Forest Hills Distributors, Inc., 692
F.2d 214, 217 (1st Cir. 1982); see also 2 Jones on Evidence § 13:12 & § 13:15 (7th ed. 2019 update).
239
If the President could order all Executive Branch agencies and officials to defy House impeachment
inquiries, and if the House were unable to draw any inferences from that order with respect to the President’s
alleged misconduct, the impeachment power would be a nullity in many cases where it plainly should apply.

43
But especially given the President’s obstruction of Congress, the House is free under the
Constitution to consider reliable testimony from officials who overheard—or later learned
about—statements by the President to witnesses whose testimony he has blocked.240

To summarize: just like grand jurors and prosecutors, the House is not subject to
rigid evidentiary rules in deciding whether to approve articles. Members of the House are
trusted to fairly weigh evidence in an impeachment inquiry. Where the President illegally
seeks to obstruct such an inquiry, the House is free to infer that evidence blocked from its
view is harmful to the President’s position. It is also free to rely on other relevant, reliable
evidence that illuminates the ultimate factual issues. The President has no right to defy an
impeachment inquiry and then demand that the House turn back because it lacks the very
evidence he unlawfully concealed. If anything, such conduct confirms that the President
sees himself as above the law and may therefore bear on the question of impeachment.241

C. Abuse of Presidential Power is Impeachable

The powers of the President are immense, but they are not absolute. That principle
applies to the current President just as it applied to his predecessors. President Nixon erred
in asserting that “when the President does it, that means it is not illegal.”242 And President
Trump was equally mistaken when he declared he had “the right to do whatever I want as
president.”243 The Constitution always matches power with constraint. That is true even of
powers vested exclusively in the chief executive. If those powers are invoked for corrupt

240
Under the Federal Rules of Evidence—which, again, are not applicable in Congressional impeachment
proceedings—judges sometimes limit witnesses from offering testimony about someone else’s out-of-court
statements. They do so for reasons respecting reliability and with an eye to the unique risks presented by
unsophisticated juries that may not properly evaluate evidence. But because hearsay evidence can in fact be
highly reliable, and because it is “often relevant,” Tome v. United States, 513 U.S. 150, 163 (1995), there are
many circumstances in which such testimony is admissible in federal judicial proceedings. Those
circumstances include, but are by no means limited to, recorded recollections, records of regularly conducted
activity, records of a public office, excited utterances, and statements against penal or other interest.
Moreover, where hearsay evidence bears indicia of reliability, it is regularly used in many other profoundly
important contexts, including federal sentencing and immigration proceedings. See, e.g., Arrazabal v. Barr,
929 F.3d 451, 462 (7th Cir. 2019); United States v. Mitrovic, 890 F.3d 1217, 1222 (11th Cir. 2018); United
States v. Woods, 596 F.3d 445, 448 (8th Cir. 2010). Ironically, although some have complained that hearings
related to the Ukraine affair initially occurred out of public sight, one reason for that measure was to ensure
the integrity of witness testimony. Where multiple witnesses testified to the same point in separate,
confidential hearings, that factual conclusion may be seen as corroborated and more highly reliable.
241
The President has advanced numerous arguments to justify his across-the-board defiance of the House
impeachment inquiry. These arguments lack merit. As this Committee recognized when it impeached
President Nixon for obstruction of Congress, the impeachment power includes a corresponding power of
inquiry that allows the House to investigate the Executive Branch and compel compliance with its subpoenas.
242
Document: Transcript of David Frost’s Interview with Richard Nixon, 1977, TEACHING AMERICAN
HISTORY.
243
Michael Brice-Saddler, While Bemoaning Mueller Probe, Trump Falsely Says the Constitution Gives
Him ‘The Right To Do Whatever I Want”, THE WASHINGTON POST, July 23, 2019.

44
reasons, or in an abusive manner that threatens harm to constitutional governance, the
President is subject to impeachment for “high Crimes and Misdemeanors.”

This conclusion follows from the Constitution’s history and structure. As explained
above, the Framers created a formidable Presidency, which they entrusted with “the
executive Power” and a host of additional authorities. For example, the President alone can
confer pardons, sign or veto legislation, recognize foreign nations, serve as Commander in
Chief of the armed forces, and appoint or remove principal officers. The President also
plays a significant (though not exclusive) role in conducting diplomacy, supervising law
enforcement, and protecting national security. These are daunting powers for any one
person to wield. If put to nefarious ends, they could wreak havoc on our democracy.

The Framers knew this. Fearful of tyranny in all its forms, they saw impeachment
as a necessary guarantee that Presidents could be held accountable for how they exercised
executive power. Many delegates at the Constitutional Convention and state ratifying
conventions made this point, including Madison, Randolph, Pinckney, Stillman, and
Iredell. Their view was widely shared. As James Wilson observed in Pennsylvania, “we
have a responsibility in the person of our President”—who is “possessed of power”—since
“far from being above the laws,” he is “amenable to them … by impeachment.”244
Hamilton struck the same note. In Federalist No. 70, he remarked that the Constitution
affords Americans the “greatest securities they can have for the faithful exercise of any
delegated power,” including the power to discover “with facility and clearness” any
misconduct requiring “removal from office.”245 Impeachment and executive power were
thus closely intertwined in the Framers’ constitutional plan: the President could be vested
with awesome power, but only because he faced removal from office for grave abuses.

The architects of checks and balances meant no exceptions to this rule. There is no
power in the Constitution that a President can exercise immune from legal consequence.
The existence of any such unchecked and uncheckable authority in the federal government
would offend the bedrock principle that nobody is above the law. It would also upend the
reasons why our Framers wrote impeachment into the Constitution: the exact forms of
Presidential wrongdoing that they discussed in Philadelphia could be committed through
use of executive powers, and it is unthinkable that the Framers left the Nation defenseless
in such cases. In fact, when questioned by Mason in Virginia, Madison expressly stated
that the President could be impeached for abuse of his exclusive pardon power—a view
that the Supreme Court later echoed in Ex Parte Grossman.246 By the same token, a
President could surely be impeached for treason if he fired the Attorney General to thwart
244
2 Elliot, Debates in the Several State Conventions, at 480.
245
Alexander Hamilton, Federalist No. 70, at 456.
246
3 Elliot, Debates in the Several State Conventions, 497-98; Ex Parte Grossman, 267 U.S. at 121. Madison
adhered to this understanding after the Constitution was ratified. In 1789, he explained to his colleagues in
the House that the President would be subject to impeachment for abuse of the removal power—which is
held by the President alone—“if he suffers [his appointees] to perpetrate with impunity High crimes or
misdemeanors against the United States, or neglects to superintend their conduct, so as to check their
excesses.” 1 Annals of Congress 387 (1789).

45
the unmasking of an enemy spy in wartime; he could impeached for bribery if he offered
to divulge state secrets to a foreign nation, conditioned on regulatory exemptions for his
family business.247 Simply put, “the fact that a power is exclusive to the executive—that
is, the president alone may exercise it—does not mean the power cannot be exercised in
clear bad faith, and that Congress cannot look into or act upon knowledge of that abuse.”248

The rule that abuse of power can lead to removal encompasses all three branches.
The Impeachment Clause applies to “The President, Vice President and all civil Officers
of the United States,” including Article III judges.249 There is no exception to impeachment
for misconduct by federal judges involving the exercise of their official powers. In fact, the
opposite is true: “If in the exercise of the powers with which they are clothed as ministers
of justice, [judges] act with partiality, or maliciously, or corruptly, or arbitrarily, or
oppressively, they may be called to an account by impeachment.”250 Similarly, if Members
of Congress exercise legislative power abusively or with corrupt purposes, they may be
removed pursuant to the Expulsion Clause, which permits each house of Congress to expel
a member “with the Concurrence of two thirds.”251 Nobody is entitled to wield power under
the Constitution if they ignore or betray the Nation’s interests to advance their own.

This is confirmed by past practice of the House. President Nixon’s case directly
illustrates the point. As head of the Executive Branch, he had the power to appoint and
remove law enforcement officials, to issue pardons, and to oversee the White House, IRS,
CIA, and FBI. But he did not have any warrant to exercise these Presidential powers
abusively or corruptly. When he did so, the House Judiciary Committee properly approved
multiple articles of impeachment against him. Several decades later, the House impeached
President Clinton. There, the House witnessed substantial disagreement over whether the
President could be impeached for obstruction of justice that did not involve using the
powers of his office. But it was universally presumed—and never seriously questioned—
that the President could be impeached for obstruction of justice that did involve abuse of
those powers.252 That view rested firmly on a correct understanding of the Constitution.

Our Constitution rejects pretensions to monarchy and binds Presidents with law. A
President who sees no limit on his power manifestly threatens the Republic.

247
Scholars have offered many examples and hypotheticals that they see as illustrative of this point. See
Bowman, High Crimes and Misdemeanors, at 258; Black & Bobbitt, Impeachment, 115; Hemel & Posner,
Presidential Obstruction of Justice, at 1297; Tribe & Matz, To End a Presidency, at 61.
Jane Chong, Impeachment-Proof? The President’s Unconstitutional Abuse of His Constitutional Powers,
248

LAWFARE, Jan. 2 2018.


249
U.S. CONST. Art. II, § 4.
250
Bradley v. Fisher 80 U.S. 335, 350 (1871).
251
U.S. CONST. Art. I, § 5, cl. 2.
252
See generally 1998 Background and History of Impeachment Hearing.

46
D. Presidential Pretexts Need Not Be Accepted at Face Value

Impeachable offenses are often defined by corrupt intent. To repeat Iredell, “the
president would be liable to impeachments [if] he had … acted from some corrupt motive
or other,” or if he was “willfully abusing his trust.”253 Consistent with that teaching, both
“Treason” and “Bribery” require proof that the President acted with an improper state of
mind, as would many other offenses described as impeachable at the Constitutional
Convention. Contrary to occasional suggestions that the House may not examine the
President’s intent, an impeachment inquiry may therefore require the House to determine
why the President acted the way he did. Understanding the President’s motives may clarify
whether he used power in forbidden ways, whether he was faithless in executing the laws,
and whether he poses a continuing danger to the Nation if allowed to remain in office.

When the House probes a President’s state of mind, its mandate is to find the facts.
There is no room for legal fictions or lawyerly tricks that distort a clear assessment of the
President’s thinking. That means evaluating the President’s explanations to see if they ring
true. The question is not whether the President’s conduct could have resulted from innocent
motives. It is whether the President’s real reasons—the ones actually in his mind as he
exercised power—were legitimate. The Framers designed impeachment to root out abuse
and corruption, even when a President masks improper intent with cover stories.

Accordingly, where the President’s explanation of his motives defies common


sense, or is otherwise unbelievable, the House is free to reject the pretextual explanation
and to conclude that the President’s false account of his thinking is itself evidence that he
acted with corrupt motives. The President’s honesty in an impeachment inquiry, or his lack
thereof, can thus shed light on the underlying issue.254

President Nixon’s case highlights the point. In its discussion of an article of


impeachment for abuse of power, the House Judiciary Committee concluded that he had
“falsely used a national security pretext” to direct executive agencies to engage in unlawful
electronic surveillance investigations, thus violating “the constitutional rights of
citizens.”255 In its discussion of the same article, the Committee also found that President
Nixon had interfered with the Justice Department by ordering it to cease investigating a
crime “on the pretext that it involved national security.”256 President Nixon’s repeated
claim that he had acted to protect national security could not be squared with the facts, and
so the Committee rejected it in approving articles of impeachment against him for targeting
political opponents.

253
Id., at 49.
254
See Tribe & Matz, To End A Presidency, at 92 (“Does the president admit error, apologize, and clean
house? Does he prove his innocence, or at least his reasonable good faith? Or does he lie and obstruct until
the bitter end? Maybe he fires investigators and stonewalls prosecutors? … These data points are invaluable
when Congress asks whether leaving the president in office would pose a continuing threat to the nation.”).
255
Committee Report on Nixon Articles of Impeachment (1974), at 146.
256
Id., at 179.

47
Testing whether someone has falsely characterized their motives requires careful
attention to the facts. In rare cases, “some implausible, fantastic, and silly explanations
could be found to be pretextual without any further evidence.”257 Sifting truth from fiction,
though, usually demands a thorough review of the record—and a healthy dose of common
sense. The question is whether “the evidence tells a story that does not match the
explanation.”258

Because courts assess motive all the time, they have identified warning signs that
an explanation may be untrustworthy. Those red flags include the following:

First, lack of fit between conduct and explanation. This exists when someone claims
they were trying to achieve a specific goal but then engaged in conduct poorly tailored to
achieving it.259 For instance, imagine the President claims that he wants to solve a particular
problem—but then he ignores many clear examples of that problem, weakens rules meant
to stop it from occurring, acts in ways unlikely to address it, and seeks to punish only two
alleged violators (both of whom happen to be his competitors). The lack of fit between his
punitive conduct and his explanation for it strongly suggests that the explanation is false,
and that he invented it as a pretext for corruptly targeting his competitors.

Second, arbitrary discrimination. When someone claims they were acting for a
particular reason, look to see if they treated similarly-situated individuals the same.260 For
example, if a President says that people doing business abroad should not engage in specific
practices, does he punish everyone who breaks that rule, or does he pick and choose? If he
picks and chooses, is there a good reason why he targets some people and not others, or
does he appear to be targeting people for reasons unrelated to his stated motive? Where
similarly-situated people are treated differently, the President should be able to explain
why; if no such explanation exists, it follows that hidden motives are in play.

Third, shifting explanations. When someone repeatedly changes their story, it


makes sense to infer that they began with a lie and may still be lying.261 That is true in daily
life and it is true in impeachments. The House may therefore doubt the President’s account
of his motives when he first denies that something occurred; then admits that it occurred
but denies key facts; then admits those facts and tries to explain them away; and then

257
Purkett v. Elem, 514 U.S. 765, 776–77 (1995) (Stevens, J., dissenting).
258
Dep’t of Commerce v. N.Y., No. 18-966, at 27 (U.S. Jun. 27, 2019).
259
See Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620, 632 (1996); Albemarle Paper Co. v. Moody, 422 U.S. 405, 425 (1975);
Miller-El v. Dretke, 545 U.S. 231, 260 (2005).
260
Flowers v. Mississippi, 139 S. Ct. 2228, 2249 (2019); Miller-El v. Cockrell, 537 U.S. 322, 345 (2003).
261
See Foster v. Chatman, 136 S. Ct. 1737, 1754 (2016); Evans v. Sebelius, 716 F.3d 617, 620–21 (D.C. Cir.
2013); Geleta v. Gray, 645 F.3d 408, 413–14 (D.C. Cir. 2011); EEOC v. Sears Roebuck & Co., 243 F.3d
846, 853 (4th Cir.2001); Domínguez–Cruz v. Suttle Caribe, Inc., 202 F.3d 424, 432 (1st Cir. 2000); Thurman
v. Yellow Freight Sys., Inc., 90 F.3d 1160, 1167 (6th Cir. 1996).

48
changes his explanation as more evidence comes to light. Simply stated, the House is “not
required to exhibit a naiveté from which ordinary citizens are free.”262

Fourth, irregular decisionmaking. When someone breaks from the normal method
of making decisions, and instead acts covertly or strangely, there is cause for suspicion. As
the Supreme Court has reasoned, “[t]he specific sequence of events leading up the
challenged decision” may “shed some light on the decisionmaker’s purposes”—and
“[d]epartures from the normal procedural sequence” might “afford evidence that improper
purposes are playing a role.”263 There are many personnel and procedures in place to ensure
sound decisionmaking in the Executive Branch. When they are ignored, or replaced by
secretive irregular channels, the House must closely scrutinize Presidential conduct.

Finally, explanations based on falsehoods. Where someone explains why they


acted a certain way, but the explanation depends on demonstrably false facts, then their
explanation is suspect.264 For example, if a President publicly states that he withheld funds
from a foreign nation due to its failure to meet certain conditions, but the federal agencies
responsible for monitoring those conditions certify that they were satisfied, the House may
conclude that the President’s explanation is only a distraction from the truth.

When one or more of these red flags is present, there is reason to doubt that the
President’s account of his motives is accurate. When they are all present simultaneously,
that conclusion is virtually unavoidable. Thus, in examining the President’s motives as part
of an impeachment inquiry, the House must test his story against the evidence to see if it
holds water. If it does not, the House may find that he acted with corrupt motives—and
that he has made false statements as part of an effort to stymie the impeachment inquiry.

E. Attempted Presidential Misconduct Is Impeachable

As a matter of settled constitutional law, and contrary to recent suggestions


otherwise, attempted Presidential wrongdoing can be impeachable. This is clear from the
records of the Constitutional Convention. In the momentous exchange that led to adoption
of the “high Crimes and Misdemeanors” standard, Mason championed impeaching
Presidents for any “great and dangerous offenses.” It was therefore necessary, he argued,
to avoid a narrow standard that would prevent impeachment for “attempts to subvert the
Constitution” (emphasis added). Then, only minutes later, it was Mason himself who
suggested “high Crimes and Misdemeanors” as the test for Presidential impeachment. The
very author of the relevant constitutional text thus made clear it must cover “attempts.”

262
United States v. Stanchich, 550 F.2d 1294, 1300 (2nd Cir. 1977) (Friendly, J.) (making a similar point
about federal judges).
263
See Vill. of Arlington Heights v. Metro. Hous. Dev. Corp., 429 U.S. 252, 267 (1977).
264
See, e.g., Reeves v. Sanderson Plumbing Products, 530 U.S. 133, 147 (2000); Geleta v. Gray, 645 F.3d
408, 414 (D.C. Cir. 2011); Czekalski v. Peters, 475 F.3d 360, 366 (D.C. Cir. 2007); Murray v. Gilmore, 406
F.3d 708, 716 (D.C. Cir. 2005); Salazar v. Wash. Metro. Transit Auth., 401 F.3d 504, 511–12 (D.C. Cir.
2005); Anderson v. Zubieta, 180 F.3d 329, 348 (D.C. Cir. 1999).

49
The House Judiciary Committee reached this conclusion in President Nixon’s case.
Its analysis is compelling and consistent with Mason’s reasoning:

In some of the instances in which Richard M. Nixon abused the powers of


his office, his unlawful or improper objective was not achieved. But this
does not make the abuse of power any less serious, nor diminish the
applicability of the impeachment remedy. The principle was stated by
Supreme Court Justice William Johnson in 1808: “If an officer attempt[s]
an act inconsistent with the duties of his station, it is presumed that the
failure of the attempt would not exempt him from liability to impeachment.
Should a President head a conspiracy for the usurpation of absolute power,
it is hoped that no one will contend that defeating his machinations would
restore him to innocence.” Gilchrist v. Collector of Charleston, 10 F. Cas.
355, 365 (No. 5, 420) (C.C.D.S.C. 1808).

Adhering to this legal analysis, the Committee approved articles of impeachment against
President Nixon that encompassed acts of attempted wrongdoing that went nowhere or
were thwarted. That includes President Nixon’s attempt to block an investigation by the
Patman Committee into the Watergate break-ins,265 his attempt to block testimony by
former aides,266 his attempt to “narrow and divert” the Senate Select Committee’s
investigation,267 and his attempt to have the IRS open tax audits of 575 members of George
McGovern’s staff and contributors to his campaign, at a time when McGovern was
President Nixon’s political opponent in the upcoming 1972 presidential election.268
Moreover, the article of impeachment against President Nixon for abuse of power charged
that he “attempted to prejudice the constitutional right of an accused to a fair trial.”269

History thus confirms that defiance by his own aides do not afford the President a
defense to impeachment. The Nation is not required to cross its fingers and hope White
House staff will persist in ignoring or sidelining a President who orders them to execute
“high Crimes and Misdemeanors.” Nor can a President escape impeachment just because
his corrupt plan to abuse power or manipulate elections was discovered and abandoned. It
is inconceivable that our Framers authorized the removal of Presidents who engage in
treason or bribery, but disallowed the removal of Presidents who attempt such offenses and
are caught before they succeed. Moreover, a President who takes concrete steps toward
engaging in impeachable conduct is not entitled to any benefit of the doubt. As one scholar
remarks in the context of attempts to manipulate elections, “when a substantial attempt is
made by a candidate to procure the presidency by corrupt means, we may presume that he

265
Committee Report on Nixon Articles of Impeachment (1974), at 64.
266
Id., at 120.
267
Id.
268
Id., at 143.
269
Id., at 3.

50
at least thought this would make a difference in the outcome, and thus we should resolve
any doubts as to the effects of his efforts against him.”270

Common sense confirms what the law provides: a President may be impeached
where he attempts a grave abuse of power, is caught along the way, abandons his plan, and
subsequently seeks to conceal his wrongdoing. A President who attempts impeachable
offenses will surely attempt them again. The impeachment power exists so that the Nation
can remove such Presidents from power before their attempts finally succeed.

F. Impeachment is Part of Democratic Governance

As House Judiciary Committee Chairman Peter Rodino emphasized in 1974, “it is


under our Constitution, the supreme law of our land, that we proceed through the sole
power of impeachment.”271 Impeachment is part of democratic constitutional governance,
not an exception to it. It results in the President’s removal from office only when a majority
of the House, and then a super-majority of the Senate, conclude that he has engaged in
sufficiently grave misconduct that his term in office must be brought to an early end. This
process does not “nullify” the last election. No President is entitled to persist in office after
committing “high Crimes and Misdemeanors,” and no voter is entitled to expect that their
preferred candidate will do so. Under the Constitution, when a President engages in great
and dangerous offenses against the Nation—thus betraying their Oath of Office—
impeachment and removal by Congress may be necessary to protect our democracy.

The Framers considered relying solely on elections, rather than impeachment, to


remove wayward Presidents. But they overwhelmingly rejected that position. As Madison
warned, waiting so long “might be fatal to the Republic.”272 Particularly where the
President’s misconduct is aimed at corrupting our democracy, relying on elections to solve
the problem is insufficient: it makes no sense to wait for the ballot box when a President
stands accused of interfering with elections and is poised to do so again. Numerous Framers
spoke directly to this point at the Constitutional Convention. Impeachment is the remedy
for a President who will do anything, legal or not, to remain in office. Allowing the
President a free pass is thus the wrong move when he is caught trying to corrupt elections
in the final year of his first four-year term—just as he prepares to face the voters.

Holding the President accountable for “high Crimes and Misdemeanors” not only
upholds democracy, but also vindicates the separation of powers. Representative Robert
Kastenmeier explained this well in 1974: “The power of impeachment is not intended to
obstruct or weaken the office of the Presidency. It is intended as a final remedy against
executive excess … [a]nd it is the obligation of the Congress to defend a democratic society

270
Black & Bobbitt, Impeachment, at 93.
271
Debate on Nixon Articles of Impeachment (1974), at 2.
272
Elliot, Debates on the Adoption of the Federal Constitution, at 341.

51
against a Chief Executive who might be corrupt.”273 The impeachment power thus restores
balance and order when Presidential misconduct threatens constitutional governance.

VII. Conclusion

As Madison recognized, “In framing a government which is to be administered by


men over men, the great difficulty lies in this: You must first enable the government to
control the governed; and in the next place oblige it control itself.”274 Impeachment is the
House’s last and most extraordinary resort when faced with a President who threatens our
constitutional system. It is a terrible power, but only “because it was forged to counter a
terrible power: the despot who deems himself to be above the law.”275 The consideration
of articles of impeachment is always a sad and solemn undertaking. In the end, it is the
House—speaking for the Nation as a whole—that must decide whether the President’s
conduct rises to the level of “high Crimes and Misdemeanors” warranting impeachment.

273
Debate on Nixon Articles of Impeachment (1974), at 16.
274
James Madison, Federalist No. 51, at 356.
275
Jill Lepore, The Invention - And Reinvention – Of Impeachment, THE NEW YORKER, Oct. 21 2019.

52

You might also like