Clancy Martin - The Philosophy of Deception-Oxford University Press (2009)
Clancy Martin - The Philosophy of Deception-Oxford University Press (2009)
Clancy Martin - The Philosophy of Deception-Oxford University Press (2009)
1
2009
1
Oxford University Press, Inc., publishes works that further
Oxford University’s objective of excellence
in research, scholarship, and education.
987654321
Printed in the United States of America
on acid-free paper
For Robert C. Solomon (1942–2007)
beloved teacher, mentor, and friend
This page intentionally left blank
Contents
Contributors, ix
Index, 277
Contributors
ix
x Contributors
Clancy Martin
Sometimes we tell a lie, and there’s no doubt about it. The classic exam-
ple is the lie a child tells when asked by his mother if he broke the cookie
jar. “I don’t know who did it,” the boy says, and he is lying: he knows full
well that the jar fell from the counter and shattered when he was reach-
ing hopefully down and in for the last cookie. Similarly, there are cases
of self-deception that are so straightforward no reasonable person can
deny that here, at least, someone is lying to himself. To take an example
suggested by Amelie Rorty in her chapter in this collection: your enor-
mously accomplished, MacArthur-winning full professor friend comes to
you and says, “They just denied my husband tenure, but the fact is his
research is so much better than my own.” Here we see that whatever
her motives—as Rorty points out, and Alfred Mele would agree, those
motives may be considerably more complex than they initially appear—
your friend is simply lying to herself. The boy in the first example is lying,
and he knows it, he’s not in the least self-deceived about it; the woman in
the second example is thoroughly self-deceived, and she does not know it
(though we would say that at some level she must), and therefore she is
not lying when she reports her belief to you.
But most of the lies we tell, whether we are telling them to one another
or to ourselves, are not nearly so clear-cut. Lies and self-deceptions seem
to exist along a continuum, with cases like the extreme ones I just men-
tioned on either end, and in the middle the many cases where the lies we
tell others are inseparably mixed up with lies we tell ourselves. As Robert
C. Solomon says, “Deception and self-deception are mutually entangled
phenomena . . . to fool ourselves, we must either fool or exclude others;
and to successfully fool others, we best fool ourselves” (page 25, this vol-
ume). During the worst days of the second war in Iraq, the cover of the
European edition of the Economist showed President George W. Bush
walking arm in arm with British Prime Minister Tony Blair, with the title
“Sincere Deceivers.” The point, of course, was that it was neither the case
that Bush and Blair took themselves to be telling the truth during the
3
4 The Philosophy of Deception
run-up to the war and then found themselves to be mistaken (though this
was the official story both preferred), nor was it the case that they cyni-
cally lied in order to manipulate their countries into going to war. One
suspects that the truth was more complicated, more interesting, and more
frightening: what happened, we might hypothesize, is that both leaders
deceived themselves and deceived one another, believing their own lies
and the lies each was telling the other, for strategic reasons so that they
could achieve the goals they had in mind, and once they were involved
in this dizzying whirl of motivated deceptions and self-deceptions, they
suddenly found themselves in a position to sell their deceptions with real
sincerity to the public. The young Nietzsche put it nicely:
With all great deceivers there is a noteworthy occurrence to which they
owe their power. In the actual act of deception, with all its preparations,
its enthralling in voice, expression and gesture, in the midst of the scenery
designed to give it effect, they are overcome by belief in themselves Self-
deception has to exist if a grand effect is to be produced. For men believe in
the truth of that which is plainly strongly believed.1
In part I of this book, the essays tend to be concerned with what we might
call the how of deception: the ways in which deception, both of oneself
and others, is actually carried out in human life. This concern naturally
takes us into some quite technical theoretical territory: take the case of
Wrathall’s phenomenology of deception in sense-perception, for exam-
ple. But the larger emphasis here is generally on deception in our human
lives. The essays in part II tend to be more concerned with theoretical
philosophical debates in the literature on deception and self-deception.
Thomas Carson’s excellent and exhaustive analysis of the definition of
lying and other similar concepts, for example, covers all of the technical
philosophical terrain on that notoriously difficult project. Similarly, Mele’s
piece brings us completely up to date on the literature in self-deception.
I will now briefly canvass the individual chapters. As noted, Frankfurt’s
contribution is an assembly of work he has already published. It opens
with his claim that the harm that lies do us results from their interfer-
ence with our efforts to understand things as they truly are: “the real state
of affairs” (37). Lies thrust us into an imaginary world that we cannot
live in or rely on. Frankfurt goes on to discuss Kant’s and Montaigne’s
claim that lies undermine human society. Here Frankfurt argues, agree-
ing with Solomon’s position, that Kant and Montaigne have gone too far:
although it is true that lies can tear the social fabric apart, they can also
6 The Philosophy of Deception
knit it together, and we are all quite familiar with the process of finding
our ways through the twists and turns of ordinary social deceptions. What
really bothers us about the lie, Frankfurt plausibly claims, is the harm a
lie does to us as individuals. We take lies personally, and it is the personal
betrayal that hurts.
Frankfurt develops his personal take on the harm of the lie with a
discussion of the poet Adrienne Rich. For Rich, the liar puts himself in a
place of terrible loneliness: by hiding his mind from others, he perilously
removes himself from human society. (This may also, of course, be a rea-
son to lie: the liar may enjoy, even cherish, the feeling of having a secret
place where only he may go, a place where he is wholly himself alone.)
This self-estrangement performed by the liar is part of what harms us
when we are told lies, Frankfurt argues: it is a kind of blow to us to be
pushed away. Still worse, he says, is the way a lie “leads one to feel a little
crazy” (40; here he is quoting Rich). That is, when we trust someone, we
deeply believe we can rely on what they say, and when we learn we have
been deceived our feeling of reality is interfered with. We learn that our
own ability to judge is unreliable, and we are not sure what we should
believe and what we should suspect.
In his marvelous, first-rate analysis of Shakespeare’s Sonnet 138,
where Frankfurt shows that it is possible to both know a lie is a lie and
yet believe it; to tell a lie to someone knowing that that person will
understand that it is a lie, and yet expect him or her to believe it; and
to understand that the lies being told are essential to a lovers’ intimacy
that cannot be created in any other way. Frankfurt’s contribution closes
with several excerpts from his now famous essay “On Bullshit,” outlin-
ing his definition of bullshit—using a story about Wittgenstein and Fania
Pascal—and explaining his claim that bullshit may be more dangerous
to the truth than lies.
William Ian Miller’s contribution is, as he says, “a genealogy on deceit
in war and trade” (50). He starts with deceit in Ovid and the Old Testa-
ment and works his way all the way up to the present day, considering
the deceptions of such famous tricksters as Odysseus, David, the Vikings,
Machiavelli, William the Conqueror, even Montaigne. He then consid-
ers the practices of some famous deceivers in our contemporary business
culture, such as Bernie Ebbers, Dennis Koslowski, and Kenneth Lay (and
their like). Miller concludes by asking: what is it in us that prefers the
trickster and deceiver to his dupe?
Mark Wrathall’s contribution is a phenomenological interpretation and
development of Nietzsche’s observation that “a perspectival, deceptive
character belongs to existence” (67). Wrathall uses Merleau-Ponty and
Heidegger to explore what it means to experience perceptual deception
and asks to what degree are we ourselves responsible for the deceptions
that occur in perceptual experience. For Wrathall, “the phenomenology
of deception . . . points us to the inherently meaningful structure of the
perceptual world” (77). Through studying how these deceptions occur,
Introduction 7
we realize how deeply we are mentally and creatively engaged with per-
ceptual phenomena.
David Sherman raises an attack against the usual ways of understand-
ing self-deception on the grounds that such ways operate with too thin
a notion of truth and true belief. He outlines a more adequate way of
understanding truth, deception, and self-deception through an account
of sociohistorical truth and sociohistorical deception that he develops out
of Kant and Hegel. Crucial to Sherman’s story is his division between first-
order belief formation and second-order belief formation: the space
between these two is, he argues, the space of self-deception. Like
Wrathall, Sherman uses Heidegger to bolster his account, and the essay
concludes with a strikingly original analysis of the relationship between
self-deception and Sartre’s notion of bad faith.
Kelly Oliver introduces the notions of psychoanalysis and the subcon-
scious to further complicate the problem of deception and self-deception.
She writes, “insofar as unconscious forces drive us beyond our control and
even beyond our knowledge, then we are all and always a bunch of liars”
(104). Oliver discusses the differences between humans and nonhuman
animals in the work of Lacan, posing the questions: To what degree is
humans’ capacity to lie a function of their capacity for speech? And is
there a difference between pretending (as nonhuman animals do) and
pretending to pretend (as we do)? Oliver follows Derrida in concluding
that at least one difference between human and nonhuman animals is
that “animals may be capable of deception, but man is the self-deceptive
animal” (114). (Interestingly, recent studies on bluffing suggest that there
may be an evolutionary advantage to self-deception, which many differ-
ent kinds of animals practice: see David Lingstone Smith’s book Why We
Lie: The Evolutionary Roots of Deception and the Unconscious Mind (2004)
for a variety of studies and examples). But Oliver and Derrida agree that
the distinction between pretense and lie that Lacan rests on is unsupport-
able: the answer to Oliver’s question is yes, nonhuman animals lie just as
well as we do.
Paul Ekman, who is probably the most famous expert on lying alive
today, considers two questions here: (1) Why are most people so lousy at
catching liars? (2) What are the micro expressions that give liars away, and
given that they are easy to learn, why do we have such trouble learning
them? An interesting part of Ekman’s piece, which begins with a discussion
of his definition of lying, is that he does not think one must speak in order
to lie, and he thinks one can lie without falsifying (I have to say that I think
he is right about this). Ekman then proceeds to canvass the research on
catching liars, which includes interesting information about why and when
people lie, and at what costs they are willing to lie. Among many other rea-
sons, Ekman argues that we are poor lie catchers (and poor liars) because
of our evolutionary history and our ancestral environment: Ekman thinks
that back in our early development as humans, lying was easily detected
and swiftly and severely punished. Another particularly delightful reason
8 The Philosophy of Deception
is that “our parents teach us not to identify their lies” (126). And adding
weight to the central thesis of this volume, he argues that we are bad
at identifying liars because “we often want to be misled; we collude in
the lie unwittingly [or wittingly?] because we have a stake in not know-
ing the truth” (126). Ekman uses a famous exchange between Neville
Chamberlain and Adolf Hitler to illustrate the point.
As do the opening pages of Frankfurt’s piece, Alan Strudler’s essay
addresses the tough question of what makes lying wrong. Using Bernard
Williams’s idea that deception is wrong because (1) it involves a breach of
trust, and/or (Williams is unclear) (2) it is a manipulation of the dupe by
the deceiver, Strudler offers a brilliant analysis rich with terrific thought
experiments to argue that “not all manipulation in deception involves a
breach of trust, and that deception that involves a breach of trust may
involve a wrong that is distinguishable from that which occurs in other
deception (139). Strudler argues that deception is often a form of legit-
imate self-defense, and in those instances should be governed by those
norms. I consider this essay the best work I have ever read on deception and
trust, and I expect it to become a classic in the literature on deception.
Thomas Carson’s chapter is the most thorough canvass of the literature
on the definition of lying available today. As he says, he “offers defini-
tions of the concepts of lying and deception and explains the distinctions
between lying, deception, withholding information, ‘keeping someone
in the dark,’ bullshit, spin, and half-truths” (153). He shows that many
of the debates about the nature and morality of lying can be reduced
to confusions and disagreements about (sloppy) definitions of the dif-
ferent phenomena. He develops his own definition of lying: “deception
is intentionally causing someone to have false beliefs” (153). One of the
pleasures of Carson’s article, like Strudler’s, is working through his many
ingenious cases and thought experiments to see how subtle and precise
this definition is (I still disagree with it, as does Ekman, but that’s as may
be). Carson also does a terrific job of analyzing and refining Frankfurt’s
notion of bullshit, and adds yet another player to the philosophical game
here with his carefully defined notion of “spin.”
In his essay, Michael Lynch argues that thinking about deception can
teach us a great deal about the nature of value and truth, what we can
expect from a theory of truth, and why some truth theories are doomed
to inadequacy. He opens his piece with his own account of the nature
of lying and how it should be distinguished from deception (as an aside,
I think it shows how rich and difficult the problem of defining “lie” actu-
ally is that there are so many different and well-defended definitions of
“lie” within this single volume). He then reviews several ways in which
the connections between deception and truth show us what a workable
theory of truth would have to look like. Finally, Lynch offers a concise and
persuasive argument that there is something intrinsically valuable about
the truth, even if that intrinsic value is “merely” psychological. All things
being equal, we simply prefer the truth.
Introduction 9
The essays by James Edwin Mahon and David Sussman deal with
Kant’s notorious claim that when we lie we are always acting immorally,
whatever the circumstances may be. Mahon points out that the hysteria
of philosophers over this claim of Kant is not really warranted, given that
“there are three senses of a lie to be found in Kant’s moral philosophy [the
ethical, the juristic, and the sense of right], and three corresponding duties
not to lie” (202). Mahon also adds to the debate about the definition of
lying, pointing out that for Kant a lie is “the making of an untruthful
statement with the intention that it be believed to be true” (203). There
are thus many cases, Mahon points out, in which Kant would not take the
statement or deceptive action under consideration to be a lie (the cate-
gory “lie,” for Kant, is quite narrow). So, for example, the many formalized
lies of etiquette and politeness—such as writing “Your humble servant” at
the end of a letter—are, though untruths, not lies, since they are clearly
not made with the intention that the untruthful statement be believed to
be true. Juristic lies are a still narrower category than (un)ethical lies. By
the end of his essay, Mahon convinces the reader that Kant’s prohibition
on lying is not nearly so outrageous, sweeping, and difficult to defend as it
has almost always been taken to be.
Sussman begins his essay by admitting how strongly Kant does seem to
denounce lying and, indeed, self-deception. “Kant approvingly notes that
scripture presents evil coming into the world not through the first murder,
but through the first lie (MM 6:431), and considers our endemic propen-
sity to hypocrisy and self-deception to be at the heart of the ‘radical evil
in human nature’ that is the fundamental source of all moral corruption”
(225). Sussman further elaborates Kant’s attacks on lying, including his
famous claim that truthfulness is an unconditional duty, and he then com-
plains (you can hear the charming tones of Sussman’s teacher Christine
Korsgaard in this remark): “These outrageous conclusions are a gift to
Kant’s enemies and a calamity for his friends” (226). Sussman goes on to
argue that although the conclusions of Kant’s ‘A Supposed Right to Lie’
are “wildly implausible, they do have substantial motivation within Kant’s
practical philosophy” (230). Sussman then elaborates Kant’s discussion of
who has and who does not have a right to the truth and introduces a notion
of “defensive lie” quite similar to that of Strudler. But Kant is not willing to
endorse defensive lying, because, Sussman argues, for Kant, defensive lies
presuppose a principle at odds with the “quasi-contractual commitments”
that are the “necessary preconditions of any social order” (239). Sussman
concludes that Kant can justify a lie to the would-be murderer at the door
in at least some circumstances—if the murderer is putting one under pres-
sure to respond, for example—but that Kant’s prohibition against lying
remains much stronger than many of us might like.
The last two essays are on self-deception. Amelie Rorty presents a
summary of her many thoughtful, persuasive, and articulate defenses
of the practice of self-deception, and reviews forms of self-deception
about which we should be ambivalent and wary. Although “many
10 The Philosophy of Deception
Robert C. Solomon
Nietzsche once asked, “Why must we have truth at any cost anyway?”1 It was
an odd question, coming from the philosopher who prided himself, above
all, on his brutal honesty, and it is an obscene question, in any case, for the
profession that sees itself as solely seeking the truth. Even those philosophers
who challenge the very idea of truth, not just Nietzsche and Nagarjuna but
Jacques Derrida and Richard Rorty, are scrupulous and unforgiving when it
comes to deception, misrepresentation and so-called creative misreadings, at
least of their own work.2 Philosophers in general insist on the truth even if
they do not believe in “the Truth.” They despise deception, and they ridicule
the self-deception of the “vulgar,” which it is their mission to undo.
Australian philosopher Tony Coady probably speaks for most philoso-
phers when he writes, “dishonesty has always been perceived in our culture,
and in all cultures but the most bizarre, as a central human vice. Moreover
the specific form of dishonesty known as lying has generally been scorned,
and the habitual liar treated with contempt. There are perfectly good rea-
sons for this.” But, he adds, “we should note that this perception is consistent
with a certain hesitancy about what constitutes a lie and with the more than
1. Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, trans. W. Kaufmann (New York: Random House,1966).
2. Consider Nietzsche’s late lament “Has anyone understood me?” (Ecce Homo)
Consider too Derrida’s indignant response to widespread criticism of his work when he
was offered an honorary degree at Cambridge in the spring of 1992. “I have never written
any such thing!” he insisted to the press and against his critics, hardly indifferent to the
truth of the matter. This is not, of course, a refutation of the position (any more than
the perils of Pyrrhus constituted a refutation of ancient skepticism). But it is a pragmatic
paradox of considerable interest, what Bernd Magnus (following Fish) calls a
“self-consuming concept.”
15
16 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
3. C. A. J. Coady, “The Morality of Lying,” in To Tell a Lie: Truth in Business and the
Professions (Sydney: St. James Ethics Center, 1992), 7–12.
4. Indeed, Sidgwick further suggested that philosophers might be well-instructed to
lie systematically to their readers. While he firmly believed in the truth of the doctrine of
utilitarianism, he also believed that public knowledge of that doctrine might have results
that would be disastrous. Accordingly, the promotion of the utilitarian doctrine in practice
required its systematic deception.
5. For example, one might deny that a person has a right to the truth in question. Do
Nazis have a right to know where their innocent victim is hiding? Does an eavesdropper
have the right to overhear only truths? Did Special Prosecutor Kenneth Starr have a right
to ask or hear the truth about his quarry’s private sex life? It is said that dishonesty is a
form of injustice, but in that case greater injustices may excuse or override the injustice of
a lie. One might even refuse to call unjust lies “lies.” This maneuver would presumably also
eliminate jokes and fictions as lies, at least where the audience does not expect to hear the
truth. One critical concern here, of course, is the case of “white lies,” often based on social
conventions. See C. A. J. Coady, Testimony (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992). Even
more interesting are those cases and cultures in which social convention is considered
mandatory and “trump,” even at the expense of what we would consider an outright lie.
Self, Deception, and Self-Deception in Philosophy 17
together and support one another. It would also eliminate all of those cases
in which cultural considerations clearly dictate deception in the name of
politeness, or appropriateness, or for the sake of face or feelings, whatever
the unvarnished and possibly rude truth may be. To define lying as wrong
or to limit “lying” to just cases of wrongful deception begs important ques-
tions, one of which is Nietzsche’s “Why must we have truth at any cost any-
way?” And as we already noted, Nietzsche is not alone. Plato and Sidgwick
both defend the high-minded lie, and one of the attitudes advocated for
novice monks, I am told, is the obvious falsehood “I am the worst person
in the world.” In Buddhism, the demand for truth and truthfulness seems
to include acquiescence in the face of such astounding precepts, all in the
name of their salutary affects. Nietzsche pursues a very different program,
of course, defending desirable untruths that are inspiring and conducive to
creativity, self-realization, and the “will to power.” But the point, it seems to
me, is the same: Truth is in the service of values, not the other way around.
“Dishonesty is a form of injustice, a vice,” Coady says, echoing the harsh
condemnations of Augustine and Kant. “It deforms the liar and debases the
currency of language.” But not all untruths are malicious, and not all decep-
tions are lies. The truth hurts, and sometimes it destroys. Lies can protect
and inspire, and deception can serve noble ends. Self-deception sustains
the illusions that sustain us, and though conducive to pathological dys-
function it is self-deception and not the truth alone that shall set us free.6
Indeed, in many if not most cases of self-deception (and deception too) the
question of truth can be a source of considerable consternation, not just
for the perplexing reasons long advocated by epistemological skeptics but
rather because of the self-fulfilling (and sometimes self-denying) features
of our beliefs about our selves and those aspects of the world that matter
most to us. A saintly man considers himself wicked. What is the truth of
the matter? A mass murderer with strong political beliefs, a “terrorist” in
the eyes of the press, considers herself a noble freedom fighter. Who is right
and who is wrong? A lover trusts and defends the beloved, no matter how
hideous the evidence to the contrary. Is this self-deception, or is it just—
love? The truth in such matters is rarely a matter of “the facts” alone.
DECEPTION IN PHILOSOPHY
Socrates insisted that he was telling the truth when he claimed to know
nothing, an argumentative strategy that was doubly a lie. For many philoso-
phers and scientists too, we readily recognize that the search for truth may
be something of a cover, a noble facade for working out personal problems,
pleasing their parents, or pursuing personal ambition. Nietzsche suggested
that every great philosophy is “the personal confession of its author and a
kind of involuntary and unconscious memoir.”10 But unselfconscious self-
revelation is hardly the same as telling the truth, and when philosophers
such as Nietzsche go on to argue that there is, in fact, no truth, refusing
to tell the truth might become a kind of truthfulness and insisting on the
truth becomes a philosophically venal sort of lie.11
And yet, Socrates, we are told, died for the sake of his honesty. Epictetus
the early Stoic defended above all the principle “not to speak falsely.” In
more modern times, Immanuel Kant took the prohibition against lying
as his paradigm of a “categorical imperative,” the unconditioned moral
law.12 There could be no exceptions, not even to save the life of a friend.
Even Nietzsche took honesty to be one of his four “cardinal” virtues, and
Albert Camus praises his own invention, “the stranger” Meursault, as a
hero for the truth. Fellow “existentialist” Jean-Paul Sartre insisted that
deception is a vice, perhaps indeed the ultimate vice. 13 Sartre argued ada-
mantly on behalf of the “transparency” of consciousness, thus enabling
him to argue (against Freud) that all deception is in some sense will-
ful and therefore blameworthy. Today one reads American ethicists,
e.g. Edmund Pincoffs, who insists that dishonesty is so grievous a vice that
its merits cannot even be intelligibly deliberated.14 In this, unlike many
other matters, philosophy and common sense seem to be in agreement.
And whether philosophy merely follows and reports on the Zeitgeist or
actually has some hand in directing it, it would be safe to say that the
philosophical championing of honesty is an accurate reflection of popular
morality. Lying, for philosophers and laymen alike, is wrong.15
But what does it mean to insist that lying is wrong, and how wrong is it
really? The blanket pronouncements of the philosophers typically conceal
more than they reveal, and the best questions are left under the covers. Is a
lie told to embellish an otherwise tedious narrative just as wrong as a lie told
in order to cover up a misdeed and avoid punishment? Is a lie told in desper-
ation any less wrong than a calculated, merely convenient lie? Is a lie told out
of self-deception more or less wrong than a clear-headed, tactical lie? (Is the
former even a lie?) Are all lies wrong—is lying as such wrong?—or do some
lies serve an important function not only in protecting one another from
harm (especially emotional harm) but in developing and protecting one’s
own sense of individuality and privacy? One might better think of lying
as diplomatic, as fortification, as essential protection for a necessarily less
than candid self. Or, one could just think of honesty as merely one among
many of the virtues, not a fundamental virtue at all. Stephen Carter tells the
story of a man on his deathbed who tells his wife about a long affair, just to
“cleanse his conscience.” Carter rightly questions whether such honesty is in
any way admirable, or rather just an inconsiderate cruelty.
It is worth noting that Aristotle, in his catalog of moral virtues, lumped
“truthfulness” together with “friendliness” and “wit,” important traits to
choose in a friend or colleague, to be sure, but hardly the cornerstone
without which the entire edifice of morality would fall down. Moreover,
what Aristotle meant by “truthfulness” primarily concerned the telling of
one’s accomplishments, “neither more nor less”—in contemporary terms,
handing in an honest resumé.16 He did not seem at all concerned about
social lies, “white lies” or, for that matter, even political lies except insofar
as these contributed to injustice or corruption. 17 Critics have often chal-
lenged Kant’s analysis of honesty as a “perfect duty,” appealing to our
natural inclination to insist that it is far more important to save the life
of a friend than it is to tell the truth to the Nazis who are after him. But
if there is even one such case in which it is right to lie and honesty can
be overridden, then the “perfect” status of the duty not to lie is compro-
mised, and the question is opened to negotiation.
It is in the light of such dogmatic (“a priori”) condemnation too that we
can understand the perennial controversy surrounding the seemingly inno-
cent “white lie,” the lie that saves instead of causing harm. And, to say the
obvious (though it is often neglected by philosophers), lies can also enter-
tain, as theater and as fiction, and not only on the stage or on the page.
Indeed, lies can also be useful and fascinating in philosophy. Not only do
they provide promising “heuristic” goads to further thinking, they provide
some of the essential subject matter as well. How many dozens of professors
are now employed because some Cretan, millennia ago, supposedly declared
that “all Cretans are liars” and thus generated the most basic paradox in logic
and philosophy. (If he told the truth, then he was lying, but if he was lying,
16. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, trans. T. Irwin (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1944). Clancy
Martin, “Nietzsche on Deception” (Ph.D. diss., University of Texas (2003), and elsewhere,
has argued this thesis at some length.
17. Aristotle, Politics. trans. B. Jowett in The Works of Aristotle, ed. R. McKeon
(New York, Random House, 1941).
Self, Deception, and Self-Deception in Philosophy 21
then. ) Is there anything wrong with a lie when it causes no harm? And is
it always true that we should tell the truth “even when it hurts”?
Behind the blanket prohibition of lying we can discern the outlines of a
familiar but glorious philosophical metaphor, the truth as bright, plain and
simple, standing there as the Holy Grail of Rationality, while dishonesty, on
the other hand, is dark and devious, the ill-paved path to irrationality and
confusion. In revealing the truth, we think of consciousness as transparent
through and through; in deception we detect an opacity, an obstacle, a wall
within consciousness. The honest man and the true philosopher know all
and tell all (except in Socrates’ case, since he insists that he does not know
anything). Nevertheless, Socrates’ student Plato offers to lead us out of the
shadows and into the light, even at great peril. The philosopher illuminates
that which the liar and the layman leave in the dark, including his or her own
inner soul.18 Truth and light are good; deception and darkness are bad or evil,
leading not only to ignorance and harm but to the degradation of rationality,
the abuse of language and the corruption of the soul. But philosophy, one
begins to suspect, has overrated these metaphors of clarity and transparency.
The obvious truth is that our simplest social relationships could not exist
without the shadows and darkness provided by deception and lies.
In his novel The Idiot, Fyodor Dostoevski gave us a portrait of a man
who had all of the virtues, including perfect honesty. 19 He was, however,
an utter disaster for everyone he encountered. More recently, Albert
Camus presented us (in The Stranger) with an odd “anti-hero,” “a hero for
the truth” who was unwilling to lie.20 It is not surprising that he comes off
as something of a monster, inhuman, “with virtually no human qualities
at all” (as the prosecutor points out at his trial for murder). On a more
mundane and “real life” philosophical level, one cannot imagine getting
through an average budget meeting or a cocktail party speaking nothing
but the truth, the whole truth and nothing but the truth. If one wished to
be perverse, he or she might well hypothesize that deception, not truth,
is the cement of civilization, a cement that does not so much hold us
together as it safely separates us and our thoughts. We cannot imagine
social intercourse without opacity.
Steve Braude, a philosopher who works extensively in parapsychol-
ogy, illustrates the importance of deception with a simple experiment. He
asks his audience if anyone would take a pill (which he has supposedly
invented) that will allow them to read the minds of everyone within a
hundred-yard radius. Not surprisingly, no one accepts the offer. We can all
imagine the bored and restless thoughts flickering through a friend’s mind
as we describe our latest trauma or the adventure of the day, the distracted
and hardly flattering thoughts of our students as we reach the climax of
the lecture two minutes before the class bell rings, and the casual and not
at all romantic thoughts of a lover in a moment of intimacy. “What are you
thinking?” is an extremely dangerous and foolish question, inviting if not
usually requiring the tactical but flatly deceptive answer, “Oh, nothing.”
Philosophers have long whitewashed the threatening nature of the truth.
Many of them adopt, without irony, a secularized version of the religious
banner “the truth shall set you free.”21 But, against the philosophers, we all
know that sometimes the truth hurts and the harm is not redeemed, that
the truth is sometimes if not often unnecessary, that the truth complicates
social arrangements, undermines collective myths, destroys relationships,
and incites violence and vengeance. Deception is sometimes not a vice
but a social virtue, and systematic deception is an essential part of the
order of the (social) world. In many societies, social harmony is valued far
more than truthfulness as such, and to tell the other person what he or
she wants to hear rather than what one might actually feel or believe is
not only permitted but expected. In such circumstances, do we still want
to speak of “deception” at all? And could we not begin to see our own
enlightened emphasis on “seeking the truth at all costs” (as Ernst Jones
wrote admiringly of Sigmund Freud) as one more ethnocentric peculiar-
ity, another curious product of our strong sense of individualism and a
particularly unsociable conception of “the truth”?
The difficulty making such distinctions [between real and only appar-
ent truthfulness] is almost as great for liars as for their dupes, because
self-deception enters into such estimates to such an extraordinary degree.
Hypocrites half believe their own stories, and sentimentality makes fraud
take on the most innocuous tints.
—Sissela Bok, Lying
The true hypocrite is the one who ceases to perceive his deception, the one
who lies with sincerity.
—André Gide, Counterfeiters (1955)
21. It is perhaps not without intentional ambiguity that this originally religious
injunction (John 8:32) is engraved on the administration building of the University of
Texas at Austin.
22. This is the formulation discussed in the analytic literature, for example, in Brian
McLaughlin, “Self-deception and the Structure of the Self,” in Ames and Wimal
Self, Deception, and Self-Deception in Philosophy 23
Dissanayake, Self and Deception, 31–52, and it is the point of departure even for those who
reject the paradox, e.g. Herbert Fingarette in his excellent little book Self-Deception (New
York: Humanities Press, 1969). It is also used by Jean-Paul Sartre at the beginning of his
famous discussion of “bad faith” (mauvaise foi) in Being and Nothingness, 86–116, but this is
unfortunate, as bad faith is clearly a much broader and richer concept than self-deception.
In fact, Sartre uses the paradox only to set up a show trial against Freud’s psychological
determinism and attack his notion of “the Unconscious.” The “knowing p and not-p”
paradox plays virtually no role in either his examples or his subsequent arguments. I would
suggest that the examples in the early (pt. 1) chapter on “Bad Faith” might better be
looked at in the light of the concepts of being-for-others and the all-important notions of
freedom and responsibility in pts. 3 and 4 respectively. Indeed, I would argue that Sartre’s
attack on Freud and his casual treatment of the paradoxes of self-deception are at most
secondary if not incidental to his overall aim, which is to attack what Kathleen Higgins
has called the “atmosphere” of irresponsibility that he perceived in Parisian society. (Of
course, as so often, the same charge has been turned in turn on Sartre himself, by Herbert
Lottman, in his detailed chronicals of the actual [lack of] involvement of Sartre and his
comrades in the Resistance and the War.)
23. E.g. Carolyn Ristau on broken wing displays by waterbirds: C. Ristau, “Aspects of
the Cognitive Ethology of an Injury-feigning Bird, the Piping Plover,” in Cognitive Ethology:
The Minds of Other Animals, ed. C. Ristau (Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1991). See also Robert
M. Sefarth and Dorothy L. Cheney, How Monkeys See the World (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press), on deceptive monkey shines among our fellow primates.
24. I owe this tentative suggestion to Annette Baier.
24 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
25. J. P. Sartre, Existentialism and Human Emotions (New York: Citadel Press), 1957;
Fingarette, Self-Deception.
26. Robert Audi, “Self-deception, Rationalization, and Reasons for Acting,” in
Perspectives on Self-Deception, ed. B. McLaughlin and A. Rorty (Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1988).
Self, Deception, and Self-Deception in Philosophy 25
27. A term that Jean-Paul Sartre borrows from chemistry in Being and Nothingness, 99f.
Metastability has a tentative stability, an appearance of stability, but the slightest intrusion
or misstep brings about total disaster. Consider a waiter carrying an overly full tray of cups
of hot coffee. All goes smoothly until the first jiggle, and a single boiling hot drop touches
his bare skin. He flinches slightly, and ...
28. Ibid., 112ff.; see Marcia Baron, “What Is Wrong with Self-Deception?” in
McLaughlin and Rorty, Perspectives on Self-Deception.
29. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, pt. 3. Philosophers typically talk as if our sense
of personal identity were just an internal affair (of self-revelation or memory or the
transcendental unity of consciousness). Indeed, Sartre’s analysis of the self in Being and
Nothingness too readily appears to be what I will call an “internalist” account. (Even the
name “for-itself” has obvious Cartesian credentials.) But in our obligatory reading of Sartre
in the context of discussions of self-deception, I would like to urge that three textual
points be kept in mind: (1) that the famous, often-reprinted chapter on “Bad Faith” is
one (remarkably short) early chapter in an eight-hundred-page book, and the subject is
rarely mentioned again. (2) That Sartre insists the “being-for-others” is on an “ontological
par” with the other two modes of being, “being-for-itself” and “being-in-itself.” He is
not, therefore, a traditional Cartesian dualist and his concept of self is not an internalist
account. In fact, Sartre’s argument and his examples are quite at odds with the ontological
apparatus he has provided for us in that early chapter of his humongous book. The
examples, which have been rightly criticized as inadequate by Allen Wood, “Ideology,
26 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
ways, notably by ignoring or distracting oneself, but none of these ploys has
a ghost of a chance if others cannot be distracted or fooled—or at least put
off—as well. Deception and self-deception are intimately intertwined. We
fool ourselves in order to fool others, and we fool others in order to fool
ourselves. And to make it more complicated (as it should be), we do not
always know which is which, who is self and who is other.
Deception between persons is rarely so cynical that it does not involve
more than a trace of sincerity and belief, in most cases the belief that
even if this particular “fact” is false, the truth that the lie is protecting is
far more significant than the act of lying. Thus we have the lover who
lies to protect his love, or the scientist who fudges her results to “prove”
a hypothesis she just “knows” to be true. Sissela Bok rightly suggests that
there is a thin line at best separating the lie for the sake of the truth and
the lie that marks one a liar. Lying for the sake of the truth is a paradox
that already requires a considerable amount of self-deception. Deception
between persons is rarely if ever unmotivated, and even a mischievous
lie “for its own sake” (the familiar “shaving” of one’s age, for example) is
typically a cover-up for other lies, insecurities and distrust. Thus Samuel
Johnson wrote, of self-deceptive men who would be virtuous, “having
none to recall their attention to their lives, they rate themselves by the
goodness of their opinions, and forget how much more easily men may
show their virtue in their talk than in their actions.”
If we understand deception and self-deception as exemplifying an
essential aspect of self-consciousness rather than as a willful violation of
principle or antisocial act, we begin to lose that sense of blanket con-
demnation of “lying as wrong” and come to understand deception and
self-deception as part of the matrix of human relations, neither good nor
evil as such but inviting sympathy and understanding rather than blame.
Amelie Rorty recites the touching case of a talented young doctor who
refuses to recognize in herself all of the evident symptoms of cancer. Her
behavior and her training make it obvious that, in some sense, she does
know of her condition, but the explicit recognition would be devastating.
And so she pretends, to herself and others (though convincing no one but
herself). Is there anyone who would call such behavior blameworthy? 30
People tell lies not only to avoid punishment or to impress others but
because they need to define and protect themselves (their selves) and cope
False Consciousness, and Social Illusion,” in McLaughlin and Rorty, Perspectives on Self-
Deception, 133–271, involve “being-for-others” as well as the categories of “facticity” and
“transcendence” he explicitly employs there. Thus construed, they escape many of Wood’s
(and other traditional) objections. (3) In an earlier work, The Transcendence of the Ego,
Sartre insists that the self is not “in” consciousness but is “outside of us in the world, like
the consciousness of another.” His is therefore what I will call an “externalist” account of
the self, not a Cartesian account at all.
30. Amelie Rorty, The Deceptive Self: Liars, Layers and Lairs,” in Rorty and
McLaughlin, Perspectives on Self-Deception.
Self, Deception, and Self-Deception in Philosophy 27
34. Leon Festinger, Cognitive Dissonance (Evanston, Ill.: Row Peterson, 1957).
35. In Fiji, before the arrival of the British, Viti Levu was considered, with some
reason, the center of the earth, its largest land mass, surrounded by ocean and a few
hundred modest islands. In the nineteenth century, when first confronted with a map of
the world, Fijians reacted first with predictable denial, then humiliation. It was then that
the story of the great African canoe Kannitow became established among the Fijians,
despite its dubious veracity. Our British commentator scoffs. But then thinking of the
standard stories of our own culture (Columbus’s discovery, the conquest of the West, the
beacon of democracy and freedom in the world), are our stories any more reasonable?
Self, Deception, and Self-Deception in Philosophy 31
the attention should be on the social context and the relationship—in the
above case essentially transient—and not on the lie or the consequences of
the lie exclusively.
It is a mistake to think about and condemn deception and self-deception
sui generis. There are legitimate lies in literature, heuristics in science,
myth in religion and philosophy. These are not just isolated fictional
frames with at most metaphorical connections to considerations of self or
extremely tenuous “expressions” of ourselves and our relations with other
people. Quite the contrary, these are the “myths and metaphors we live
by,” according to many authors from the ancients to our contemporaries. 36
Once we give up the philosophical tendency to generalize about decep-
tion and self-deception in the abstract and focus instead on the particular
phenomena of lying, the intentions and motives behind them, the context
as well as the consequences and the interpersonal relationship between
the participants, it becomes increasingly obvious that most lies are not
merely lies but also self-deception and part of a larger matrix of beliefs
and emotions that define not only this relationship but a community or
a culture.
The lies of love (or pretended love) depend for their credibility on a
remarkable institution that defines and gives structure as well as elabo-
rate discourse to a seemingly “primitive” emotion.37 Consider how much
cultural apparatus goes into the simple but (when it is false) vicious lie
“I love you.”38 The individual passion can be more or less faked, but the
words take on a force of their own. This because that affirmation, and its
requisite response (“I love you too,” is part of the culture, one of those
programmed exchanges that once initiated, can only be followd by the
response “I love you, too,”—or result in a calamitous breakdown. But
apart from outright lies about love, how often are we confused, or filled
with doubts, and the saying of it provides a way of clarifying those doubts,
by way of a “leap” (not of faith, but of commitment of sorts)? Is that a lie?
Self-deception, like deception, is not always motivated by self-interest,
cold and calculating, but by our engagement in an emotionally charged
world in which things matter to us, in which the truth is by no means clear
and wishful thinking and the expectations of others weigh more on us
than that abstract metaconception known to us as “the Truth.”
Deception and self-deception are part and parcel of our engagements
in the world including, not least, in the development and maintenance of
our image and sense of ourselves. Deception is first of all a way of relating,
a not entirely accurate presentation of self to others and to oneself. There
is no single point where presentation becomes deception, where pretense
36. George Lakoff and Mark Johnson, Myths We Live By (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1980).
37. Roland Barthes, A Lover’s Discourse (New York: Farrar Straus and Giroux, 1977).
38. Jeffrey Masson has a delightful book with the title Dogs Never Lie about Love. The
implication, of course, is that we often do.
32 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
It has often been pointed out, with various degrees of obfuscation in cur-
rent “Continental” philosophy, that the self is double. This can be put in a
number of ways, beginning with the obvious, that we see ourselves “from
the inside” but can also be seen (and sometimes see ourselves) “from the
outside,” from a second- or third-person (misleadingly called “objective”)
point of view. But the complex relations between these two (or three)
viewpoints gives rise to some deep suspicions and the seemingly outra-
geous charge that the self is intrinsically duplicitous, not only double but,
as we say, “two-faced.” In The Fall, Camus has his character Clamence
confess this ambiguity, which he goes on to demonstrate in his progressive
seduction of his almost mute interlocutor and the reader.41 The face pre-
sented to the world is at odds with the face that smiles knowingly inward.
39. This is the point where proposition-minded philosophers too readily isolate
false verbal self-ascriptions of such presentations and point to them as the paradigm of
deception—lying, in effect, about who one is. (Aristotle treats “truthfulness” this way,
Nichomachean Ethics 4.9.) But a more typical and more interesting case is the person
with some but still quite limited knowledge who acts as if he or she is an expert without
ever claiming to be so. As casual conversation and social self-presentation, this is innocent
enough. But in a context in which a real expert is or becomes urgently needed, it becomes
not only deception but fraud and betrayal. So, too, it is not deception to “act friendly” with
a person for whom one has no special affection. Nor is it even obvious that proclaiming
one’s friendship in such circumstances, as encouragement or a friendly gesture, for
example, is deception or in any way blameworthy. It is only when the expectations of the
so-called friend (or in rare cases, other people) are such that the true devotion of a friend
is called for and not forthcoming that, in retrospect, the entire performance gets indicted.
40. Nietzsche, “Truth and Lie in the Extra-moral Sense”; Jean Baudrillard, Selected
Writings (Palo Alto: Stanford University Press, 1988).
41. Camus, The Fall.
Self, Deception, and Self-Deception in Philosophy 33
But, then again, perhaps the face that smiles inward is itself an illusion,
only a reflection of the looks it absorbs from others.42
With this in mind, let me distinguish between two different models
of self-deception, which in turn depend on two quite different models of
the self. In dull and often ambiguous analytic jargon, the two might be
referred to as the internalist and the externalist models of self-deception,
and they are based respectively on similarly internalist and external-
ist accounts of the self. An internalist views self-deception as a relation
between a person and a set of beliefs (broadly construed, which may or
may not involve the contradictory “believing p and not-p” paradox that
preoccupies so much of the analytic literature). Accordingly, internalist
models of self-deception tend to be concerned with the internal structure
or architecture of the self. Thus Freud divides the self into consciousness
and an unconscious, a troubled house with an inaccessible basement, and
later into “agencies.” Amelie Rorty ingeniously suggests that the self is
something like a medieval city, a virtual labyrinth of pathways and neigh-
borhoods functioning independently and without knowledge of the oth-
ers.43 Less architectural theorists look for ways of gerrymandering belief
or bypassing belief altogether, by way of “avowals” or other acknowl-
edgments.44 The problem for the internalist, perhaps but not necessarily
made more intractable by paradox, is to understand how one can in some
sense “know and not seem to know.” Self-deception, in other words, is
first of all an epistemological problem.
The externalist, on the other hand, sees self-deception as a social
phenomenon. It has to do not so much with a person and his or her
beliefs as it has to do with a person and his or her roles and relationships.
Self-deception is a consequence of wanting to be thought of and treated
in certain ways and not others by other people. One’s self-conceptions
are the product and not the source of the opinions of others, and self-
deception is thus an attempt to manipulate those opinions and not just
one’s own. I think the idea that we fool ourselves in order to fool others
more often than not gets it backwards, and the idea that in self-deception
we first of all lie to ourselves is just plain wrong. Self-deception begins
and continues by playing a part, by acting the good husband, the respon-
sible citizen, the competent, healthy professional. This may or may not
be accompanied by self-avowal. It may or may not be accompanied by
rationalization or denial. Self-deception is thus first of all a performance,
if sometimes a performance enjoyed only by oneself. Thus Sartre argues
that being-for others is an essential ingredient of the self, even when oth-
ers are not around.45
42. Suggestions of this sort abound in the wonderful work of Erving Goffman, notably
The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life (New York: Doubleday, 1959).
43. Rorty, “Deceptive Self.”
44. Fingarette, Self-Deception.
45. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, pt. 3, ch. 1, esp. sec. 4, “The Look.”
34 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
46. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, pt. 3, ch. 1, esp. sec. 4, “The Look.” 110–11.
47. Roger Ames, “The Classical Chinese Self and Hypocrisy,” in Ames and Dissanayake,
Self and Deception, 219–40.
48. E.g. Hegel, in the Phenomenology, “Lordship and Bondage,” P. F. Strawson
in Individuals, and grudgingly even Sartre, in “The Reef of Solipsism,” in Being and
Nothingness, 303 ff.
49. Pilote de Guerre, quoted in Merleau-Ponty, The Phenomenology of Perception
(London: Routledge and Kegan-Paul, 1962).
Self, Deception, and Self-Deception in Philosophy 35
here between a very general claim that one will have no concept of self
at all unless he or she grows up in some society and the more particular-
ist claim that a person learns to cultivate a particular self—a Texan or
a Chuangzou or Maori self, for example—only by growing up in Texas
or Chuangzou or Tanderoa [New Zealand]).50 To insist that the self is
constructed, however, is not yet to claim that the construction is of any
particular typology, in particular, it does not mean that the self so con-
structed is a social self. The American “rugged” individualist is a socially
constructed self, as is the infamously antisocial Ik.51
To say that the self is socially constructed as a social self is to make a
very particular kid of claim, which must be distinguished from the other
two. The Chinese self is socially constructed as a social self, an interde-
pendent self, but, again, we need to make at least one further problematic
distinction. The social construction of self proceeds in part by way of
a language, a language which includes a certain vocabulary of selfhood.
In this language we learn to talk about ourselves in certain ways. A self-
consciously individualist culture will naturally emphasize the importance
of such notions as individuality, autonomy and independence. A self-
consciously communitarian culture will naturally emphasize the impor-
tance of such notions as community, loyalty, duty, and kinship. But how
we talk about ourselves is only a partial indication of how we think about
ourselves and how we actually behave. The social construction of self also
proceeds without language, without self-description, by way of ten thou-
sand non-verbal cues and examples, everything from a mother’s refusal to
leave her infant alone even for a minute and the fact that people tend not
to look each other in the eyes to the waging of war and the celebration of
religious rituals. It is perfectly possible, therefore, for a culture to cultivate
a way of talking about themselves and the self that is somewhat at odds
with the ways in which they actually conceive of themselves and their
relationships to one another. Indeed, in times of social tension or disloca-
tion or in order to distinguish oneself from an alien culture, such diver-
gence of self-conception from practice may be extremely common.52
The resultant complexity of the self—as opposed, say, to the relatively
simplistic Cartesian model of the self—obviously invites self-deception,
deception about the self. If there is no self other than that which is con-
strued, socially constructed, and constructed as social, it might be thought
dubious in what sense there is a self to be deceived about. There are, of
course, any number of logical and deconstructionist tricks to blow up
50. Both the general and the particularist claim are developed, for example, by Clifford
Geertz, Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1966). Both are suggested, at
least, by Hegel in “Lordship and Bondage.”
51. Colin Turnbull, The Mountain People (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1974).
52. For two good philosophical discussions of this, see Alasdair MacIntyre’s After
Virtue, especially the opening chapters, and Nietzsche’s classic discussion of the Greeks in
his Birth of Tragedy, trans. W. Kaufmann (New York: Random House, 1967).
36 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
Deception and self-deception, I have argued, are among the many ways
in which we navigate our way in the social world. Self-deception, in par-
ticular, is a way that we attend to our navigating, and in our increasingly
complex world, it is by no means clear that deception and self-deception—
understood as mechanisms for getting along in the world—are always
vices. It is one of the joys of philosophy that comes from realizing that
our ideas about ourselves and our place in the world are not truths but
experiments, whose outcome is always tentative. But all of this existential
freedom comes along with a cost, all too evident in current American
politics. If deception and self-deception can be instrumental in further-
ing one’s dreams and fantasies, they can also be the ruination of all of us.
There are limits to existential freedom. And that makes it imperative, as
we weigh the skeptical conclusions of this essay, to come down firmly
in favor of the truth. There are two many lies and self-deceptions in the
world that are just not forgivable.
ACKNOWLEDGMENT
Portions of this essay are adapted from “Self, Deception, and Self-Perception in
Philosophy,” a chapter I wrote for Self and Deception, ed. Roger Ames and Wimal
Dissanayake (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1996), 91–122.
Harry Frankfurt
[I]
How do lies injure us? Actually, as everyone knows, there are many famil-
iar circumstances in which lies are not truly injurious to us at all. They
may sometimes be, on the whole, genuinely beneficial. For instance, a lie
may protect us in one way or another from becoming aware of certain
states of affairs, when no one (including ourselves) has anything in par-
ticular to gain from our being aware of them and when our awareness of
them would cause us or others serious distress. Or a lie may divert us from
embarking on a course of action that we find tempting but that would in
fact lead to our doing ourselves more harm than good. Clearly, we must
sometimes acknowledge that, all things considered, having been told a lie
was actually helpful to us.
Even so, we often feel at such times that there was surely something
bad about what the liar did. In the circumstances, it may be reasonable for
us to be grateful for the lie. Whatever good the lie may turn out to have
done, however, we believe at bottom that a better alternative would have
been for the beneficial effects of the lie to have been achieved by sticking
to the truth without any recourse to lying.
The most irreducibly bad thing about lies is that they contrive to inter-
fere with, and to impair, our natural effort to apprehend the real state of
affairs. They are designed to prevent us from being in touch with what
is really going on. In telling his lie, the liar tries to mislead us into believ-
ing that the facts are other than they actually are. He tries to impose his
will on us. He aims at inducing us to accept his fabrication as an accurate
account of how the world truly is.
Insofar as he succeeds in this, we acquire a view of the world that
has its source in his imagination rather than being directly and reliably
grounded in the relevant facts. The world we live in, insofar as our under-
standing of it is fashioned by the lie, is an imaginary world. There may be
worse places to live; but this imaginary world won’t do for us, at all, as a
permanent residence.
37
38 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
Lies are designed to damage our grasp of reality. So they are intended,
in a very real way, to make us crazy. To the extent that we believe them,
our minds are occupied and governed by fictions, fantasies, and illusions
that have been concocted for us by the liar. What we accept as real is
a world that others cannot see, touch, or experience in any direct way.
A person who believes a lie is constrained by it, accordingly, to life “in his
own world”—a world that others cannot enter, and in which even the liar
himself does not truly reside. Thus, the victim of the lie is, in the degree of
his deprivation of truth, shut off from the world of common experience
and isolated in an illusory realm to which there is no path that others
might find or follow.
[ II ]
[ III ]
Truth and caring about truth concern us, then, in ways that do not bear
simply on our quotidian practical interests. They have a deeper and
more damaging significance as well. One of the most rewarding of con-
temporary poets, Adrienne Rich, offers an account of the malign effect
that lying inevitably has—apart from its harmful effect on the person
to whom the lie is told—on the liar herself. With poetic exactitude, she
observes that “the liar leads and existence of unutterable loneliness,” 1
The loneliness is precisely unutterable because the liar cannot even reveal
that she is lonely—that there is no one in her fabricated world—without
disclosing, in doing so, that she has lied. She hides her own thoughts,
pretending to believe what she does not believe, and thereby she makes
it impossible for other people to be fully in touch with her. They cannot
respond to her as she really is. They cannot even be aware that they are
not doing so.
The liar refuses to permit himself, to the extent that he lies, to be
known. This is an insult to his victims. It naturally injures their pride. For
it denies them access to an elementary mode of human intimacy that
1. “Women and Honor: Some Notes on Lying,” in Adrienne Rich, Lies, Secrets and
Silence (New York: 1979), 191.
40 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
is normally taken more or less for granted: the intimacy that consists in
knowing what is on, or what is in, another person’s mind.
In certain cases, Rich notes, lies may cause an even more profound sort
of damage. “To discover that one has been lied to in a personal relation-
ship,” she says, “leads one to feel a little crazy.”2 Here again, her observa-
tion is perspicuous. When we are dealing with someone whom we hardly
know, we have to make a more or less deliberate assessment of her reli-
ability in order to satisfy ourselves that what she tells us coincides with
what she actually believes; and this assessment ordinarily pertains only to
certain specific assertions that she has made. With our close friends, on the
other hand, both of these conditions are usually relaxed. We suppose that
our friends are generally honest with us, and we take this pretty much for
granted. We tend to trust whatever they say, and we do so, mainly, not on
the basis of a calculation establishing that they are currently telling us the
truth, but because we feel comfortable and safe with them. As we famil-
iarly put it, we “just know that they wouldn’t lie to us.”
With friends, the expectation of access and intimacy has become natu-
ral. It is grounded not in a calculated judgment but in our feelings—that
is, in our subjective experience, rather than in any intellectual assessment
based on pertinent objective data. It would be too much to say that our
inclination to trust our friends belongs to our essential nature. But it could
be properly enough said, as we sometimes do in fact say, that trusting
them has come to be “second nature” to us.
That is why, as Rich observes, discovering that a friend has lied to us
engenders in us a feeling of being a little crazy. The discovery exposes to
us something about ourselves—something far more disturbing than merely
that we have miscalculated, or that we have made an error of judgment.
It reveals that our own nature (i.e., our second nature) is unreliable, hav-
ing led us to count on someone we should not have trusted. It shows us
that we cannot realistically be confident of our own ability to distinguish
truth from falsity—our ability, in other words, to recognize the differ-
ence between what is real and what is not. Successfully deceiving a friend
implies, needless to say, a fault in the one who tells the lie. However, it also
shows that the victim of the deception is defective, too. The liar betrays
him, but he is betrayed by his own feelings as well.
Self-betrayal pertains to craziness because it is a hallmark of the irra-
tional. The heart of rationality is to be consistent; and being consistent, in
action or in thought, entails at least proceeding so as not to defeat oneself.
Aristotle suggested that an agent acts rational insofar as he conforms his
actions to the “mean”—that is, to a point midway between excess and
deficiency. Suppose that, for the sake of good health, someone follows a
diet that is either so meager or so indulgent that it not only fails to improve
her health but actually leads her to become less healthy than she was.
2. “Women and Honor: Some Notes on Lying,” in Adrienne Rich, Lies, Secrets and
Silence (New York: 1979),186.
On Truth, Lies, and Bullshit 41
Aristotle urges that it is in this defeat of her own purpose, in this self-
betrayal, that the practical irrationality of the person’s divergence from
the mean consists.
Intellectual activity is undermined, similarly, by logical incoherence.
When a line of thought generates a contradiction, its further progressive
elaboration is blocked. In whatever direction the mind turns, it is driven
back: it must affirm what it has already rejected or it must deny what it
has already affirmed. Thus, like behavior that frustrates its own ambition,
contradictory thinking is irrational because it defeats itself.
When a person discovers that he has been told a lie by someone in
whose reliability he had found it natural to have confidence, this shows
him that he cannot rely on his own settled feelings of trust. He sees that
he has been betrayed, in his effort to identify people in whom he can have
confidence, by his own natural inclinations. These have led him to miss
the truth rather than attain it. His assumption that he could guide himself
in accordance with his own nature has turned out to be self-defeating,
and hence irrational. Since he finds that he is by nature out of touch with
reality, he may well fell that he is a little crazy.
[ IV ]
[V]
Wittgenstein once said that the following bit of verse by Longfellow could
serve him as a motto:3
In the elder days of art
Builders wrought with greatest care
Each minute and unseen part
For the Gods are everywhere.
The point of these lines is clear. In the old days, craftsmen did not
cut corners. They worked carefully, and they took care with every aspect
of their work. Every part of the product was considered, and each was
designed and made to be exactly as it should be. These craftsmen did not
relax their thoughtful self-discipline even with respect to features of their
work that would ordinarily not be visible. Although no one would notice
if those features were not quite right, the craftsmen would be bothered
by their consciences. So nothing was swept under the rug. Or, one might
perhaps also say, there was no bullshit.
It does seem fitting to construe carelessly made, shoddy goods as in
some way analogues of bullshit. But in what way? Is the resemblance
that bullshit itself is invariably produced in a careless or self-indulgent
manner, that it is never finely crafted, that in the making of it there is
never the meticulously attentive concern with detail to which Longfellow
alludes? Is the bullshitter by his very nature a mindless slob? Is his prod-
uct necessarily messy or unrefined? The word shit does, to be sure, suggest
this. Excrement is not designed or crafted at all; it is merely emitted, or
dumped. It may have a more or less coherent shape, or it may not, but it
is in any case certainly not wrought.
The notion of carefully wrought bullshit involves, then, a certain inner
strain. Thoughtful attention to detail requires discipline and objectiv-
ity; it entails accepting standards and limitations that forbid the indul-
gence of impulse or whim. It is this selflessness that, in connection with
bullshit, strikes us as inapposite. But in fact it is not out of the question
at all. The realms of advertising and of public relations, and the nowadays
closely related realm of politics, are replete with instances of bullshit so
unmitigated that they can serve among the most indisputable and clas-
sic paradigms of the concept. And in these realms there are exquisitely
sophisticated craftsmen who—with the help of advanced and demand-
ing techniques of market research, public opinion polling, psychological
is, Pascal really does not know how run-over dogs feel. Even so, when she
says what she does, she is plainly not lying. She would have been lying
if, when she made her statement, she was aware that she actually felt
quite good. For however little she knows about the lives of dogs, it must
certainly be clear to Pascal that when dogs are run over, they do not feel
good. So if she herself had in fact been feeling good, it would have been a
lie to assert that she felt like a run-over dog.
Pascal’s Wittgenstein intended to accuse her not of lying but of misrep-
resentation of another sort. She characterizes her feeling as “the feeling of
a run-over dog.” She is not really acquainted, however, with the feeling to
which this phrase refers. Of course, the phrase is far from being complete
nonsense to her; she is hardly speaking gibberish. What she says has an
intelligible connotation, which she certainly understands. Moreover, she
does know something about the quality of the feeling to which the phrase
refers: she knows at least that it is an undesirable an unenjoyable feeling,
a bad feeling. The trouble with her statement is that it purports to convey
something more than simply that she feels bad. Her characterization of
her feeling is too specific; it is excessively particular. Hers is not just any
bad feeling but, according to her account, the distinctive kind of bad feel-
ing that a dog has when it is run over. To the Wittgenstein in Pascal’s story,
judging from his response, this is just bullshit.
Now assuming that Wittgenstein does indeed regard Pascal’s charac-
terization of how she feels as an instance of bullshit, why does it strike
him that way? It does so, I believe, because he perceives what Pascal says
as being—roughly speaking, for now—unconnected to a concern for the
truth. Her statement is not germane to the enterprise of describing reality.
She does not even think she knows, except in the vaguest way, how a run-
over dog feels. Her description of her own feeling is, accordingly, some-
thing that she is merely making up. She concocts it out of whole cloth;
or, if she got it from someone else, she is repeating it quite mindlessly and
without any regard for how things really are.
It is for this mindlessness that Pascal’s Wittgenstein chides her. What
disgusts him is that Pascal is not even concerned whether her statement is
correct. There is every likelihood, of course, that she says what she does
only in a somewhat clumsy effort to speak colorfully, or to appear viva-
cious or good-humored; and no doubt Wittgenstein’s reactions—as she
construes it—is absurdly intolerant. Be this as it may, it seems clear what
that reaction is. He reacts as though he perceives her to be speaking about
her feeling thoughtlessly, without conscientious attention to the relevant
facts. Her statement is not “wrought with the greatest care.” She makes it
without bothering to take into account at all the question of its accuracy.
The point that troubles Wittgenstein is manifestly not that Pascal has
made a mistake in her description of how she feels. Nor is it even that she
has made careless mistake. Her laxity, or her lack of care, is not a matter of
having permitted an error to slip into her speech on account of some inad-
vertent or momentary negligent lapse in the attention she was devoting to
46 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
getting things right. The point is rather that, as far as Wittgenstein can see,
Pascal offers a description of a certain state of affairs without genuinely
submitting to the constraints which the endeavor to provide an accurate
representation of reality imposes. Her fault is not that she fails to get
things right, but that she is not even trying.
This is important to Wittgenstein because, whether justifiably or not,
he takes what she says seriously, as a statement purporting to give an
informative description of the way she feels. He construes her as engaged
in an activity to which the distinction between what is true and what is
false is crucial, and yet as taking no interest in whether what she says is
true or false. It is in this sense that Pascal’s statement is unconnected to
a concern with truth: she is not concerned with the truth-value of what
she says. That is why she cannot be regarded as lying; for she does not pre-
sume that she knows the truth, and therefore she cannot be deliberately
promulgating a proposition that she presumes to be false: her statement is
grounded neither in a belief that it is true nor, as a lie must be, in a belief
that is not true. It is just this lack of connection to a concern with truth—
this indifference to how things really are—that I regard as the essence of
bullshit.
[ VI ]
the same way that bullshitting tends to. Through excessive indulgence in
the latter activity, which involves making assertions without paying atten-
tion to anything except what it suits one to say, a person’s normal habit of
attending to the ways things are may become attenuated or lost. Someone
who lies and someone who tells the truth are playing on opposite sides, so
to speak, in the same game. Each responds to the facts as she understands
them, although the response of the one is guided by the authority of the
truth, while the response of the other defies that authority and refuses
to meet its demands. The bullshitter ignores these demands altogether.
She does not reject the authority of the truth, as the liar does, or oppose
herself to it. She pays no attention to it at all. By virtue of this, bullshit is
a greater enemy of the truth than lies are.
On Truth, Lies, and Bullshit 49
49
50 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
SKILL
Let me start with a frolic and a small detour. Take the case of boxing,
football, or any sport that involves facing off against an opponent rather
than, say, track or golf, which involves tests that require comparisons
of discrete individual performances. 4 Football is all about making your
opponent think you are going to pass rather than run, run here rather
than there, throw to this receiver rather than that one. Receivers develop
moves to fake out defenders. Boxers and wrestlers feint, set up their
opponents. Moves are the name of the game. And while we delight in the
player who is so strong and powerful that he need not develop the skills
3. One might secure a reputation for courage with one grand performance early in
one’s career and thereby gain enough credit to make room for considerable prudence
thereafter, but even then there would be gossiping. See, e.g., Polybius (10.3) on Scipio
Africanus.
4. Though races longer than four hundred meters involve strategizing, and positioning
tactics, and golfers may try to get into each other’s heads, the rough distinction survives.
Deceit in War and Trade 51
of trickery and fakery and need do nothing more than charge straight
ahead and overcome with brute strength, he is the exception; even he
will eventually confront someone who is his match in sheer strength and
then the one who can trick, feint, and fake will defeat the other. There is
no moral problem here. And the analogy with war works.
What if, however, the big strong brute, a Goliath, gets taken down
from afar by someone who brings a different technology to bear, not quite
within the rules of the game Goliath thinks he is playing, but within the
rules of the game his opponent thinks is the real game at hand? A moral
problem begins to emerge, rather different from the one that arises when
a man nine cubits and a span tall decked out in armor from head to toe
bearing a spear crafted with the latest Iron Age metallurgy goes against
an untested youth without armor still using Stone Age technology. Asym-
metry of force raises different moral problems from those raised by guile
and deceit, though one of the goals of deceit may be to gain a local advan-
tage so that you become, relatively speaking and for a brief exploitable
moment, the one holding the winning hand.
For us, drugging one’s opponent is clearly outside the game, yet more
than a few athletes think that drugging oneself can do nice work if you
can sneak it in: thus the tawdry tales that are the daily fare of baseball,
swimming, cycling, cross-country skiing, track and field, even golf. The fact
that we recognize a distinction between the deceit that is openly part of
the skill set of a particular game and the deceit of juicing oneself up with
undetectable chemicals has a history. Witness the Iliad, and many a medi-
eval romance, in which it is not yet clear that actions like bribing judges,
enlisting the gods on your side, sticking poles in the spokes of the other’s
wheels, poisoning your sword in a duel, using magic weapons, and claim-
ing a privilege that entitles you to win a race by virtue of your social rank
rather than your speed were not clearly outside the game. Though some
advances have been made, sometimes it is one step forward, two back.
The boundaries separating one game from another, or the inside from
the outside, are often in dispute. Archers, though very effective at kill-
ing at relatively small risk to themselves, like Paris or the English long-
bowmen, were looked down on by the men who fought mano a mano,
like Hector or knightly men-at-arms. That David could stay well out of
reach of Goliath’s javelin and hit him from afar with a force-multiplying
sling—is that a move, a tactic in the game; or not the same game? Bald
trickery and cheating if you are a Philistine, a glorious triumph if you are
a Judean. In the age of chivalry, a thirteenth-century French legal compi-
lation defines treachery in war, “treason” in his idiom, as hitting someone
who could not see what hit him.5 This was meant to give a bad name to a
5. “Treachery is when one attacks a man so that he cannot see the blow coming ...or
when one surprises another and strikes him when he cannot defend himself”; Li livres de
Jostice et de Plet, ed. Rapetti [sic], in Collection de Documents Inédits sur l’Histoire de France
(Paris: Firmin Didot, 1850), bk. 19, ch. 19, p. 297. (Thanks to Stephen D. White for this
citation, and see his “Alternative Constructions of Treason in the Angevin Political World:
52 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
knight who snuck up from behind, but mostly it meant woe for the poor
crossbowmen a hundred meters behind the general melee who ran out of
bolts. Bowmen were not held for ransom, as a captured knight would be,
but were butchered for their “treachery,” though of course one made sure
to have as many as one could afford serving one’s own cause. 6
There is an anxiety, though fainter in our day than in earlier times,
that lurked in the notion of skill and deftness that is evidenced by an
insistent “duplicity,” a conflicted moral tone, in more than a few of the
words in English meaning skill. The word cunning in Middle English was,
in fact, the word for technical skill such as a craftsman might possess; a
cunning silver smith was one who did beautifully intricate and admirable
work. By the end of the sixteenth century, cunning had begun to acquire
a pejorative sense that ended up driving out the morally neutral and posi-
tive senses it had had.7 There was also the pun and confusion in Middle
and early Modern English caused by two mysteries of different origin, one
Greek, the other Latin. The former was the mystery of religion, the mys-
teries of the faith, which we still employ secularly today when reading a P.
D. James mystery; the second mystery was the mystery 8 of craft, with craft
bearing the sense of skill, art, trade, as, for instance, Chaucer’s Reeve, who
“in youthe ...hadde lerned a good myster; / He was a wel good wrighte,
a carpenter.”9 This mystery was confused with mastery, for fairly obvious
reasons of near homonymity, and by the coincidence that a person who
passed beyond being a journeyman in his "myster" became a "master" in
his craft. The result is a triple pun, each form suggesting in its own way
a sleight of hand: sleight, by the way, like cunning, bears the competing
senses of both trick and skill, though the latter sense was already rare by
the nineteenth century.10 And then add to that the double meanings of
the word craft just used,11 whose bad and good senses coexisted from the
Traïson in the History of William Marshal,” e-Spania, 4 (décembre 2007), 1–47, mis en ligne
le 21 décembre 2007: http://e-spania.revues.org/document2233.html. Consulté 10 avril
2008.) I discuss various revenge cultures in which it was perfectly acceptable to dispatch
one’s vengeance target without him knowing what or who had hit him in Eye for an Eye
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 150–51.
6. On butchering crossbowmen, see Matthew Strickland, War and Chivalry: The
Conduct and Perception of War in England and Normandy, 1066–1217 (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1996), 180–81. Nonetheless, knights in chivalric battle employed
nearly all the tricks advised by Sun Tzu; the most usual one being to avoid battle altogether
and substitute for it the plundering of one’s opponents’ peasants; see John Gillingham,
“War and Chivalry in the History of William Marshal,” in Gillingham, Richard Coeur de Lion:
Kingship, Chivalry and War in the Twelfth Century (London: Hambledon Press, 1994), 227–41.
7. OED, cunning sb. For an engaging dissection of cunning see Don Herzog, Cunning
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2006).
8. OED, mystery 2, from Medieval Latin misterium, altered form of ministerium.
9. Canterbury Tales, General Prologue, vv. 613–14.
10. OED, sleight sb. 1.
11. OED, craft sb. 1.
Deceit in War and Trade 53
twelfth century, and one sees a deep mistrust of the moral quality of skill
and those who were skilled. They were felt to be uncanny, as if they were
so many otherworldly tricksters.
Not only technical skills but intelligence itself raised grounds for suspi-
cion and was of uncertain moral warrant. The serpent, after all, “was more
subtil than any beast of the field.” Many felt intelligence was in league
with the devil: the “cunning man” or the “cunning woman” was also the
specialist in black arts, which is another sense cunning took on. The mor-
alists hailing reason as a virtue ran up against the popular understanding
that reason was nothing more than a stick in the bundle of tricks clerics
and lawyers used to make sure the game being played was one favoring
their own skill set: wordplay rather than swordplay.12
Heroes of the sort who were known as crafty, subtle, wily, “wise,” an Odys-
seus or a David, would always test the boundaries and ultimately accept
expedience as the chief arbiter of their consciences. That Odysseus goes out
one night to kill sleeping allies of the Trojans is part of what it meant to be
wise in his world, but that the battle-brave, traditionally heroic Diomedes
does the actual butchering, while Odysseus drags the bodies away so as not
to worry the horses into making too much noise to spoil the fun, is conven-
tionally understood to show that Homer is critiquing the ugly business that
not merely compromised the heroic ethic, but in some sense sustained it.13
But perhaps we are making Homer subtler than he meant to be by mak-
ing him more congenial to our own deep ambivalence regarding honor
and the heroic ethic. Why assume that, in the night-killing episode, he is
undermining Odysseus or Diomedes, morally or otherwise? For Homer,
it is mostly a comic interlude anyway, an excuse to get raucous laughter
at the expense of the groveling coward, Dolon, captured by Diomedes
and Odysseus. Homer may be rather indifferent to the moral implica-
tions, if any, of spearing sleeping soldiers if doing so made tactical sense,
especially when it prompts a good laugh. He may merely have meant to
indicate that heroes get to charge ahead and act heroically by day—no
mean feat—as long as they have someone minding the purely practical
side of things, taking advantage where advantage is to be had, at night.
And one person, a thoroughly respectable person at that, could play both
roles: upstanding man of courage by day, a sly and sneaky killer by night.
Besides, whatever the moral cost that attends night killing is rather neatly
balanced by the moral failure of the sleeping victims: they die for their sin
of culpable complacency.
12. See Fredric Cheyette, “The Invention of the State,” in B. K. Ladner and K. R. Philp,
eds. Essays on Medieval Civilization (Austin: University of Texas Press, 1978), 143–78.
13. Iliad 10.480–510.
54 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
14. Iliad 6.232; Robert Fitzgerald. trans. (Garden City, NY: Anchor, 1974). Homer’s
joke at Glaukos’s expense is more complex than it appears at first glance. The difference
in value between Diomedes and Glaukos’s armor would only be one hundred to nine
in an armorer’s shop, and that is part of the wit of the joke, for it wryly introduces hard
mercantile concerns that both fund and are the object of much glory seeking. Back in
the Trojan camp, the bronze armor of Diomedes, because it had belonged to the great
Diomedes, would have a premium attached to it. In the Greek camp, the gold armor
gains little for having been Glaukos’s, though its value might still be enhanced beyond
comparable gold armor by its now having the comic tale of its acquisition attached to it.
15. See for fuller discussion my The Mystery of Courage (Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 2000), 162–67.
16. Thus Snorri the Priest in Eyrbyggja Saga and Laxdæla Saga; Sturla in Sturlu Saga.
Gudrun in Laxdaela Saga. Compare the easier-to-scare Mord Valgardsson in Njál’s saga.
Deceit in War and Trade 55
How much sapientia was needed, though, if the Trojans, after holding out
behind walls and in battle for ten years, could fall for the Trojan horse?
But then the Trojans had as yet no proverb saying “Fear Greeks bearing
gifts,” until Laocoön coined it on the spot, though the spot was in the
Aeneid, and thus too late to help Troy; moreover, in the Aeneid it did not
have the force of a proverb but of an impious novelty, and within an hour
Laocoön and his sons were devoured by sea-serpents.
How could a trick like that work? Virgil has to devote considerable
effort to make the tale told by Sinon, the Greek “deserter,” convincing
enough for the Trojans to appear as something less than idiots for having
believed him. Virgil could hardly wish his Romans to be descended from
Trojan fools, no matter how heroic the escapee Aeneas might be. Surely,
the Trojans had their own trickster tales that expressed the same prover-
bial wisdom as the tale of the horse. Everyone does. The Trojans had their
moralists and comedians who either warned against or complained about
the wiliness of their slaves, their women, and their enemies and coined
proverbs about the poison that lurked within the benignest of gifts, but
still the deceit worked.
Deceit works as well as it does because humans are so easy to set up
for the fall. Warnings of doom go unheeded. And why shouldn’t they?
Cassandra raises the same problems all prophets raise: it is very hard to
tell the false doomsayer from the true, for even the false one gets it right
some of the time, given that we get sick, have accidents, grow old, and
die. It might thus be rational not to listen to Cassandra, unless she can
come up with some hard evidence that the straits are more dire than
usual.17 Besides, doomsayers are a dime a dozen. Why should Caesar have
been wary about the Ides of March, when he no doubt had been treated
to years of being warned to beware the Nones of February, the Kalends
of June, and so on. He had to ignore doomsayers, or he would never have
left the house, and would never, for certain, have been the world histori-
cal figure he was.
But even if the Trojans had the story of the Trojan horse or believed
Cassandra, the fact is that the same trick can work again and again. Like
the plots of novels, there are a limited number of tricks, and they merely
have to trick themselves out in slightly different costumes to work in
every generation. The very predictability of known deceits that have
been employed for the umpteenth time give the trickster the advantage
of his or her mark’s complacency with regard to that particular trick: no
17. Obviously, reason alone does not block our ears to Cassandra’s panicky predictions.
Our deafness to her doomsaying is also a sign of what in the sixteenth century was called
the sin of security, a culpable looking on the bright side of things, “a forgetting mortalitie,”
in Thomas Nashe’s words; see my Faking It (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2003), 28. But we also may, not unjustly, mistrust the doomsayer as motivated by a
dispositional pessimism that resents the pleasure of those who are eating, drinking, and
being merry, who may be doing so not out of a culpable sense of security but because that
is how they are choosing to meet their ends, not how they are choosing to live their lives.
56 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
one is going to get me on that one, and so we lower our defenses and get
fooled again.18
But war raises the stakes: if the standard trickster makes us pay for our
greed and our vanity, the emotional backdrop of war is dominated by fear
for life. Lighting more campfires than you have men to warm in order to
make the enemy believe you have a larger force has been employed hun-
dreds of times in scores of wars. It is not as if the enemy does not know
the trick (they have employed it more than a few times themselves, and
perhaps at the same time you are employing yours); it is just that they are
scared and likely to err on the side of nonconfrontation. And on occasion,
they have lit fewer campfires than needed to entice you into battle when
they have the advantage in numbers. So what do those campfires mean?
If you are being tricked into more wariness than it was wise to have at a
particular moment, and you thus let a small enemy force slip away under
the cover of darkness, you at least are alive to get it right, or wrong again
perhaps, the next time. But even without fear as the backdrop, in mere
matters of anticipation and reading another’s intentions, as in a basket-
ball game, for instance, the same crossover move works again and again,
against people who are skilled players themselves and have seen it a thou-
sand times: it is not the move itself but the timing of it that bears a good
portion of its guile.
Though both sapientia and wisdom are words that indicate a virtue and
bring virtuous associations to mind, the “wise” in wisdom, even the sapiens
in sapientia, can end up partaking of the more dubious world of feints
and double moves—that is, of craft, cunning, and sleights—as much as
of the world of wise counsel, prudence, and subtle strategy. The kind of
“wisdom” that was required in the midst of ancient battle shared more
with the skill of crossover dribbles and how to anticipate them, when to
fake right and go left, than with high matters of strategy. Thus, in the Bat-
tle of Maldon—an Anglo-Saxon poem of extraordinary power composed
shortly after the battle (991 A.D.) it commemorates—the English leader
is called fród, a word bearing the meanings “wise, skillful, sage, old,” for
spearing a Viking through the neck in close combat, after that same Viking
has wounded him. Fród applies to him in part as an epithet for being the
leader of the English troop, an elder, but the nearest referent for fród in
the text is the spearing. The Old English says the hand of the fród warrior
“guided” his spear through the neck of the Viking (“Fród wæs sé fyrdrinc”;
he let his “francan wadan / þurh ðæs hysses hals, hand wísode”).19 He is fród
18. Some betrayals are so openly negotiated that it boggles the mind that they can
work; one needn’t even build a horse. In eleventh-century Byzantium, we see people who
are guarding city walls having “cautious” but obviously quite loud conversations with
besiegers below about opening the gates, and this after the besiegers have walked around
shouting up to various defenders to find out who could be bought; see Anna Comnena,
The Alexiad 2.9, trans. E. R. A. Sewter (London: Penguin, 1969), 95–96.
19. The Battle of Maldon, vv. 140–42.
Deceit in War and Trade 57
Surely, in the golden age when men were men and met in battle the way
Hector met Achilles (though Hector started running) and not quite as
David met Goliath, there was no perfidy, no tricksterism. Why? Because
our forefathers were too honorable, too virtuous—or too dumb—to set
the other one up with a stab in the back or with poison in the night.
Or was it only that they liked to tell stories of grand virtue, which
on occasion they aspired to, but, mercifully, still kept a few tricks up
their sleeve, about which they also told tales? Montaigne takes on these
issues right at the start of his Essays, devoting essays 5 and 6 of Book I
to them.
Essay 5 bears the title “Whether the Leader of a Besieged Place Should
Go Out to Negotiate.” The answer is no, by gum, don’t do it! unless you
want to see your walled town breached while you are talking peace out-
side. Hence the title of essay 6, which continues the theme of 5: “The
Hour of Negotiations Is Dangerous.”
This leads Montaigne to musings on fair play versus deceit and expedi-
ence. First he takes on the issue of a glorious past, when men were too
honorable to be so treacherous as to win wars while pretending to make
peace. He tells of a Roman legate, Marcius,23 who secured a truce with
his opponent, Perseus, the king of Macedonia, in order to buy time to
reinforce his troops. But the Senate disapproved of Marcius’s behavior
as contrary to the ancient practice of their fathers, which was “to fight
with courage, not with sleights, not by surprise or night ambushes, nor by
feigned flight and unexpected about-faces, nor to have undertaken a war
unless it was first declared, and often designating the hour and place of
battle.” To behave as Marcius did was to act, they said, with “Greek crafti-
ness or Punic cunning, for whom it was actually less glorious to win by
force than by fraud.”
The view attributed to the Senate was not all tough talk, easy for old
men safe in Rome to engage in. Some policy was alleged for the old vir-
tuous way of no feints and sleights: “Only those recognize themselves
defeated who know they have been beaten by valor, troop by troop, in a
fair and just war.”24 In other words, you gain threat advantage by tromping
the smithereens out of an enemy when they are ready for you and are giv-
ing their best. They will then come away with no easy excuses to prime a
self-deceiving belief in their own superiority. They will be very reluctant
to try again and will accept defeat as the order of things. Winning on the
sly with deceit is not as destructive of the other side’s will to take up the
cause again.
A point before continuing with my theme: it appears to be an oft-
occurring, anxious fantasy of the powerful to believe that some subset of
peoples whom they have defeated and abused are all cunning and craft,
and defiling, loathsome and dangerous for being so. Thus in the Roman
view the Carthaginians and the Greeks were all guile and deceit, and
thus, though sometime later, in just about everyone’s paranoid fantasies,
the Jews, who for more than a thousand years have served as the univer-
sal cunning and guileful Other. Guile gets you only so far, as I suppose
the old men of the Senate well knew. Guile may get you a victory here
and there and at lower cost than if it were gained without guile but we
need only look at the lot of the Greeks, Carthaginians, and Jews, that is,
at the big-time wily losers. Guile needs more than guile: it also needs
23. Montaigne, Oeuvres Complètes, ed. Maurice Rat (Paris: Gallimard, 1962).
Montaigne actually has Lucius Marcius, which must be an error for Quintus Marcius. It
was Lucius Aemilius Paulus who defeated Perseus in the Third Macedonian War, who
had the highest reputation, not Quintus Marcius, who was known for deceitfulness.
Translations are mine.
24. A nearly opposite argument is made in Thucydides 4.19: an outnumbered party
suggests to the opposition that an honorable peace will bring much better consequences
than one side overwhelming the other, for then the overwhelmed will want to get even,
whereas honor will require them not to break a peace they negotiated. The argument is,
not surprisingly, made by those who are about to get overwhelmed.
Deceit in War and Trade 59
a durable fist to secure the advantage guile gains (unless, like the more
conventional small stakes conman, you skip town before the dupe knows
he has been fleeced).25 Though the guileful might have contempt for the
lack of subtlety of the mighty whom they see as big dumb brutes, the
mighty brutes are not so dumb; that they are is a fantasy of the defeated.
The mighty rightly suspect—precisely because they are smart—that the
cunning fear brute toughness, more rightly than the mighty do wiliness.
The cunning weak have rather less margin for error than the mighty. Nor
are the mighty victors averse to recruiting the cagiest of the losers as, yes,
trusted advisors.
It seems, Montaigne says, that “these good men [the Senators] had
not yet learned of this belle sentence [quoting Virgil]: ‘Trick or courage . . .
between enemies, it doesn’t matter.’ ”26 Virgil notwithstanding, the Flo-
rentines more than a thousand years later would give their enemies, says
Montaigne, a month’s notice before engaging in battle.27 Now, he observes,
we are harder-nosed realists, we are less “superstitious,” and we believe
that he has “the honor in war, who has the gains Where the skin of the
lion doesn’t work, better sew on a bit of the fox’s.” And no time is riper
for deceit than during peace negotiations, especially for those under siege,
who might have to leave the security of their walled fortress to parley:
“and for this reason all military men in our times give voice to the rule
that a governor of a place under siege should never, himself, go outside to
negotiate.” Mistrust and cynicism are current, and the proverbial wisdom
that sustains them is ancient.
’Twas ever thus, whether among Homeric heroes, the virtuous Romans
of the Republic, or the knights at the dawn of the chivalric age. William
of Malmesbury (c. 1120) says of William the Conqueror early in the
Conqueror’s career: “How can I do justice to the incredible courage and
self-confidence he showed in never stooping to a surprise attack, always
naming the day beforehand, as though his proud spirit disdained the nor-
mal practice of our times.”28 Similarly, most people were pretty sharp about
making sure hostages were exchanged before negotiating, but then even
25. Before Jews acquired a reputation for cunning, they first tried taking on the
Romans the good old Roman way, by force. The Romans incurred considerable losses in
finally crushing Bar Kochba’s rebellion in 135 CE. That was the last time a Jewish army
would take the field until 1948. The Punic example notwithstanding, one would almost be
tempted to see a correlation between the attribution of cunning to an entire people and
their lack of an army.
26. Aeneid 2.390.
27. Giving a month’s notice is not a grand gesture against Florence’s interest: though
it may give the enemy time to prepare, it also gives time for at least one political faction
among the enemy to betray their cause or time to undermine the courage of those who
have a month to sleep on the prospect of a fight. The month’s warning, of course, is really
only available to the side that already has the threat advantage.
28. William of Malmesbury, Gesta Regum Anglorum [The history of the English kings],
trans. R. A. B. Mynors (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998), sec. 234.
60 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
these exchanges could be tricks, as when the hostage you thought you
were getting, a person of high value and closely connected to the com-
mander on the other side, turned out to be one of low value, about whom
they could care less if he got butchered when they violated the truce,
as they had always meant to do. Despite the cynicism and mistrust and
despite the ancient wisdom of wolves donning sheep costumes, guards
were dropped yet again and again.29
Even guard-dropping may not be irrational, for wariness can be exces-
sive. One needs to decide how costly one’s wariness is as against the risk
of passing up golden opportunities, only some of which may turn out to
have been thinly gilded. Yet the deceits that work are lamented precisely
because one was so stupid not to have seen through them, not to have
taken precautions, because in fact the trick would have been so cheap to
insure against, so easy to discover—please make sure the sentry is a natu-
ral insomniac, and do not out go out to parley if you are the leader of the
fortress. Send a proxy, preferably a distinguished man of your entourage
whose wife you covet.
Montaigne continues the discussion in the next essay, giving an exam-
ple from his own neighborhood during the religious wars. One party com-
plained of the treachery of the other, but Montaigne seems to think that
given the norms of the time, each was foolish to have trusted the other.
He comes pretty close to embracing, or at least accepting, the hard truth
that this is how the game is played, so one had better wise up: “For it is not
said that, at a given time or place, we are not permitted to take advantage
of the stupidity of our enemies just as we do of their cowardice.”
If you can slaughter cowardly enemies, why not also the fools who
trust your white flag, who believe your overtures of peace? 30 As regards
the enemy’s gullibility, his trust in appearances, his susceptibility to being
tricked, Montaigne gives the practical view: in “a given time or place,”
stupidity should get no special treatment from our consciences. Exactly
when and where these given times and places are he does not say. He
means to suggest that the privilege granted to take advantage of stupidity
is not as broad as the right to benefit from the enemy’s cowardice, but it
is not much narrower either. Yes, to take advantage of the enemy’s stupid-
ity is ugly business, and we have bad words for it, like deceit, treachery,
guile, fraud, but we also have to contend with winning versus losing; and
the stakes are so high: our very lives, our freedom or our slavery, which
means mostly the enslavement of our wives, mothers, and daughters. So
you pass up the opportunity to steal the war because your opponent was
stupid enough to trust you without taking precautions. Will you gain your
29. Thus, to some, it is naively complacent to seek negotiated assurances from North
Korea or Iran not to build nuclear weapons.
30. Considering no mercy was shown to cowards in one’s own ranks, it was hard to
expect it to be shown to ones in the enemy’s. Culpable stupidity is the sin of commanders.
The private soldier’s stupidity hardly matters, unless he is a stupid, sleepy, and gullible sentry.
Deceit in War and Trade 61
enemy’s gratitude, or just his sigh of relief while he thinks you an even
greater fool for not cashing in on the opportunity than he was for so
carelessly providing you with it? One posts sentries as a routine matter
against the deceit of night attack;31 why, too, shouldn’t figurative sentries
be posted during peace parlays or when the enemy comes out waving a
white flag?
TRADE
Deceit was a necessary player in war, but it was not officially supposed to
be there. Deceit ran against war’s high moral grain; it was dishonorable. If
courage alone could be counted on to win, then courage was morally pref-
erable to winning by deceit (unless you were, in Roman eyes, a Greek or
a Carthaginian who preferred to win by deceit even when you could win
by force). War was, by one moral theory, supposed to be a testing ground
of the purest virtue—courage. In fact virtue—virtù—was courage itself,
before the word got expanded and generalized to cover goodnesses of a
more peaceful stripe. Never mind, as noted, that wiser heads were more
than able to work around the official ideology of courage—but I would
be surprised if even those heads were consistently cynical. Odysseus cares
no less than Ajax that people respect his fighting ability, his straight-up
martial skills.
Trade was quite the other way around. Deceit was the name of the
game. And no virtue was held to inhere in chaffering, except ones like
prudence that suspiciously mimicked cowardliness if you scraped away
the makeup and paint. Long before it fell to Marxian academics to sneer
at traders, the role of sneerer was played by aristocrats, from the high-
caste warriors of Homer, to medieval nobles, to fainéant impoverished
lords at fancy watering holes in the nineteenth and early twentieth centu-
ries. Traders have gotten even worse treatment from lowly peasants, who
occasionally rose up and murdered them in pogroms, whether they were
Chinese in Southeast Asia, Germans in the Slavic hinterlands, Armenians
in Turkey, or Jews pretty near anywhere.
There was much self-serving self-deception in the ancient aristocratic
views of the cowardly trader, especially about those traders who were
involved in long-distance trade. A merchant needed to be a tough guy back
then to defend his goods, since the warriors who sneered at him tended
to be, not to put too fine a point on it, pirates; 32 while other traders, your
competitors, were not averse to piracy themselves, and that meant you
31. The Trojan allies whom Diomedes butchered are said to have counted on the
Trojans to post a watch. The children and wives of these allies were safe far away, so they
felt less sense of urgency to post their own sentries, trusting to the Trojans, who had more
at stake. The Trojans, however, were keeping a very lax watch; Iliad 10.415–22.
32. See, e.g., Iliad 1.366.
62 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
weren’t either. In the Scandinavian north, it was often hard to tell from
one week to the next whether a Viking ship carried traders or raiders. If
the place they were approaching looked well defended, they put on their
trading hats; if it looked ripe for plundering, they put on their helmets
(not horned, despite nineteenth-century depictions to the contrary).33
What they plundered in one place became the cargo—often women—
they sold in the next. One way or another, raiding involved some trading.
In war, the victim of a stratagem or deceit was “surprised.” Indeed, the
noun surprise first comes into English with the specifically military mean-
ing of being taken unawares by the enemy. 34 In trade, a buyer could not be
“surprised” as a man of courage might be in war, because the buyer
expected to be cheated by the seller, and the seller in his turn to be stiffed
by the buyer. The mutuality of the feeling, however, was not quite congru-
ent. Sellers who purveyed to the nobility could end up stiffed, with the
noble, if he cared to give an answer to someone so beneath him, claiming
that no payment was justified because the seller had cheated him. Some-
times a buyer showed up in force to “buy” the goods with muscle, coming
very close to piracy, but would leave behind a payment at a “fair” price he
determined.35 But let’s leave kings and barons, raiders and long-distance
traders out of it and take instead a simple transaction in the county mar-
ket on market day. There the belief was that sellers held all the cards.
Buyers expected, quite simply, to be tricked; that is what it meant to buy
until only rather recently.
If the satirists and moralists of the fourteenth through the seventeenth
century are to be believed,36 the odds were that the merchant’s scale was
biased in his favor, that he kept one set of weights to measure the goods
bought and another to measure the goods the buyer handed over in pay-
ment.37 Were his goods watered down, adulterated, shoddy? Probably, but
then so were everyone else’s. At least everyone thought that such was the
case. Was the meal wormy, the meat tainted? If it wasn’t, the price would
have been still higher. When prices—obeying inexorable laws of supply
and demand—went up, buyers felt sellers were cheating and gouging, but
when abundance drove prices down, buyers gave sellers no credit whatso-
ever. The feeling of being had was programmed into the buyer’s position.
This is not the deceit of a sneak attack during a truce, in which one had
a rosier view than the situation turned out to warrant. In the regime of
brutal scarcity that characterized preindustrial economies, deceit in trade,
unlike deceit in war, was expected, and perceived whether it was there or
not. It was the product of a distinctly unrosy view that characterized any
commerical transaction. Deceit was the devil’s way, and thus the way of
the world, for the fallen world was the devil’s domain. Where there was
plenty, it was possessed not by the just but by the unrighteous.
Several factors helped add fuel to the fire of these suspicions, even
beyond their confirmation by fact:
1. Prices did go down when supplies increased relative to demand,
and then lower prices set a benchmark from which any upward
variation meant deceit.
2. Aristotle, Christianity, and the law (Islam was no better), all self-
deceptively clueless about the time value of money, raised
impossible expectations that loans and credit should be interest
free, that interest was unnatural and a swindle.
3. There was a sense, fostered by the ubiquity of poverty, that
transactions were zero-sum at best. A buyer could see that some
people were doing better than he was, and they were not distant lords
and ladies but people close by who were selling or extending credit
to him. In fact, these sellers were not much better off than he, but he
believed they were getting more than their fair share of the very small
pie. We might condemn this as envy, but given the poverty levels, envy
might have been the form a desperate life-force was forced to take.
4. There were fantasies of plenty, but they just frustrated the buyer.
For if there had been an Eden, and there was somewhere a Land
of Cockayne, he was not about to be an invitee. Better to engage in
petty thievery, secretive and unneighborly, to be a cheat yourself.
Mostly, though, the peasant’s deceit took the form not of taking
from but of keeping from: keeping his best cheese from the tithe-
hungry priest, his largest eggs and fattest hen, if such he had, from
his lord’s bailiff when he came to collect rents in kind. And if the
peasant unloaded his shoddiest goods on the priest and the bailiff,
well, then he, too, could smirk the smirk of the guileful. Such,
such, were the joys.
And what of the seller, who knew that the buyer loathed him? He
might maintain a pretense of honesty; might even be honest and kind and
extend credit to hard-strapped buyers, hoping that when the next bad
64 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
harvest came, as it inevitably did, they would refrain from burning him in
his home. Buyers, he knew, refused somehow to recognize that the seller
had himself been a buyer when dealing with his purveyor—that he had
incurred costs. And like any buyer, the seller believed he was being cheated
by his vendor. The baker knew that the prices he charged buyers, who
believed he was cheating them, were a function of what he himself had
to pay the miller, who he in turn believed was cheating him. The laws of
supply and demand were thus both known and not known by the same
person, depending on whether he was situated as a seller or a buyer.
To this day, it takes several undergrad economics courses to come to
understand that when gasoline prices jump, it is not the gas-station owner,
or even some evil corporation, swindling us (though it might be the effect
of the OPEC cartel) but that it is the predictable effect of ups and downs
in supply caused by hurricanes, war, refining capacity, and increased or
decreased demand in China and India. The politician believes that the
voters think like our medieval buyers, so he claims the gasoline purveyors
are gouging. Is the politician deceiving or self-deceiving when he does so?
Like the medieval seller, he seems to have only an intermittent under-
standing of supply and demand. Notice, too, that for us, the politician is
occupying a position the modern seller has largely vacated: that of the
structural deceiver, the sleight-of-hand chiseler, the devil’s familiar—
though we excuse some if they are charming. And no differently from the
medieval buyer, we do little more than grumble and occasionally, but very
rarely, rise up in a modest jacquerie and throw the bums out; mostly we
just get fooled again.
But a miracle happened: if deceit did not quite vacate the domain of
trade, it ceased to be its presiding deity. Finally, buyers’ fantastic expec-
tations of the bargain they felt justly entitled to started to be met for a
widening segment of the population in some parts of the world. We might
start with seventeenth-century Holland or eighteenth-century England,
but by the mid–twentieth century in the now rich Western world, mem-
bers of a very broad middle class, which included significant numbers of
those by other estimations deemed to be working class, accepted sellers,
with no resentment at all, as respectable members of their community.
We now believe in Best Buy, Tesco, and IKEA, and we are not fools for so
believing. We can even return what we have bought and get our money
back at our whim.38
Of course, all that wealth spontaneously generated myriad swindlers
and deceits the costs of which were to be measured in amounts heretofore
unthinkable.39 In an earlier draft of this piece, before the collapse of world
financial markets I could write this: “But with wealth and abundance,
38. For items of greater economic moment, like cars, lemon laws came to the rescue.
39. In the mid–nineteenth century, Herman Melville, no different from a medieval
moralist, could envisage American society as a series of nested and infinitely generative
cons; Melville, The Confidence Man (1857).
Deceit in War and Trade 65
40. See Herzog, Cunning, 61–64, on his correspondence with such an emailer.
66 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
But then, we are all ripe to be deceived by others. Our own commit-
ment to good manners requires that we believe the acts others are putting
on. “Social life would not last long if men were not taken in by each other,”
says La Rochefoucauld. Goffman suggests that the primal social virtue of
tact requires that we go along with less than perfect performances, lest
we make a scene.41 Thus we accept as true, if only for the moment, the
pretenses of politeness and feigned pleasure others take in our company,
the excuses for why someone is late or has refused our invitation. This
“going along” is a moral requirement of sorts, and it gives the conman his
wedge even against people who are not fools but are simply doing what
well-socialized people must do. And that is when we turn against him.
We shift our sympathies when the swindler preys on the virtues of his
marks rather than on their vices, when they are plucked because they are
kind, charitable, hospitable, selfless, mannerly (or maybe just trying to
save for their retirement or kids’ college education or retirement). And
we mostly continue to sympathize, even when we begin to think that
that well-mannered and charitable soul who just got taken should have
been a little more alert to the risks of his goodness. If you want to help
real down-and-out characters, better get some street smarts to assist your
charity. And so when he has been fleeced for perhaps the second or third
time, then, though we still think the swindler a worm, we begin to find
the kindly soul’s naiveté, even his goodness, culpably stupid.
Whom we sympathize with seems to be subject to cyclic variation.
Thus the law swings from little sympathy for buyers, caveat emptor, to
aggressive solicitude—caveat vendor—no matter how stupid the buyer
may be. Stick it to the manufacturer; impose strict liability, punitive dam-
ages. Attorneys thus advise manufacturers to put warning labels on their
products. But then the inevitable shift of sympathies sets in, not because
people feel sorry for the nameless shareholders of a big corporation but
because the sufferance of fools can only go so far. My eleven-year-old son
takes great delight in reading warning labels and exploding in laughter:
“Hey dad, look at this package of sliced turkey pepperoni: ‘Warning: do
not eat packet’”—not the packaging, which even a fool knows not to eat,
but the sealed packet of preservative, which apparently looks too good to
some people to pass up. That the commercial showing a guy driving a car
off a cliff has the subtitle “professional stunt driver, do not attempt” tickles
him to no end. And he sits innocently mystified by the erectile dysfunc-
tion commercials during football games that conclude with hastily read
warnings about what to do if your erection lasts three or more days. Now,
if ever a fool had it coming. And damn, if that is not an unintended pun.
41. Compare the deceit that is so artful that the deceiver apparently wants credit
for the excellence of his show as a show, and may blow his own cover to get the proper
recognition of his art. La Rochefoucauld suggests that here, too, it would be bad form not
to fall victim: “some disguised deceits counterfeit truth so perfectly that not to be taken in
thereby would be an error in judgment”; Maxim No. 282.
Deceit in War and Trade 67
Mark A. Wrathall
67
68 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
1. Page citations from Sein und Zeit refer to the “H” numbers, which are based on the
pagination of the original German edition (Verlag Max Niemeyer, 1927), and which can be
found in the margins of both English language translations of Being and Time, as well as in
the margins of the Gesamtausgabe edition of Sein und Zeit (Klostermann, 1977).
2. Thus, as Komarine Romdenh-Romluc points out, even when addressing cases
of hallucination, Merleau-Ponty draws on “actual cases of hallucinatory experience” as
described in the clinical literature. See “Merleau-Ponty’s Account of Hallucination,”
European Journal of Philosophy (forthcoming).
On the “Existential Positivity of Our Ability to Be Deceived” 69
3. It is not at all clear how this move can accommodate the many, perhaps prevalent,
cases in which I perceive something slightly wrongly. I buy a green tie to go with my green
suit, for example, only to find when I get home that the tie was in fact brown. What did I
see in the department store? I saw a tie—there can be no denying that much. But it seems
wrong to say that I saw a green tie, given that the tie was brown. And yet, if I had seen a
brown tie, I wouldn’t have bought it.
4. Resisting this temptation would not necessarily require one to deny that there is
some determinate, objective fact of the matter about the makeup of the physical universe.
But it would require one to acknowledge a possible distinction between the physical
universe—what Merleau-Ponty sometimes refers to as the “world in itself” (see, e.g., PP 10
and 39) and the perceptual world.
70 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
all the difficulties arise from the fact that objective thought, the reduction
of things as experienced to objects, of subjectivity to the cogitatio, leaves no
room for the equivocal adherence of the subject to preobjective phenom-
ena. The consequence is therefore clear. We must stop constructing halluci-
nation, or indeed consciousness generally, according to a certain essence or
idea of itself which compels us to define it in terms of some sort of absolute
adequation. ([PP] 336)
5. I should note that in these passages, Heidegger’s ultimate goal is to understand how
it is possible to say something that is deceptive, rather than something that is simply false.
A false assertion need not be deceptive if it couldn’t possibly induce you to believe it.
So Heidegger tackles the problem of the lie by first asking how it is that we can perceive
erroneously, since it is such a perception that ultimately makes the lie believable. I note
this only because Heidegger introduces language into the discussion at certain points, and
I’m going to completely ignore those for my purposes. I don’t think that by systematically
ignoring that side of Heidegger’s analysis I’m doing any violence to his account of
deceptive perceptual experiences.
On the “Existential Positivity of Our Ability to Be Deceived” 73
7. Heidegger thinks that we need to understand this to grasp the Greek notion of
the pseudos, the false. “This is the fundamental meaning of the Greek pseudos: to so twist
something that one does not see how it genuinely is. Pseudos is that which distorts and
twists” (GA 36/37:227).
On the “Existential Positivity of Our Ability to Be Deceived” 75
which the author hides, an alias that covers him up” (GA 36/37:227). It’s
not false in the sense that there is nobody who answers to it. To the con-
trary, the pseudonym directs one to the author of the book, but does it in
such a way that “one does not see how he or she genuinely is.” Likewise, in
a perceptual error, we do see something (it is not a hallucination). But we
see it in such a way that it doesn’t show itself as it genuinely is. “Pseudos is
a showing that passes something off as something; thus it is more than a
mere covering up without passing it off as other than it is” (GA 17:32).
The discussion of the structural conditions of perception, moreover,
lets us recognize that the possibility of perceptual deception is built into
the very structure of our world. It is a “basic fact, in the sphere of dealing
with the world,” Heidegger insists, that error and deception “are inter-
woven in a completely fundamental way, and do not merely occur as
defective properties that one must overcome” (GA 17:39). Heidegger
thus offers a more equitable division of labor, attributing the blame for
the deception to the world and to the things in the world as much as to
our way of comporting ourselves in the world. It could be the case, of
course, that we are primarily responsible for the error, insofar as we might
respond wrongly to the solicitation. We might, for instance, lack the skills
to respond appropriately to what the situation calls on us to do. It might
be that I would be more susceptible to being deceived by the bush than a
deer hunter would—he probably has much better skills for distinguishing
deer from other things that might suggest a deer. At least, given that he
goes looking for deer with a loaded gun, I hope he has better skills. But,
even in this case, my deception is motivated to a considerable degree by
the skills I have and use effectively in coping with this sort of context.
As Heidegger puts it in the 1923–1924 lecture course, “the possibility
of deception lies . . . in an erroneous seeing, which is not motivated by
a careless consideration, but rather in the manner in which the existing
[human] being lives and encounters the world itself” (GA 17:36).
Thus we are not solely responsible for being deceived. It is also the case
that, at least sometimes, things in the world conspire to lead us to per-
ceive them wrongly: “there are entities that in their specific being have the
characteristic that they pass themselves of as something that they are not,
or as so characterized as they are not—where the possibility of deception
thus does not lie primarily in a wrong way of taking them up, but rather
in the entity itself ” (GA 17:32). He goes on to explain:
the things can elude us, and that is not to say they disappear. The elusiveness
of things comes to life by virtue of the fact that we encounter them circum-
stantially. We do not see a thing as . . . an object of scientific investigation.
This existence of things is much richer and offers much more fluctuating
possibilities than are thematically prepared. Because the world in its rich-
ness is only there in the particular concreteness of living, the elusiveness
is also much more encompassing and, with it, the possibility of deception is
there. The more concretely I am in the world, the more genuine is the exis-
tence of deception. (GA 17:37)
76 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
I think that Heidegger is pointing here to the way real entities and
contexts necessarily orient us toward more than can possibly be present
to us at any given moment. Merleau-Ponty makes a similar point in noting
that vision is “an operation which fulfills more than it promises” (PP 377).
For instance, when I see the facade of a house, I am oriented already to
the back and sides of the house. My vision of the front “promises” an
experience of the other sides. But the experience of seeing the other sides
is always much richer than what the promise prepared me for. So, like
Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty sees in the present experience an orientation
toward much more than can be presently experienced. Thus, perception
throws me open to a world, but can do so only by outrunning both me
and itself. Thus the perceptual “synthesis” has to be incomplete; it cannot
present me with a “reality” otherwise than by running the risk of error. It is
absolutely necessarily the case that the thing, if it is to be a thing, should
have sides of itself hidden from me. (PP 377)
We are thus always both open to the world and lacking certainty about it.
The lack of certainty is not a negative but a positive—it is that in virtue
of which we can understand and intend more than is present to us at any
given moment.
RESISTING TEMPTATION
Figure 4.1.
cannot be shifted. It is this meaning inseparable from the figure, this trans-
formation of the phenomenon, which motivates the false judgment and
which is so to speak behind it. (PP 35)
Illusions and other such deceptions point up the fact that we first of
all encounter meaningful structures, and we encounter particular enti-
ties in terms of their meanings. Something is meaningful when it leads
one who grasps the meaning beyond what is presented. To say that per-
ception is meaningful through and through is to say that there is noth-
ing experienced in perception that is absolutely and fully given in the
present; everything we perceive directs us beyond itself, attunes us to
anticipate further experiences. A color leads us to anticipate a modula-
tion of color as lighting conditions change. A shape or form leads us to
anticipate further adumbrations of the form as it moves relative to us.
Thus, what everything is is experienced in perception in virtue of what
Merleau-Ponty calls “the mode of existence and coexistence of perceived
objects . . . the life which steals across the visual field and secretly binds
its parts together” (PP 35).
Given the inherently meaningful structure of perception, it follows that
there is no particular thing about which we might not be deceived. There
is no bedrock component of our experience about which we couldn’t get
it wrong, because everything has the meaning that it has only in virtue
of the structure of meanings that solicit us to further exploration.8 The
But this is not to say that anything goes. How are we to preserve the
distinction between deceptive and genuine perceptions, once we grant
that there are an indefinite number of different ways to perceive any given
perceptual field? We start from the notion of the inherent meaningfulness
of perception. This means that to perceive is to be drawn into or pointed
toward paths of further perceptual exploration and action. The distinc-
tion between genuine and deceptive perceptions is found in the degree to
which they lead us well, in the sense that they allow us to keep our grip
on the world around us. As Merleau-Ponty puts it,
my perception brings into coexistence an indefinite number of perceptual
chains which, if followed up, would confirm it in all respects and accord
with it. My eyes and my hand know that any actual change of place would
80 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
But now the fact that we can be deceived in perception, and yet nev-
ertheless correct our being deceived through further perception, shows
something important about the relationship in which we stand to our
perceptual experiences—namely, that “the percept is and remains, despite
all critical education, on the hither side of doubt and demonstration”
(PP 344). It’s important to attend to the nuances of this claim: Merleau-
Ponty is not claiming that I’m always correct about what I perceive.
Rather, that in the act of perceiving, my perception is not in the game of
being true or false. I can’t be mistaken in my perception in the sense that
what I perceive is false. But my perception is nevertheless correctible in
the sense that a prior perception can be “cancelled” or “crossed out”—we
come to recognize that the way we were seeing the world was not opti-
mal, given the practical aims implicit in our mode of engagement with the
world. “I say that I perceive correctly when my body has a precise hold on
the spectacle, but that does not mean that my hold is ever all-embracing”
(PP 297)—that is, for any given perceptual hold on the world, we could
recognize that other holds are possible, that this way of getting to grips
with the world has not come to terms with everything in the world, that
other ways of engaging the world might be more or less successful, or
guided by different concerns.
This view of perception will seem paradoxical as long as we think of
the success conditions of perception in the same way we think of the
success conditions of belief. But the paradox dissolves when we see per-
ception instead in terms of action, practical engagement with the world.
If I am pouring water into a glass, we don’t say that my way of gripping
the pitcher and holding the glass is “false.” It might be a mistaken way of
On the “Existential Positivity of Our Ability to Be Deceived” 81
pouring the water in the sense that it will lead me to spill the water. And
there are undoubtedly better and worse ways of holding the pitcher and
the glass. But success here is not a matter of our grip conforming to an
ideal grip—it’s a matter of the action unfolding itself in such a way that it
allows me to achieve my goals in the world.
And this, in turn, suggests that it is wrong to think of perception in
terms of the possession of propositional contents. To see that there is a
stone on the path is not necessarily to have a particular attitude toward
the propositional content: there is a stone on the path. “I see the illu-
sory stone,” Merleau-Ponty argues instead, “in the sense that my whole
perceptual and motor field endows the bright spot with the significance
‘stone on the path’. And already I ready myself to feel under my foot this
smooth, firm surface” (PP 297, translation modified). I am, correspond-
ingly, deceived in seeing the stone if, for example, the resulting bodily
attitude causes me to stumble, or to change directions into a less optimal
path.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
A number of people have posed challenging questions and offered helpful com-
ments in response to earlier drafts of this chapter. I am particularly indebted
and grateful to Bert Dreyfus, Charles Siewert, Wayne Martin, Sean Kelly, Taylor
Carman, Iain Thomson, Bill Blattner, and Stefan Käufer for the fascinating discus-
sions this article occasioned.
82 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
David Sherman
A good deal of progress has recently been made toward resolving some
of the more troubling of the so-called paradoxes of self-deception. Two
interrelated paradigmatic shifts, in particular, are worth mentioning in
this regard. As an initial matter, the paradox that self-deception requires
one simultaneously to believe and not believe the truth about which
one is self-deceived is in the process of unraveling, for the assump-
tion on which it is based, that (intrapersonal) self-deception should
be understood on the model of (interpersonal) deception, is increas-
ingly being called into question. Arguments against this terminologi-
cally driven view, characteristically referred to as “the lexical approach,”
have rightly rejected the notion that there is something inherent in the
phenomenon of self-deception that requires the self-deceived person
simultaneously to believe and not believe the truth, 1 even if the (rather
misleading) term “self-deception” itself seems to presuppose this duali-
ty.2 Moreover, and, perhaps, more fundamentally, given that it seems
to be presupposed by the lexical approach, the paradox that self-de-
ception undercuts itself by virtue of the very condition of its possibil-
ity (i.e., how can I deceive myself if I deliberately set myself to the
task of doing so) is in the process of unraveling, for the assumption on
which it is based, that self-deception should be understood as an inten-
tional activity, is also increasingly being called into question. Arguments
against “the intentionalist approach” have adopted the notion that self-
deception should be understood as “motivated irrational belief,” and that
82
Self-Deception, Deception, and the Way of the World 83
the motivating desires that skew the process of belief formation can go
all the way down.3
Despite this progress, problems remain. The social component of self-
deception, in particular, has been badly neglected, as much of the
literature on self-deception implicitly bears the mark of a monadic pre-
dilection, and this neglect has resulted in a failure to fully appreciate
the nature of the phenomenon. Many of our most basic beliefs, the ones
that fundamentally orient us toward the world, are socially constructed
and supported, and these basic beliefs are what often motivate “moti-
vated irrational belief.” Even Leibniz’s “windowless” (rational) monads,
which might be understood to form irrational beliefs on the basis of first-
order motivations caused by the internal interplay between (dynami-
cal) appetition and their distinctive underlying states (“perceptions”), are
ultimately “mirrors of the universe,” and all of their actions unswervingly
reflect the second-order motivation that is God’s “preestablished har-
mony.” Unhappily, this metaphysical account might not be the worst one
for making sense of self-deception in contemporary society. One need
not probe particularly deeply to come to the conclusion that beneath a
nominal individualism, which would understand all of our belief-skew-
ing motivations as internally generated, there is an all but ubiquitous
social totality that externally constructs these belief-skewing motivations
and passes them off as the individual’s own: second-order motivations
thus come off as first-order ones, and discerning what, if anything, truly
remains of the latter becomes exceedingly problematical. As a result, we
might be inclined to careen from pillar to post, from an unremittingly
individualistic account of self-deception to an unremittingly social con-
structivist one, but this inclination, too, should be resisted. Viewing “the
self,” with its desires and beliefs, as nothing more than a fiction produced
by overarching relations of discourse or power, which is how the social
constructivist views matters, makes no more sense of the phenomenon
of self-deception than individualistic approaches do. Depending on the
social constructivist, either self-deception is understood wholly in terms
of the larger society, regardless of that society’s own internal coher-
ence, or it is understood as an all-pervading phenomenon, given that the
3. It is with this last turn of the screw that Ariela Lazar distinguishes her view from
Mele’s in “Deceiving Oneself or Self-Deceived? On the Formation of Beliefs ‘under
the Influence,’ ” Mind 108 (April 1999), 265–90. Two points must be made here. First,
although Lazar does not entirely rule out the applicability of the intentionalist approach in
all cases of self-deception, which I take to be a mistake (if we understand “intentionalist”
in as robust a sense as she does), she is right to contend that if the intentionalist approach
does not apply “the requirement that the process of self-deception originates in the
subject’s holding the rational belief becomes obsolete” (270 n. 10). Second, in seizing on
the notion of “motivated irrational belief,” Lazar draws on the work of David Pears, one
of the first to make this distinction, but she goes beyond Pears (and Mele) by largely (if
not entirely) rejecting the intentionalist approach, which is not necessarily inconsistent
with the notion of “motivated irrational belief” (268 n. 7). See David Pears, Motivated
Irrationality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984).
84 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
societal conventions that overrun “the self” are also intelligibility’s very
condition of possibility.
The individualist and social constructivist models of self-deception
each manifest a one-sided view of self-deception, and, to better under-
stand the phenomenon, it is necessary to view it as a dialectical product
of both viewpoints, which are its constituting poles. To pose the question
of self-deception as an “either/or”—that is to say, in either individual-
istic or socially constructed terms—is to falsify it from the very begin-
ning. Indeed, to pose the question in this way is to lose the phenomenon
itself: on the individualistic approach, self-deception becomes impossible,
and, on the socially constructed approach, it becomes either relativistic
or ubiquitous.4 (To oscillate between individualistic and social ways of
viewing oneself and the world, conversely, is a rather common strategy of
self-deception.) Yet self-deception, in its complex and multifarious forms,
which are more or less egregious, persists, and it persists in ways that are
readily identified by what Husserl would call “the natural attitude.”
Although, ultimately, neither the individual nor social poles is to be
privileged in making sense of self-deception, I shall begin by considering
its sociohistorical component. This is because the sociohistorical context
establishes the motivations for our behaviors, if not, in some less than uni-
versal sense, what is to count as truth itself. Nietzsche’s claim that “there
are no facts, only interpretations” is wrong if interpreted literally (which
is by no means the default position that one should take when interpret-
ing Nietzsche), but the element of truth in this claim, and what, at a
minimum, he plainly did believe, is that “the facts” are much thinner than
they are generally taken to be. Now, crucially, the types of truths that are
involved in self-deception are themselves nowhere near this thin, as they
go well beyond bare truths of the “it is snowing iff it is snowing” variety:
everything else being equal, to deny that it is snowing while one stands
4. Although Foucault does not speak in these terms, a relativistic account of self-
deception is implicit in his work, which I briefly consider later. Conversely, an account
of self-deception that would see the phenomenon as ubiquitous is implicit in Derrida’s
work. Thus, according to Derrida, Saussure rightly saw that words (written and spoken)
are arbitrary signs (“horse” might have just as well been used as “elephant” to signify
an elephant), and that signs get their meaning by virtue of their relation to other signs
in a “signifying chain,” but he continued to believe that the sign was comprised by not
only a signifier but also a signified, which means that Saussure’s sign still presupposes
some referent outside of language’s “signifying chain.” Derrida then purportedly brings
Saussure’s insight to fruition by claiming that the signified to which signifiers refer should
be lopped off, essentially suggesting that there is nothing to which language truly refers,
although the fiction of a referent is a necessary condition of intelligibility. As a result,
Derrida claims, all writing (not to mention speech, which, unlike writing, operated under
the illusion that its referent could actually be presenced) must be put “under erasure.”
What this suggests is that all writing (speech) is a deception of sorts, and thus all who
engage in writing (speech)—with the possible exception of the Derridean, who knows
that it’s all “under erasure”—engage in self-deception. All such cases of self-deception
are equally egregious, as the ineluctable presupposition of a nonexistent referent is not
amenable to any further gradations.
Self-Deception, Deception, and the Way of the World 85
sorts, but not in the way Kant thinks: it is an objective intention to the
extent that it is the expression of the laws of a particular sociohistorical
context acting through the heteronomous individual, not the expression
of an autonomous individual who transcends the particular sociohistorical
context by acting on the categorical imperative so as to legislate universal
law. This is a particularly virulent form of self-deception because, like the
Christian notion of the soul, it enables certain of its practitioners to believe
that they are above the possibility of self-deception, and, moreover, that
they have a lock on “the Truth,” which, as Nietzsche would later argue,
is the most virulent form of self-deception. As Kant himself made abun-
dantly clear, his aim was to make good the moral and spiritual imperatives
of a Christian other-worldliness on the basis of pure reason, and, conse-
quently, it was not especially unfair of Nietzsche to claim that Kant only
sought to make good “popular prejudice,” that “Kant’s joke” was “to prove
in a way that would dumbfound the common man, that the common man
was right.”7 Kant’s own bit of self-deception, indeed, might well lie in his
belief that by absolutizing the universal moment that is necessary for any
genuinely moral comportment to make good his heteronomously deter-
mined Christian commitments, he was actually offering something more.
His deception, wittingly or not, was that those who act under the rubric
of an utterly autonomous individuality validate themselves rather than
that which stands over and against them, and that they do this so as to
overcome the sort of self-deceptiveness that Kant calls our “self-incurred
tutelage,” which this approach actually tends to perpetuate.
It was Hegel’s aim to bring Kant’s Copernican revolution to fruition,
and he seized on both the necessity of apriori conceptuality and the self-
reflexivity of a unifying self-consciousness as the conditions of possibility
for any experience, but he argued, in essence, that these transcendental
conditions must be understood in social terms. 8 Although, in some sense,
Hegel ultimately seeks to make good “the individual,” or at least reconcile
the individual to the social institutions of its world, he twists the individu-
al’s self-understanding away from Kant’s individualistic account. In place
of Kant’s categories and the transcendental unity of apperception, Hegel
offers “forms of consciousness” and “Spirit,” which refer, respectively, to
the socioculturally generated categories out of which a particular society
makes sense of its world (the Zeitgeist or “spirit of the times”) and to a
collective subject (a particular society or, more universally, all of human-
ity). The basic point is that whatever the contours of the society, the col-
lective is, epistemologically, prior to the individual, and the sociocultural
categories out of which a society makes sense of its world are, at a mini-
mum, the starting point for the individuals who constitute it.
7. Friedrich Nietzsche, The Gay Science, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Random
House, 1974), 205–6 (sec. 193).
8. See, e.g., Robert B. Pippin, Hegel’s Idealism: The Satisfactions of Self-Consciousness
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989).
88 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
assumptions are not necessarily a bad thing. Human beings quite clearly
act in ways that evidence more or less persistent tendencies to strive for
particular ends, whether in terms of closed systems, such as markets, or,
indeed, in terms of the reproduction of life itself. Moreover, while Hegel
purportedly claims to speak from “the end of history” in the Phenomenol-
ogy of Spirit and, even worse, from a form of consciousness that he pro-
vocatively calls “Absolute Knowing,” I take his point to be a modest one. 9
What it means to achieve philosophical truth, or the truth about truth, is
to achieve the recognition that we constitute the world of our experience
by way of an apriori (socioculturally engendered) conceptuality, which
delineates the nature of the kinds of empirical truths we can achieve.
If we bear in mind that Hegel is speaking of second-order (instead of first-
order) belief formation, this achievement, no mean feat in itself, is not
inconsistent with Bernard Williams’s far more modest-sounding claim
that “the project of seriously pursuing the truth is one of controlling the
formation of belief.”10 In any case, Hegel’s construal of history in universal-
istic terms, which is based on the notion that the kernel of reason inherent
within our belief structures gears them toward “the truth,” sharply distin-
guishes his form of consciousness from Foucault’s relativistic episteme or
“regime of truth.”
For Hegel, this pursuit of truth does not stem from an idle philosophi-
cal commitment but, rather, from our deepest personal commitments (or,
as he puts it in the introduction to the Philosophy of History, from our pas-
sions), which themselves are but a manifestation of “the cunning of rea-
son” and, ultimately, truth working itself out in history. Hegel’s confidence
in the Phenomenology, purportedly made good from his “end of history”
perspective, is that collective belief reformation had, in fact, moved along
the right path: our knowledge, motored by a reason inherently geared
toward truth, and our interests, motored by our passions, had coincided.
Yet Hegel’s confidence, as exemplified by his own standpoint at the end
of the Phenomenology, was evidently less than warranted, as his own privi-
leging of the Prussian state less than twenty years later in the Philosophy
of Right amply attests. To clarify the problem here and what it means for
truth: it would be a mistake to categorically reject Hegel’s teleological
account, either launching forward into a social constructivism that would
see itself as bringing to fruition Hegel’s attempt to bring Kant’s revolu-
tion to fruition or falling back into a bare bones positivism that would see
truth as restricted to claims of the “it is snowing iff it is snowing” variety.
These two moves do violence to truth, and, while the underlying mechan-
ics are different, they do so in much the same way: in essence, the social
11. Bernard Williams, Truth and Truthfulness (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
2002), 133.
12. This is the fundamental point of Williams’s “Deciding to Believe,” in Problems of the
Self (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1973).
Self-Deception, Deception, and the Way of the World 91
13. Thus, the form of consciousness that immediately supplants the master-slave
relationship is stoicism, and when Hegel declares that “whether on the throne or in
chains” the aim of this form of consciousness “is to be free,” he is tacitly suggesting that the
differences between Marcus Aurelius and Epictetus (and the social classes of which they
are a part) are only a secondary matter, which is way too reductive in terms of capturing
the sociohistorical truth of the matter. See G. W. F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans.
A. V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977), 121.
14. In the opening paragraph of “Deciding to Believe,” Williams says that his claim that
we do not decide to believe goes only so far as “straightforward factual belief,” and that he
is explicitly not dealing with “religious and moral beliefs, belief in the sense of conviction
of an ideological or practical character.” Problems of the Self, 136 (emphasis added). I will be
touching on ideology momentarily, but what I am suggesting here is that the sorts of
beliefs Williams is exempting from his discussion are those that make up second-order
beliefs and, therefore, can be intentionally chosen.
92 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
against one’s genuine interests, but, instead, see it as part of an organic and
relational whole that is embodied in our social institutions. 15 For the most
part, however, by altogether rejecting the second sense of ideology, these
philosophers have, in effect, rejected the notion that there is anything
left of truth with respect to the first sense of the term, thus normalizing
the partisan nature of second-order belief (re)formation. Put somewhat
differently, the space for the second, more pejorative, sense of ideology
disappears only if there is no basis for judging ideology in the first sense
to be more or less true, and this effectively does away with the standpoint
that might critique the prevailing ideology, which is in accordance with
the tastes of social constructivism. Ideology, in the first sense, might well
be inevitable, but this does not mean that particular ideologies are all
equally true, which is effectively the case when truth itself disappears, and
this view, in itself, is not just in the service of ideology (in the second sense
of the term) but is also a manifestation of it.
What space, then, is left for truth with respect to second-order belief
(re)formation, particularly given the fact that this order of belief is geared
toward interests rather than truth? Positivism, as was indicated earlier, is
certainly not the answer, for its account of truth is too deflationary and
tends to recapitulate the sociohistorical status quo. Conversely, hard tele-
ological accounts such as Hegel’s (and I am thinking here of the Philoso-
phy of Right more than the Phenomenology of Spirit) are too inflationary, for
they are instilled with both an unwarranted necessity and an unwarranted
universality. What’s more, like positivism, they tend to recapitulate the
status quo, although from the other extreme, by making their sociohis-
torical standpoint into the culmination of truth. A middle position, one
that was staked out by Adorno, is to hang on to a teleological account but
to hang on to it in a highly qualified way. When Adorno says that “univer-
sal history must be construed and denied,” for example, he is implicitly
rejecting both the hard teleological account and social constructivism by
advocating, as J. M. Bernstein puts it, “teleology without a telos.”16 The
“truth” toward which history aims on this account is the overcoming of
deception, and, therefore, what truth means at any particular time would
be the overcoming of the deceptive sociohistorically conditioned (second-
order) beliefs of that particular time. This entails far more than can pos-
sibly be broached here, but for present purposes two things, in particular,
are worth noting. First, by “construing” universal history, a critical, truth-
oriented basis for analyzing the present state of affairs (and, therefore, our
second-order, sociohistorically conditioned beliefs) is retained, as we have
an expansive enough framework for making sense of the ways our exist-
ing form of consciousness (or second-order beliefs) falls short. (In other
15. See, e.g., Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe, Hegemony and Socialist Strategy:
Towards a Radical Democratic Politics (London: Verso Books, 1985).
16. J. M. Bernstein, Adorno: Disenchantment and Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2001), 336.
94 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
17. Allen Wood, “Ideology, False Consciousness, and Social Illusion,” in Perspectives on
Self-Deception, ed. Brian P. McLaughlin and Amelie Oksenberg Rorty (Berkeley: University
of California Press, 1988), 360.
18. The aim of manipulating the media is ultimately to manipulate what I have
been calling our second-order beliefs. And although all American administrations
try to manipulate the media, it may well be that the Bush administration's heavy-
handedness in this regard was unparalleled in American history. This project became more
auspicious with the horrors of September 11, 2001, when a new form of consciousness
was engendered, one overwhelmingly disposed to believe the Bush administration’s
propaganda, which, in large part, was designed to reinforce this disposition. Americans
have never had a particularly strong historical sense (which serves the goals of ideology
Self-Deception, Deception, and the Way of the World 95
in the pejorative sense and effectively makes good social constructivism), but historical
amnesia, coupled with a committed distractedness, became the order of the day as
activities associated with such names as the Patriot Act, Abu Ghraib, and Guantanamo
Bay, which are antithetical to basic American principles, were met with relative
equanimity. Recognizing that the bare facts, even ones that were not incompatible with
the ideological justifications for its greatly expanded power, might tend to undermine
it, the Bush administration kept tight control on a host of images. And, in the end, the
hard facts, as evinced by such images, did undermine the Bush administration’s veneer
of competence. Social critics have argued that Hurricane Katrina (rather than the
Iraq War) was what precipitated this administration’s downward political spiral (and
emboldened an obsequious media), as there was no effective way for the administration
to spin its complicity in this disaster in the face of well-documented facts, which included
unambiguous images contradicting their claims.
96 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
19. Jean-Paul Sartre, Being and Nothingness, trans. Hazel Barnes (New York:
Washington Square Press, 1956), 89.
Self-Deception, Deception, and the Way of the World 97
this formulation is that the duality that exists between the deceiver and
the one who is deceived transpires within a single consciousness. This, of
course, is standard fare, a classical statement of the problem that defines
the lexical approach, but it is not one that Sartre sticks with for very long.
After he rules out the Freudian unconscious as a satisfactory explanation
of this phenomenon, given that it only pushes the duality problem back
a step (because there must then be some censor between consciousness
and unconsciousness that both believes and does not believe x), Sartre
formulates the problem of bad faith anew. Bad faith, he says, is grounded
in “the double property of the human being, who is at once a facticity and
a transcendence,” and derives from a failure to either “coordinate” or “syn-
thesize” these two properties of the human being. 20 According to Wood,
both of these formulations are troubling, and he asks: “Does Sartre really
expect us to believe that every case of self-deception involves attributing a
contradictory concept to something? And does he think that all contradic-
tory concepts derive from the facticity-transcendence relation? Neither
claim has much plausibility, and neither receives any real defense from
Sartre.”21 Wood’s questions, which are partially motivated by his view that
Sartre wrongly rejects the Freudian unconscious, go to the heart of Sartre’s
account of self-deception, and they must be adequately addressed.
As an initial matter, the best way to address these questions is to turn
them around, for I take the dynamics of the facticity-transcendence rela-
tion to be primary, and once this relation is clarified, the “contradictory
concept” problem, which I have already suggested is a misguided formu-
lation of self-deception, can be clarified. To begin, then, for Sartre, the
facticity-transcendence relation points to the fact that there are brute
facts about all human beings (including our bodies, our pasts, our envi-
ronments, and, crucially, the collective practices of the sociohistorically
informed contexts in which we live) but that we are always also “beyond”
or “transcend” these facts to the limited extent that we are free to inter-
pret them as we choose. Structurally, this relation is not unlike the rela-
tion I discussed earlier in the context of truth: there are facts of the matter
that our ability to interpret will not change, and, indeed, better and worse
interpretations depend on our relative faithfulness toward these bare facts,
while what these facts mean, and more substantial questions concerning
what is to count as truth, are chiefly interpretive in nature. (It should be
emphasized here that although many critics take Sartre to be offering a
hyperbolic notion of freedom, part of what constitutes facticity for him
incorporates the limiting sociohistorical truths of one’s world.) According
to Sartre, bad faith arises from overemphasizing one of these properties at
the expense of the other (usually, although by no means exclusively, factic-
ity at the expense of freedom), and he offers various examples to illustrate
the two ways we can fall off the wagon. 22 Now, although Sartre gestures
in the direction of good faith, initially suggesting that it would involve
either coordinating or synthesizing these two properties, and then sug-
gesting that, contrary to bad faith (“not believing what one believes”), the
ideal of good faith is to actually “believe what one believes” and, thereby,
find “refuge in being,”23 the fact is that good faith is off limits on Sartre’s
account. To validly coordinate or synthesize facticity and transcendence
presupposes that they are functionally discrete, but, in fact, they are dia-
lectically intertwined, as transcendent freedom only exists in a factical
situation and a factical situation only arises from transcendent freedom.
Put simply, there is no (transcendent) Archimedean point from which to
coordinate or synthesize these properties, a fact that will become clearer
when considering the sociohistorical component of the factical self.
This lack of an Archimedean point, the existential unavoidability of
bad faith, and the ultimately sociohistorical nature of bad faith converge
in the context of what Sartre calls “the fundamental project.” According
to Sartre, a person’s possibilities arise within the framework of a hierar-
chy of projects and behaviors, and these projects and behaviors testify,
in turn, to the existence of a more basic project, “the initial project,”
which reflects one’s choice of oneself in the world. The content of this
self-constituting choice of oneself obviously varies from one person to
another, but the existence of the initial project itself testifies to the exis-
tence of an even more basic project, “the fundamental project,” a univer-
sal project Sartre describes as the project of being God. For Sartre, this
project is not religious but, instead, existential, essentially indicating that
human beings strive to be absolutely self-identical and yet absolutely
free. Without getting bogged down in Sartre’s terminology or in the sec-
ondary literature that this idea has generated, I take Sartre’s point to be
crucial: although the project of being God (absolutizing our facticity and
our transcendence) is itself a project in bad faith, the (empirical) pursuit
of this project by way of the initial project is, existentially, unavoidable,
as we must maintain a dialectical tension between these connected but
conflicting sides of our nature. Indeed, this is Sartre’s point when he
asserts that “freedom, which manifests itself through anguish, is charac-
terized by a constantly renewed obligation to remake the Self which des-
ignates my free being . . . [and that] this self with its a priori and historical
22. It has been pointed out that the examples are flawed in a number of ways, one of
which is that Sartre’s phenomenological descriptions are necessarily limited to his own
point of view, and that he has no basis for saying whether these people are in bad faith, as
he does not have a clue about what might actually be motivating them. I think that this is
right, and, indeed, I think that this points to the fact that attributing bad faith to another is
no simple matter, but I also think that it does not bear on the basics of his analysis of bad
faith as such. See, for example, Kathleen Marie Higgins, “Bad Faith and Kitsch as Models
for Self-Deception,” in Self and Deception: A Cross-cultural Philosophical Enquiry, ed. Roger
T. Ames and Wimal Dissanayake (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1996).
23. Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 115.
Self-Deception, Deception, and the Way of the World 99
content is the essence of man.”24 For Sartre, then, the content of our
initial project or choice of ourselves is the content of our sociohistorical
context, and, by constituting the self, this choice gives rise, in one fell
swoop, to both the possibility of a situation and to the particular situa-
tion, whose meaning derives from the content of the choice.
If bad faith goes all the way down, it is because our world-constituting
initial choice of ourselves goes all the way down, for by virtue of this
ineluctable choice we are always already oriented to the world in a highly
particularized way. This distinguishes bad faith from self-deception, and,
in fact, makes clear that bad faith is logically prior to self-deception. Thus,
according to Robert Solomon, “bad faith is not just self-deception because
it is not primarily about belief. Of course, beliefs often follow, but bad
faith is about the very nature of our engagements in the world, and then,
perhaps, we form beliefs about our engagements in the world.” This is
basically right, but for my purposes here it can be profitably reformu-
lated. Bad faith is about belief (as all faith is), if by belief what is meant is
second-order belief, and what I would like to suggest here is that Sartre’s
account of bad faith mediates sociohistorical categoriality (i.e., the pre-
vailing “form of consciousness,” to use Hegel’s phrase) and the individual.
This accounts for the obvious fact that our self-identities often substan-
tially differ even if we are born into the same sociohistorical context, and,
indeed, into similar conditions within it: every person appropriates his
or her world in a particular way, but the content of our social world is
still, ultimately, the content of our selves (and, as discussed, this certainly
seems to be Sartre’s position). Understood in this way, our social cat-
egories might be viewed as third-order beliefs, and second-order beliefs,
which are basically constitutive of the self, are an amalgam of third-order
beliefs and the individual’s particular experiences. As a result, the greater
the ability of a particular subset of social interests to shape and control
these now third-order beliefs, the more individual experiences will be
schematized in accordance with them, and the more our self-identities
will appear to be epiphenomenal with respect to the social totality. This is
the kernel of truth in social constructivism, which functions ideologically
(in the pejorative sense of the term) by making a philosophical apriori of
a sociohistorical tendency that seems to be coming to fruition in these
postmodern times.
When Sartre’s account of bad faith is properly augmented by his
account of the self-constituting initial project, the claim that bad faith
inexorably arises from the relation between transcendence and facticity,
and, moreover, that bad faith is self-deception’s condition of possibility,
becomes more compelling. Still, this does not yet directly address Wood’s
questions, whether every case of self-deception involves the attribution
of a contradictory concept and whether all contradictory concepts arise
from the facticity-transcendence relation, although it does provide the
grounds for doing so. Even if Sartre is less than clear on this himself, his
account of bad faith suggests that self-deception need not and should
not be understood as a variation on the model of interpersonal decep-
tion, which is what produces the “contradictory concept” problem, the
paradox of believing and not believing the very same thing. And, once
the interpersonal model goes by the boards, it becomes clear not only
that contradictory concepts do not arise from the facticity-transcendence
relation but also that no case of self-deception involves the attribution of
a contradictory concept.
Although the bulk of the chapter on bad faith in Being and Nothing-
ness deals with bad faith as an existential phenomenon, in the final four
pages of the chapter, Sartre turns to the epistemological questions that are
now commonly connected with the problem of self-deception. Sartre says
there that “to believe is not to believe,” which seems to raise the “contra-
dictory concept” problem, but this is not actually his point, as he goes on
to say that “every belief is a belief that falls short,” for “one never wholly
believes what one believes.”25 As Wood rightly contends, “to believe is not
to believe” is really meant to convey the fact that all beliefs are “imper-
fect,” and, at one level, he is right to explain this imperfection by point-
ing to the fact that “the human condition” is marked by “complexities,
ambiguities, uncertainties, and tensions” that “often hit us right where
we live.”26 At a deeper level, however, I take Sartre to be saying, more
radically, that because our beliefs are bound up with our self-constituting
initial projects, which are entirely ungrounded, and therefore, in Sartre’s
words, “metastable” (i.e., internally unstable and thus subject to fluctua-
tion), then our beliefs are, in essence, only as good as we are. It should be
noticed that this is not unlike what I have begun to call our third-order
beliefs, our social categoriality or form of consciousness, with which our
individual second-order beliefs stand in a dialectical relation: a person’s
overall belief structure depends on the internal coherence of his or her
“truth-makers,” both at the second and third levels, and, in both cases, part
of what makes his or her belief structures more rather than less coherent,
and thus more rather than less stable, is their relative faithfulness to the
bare facts. When Sartre says that “to believe is not to believe,” therefore,
he is not saying that there are no bare facts of the matter (which is just
what his notion of facticity would reject), and, indeed, he is not merely
saying that the bare facts are never taken up by us as such, as they are
always already bound up with our self-constituting initial projects. He
is saying, rather, that by virtue of being oriented to the world in a par-
ticular way (which is the result of the dynamical interplay between our
second- and third-order beliefs), we are always already inclined to see
the world in a particular way, and this “selective seeing” prereflectively
sifts though the variegated phenomena that perpetually confront us and
largely delineates the range of phenomena that can rise to the level of
facts for us. With respect to the “contradictory concept” problem, what
this means is that we do not actually believe and not believe the very
same thing, but, instead, that by virtue of the nature of self-consciousness,
we necessarily “spell out” some things at the expense of others,27 and what
we “spell out” is ultimately driven by our initial projects. Rather than
believe and not believe the very same thing, then, we “spell out” or make
explicit those aspects of the thing that conform to our self-understanding,
and we do not “spell out” or make explicit those aspects of the thing that
do not conform to our self-understanding. Thus, although all beliefs are
inherently “imperfect,” bad faith does not ultimately trade on this fact, as
Wood contends, but rather on the fact that we cannot be explicitly aware
of all the phenomena we experience from moment to moment: we do not
believe and not believe the very same thing, but we are more or less aware
of conflicting aspects of the very same thing, depending on the way these
aspects cut with respect to the self’s constitution. Understood in a quali-
fied way, therefore, Sartre, like Freud, trades on the notion of a “divided
mind,” even as he rejects the notion that Freud’s unconscious is needed to
account for a (relative) lack of awareness with respect to certain aspects
of a phenomenon.28
With his notion of the initial project, Sartre is also able to account for
the second (and, arguably, more fundamental) paradox of self-deception,
the problem of intentionalism (i.e., the problem of explaining how we can
“deliberately” deceive ourselves), and he does so in a way that transcends
the motivated irrationality approach. Even when it is claimed that moti-
vated irrationality can go all the way down, which obviates the need to
explain self-deception as an intentional activity, it is still usually claimed
that this occurs only when a person is in an aberrant state, as the irrational
belief is formed “under the influence” of his or her emotions and desires. 29
This aberrant state, in turn, tacitly presupposes a normal state, one in
which a person is not “under the influence,” and when in this state a per-
son is supposedly able to form rational beliefs because he or she is either
unmotivated or, more likely, motivated in a way that is undistorted by his
or her underlying interests. Yet, even this second alternative is much too
rationalistic, as it fails to account for the fact that even in one’s most dis-
passionate moods one is always already highly motivated due to the lim-
ited range of possible perspectives that are made available by one’s time
27. Herbert Fingarette makes this argument in Self-Deception (London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul, 1969).
28. Wood is thus right to say that “some sort of ‘divided mind’ explanation” is required
to account for the “selective inattention” that is part and parcel of Sartre’s account of self-
deception, but as this explanation suggests, it need not be one that depends on the positing
of “the unconscious.” See ibid., 223.
29. See, e.g., Ariela Lazar, “Deceiving Oneself or Self-Deceived? On the Formation of
Beliefs ‘Under the Influence.’”
102 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
Kelly Oliver
But an animal does not feign feigning ..... Speech begins only with
the passage from the feint to the order of the signifier, and that
the signifier requires another locus ..... For the Speech borne by the
signifier to be able to lie, that is, to posit itself as Truth.
—Jacques Lacan, Écrits (2006 )
Once psychoanalysis enters the scene, the distinction between truth and
deception becomes mired in the murky mess of the unconscious. Inso-
far as unconscious forces drive us beyond our control and even beyond
our knowledge, then we are all and always a bunch of liars. Our motives
remain opaque and beyond our grasp, and our words always say more
than we intend. Indeed, as Freud describes it, the human psyche revolves
around deception: unconscious desires and fears sneak into consciousness;
repression works to hide traumatic memories, while the repetition com-
pulsion tricks us into reliving those traumas in new forms; dreams disguise
the truth of the psyche through processes of condensation and displace-
ment to fool the ego’s censors; neuroses pass themselves off as physical
ailments; and the more we deny something in the course of analysis, the
more likely that it is true.
Lacan takes these Freudian insights further and insists that truth is
nothing more than the ability of speech to lie; in other words, speech
104
Duplicity Makes the Man 105
is nothing more than the process of making lies appear to be true. And
the capacity to make what is false appear as true is uniquely human.
While animals can pretend and can feign, according to Lacan, they cannot
make what is false appear true, which requires pretending to pretend or
feigning the feint. Conversely, for Lacan, the double deception of speech
constitute man as human. It is man’s duplicity, his double pretense, his
double-dealing, that folds the feint back onto itself, that makes man
unique among the animals.
What is this duplicity of speech that animals lack? And how can we
distinguish between pretending and pretending to pretend? What are the
implications of maintaining that only man can lie? In this essay, I take up
these questions in order to situate the role that animals play for Lacan,
and to signal the role they play for Western thought more generally. My
thesis is that Lacan uses animals to make his work appear scientific so
that he can more persuasively outline the dynamics of the human psyche.
In other words, animals appear in his work to add rhetorical force to his
descriptions of the distinctive qualities of man. We see logic familiar in
the history of philosophy whereby animals are used to shore up the bor-
ders of man; in other words, animals are called as witnesses to man’s supe-
riority.1 Within this logic, animals are more than the constitutive outside
of man. They also teach man how to be human; man is human by virtue
of animal pedagogy.
DOUBLE-DEALING ANIMALS
1. I have analyzed this logic in Rousseau, Herder, and Derrida in several articles.
See my “Animal Pedagogy: The Origin of ‘Man’ in Rousseau and Herder,” in Culture,
Theory and Critique 47, 2 (2006), 107–31; “Tropho-ethics: Derrida’s Homeopathic Purity,”
in Harvard Review (2007); and “Sexual Difference, Animal Difference: Derrida and
Difference ‘Worthy of Its Name,’ ” forthcoming. My forthcoming book Animal Pedagogy
will continue this line of thought by engaging the writings of Heidegger, Agamben, Merleau-
Ponty, Freud, and Kristeva.
106 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
Note that Lacan’s insistence that his position allows for a continuity
between animal and human psychology is formulated in the negative,
with words such as “digression,” “dispel,” “misunderstanding,” “disconti-
nuity,” and “foreign.” He does not assert a continuity but rather denies
a discontinuity, and not between animals and humans, but between one
type of psychology and another. Even his style might be read as signaling
an ambivalence about animals in relation to men. Indeed, whatever he
learns from his dog has less to do with his dog than with himself (given
that for Lacan, relations between human subjects always comes back to a
self-relation, this should be no surprise).
The tongue-in-cheek quality of the passage is signaled in the beginning
with his allusion to a little doggy-do, which perhaps reflects his opinion
of behaviorist observations. In the lecture, this passage follows a sugges-
tion that behaviorists who find the measure of man in the animal might
improve their studies by considering “trace behavior” in both. It seems that
behaviorists discover something about man by observing animal behavior,
but the continuities may not be what they think; instead they may lie in
what Lacan calls “trace behaviors” that cannot be observed using their
crude experimental techniques (which are not even on par with Lacan’s
observations while walking his dog). These trace behaviors are likely
linked to imaginary formations consistent in both animals and humans
that constituteperception as a sort of “residue of the real,” which behav-
iorists ignore (see Lacan 1988b, 257). As such, this passage may indicate
ambivalence about behaviorism as much as about animals. Indeed, at the
same time Lacan invokes their findings and cites other studies in biology,
ethnology, and zoology, he jeers at their methods. And while he endorses
studies that demonstrate the existence of the imaginary or the function
of the imago or image in animals, he discounts conclusions that implicate
what he calls the symbolic, which he reserves for man alone.
Consider another negatively worded passage noteworthy because in
this rare instance, Lacan conjures continuity between the symbolic in ani-
mals and in humans: “It can be seen that I do not shrink from seeking the
origins of symbolic behavior outside the human sphere” (2006, 225). This
remark is sandwiched between criticisms of logical positivist attempts to
Duplicity Makes the Man 107
I would have been curious to know whether subjects trained in this way
also react to the enunciation of the same term in the expressions ‘marriage
contract’, ‘contract bridge’, and ‘breach of contract’, and even when the
term is progressively shortened to the articulation of its first syllable alone:
contract, contrac, contra, contr For either the effects would no longer be
produced, thus revealing that they do not even conditionally depend on the
semanteme, or they would continue to be produced, raising the question
of the semanteme’s limits In other words, they would cause the distinc-
tion between the signifier and the signified, so blithely confounded by the
author in the English term “idea-symbol.” (2006, 226–27)
Lacan argues that words have meaning within symbolic systems by virtue
of their relationships rather than existing independently as idea-symbols.
This distinction between idea and symbol as sign again implicates the
animal.
Lacan insists that the logical positivists and behaviorists who reduce
language to nothing more than signs are mistaken. Looking for evidence,
as he says, like “bloodhounds on the scent,” he once more turns to “the
animal kingdom” to prove his point, and again with his typical irrever-
ent reverence for science: “I shall show the inadequacy of the conception
of language as signs by the very manifestation that best illustrates it in
the animal kingdom, a manifestation which, had it not recently been the
object of an authentic discovery, would have to have been invented for
this purpose” (2006, 245). Lacan gives the example of a certain bee’s
“wagging dance” that directs other bees to the location of food. Although
the bee employs a sign as a signal or even as a code, it is not language:
signs take on their value from their relations to each other in the lexical
distribution of semantemes as much as in the positional, or even flectional,
use of morphemes—in sharp contrast to the fixity of the coding used by the
bees. The diversity of human languages takes on its full value viewed in this
light. (2006 245–46)
Note that it is the fixed nature of bee codes that teaches us the full value
the diversity of human languages—although we might wonder if all bees
use the same codes and, given that there are significantly many more
types of insects than any other class of animal, it seems likely that there
are many times more insect codes than there are human ones. In any case,
the bees provide a pedagogical lesson for the psychoanalyst in terms of
human languages.
In addition to a system of signs defined by their relations to each other,
what the bee lacks, it seems, is imagination. Indeed, it may be a lack of imag-
ination that prevents them from relating their signs to each other rather
than to the location of dinner. But, as noted, Lacan has already granted
imagination to animals, so it must be more than the too direct connection
between the sign and the real that is the “bee” in Lacan’s bonnet. We get a
sense of what this is when we return to the example of the swallows, who
lack the “something more” of human language. Recall that it is the lack of
concepts that prevent swallows from “swallowizing” the universe. Even if
animals have signs and imagination, they do not have “the permanence of
the concept” (see Lacan 2006). Here, Lacan concludes that animals are
incapable of the generalization necessary for conceptualization.
Elsewhere, however, Lacan says in passing (again complaining about
behaviorist methodology) “there are enough really rather tiresome labora-
tory experiments, which show that if one holds an octopus, or any other
animal, with sufficient doggedness in from of a triangle, they will rec-
ognize it in the end, that is to generalize it” (1988b, 322). So, if animals
are capable of signs, of imagination, and even of concepts, what is lack-
ing to make their forms of communication into language? Discussing the
swallows and the bees, Lacan suggests that it is the capacity to make the
concept stand in for the thing. In other words, animals are incapable of
substitution or displacement, operations necessary for meaningful speech.
It is the play between presence and absence that engenders language:
“Through what becomes embodied only by being the trace of a nothing-
ness and whose medium thus cannot be altered, concepts, in preserving
the duration of what passes away, engender things It is the world of
words that creates the world of things” (2006, 228–29). Other animals,
then, cannot quite muster the absence at the heart of representation that
makes man the speaking animal.
In another lecture, however, continuing his fort-da giving and reeling
back in, Lacan suggests that animals are indeed capable of displacement:
Let us say that, in the animal world, the entire cycle of sexual behaviour is
dominated by the imaginary. On the other hand, it is in sexual behaviour
110 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
2. Lacan makes it clear that this imaginary function is the same in animals and man:
“Is this true for man, yes or no?...... This is nothing other than the imaginary phenomenon
which I just spelt out in detail for you in the animal” (Lacan 1988a, 138).
3. Reminiscent of Merleau-Ponty, Lacan says: “what comes to play in releasing
the complementary behavior of the male and female sticklebacks? Gestalten” (1988a,
137). Merleau-Ponty also uses the example of the stickleback to make the case for the
importance of mimesis in his Nature lectures (2003, 196). It is clear that Lacan was
influenced by Merleau-Ponty’s theories of perception (e.g., see 1988a, 58). For a discussion
of the relationship between Lacan and Merleau-Ponty on the question of the stickleback,
see my Animal Pedagogy, forthcoming.
112 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
TRUE LIES
4. Lacan’s idea that species stick to their own images and that there is no “orgy”
in nature seems extremely conservative, given his theory of the role of the image and
the imaginary in both animals and humans. Moreover, it operates with an extremely
conservative notion of sex as reproductive sex and a conservative notion of reproductive
sex at that. What about the reproductive relation between bees and flowers? What about
nonreproductive sex acts of animals with inanimate objects, plants, or animals of other
species? What about the way sexual behavior in the very animals Lacan cites changes with
their changing environment? In “Sexual Difference, Animal Difference” (forthcoming), I
argue that attending to the hugely diverse sexualities of various animal species opens up
new ways of conceiving of sex and reproduction.
Duplicity Makes the Man 113
In this passage, Lacan maintains that animals react to other animals (and to
humans) with a “dance” that indicates relationality with others. But their
very being in the world is not mediated by the dance, nor are they moved
in it by the Other in the way that constitutes humanity. The human world
is a world of signification through which subjects are constituted by virtue
of the Other of meaning that is inherited from others on whom the fledg-
ling subject is dependent for years. And although animals can pretend and
even lure, they can neither erase their tracks nor make false tracks appear
true. In other words, they cannot do what humans do when speaking,
namely, make a symbol stand in for the thing. Representation erases the
thing in favor of the concept that substitutes token for reality; animals are
incapable of this double operation of erasure and substitution, the inher-
ent duplicity of speech. Speech is the human activity of putting the feint
of erasure and substitution in the service of truth; we use words to tell the
truth about things by first erasing those very things. As Nietzsche might
say, we hide truth behind a bush and then praise ourselves when we find
it. The animal may deceive its predator or its prey, but it doesn’t deceive
itself. Animals may be capable of deception, but man is the self-deceptive
animal.
Lacan insists that speech, as distinct from language, opens the field of
signification to “noise” or superfluous meanings that “speak” unconscious
desire. He says:
the antinomy immanent in the relations between speech and language thus
becomes clear. The more functional language becomes, the less suited it is
to speech, and when it becomes overly characteristic of me alone, it loses its
function as language . . . what is redundant as far as information is concerned
is precisely what plays the part of resonance in speech. For the function
of language in speech is not to inform but to evoke. What I seek in speech
is a response from the other. (2006, 246–47)
This passage suggests that animal existence is purely utilitarian and that ani-
mals’ reactions always function to promote life; whereas human existence
is characterized by meaning in excess of use-value, the chatter with which
Duplicity Makes the Man 115
we continually and futilely try to fill the void or gap between us and the
world opened by our premature birth. This superfluous stuff is the stuff of
response and not of reaction; and, Lacan claims that animals are incapable
of any true response. Given Lacan’s repeated suggestion that there is never
any real communication between human subjects and that any appearance
of one is merely self-delusion, we might wonder what exactly he means
by “response.” Perhaps, for Lacan self-delusion is the essence of response,
which becomes something like an echo chamber or hall of mirrors.
Elsewhere, following Derrida, I have challenged whether, particu-
larly in light of psychoanalytic theory, we can maintain the distinction
between reaction and response in human beings. 5 Here, suffice it to say
that Lacan insists that “a reaction is not a response” and without evidence
from the “animal kingdom” to prove it, he is left with bald assertion and
math (see 2006, 247). His ambivalence toward both sciences, particularly
behaviorism, evidenced by his ambivalence toward animal studies, leads
him to math. It seems that as he moves closer to this “something more”
that cannot be perceived in the “animal kingdom,” he turns to mathemes
rather than to animal studies to make his work appear more rigorous; but
Lacan’s math fetish is beyond the scope of this essay, which prefers to
engage his animal fetish.
In L’animal, Derrida “deconstructs” the distinction between reaction
and response, along with the distinction between pretending and pre-
tending to pretend, or feint and feigning the feint. After all, how can we
tell the difference between pretending and pretending to pretend? How
can we distinguish first-order pretense from second-order pretense? Can
we so easily distinguish the two senses of duplicity: double actions and
double-dealing? How can we distinguish pretending from lying? Derrida
summarizes Lacan on pretense versus lie:
According to Lacan, the animal would be incapable of this type of lie, of this
deceit, of this pretense in the second degree, whereas the “subject of the sig-
nifier,” within the human order, would possess such a power and, better still,
would emerge as a subject, instituting itself and coming to itself as a subject
by virtue of this power, a second-degree reflexive power, a power that is
conscious of being able to deceive by pretending to pretend. (2002, 130)
6. Lacan describes the shift from the function of the image in the animal to the
function of the image in man as “imperceptible”: “but what is new in man is that
something is already sufficiently open, imperceptibly shifted within the imaginary
coaptation, for the symbolic use of the image to be inserted into it” (1988b, 322–23).
And it is this imperceptible shift that opens the way to speech and language, a path
closed to the animal. The difference between man and animal, then, is not something that
can be perceived on the level of the imaginary, precisely the level on which Lacan fixes
the animal.
Duplicity Makes the Man 117
evoked by Derrida but also in the physical sense, or we could say, in the
animal sense. As a thought experiment—and some environmental groups
have tested this out—try to imagine living on the earth without leaving a
trace, even for one day, for one hour, for one minute. It is as impossible for
man to erase his tracks as for any animal. But unlike most animal tracks
and traces, human tracks leave irreversible damage. And although some
animals also wreak havoc on the environment, none has done as much
as man to destroy that which sustains him. Can humanity learn to tread
lightly on the earth? Given the growing concerns about the environment
and the effect of human waste on it, and the dawn of the consequences
of global warming caused by man’s lack of concern for erasing his tracks,
wemight wonder once again what we might learn from the animals. Per-
haps they could teach us a few new steps in the dancity through which all
creatures live (and die if not lie) together.
References
Derrida, Jacques. 2006. L’animal que donc je suis. Paris: Galilée.
——— . 2005. Rogues. Trans. Pascale-Anne Brault and Michael Naas. Stanford:
Stanford University Press.
——— . 2004. “The Animal That Therefore I Am (More to Follow).” In Animal
Philosophy, ed. Peter Atterton and Matthew Calarco. London: Continuum
Press, 113–28.
——— . 2003. “And Say the Animal Responds?” In Zoontologies: The Question of the
Animal. Trans. David Wills. Ed. Cary Wolfe. Minneapolis: University of Min-
nesota Press, 121–46.
——— . 2002. “The Animal that Therefore I am (More to Follow). Trans. David
Wills. In Critical Inquiry 28 (2) (Winter), 369–418.
Lacan, Jacques. 1988a. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan. Bk. 1. Freud’s Papers of Tech-
nique 1953–1954. Trans. John Forrester. Ed. Jacques-Alain Miller. New York:
Norton.
——— . 1988ab. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan. Bk. 2. The Ego in Freud’s Theory
and in the Technique of Psychoanalysis 1954–1955. Trans. Sylvana Tomaselli. Ed.
Jacques-Alain Miller. New York: Norton.
——— . 2006. Écrits: The First Complete Edition in English. Trans. Bruce Fink.
New York: Norton.
Oliver, Kelly. 2006. “Animal Pedagogy: The Origin of ‘Man’ in Rousseau and
Herder.” Culture, Theory and Critique 47 (2), 107–31.
——— . 2007. “Tropho-ethics: Derrida’s Homeopathic Purity.” Harvard Review,
37–57.
——— . Forthcoming in Hypatia, 24:2 2009.“Sexual Difference, Animal Differ-
ence: Derrida and Difference ‘Worthy of Its Name.’ ”
——— . Forthcoming.Biting the Hand that Feeds You: Animal Pedagogy and the Sci-
ence of Kinship (Columbia 2009).
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 2003. Nature: Course Notes from the Collège de France.
Trans. Robert Vallier. Comp. Dominique Séglard, Chicago: Northwestern Uni-
versity Press.
Seshadri-Crooks, Kalpana. 2003. “Being Human: Bestiality, Anthropophagy, and
Law. Umbr(a), 97–114.
118 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
Paul Ekman
In this chapter I consider two separate but related issues. The first is why
most people are unable to accurately judge from demeanor whether
someone is lying or truthful (Ekman and O’Sullivan 1991; Ekman, Frank,
and O’Sullivan 1999; Frank and Ekman 1997). Most liars make mistakes
that could be detected but usually are missed. Both perpetrating a lie
and detecting a lie, in most people, seem to be poorly developed skills.
I will provide six explanations for why most of us do not catch liars from
demeanor.
The second topic I consider is microfacial expressions (micros) that
reveal concealed emotions. While most people do not report seeing micros,
in an hour most people can learn to do so. This raises the question, related
to the first topic, why, if it is so easy to learn, have people failed to do so?
Before addressing these issues, I will first explain how I distinguish lying
from other forms of deceit, and then discuss the evidence that suggests
that people are very poor lie catchers.
The intent of the liar is one of the two criteria I use to distinguish lies
from other kinds of deception (Ekman [1985] 2000). The liar deliberately
chooses to mislead the target. Liars may actually tell the truth, but that
is not their intent. And truthful people may provide false information—
say, bad advice from a stockbroker—but that is not their intent. A liar
has a choice; a liar could chose not to lie. We are all tempted to lie, but
we do not always do so. Lying is not irresistible; it is, by my definition, a
conscious, considered choice. I do recognize that lying can become a habit
and then be performed I don’t think you need be, it makes it awkward
with little consideration, but at least initially, all such habits began as con-
sidered choices about whether or not to do so. Presumably, a pathological
liar is compelled to lie and by my definition, therefore, is not a liar.
The second criterion for distinguishing lies from other deceptions is
that the target is not notified of the liar’s intention to mislead. A magician
is not a liar by this criterion, but Uri Geller is a liar, since Geller claimed
that his tricks were not magic. An actor is not a liar, but an impostor is.
“Let the buyer beware” is one example of an explicit warning that prod-
ucts or services may not be what they are presented to be. (Of course,
118
120 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
that warning does not appear in advertisements, nearly all of which are
designed to convey the opposite message.) Poker is still another situation
in which the rules of the game sanction and notify the players that decep-
tion will occur, and, therefore, one cannot consider bluffing to be a lie.
Sometimes notification of an intention to mislead is implicit in the
framing, to use Goffman’s (1974) term, of the situation. In real estate
transactions, the potential buyer is implicitly notified that the seller’s ask-
ing price is not the actual price the seller would accept. Various forms of
politeness are other instances in which the nature of the situation notifies
the target that the truth may not be spoken. It is not proper for the host to
scrutinize the dinner guest to determine whether the guest’s claim to have
enjoyed the evening is true any more than for the aunt to worry whether
the nephew is lying when he says that he appreciated the tie she gave him
for Christmas. In such situations, deception is expected; even if the target
might suspect that the truth is not being told, it is improper to question it.
Only certain types of deception may be allowable: The poker player can
deceive by bluffing but not use marked cards; the home seller can deceive
about the true selling price but can not conceal a known defect.
In courtship, it is ambiguous whether the parties should expect truth-
fulness. The saying “All’s fair in love and war” warns lovers not to believe all
they are told. Recent public opinion polls suggest that lies that downplay
the number of previous sexual partners are common among college-aged
adults. Yet I expect that lovers generally want to believe in the truthful-
ness of their lovers. Many popular songs testify to the betrayal felt when
lies are discovered (although some do warn that lies may be expected).
Romantic love requires that partners make collusive efforts to develop
and maintain myths about each other and the nature of the relationship.
When a police officer interviews a person suspected of a crime, the
policeman asks but typically does not expect to be told the truth, at least
not initially, if the suspect is guilty of the crime. The officer often stresses
the importance of and benefits of being truthful, though it may not actu-
ally be in the best interests of the guilty person. It is not uncommon
for the police to tell the suspect information that is not true in order to
induce a confession, and the U.S. Supreme Court has ruled that confes-
sions obtained by means of such lies are admissible. In the United King-
dom, they are not.
I differ from Bok (1982), who only considers false statements to be lies.
I argue that one can falsify without words, and one need not falsify, ver-
bally or nonverbally, to lie (Ekman [1985] 2001). Concealment is just as
much a lie as falsification, if there is an expectation that information will
be revealed. When filling out a job application that asks for a listing of all
previous employment, omitting the one from which one was fired would
be a concealment lie, for there is an obligation to reveal. In personal rela-
tionships, it is not always so clear-cut, and the liar, once discovered, and
the target may disagree about whether or not an obligation to reveal the
concealed information was in force.
Lie Catching and Microexpressions 119
to develop a skill they would need to use when confronting just such
upsetting scenes in their future work. In another of our scenarios, the
subjects had a chance to take and keep $50 if they could convince the
interrogator they had not taken it, whereas the subjects who did not take
the $50 could only earn $10 if the interrogator believed them when they
said they had not taken the $50. In another scenario, we first identified
the social issues the subjects felt most strongly about, and then asked each
subject to describe that opinion honestly (and earn $10 if believed) or to
claim to have the opposite of his or her true opinion (and earn $50 if
believed). In our most recent work, we have selected members of politi-
cally extreme action groups; they are given the opportunity to deprive an
opposing group of funds and to divert the same funds to their own group,
if they can fool the police officer who interviews them.
In most of our work, we give subjects the choice whether to lie or tell
the truth, as people have in real life. People may choose not to lie for
many reasons; one is their own knowledge, based on past experience, that
they are almost always caught. Including in the sample of liars such ter-
rible liars—people who would not choose to lie unless forced to do so by
the experimenter—could inflate the detection rate. In virtually all previ-
ous research, on either interpersonal deception or polygraph lie detection,
subjects were not given the choice whether to lie or be truthful (another
reason for discounting the metaanalyses by Bond and DePaulo). One
exception is the study of the polygraph by Ginton, Daie, Elaad, and Ben-
Shakhar (1982), in which the subjects were free to make a choice about
whether or not to cheat; they were not randomly assigned to cheat and
lie or not cheat and be truthful. Subjects in Stiff, Corman, Knizek, and
Snider (1994) were not told whether or not to cheat on a quiz. Bradley
(1988) also allowed subjects to choose whether to lie or tell the truth in
a polygraph study.
Another unique feature of our recent experiments is that we told the
subjects that they would be punished—and it was a considerable pun-
ishment—if the interrogator judged them to be lying. Both the truthful
person mistakenly judged to be lying and the liar who was detected would
receive the same punishment. Thus, for the first time in research on lying,
both the truthful person and the liar might be afraid—of being disbe-
lieved if telling the truth, of being caught if lying. If only the liar is afraid
of being accused of lying, the situation is too easy for the lie catcher and
not relevant to most of real life. And if neither the liar nor the truthful
person fear punishment, the situation has little relevance to the telling of
lies in the criminal justice world or in national security, let alone in marital
disputes, parent-child conflicts, and so on.
Although our recent experiments can claim to have more ecological
validity than most of the literature on either interpersonal deceit or poly-
graph lie detection, our findings about detectability were not much differ-
ent. Most of those who watched the videotapes and made their judgments
operated at a level of chance or only slightly better. Before exploring why
Lie Catching and Microexpressions 121
among the top five characteristics people want in a leader, friend, or lover.
And worldwide there are no end of stories, films, and songs that describe
the tragic consequences of betrayal.
My first explanation is that we are not prepared by our evolutionary
history to be either very good lie catchers or lie perpetrators. 1 I suspect
that our ancestral environment offered very few opportunities to lie and
get away with it, and the costs for being caught in a lie might have been
severe. If this speculation is correct, there would not have been any selec-
tion benefit for people who were unusually adept in catching or perpe-
trating lies. The fossil record does not tell us much about social life, so
one can only speculate about what life as hunter-gatherers might have
been like. I add to that my experience forty years ago working in what
was then a Stone Age preliterate culture in what is now called Papua
New Guinea.
There were no rooms with doors and little privacy in the small vil-
lage where I was living, in which everyone knew and saw everyone else
every day. A lie would most often be betrayed by its target or someone
else observing actions that contradicted the lie or by other physical evi-
dence. Adultery was an activity that persons often attempted to conceal
by means of lies. Such lies were uncovered not by reading the betrayer’s
demeanor when proclaiming fidelity but by accidentally catching him or
her in the act in the bush.
While lies about beliefs, emotions, and plans might be more likely to
go undetected in such an environment,2 some of those lies will eventu-
ally lead to one or another action, and then the difficulty of concealing or
falsifying actions in a setting in which there is no privacy applies.
In a society in which one’s survival depends on cooperative efforts with
other members of one’s village, the reputational loss from being caught in
a high-stakes lie might well be deadly. No one might cooperate with you if
you are known to have engaged in serious lies. You cannot change spouses,
jobs, or villages with any ease.
Cheney and Seyfarth make very similar points. An important constraint
against lying
arises from a species’ social structure. Animals that live in stable social
groups face special problems in any attempt at deceptive communica-
tion. Among socially living animals deceptive signals will probably have
to be more subtle and occur at lower frequencies if they are to go unde-
tected. Equally important, if animals live in social groups in which some
degree of cooperation is essential for survival, the need for cooperation can
reduce the rate at which unreliable signals are given. (1990, 189)
To have some special skill in detecting (or perpetrating for that matter)
lies would not have much adaptive value in such circumstances. Seri-
ous, high-stakes lies probably did not occur that often because of limited
opportunity and high costs. When lies were suspected or uncovered, it
was probably not by judgments of demeanor. I have focused just on intra-
group lies; certainly lies between groups, and their costs and detection,
could be quite different.3
While there are altruistic lies, my discussion has dealt with less friendly
lies, lies that occur when one person gains an advantage, often at the cost
of the target. When the advantage is gained by violating a rule or expec-
tation, we call that cheating. Lies sometimes may be required to accom-
plish the cheating activity, and lies are always required to conceal having
cheated. Those cheated do not typically appreciate having been cheated
and are motivated to uncover any lies involved. But my bet is that cheat-
ing was not likely to have occurred often enough in our ancestral environ-
ment to confer an advantage on those who might have been unusually
adept at spotting when it did occur. And as I argued earlier, there was
probably so little privacy that cheats would be caught by means other
than discernment of their demeanor. The biologist Alan Grafen wrote:
The incidence of cheating must be low enough that signaling remains on
average honest. As signalers maximize their fitness, this implies that the
occasions on which cheating is advantageous must be limited. Perhaps the
signalers for whom cheating is advantageous are in a minority, or . . . only
on a minority of occasions does it pay a signaler to cheat. Cheating is
expected in evolutionarily stable signal systems, but the system can be
stable only if there is some reason why on most occasions cheating does
not pay. Cheats impose a kind of tax on the meaning of the signal. The
central fact about stable signaling systems is honesty, and the debasement
of the meaning of the signal by cheats must be limited if stability is to be
maintained. (1990, 533)
By this reasoning, signals that cheat, which I would call lies, would
have a low incidence. Cosmides and Tooby’s (1992) findings suggest that
we have evolved a sensitivity to rule infractions and do not reward cheat-
ers, and this may explain why cheating does not occur often. However,
our findings suggest that people are not likely to catch cheaters on the
basis of an ability to spot their lies from their demeanor.
To summarize my argument, our ancestral environment did not pre-
pare us to be astute lie catchers. Those who might have been most adept
in identifying a liar from demeanor would have had minimal advantage.
Serious lies probably did not occur often, because lack of privacy would
have made the chances of being caught high. Lack of privacy would also
mean that lies would typically be discovered by direct observation or
other physical evidence, making it unnecessary to rely on judgments of
children. The philanderer does not want to be caught, so they both have
an interest in the lie not being uncovered. A similar logic is at work in the
following, more altruistic lie and collusive belief. A wife asks her husband
“Was there any other woman at the party whom you thought was more
attractive than me?” He lies by claiming she was the most attractive when
she was not. He does not want to make her jealous, and he does not want
to deal with her having feelings of insecuirty, and she may have a strong
desire to believe she was the most attractive.
In some kinds of collusion, the target who wants to believe the liar may
not benefit from the lie or may benefit only in the short run. Consider
what could perhaps be the most infamous example of a target believing
a liar who meant him harm. I refer to the famous meeting between the
British prime minister Neville Chamberlain and Adolph Hitler, the chan-
cellor of Germany, on September 15, 1938 (the following account is from
my [1985] 2001, 15, 16):
The world watched, aware that this might be the last hope of avoiding
another world war. (Just six months earlier, Hitler’s troops had marched
into Austria, annexing it to Germany. England and France had protested
but done nothing further.) On September 12, three days before he was to
meet with Chamberlain, Hitler demanded to have part of Czechoslovakia
annexed to Germany—inciting rioting in Czechoslovakia. Hitler had
already secretly mobilized the German army to attack Czechoslovakia, but
his army would not be ready until the end of September. If he could keep
the Czechs from mobilizing their army for a few more weeks, he would
have the advantage of a surprise attack. Stalling for time, he concealed his
war plans from Chamberlain, giving his word that peace could be pre-
served if the Czechs would meet his demands. Chamberlain was fooled;
he tried to persuade the Czechs not to mobilize their army while there
was still a chance to negotiate with Hitler. After his meeting with Hitler,
Chamberlain wrote to his sister: “in spite of the hardness and ruthlessness
I thought I saw in his face, I got the impression that here was a man who
could be relied upon when he had given his word.” Defending his poli-
cies against those who doubted Hitler’s word, Chamberlain five days later
in a speech to Parliament explained that his personal contact with Hitler
allowed him to say that Hitler “means what he says.”(Ekman, [1985] 2001,
pp. 15, 16)
was wrongfully punished, that feedback comes too late, too far removed
from the mistaken judgment, to be corrective.
This suggests that if you expose people to a lower base rate of lying,
around 50 percent, and give them corrective feedback after each judg-
ment they make, they might well learn how to accurately identify lies from
demeanor. One element in this explanation of the failure to detect liars
from demeanor is that most people do not get feedback about whether
their judgments are correct or not. Not just the police lack such informa-
tion. If you were to decide that your friend had lied to you, how would you
determine if you were correct? Most often, I expect, you would simply stop
seeing the friend. The failure to definitively check your judgment against
an independent criterion of truthfulness is probably quite common and
responsible for people generally not learning from mistaken judgments.
A last factor to consider is that most people do not know what to
look or listen for in order to make accurate judgments of truthfulness.
An abundance of misinformation appears in the popular press and in the
courses offered by organizations such as Neuro-Linguistic Programming.
Even if they know what the clues to deceit are, it appears from our recent
but still unpublished research that without special training, they will miss
one of the most valuable clues: micro facial expressions, or micros.
micro expressions out of context—with the sound turned off, and no need
to think of replies—most people do not report seeing many of them.
When I first tried to teach people how to spot micros, I was surprised
to discover how quickly they learned. After a few years, I put the training
materials, which I called the Micro Expression Training Tool (METT), on
a self-instructional CD. It shows fifty-six different people; each appears
only once. Each exposure first shows the person in a neutral expression,
and then an emotion flashes briefly (for one-fifteenth of a second), and
then the expression returns to neutral. The respondent must choose one
of seven emotions (anger, fear, sadness, disgust, contempt, surprise, fear,
happiness). There is a pretest of fourteen items, a training section, and a
review section, each of which shows expressions that are commonly con-
fused (e.g. anger versus disgust), with voiceover commentary. A practice
segment provides feedback after each judgment and the opportunity to
see each practice item repeatedly. The posttest provides information on
the extent of improvement.
It takes less than forty minutes to complete the CD, half of which
consists of training. On average, people improve 30 to 40 percent from
pretest to posttest, while those who do not receive training, practice, and
review show little change from pretest to posttest. Importantly, those who
have been trained, compared to a no-training control group, also report
discerning the emotions shown in micros contained in sound videos of
spontaneous interviews.
My next METT CD, a substantial improvement over the first, includes
more practice items, training at one-thirtieth of a second, more than one
version of anger and disgust, and a wider variety of cultural backgrounds
of the people shown. A third version provides three times as much prac-
tice as the second, and is intended to bring respondents up to a very high
accuracy level in detecting micros. A fourth version provides training in
the recognition of profile views of micros. (The CDs are available online
at http://www.paulekman.com.)
The METT is now used in the training of law enforcement, national
security, and health professionals, visa interviewers, salespersons, negotia-
tors, job recruiters, and mental health professionals. Everyone who uses the
METT is enthusiastic about what he or she has learned to see; the improve-
ment is obvious to people, even without the posttest score to document it.
It is curious that this skill can be learned so quickly by nearly everyone, and
yet most people, even highly motivated people, are not able to see micros
prior to training. If it is so useful, and if people can learn it so quickly, why
do they need our training tool to learn it? The answer, I believe, is that in
the real world we do not get the necessary experience; we do not know
that these expressions exist, and even if we did, we would not get practice
in trying to spot them and getting immediate feedback about whether
our judgments are correct. On the other hand, curiously, there are people,
about 1 percent of those we have tested, who do see micros without train-
ing, and I cannot explain why they have this ability.
132 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
I do not want to give the impression that most lies are detected because
of micros or any other sign of emotional behavior. Sometimes detection
has nothing to do with the liar’s demeanor—a lie is betrayed by incon-
trovertible evidence from another source, such as a reliable eyewitness or
physical evidence. Sometimes a liar cannot resist bragging, revealing his
secret to an untrustworthy source who turns him in. The notorious spy
John Walker sold to the Soviet Union the secret of how the United States
made the propellers on its nuclear submarines silent—very important
information, because before that the Soviets couldn’t tell where our subs
were hiding, while noisy propellers revealed the location of theirs. Walker
was not caught by a polygraph or by an astute interrogator; he bragged
to his wife about how much he was being paid, heedless of the fact that
she was now his ex-wife, and he was behind in alimony payments! She
turned him in.
There are occasions when a liar does not deliberately or unintentionally
spill the beans and there is no incontrovertible contradictory evidence.
Most criminal prosecutions that go to trial (rather than being settled by
a plea bargain) are like that. The decision about truthfulness is made
by a jury, in some part at least by evaluating demeanor, trying to decide
whether witnesses are telling the truth on the basis of what they say and
how they say it. In such cases, the lie is not usually about what emotion is
being felt at the moment of the lie but is about an action—usually, though
not always, an action that has already occurred. But even on the witness
stand, emotions can become involved in lying.
Micros are only one type of clue that must be followed in evaluating
truthfulness (even if so far our research on deception has suggested they
are the most important). The accuracy achieved by using micros alone,
while statistically significant, is not high enough to have practical use.
Macroexpressions, symbolic gestures (emblems), voice, and speech con-
tent must also be considered to obtain very high accuracy in evaluating
truthfulness. My book Telling Lies (2001; 2009) describes these and other
important issues relating to why people lie, and when it is most and least
possible to evaluate truthfulness.
Basically, it is only changes in behavior that matter, changes in behavior
that occur when there is a change in the topic under discussion. If I am
always hesitant when I talk, it should be disregarded unless my hesita-
tions increase markedly or decrease markedly (suggesting rehearsal). Sec-
ond, even a marked hesitation in a response to a question to which there
should be an easy answer might be due to a totally innocent process. Even
if I am not duplicitous, I might be hesitant if questioned by my wife about
where I was when she was unable to reach me if, say, I am thinking about
why my wife seems suspicious of me or if I am trying to decide whether
I should call her on it. That is why I call all such behavioral signs hot spots,
not signs of lying; they mark a place where you need to find out more by
questioning, background checks, and so on. Alternative explanations of
Lie Catching and Microexpressions 133
why the behavior occurred have to be ruled out before concluding that a
change in behavior is evidence of lying.
Only Pinocchio had an obvious sign that would only show up when he
was lying. The rest of us at best have hot spots. Even if my face registers
a microexpression of fear when my spouse asks me about being parked
outside the St. Regis hotel in the middle of the afternoon when I usually
would be at work, it is only be a hot spot. I might be afraid my wife is not
going to believe me, or I might be worried about the state of our marriage
if she has such doubts about me. I might be concealing my fear because
I do not want her to know I am having such questions about her and our
marriage, even though I have done nothing she would consider wrong.
Of course, the fear might be showing up because am I about to deny an
actual infidelity. But since it is only a hot spot, more information is needed
to clarify what generated the emotion being concealed.
Emotions do not tell us their sources. When we see signs of a concealed
emotion in a micro, or we see a normal facial expression that contradicts
a speaker’s words, voice, or gesture, that is a hot spot. Hot spots are not
proof of lying; they merely mark places where we need to find out more
to make an accurate evaluation of truthfulness.
A final caution: not everyone who suppresses or represses an emotion
shows a micro. We have found micros in about half of the people who
are deliberately lying in our research studies. The presence of a micro
means something (an emotion exists and it is being concealed), but its
absence does not tell us whether concealment is or is not occurring. We
still do not know why only some people generate micros when they con-
ceal emotions.
More generally, we have not found any behavioral change that always
occurs in every person who is lying; that is why lie catchers must learn
to be alert to every aspect of demeanor, for it is never possible to know
ahead of time where the important information will show up. This news
always disheartens television interviewers and print media writers, who
are disappointed I cannot tell them the surefire behavioral clues to deceit.
They do not exist. Anyone who says there is an absolutely reliable sign of
lying that is always present when someone lies and never present when
someone is truthful is either misguided or a charlatan.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Large portions of the discussion here on why we do not catch liars were previ-
ously published in Social Research 63, 3 (Fall 1996), 801–17; part of the discussion
of micros appeared in my essay “Emotions and Lying,” in Emotions Revealed, 2nd
ed. (New York: Holt, 2007).
I am grateful to Mardi J. Horowitz, M.D., for providing the opportunity to
examine interviews with patients who had repressed specific emotions.
134 The Practices of Deception and Self-Deception
References
Bok, S. 1982. Secrets. New York: Pantheon.
Bond, C. F., and B. M. DePaulo. 2006. “Accuracy of Deception Judgments.” Person-
ality and Social Psychology Review 10, 214–34.
Bradley, M. T. 1988. “Choice and the Detection of Deception.” Perceptual and
Motor Skills 66, 43–48.
Bugental, D. B., W. Shennum, M. Frank, and P. Ekman. 2000. “‘True Lies’: Chil-
dren’s Abuse History and Power Attributions as Influences on Deception
Detection.” In Attribution, Communication Behavior, and Close Relationships,
ed. V. Manusov and J. H. Harvey. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
248–65.
Cheney, D. L., and M. Seyfarth. 1990. How Monkeys See the World. Chicago: Uni-
versity of Chicago Press.
Cosmides, L., and J. Tooby. 1992. “Cognitive Adaptations for Social Exchange.” In
The Adapted Mind, ed. J. Barkow, L. Cosmides, and J. Tooby. New York: Oxford
University Press.
DePaulo, B. M., and R. L. Pfeifer. 1986. “On-the-job Experience and Skill at
Detecting Deception.” Journal of Applied Social Psychologv 16, 249–67.
Ekman, P., 2001.Telling Lies: Clues to Deceit in the Marketplace, Marriage and Poli-
tics (1985). 3rd ed. New York: Norton.
Ekman, P., and W. V. Friesen. 1969. “Nonverbal Leakage and Cues to Deception.”
Psychiatry 32, 1, 88–105.
Ekman, P., and W. V. Friesen. 1974. “Detecting Deception from Body or Face.”
Journal of Personality and Social Psvchology 29, 288–98.
Ekman, P., and M. N. O’Sullivan. 1991. “Who Can Catch a Liar?” American Psy-
chologist 46, 913–20.
Ekman, P., M. O’Sullivan, and M. Frank. 1990. “A Few Can Catch a Liar.” Psycho-
logical Science 10, 3.
Frank, M., and P. Ekman. 1997. “The Ability to Detect Deceit Generalizes across
Different Types of High Stake Lies.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology
72, 1429–39.
Ginton, A., N. Daie, E. Elaad, and G. Ben-Shakhar. 1982. “A Method for Evaluat-
ing the Use of the Polygraph in a Real-life Situation.” Journal of Applied Psychol-
ogy 67, 131–37.
Goffman, E. 1974. Frame Analysis. New York: Harper and Row.
Grafen, A. 1990. “Biological Signals as Handicaps.” Journal of Theoretical Biology
144, 517–46.
Griesil, Dorothee, and J. C. Yuille. 2005. “Credibility Assessment in Eyewitness
Memory.” In Handbook of Eyewitness Psychology, vol. 1, Memory for Events, ed.
M. Toglia, R. Lindsay, D. Ross, and D. Read. Mahwah , N.J.: Erlbaum.
Haggard, Ernest A., and Kenneth S. Isaacs.1966. “Micro-momentary Facial Expres-
sions as Indicators of Ego Mechanisms in Psychotherapy.” In Methods of Research
in Psychotherapy, ed. Louis A. Gottschalk and Arthur H. Auerbach. New York:
Appleton Century Crofts.
Kraut, R. E., and D. Poe. 1980. “On the Line: The Deception Judgments of Cus-
toms Inspectors and Laymen.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 39,
784–98.
Levine, T. R., and, S. A. McCornack. 1992. “Linking Love and Lies: A Formal Test
of the McCornack and Parks Model of Deception Detection.” Journal of Social
and Personal Relationship 9, 143–54.
Lie Catching and Microexpressions 135
Alan Strudler
Note: This essay is a revised version of “Deception Unraveled,” Journal of Philosophy 102,
no. 9 (2005), 458–473.
1. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002, ch. 5.
139
140 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
and then explore how ideas of breach of trust and manipulation more
generally may help explain these tensions. I will also examine the possibil-
ity of a more extended application of my argument.
Many of the cases that I discuss will be taken from commercial life. There
are two related reasons for this. First, what makes deception often seem
acceptable are strategic factors, for example, the need to protect private
or proprietary information; these factors are comparatively accessible in
commercial contexts. Second, the leading philosophical discussions often
concern deception about bewildering problems of life and death, love and
betrayal. Yet morality matters not only in such matters of high stakes but
also in the mundane choices we face every day. Commercial life promises
cases of deception that are emotionally cool enough to limit the risk of con-
founding but rich enough to bring out the structure of deception, I suggest.
You are thinking about buying a used car from me. You live in the des-
ert, where you take long drives on lonely roads, so you want a car with
a cooling system that works well. You ask me about the condition of my
car’s radiator. I tell you that a mechanic inspected the car this morning,
and that he said that the radiator is fine. I know more, but do not say: the
radiator would leak if I had not poured Gunk in it to temporarily plug
a hole. I brought the car to this mechanic because he was incompetent,
would not notice the Gunk, and hence would provide good cover for me.
When I told you that the mechanic found no problem with the radia-
tor, did I wrong you? I did not lie. By repeating, without comment, the
words of the mechanic, I created an impression that there was no reason
to doubt what he said. I wrongly deceived you. I told a truth, but mis-
led you. What more can be said about the wrong that I committed? By
deceiving you, did I, as Williams might suggest, wrongly manipulate you?
Or breach your trust?
On the surface, the charge of wrongful manipulation seems plausible.
I take it as a sufficient even though not exhaustive characterization of
manipulation that one person manipulates another when he intentionally
causes that person to behave as he wishes through a chain of events that
has the desired effect only because the manipulated person is unaware
of that chain.2 This case, “Car Sale,” seems manipulative according to this
characterization, because in it I cause you to have a false belief in order
to get you to behave as I wish, and in doing so, I willfully hide from you
facts about the causal process, including the fact that the mechanic was
tricked. Also, I seem to breach a trust: by my behavior, I seem to vouch
2. I acknowledge that other kinds of manipulation, for example, that which operates
by preying on a person’s emotions, may be transparent to their victims. But these are not
my concern here.
Deception and Trust 141
for the mechanic’s assessment, inviting your trust and then breaching it.
There is perhaps a strong tie between breach of trust and manipulation in
“Car Sale.” After all, my success in manipulating you seems deeply bound
with my success in getting you to trust what I convey about my experi-
ence with my mechanic.
Soon I will argue that in assessing the wrongness of a particular decep-
tive act, it is important to distinguish between breach of trust and other
manipulation elements. In cases such as “Car Sale,” the distinction may
appear less than clear. But it does not take much changing of the case to
sharpen this appearance. One might do so, for example, by supposing that
I cultivate trust by solemnly explaining that for the last ten generations,
my family’s deepest commitment has been to Quaker values according to
which it is more important to be honest and forthcoming, and to act for
the sake of others, than to make money. My pronouncements—true but
misleading, because they represent my family’s past but not my present
intentions—are a solicitation of trust, and may play a distinctive causal
role in eliciting your confidence in what I say or suggest. By making these
pronouncements, I convey that you can rely on my goodwill, that is, my
intention to act for your sake and not simply for my advantage.3 I manipu-
late you, because in ways that I willfully hide from you, I cause you to
have a false belief about whether I have goodwill toward you, and then
exploit that belief in order to get you to behave as I wish. But because
I emphasize the goodwill inherent in my Quaker background, trust plays
a distinctive role in this manipulation.
Anyone who has glimpsed the recent large literature on trust will
notice that not all would accept my characterization of trust in terms
of goodwill. Sometimes, one might object, you trust another person to
be truthful not because of his goodwill, but because you know that it
is in his interest to advance your interest, and he has reason to think
that his being truthful will advance your interest. 4 For example, a repeat
buyer of fish may believe the fishmonger’s report of freshness because he
knows that it is in the fishmonger’s interest to retain him as a future cus-
tomer, and not because the fishmonger has goodwill in a stronger sense.
The fishmonger, as I imagine him, exhibits no goodwill, because he does
not act for the sake of his customer, but instead acts in order to get an
advantage for himself. No doubt the sort of reliability the fishmonger
demonstrates is socially important. At least for purposes of this essay, his
reliability is best characterized without using the idea of trust. I propose
that one may regard someone as reliably truthful because of his goodwill,
and one may be regard someone as reliably truthful because of personal
3. The idea that trusting a person requires viewing that person as possessing relevant
goodwill is ably advanced in Annette Baier, Moral Prejudices (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1995), ch. 6.
4. For representative examples of this approach, see Elinor Ostrom and James Walker,
eds., Trust and Reciprocity (New York: Sage, 2003).
142 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
you to believe that there is an external basis for my truthfulness, and then
using that credibility to cause you to have a false belief. There is, thus,
substantial variation in manipulation. One can deceive a person in a way
that manipulates him but does not breach his trust.
So far, I have tried to sketch two distinguishable processes through
which deception occurs: manipulation that involves a deceiver breaching
trust and simple manipulation, which does not rely on the idea of trust
in this way. In the next section I will argue for the moral acceptability
of certain deception that does not rely on trust. I aim then to show how
adding an element of trust makes a difference for the moral assessment
of deceptive acts.
UNAVOIDABLE DECEPTION
“House Sale” and “Car Sale” are not morally on par, but they involve
important similarities. In both cases, a party deceives in order to hide
information that his bargaining foe would find useful. Both cases there-
fore involve protecting oneself against possibly damaging invasive queries.
Even so, the two cases differ in a way that renders salient some limits on
the right to use self-defense. Hence I will argue for the moral acceptabil-
ity of deception about settlement preferences in “House Sale,” and then
distinguish it from the deception in “Car Sale.” My argument will draw on
traditional ideas about the norms of self-defense.
Consider a case of self-defense from outside the realm of deception.
I credibly threaten to slug you. May you use force to prevent my immi-
nent attack? It depends. One may use violence defensively only if it is
unavoidable, that is, only if one cannot otherwise, through less costly
means, prevent an attack. Call this the avoidability principle. If there is
a policeman nearby whom I do not see but you know could, through
nonviolent intimidation, secure the peace, then the avoidability principle
requires that you ask for his help rather than use force. The avoidability
principle, thus described, applies to the use of violence in self-defense.
We can easily extend it so that it applies to the use of deception in self-
defense, saying simply: “One may use violence or deception defensively
only if it is unavoidable, that is, only if one cannot otherwise, through less
costly means, prevent an attack.” In its defensive use, deception seems
often to satisfy this principle. Indeed, the idea of unavoidability is part of
the most discussed example—at least among philosophers—of acceptable
deception: a murderer asks you for the location of his intended victim,
who happens to be hiding in your cellar, and you contemplate deceiving
him. Few doubt that it is morally acceptable to deceive in “Murderer.” By
deceiving in this case, one defends an innocent person against a wrongful
threat, and uses the least objectionable means possible to do so.
“House Sale” is not “Murderer.” Nothing profound is at stake. Life goes
on if one does not deceive. Indeed, there are several ways to avoid deceiv-
ing: one might disclose one’s pricing preferences, or refuse to answer
queries aimed at eliciting those preferences, or simply walk away from
the deal. Because the deception in “House Sale” seems easy to avoid and
hence in some sense avoidable, the deception may appear not to satisfy
the conditions for legitimate self-defense, and thus appear morally dubi-
ous. These appearances, I will argue, are illusory: available paths of avoid-
ance have costs that one should not be expected to bear. There are limits
on what one must do to avoid defending oneself, even outside the realm
of deceptive defense. In the traditional jurisprudence of self-defense, these
limits may be understood in terms of the duty to retreat. Thus, if someone
threatens to attack a person on that person’s property, and the prospective
victim can safely avoid the attack by retreating into his home, then he has
no duty to retreat rather than to fend off the attack using reasonable
force; when he stands on the right to not retreat, he may use reasonable
force to protect himself. In this case, the use of force remains unavoidable,
Deception and Trust 145
LIMITS OF UNAVOIDABILITY
right to use force to protect against trouble that I have sought out. More
generally, a person has no right to claim that self-defense is unavoidable
when he bears some responsibility for the attack he faces.
The relevance of this limit on the right to self-defense can be seen in
a recurring problem of deception in securities law. The problem involves
cases in which corporate officers are asked about arguably proprietary
information that would, if disclosed, adversely affect the value of their
firm’s stock. Suppose that a firm’s viability is staked to the successful
development of a particular product. And suppose that there has been
a setback in its development. You, a corporate officer, are optimistic that
the product will eventually be a success, but reasonable people might dis-
agree. If word gets out about the difficulties, the value of the firm’s stock
might be so adversely affected that the firm would be unable to develop
the product. What should you do when journalists and your shareholders
ask about progress on the product? If you disclose, the harm is clear. If you
say “No comment,” you encourage adverse inferences that will likely have
the same harmful effect because people will wonder what you are hiding.
When facing these problems, many firms find ways to say things that are
literally true but misleading; they deceive in order to protect what they
regard as proprietary information. Is this deception acceptable?
Courts disagree about how to handle this problem. Some tolerate mis-
leading statements; others do not. Judge Richard Posner takes the tolerant
approach in Eisenstadt v. Centel,5 an influential case in which the pro-
prietary information was not about product development but about an
unsuccessful auction. If word got out about the auction, it would depress
stock prices. So corporate officers faced a sensitive problem when jour-
nalists and members of the public asked about the success of the auction.
Centel’s most troubling comment, in response to these queries, was to say
that the bidding process went well.6 In fact, only a handful of parties bid,
and none came close to an acceptable price. The auction was a bust.
I find cogent the case that Centel wrongly deceived its stockhold-
ers. Posner does not. He maintains that Centel’s comment that the bid-
ding process went well was true, because “the auction process went as
smoothly as could be desired.”7 By that, he means merely that the auction
opened in an orderly way, bids were taken, assessed, and so forth. Sub-
stantively, Posner acknowledges, the auction “failed,” because it produced
very few bids and no remotely acceptable bid. Since the auction failed,
was Centel’s statement that the process went well misleading, if not false?
Posner thinks not, because he believes that it was plain that the intended
audience would not form a false belief on the basis of Centel’s statement
about the auction process. Posner’s assertion about audience response to
Centel’s statement is, of course, pure conjecture; he gives no evidence
for it. Worse, it relies on mystery. If it is as obvious as Posner maintains
that nobody would believe Centel’s statement and suggestions, then why
should corporate officers bother to make them? Why say or suggest some-
thing that you know your audience will not believe? Posner’s answer to
this question invokes an analogy with writing letters of recommendation
in an environment in which inflation, or exaggeration of praise, is the
norm. If it is the community norm to say that merely good candidates
are wonderful candidates, then if one says that one’s own merely good
candidate is (merely) good, one’s words, or what one suggests by uttering
those words, will be understood according to the community norm, and
one will send a false message about the candidate, Posner thinks.
By invoking the letter-writing analogy, Posner suggests that saying that
the auction process went well is merely a complex way of conveying
some minimal truth about the auction, perhaps that the process started
and ended smoothly. But the letter-writing analogy is inapt. In its state-
ments about bidding, Centel did more than exaggerate an evaluation. It
encouraged false belief about the occurrence of specific events. Contrary
to Posner’s benign view, there are plausible scenarios in which even a rea-
sonable person would form false beliefs on the basis of Centel’s statement
that the bidding process went well, and conclude that acceptable bids
were made. A reasonable person might not notice that Centel praised the
bidding process rather than the bids themselves. More important, even
if a reasonable person did notice the word “process,” he might still quite
plausibly believe that some acceptable bids were made, because he might
reasonably think that part of a successful process is that acceptable bids
are made. It is easy to imagine other statements about process that, like
Centel’s, are misleading. Suppose that a scientist says that the experimen-
tal process goes well; his justification is that he successfully collected and
tested all needed data; but he does not mention that the data disconfirm
his hypothesis. Or suppose that a lawyer claims that the trial process goes
well; his justification is that all witnesses show up, the proceeding begins
and ends in a timely way, and procedural formalities are respected; but
he does not mention that he is decisively losing. The scientist’s and the
lawyer’s attempts to hide behind a technical idea of pure process are ruses
aimed at hiding failure. So is Centel’s.
The best argument for Centel cannot rely on Posner’s idea that its offi-
cers said nothing false or misleading. Instead, that argument must estab-
lish something that a judge might understandably be reluctant to say:
that it was morally acceptable for Centel to make a false or misleading
statement. In trying to make that argument, the similarity between “Cen-
tel” and “House Sale” is crucial. In “House Sale,” it is morally acceptable
to make misleading statements for defensive reasons: in order to fend off
queries about matters that, if disclosed, might prove harmful, and about
Deception and Trust 149
which one’s audience has no right to know. Centel’s best argument must
make the case that it was similarly acceptable for Centel to make mis-
leading statements that would fend off queries about matters that, if dis-
closed, might prove harmful, and about which the audience had no right
to know. There is a problem for such an argument. “Centel” and “House
Sale” differ in a crucial respect that bears on the issue of the avoidability
of deception. Centel officers, unlike the house seller, could have ex ante
adopted a policy that would allow them to avoid the need to deceive.
Suppose that Centel announced a policy before the auction: we will hold
an auction, but we will make no comment about it until one month after
the auction ends. Then there would have been no need to make a mislead-
ing statement about the auction process because Centel’s silence would
not be subject to the adverse interpretation that the truth was too ugly
to speak. This was an option more readily available to Centel than to the
house seller because unlike Centel, the house seller is not an institution
with the capacity to make public commitments in advance of a transac-
tion. But Centel chose not to make that public commitment, knowing
that the intrigue of an auction might strengthen stock prices. By choosing
to stay silent, Centel created the conditions that made it necessary for it
to defend itself from queries about the auction. Because it was responsible
for its need to deceive, it forfeited the right to use deception defensively,
and wrongly deceived people about its auction.
In this section, I have used the example of Centel to argue that norms
of self-defense are important in assessing deception, and not reducible
to considerations such as an audience’s right to know. Some deception is
morally acceptable, I have maintained, because it provides an unavoidable
defense against invasive queries that threaten harm. I have also argued
that Centel’s deceptive statements do not satisfy the unavoidability con-
dition, and were therefore wrong. Centel’s predicament was not unique.
As I suggested, it is shared by many firms that face the prospect of disclos-
ing embarrassing news. One may, of course, disagree with me about how
a firm should respond to this predicament. If my argument so far is cor-
rect, then the best way of doing so acknowledges the relevance of norms
of self-defense, arguing that an analogy with “House Sale” is strong: that
because no feasible strategy of precommitment to silence is available, the
right of self-defense warrants making misleading statements.
DECEPTIVE WRONGS
No doubt some, taking a position I will call moral purism, would react
differently to the prospect of intrusive queries in competitive contexts
like “House Sale” and “Centel,” saying that because deception is inherently
wrong, no matter how much it might cost to forswear it, one should not
deceive. In important respects, moral purism resembles pacifism, which
finds wrong in all intentional violence. Something is true in pacifism.
Deception and Trust 151
Thomas L. Carson
Conceptual questions about the nature of lying and deception are prior
to questions about the moral status of lying and deception. Any theory
about the moral status of lying (or deception) presupposes an account of
what lying (or deception) is.
This essay offers definitions of the concepts of lying and deception
and explains the distinctions between lying, deception, withholding infor-
mation, “keeping someone in the dark,” bullshit, spin, and half-truths.
In section 1, I propose a definition of lying. Roughly, a lie is a deliber-
ate false statement that the speaker warrants to be true. Three features
of my definition are noteworthy. First, I argue that standard dictionary
definitions overlook a necessary condition of lying, namely, that the liar
cannot believe that the statement she makes is true. Second, contrary to
most standard definitions, I argue that lying does not require that the liar
intends to deceive others. (I appeal to cases in which one is compelled or
enticed to make false statements, cases of lying in which one can benefit
by making false statements, even if they don’t deceive others, and cases
of bald-faced lies in which the liar knows that others know she is lying
and therefore has no hope or intention of deceiving them.) Third, I hold
that in order to tell a lie, one must make a statement that one warrants to
be true. According to my definition, any lie violates an implicit promise
or guarantee that what one says is true. My definition makes sense of the
common view that lying involves a breach of trust. To lie, on my view, is
to invite others to trust and rely on what one says by warranting its truth
and, at the same time, to betray that trust by making a false statement that
one does not believe to be true.
In section 2, I propose a definition of deception and discuss the rela-
tionship between deception, withholding information, and keeping some-
one in the dark. Roughly, deception is intentionally causing someone to
have false beliefs. This definition is close to the mark. However, it needs
to be qualified to deal with cases such as the following. I intentionally
cause you to believe statement X and X is false, but I neither believe
that X is true nor believe that X is false. (In this case I do not cause you
to believe a statement that I believe to be false.) There are two main
153
154 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
believe that what he says is false (or not believe that it is true) suggest the
following definition of lying:
L1. A person S tells a lie iff: 1. S makes a false statement x, 2. S believes
that x is false or probably false (or, alternatively, S doesn’t believe that x is
true), and 3. S intends to deceive another person by means of stating x (by
stating x, S intends to cause another person to have false beliefs).4
4. Linda Coleman and Paul Kay argue that these three conditions give us an account of
central or paradigm cases of lying. According to Coleman and Kay, anything that satisfies
all three conditions is clearly a lie. However, when a statement satisfies only two of the
three conditions, it is not clear whether or not it counts as a case of lying. Linda Coleman
and Paul Kay, “Prototype Semantics: The English Verb ‘Lie.’ ” Language 57 (1981), 26–44.
Arnold Isenberg defines a lie as a statement that one believes to be false and is intended
to deceive others, “Deontology and the Ethics of Lying,” Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research 24 (1964), 465–80. Isenberg’s definition is equivalent to L1 without the
stipulation of condition 1 that statement x is false. Bernard Williams proposes a definition
of lying very similar to Isenberg’s. Williams’s definition is as follows: “I take a lie to be an
assertion, the content of which the speaker believes to be false, which is made with the
intention to deceive the hearer with regard to its content”; Truth and Truthfulness: An Essay
in Genealogy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002), 98. Unlike Isenberg, Williams
stipulates that the liar must intend to deceive others about the content of the statement
in question. Isenberg and Williams’s definitions are very similar to the following definition
that Sissela Bok attributes to Augustine: “having one thing in one’s heart and uttering
another with the intention to deceive”; Lying (New York: Pantheon Book, 1978), 33. Bok
herself defines a lie as “any intentionally deceptive message which is stated,” 13.
158 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
so much at odds with ordinary language. Using the term “lying” in accor-
dance with this definition is likely to engender confusion. Defenders of
L2 face a very strong burden of proof. Pragmatic considerations also seem
to weigh against this definition of lying. Definition L2 makes it impossible
for us to determine whether or not certain acts are lies until we have first
resolved difficult and controversial moral questions (about whether or
not someone has a right to know the truth). 7 It is a matter of consider-
able controversy exactly when other people do and do not have a right to
know the truth about particular matters. If we accept L2 (or any similar
definition), then we can’t call a statement a lie unless we have reason to
think that the audience has a right to know the truth. There are good
pragmatic reasons for us to use the concept of lying to help point out
and distinguish between salient features of actions and thereby assist us
in making moral judgments. In order to serve this purpose, the concept of
lying must be defined independently of controversial moral assumptions.
Some people endorse definitions such as L2 in order to defend the
absolutist view that lying is always wrong. (I don’t know of any other rea-
sons to accept L2). However, L2 does not rule out ostensibly clear cases
of morally permissible lying. Consider the following example. A man has
just had open heart surgery and is temporarily in a precarious state of
health. His surgeon says that he must be shielded from any emotional
distress for the next few days. Unbeknownst to the patient, his only child,
Bob, has been killed in an automobile accident. When the patient awakens
after the surgery, he is surprised that Bob isn’t there and he asks, “Where
is Bob?” You fear that in his condition, the shock of learning about Bob’s
death might cause the man to die. So you lie and say that his son has been
delayed, all the while firmly intending to tell him the truth and apologize
for lying when he is out of danger. Given appropriate qualifications, it is
morally permissible to lie to the patient. Definition L2 doesn’t exclude
this as a case of lying—surely the father has a right to know the truth
about his son’s death. This seems to be a case of morally permissible lying
that violates someone’s right to know the truth. Not every case of making
a false statement to save the life of an innocent person is a case of making a
false statement to someone who has no right to know the truth.
7. See Bok, Lying, 14–15. Bernard Williams also argues against attempts to construe
the concept of lying very narrowly in order to make plausible the view that lying is always
wrong no matter what the consequences; see Truth and Truthfulness, 105.
Lying, Deception, and Related Concepts 161
students are guilty whenever they are charged. A student is caught in the
act of cheating on an exam by copying from a crib sheet. The professor
fails the student for the course, and the student appeals the professor’s
decision to the dean, who has the ultimate authority to assign the grade.
The student is privy to information about the dean’s de facto policy and,
when called before the dean, he (the student) affirms that he didn’t cheat
on the exam. He claims that he was not copying from the crib sheet. He
claims that he inadvertently forgot to put his “review sheet” away when the
exam began and that he never looked at it during the exam. The student
says this on the record in an official proceeding and thereby warrants the
truth of statements he knows to be false. He intends to avoid punishment
by doing this. He may have no intention of deceiving the dean that he
didn’t cheat. (If he is really hard-boiled, he may take pleasure in thinking
that the dean knows that he is guilty.) An objector might continue and say
that surely the student intends to deceive someone—his parents or future
employers. However, this isn’t necessarily the case. The student may not
care whether or not others know that he cheated (he might freely and
cynically tell others about his cheating) but simply want to have his grade
changed. (If it helps, suppose that the will of a deceased relative calls
for the student to inherit a great deal of money if he graduates from the
college in question with a certain grade-point average.) These two cases
of lying without intending to deceive others are crucial for my argument
in this article. Later (section 1.10), I will return to these two cases and
explain why my definition counts them both as cases of lying.
Let me digress briefly to explain the notion of an intentional act.
Roughly, the intended consequences of an act are those that one either
(1) aims at for their own sake, or (2) foresees and regards as part of a
causal chain leading to consequences that one desires or aims at for their
own sake.8 Consider the following example. The leader of nation X plans
an air attack on armaments factories in nation Y. The ultimate aim of the
attack is to end the death and suffering caused by the war. The leader of X
regards the destruction of these factories as a necessary means to ending
the war and the attendant suffering. The leader foresees that the attack
will kill civilians living in areas adjacent to the factories. 9 The death of
these people is not a means that (causally) contributes to the goal of end-
ing the war. Rather, it is an unavoidable “side effect” of the bombing. This
consequence is not “intended” but merely foreseen. “Terror bombing,” on
8. See Alvin Goldman, A Theory of Human Action (Englewood Cliffs, N. J.: Prentice-
Hall, 1970), ch. 3; and Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars (New York: Harper and Row,
1977), 153–56. Traditional “just war theory” makes much of the distinction between what
is intended and what is merely foreseen. This distinction also has a very important place in
scholastic ethics and is central to the “doctrine of the double effect.”
9. Franklin Roosevelt and American military leaders were acting in exactly this way
when they ordered massive precision daylight bombing attacks on German armaments
factories and other military targets during World War II.
162 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
the other hand, involves the intention to kill innocent civilians. Suppose
that the leader of a nation at war orders the bombing of an enemy city.
She aims to end the war by demoralizing the civilian population of the
enemy country.10 Demoralizing the civilian population is to be accom-
plished by killing large numbers of civilians. Here, the killing of the civil-
ians is not just a side effect but an essential part of the causal chain leading
to the ultimate goal of the bombing. Leaders who order the bombing of
cities for these reasons intend to kill civilians. (This holds even if the lead-
ers in question don’t desire the killing of the civilians as an end in itself
and even if they deeply regret the killing of the civilians.)
10. The British night-time attacks on German cities and the American firebombing
and nuclear attacks on Japanese cities at the end of World War II aimed at killing innocent
civilians as a means to demoralizing the enemy and thereby diminishing their will to
continue fighting. In this sense, it is arguable that Churchill, Roosevelt, and Truman were
all “terrorists.”
11. Thomas Feehan and Roderick Chisholm, “The Intent to Deceive,” Journal of
Philosophy 74 (March 1977), 152. Chisholm and Feehan note that their definition
is “essentially the same as that proposed by Frege” (152). They quote the following
definition of lying from Frege: “In ‘A lied in saying that he had seen B’, the subordinate
clause designates a thought which is said (1) to have been asserted by A (2) while A was
convinced of its falsity.” “Über Sinn und Bedeutung,” in Translations from the Philosophical
Writings of Gottlob Frege, ed. Peter Geach and Max Black (Oxford: Blackwell, 1952), 66.
Charles Fried defends a very similar definition (he acknowledges his debt to Chisholm and
Feehan): “A person lies when he asserts a proposition which he believes to be false”; Right
and Wrong, (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1978), 55; also see 59. He claims
that in order to assert a proposition one must intend that it be believed (56–57). His
definition implies that the intent to deceive others is a necessary condition of lying and is,
therefore, open to the sort of objection presented above.
12. “Intent to Deceive,” 152.
Lying, Deception, and Related Concepts 163
ironically, one plays oneself down, but one gives a “signal of irony”—perhaps
by means of tone and choice of words—and this signal indicates that one is
not to be taken seriously and hence one is not making an assertion.13
17. “My Basic Logical Insights,” in Posthumous Writings, trans. P. Long and R. White
(Oxford: Blackwell, 1959), 151.
18. “Facts and Propositions,” in Ramsey, The Foundations of Mathematics, (London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1931), 142.
19. Analysis 9 (1949), 83–97.
Lying, Deception, and Related Concepts 165
having an extramarital affair and you deny it. My responding with “But it’s
true that she is having an affair” can constitute a stronger, more emphatic
response than simply repeating “she is having an affair.” In many border-
line cases, it is unclear whether or not making a statement involves war-
ranting its truth. In such cases, saying that x is true warrants the truth of
x, but merely saying that x (without saying that x is true) does not. For
example, suppose that I know of a humorous and improbable fact about
Judy. I wish to state this fact and warrant its truth in the context of a
humorous “bull session.” Simply stating the fact in this situation probably
is not warranting its truth. In order to accomplish this, it may be neces-
sary for me to say something like “It’s true that ; I’m not kidding.”
Strawson’s criticisms of the very strong version of the transparency thesis
according to which “x” and “it’s true that x” can always be used inter-
changeably are consistent with my view that, in ordinary contexts, the
expression “it’s true that” adds nothing to the meaning of a statement. The
fact that saying “it’s true that x” sometimes is a stronger warranty of the
truth of x than just saying “x” is consistent with my view that, ordinarily, a
person who states something warrants its truth (indeed, this fact presup-
poses the truth of my view).
20. See John Searle, “How to Derive ‘Ought’ from ‘Is,’ ” in Theories of Ethics, ed.
Philippa Foot (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1968), 103–4. The default warranty of
truth is an example of what Paul Grice calls a “conversational implicature.” Like other
conversational implicatures, it is governed by rules and expectations understood by
language users. See Paul Grice, Studies in the Way of Words (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1989), chs. 2 and 3.
166 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
analysis that they count as such.22 Many instances of bluffing are border-
line cases of warranting/lying.23
22. It might be argued that the notion of warranting makes implicit appeal to the
notion of intention. It has been suggested to me that “to warrant the truth of a statement
is to make an utterance under conditions where normally the speaker intends that others
believe him.” This suggests that I have removed the notion of the intention to deceive
from the concept of lying only to smuggle it back in under the rubric of the concept
of warranting. Normally, we intend that others believe our statements. It is difficult to
imagine how it could be the case that the use of language involves the default warranty
of truth if this were not the case. There would be no point in warranting the truth of what
we say unless we sometimes intended that others believe what we say. There would be
no point in having a default presumption that any given statement is warranted to be true
unless we usually intended that others believe what we say. (The [or a] purpose of having
such a warranty is to make it more likely that people will believe what we say.) I accept all
of this, but it leaves untouched my earlier objection to the standard dictionary definitions
of lying. According to these definitions, a particular statement on a particular occasion
cannot be a lie unless the person who makes it intends thereby to mislead others. I believe
that I have shown this to be untenable.
23. See my essay “Second Thoughts on Bluffing,” Business Ethics Quarterly 3 (1993),
317–41.
168 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
reliance on what is stated, even if the liar hopes and knows that her audi-
ence won’t believe or rely on her statements.
The cases presented in section 1.5 illustrate several distinct sorts of rea-
sons one can have for lying in such cases. It might be the case that one will
benefit simply by making the false statement in question, for example, by
receiving a bribery payment or avoiding a harm that was threatened. So,
one might lie by making a false statement in order to receive the benefit
or avoid the harm. In addition, one might lie in order to “go on record” as
saying something. The student in my earlier example from section 1.5 lies
in order to go on record claiming to be innocent. He does this because
he knows that this will make it less likely that he will be punished for
cheating.
Convention dictates that there are circumstances that remove the
default warranty of the truth for our statements. The great majority of the
cases in which the warranty of truth does not hold involve storytelling
or attempts to be humorous. Indeed, it is difficult to think of statements
that are not warranted as true that do not involve either storytelling or
humor. In the case of statements that are clearly not intended be humor-
ous or tell a story, the default warranty of truth is very strong. The stu-
dent’s statement to the dean is such a case. If the student’s response to the
dean’s questions include obvious winks and nods and unguarded nervous
laughter, then the warranty of truth may be removed (or at least it is cast
into doubt).24 However, if the student “plays it straight” and looks grave
and serious, then his statements are warranted to be true and count as lies
according to my definition. It is not paradoxical or contradictory for me
to promise you that a statement is true, when I know that you know that
I know it isn’t true. I can promise you something, even if you and I both
know that I won’t keep the promise; I can also make a promise to you in
bad faith even if I know that you know that I am making the promise
in bad faith. In such a case, my promise invites your reliance, but you
would not be justified in relying on what I say. Thus, my warranting the
truth of something I say to you justifies you in complaining to me if it isn’t
true, even though it doesn’t always justify you in relying on it.
Whether or not a person warrants the truth of what she says on a
given occasion depends on the context and the relevant local conventions
embedded in that context. Far too many possible contextual factors are
relevant for it to be possible to state necessary and sufficient conditions
for warranting the truth of a statement. However, the following observa-
tions help explicate the notion of warranting the truth of a statement.
24. It might not be possible for the student to lie to the dean with the intention of
causing him to disbelieve what he says by accompanying his statement with a series of
winks and nods. The winks and nods may remove the default warranty of truth. For my
purposes, I don’t need to deny this. I only need to claim that it is possible to lie without any
intention of deceiving others (about the truth of what one is saying, or about one’s own
sincerity, or anything else).
Lying, Deception, and Related Concepts 169
country tells me a very bizarre story on April Fool’s Day. I don’t know
whether he knows anything about American practices and understand-
ings about April Fool’s Day. In the absence of other contextual clues, it
is unclear whether he warrants the truth of what he says. Suppose that a
professor is well known for her animated, humorous, and Socratic style of
teaching. She often says false things to her classes to see if they are atten-
tive. When she does this, she berates her students if they fail to catch her.
She begins her lecture with an improbable-sounding historical anecdote.
In this context, it is unclear whether the professor warrants the truth of
what she says. In the course of Socratic classroom debates in which pro-
fessors play the devil’s advocate, it is often unclear whether they warrant
the truth of what they say—philosophy classrooms are rife with this kind
of ambiguity.
This sort of ambiguity is increased if the speaker (writer) and the audi-
ence are members of different societies that have different conventions
and expectations about truth-telling and warranting the truth of state-
ments. There are often contexts in which one party expects that what is
said is warranted to be true and the other party does not.25
25. J. A. Barnes gives numerous examples of this; see Pack of Lies, 114, and elsewhere.
26. Alternatively, we could say that in order to lie one must believe that one is
warranting the truth of what one says. I believe that my condition 4 is preferable to this
alternative condition, because there are many cases of lying in which the liar has no
conscious beliefs about whether or not she is warranting what she says.
170 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
27. Chisholm and Feehan also relativize the concept of lying in this way. Their
definition is a definition of what it is for one to lie to a particular person. Although they
don’t explicitly say this, their definition allows for the possibility that one and the same
statement could be a case of lying to one person but not a case of lying to the other.
28. Those who don’t share my view that a lie must be a false statement might wish to
modify L5 as follows:
L5'. A person S tells a lie to another person S1 iff: 1. S makes a statement x
to S1, 2. S believes that x is false or probably false (or, alternatively, S doesn’t
believe that x is true), 3. S states x in a context in which S thereby warrants the
truth of x to S1, and 4. S does not take herself to be not warranting the truth of
what she says to S1.
172 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
by all that the answer needs to be extremely accurate and precise (e.g., an
engineer at a radio station who needs to know when to begin broadcasting
a program or an astronaut who needs to know when to begin a maneuver)
then my statement is false. On the other hand, if I am asked this question
by my wife while taking a leisurely walk on our vacation when neither
of us needs to know exactly what time it is, my answer should count as a
true statement. My concept of warranting proves useful for dealing with
this issue. In some contexts, one warrants what one says as true to a high
degree of accuracy and precision. In other contexts, statements are not
warranted to be true to a high degree of accuracy.
Some hold that a necessary condition for telling a lie is that commu-
nication actually occurs, that is, that what is said is actually conveyed or
communicated to another person.29 (This could also be construed as a
necessary condition for making a statement.) According to this view, I can
attempt to lie, but fail, if I don’t communicate successfully. Suppose that
I speak to someone and intentionally say something that is false in a situa-
tion in which I know that I am warranting the truth of what I say. On the
view in question, my utterance can’t be a lie unless I succeed in communi-
cating with the other person. If the person to whom I am speaking is deaf
or doesn’t speak the language I am using, then I haven’t succeeded in mak-
ing a statement to her and I cannot be said to have lied to her (although
I attempted to). Or, to take another example, suppose that I am talking
to you in a different room of a house so that we can’t see each other. The
conversation stops for half an hour. After this interval, I intentionally say
something I know to be false intending to warrant the truth of what I say.
But, unbeknownst to me, you have left the house (you are many miles
away) and do not hear what I say. I am inclined to think that in this case
I didn’t lie to you, although I intended to. Others report very different
intuitions about this case. I don’t have any decisive arguments that settle
this question. In any case, we can leave the definition of lying as it is. To
endorse my definition, we don’t need to settle the question of whether
making a (false) statement requires that one succeeds in communicating
with another. This question concerns the proper interpretation of the first
condition of the definition. The question is whether successfully commu-
nicating with another person is necessary for making a statement.30
29. For example, Frederick Siegler, “Lying,” American Philosophical Quarterly 3 (1966),
128–36, and Fried, Right and Wrong, 57.
30. There are some related issues and puzzles that should be briefly noted here. What
should we say about statements that are successfully conveyed to others, but only long
after they are made? Suppose that a historical figure writes many false things in his diary in
the hope of misleading future readers and historians. The diary isn’t read by anyone until a
hundred years later. When he writes this, can we say that he is lying? Can we say that he is
lying, but that his lying (now) depends on what will happen in the future? Suppose that a
politician writes a false account in his diary hoping to mislead future historians. The diary
is later destroyed, and no one else ever reads it. Should we say that he intended to lie but
failed to because his statements were never successfully conveyed to anyone else?
Lying, Deception, and Related Concepts 173
31. Bill Tolhurst was the first of several who made this suggestion to me.
32. Right and Wrong, 56.
174 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
S utters sentence “S,” where “S” means that P, in doing which either he
expresses his belief that P, or he intends the person addressed to take it
that he believes that P.33
When combined with L6, this definition of assertion implies that, in order
to lie to you in stating proposition X, I must state X to you in condi-
tions that I believe justify you in believing that I accept X and intend to
contribute to your believing that I accept X. As I have shown, however, a
notoriously dishonest person can lie to you in stating X even if he knows
that you are not justified in believing that he accepts X and he knows that
you are not justified in believing that he aims or intends to cause you to
believe that he believes that X.
35. Barnes, Pack of Lies, defends this claim at length and gives numerous examples.
36. See Barnes, Pack of Lies, 113.
37. Barnes, Pack of Lies, 166.
38. Barnes, Pack of Lies, 15, and 113–14.
39. Barnes gives numerous examples of this; see 114 and elsewhere in Pack of Lies.
176 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
same time, to betray that trust by making false statements that one does
not believe.40
2. DECEPTION
40. See Chisholm and Feehan: “The liar would have his victim believe that, at the
moment at least, the liar is someone in whom he may place his faith. Thus we may say,
with St. Augustine: “No liar preserves faith in that about which he lies. He wishes that he
to whom he lies have faith in him, but he does not preserve faith by lying to him” (“Intent
to Deceive,” 152). (The quotation from Augustine appears in “Christian Instruction,” in
Fathers of the Church, vol. 2, Writings of St. Augustine, vol. 4, trans. John Gavigan [New
York: CIMA, 1947], 57.) Also see Fried, Right and Wrong: “A lie invites belief in an
assertion which the speaker knows to be false,” 57.
41. New York: Oxford University Press, 1993.
Lying, Deception, and Related Concepts 177
This is much closer to the mark than the previous definition, but sev-
eral questions remain. What if I intentionally cause you to believe that
x where x is false and I neither believe that x is true nor believe that x
is false? For example, suppose that I want you to believe x where x is
false and I haven’t given any thought to the question of whether x is true
or false. (Such statements are characteristic of bullshit.) 43 If we want to
count this as a case of deception, we should reject D1 in favor of some-
thing like the following:
42. Al Mele, for one, claims that it is possible to deceive others unintentionally; see his
Self-Deception Unmasked (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001), 8–9.
43. Harry Frankfurt claims that lack of concern for the truth and falsity is one of the
most salient features of bullshitters. On Bullshit (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
2005), 33–34, 47–48, and 56–57.
178 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
D2. A person S deceives another person S1 if, and only if, S intentionally
causes S1 to believe x, where x is false and S does not believe that x is true.44
44. The distinction between D1 and D2 closely parallels the distinction I discussed in
section 1.2 between the view that a necessary condition of telling a lie is that one makes
a false statement that one believes is false (or believes is probably false) and the view that
a necessary condition of telling a lie is that one makes a false statement that one doesn’t
believe to be true.
45. This needs to be qualified in light of the next paragraph; D1' (later) gives sufficient
conditions for deception.
Lying, Deception, and Related Concepts 179
beliefs about this are vague and incomplete. In this case, I have prevented
you from gaining certain information. However, I haven’t caused you to
acquire any false beliefs and, therefore, I haven’t deceived you about any-
thing. Preventing someone from learning the truth about X is not the same
as causing her to have false beliefs about X (deceiving her about X).
We need a term other than “deception” to describe cases of preventing
others from learning the truth. The English expression that most closely
describes this is “keeping someone in the dark.” Intentionally and actively
preventing someone from learning something counts as keeping him in
the dark. Sometimes withholding information or failing to correct a per-
son’s false beliefs counts as keeping her in the dark. A lawyer keeps her
client in the dark if she fails to inform him that a certain course of action
she is advising him to take is likely to result in his being the subject of a
lawsuit. However, not every case of failing to correct another person’s false
beliefs or remove his ignorance about something one knows about counts
as “keeping someone in dark.” (I am not keeping my neighbor in the dark if
I fail to inform her about my past membership in the Cub Scouts.)
Here is a first stab at a definition of “keeping someone in the dark” (this
is both a proposal and an attempt to fit with ordinary language):
A person S keeps another person S1 in the dark about X (where X is
something that S1 doesn’t know) if, and only if, either: 1. S actively and
intentionally prevents S1 from learning about X, or 2. S fails to inform
S1 about X when either: (1) S knows that S1 wants the information in
question and S can easily give it to S1, or (2) S occupies a role or position
in which he is expected to provide S1 with the sort of information in
question.
Suppose that I attempt to prevent you from discovering the truth by caus-
ing you to be less diligent in your pursuit of the evidence or by tempo-
rarily diminishing your cognitive functioning. For example, suppose that
you are a detective working on a murder case. I know that my daughter
Astrid is guilty of the crime. But there is strong prima facie evidence that
John committed the murder, and no one suspects Astrid. Unless you are
diligent and alert, you will not suspect Astrid and will probably come to
believe that John is the murderer. I might try to cause you to believe that
John is guilty by causing you to have a bad night’s sleep or by tempting
you to get drunk with me. Suppose that I succeed in this. I get you drunk
and make noise during the night to cause you a very bad night’s sleep. The
next day you are hung over and very tired. As a result, you overlook key
clues about Astrid and come to believe that John is guilty. Suppose that
you would have discovered the truth were it not for my actions. In this
case, I have deceived you (in a very indirect way) about John’s guilt and
Astrid’s innocence. My actions intend and bring it about that you believe
falsely that John is guilty and Astrid is innocent.
Briefly consider a variation on this case. I don’t try to cause you to have
false beliefs about Astrid but just try to prevent you from acquiring true
beliefs about her. Suppose that you are unaware of Astrid’s existence. I want
180 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
to prevent you from learning the truth (that she is guilty), but I am not try-
ing to cause you to have any false beliefs about Astrid (that she is innocent),
since my purposes are served equally well if you remain unaware of her
existence. If I cause you to believe that John is guilty in order to protect
Astrid, I am deceiving you about John’s guilt and keeping you in the dark
about Astrid’s guilt, but I am not deceiving you about her guilt.
One last puzzle. Consider the following case. I intentionally tamper
with and alter the relevant evidence in order to try to cause you to believe
X when I know that X is false. Unbeknownst to me, you already believe
X. I don’t cause you to believe X, but I strengthen your belief that X. At
a later date, you acquire prima facie evidence for thinking that X is false.
You persist in believing X, but you would have ceased to believe X were it
not for my past action. Is this deception? Have I deceived you about X? It
is unclear what we should say about this case. Tentatively, I would say the
following. At the time I act, I haven’t deceived you into believing that X,
since I did not cause you to believe X. However, my actions will deceive
you into believing X at a later date.
My definition comes fairly close to capturing how most people use
the word “deception.” Since not everyone shares the same linguistic intu-
itions about how the word “deception” should be used, no definition of
deception can be consistent with everyone’s linguistic intuitions. There
are good pragmatic reasons to accept my definition. The concepts of lying
and deception are important from the moral point of view because they
help us pick out morally salient features of actions and classify different
types of actions. It is helpful to classify or categorize different types of
actions before we assess them morally. It is not helpful to assess the moral
status of deception or any other class of actions without first clearly delin-
eating that class of actions. The morally salient feature of deception is that
it involves intentionally causing others to have false beliefs. My concepts
of misleading others (causing others to have false beliefs) and deceiving
others (intentionally causing others to have false beliefs) pick out morally
salient features of actions and help facilitate normative assessments of
action. This is a distinction we should mark in some way. There is a clear
distinction between withholding information and deception. There is also
a clear distinction between intentionally preventing others from learning
the truth and deception.
46. Here, Frankfurt’s view would more plausible if he said “intends to deceive us about”
instead of “deceives us about.” Succeeding in deceiving others is not a necessary condition
for bullshit. One can bullshit others even if the fact that one is bullshitting is apparent to
them.
47. Frankfurt, On Bullshit, 54.
48. Ibid., 17–18. Frankfurt describes bullshit as a form of bluffing. He says that bluffing
is a mode “of misrepresentation or deception” (46). Also see 12 and 14.
49. Frankfurt, On Bullshit, 19.
Lying, Deception, and Related Concepts 183
not willing to nominate anyone who supports Roe v. Wade. She firmly
intends to nominate only people who oppose abortion and the Roe v.
Wade decision and has privately promised some antiabortion leaders that
she will do this. Answering the question truthfully is likely to cost her the
votes of many people who support abortion. Lying and saying that she
would be willing to nominate someone who supports abortion and Roe
v. Wade would cost her the votes of many people who oppose abortion.
The candidate wishes that the question had not been asked and gives the
following bullshit reply that completely fails to answer or address the
question that was asked: “Look, there are lots of things to be taken into
account when nominating someone for the Supreme Court. This isn’t
the only relevant consideration. I want someone with a good legal mind
and judicial experience who supports my judicial philosophy of follow-
ing the constitution as it is written.” (Note that the question does not ask
whether a potential nominee’s views about abortion are the only relevant
considerations. Rather, it asks whether the candidate will make opposi-
tion to abortion and Roe v. Wade a necessary condition for nominating
someone for the court.)
Similar examples of evasion by means of bullshit occur when people
are asked to testify in court or in other semilegal proceedings. Suppose
that I am a witness in court and am asked a question about a friend who
committed a crime I witnessed. An honest answer will incriminate him;
lying will make me guilty of perjury. Refusing to testify will make me
guilty of contempt of court. In this situation, resorting to evasive bullshit
is an attractive option for me.
Bullshit does not require the intention to deceive. Some cases of evasive
bullshit don’t involve the intention to deceive others. In cases of evasion,
we often want to deceive others and make them think we are answering
or trying to answer their questions. Witnesses and politicians who engage
in evasive bullshitting typically intend that others (mistakenly) believe
that they are trying to answer their questions. However, not all cases of
evasion by means of bullshit involve the intent to deceive in this way.
There are some cases in which one is rewarded for making a performance
in response to a question; in some of these cases, one will be rewarded
for saying almost anything rather than saying nothing. There are cases in
which one knows that one can obtain rewards for bullshit responses to
questions without deceiving other people about anything (including the
fact that what one says is pure bullshit). Consider the following example.
I am a student who needs to receive a good grade in a class. I am assigned
to write a short essay on a very clearly and precisely defined topic. I know
nothing about the topic and can’t write on it at all. But I know that my
instructor will give me partial credit for turning in something, however
incompetent and far off the topic. The worst grade I can receive for writing
something that is completely incompetent and off the topic is an F—60
percent. If I write nothing, I will receive a zero—0 percent. In producing
a bullshit answer, I am not attempting to mislead my teacher about my
Lying, Deception, and Related Concepts 185
55. Here is an example of such an answer. A student is asked the following question
on an exam for an applied ethics class: “Briefly describe the facts of the case of Dodge v.
Ford and answer the following question: Was Henry Ford morally justified in his actions
in this case? Defend your answer.” The student hasn’t read the case, nor was she in class
when it was discussed, so she can’t describe the facts of the case. Since she doesn’t know
what Henry Ford did in the case of Dodge v. Ford, she can’t possibly formulate a coherent
argument for thinking that he was or was not morally justified in what he did. She
gives the following bullshit answer: “In today’s society there are many important ethical
questions about the role of business in the larger society. These are important questions
since business and its actions play such a large role in today’s society. We have addressed
these questions in our class. Milton Friedman holds that the only obligation of business is
to make money for the shareholders, provided that it avoids fraud, deception, and unfair
competition. R. Edward Freeman holds that corporations should be run for the benefit of
all their ‘stakeholders.’ Utilitarians hold that corporations should promote the social good.
The Ford Motor company had many obligations in this case. In this case, I think that the
obligation to society was the most important obligation. The company failed to live up
to this obligation, to an extent, but this is not a black or white issue. In any case, Henry
Ford didn’t adequately fulfill his duty to the public.” In the sort of case I have described, a
student could produce this kind of bullshit answer without intending to deceive anyone.
186 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
writes are false, she will be marked down. In that case, she will be very
careful to write only things that are true and accurate, even though she
knows that what she writes is not an answer to the question.
A politician who gives evasive bullshit answers to difficult questions
might still be concerned with the truth of what he says. Suppose that
he fears that the media will dissect his every public word and catch him
in false and inaccurate statements. In that case, he will care very much
whether what he says is true. Not only will he carefully craft evasive
bullshit statements and answers, he will be careful to make sure that what
he says is true.
Similarly, the witness in court who gives evasive bullshit answers may
be very concerned to say only things that are true so that he can avoid
charges of perjury. Contrary to Frankfurt’s claim that bullshitters are not
concerned with whether the statements they make are true or false,56 the
bullshitting witness may be very concerned with the truth value of his
statements.
Some bullshit deceives others and much bullshit is intended to deceive
others, but contrary to what Frankfurt says, some bullshit is not intended
to deceive others. One can bullshit even if one knows that one’s bullshit-
ting is completely transparent to others. One can lie without bullshitting,
and most bullshitting does not involve lying, but, Frankfurt to the con-
trary, one can produce bullshit while lying. Although Frankfurt’s claim
that bullshitters are unconcerned with the truth of what they say is an
apt and insightful description of much bullshit, some bullshitters are con-
cerned with the truth of what they say. Therefore, Frankfurt’s claim that
unconcern with the truth of what one says is the essence of bullshit is
mistaken. I don’t have a better alternative definition of bullshit that I am
prepared to defend. I suspect that the concept of bullshit is too loose and
amorphous to admit of a definition in terms of necessary and sufficient
conditions. Frankfurt, himself, says as much. 57 To paraphrase Frankfurt’s
own hopes for his account of bullshit, it is “helpful” (very helpful indeed)
but not “decisive” (definitive).58
stripes often spin their interpretation of events so that those events seem
consistent with their ideological commitments. Sometimes the interpre-
tations they spin are correct but sometimes not. If someone spins the
interpretation of an event, then his interpretation is biased and unreliable,
but not necessarily incorrect.
One common way of spinning events involves asserting “half-truths.”
Half-truths are true statements or sets of true statements that selectively
emphasize facts that tend to support a particular interpretation or assess-
ment of an issue and selectively ignore, or minimize, other relevant facts
that tend to support contrary assessments. For example, a politician spins
the interpretation of recent events to support the claim that his policies
were successful if he describes the good consequences of those policies in
great and vivid detail and omits any mention of their bad consequences.
A man’s description of his marriage to a friend (or the description he gives
to himself) is a half-truth if it contains a long and accurate account of
unkind and hurtful things that his wife has said and done to him but men-
tions only a few of the equal (or greater) number of unkind and hurtful
things he has said and done to her. Statements or narratives that involve
spin can be misleading if they advance unreasonable interpretations of
events and incline other people to accept those interpretations. Mislead-
ing spin counts as deception if the “spinner” knows or believes that the
interpretation he defends is unreasonable/implausible. If spin involves
making deliberate false claims about one’s state of mind (how one thinks
events should be interpreted), it usually involves lying. Even when there
is no lying or deception involved, spinning often calls into question one’s
intellectual honesty. Often we spin evidence to protect our cherished
beliefs when that evidence ought to cause us to question those beliefs.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I am greatly indebted to many friends and colleagues for helpful criticisms and
suggestions about numerous earlier versions of this chapter. Thanks to Joe Men-
dola, Bruce Russell, Bill Tolhurst, Mike Gorr, Kent Machina, Tom Beauchamp,
George Brenkert, Al Mele, Clancy Martin, J. D. Trout, Mark Chakoian, and Nora
Carson. This article is a shortened version of chapters 1 and 2 of my book Lying
and Deception: Theory and Practice (forthcoming). The first section was published
as “The Definition of Lying,” Nous 40 (April 2005), 284–306. Parts of section 2
(paragraphs 1 and 4–8) are included in my article “Deception and Information
Disclosure in Business and Professional Ethics,” in The Oxford Handbook of Busi-
ness Ethics, ed. Tom Beauchamp and George Brenkert (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, forthcoming).
188 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
10
Michael P. Lynch
Philosophers who worry about the nature of truth rarely worry about
the nature of deception. This is partly due to a sensible division of
labor. When philosophers ask “What is truth?” they take themselves
to be asking about a particular property of our beliefs. Defining that
property—or as is fashionable, claiming that it can’t be defined—is a
matter of metaphysics and the philosophy of language. To talk about
deception or lying on the other hand is to talk about the messy realm
of human interaction. And that is the province of the ethicist. The
general assumption seems to be that the philosophy of deception is
to the philosophy of truth as bioethics is to the philosophy of biology.
Nice stuff to know, undoubtedly important, but really not quite to the
point.
To the layperson, this is apt to seem completely backward. Most
folks, if they think about truth at all, think of deception first and truth
second. Deception, after all, is a real human universal; it knows no
boundaries. Most people are interested in what philosophers say about
truth because they are fascinated by deception, not the other way
around.
In this essay, I will try to say something about both deception and
truth, with an eye toward vindicating the layperson’s sense of what is
important. I think that our attitudes toward deception tell us something
important about both the nature and value of truth. These reflections in
turn underline a more general lesson: that truth is a concept best under-
stood in terms of the role it plays in our overall cognitive life.
This chapter is organized as follows. In part 1, I lay out what I take
deception to be, and argue that, unlike lying, it is conceptually linked
to truth. In part 2, I give some reasons for thinking that certain theories
of truth are implausible in virtue of what they imply about deception.
Since we arguably have a better grip on deception than on truth, this is
bad news for such theories. In part 3, I reflect on what our understanding
of deception tells us about how and why we value truth. I conclude by
drawing out a general lesson from these reflections about the possibility
of giving a meaningful theory of truth.
188
190 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
1. DECEPTION
First there was the Word. And then there was the Lie. Lying is a public act,
an act of speech. Deception, on the other hand, runs the behavioral gamut.
As everyone knows, you can deceive without lying, indeed, without even
speaking: sleight of hand, emotional misdirection, or simply pointing in
the wrong direction (“He went that way”) will do just as well. This line of
thought encourages us to think of lying as a form of deception.
This is understandable, but mistaken. It is understandable since one
can’t define lying without appealing to deception. Lying isn’t just saying
what one doesn’t believe. Actors do that in the course of their profession,
and they aren’t lying, they are acting. To lie is to say what one doesn’t
believe with the intention of deceiving.1 Lying and deception are concep-
tually linked in this way, but in fact lying is not a form of deception. For
one can also lie but not deceive. Lying requires an intention to deceive,
but what is intended may not happen: the listener may not be deceived.
This might happen in two ways. First you might be skeptical and not
believe what the liar says. Second, you might believe what he says but he
inadvertently says what is true. In either case you were lied to, but you
were not deceived.
It is this second case that is most important. Supposed I believe that
the butler killed Col. Mustard in the library with the candlestick. Being
a friend of the butler, I tell you what I think is false—that the butler was
sunning himself in Hawaii at the time. You believe what I say, and take
me to be sincere. But in fact I am mistaken, and the butler was in Hawaii,
as you already know. I have lied: I’ve told you what I thought was false in
order to mislead you. But I didn’t succeed. I wanted to deceive you about
the butler’s whereabouts at the time of the foul deed in question, but you
were not deceived about his whereabouts.
Of course, this is consistent with my deceiving you about something
else. Since you believed that I was sincere, then I have deceived you about
the fact that I wanted to deceive you. I’ve concealed my intentions, as
we say. Indeed, any time I lie to you, and you don’t detect the lie, I have
deceived you about my lying to you. But this is an independent matter
from whether I deceive you about the subject matter of the lie.
So it is wrong to say that lying is a form or kind of deception. One can
lie without deceiving and deceive without lying. We might say that a suc-
cessful lie is a kind of deception. But even here we must be careful. If by
“successful lie” we mean an act that succeeds at being a lie, then as just
1. For a defense of this view of lying, see Michael P. Lynch, True to Life (Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press, 2004). Compare Donald Davidson, “Deception and Division,” in The
Multiple Self, ed. J. Elster (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), 79–93. A
standard conception is Sissela Bok, Lying: Moral Choice in Public and Private Life (New
York: Vintage, 1979); see also Bernard Williams’s treatment in his Truth and Truthfulness
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002), 102–4.
Deception and the Nature of Truth 189
indicated, lies, successful or not, don’t always lead to deception. But if, as
we probably should, we take “successful lie” to mean a lie that succeeds
at doing what the liar intends, then successful lies are a type of deception.
But not all lies, thankfully, are successful.
One way of putting the point I’m making here is that “deceive” is a
success term. I deceive you only insofar as I actually succeed at misleading
you or directing you away from the truth. Moreover, this misleading must
be willful or nonaccidental. This is because those who give us wrong infor-
mation by accident are not deceitful, but simply in error. In the admit-
tedly technical way I will be using the term here, a willful action is one
that is the result of a motivating reason, whether or not one is conscious of
that reason. I can willfully mislead you without doing so with conscious
intention: I may deceive you about Lancelot’s devotion to you because
I desire you for myself, even if I am unaware of my true motivations.2
Likewise, I might deceive myself about your feelings by causing myself to
turn away from the evidence simply because of my unconscious desire to
want your feelings to be other than what they are.
With “willfulness” understood in this very broad way, we can suggest a
particular constraint on deception:
X deceives Y only if X willfully causes Y to have a false belief.
But this is not quite right. I can deceive you even if I don’t cause you
to believe something false.3
Consider the shell game. The con man presents three shells, one of
which has a penny underneath. He moves the shells around and asks you
to pick the shell with the penny. If done right, it looks easy, but isn’t. The
reason is that he distracts you (usually with subtle hand movements) so
that you fail to track the right shell. This causes you to fail to know where
the penny is. But one can lack knowledge without having a false belief.
One can be simply confused, and that is typically the case with such
tricks. You don’t know what to think, and so simply guess. If so, then the
con has succeeded—you’ve been deceived—because then the odds are in
the con man’s favor. This suggests that one can be deceived not only be
believing what is false but by not believing what is true. That is:
X deceives Y only if X willfully causes Y to fail to believe what is true.
But even this isn’t quite right. Can’t I deceive you into believing the
truth? Suppose you believe falsely that Guinevere hates you when in fact
she is madly in love with you. Pretending to be Guinevere, I write you a
love note, you change your mind, and everyone lives happily ever after.
I’ve deceived you but I’ve also caused you to believe what is true; but
what I’ve deceived you about is not the truth I’ve caused you to believe.
I’ve deceived you about who wrote the letter, but I’ve not deceived you
about Guinevere’s devotion. Nonetheless, this teaches us that deception
is always deception with regard to something:
X deceives Y with regard to f only if X willfully causes y to fail to believe
what is true with regard to f.
This is the sort of position you end up with if you define truth in terms
of warranted assertibility or belief, and then adopt Richard Rorty’s posi-
tion that “warrant as a sociological matter, to be ascertained by observing
the reception of S’s statement by her peers.” 4 As Rorty once infamously
put it, truth then becomes a matter of what your peers let you get away
with.
One—among many—reasons to reject the simple consensus view is
that it doesn’t jibe with what we know about our ability to be deceived.
If my earlier reflections on deception were correct, you are deceived only
when someone willfully causes you to not believe what is true. This sug-
gests that on the foregoing theory of truth, there are at least two ways
you might deceive me: by causing me to lack a belief that is otherwise
accepted in my community, or by getting the community to accept some-
thing I don’t. Either way, you willingly cause me to not believe what is
true. But that seems off, to say the least. Suppose I don’t believe you are
honest but you wish to deceive me into thinking you actually are. If by
use of a clever advertising campaign you convince everyone else in my
community that you are honest, peer pressure may eventually cause me
to doubt my previous belief; but if I am stubborn and don’t change my
mind, the mere fact that you have convinced others won’t make you honest,
or my assessment of your character mistaken. You can’t deceive me by
convincing someone else that something is the case.
If this weren’t bad enough, the simple consensus theory entails that
it is impossible to deceive the entire community. According to the view,
if what is accepted within my community is p, then it is true that p.
Thus, the community cannot be caused to be in ignorance or error about
what they accept, for it is by definition true. But of course this is non-
sense. Entire communities can and have been deceived about all sorts of
things.
Most folks—we hope!—don’t take the simple consensus view seriously.
But the foregoing objections are worth noting because they illustrate how
a theory of truth can go awry simply by way of what it implies about the
possibilities for deception. Since we have a better grip on deception than
on truth, a theory of truth that gets deception wrong is, to that degree,
implausible.
The foregoing points also suggest another lesson: that there is a con-
ceptual linkage between how objective an account takes truth to be and
the extent to which the account makes us vulnerable to deception. The
simple reason for this is that the twin hallmarks of objectivity are igno-
rance and error. What we believe may not be true, and what is true we may
not believe. The more room an account leaves for ignorance and error, the
more objective it intuitively counts as being. And since deception is the
willful causing of ignorance and error, this suggests that the more vulner-
able a theory of truth leaves us to deception, the more objective it is. But
the linkage also goes the other way as well: the more objective a theory of
truth, the more vulnerable it leaves us to deception.
To see this second point, consider radical deception. We are vulnerable
to being radically deceived about some matter just when we are vulner-
able to being caused to be in perpetual and undiscoverable ignorance or
error about it. Consider a traditional correspondence theory according
to which truth consists in correspondence with mind-independent fact.
Such theories are nonepistemic: whether a belief corresponds to the facts
does not depend in any way on whether we believe, justifiably or not,
that it does. Humans do seem vulnerable to radical deception if truth is
radically nonepistemic. For if truth has nothing to do with the epistemic
status of our beliefs, then we might be deceived in trusting even our best
theories of the world. We may be deceived by the Cartesian demon, or
be brains in vats. Hence, it may seem that we can’t be sure that we really
know what we think we know. Thus the usual complaint against cor-
respondence, nonepistemic theories of truth: they make us vulnerable to
Deception and the Nature of Truth 193
5. For a similar point linking skepticism and realism, see J. Heil, “Mind and
Knowledge,” in Oxford Handbook on Epistemology, ed. P. Moser (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2002), 316–35.
6. See Wright’s Truth and Objectivity (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,
1992). His term is “superassertibility.” I use “superwarrant” both because my account of the
notion is a bit different from his own, and because I find it a more perspicuous label.
194 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
This claim is clearly distinct from (P). Nonetheless, it has some of the
same consequences. In particular, it rules out the possibility of radical
deception. For (SW) and our account of superwarrant seemingly under-
write the claim that
If <p> is superwarranted, <p> is knowable.
This is just to draw out the obvious: that any account of truth like (SW),
which defines truth partly in terms of warrant or a belief’s epistemic sta-
tus, will have to admit that truth is “epistemically constrained.” But now
it is a simple matter to show that any such theory limits the possibilities
for radical deception. For if we accept that if p, it is knowable that p, then
presumably we should also accept the following:
If <p> is knowable, then p is not something about which reflective
humans may remain perpetually and undetectably ignorant.
But if the fact that p is not something about which reflective humans
may remain forever ignorant, then it is not something about which we can
be eternally deceived. We are immune from radical deception because at
some point, to someone, the truth will out, so to speak. In short, (SW)
appears to imply that
If p, then it is impossible to be radically deceived about p.
we were to stop here, we would overlook and important point. For even
if truth can’t be identified with superwarrant, it may still be plausible that
some propositions are made true by being superwarranted. Indeed, this is
just the sort of possibility that a pluralist theory of truth allows for.7 Such
theories, at a minimum, are committed to the idea that
(ST): Necessarily, for any proposition, if it is true, then it has some
property F such that, necessarily, if a proposition if F, it is true.
but also:
It is possible that there are some propositions that are T but not F.
This limited pluralism about the base properties for truth says noth-
ing about the property of truth itself other than it is a single higher-level
property that is asymmetrically dependent on other properties. Intuitively,
these other properties are those that make propositions true. Perhaps for
some sorts of propositions, the property that makes them true is super-
warrant. Indeed, the foregoing reflections help to show us which sorts of
propositions are likely to be candidates: propositions about which it is a
priori the case that we cannot be radically deceived. What sort of proposi-
tions might these be? One suggestion—and here I only put this forward as
a representative suggestion—would be moral propositions. Many writers,
holding quite different normative ethical theories, think moral wrongness
is conceptually tied to responsibility and blameworthiness. “We do not
do call anything wrong,” as Mill writes, “unless we mean to imply that a
person ought to be punished in some way or other for doing; if not by
law, by the opinion of his fellow creatures; if not by opinion, then by the
reproaches of his own conscience.”8 What is wrong is what we can be jus-
tifiably held responsible for doing—what is worthy of blame, in short. If
so, then the following argument seems cogent:
7. For two versions of alethic pluralism see Michael Patrick Lynch, Truth as One and
Many: A Pluralist Manifesto (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009); Wright, Truth and
Objectivity and Saving the Differences (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2004);
and “Truth and Multiple Realizability,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82 (2004),
384–408.
8. Mill, Utilitarianism, ch. 5. See also Stephen Darwall, The Second-person Standpoint,
(Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 2006), 27. Robert Adams, Finite and
Infinite Goods (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002), 233–38; Allan Gibbard, Wise
Choices, Apt Feelings (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), 42; John Skorupski, Ethical
Explorations (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), 142.
196 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
out of that linkage earlier. Where truth is maximally objective, we are vul-
nerable to radical deception. It is plausible that we are vulnerable to such
deception, and therefore theories of truth that artificially limit the nearly
limitless ways humans might be in ignorance or error, hence the ways they
may be deceived, should be rejected. But where the possibility for radical
deception is in fact already limited, such theories may in fact be plausible
accounts of what makes some propositions true.
In the previous section, I reviewed some of the ways the conceptual link-
age between deception and truth can, and should, affect how we think
about the metaphysics of truth. I now turn to question of how that link-
age affects how we think about the value of truth. Since I’ve addressed
this issue at length elsewhere, I’ll be brief.10
People don’t like to be deceived—by their mechanic, their boss, their
friend, their lover, anyone. One reason for our dislike is obvious: when
you are deceived, someone has caused you to not believe what is true, or
even to believe what is false. Either way, they’ve willfully placed them-
selves between you and the facts. And that can be a dangerous thing. But
even if it is not overtly dangerous, it is likely to interfere with one’s plans,
to change them, or to simply make them go awry. Either way, we are
less likely to get what we want. And that of course is typically the point:
the deceiver deceives to get his way, not (generally speaking) to facilitate
yours. There are exceptions of course, but generally speaking, we hate to
be deceived because deception has negative practical consequences.
But our dislike of deception goes deeper than that. One reason to think
so is that most folks would prefer not to be deceived even if it would make
no difference to one’s experiences. Suppose you had to choose between
two doors. Once you make the choice of which door to enter, you will
forget that you ever made a choice at all. Behind door number one is your
life just as it is now. Your friends are friendly, and your lover loves you.
Behind door number two is a very similar life, with one very important
exception: here some of your friends and your lover really despise you.
But you will never discover that fact: their deceit will be perfect. From
the inside, both lives will be indistinguishable: where the first causes you
joy, the second does also; where the first causes you pain, the second does
as well; and so on to the grave. Yet in the second, your life is the life of the
fool: you are deceived.
Forced to choose, almost all of us will prefer the first life over the sec-
ond. Perhaps some may be ambivalent; they’ll flip a coin. Presumably, no
one will actively prefer the second over the first. Either way, your reac-
tion tells you something about how deeply you dislike deception. If you
10. See True to Life, and “Replies to Critics,” Philosophical Books 46 (2005), 331–42.
198 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
are ambivalent, then deception matters less to you than it does to others.
What matters is how you feel and experience life; if the truth of your
beliefs has no effect on those feelings and experiences, then you don’t care
whether you are being deceived or not. One door is as good as another.
Most of us, however, will find this attitude odd, even repugnant. We don’t
just want to seem to have friends and lovers, we want friends and lovers,
even if there were no discernible difference between the one case and the
other. Moreover, we want to want to be that way: we care about not being
deceived. We would no more wish to be ambivalent about which door to
enter than we would wish to willingly enter into a deception.
Our attitude toward such choices also tells us something about our
attitudes toward truth. Given the conceptual connection between truth
and deception, this is not surprising. The fact that we prefer not to be
deceived—even when the deception is undetectable—suggests that our
preference for believing whatever is true over not doing so remains even
when it would have no effect on how we experience life. And this in turn
suggests that it is a basic preference—not derived from a preference for
something else. Moreover, it is not a mere preference—I don’t just want
to believe whatever is true; I care about doing so. And if I care about not
being deceived for more than instrumental reasons, I care about believing
what is true for more than instrumental reasons. I care about it “for its
own sake.”11
It is worth emphasizing that this line of reasoning is not intended to
show, absurdly, that we want all of our actual beliefs to be true. I believe
many propositions that I don’t want to be true. Beliefs about the future of
global warming or the continuing spread of AIDS in Africa number among
them. But the fact that I don’t want these particular propositions to be
true is entirely consistent with it being the case that I care about believing
what is true and only what is true, whatever that turns out to be.
Nor does our disvaluing of deception and consequent valuing of true
belief mean that truth is our only or ultimate value. It obviously is not.
Sometimes other things matter more than truth. Thus, more of us would
be willing to be deceived, or to deceive ourselves, if we thought that more
good than bad would come of it overall, or that the matter was so trivial
that the point was essentially moot. But this fact is entirely consistent
with the fact that considered by itself, deception is still something we
deeply wish to avoid, and believing what is true is something we care
about achieving. What this shows is that, like almost everything else we
care about, true belief is a pro tanto value. It is something we care about
other things being equal.
11. What we care about is the state of affairs of believing what is true. This value or
end is to be distinguished from the fact that it is correct to believe a true proposition—or
that the standard of correctness for belief is truth. See Lynch, True to Life, and “The Truth
of Values and the Values of Truth,” in Epistemic Value, eds. A. Haddock, A. Millar, and
D. Pritchard (Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcoming).
Deception and the Nature of Truth 199
4. CONCLUSION
Philosophers like me who think about truth for a living are, funnily
enough, often the least likely to believe that there is anything all that
interesting to say about truth. One reason for this is that most of us know
too well the failures of traditional theories like the correspondence theory
or Peirce’s pragmatic view. Such theories are reductive: they try to identify
truth with some single property that all and only true propositions have in
common. But such attempts are beset by counterexamples. Theories that
seem plausible when applied to propositions about the middle-sized dry
goods of everyday life (like certain versions of the correspondence theory)
seem much less plausible when applied to propositions about abstract
entities like numbers or norms. And theories that seem more plausible
when applied to propositions about norms (such as superwar- rant) are
much less plausible when applied to propositions about the physical world
around us.13 Partly as a result, many philosophers working on truth today
are attracted to one form or other of deflationism, accord- ing to which,
roughly, everything that needs to be said about truth can be gleaned from
our inclination to accept instances of the T-schema.14 From this standpoint,
it is simply a mistake to think with the traditional theories that truth has
any sort of “nature” that is worth explaining. It is a useful concept for sure,
providing a handy semantic ladder by which we can ascend and generalize
over infinite strings of propositions, but it is not to be confused with a
property that needs deep metaphysical investigation. In my view, the
considerations raised in this article suggest that there may be more to say
about truth than jaundiced deflationists believe, even if it isn’t the sort of
thing traditionalists look for. What the foregoing thoughts suggest is that
truth is a concept that is intimately related to a host of other concepts—
deception, ignorance, objectivity, value. Truth seems in fact to sit in a
network of such interrelations. Consequently,
12. Of course, this is distinct from showing that truth actually is worth caring about.
For arguments to that effect, see ch. 8 of True to Life.
13. For further arguments to this effect, see Lynch, “Truth and Multiple Realizability.”
14. Representative deflationists include P. Horwich, Truth, 2nd ed. (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1998), and H. Field, Truth and Absence of Fact (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2001). For some remarks that overlap with the foregoing, see Donald Davidson,
“The Folly of Defining Truth,” in The Nature of Truth, ed. M. P. Lynch (Cambridge, Mass.:
MIT Press, 2001).
200 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
there is reason to think that revealing these interrelations will shed light
on the concept of truth, by illuminating what can be described as the
functional role truth plays within our overall cognitive economy. Inves-
tigating truth’s role will most likely not aid us in a reductive analysis of
truth. It will not reveal the secret essence of truth. But it will tell us more
about what truth does for us—how it functions in our thought—not just
in logic or in epistemology, but in the broader realm of messy human
interactions, the realm that the layperson lives in, the realm we live in
ourselves.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Thanks to the following individuals for helpful discussion: Paul Bloomfield, David
Capps, Daniel Massey, Joel Kupperman, and Terry Berthelot.
Deception and the Nature of Truth 201
11
As one philosopher has remarked, “one cannot help noticing the heat
with which [Kant] treats the question of lying.”1 To this it must added,
one cannot help noticing the heat with which other philosophers treat the
question of Kant on lying. More than any other element of his moral phi-
losophy, Kant’s writings on lies have elicited an unprecedented amount of
abuse. One philosopher has accused Kant of being “hysterical” in his ethi-
cal writings on lies. Another has accused Kant of “repellent fanaticism” 2 in
his essay On a Supposed Right to Lie from Philanthropy from 1797, where
Kant argues that it would be a crime to lie to a would-be murderer even
to save an innocent life.3 Those scholars who have argued that this con-
clusion in his late work is not entailed by his philosophy of right have
seen fit to accuse him of “bad temper in his old age.”4 This is surely a
case of philosophers shedding more heat than light on a subject, however.
A thorough examination of Kant’s writings on lies—both in the ethics and
in the philosophy of right—is required before accusing him of hysteria,
fanaticism, or bad temper. The importance of this examination can hardly
be underestimated, since it is still true that “some philosophical textbooks
give such prominence to the Kantian view of the lie that the rest of Kant’s
201
202 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
5. Hofmeister, “The Ethical Problem of the Lie in Kant,” 353. Although the following
instance of a rejection Kant’s entire ethics (or a significant part thereof) due to his
prohibition on lying is an old one, nevertheless it is instructive: “The notion of the test
of universalisation as a practical criterion has been unanimously rejected by the critics,
and doubtless with good reason. The arguments against it are probably familiar to every
student in the elementary stages of moral philosophy. We have all been introduced very
early to the figure of the innocent man pursued by murderers whose life can be saved by
a timely lie. There is no need to work over this well-trodden ground again”; G. C. Field,
“Kant’s First Moral Principle,” Mind 41 (1932), 19. It is interesting to note that a cheap
edition of a translation of the Groundwork aimed at undergraduates is now accompanied
by a translation of the Right to Lie as a supplementary text, giving the Right to Lie great
prominence: Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, with On a Supposed Right to Lie Because
of Philanthropic Concerns, trans. and ed. James W. Ellington (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993).
6. References to Kant’s works in this chapter are given parenthetically, using the
abbreviations of individual works listed here. First are cited the volume and page
number in the standard edition of Kant’s works, Kants gesammelte Schriften, ed. Königlich
Preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften [subsequently Deutsche, now Berlin-
Brandenburg Akademie der Wissenschaften], original ed. Wilhelm Dilthey (Berlin: Reimer
[subsequently de Gruyter] 1900–), followed by the page number in the translation listed
here. Unless otherwise indicated, all emphases are in the original.
A: Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View [Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht]
(1798), trans. Mary J. Gregor (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1974).
AN: Announcement of the Near Conclusion of a Treaty for Eternal Peace in Philosophy
[Verkündigung des nahen Abschlusses eines Traktes zum ewigen Frieden in der
Philosophie] (1796), trans. Peter Fenves, in Raising the Tone of Philosophy: Late Essays
by Immanuel Kant, Transformative Critique by Jacques Derrida, ed. Peter Fenves
(Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993), 83–100.
C: Correspondence [Kant’s Briefwechsel], trans. and ed. Arnulf Zweig (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1999).
CPR: Critique of Practical Reason [Kritik der praktischen Vernunft] (1788), trans. Mary
J. Gregor, in Practical Philosophy, trans. and ed. Mary J. Gregor and Allen W. Wood
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 133–271.
G: Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals [Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten]
(1785), trans. Mary J. Gregor, in Practical Philosophy, trans. and ed. Mary J. Gregor and
Allen W. Wood (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 37–108.
LE: Lectures on Ethics [Vorlesungen über Ethik] (1924), trans. Peter Heath and ed. Peter
Heath and J. B. Schneewind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997).
MM: The Metaphysics of Morals [Die Metaphysik der Sitten] (1797), trans. Mary J. Gregor,
in Practical Philosophy, trans. and ed. Mary J. Gregor and Allen W. Wood (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1996), 353–603.
M: On the Miscarriage of All Philosophical Trials in Theodicy [Über das Misslingen aller phil-
osophischen Versuche in der Theodizee] (1791), trans. George di Giovanni, in Religion and
Rational Theology, ed. and trans. Allen W. Wood and George di Giovanni (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1996), 24–37.
RL: On a Supposed Right to Lie from Philanthropy [Über ein vermeintes Recht aus Menschen-
liebe zu lügen] (1797), trans. Mary J. Gregor, in Practical Philosophy, trans. and ed. Mary
J. Gregor and Allen W.Wood (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 611–15.
The Truth about Kant on Lies 203
WHAT IS A LIE?
Kant does not give a single answer to the question of what is a lie. Instead,
he tells us what a lie is in the ethical sense, what a lie is in the juristic
sense, and what a lie is in the sense of right. 7 Nevertheless, it is possible to
say what is common to a lie in all three senses, as well as what differenti-
ates a lie in one sense from a lie in the other senses. What is common to
a lie in all three senses is that it is an intentional action of a certain kind.
More specifically, it is the making an untruthful statement with the intention
that that statement be believed to be true. This entails that three conditions
must be met for a lie in all three senses.
The first condition that must be met for a lie in all three senses is that a
statement must be made. A person may be said to make a statement when
a person believes that there is some expression, and some language, such
that one of the standard uses of that expression in that language is that of
expressing some proposition, and the person utters, writes, or signs that
expression with the intention that it be believed that she intended to utter
(etc.) that expression with that standard use.8 Making a statement there-
fore requires the use of conventional signs, as opposed to natural or causal
signs. A person lies “when a person gives signs indicative of thoughts that
he does not have” (LE, 27:700 [p. 426]). Kant sometimes speaks of this
statement condition in terms of words: “communication of one’s thoughts
to someone through words that yet (intentionally) contain the contrary of
what the speaker thinks” (MM, 6:429 [p. 552]). However, conventional
signs are not limited to spoken or written words; they include sign lan-
guage, smoke signals, semaphore signals, Morse code, and so forth.9 They
also include nodding one’s head, winking one’s eye, and shrugging one’s
shoulders.10 In the case of a person who does not utter (etc.) a declara-
tive sentence, but who, for example, curses, or utters an interjection or an
exclamation, or issues a command or an exhortation, or asks a question,
or says “Hello,” then, if it is not one of the standard uses of that expression
in that language to express some proposition, and the person does not
intend that it be believed that she intended to utter (etc.) that expression
7. The claim that there are three senses of a lie in Kant’s moral philosophy is not
original to this essay. John E. Atwell says about Kant that “he condemns lying on three
grounds: (1) as a lying promise, it violates a perfect duty to others, and thus infringes
someone else’s rights; (2) as a lie in general, it violates a strict duty to oneself; and, as we
shall see here, (3) a lie violates the rights of mankind”; Ends and Principles in Kant’s Moral
Thought (Dodrecht: Nijhoff, 1986), 193–94 (references omitted). These three grounds
for the condemnation of lying correspond to the three senses of a lie, namely, a lie in the
juristic sense, a lie in the ethical sense, and a lie in the sense of right.
8. Roderick M. Chisholm and Thomas D. Feehan, “The Intent to Deceive,” Journal of
Philosophy 74 (1977), 150.
9. Sissela Bok, Lying: Moral Choice in Public and Private Life (New York: Random
House, 1978), 13.
10. Chisholm and Feehan, “Intent to Deceive,” 149.
204 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
with that standard use, it follows that she is not making a statement when
she does any of these things. If she is not making a statement when she
does any of these things, it follows that she cannot be lying when she does
any of these things, although she may be attempting to deceive.11
Kant gives at least two examples of actions in which nonconventional
signs are used in an attempt to deceive. The first is packing one’s bags—a
natural sign of intending to leave on a journey—in order to have a thief
falsely believe that one is intending to leave, so that one may catch the
thief: “a pretended journey, to uncover and thwart a crime” (LE, 27:699–
700 [p. 426]). The second involves the Scottish speculator John Law,
whose company for investment in Louisiana, Compagnie Perpetuelle des
Indes, went bankrupt. Law continued to build his house in France—a nat-
ural sign of intending to stay—in order to have people falsely believe that
he was not leaving, so that he could flee France. In neither case is a lie told,
since in neither case is a statement made:
if I pack my bags, for example, people will think I am off on a journey, and
that is what I want them to believe; but they have no right to demand any
declaration of will from me. That is what the famous John Law did; he
kept on building, and when everyone was thinking: He’ll never leave, off he
went. (LE, 27:447 [p. 202–3])
Since a lie in all three senses requires that a statement be made, there
can be no so-called lies of omission or concealment lies, according to Kant.
In Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View, after stating that “the mere
fact that any prudent man finds it necessary to conceal a good part of his
thoughts makes it clear enough that every member of our race is well
advised to be on his guard and not to reveal himself completely” (A, 7:332
[p. 192]), Kant distinguishes between three different things: dissimulation
(concealment, reticence), that is, intentionally not making a statement,
which may involve no deception; deception, which may involve keeping
silent with the intention that something false be believed to be true, that
is (deception by omission), and hence, that may involve no lying; and
finally, lying:
So it already belongs to the basic composition of a human creature and to
the concept of his species to explore the thoughts of others but to withhold
one’s own—a nice quality that does not fail to progress gradually from dis-
simulation to deception and finally to lying. (A, 7:153 [p. 32])
11. For the contrary argument that it is possible to lie by using, for example,
interrogatives and imperatives, see Henry S. Leonard, “Interrogatives, Imperatives, Truth,
Falsity and Lies,” Philosophy of Science 26 (1959), 172–86.
The Truth about Kant on Lies 205
different from that lack of sincerity that consists in dishonesty in the actual
expression of our thoughts. (C, 11:332 [p. 411])
The second condition that must be met for a lie in all three senses is
that the statement that is made must be believed to be false by the per-
son who makes the statement. That is, the statement that is made must
be untruthful. Importantly, it is not required that the statement be false.
The statement that is made may be true. However, if the statement that
is made, whether true or false, is believed to be false by the person who
makes it, then the statement that is made is untruthful:
One cannot always stand by the truth of what one says to oneself or to
another (for one can be mistaken); however, one can and must stand by the
truthfulness of one’s declaration or confession, because one has immediate
consciousness of this. For in the first instance we compare what we say with
the object in a logical judgment (through the understanding), whereas in
the second instance, where we declare what we hold as true, we compare
what we say with the subject (before conscience). Were we to make our
declaration with respect to the former without being conscious of the latter,
then we lie, since we pretend to something else than what we are conscious
of. (M, 8: 267–68 [p. 34])
Since untruthfulness is required for a lie in all three senses, it follows that
it is not a lie, in any of the three senses, if someone makes a truthful, but
false, statement. However, it may be a lie, in all three senses, if someone
206 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
Since untruthfulness is required for a lie in all three senses, it follows that
it is not a lie in any of the three senses to make a truthful statement with
the intention that some believed-false statement be believed to true. Kant
gives an example of making a truthful statement with the intention that a
believed-false statement be believed to be true in the course of discussing
intentionally deceptive truthfulness:
A moral casuistic would be very useful, and it would be an undertaking
much to the sharpening of our judgement, if the limits were defined, as
to how far we may be authorized to conceal the truth without detriment
to morality. Along with lying we may include: (a) aequivocatio moralis,
i.e. moral ambiguity, insofar as it is deliberately employed to deceive the
other; for example, a Mennonite swore an oath that he had handed over the
money he owed to his creditor, and in a literal sense he could swear this, for
he had hidden that very sum in a walking stick and asked his adversary to
hold it. (LE, 27:701–2 [p. 428])
12. For more on the distinction between lies and intentional deception, see my “Kant
and Maria von Herbert: Reticence vs. Deception,” Philosophy 81 (2006), 417–44, and “A
Definition of Deceiving,” International Journal of Applied Philosophy 21 (2007), 181–94.
Note that Kant does not consider the case of someone making an untruthful statement
without the intention that that statement be believed to be true, but with the intention
that some other believed false statement be believed to be true.
The Truth about Kant on Lies 207
The third condition that must be met for a lie in all three senses is that
it must be intended that the untruthful statement be believed to be true.
To make an untruthful statement with the intention that it be believed
to be true is to have an intention to deceive about the contents of the
untruthful statement. Hence, an intention to deceive about the contents
of the untruthful statement is necessary for a lie in all three senses. Mak-
ing an untruthful statement without the intention that it be believed to be
true—without an intention to deceive about the contents of the untruth-
ful statement—is not a lie in any of the three senses:
A white lie is often a contradictio in adjecto [contradiction in terms]; like
pretended tipsiness, it is untruth that breaches no obligation, and is thus
properly no lie. Joking lies, if they are not taken to be true, are not immoral.
But if it be that the other is ever meant to believe it, then, even though no
harm is done, it is a lie, since at least there is always deception. (LE, 27:62
[p. 28])
Although it is necessary for a lie in all three senses that the untruthful
statement that is made be intended to be believed to be true, it is not neces-
sary for a lie in any of the three senses that it be believed to be true. That
13. Kant may not be consistent on this matter, however. In his lectures he says that
courtiers and politicians are lying in the ethical sense (at the very least): “If untruth
presupposes cleverness and skill, we get artful lying and repute; courtiers and politicians,
for example, have to achieve their aims by lying, and everyone should flee any position in
which untruth is indispensable to him” (LE, 27:62 [p. 28]).
208 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
14. It may well be that, in such a case, the person is deceived about what the liar
believes and about what the liar intends. However, it is possible to imagine a case in which
one knows that someone will lie about some matter, but one also knows that the person is
mistaken about this matter, and that the lie will be true, although one does not know what
the lie will be. In such a case, when one believes to be true what the liar says, one is not
being deceived about anything.
15. D. S. Mannison, “Lying and Lies,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 47 (1969), 135.
Charles Fried, however, calls a “case in which the hearer not only does not believe what
he is being told, but does not even believe that the speaker believes it” an “attempted lie”
rather than a lie; Right and Wrong (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1978), 59.
The Truth about Kant on Lies 209
A lie in the juristic sense is much narrower in scope than a lie in the ethi-
cal sense. It is the making of an untruthful statement to a particular other
person (or particular other persons) with the intention that this person
believe that statement to be true and be harmed by believing that state-
ment to be true: “jurists insist upon adding for their definition, that it must
harm another (mendacium est falsiloquium in [praejudicium]17 alterius [a lie
is an untruthful statement that harms another])” (MM, 8:426 [p. 612]).
16. I have substituted “declaration” for “statement,” since the word used by Kant is
Erklärung, which is best translated as “declaration.”
17. Although it says “praeiudicium” in the text, there is good reason to believe that
there is a misprint in the Latin in Kants gesammelte Schriften here (possibly as a result of a
misprint in the original publication) and that it should be praejudicium.
The Truth about Kant on Lies 211
In one place in his lectures on ethics, Kant calls a lie in the juristic
sense a falsiloquium in praejudicium alterius: “In law a mendacium is afal-
siloquium in praejudicum alterius, and cannot be anything else there” (LE,
27: 448 [p. 203]). In several other places in his lectures, Kant is more
precise, and says that a lie in the juristic sense is a falsiloquium dolosum
in praejudicum alterius, an intentionally deceptive untruthful statement
that harms another: “The jurist recognizes and applies this only insofar
as it involves a violation of the duties towards others (officii juridicorum
[juridical duties]), and he understands thereby a falsiloquium dolosum in
praejudicum alterius; he is therefore looking to the consequences and rela-
tion to others” (LE, 27:604–45 [p. 350–51]).
In sensu juridico [legal/juridical sense] the mendacium is a falsiloquium dolo-
sum in praejudicium alterius, but in sensu ethico [ethical sense] it is already
any deliberate untruth. (LE, 27:701 [p. 427])
In his lectures, Kant explains the distinction between a lie in the ethical
sense and a lie in the juristic sense:
Hence an untruth differs from a lie in this, that both, indeed, contain a
falsiloquium, i.e., a declaration whereby the other is deceived, but the latter
is uttered with an associated intention to injure the other by the untruth.
Hence, too, a lie is subject to judicial reprimand, at least an offence, but not
as an untruth. In ethics, though, every falsiloquium, every knowing decep-
tion, is impermissible, even though it be not immediately coupled with an
injury, and would not be imputable coram foro juridico [before a court of
law]. (LE, 27:700 [p. 426–27])
A lie in the sense of right is broader in scope than a lie in the juristic sense,
but narrower in scope than a lie in the ethical sense. It is the making of an
untruthful statement to others with the intention that others believe that
212 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
In his lectures, Kant refers to a lie “from the moral viewpoint,” which
includes right, as a falsiloquium in praejudicium humanitatis, an untruthful
statement that harms humanity:
A mendacium is thus a falsiloquium in praejudicium humanitatis even when
it is not also in violation of any particular jus quaesitum [special right]
of another. In law a mendacium is a falsiloquium in praejudicium alterius,
and cannot be anything else there, but from the moral viewpoint it is a
falsiloquium in praejudicium humanitatis. (LE, 27:448 [p. 203])
Making any untruthful statement to others with the intention that oth-
ers believe it to be true entails intending to undermine rights based on
contracts. Therefore, making any untruthful statement to others with
the intention that others believe it to be true entails intending to harm
Kant gives several examples of lies in the sense of right that are not lies
in the juristic sense. One is the lie to the would-be murderer that one’s
friend is not in one’s house. This is a lie in the sense of right, but it is not
a lie in the juristic sense. Since the would-be murderer has forfeited his
rights by setting out on a course of murder, one cannot intend to violate
his rights by making the untruthful statement “No” to him with the inten-
tion that he believe it to be true. One is, however, intending to violate the
right of humanity:
I indeed do no wrong to him who unjustly compels me to make the state-
ment if I falsify it, I nevertheless do wrong in the most essential part of duty
in general by such falsification, which can therefore be called a lie (though
not in the jurist’s sense). (RL, 8:426 [p. 612])
Another example of a lie in the sense of right that is not a lie in the
juristic sense is the lie to someone who has lied to one. Since the liar has
forfeited his rights by his lie, one cannot intend to violate his rights by
making an untruthful statement to him with the intention that he believe
it to be true. One is only intending to violate the right of humanity: “Who-
ever may have told me a lie—I do him no wrong if I lie to him in return,
but I violate the right of mankind” (LE, 27:447 [p. 203]).
Another example of a lie in the sense of right that is not a lie in the
juristic sense is that of publishing an untruthful statement about an event
with the intention that it be believed to be true by others. Here there is
no particular other person to whom the untruthful statement is made
with the intention that it be believed to be true, and hence, no intention
to violate the rights of a particular other person. However, it is intended
that the right of humanity be violated:
214 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
As another commentator has said about this example: “But suppose, what
is more likely to occur, that the house-owner lies to the would-be mur-
derer, the innocent friend is saved, and soon thereafter the police appre-
hend the intruder. Everything turns out well—except, according to Kant,
the house-owner may be charged with violating the juridical duty not
to lie.”19 In order not to confuse the second and third senses of lie here,
however, it is preferable to refer to the “juridical duty not to lie” as the
duty of right not to lie.
While every lie in the sense of right is also a lie in the ethical sense, not
every lie in the ethical sense is also a lie in the sense of right. In particular,
lies to oneself are not lies in the sense of right.
With a lie in the ethical sense, a lie in the juristic sense, and a lie in
the sense of right explained, it is possible to look at the different duties
not to lie in the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, the Critique of
Practical Reason, The Metaphysics of Morals, and On a Supposed Right to
Lie from Philanthropy.
However, he does not explain which sense of lie he has in mind, and
hence, which duty not to lie he has in mind.
In Section I he asks “may I, when hard pressed, make a promise with
the intention not to keep it?” (G, 4:402 [p. 57]) As later versions of the
same example make clear, by “hard pressed” he means hard pressed for
money, and by “a promise with the intention not to keep it” he means a
lying promise to get money. Kant argues that “I could indeed will the lie,
but by no means a universal law to lie” (G, 4:403 [p. 57]), and concludes
that one must “be truthful from duty” (G, 4:402 [p. 57]). Granted that
a duty to “be truthful” is a duty not to lie (as opposed to a duty to be
candid),20 his conclusion is that there is a duty not to lie. However, once
again, he does not say which sense of a lie he has in mind, and hence,
which duty not to lie he has in mind. The example of a lie that he gives—a
lie to get money—is an untruthful statement made to a particular other
person with the intention that this person believe it to be true and be
harmed by believing it to be true (by depriving him of what is rightfully
his, namely, his money). It is a lie in all three senses of a lie. Hence, the
duty not to lie in question could be a broad ethical duty, a narrower duty
of right, or an even narrower juristic duty.
In section 2, Kant gives examples of “duties to ourselves and to other
human beings” that are “perfect and imperfect” (G, 4:421 [p. 73]). Here
he argues that a person who acts in accordance with the maxim “when
I believe myself to be in need of money I shall borrow money and promise
to repay it, even though I know that this will never happen” (G, 4:422
[p. 74]) violates a “necessary duty to others or duty owed them” (G, 4:429
[p. 80]), that is, a perfect duty to others.21 Since this is the example of
a lie that he gives in section 1, and since he makes the same argument
against this lie that he makes in section 1 (that a maxim of making a lying
20. Kant can be said to agree with Marcus Singer that the dictum “‘one ought to
tell the truth’ ” is “subject to certain understood but unstated conditions,” namely, “if one
is called upon to speak, or if one says something, then one should tell the truth; if one
is asked a question, and one decides to answer it, then one should answer it truthfully.
The rule as so stated clearly does not require anyone to answer every question that he is
asked . . . The positive formulation of the rule, as well as the negative formulation, leaves it
open to one to be silent. .... The rule ‘One ought to tell the truth’ is logically and morally
equivalent to the rule ‘One ought not to lie’ ”; “Negative and Positive Duties,” Philosophical
Quarterly 15 (1965), 99–100. In the Doctrine of Virtue, pt. 2 of The Metaphysics of Morals,
Kant clearly distinguishes between being truthful and being candid: “Between truthfulness
and lying (which are contradictorie oppositis [contradictory opposites]) there is no mean;
but there is indeed a mean between candor and reticence (which are contrarie oppositis
[contrary oppositis]), since one who declares his thoughts can say only what is true without
telling the whole truth” (MM, 6:433 n. 1 [p. 556n. 1]). For more on the distinction between
truthfulness and candor, see my “Kant on Lies, Candour and Reticence,” Kantian Review 7
(2003), 102–33.
21. As Mary J. Gregor points out, “Less frequently, Kant uses ..... ‘necessary’ as
synonymous with ‘perfect’ duty”; Laws of Freedom (Oxford: Blackwell, 1963), 97.
216 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
22. In the Doctrine of Right, Kant says that all duties of right (and all juristic duties) are
indirectly ethical duties: “So while there are many directly ethical duties, internal lawgiving
makes the rest of them, one and all, indirectly ethical” (MM, 6:221 [p. 385]).
23. At least one commentator has argued that the perfect duty to others at issue in the
Groundwork cannot be a duty not to lie, but must be a duty to keep promises to others,
on the basis that the duty in question is a duty to others, and not a duty to oneself: “I
take it that a lying promise, as Kant calls it, is a promise one never intends to keep. Qua
promise its not being kept is a violation of duty to the promisee, and hence is classified
as a violation of a perfect duty to another. In contrast, as we shall see below, when Kant
discusses lying in the The Metaphysics of Morals, he discusses it as a violation of a duty to
oneself”; Nelson Potter, “Duties to Oneself, Motivational Internalism, and Self-Deception
in Kant’s Ethics,” in Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals, ed. Mark Timmons (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2002), 373 n. 7; emphases in original). However, this is wrong. Kant is
well aware of the distinction between making a lying promise and breaking a promise
made truthfully: “There are also lies whereby the other is cheated. To cheat is to make a
lying promise. Breach of faith is when we promise something truthfully, but do not have
so high a regard for the promise as to keep it” (LE, 27:449 [p. 204]). As Otfried Höffe has
said, “in the case of false promises, Kant is not, as is often assumed, concerned with the
injunction to keep promises under all circumstances.......Kant is not concerned with the
observable sequence of events, in which a promise is made and then kept or broken, but is
instead concerned with honesty as the subjective principle determining the will. He asks
whether it is morally permissible for someone in need to give a promise that he does not
intend to keep. The false promise ...... is seen as an instance of lying and deceit; Immanuel
Kant, trans. Marshall Farrier (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1994), 154.
24. Despite what is said here, for an argument that the duty not to lie at issue in the
Groundwork is an ethical duty, see my “Kant and the Perfect Duty to Others Not to Lie,”
British Journal for the History of Philosophy 14 (2006), 653–85.
25. Onora O’Neill, “Kant’s Virtues,” in How Should One Live? Essays on the Virtues, ed.
Roger Crisp (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996), 83.
The Truth about Kant on Lies 217
Most lies are not lies in the juristic sense. A lie to obtain money is a lie in
all three senses of a lie, and therefore is a lie in the juristic sense of a lie.
Kant surely did not choose his example of a lie in the Groundwork lightly.
There is some reason to hold, therefore, that the duty not to lie to others
in the Groundwork is a juristic duty. Nevertheless, it is not certain that the
duty is a juristic duty.
It is also not certain what kind of duty not to lie is at issue in the Cri-
tique of Practical Reason. Indeed, it is not certain that there is a single duty
not to lie at issue in the Critique. In the Critique, Kant gives, as an example
of a duty, “[one] ought never to make a lying promise” (CPR, 21 [p. 154]).
He also gives, as example of a lie, giving untruthful testimony in court,
and argues for a duty to be truthful on the basis of this example:
Has not every even moderately honorable man sometimes found that he
has abstained from an otherwise harmless lie by which he could either
have extricated himself from a troublesome affair or even procured some
advantage for a beloved and deserving friend, solely in order not to have
to despise himself secretly in his own eyes? When an upright man is in the
greatest distress, which he could have avoided if he could only have disre-
garded duty, is he not sustained by the consciousness that he has maintained
humanity in its proper dignity in his own person and honored it, that he has
no cause to shame himself in his own eyes and to dread the inward view of
self-examination? (CPR, 5: 87–88 [p. 210–11])
218 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
However, by “harmless lie” here Kant surely means harmless to the par-
ticular individual to whom the lie is told, since such a lie would still be
harmful to humanity. The duty not to lie here could therefore be a duty
of right not to lie or an ethical duty not to lie. However, given what Kant
says about it—“solely in order not to despise himself secretly in his own
eyes”—it seems that he is talking about an ethical duty not to lie.
Nevertheless, it is not certain what duty not to lie at issue in the Critique,
or indeed, that there is a single duty not to lie at issue in the Critique.
Since a lie in the sense of right also does not necessarily violate the
rights of a particular other person (although it necessarily “harms . . .
humanity generally”; RL, 8:426 [p. 612]), the claim that a lie in the
ethical sense does not necessarily violate the rights of a particular other
person is insufficient to distinguish between a lie in the ethical sense
and a lie in the sense of right. However, Kant also says that a lie to one-
self is a lie in the sense of ethics, even though it is intentionally harmless
to others:
uses oneself (as a natural being) as a mere means to an end. When one
lies, one (as a moral being) treats oneself (as a natural being) as a “speaking
machine,” that is, as a thing:
But communication of one’s thoughts to someone through words that
yet (intentionally) contain the contrary of what the speaker thinks on the
subject is an end that is directly opposed to the natural purposiveness of
the speaker’s capacity to communicate his thoughts The human being
as a moral being (homo noumenon) cannot use himself as a natural being
(homo phaenomenon) as a mere means (a speaking machine), as if his natural
being were not bound to the inner end (of communicating thoughts), but
is bound to the condition of using himself as a natural being in agreement
with the declaration (declaratio) of his moral being and is under an obliga-
tion to himself to truthfulness. (MM, 6:429–30 [p. 553])
26. Nelson Potter has said in various places that “somewhat surprisingly Kant regards
lying, not as a violation of a duty to another, but as a violation of a duty to oneself; “How
to Apply the Categorical Imperative,” Philosophia 5 (1975), 415 n. 5 (and “Duties to
Oneself in Kant’s Ethics,” 386). However, the ethical duty not to lie must be a duty to
oneself, in order to prohibit lies to oneself.
220 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
The Right to Lie is exclusively concerned with a lie in the sense of right,
a falsiloquium dolosum in praejudicium humanitatis. The case Kant is con-
cerned with in this essay is a case raised by Benjamin Constant 27, that of
making the untruthful statement “No” to a would-be murderer asking if
one’s friend is in one’s house, with the intention that the would-be mur-
derer believe the untruthful statement to be true. This is not a lie in the
juristic sense, since in so acting one is not intending to violate the rights
of the would-be murderer (he has forfeited his rights by setting out on a
course of murder). However, it is a lie in the sense of right, since one is
necessarily intending to violate the right of humanity:
although I indeed do no wrong to him who unjustly compels me to make
the statement if I falsify it, I nevertheless do wrong in the most essential
part of duty in general by such falsification, which can therefore be called a
lie (though not in the jurist’s sense); that is, I bring it about, as far as I can,
that statements (declarations) in general are not believed, and so too that
all rights which are based on contracts come to nothing and lose their force;
and this is a wrong inflicted upon humanity generally. (RL, 8:426 [p. 612])
28. Paul Guyer, Kant (New York: Routledge, 2006), 403 n. 14.
29. Paul Griffiths, Lying: An Augustinian Theology of Duplicity (Grand Rapids, Mich.:
Brazos Press, 2004), 192.
30. Allen Wood has said that “the term “declaration” (Aussage, Deklaration, Latin
declaratio)” only refers to a statement that is made “in a context where others are
warranted or authorized (befugt) in relying on the truthfulness of what is said, and makes
the speaker liable by right, and thus typically subject to criminal penalties or civil damages,
if what is said is knowingly false” (Kantian Ethics, 241). However, in the Doctrine of Virtue,
when Kant says that “The human being . . . is bound to the condition of using himself as
The Truth about Kant on Lies 223
Although Kant does not discuss the duty of right not to lie in the Doc-
trine of Right, he does discuss the duty in the lectures on moral philosophy
in 1784–85 (LE, 27:446–50 [p. 202–5]). This undermines the claim that
the argument in the Right to Lie for the duty of right not to lie is primarily
a response to Constant,31 as well as the claim that it is a product of bad
temper in his old age.32
Some commentators have argued that there is an “apparent discrep-
ancy”33 between the Right to Lie and the Doctrine of Right. They argue
that Kant “explicitly accepts here [Doctrine of Right] the view which he
rejects in the essay ‘On the Right to Lie’—the view, namely, that in law
an untruth is a lie only if it is to the prejudice of some one else (in praeju-
dicium alterius).”34 They argue that, according to the Doctrine of Right,
there is a right to tell lies to others, even if such lies are vicious, so long
as they are not intended to violate the rights of particular other persons:
“lying is always morally wrong, but he also thinks that as long as a lie is
not intended to deprive someone of her rights or property it should not be
prohibited by law.”35 Since the Doctrine of Right “expressly permits lying”36
to others, when it is not intended to violate the rights of particular other
persons, and since the Right to Lie expressly prohibits lying to others, there
is an apparent discrepancy between the Right to Lie and the Doctrine of
Right.
However, there is no apparent discrepancy between the Right to Lie
and the Doctrine of Right. When, in the Doctrine of Right, Kant says that
“the only kind of untruth we want to call a lie, in the sense bearing upon
rights [im rechtlichen Sinne], is one that directly infringes upon anoth-
er’s right, e.g., the false allegation that a contract has been concluded
with someone, made in order to deprive him of what is his (falsiloquium
a natural being in agreement with the declaration (declaratio) of his moral being” (MM,
6:430 [p. 553]), he is referring to declarations to oneself and to God as well as to others.
A declaration (declaratio) does not, therefore, only refer to a statement made in a context
where others are warranted or authorized in relying on the truthfulness of what is said.
31. See Robert J. Benton, “Political Expediency and Lying: Kant vs. Benjamin
Constant,” Journal of the History of Ideas 43 (1982), 135–44.
32. As Manfred Kuehn says, “while some have wanted to explain it [Right to Lie] away
as a product of Kant’s old age, it seems clear that it represents his considered view on the
subject, and that he would have presented essentially the same arguments at the time he
was writing the Groundwork; Kant: A Biography (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2001), 403.
33. Sedgwick, “On Lying and the Role of Content in Kant’s Ethics,” 58.
34. Paton, “An Alleged Right to Lie,” 199–200.
35. Allen D. Rosen, Kant’s Theory of Justice (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press,
2003), 70 n. 88.
36. Hiram Caton, “Truthfulness in Kant’s Metaphysical Morality,” in Essays in
Metaphysics, ed. Carl G. Vaught (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press,
1970), 38 n. 57.
224 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
dolosum)” (MM, 6:238n. 1 [p. 394 n. 1]), he is talking about a lie in the
juristic sense. He is saying that the only kind of intentionally deceptive
untruthful statement that is called a lie, in the juristic sense, is one that
is intended to directly violate the rights of a particular person (a “par-
ticular jus quaesitum [special right] of another” (LE, 27:448 [p. 203]).
This is compatible with saying that the kind of intentionally deceptive
untruthful statement that is called a lie, in the sense of right, is one that
is intended to violate the right of humanity (“Recht der Menschheit” (LE,
27:447 [p. 203]). It is just that every intentionally deceptive untruthful
statement made to others is a lie in the sense of right.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I would like to thank Allen Wood for discussions about Kant on lies, and for pro-
viding me with an advance copy of the chapter on lies from his Kantian Ethics.
I would also like to thank Andrew Chignell and the Sage School of Philosophy
at Cornell University for facilitating these discussions during Wood’s visit to
Cornell. Much earlier versions of parts of this essay were read at Duke Univer-
sity, Washington and Lee University, Harvard University, and the University of
Pittsburgh in 1999 and 2000, as well as at the Eastern Division meeting of the
American Philosophical Association in 2000, and at San Diego University in 2003.
I would like to thank all respondents and audiences on those occasions for their
comments. This essay was written while I was a Visiting Fellow in the Philoso-
phy Department at Princeton University in 2006–2007. I would like to thank
the Philosophy Department at Princeton, and especially Desmond Hogan, for
their warm hospitality. My sabbatical leave at Princeton was made possible by a
Hewlett-Mellon Fellowship from Washington and Lee University, and I would
like to thank my university for their continued generosity.
The Truth about Kant on Lies 223
12
David Sussman
[I]
225
226 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
2. Kant does not hold that we have to be particularly forthcoming about such
information, and generally thinks that a fair degree of reserve is necessary for the
maintenance of social life and self-respect. In the Lectures on Ethics, he says that we may
even dissemble, so long as we do not actually assert anything contrary to what we believe:
“We may knowingly deceive the other in a permissible way, if we try by our action or
utterance to promote the truth, or avert an evil; e.g. a pretended journey, to uncover or
thwart a crime.” (LE, 27:700). So long as another “has no right to infer from my utterance
a declaration of intent . . . I have told him no lie” (LE, 444–47 [Collins]). However, we may
not dissemble simply to “sniff out” another person’s views.
On the Supposed Duty of Truthfulness 227
3. See Christine M. Korsgaard, “The Right to Lie: Kant on Dealing with Evil,” in
Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 135–37.
Korsgaard argues that while the formula of universal law can allow maxims of lying
to the murderer, those maxims cannot pass the tests of the formula of humanity. The
latter conclusion assumes, however, that the formula of humanity admits of determinate
application without having to introduce the idea of a right that is the focus of Kant’s
dispute with Constant.
4. Although Kant himself exploited such language to escape from the promise he made
to Frederick Wilhelm II to never again write on religious topics. In an instance of the sort
of reservatio mentalis that he classes as a lie (LE, 27:702 [Vigilantius]) Kant claimed that
because he made the promise only as “Your Majesty’s most loyal subject,” he was released
from his obligations at the event of Frederick’s death (Conflict of the Faculties, 7:10).
228 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
considers nothing like the case inquiring assassin in his casuistical discus-
sions.5 Even if he is not a consistent rigorist, Kant still seems to think that
we have stronger reason to lie to protect an author’s vanity than to defend
the life of a friend who is under our protection.
Admittedly, the Doctrine of Virtue’s casuistical discussion is preceded by
a condemnation of lying that is almost as severe as that of “On a Supposed
Right.” Kant argues that all lies are violations of a basic duty to ourselves as
moral beings, in that they contravene the teleology of basic human pow-
ers. A lie “is directly opposed to the natural purposiveness of the speaker’s
capacity to communicate his thoughts, and is thus a renunciation by the
speaker of his personality, and such a speaker is a mere deceptive appear-
ance of a human being, not a human being himself” (MM, 6:429). For
Kant, lies renounce one’s personality even when “done out of frivolity or
even good nature . . . or to achieve a really good end” (MM 6:429).
This condemnation of lying seems to depend on Kant’s general ten-
dency to inflate the normative demands of teleological thinking. Some
such teleological claim is certainly plausible. It is hard to see how anything
like speech could have arisen if its characteristic use had been to deceive
or manipulate others. How can any individual come to master a language
if she does not take the vast majority of what she is told or of how others
present themselves at face value? For communication to be possible, com-
petent speakers must generally take it for granted that one needs a special
reason to lie, but no such reason to tell the truth. This is not to deny that
there can be pathological liars, who lie habitually and gratuitously. For
the basic teleological point to go through, it is enough that such cases are
necessarily exceptional, being parasitic on an implicit trust in the truth-
fulness of others commonly shared throughout a society. Although there
can be pathological liars, there cannot be any self-sustaining communities
of them.
However, such teleological reflections do support anything like an
absolute prohibition of lying. Kant often assumes that having identi-
fied a natural purpose of some power, we may immediately conclude
that we have moral obligation never to use that power in ways that
would deviate from or defeat that purpose. In the Groundwork, Kant
argues that we may not commit suicide out of self-love, in part because
5. The closest he comes is in the example of a servant who has been ordered to lie
about his employer’s whereabouts. Kant claims that should the employer then be able to
commit a crime, the servant shares in his guilt, since the servant “violated a duty to himself
by his lie, the results of which his own conscience imputes to him” (MM, 6:431). Here
Kant does not appeal to any of the considerations that will be central to his analysis of
the “murderer at the door” case. Kant does not claim that the servant violates any duty to
humanity in general with respect to the basis of contracts or political life. Kant does not
even claim that the servant has wronged those to whom he has lied. He argues only that
the servant has violated a duty to himself, which is apparently enough by itself to make him
culpable for any resulting crimes.
On the Supposed Duty of Truthfulness 229
The journal’s editor notes that Constant had told him that Kant was
the “German philosopher” in question, and in response Kant allows “that
I actually said this somewhere or other, though I cannot recall where”
(SRL, 8:426). Yet Kant seems never in fact to have advanced this remark-
able position in any prior work. In his earlier ethics lectures, he had instead
argued that lying may be permitted as form of self-defense, if such deceit
is necessary to prevent a wrong being done to oneself:
For example, somebody, who knows that I have money, asks me: Do you
have money at home? If I keep silent, the other concludes that I do. If I say
yes, he takes it away from me; if I say no, I tell a lie; so what am I to do? So
far as I am constrained, by force used against me, to make an admission, and
a wrongful use is made of my statement, and I am unable to save myself by
silence, the lie is a weapon of defense…. Hence there is no case in which
a necessary lie should occur, save where the declaration is wrung from me,
and I am also convinced that the other means to make a wrongful use of it.
(Lectures on Ethics (LE), 27:448 [Collins]).
notorious irascibility of Kant’s last years. Paton speculates that the essay is
little more than Kant’s overreaction to the perceived slight of being caus-
ally characterized as merely “a German philosopher” by Constant.6
In any event, Kant probably had little love for Constant to begin with.
Robert Benton notes that Constant had written Des reactions politiques as
an apology for the Directory that came to power in France in opposition
to the Revolution’s more radical elements.7 Kant, “the old Jacobin,” may
well have seen the Directory as betraying the highest aspirations of the
Revolution (such as universal suffrage and economic equality). Constant
apparently wrote the pamphlet not out of political conviction but only
as an attempt to secure a position with the new regime in France.8 We
should not be surprised, then, to find Kant attacking not Constant’s actual
argument but rather the political opportunism that Kant may have seen
as the real motivation behind the essay.9
[ II ]
Yet for all its problems, we should not dismiss “On the Supposed Right to
Lie from Philanthropy” as merely a product of Kant’s wounded pride or
failing powers. Although the conclusions of the essay are wildly implau-
sible, they do have substantial motivation within Kant’s practical philoso-
phy. To appreciate the significance of the essay, we must first recognize
the essentially political nature of the problem Kant is considering. 10 He
does not treat the inquiring murderer as an ordinary moral problem that
requires direct application of the categorical imperative to some suitably
formulated maxim. Kant is quite clear that we would do no wrong to the
murderer by lying to him in these circumstances, as we would in cases of
deceit that are directly proscribed by the moral law. For Kant, the prob-
lem of how to respond to the murderer only arises when the situation is
considered as a matter of right (Recht), that is, in terms of those aspects of
morality that bear on our relations as free and equal members of a politi-
cal community, as they may be enforced by a just legal system. 11 For Kant,
the murderer presents no dilemma outside of such a civil condition. In a
“state of nature,” everyone would be
authorized to do to others anything that does not in itself diminish what
is theirs, so long as they do not want to accept it—such things as merely
communicating his thoughts to them, telling or promising them something,
whether what he says is true and sincere or untrue and insincere . . . for it
is entirely up to them whether they want to believe him or not. (MM,
6:238)
11. If so, then Kant’s teleological reflections about lying as a violation of a duty to
oneself, even if they could be sustained, would not bear on the case. Kant is clear that all
questions of duties to oneself fall within the domain of virtue, which is quite distinct from
issues of right.
12. If so, then the “non-ideal theory” that Korsgaard thinks Kant needs is already largely
present, if not complete, in his Doctrine of Right. See Korsgaard, “The Right to Lie,” 147–54.
232 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
[ III ]
Here Kant may have a plausible general reply to Constant’s claim that,
in order to have a potentially enforceable duty to tell the truth, there
must be a particular individual to whom we owe the truth. Kant recog-
nizes that we may also have duties based not in the claims of assignable
persons, but also with respect to what is needed to sustain the minimal
trust needed for any sort of just social order. Yet this reply hardly seems
adequate to the example Constant presents. By lying to the would-be
murderer, I hardly repudiate my commitments to speak truthfully and
uphold contracts in normal circumstances. Here my target is simply those
who would seek to exploit such honesty in order to violate the basic
rights of others. Such an attitude would seem to admit of being publicly
shared and avowed without having to renounce the basic commitments
needed to sustain a political community.
It is also hard to believe that such a defensive lie would have the effect
of undermining our general trust in contracts and promises. If my lie is
effective, it may well remain secret, and in this case there will be no such
repercussions whatsoever. Even if my lie is revealed, my motives should
become apparent as well, such that neither my honesty nor that of anyone
234 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
else need come into doubt. Criminals might lose faith in any declara-
tions that they extort from innocent bystanders, but this would seem to
strengthen rather than undermine any effective regime of rights. While
we might not be able to effectively deceive such criminals, we would at
least be able to give them a useless response, and so resist their attempts
to make us complicit in their evil designs. In contrast, an absolute duty
of truthfulness would put us in the power of anyone who can intelligibly
address a question to us.13 Yet Kant insists that “truthfulness is a duty that
must be regarded as the basis of all duties grounded on contract, the law
of which is made uncertain and useless if even the least exception to it is
admitted” (MM, 8:427). He maintains this even though the actual laws
of contract have in fact tolerated all sorts of exceptions and qualifications
without thereby becoming completely “uncertain and useless,” at least for
ordinary purposes.
[ IV ]
In “On Lying and the Role of Content in Kant’s Ethics,” Sally Sedgwick
argues that in “On a Supposed Right” Kant is only opposing the general
principle that duties of right may be set aside whenever this would help
another person, at least if so doing does not harm anyone else. The full
title of the essay is after all “On a Supposed Right to Lie from Philan-
thropy” (Menschenliebe). Kant would be on firm ground in arguing that we
could not stand in relations of right if each individual were authorized to
lie, break a promise, ignore a contract, or lay hold of another’s property
whenever she sincerely thought that enough good might come to another
because of it. In this case, our rights would once again depend on the
judgment and goodwill of particular individuals. The true extent of our
freedom would depend on whether others think that ignoring our rights
would contribute to someone’s welfare. Our right would be conditioned
by the particular degree of importance that others happen to accord the
imperfect duty of beneficence and the various sorts of attachments they
might have to those to whom it might be shown.
Kant observes that “from one’s right to require another to lie to one’s
advantage would follow a claim opposed to all lawfulness” (SRL, 8:428)
and concludes that the duty of honesty, as a “sacred command of rea-
son,” is one “not to be restricted by any inconveniences” (SRL, 8:428).
Sedgwick contends that Kant is considering only the basic principles
of our political relations, and does not mean to rule out more specific
“principles of application” that might allow lying in special cases like the
one Constant proposes. Supposedly, Kant holds only that lying can never
be justified by direct appeal to the benefits it might bring. Any such
13. Korsgaard contends that we have in fact a “perfect duty of virtue” to ourselves not
to allow our goodwill to be used as a “tool of evil” (“The Right to Lie,” 145–46).
On the Supposed Duty of Truthfulness 235
[V]
Kant claims that in lying to the murderer, we would “do wrong formally
though not materially” (SRL, 8:429; also LE, 27:449 [Collins]) but never
explains what the distinction between formal and material wrongs comes
to in this context. The contrast seems to be between wronging someone
in particular (i.e., violating a particular person’s rights) and acting from a
principle that conflicts with the possibility of rightful relations in general,
even when no particular person’s right is violated. Yet if Kant thinks that
14. See Alasdair MacIntyre, “Truthfulness and Lies: What Can We Learn from Kant”?
in MacIntyre, Ethics and Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 129–30.
Sedgwick recognizes the difficulty Kant’s remarks here pose for her reading, but dismisses
them as part of a polemical overreaction by Kant to Constant’s political opportunism;
Sally Sedgwick, “On Lying and the Role of Content in Kant’s Ethics,” Kant-Studien 82
(1991), 42–62.
On the Supposed Duty of Truthfulness 237
the objectionable principle at stake in this case is that our rights may be
ignored when doing so promotes utility, he is just refusing to think seri-
ously about the case Constant presents.
However, there is another way we might think about the distinction
between formal and material wrongs that might give Kant’s objections
more force. In matters of right, every act we take has a twofold nature that
may provide a plausible way of interpreting the material/formal distinc-
tion. Our acts have a material aspect determined by the end at which they
aim. This aspect of my act, and its moral significance, would remain the
same even if I were in a state of nature. Yet in a civil condition, our choices
also have a political form or aspect. In addition to adopting an end, in
each choice I arrogate a certain power to myself. Insofar as I take myself
to be in rightful relations, I am implicitly claiming that I am entitled to act
on such a decision in such a circumstance. Kant thinks that for an act to
be rightful, it must accord with the “universal principle of right” in both
these respects. The pursuit of the end must be consistent with the law-
governed external freedom of others with respect to similar pursuits, and
any implicit assumption of entitlement or authority must be consistent
with the equal and law-governed assignment and free exercise of such
powers by everyone else as well.
These two requirements can come apart for Kant. The most notorious
example is his other outrageous conclusion: the claim that all political
revolution is morally wrong. Kant holds that a government’s authority
derives from its role as the embodiment of our collective authority to
specify and enforce our rights. As such, any law must at least be such that
it could have proceeded from the “general will” of a body politic commit-
ted to maintaining rightful relations among its members (regardless of the
actual mechanisms of legislation). Kant recognizes that a particular gov-
ernment may completely fail in these tasks: its laws might be incompat-
ible with anything that could count as a general will, and the government
may even have abandoned the pretense of maintaining rightful relations
altogether. Such a government would be illegitimate, and could not prop-
erly demand our obedience. Nevertheless, Kant holds that it would still be
wrong for citizens in such circumstances to revolt against this govern-
ment. Although he thinks that we must not comply with immoral laws or
commands, we nevertheless may not offer resistance in any way that
would undermine or repudiate of the government’s authority in general.
In such grim situations, revolution is not materially wrong; since the
government is indeed illegitimate, the revolutionary violates no real claim
it might have to his allegiance. Yet revolution would still be formally wrong
in much the same way the lying to the murderer might be. The revolu-
tionary assumes the right to judge the adequacy of the government, and to
release himself from obedience if he finds these institutions unsatisfac-
tory. For Kant, no set of rightful relations could assign such a prerogative
to individuals. The problem is not merely the risk that people might mis-
judge a decent government and undermine truly legitimate institutions.
238 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
For Kant, it is the mere fact that an individual would be taking himself
to be entitled to make such a decision, even if he can do so infallibly, that
would immediately vitiate any rightful relations he might have.15
For Kant, political authority is grounded in the need to sustain rights in
such a way that no person’s right depends on the judgment or goodwill of
any other person. No government could perform this function if individu-
als were authorized to decide, as individuals, whether and when they owed
it their allegiance. In this case, each citizen’s rights would still ultimately
depend on discretion and good will of others, and so we would remain in
what is effectively a state of nature, however peaceful and harmonious it
might be. For Kant, a government could be properly repudiated not by
individuals taken severally, but only by the body politic acting as a whole.
Yet Kant thinks that we must take the extant government as the only
institution through which such collective decisions can be expressed or
collective actions taken. As a result, for there to be a permissible way for
the people to challenge the government, they must already have some
alternate way of acting as a people, independent of that government. And
so a revolution would have already to be successfully completed before it
could be even begun.
A similar analysis can be applied to the supposed right to lie in defense
of someone’s rights.16 Unlike the revolutionary, the defensive liar is not
challenging the legitimacy of anyexisting political institutions. Instead, she
is only considering whether the assailant is entitled to the protections of
his rights in the usualway. By choosing to lie, she claims an entitlement to
do what would otherwise be wrong insofar as this is necessary to prevent
a serious violation of another’s rights. Like the revolutionary, the liar may
be perfectly right about the particular case. The murderer has no more
of a legitimate complaint against the liar than a despotic government has
against the revolutionary. Nevertheless, the liar might still be committing
a “formal wrong” against the body politic by essentially taking the law into
her own hands. She takes herself to be released from her normal obliga-
tions because of her own assessment of the ultimate intention behind
murderer’s question, even though he is within his rights simply to ask.
For Kant, any authorization to so judge the overall intentions of others
would be inconsistent with the common allegiance to the body politic
that makes determinate relations of right possible. If our rights are not to
depend on anyone’s personal discretion, then the state cannot be under-
stood as just a tool that individuals use to adjudicate and manage their
15. Here I am indebted to Christine M. Korsgaard, “Taking the Law into our Own
Hands: Kant on the Right to Revolution,” in Reclaiming the History of Ethics, ed. Andrews
Reath, Barbara Herman, and Christine M. Korsgaard (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1997) 297–328. See also Sarah Williams Holtman, “Revolution, Contradiction, and
Kantian Citizenship,” in Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals, ed. Mark Timmons (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2002), 209–32.
16. For a similar suggestion see Atwell, Ends and Principles in Kant’s Moral Thought, 198.
On the Supposed Duty of Truthfulness 239
prior rights and interests. If this were the case, citizens would be entitled
to quit civil society whenever they judged that the state had failed to
properly perform its function, and all rights would once again ultimately
rest on the goodwill of individuals. Citizens can avoid this result only
if they refuse to acknowledge any position outside of civil society from
which they might call its basic legitimacy into question. Every individual
must fundamentally identify with the body politic, and take her role as
part of that collective authority to be who she most truly is. No matter
how bad things become, she must understand her rights not as an individ-
ual possession, but as something fundamentally assigned to her through
the exercise of a more basic joint sovereignty.
The revolutionary repudiates this self-understanding by taking himself
to be released from his political obligations once he judges the govern-
ment to be defective. In defensive lying, I would similarly usurp the proper
enforcement authority of the entire community. Here I take myself to be
entitled to release myself from my normal obligations on the basis of my
assessment of someone’s ultimate intentions. In so doing,
we have implicitly broken the pactum, and acted contrary to the right of
humanity The case of emergency subverts the whole of morality, since
if that is the plea, it rests upon everyone to judge whether he deems it an
emergency or not; and since the ground here is not determined, as to where
emergency arises, the moral rules are not certain. (LE, 27:449 [Collins]).
[ VI ]
assailant in a more normal context. It seems that I may not lie, threaten, or
use even mild force even if I am the person the murderer is seeking. If all
enforcement must proceed through the proper institutions, then all I can
do is call the police. If they cannot or will not act in time, it would seem
that my only appeal is to heaven.17
Unfortunately, Kant never discusses emergency self-defense at any
length. In the introduction to the Doctrine of Right, he claims that we may
sometimes defend ourselves in ways that would normally violate some
right. Kant considers what he takes to be the spurious “‘right’ of neces-
sity,” which would authorize a person to do anything she needs to save
her own life. In arguing against this supposed right, Kant distinguishes
such cases from “the issue of a wrongful assailant upon my life whom
I forestall by depriving him of his life (ius inculpatae tutelae), in which
case a recommendation to show moderation (moderamen) belongs not to
right but only to ethics” (MM, 6:235). Here there is no prohibition on the
use of deadly force, but merely a suggestion that we try to limit the force
used that falls outside of the domain of right. Yet if in an emergency I may
respond to the threat of violence with violence, why not merely with a
lie? Could my justification for doing so in Constant’s example be weaker
because I would be trying to save the life of another person, rather than
my own?
Given that Kant accepts the possibility of legitimate individual self-
defense, “On a Supposed Right” may only be protesting a particular way
of conceiving of such resistance. We might think that when the murderer
comes to my door, and the police cannot help me, I enter into a local and
temporary state of nature with him. I would then be entitled to act in
whatever ways would be permissible in such a state, such as by lying or
using force. Kant must reject this tempting interpretation, because any
state of nature, even a supposedly temporary and local one, would com-
mit practical reason to a self-contradiction that would permanently vitiate
its authority. By countenancing the option of withdrawing to such a state,
even as an emergency measure, a citizen would renounce her fundamen-
tal identity as part of a particular body politic, and with it any possibility
of rightful relations.
However, Kant has the resources to understand self-defense in a way
that does not invoke any such temporary or limited state of nature. He
holds that rights must be generally enforceable in ways that do not rest on
individual discretion and initiative. If self-defense were always illegitimate,
then our rights would once again end up depending on the goodwill of
particular others in every instance where the police could not effectively
17. See John Locke, Second Treatise of Government, ed. C. B. Macpherson (Indianapolis:
Hackett, 1980), 91–92.
240 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
intervene. If so, then we can know a priori that any general will com-
mitted to maintaining rightful relations would delegate some of its basic
enforcement authority to individuals who find themselves in such situa-
tions. Just as Kant thinks that any general will would have to specify some
rights of property, contract, and household authority, so too it would have
to assign some of the police power to individuals who confront these
emergencies.
As a matter of what pure reason demands, the extent of this power
is largely indeterminate, and will depend on actual political institutions
for its full specification, just like our other basic rights. Even so, we can
know a priori that there must be some such emergency powers, and so
can reject out of hand the position that we have no special authorization
of self-defense at all. No general will could leave us utterly powerless
to resist attacks on our own rights or those of others. We may then be
entitled to assume at least authorization to lie in circumstances supposed,
insofar as this seems to be the most minimal effective resistance that
can be conceived. The murderer is after all threatening one of the most
important rights, and the lie is specifically targeted to frustrate only his
attack, leaving his other rights and interests largely unaffected (unlike the
use of force). If I am not authorized to do even this, I am left completely
at the murderer’s mercy.
Admittedly, in such self-defense an individual would still have to act
on her own judgment, but this need be no more problematic than the
fact that particular police officers have to make their own decisions in
the performance of their duties. Yet the police do not conceive of their
actions as being guided directly by their own moral judgment as private
citizens. Instead, public institutions exist to hold the police accountable
in the exercise of the special discretion that comes with their role, and
police officers properly deliberate and act in light of this fact. Similarly, in
self-defense a person has to make up her own mind about many things. In
so doing, she may take on new legal responsibilities, becoming specially
liable for the exercise of good judgment here in ways that go beyond
what might be required of citizens generally.18 What is crucial here is that
we approach self-defense not as private individuals suddenly thrust into
a state of nature, but as agents implicitly deputized to enforce the law in
the event of certain kinds of emergency. We do so in a morally appropri-
ate way so long as we accept in good faith any restrictions and special
responsibilities associated with this role that would issue from any truly
general will.
18. Although it is hard to believe that anyone could be held responsible for such
unlikely calamities as those Kant describes, when the lie unwittingly leads the murderer
to his victim. Arguably, no general will would assign such strict liability to individuals who
have to act in such emergencies.
On the Supposed Duty of Truthfulness 243
[ VII ]
Constant’s example may present a special problem in that the liar lies not
in response to any wrong the assailant has committed, but only in antici-
pation of crimes that he is expected to commit. The would-be murderer
does not obviously violate anyone’s rights by simply asking after his vic-
tim. In contrast, when I kill an attacker in self-defense, I am obstructing
a wrongful act that is already under way. For Kant, as fellow members
of the body politic we must relate to one another as fundamentally free
and responsible beings. This attitude must govern not just personal rela-
tions, but the relations between individuals and various political and legal
institutions. In preemptive self-defense (like preventative detention), we
would condition someone’s rights not on what he is actually doing, but on
the basis of some prediction of what he will do. His rights as a free, ratio-
nal agent would then be subordinated to a view of him as a determined
natural system, to be managed and controlled in ways not that different
from other physical phenomena.
For Kant, such a fundamentally predictive stance toward people is
incompatible with basic relations of right. No general will could recognize
such a police power that would generally regard others in this way. Yet if
such a power could not be assigned to the police, it cannot be available to
individuals acting as emergency deputies. This limitation need not apply
to other kinds of self-defense. When I kill my attacker, I am responding to
his free choices as an intelligible being, rather than anticipating his future
behavior as a merely sensible one. An authorization to resist in such cases
need not conflict with the basic understanding of ourselves that is the
precondition of all substantial rights, in that it is not conditioned by any
sort of psychological prediction. The important distinction is not between
lying and using force. Instead, it is between frustrating a crime already in
progress and forestalling a crime that has yet to begin. Kant could allow
that we may lie to defeat some criminal effort (e.g., by telling a mugger
that one has no money). The problem with Constant’s case is that in his
inquiries, the murderer has yet to overstep his rights, and so it seems that
the liar could not yet be authorized to step beyond hers.
The question here ulimtately turns on what counts as part of an
attempted crime. If the assassin’s inquiry is an act that is really distinct
from his attempt at murder, then I cannot be authorized to lie to him,
regardless of what I can reasonably and confidently predict about what
he will do with my answer. However, it may be more accurate to see his
inquiry as just the first part of his attempt to kill. This becomes all the
more plausible if, as Kant suggests, the murderer is already exerting some
kind of pressure on me to answer. The question would then be a compo-
nent of a wrongful act already in progress that authorizes me to lie or use
some degree of force against him in response.
Admittedly, we cannot appreciate the wrongness of the assailant’s
question by considering it in isolation from the overall pattern of activity
242 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
19. The situation is more vexed if the would-be murderer is himself acting as an agent
of the state. If I am right, this case should not be conceived of as a private person opposing
the political authority, but rather as a conflict between two different enforcement powers
of the state.
On the Supposed Duty of Truthfulness 243
13
User-Friendly Self-Deception
A Traveler’s Manual
Amelie Rorty
Note: An early version of this chapter was delivered at colloquia at the East-West Center
in Honolulu, Hawaii and at Williams College. I am grateful to Annette Baier, Brian
McLaughlin, Sam Fleischacker, and Steven Gerrard for comments.
1. One variety of self-deception: X is self-deceived about p when
(1) X believes that p at t (where t covers a reasonable span of time);
(2) Either (a) X believes not-p at t, or (b) X denies that he believes p at t;
(3) X recognizes that p and not-p conflict;
(4) X denies that his beliefs conflict, advancing an improbable ad hoc reconciliation,
making no attempt to suspend judgment or to determine which belief is defective.
Since conditions 1 and 2 are parallel to conditions 3 and 4, the attribution of self-
deception is regressive. It is typically justified by an inference to the best explanation, an
account of what X would normally believe, perceive, notice, infer. For more elaborate
formulations of these conditions, see Leon Festinger, Cognitive Dissonance (Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 1957), and B. McLaughlin, “Exploring the Possibility of Self-
deception in Belief,” R. Audi, “Self-deception, Rationalization and Reasons for Acting,” and
A. O. Rorty, “The Deceptive Self: Liars, Layers and Lairs,” in Perspectives on Self-Deception,
ed. B. McLaughlin and A. Rorty (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1988). Please also
see the essay of Al Mele included in this collection.
244
User-Friendly Self-Deception 245
2. After having raised the paradox of analysis in the Meno, and come to the brink of
skepticism, Socrates says: “we shall be better, braver and more active if we believe we
should inquire than if we believe we cannot discover what we do not already know. That is
something for which I am ready to fight in word and deed to my utmost ability” (86B).
246 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
3. See A. O. Rorty, Mind in Action (Boston: Beacon Press, 1988); and A. Mele,
Irrationality: An Essay on Akrasia, Self-Deception and Self-Control (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1987),; D. Pears, Motivated Irrationality (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1984); M. Martin, ed., Self-Deception and Self-Understanding (Kansas: University of Kansas
Press, 1985); and Jon Elster, Sour Grapes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983).
User-Friendly Self-Deception 247
hand that encompasses common practice and common speech, the phe-
nomena that appear on the fringes of our presumptive rationality play a
significant role in virtually all our activities. Beyond the constraints set
by constructing a comprehensive theory of intellectual and psychological
functioning—one that explains extremely diverse cognitive, motivational,
and affective phenomena—there is no fact of the matter about whether
we should be strict or latitudinarian constructionists about the criteria
for the identity of the deceiver and the deceived or about the conditions
that identify cases of deception. Because we typically position ourselves
dialectically, emphasizing the conceptions that have been neglected by
our immediate predecessors, we can expect a continuous (re)cycling of
latitudinarian and strict characterizations of self-deception.
We are in the awkward position of stipulating definitions that will
satisfy our technically exacting colleagues in the cognitive sciences,
while also carrying on with what passes for common sense and ordinary
language. In analyzing and evaluating self-deception, we are engaged
in the method of reflective equilibrium, attempting to balance our
(shared) considered judgments and practices with our principle-laden
theories, as if our ordinary judgments and practices were not already
theory-laden.4
Moreover, self-deception need not involve any belief at all: the pro-
cess and the outcome can be protointentional or subdoxastic. 7 When
someone systematically deflects the natural direction of her gaze, ignoring
phenomena that she would normally find salient, her ignorance can be an
instance of self-deception as well as an instrument designed to achieve it.
Systematic, persistent resistance to correction can be internal to the pro-
cesses of believing: it can indicate the functional role of a relatively trivial
belief or a subdoxastic intentional disposition, rather than its epistemic
status.8
Further: stylized or ritualized actions—culturally specific actions that
conventionally express complex attitudes—can deceive. We adopt certain
postures and gestures to show a self-confidence we do not actually pos-
sess. An inclination of the head, a way of gazing, an intonation pattern can
deceptively suggest intimacy.9 Similarly, self-deception can be expressed
in gesture and action: the gestures of an aging coquette—the head at an
angle, the languorous eyes, the flirtatious smile—are not only designed to
help create and sustain an illusion: they can also be its primary expression.
While the beliefs that are implicated in such action—beliefs that such
gestures retain whatever charm they might once have had—are some-
times mistaken without being self-deceived, the coquette’s anxious look
in the mirror as she applies layer after layer of lipstick and rouge indicates
that she also knows better.
4. Self-deception need not focus on important matters: it can range
from the momentous to the minute, from the sublime to the ridiculous.
It can focus on the primary projects of a life (those of a politician or a
parent) . . . or on a new hairdo.
5. Self-deception need not be self-centered. To be sure, self-deception
is—along with other epistemic and psychological attitudes—explained
largely by the deceiver’s system of beliefs, habits, and desires; but although
7. See Annette Baier, “Ignorance and Self-Deception,” in Deception and the Self,
ed. R. Ames and W. Dissanayake (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003);
and M. Johnston, “Self-deception and the Nature of Mind,” in McLaughlin and Rorty,
Perspectives on Self-Deception, 37–55. Since many preintentional activities can sometimes
function in a fully intentional form, I prefer to speak of protointentional rather than
subintentional activities.
8. Following the model of analyses of justified belief, analyses of self-deception
typically specify necessary and sufficient logically distinct conditions—reified as
independent psychological states—whose conjunctive present themselves as casesof self-
deception. If the conditions of justified belief can be condensed in one activity, so can
those of self-deception. “The same liberty may be permitted to moral, which is allowed
to natural philosophers; and ‘tis very usual with the latter to consider any motion as
compounded and consisting of two parts separate from each other, tho’ at the same time
they acknowledge it to be in itself uncompounded and inseparable”; Hume, A Treatise of
Human Nature, 493.
9. See Bruce Wilshire, “Mimetic Engulfment and Self-Deception,” in McLaughlin
and Rorty, Perceptions on Self-Deception, 144–169.
User-Friendly Self-Deception 251
likely to deflect attention away from what one does not wish to see. The
best way for a gambler to deceive herself—to avoid noticing her lover’s
roving eye—is to schedule their assignations at the casino or the racetrack
instead of at the disco.
Opacity, vagueness, and overdetermination are the deceiver’s friend.10
Just as we use the ambiguity of polite, ritualized speech to mislead others
(“I had a wonderful time.” “I’ve been hoping to run into you so we could
arrange to have lunch.”), so we fuse the multiple functions of speech acts
when we talk to ourselves. In hopes of levering ourselves to our desks, we
gloss a vague thought as if it were a firm intention; we say “I’ll spend the
weekend finally getting to all those letters I must write.” The more pub-
licly such pronouncements are made, the more force the lever can exert.
Any experience is open to an indefinite number of true and even rel-
atively salient descriptions. To recommend a brash and hostile student,
we call attention to her energetic initiative in discussion. In the interest
of maintaining one’s loyalty to one’s unreliable or treacherous friends, we
praise their originality. While such cases do not involve lying, we typically
do intend to deceive by distraction. Of course, we might well have a sec-
ond-order policy that rationalizes and justifies strategies of this kind. But
they are none the less deceptive for having been rationalized and justified.
Shifting the level of generality of descriptions and explanations is also an
excellent strategy of deception and self-deception. To deflect attention from
the sordid, exasperating, and frustrating details of our major projects—par-
enting, teaching, political action—we move to general abstractions, lump-
ing these details together under the heading “No pain, no gain. It’s all worth
it in the end,” forgetting that when we are making important decisions,
it is often this—whether there is something about the activity that out-
weighs the trouble it brings—that is in question. Or we move in the other
direction: we can deceive someone (including ourselves) into accepting an
undesirable job by focusing on a few genuinely attractive details, drawing
attention away from a general, all-things-considered evaluation.
Second-order policies that legitimate specific self-manipulative strate-
gies are sometimes also canny instruments of self-deception, as follows.
10. See Iris Murdoch, “The Idea of Perfection,” in The Sovereignty of the Good (London:
Routledge Kegan Paul, 1970).
252 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
11. See Sartre, Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions (London: Methuen, 1962), and
Existentialism and Humanism, Anti-Semite and Jew (New York: Grove Press, 1948).
12. See William James, “The Will to Believe,” in; Pascal, Pensees 13; Bas van Fraassen,
“The Peculiar Effects of Love and Desire,” in McLaughlin and Rorty, Perspectives on Self-
Deception, 234–261.
User-Friendly Self-Deception 253
rather than a second-order rational policy that prompts accepting the self-
deceptions that accompany standard modes of imagining and believing.
We’d engage in these activities even if we didn’t approve of our doing so.
The more interesting forms of self-deception are local rather than global.
Without some species of self-deception, our dedications, our friendships,
our work, our causes would collapse. In deciding to have children, we
ignore the travails of parents, obliterating our otherwise keen awareness
of the typical relations among parents and children; in devoting ourselves
to writing philosophy, we conveniently forget how little philosophy we
are willing to read; in the interest of sanity and joy, we sidestep our deep
ambivalences about our kith and kin.
The benefits of individual self-deception are obvious to its practitioners;
the benefits of its socially induced forms are often more compelling.14 The
appearance of earnest and wholehearted conviction about one’s projects—
defending a philosophic position, proposing a curricular reform, raising
funds for a cherished cause—is commonly taken as an indication of trust-
worthy reliability. Disguising and submerging the ambivalence that is natu-
ral to most of our enterprises not only brings us the energy, verve, style, and
ease that successful action requires; it also helps to assure the social coop-
eration that is equally essential to our individual and collective projects. A
good deal of the polite conversation of social life—the public description of
the joys of our social roles and functions (friend, mother, teacher, scholar)—
channels and streams us to play our parts without the mess, confusion, and
upheaval that would occur if we openly expressed our natural and sensible
ambivalence about these roles. It is virtually impossible to imagine any soci-
ety that does not systematically and actively promote the self-deception of
its members, particularly when the requirements of social continuity and
cohesion are subtly at odds with one another and with the standard-issue
psychology of those members.15 Socially induced self-deception is an instru-
ment in the preservation of social cooperation and cohesion.
14. See “Some Social Uses of the Forbidden,” Psychoanalytic Review 12 (Feb.–Mar., 1972).
15. Since they do not involve beliefs in propositional form, such conflicts are not,
of course, technically speaking, contradictions. (See R. Marcus, “Moral Dilemmas and
Consistency,” in C. W. Gowans, Moral Dilemmas [Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987].)
Other essays in this volume provide a useful background for understanding some of the
motivation for self-deception. See also Festinger, Cognitive Dissonance.
User-Friendly Self-Deception 255
(1) The immediate agent of self-deception is the last active link in a causal
chain that generates the work of deception. That work is not always carried
out by individual persons: its agents can be subsystems of the self. Such sub-
systems are extremely various: they can range from subpersonic protointen-
tional perceptual dispositions to internalized idealized group identifications.
Neo-Freudians,17 cognitive psychologists,18 and social theorists19 dif- fer
in their analyses of the components that constitute the self, but they
agree in characterizing it as made up of relatively independent subsys-
tems whose interaction is often only precariously integrated. For them,
the explanation of the phenomena of self-deception lies in our complex
16. See Tyler Burge, “Individualism and Psychology,” Philosophical Review (1986), and
“Intellectual Norms and the Foundations of Mind,” Journal of Philosophy (1987). Burge
argues that the individuations of intentional states essentially refer to social practices.
See also Alvin Goldman, “Varieties of Cognitive Appraisal,” Nous 13 (1979), 22–38, for a
useful discussion of the variety of criteria by which beliefs are assessed.
17. See Freud, “Repression,” and “The Unconscious,” in The Standard Edition of
the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud (1915), and “Splitting the Ego in
the Service of Defence,” in Standard Edition (1938); R. Schafer, A New Language for
Psychoanalysis (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1976); D. Sachs, “On Freud’s Doctrine
of the Emotions,” in Freud, ed. R. Wollheim (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1974), 101–124; H. Kohut, The Restoration of the Self (New York: International University
Press, 1977); R. Wollheim, The Thread of Life (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,
1984).
18. See D. Dennett, “Three Kinds of Intentional Psychology,” in Reduction, Time
and Reality, ed. R. Healy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981); D. Davidson,
“Paradoxes of Irrationality,” in Philosophical Essays on Freud, ed. J. Hopkins and R.
Wollheim (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), and “Deception and
Division,” reprinted in Action and Events, ed. E. LePore and B. McLaughlin (New York:
Blackwell, 1985); Johnston, “Self-deception and the Nature of Mind”; S. Stich, “Beliefs
and Subdoxastic Systems,” Philosophy of Science (1978), and Fragmentation of Reason
(Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1990).
19. For an account of the distinctive aspects and features of identity, see Alfred Schutz,
Collected Papers (Amsterdam: Martinus Nojhoff), esp. 16–18, 221–22; G. H. Mead, Mind,
Self and Society (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1934), esp. 144–45, 149–52; A.
Rorty and D. Wong, “Aspects of Identity and Agency,” in Identity, Character and Morality,
ed. O. Flanagan and A. Rorty (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1990), 121–133.
256 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
20. See Johnston, “Self-Deception and the Nature of Mind,” and MacLaughlin, “Self-
Deception and the Nature of Mind,” for discussions of the presumed incoherence of self-
deception is incoherent and its reduction to other-deception.
21. See Adam Morton, “Partisanship,” in McLaughlin and Rorty, Perspectives on Self-
Deception, 212–235.
User-Friendly Self-Deception 257
24. See Roy Sorensen, Thought Experiments (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992).
Sorensen remarks that the standard modes of argumentation have their shortcomings as
well as their strengths. He recommends what he calls a “diversified portfolio” of argument
forms.
User-Friendly Self-Deception 259
Even though its authority rarely carries executive power, it is the active,
permanent possibility of asking critically evaluative questions that preserves
us from dangerous folly. “When is self-deception self-defeating? What is really
beneficial and to whom?” There are, to be sure, a variety of context-depen-
dent criteria for such evaluations; and each subsystem has its own claims for
special privilege. Still, at any given level, for any subscripted measure of util-
ity or rationality, intrapsychic might does not make intrapsychic right or even
intrapsychic utility. Socratic inquiry—actively pressing for self-critical evalu-
ation—is the only safeguard against the damaging uses of self-deception, or
indeed of any of our intellectual or psychological devices.
In evaluating the self-deception of our friends and enemies, in retrospec-
tively gauging our own, we are directed by judgments about the merits of
the ends it serves, as well as judgments about whether those ends could
have been better served by other means. In making such evaluations, we
need to think laterally as well linearly, systematically as well as episodically.
We need to consider the global effects of all our epistemic and psychologi-
cal activities—their addictive qualities as well as their immediate benefits.
When they are successful, psychological and intellectual activities typically
tend to become rapidly entrenched, ramified, and generalized.
But we have very little latitude in monitoring our psychological activi-
ties, and still less in forming them. Our epistemological strategies become
habitual before we are aware of their patterns and consequences. As phi-
losophers, the best thing we can do about self-deception is what we should
do about our other psychological and intellectual activities: engage our-
selves in the Stoic task of understanding the minute details of its operations.
Since we are highly susceptible to socially induced self-deception, the wis-
est practical course is to be very careful about the company we keep. But
it is no easy task to determine where our best protection lies. On the one
hand, prudence counsels avoiding the company of charismatic rhetoricians
who might mislead us. On the other hand, it’s not easy to identify epistemic
seducers, particularly when we benefit from hospitality to a wide range of
opinions, each with a distinctive critical perspective on our favorite illusions.
Unfortunately, self-deception is just the thing that prevents us from seeking
its best therapy: it doesn’t know when to expand, and when to limit its epis-
temological company. Fortunately, we have many other kinds of reasons for
being astute about the company we keep. With luck, a canny self-deceiver’s
other psychological and intellectual habits—a taste for astringency and a
distrust of hypocrisy, for instance—can prevent the wild imperialistic ten-
dencies of self-deception from becoming entrenched and ramified.
But that is a matter of luck; and as we know, ambivalence is the best
attitude toward luck.
260 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
14
Alfred R. Mele
1. For citations of this tradition in philosophy, psychology, psychiatry, and biology, see
Mele 2001, 125 n. 1. Stereotypical interpersonal deception does not exhaust interpersonal
deception.
260
Have I Unmasked Self-Deception or Am I Self-Deceived? 261
criticisms are correct, and a few days later, when Rex rereads his article
and the comments in a more impartial frame of mind, it is clear to him
that this is so.
2. Positive misinterpretation. Our desiring that p may lead us to inter-
pret as supporting p data that we would easily recognize to count against
p in the desire’s absence. For example, Sid is very fond of Roz, a college
classmate with whom he often studies. Because he wants it to be true
that Roz loves him, he may interpret her declining his invitations to
various social events and reminding him that she has a steady boyfriend
as an effort on her part to “play hard to get” in order to encourage Sid
to continue to pursue her and prove that his love for her approximates
hers for him. As Sid interprets Roz’s behavior, not only does it fail to
count against the hypothesis that she loves him, it is evidence that
she does love him. This contributes to his believing, falsely, that Roz
loves him.
3. Selective focusing/attending. Our desiring that p may lead us to fail
to focus attention on evidence that counts against p and to focus instead
on evidence suggestive of p. Beth is a twelve-year-old whose father died
recently. Owing partly to her desire to have been her father’s favorite,
she finds it comforting to attend to memories and photographs that place
her in the spotlight of her father’s affection and unpleasant to attend to
memories and photographs that place a sibling in that spotlight. Accord-
ingly, she focuses her attention on the former and is inattentive to the
latter. This contributes to Beth’s coming to believe—falsely—that she
was her father’s favorite child. In fact, Beth’s father much preferred the
company of her brothers, a fact that the family photo albums amply
substantiate.
4. Selective evidence-gathering. Our desiring that p may lead us both
to overlook easily obtainable evidence for not-p and to find evidence for
p that is much less accessible. Betty, a political campaign staffer who
thinks the world of her candidate, has heard rumors from the opposi-
tion that he is sexist, but she hopes he is not. That hope motivates her
to scour his past voting record for evidence of his political correctness
on gender issues and to consult people in her own campaign office about
his personal behavior. Betty may miss some obvious, weighty evidence
that her boss is sexist—which he in fact is—even though she succeeds
in finding less obvious and less weighty evidence for her favored view.
As a result, she may come to believe that her boss is not sexist. Selective
evidence-gathering may be analyzed as a combination of hypersensitivity
to evidence (and sources of evidence) for the desired state of affairs and
blindness—of which there are, of course, degrees—to contrary evidence
(and sources thereof ).
In none of these examples does the person hold the true belief that
not-p and then intentionally bring it about that he or she believes that p.
Have I Unmasked Self-Deception or Am I Self-Deceived? 263
Yet, assuming that these people acquire relevant false, unwarranted beliefs
in the ways described, these are garden-variety instances of self-deception
(or so I claim).2 Rex is self-deceived in believing that his article was
wrongly rejected, Sid is self-deceived in believing certain things about
Roz, and so on.
We can understand why, owing to her desire to have been the one her
father’ loved most, Beth finds it pleasant to attend to photographs and
memories featuring her as the object of her father’s affection and painful
to attend to photographs and memories that put others in the place she
prizes. But how do desires that p trigger and sustain the two kinds of mis-
interpretation and selective evidence-gathering? It is not as though these
activities are intrinsically pleasant, as attending to pleasant memories, for
example, is intrinsically pleasant.
Attention to some sources of unmotivated biased belief sheds light
on this issue. Several such sources have been identified (see Mele 2001,
28–31), including the following two:
1. Vividness of information. A datum’s vividness for us often is
a function of such things as its concreteness and its sensory,
temporal, or spatial proximity. Vivid data are more likely
to be recognized, attended to, and recalled than pallid data.
Consequently, vivid data tend to have a disproportional influence
on the formation and retention of beliefs.
2. The confirmation bias. People testing a hypothesis tend to search
(in memory and the world) more often for confirming than for
disconfirming instances and to recognize the former more readily
(Baron 1988, 259–65). This is true even when the hypothesis is
only a tentative one (and not a belief one has). People also tend to
interpret relatively neutral data as supporting a hypothesis they are
testing (Trope et al. 1997, 115).
Although sources of biased belief apparently can function inde-
pendently of motivation, they also may be triggered and sustained by
desires in the production of motivationally biased beliefs.3 For example,
desires can enhance the vividness or salience of data. Data that count
in favor of the truth of a proposition that one hopes is true may be
rendered more vivid or salient by one’s recognition that they so count.
2. If, in the way I described, Betty acquires or retains the false belief that her
boss is not sexist, it is natural to count her as self-deceived. This is so even if, owing
to her motivationally biased evidence-gathering, the evidence that she actually has
does not weigh more heavily in support of the proposition that her boss is sexist than
against it.
3. I develop this idea in Mele 1987, ch. 10, and 2001. Kunda 1990 develops the same
theme, concentrating on evidence that motivation sometimes primes the confirmation bias.
Also see Kunda 1999, ch. 6.
264 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
4. For motivational interpretations of the confirmation bias, see Friedrich 1993 and
Trope and Liberman 1996, 252–65.
5. See Mele 2001, 31–49, 63–70, 90–91, 96–98, 112–18.
Have I Unmasked Self-Deception or Am I Self-Deceived? 265
Here, he plainly has straight self-deception in mind, but he should not stop
there.Whereas for many people it may be more important to avoid acquiring
the false belief that their spouses are having affairs than to avoid acquiring the
false belief that they are not so engaged, the converse may well be true of
some insecure, jealous people. The belief that one’s spouse is unfaithful
tends to cause significant psychological discomfort. Even so, avoiding falsely
believing that their spouses are faithful may be so important to some peo-
ple that they test relevant hypotheses in ways that, other things being equal,
are less likely to lead to a false belief in their spouses’ fidelity than to a false
belief in their spouses’ infidelity. Furthermore, data suggestive of infidelity
may be especially salient for these people and contrary data quite pallid by
6. Whether and to what extent subjects display the confirmation bias depends on such
factors as whether they are given a neutral perspective on a hypothesis or, instead, the
perspective of someone whose job it is to detect cheaters. See Gigerenzer and Hug 1992.
266 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
comparison. Don Sharpsteen and Lee Kirkpatrick observe that the “jealousy
complex”—that is, the “thoughts, feelings, and behavior typically associated
with jealousy episodes”—is interpretable as a mechanism “for maintaining
close relationships” and appears to be “triggered by separation, or the threat
of separation, from attachment figures” (1997, 627). It certainly is conceiv-
able that, given a certain psychological profile, a strong desire to maintain
one’s relationship with one’s spouse plays a role in rendering the potential
error of falsely believing one’s spouse to be innocent of infidelity a “costly”
error, in the FTL sense, and more costly than the error of falsely believing
one’s spouse to be guilty. After all, the former error may reduce the prob-
ability that one takes steps to protect the relationship against an intruder.
The FTL theory provides a basis for an account of both straight and twisted
self-deception (Mele 2001, ch. 5).
7. People may be deceived into believing something that they are not deceived
in believing (see Mele 1987, 127–28). A might execute a tricky plan for deceiving B
into believing something that, unbeknownst to A, is true. And A might thereby cause B
to believe this proposition, p. Since p is true, B is not deceived in believing it. Even so, it
is plausible that A deceived B into believing it, if A caused B to believe that p partly by
deceiving him into believing some false propositions suggestive of p.
268 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
If it were to turn out both that my proposed sufficient conditions for self-
deception are not sufficient and that my answer to the explanatory ques-
tion applies only or primarily to phenomena that satisfy my conditions
but fall short of being self-deception, that would definitely be a prob-
lem. But this is not how the conceptual critics of Self-Deception Unmasked
(Mele 2001), whose work is to be discussed here, see things. They are
willing to allow that my answer to the explanatory question applies to
what they count as self-deception. Even so, if the conditions I proposed
are not sufficient for self-deception, some thought should be given to how
to beef them up.
Dana Nelkin argues that “a necessary condition of self-deception is the
desire to believe that p is true, and that this desire causes the self-deceiver
to treat her evidence in a biased way” (2002, 393). She incorporates
this condition into my proposed sufficient conditions for entering self-
deception in acquiring a belief that p in an attempt to provide individu-
ally necessary and jointly sufficient conditions for the phenomenon (394).
Whereas I see an appropriately cautious version of the FTL theory as
providing a basis for a unified account of how both straight and twisted
self-deception happen (Mele 2001, 96–98), Nelkin argues for the need
to postulate a desire to believe that p in this connection. She argues, for
example, that “the jealous husband, who, by hypothesis, does not desire
that his wife is having an affair, does nevertheless want to believe that
she is,” if he is self-deceived in believing that she is so engaged (Nelkin
2002, 395). Nelkin makes it clear both that “the desire to believe is to be
thought of as a real, causally efficacious mental state, and not merely as
an abstraction from our attributions of self-deception” (394) and that it
“need not be conscious” (395).
Imagine two jealous husbands with very similar evidence in very simi-
lar circumstances. Each acquires the false, unwarranted belief that his wife
is having an affair—the belief that a, for short. Impartial observers judge
that the men are clearly and equally unwarranted in believing that a.
The men deal with the evidence in very similar, biased ways; data sugges-
tive of infidelity are especially salient for both; and they spend the same
considerable amount of time and energy mulling the matter over. One of
the men, Jack, has an unconscious desire to believe that a. This desire is
“a real, causally efficacious mental state.” It causes Jack to treat pertinent
evidence in a biased way, and that treatment results in Jack’s acquiring the
belief that a. The other man, John, lacks a desire to believe that a, but he
does have desires that contribute to his having acceptance and rejection
thresholds for a that are just like Jack’s. Suppose, for good measure, that
John has a desire not to acquire a false belief that his wife is innocent of
infidelity and that this desire causes him to treat pertinent evidence in a
biased way, which treatment results in his acquiring the belief that a. John
may also have a desire not to acquire the false belief that his wife is guilty;
Have I Unmasked Self-Deception or Am I Self-Deceived? 269
but if he does, it is much weaker than the desire just mentioned. (A desire
not to acquire a false belief that p is a desire not to believe that p if p is false;
it is not simply a desire not to believe that p.)
On Nelkin’s view (assuming the absence of relevant causal deviance),
the facts about Jack and John entail that Jack enters self-deception in
acquiring the belief that his wife is having an affair, whereas John does not.
The role attributed to the desire to believe that p in Nelkin’s attempted
analysis is a causal one: “this desire causes S to treat evidence concerning
the truth value of p in a biased way” (2002, 394). If desires to believe
that p are well suited for this causal work, so are desires not to acquire a
false belief that not-p. So her claim that S’s having a desire specifically to
believe that p is a conceptually necessary condition of S’s entering self-
deception in acquiring a belief that p is implausible. And given the simi-
larities between the cases of Jack and John, it is very plausible that if Jack
is self-deceived, so is John.
Several philosophers who, like Nelkin, are willing to take (much of) the
explanatory portion of my view on board have argued that self-deception
necessarily involves a failure of self-knowledge and that a person may
satisfy my proposed sufficient conditions for self-deception in the absence
of a failure of the required kind (Holton 2001; Funkhouser 2005; Scott-
Kakures 2002). According to Richard Holton, the following is a case in
point:
Catherine has applied for several jobs recently, and has been unsuccessful
each time. She has also been horribly disappointed each time. She puts
her disappointment down to too much thought. On each occasion she had
spent a great deal of time thinking about the job, had, as a result, imagined
just what it would be like to get it, and so had been devastated when she
didn’t. She has just decided to apply for another job. She thinks that it is
clearly better than her current job; otherwise she wouldn’t be putting in for
it. But she has resolved not to think too deeply about what it is like, or to
examine the evidence that she has; at least not until or unless she gets an
offer. She knows that, were she to think more about the job, there is some
chance that her opinion of its merits would change; but she thinks that the
possibility of error here is worth risking to maintain her equanimity. As it
happens she is radically wrong about the job. It is a terrible job, far worse
than her current one, as a little more reflection would have shown her.
(2001, 60–61)
8. Here I am assuming that, when a person acquires and retains an x, his acquiring it is
among the causes of his retaining it and that the causes of his acquiring it are among the
indirect causes of his retaining it.
270 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
If I had read Rorty’s vignette out of context, I would have been con-
fident that Androvna knew—consciously—that she had cancer but did
not want to reveal that to others. That hypothesis certainly makes good
sense of the details offered. Even so, it is conceivable that Androvna is
self-deceived. If she is, what explains the detailed will and the effusive
letters? Some will suggest that, “deep down” or unconsciously, Androvna
knows or believes that she is dying and that this accounts for these activi-
ties. Assuming that it is conceivable that Androvna does not consciously
believe that she has cancer in the circumstances Rorty describes, is it also
conceivable that she does not unconsciously believe this either?
Yes, it is. Androvna’s not believing, unconsciously or otherwise, that she
has the disease is consistent with her consciously believing that there is a
significant chance that she has it, and that belief, in conjunction with rel-
evant desires, can lead her to make out a will, write the letters, and deflect
questions. (Notice that she may be self-deceived in believing that there is
only a significant chance that she has cancer.) Given Rorty’s description
of the case and the assumption that Androvna lacks the conscious belief
that she has cancer, is it more likely (1) that she believes unconsciously
that she has the disease (has a “type 1” cancer-belief ), or (2) that she
consciously believes that there is a significant chance that she has cancer
without also believing, unconsciously or otherwise, that she has it (has a
“type 2” cancer-belief )? Base rate information is relevant here. My stu-
dents know that there are a great many more blue-collar workers than
lawyers. Yet when I ask them whether a man wearing a nice suit and a tie
is more likely to be a lawyer or a blue-collar worker, most of them answer,
“a lawyer”—at least until the relevance of base rates is made salient. What
are the relative frequencies of type 1 and type 2 beliefs (i.e., unconscious
beliefs of the sort that Funkhouser may want to attribute to Androvna
and conscious beliefs that there is a significant chance that p that fall
short of being beliefs that p)?9 Until one has at least a partial basis for an
answer to this question that would help underwrite the judgment that
Androvna unconsciously believes that she has cancer, one is not entitled
to be confident that she has such a belief. Plainly, we have and act on a
great many type 2 beliefs. For many of us, such beliefs help to explain why
we purchase home insurance, for example, or take an umbrella to work
when we read in the morning paper that there is a 30 percent chance of
rain. If there is anything approaching comparably weighty evidence of
frequent type 1 beliefs, I am not aware of it.10
9. Those who prefer to think in terms of degree of belief should read such expressions
of mine as “S believes that p” as shorthand for “S believes that p to a degree greater than
0.5 (on a scale from 0 to 1).”
10. The concept of unconscious belief in play here does not include so-called “standing
beliefs”—dispositions of a being to have occurrent beliefs that p, which dispositions have a
partial source in occurrent beliefs that p that the being had earlier.
274 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
she does not have cancer; (Hf ) Androvna does not believe that she does
not have cancer, but she does believe that she believes that she does not
have cancer. Funkhouser can stipulate that if Hm is true, then Androvna is
not self-deceived in believing what she does, but stipulation is uninterest-
ing. What might be interesting is an argument that in no Androvna-style
case does the protagonist have the pertinent motivated false first-order
belief. Unless I am deceived, a convincing argument for this will not be
forthcoming.
Funkhouser and I also agree about how false beliefs are produced in
cases of what he calls “self-delusion” ( but not “self-deception”)—namely,
in the same ways they are produced in the Androvna-style cases. In light
of the fact that we agree about this and in light of the points made in the
preceding two paragraphs, a debate about whether or not we should say
that “self-delusion,” in this sense, is a species of self-deception does not
promise to be very interesting.
So have I unmasked self-deception, or am I self-deceived? In Self-
Deception Unmasked and in earlier work, I tried to show that self-deception
is masked by traditional models of the phenomenon that treat it as an
intrapersonal analogue of stereotypical interpersonal deception. Accord-
ing to these models, self-deceivers intentionally deceive themselves into
believing that p, and there is a time at which they believe that p is false
while also believing that p is true. I offered an alternative model of self-
deception and a detailed explanation of how garden-variety self-deception
happens. The critics whose work I have discussed in this article are happy
enough with the explanatory portion of my position. Their worries are
about what I count as self-deception. Someone might claim that if I have
directly unmasked anything, it is not self-deception. Funkhouser comes
close to claiming that; but for the reasons I have offered, I am unper-
suaded. The other critics whose work I have discussed here defend posi-
tions on self-deception that are more similar to mine. Nelkin attempts to
augment my proposed sufficient conditions for entering self-deception
in acquiring a belief that p in such a way as to arrive at individually nec-
essary and jointly sufficient conditions, and Holton and Scott-Kakures,
focusing on self-knowledge, attempt to improve on my proposed suffi-
cient conditions for self-deception. As I explained, I am happy to add a
failure-of-self-knowledge condition to my list of jointly sufficient condi-
tions, and so doing is consistent with my having unmasked self-deception.
Of course, in this article, I have discussed the work only of some critics;
some readers may worry that I am guilty of one-sided evidence-gathering.
However, I have responded to a great many critics elsewhere (especially
in Mele 1997 and 2001), and I wanted to examine interesting objections
to my position on self-deception that I had not yet examined.11
11. For helpful feedback, I am grateful to Eric Funkhouser, Dana Nelkin, Dion
Scott-Kakures, and Neil Van Leeuwen.
276 Truth, Lies, and Self-Deception
References
Audi, R. 1982. “Believing and Affirming.” Mind 91, 115–20.
——— . 1985. “Self-Deception and Rationality.” In Self-Deception and Self-
Understanding, ed. M. Martin. Lawrence: University of Kansas Press, 169–94.
——— . 1997. “Self-Deception vs. Self-Caused Deception: A Comment on Profes-
sor Mele.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20, 104.
Baron, J. 1988. Thinking and Deciding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Davidson, D. 1985. “Deception and Division.” In Actions and Events, ed. E. LePore
and B. McLaughlin. Oxford: Blackwell, 138–48.
Friedrich, J. 1993. “Primary Error Detection and Minimization (PEDMIN) Strate-
gies in Social Cognition: A Reinterpretation of Confirmation Bias Phenomena.”
Psychological Review 100, 298–319.
Funkhouser, E. 2005. “Do the Self-Deceived Get What They Want?” Pacific Philo-
sophical Quarterly 86, 295–312.
Gigerenzer, G., and K. Hug. 1992. “Domain-Specific Reasoning: Social Contracts,
Cheating, and Perspective Change.” Cognition 43, 127–71.
Holton, R. 2001. “What Is the Role of the Self in Self-Deception?” Proceedings of
the Aristotelian Society 101, 53–69.
Kunda, Z. 1987. “Motivated Inference: Self-Serving Generation and Evaluation of
Causal Theories.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 53, 636–47.
——— . 1990. “The Case for Motivated Reasoning.” Psychological Bulletin 108,
480–98.
——— . 1999. Social Cognition. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
McLaughlin, B. 1988. “Exploring the Possibility of Self-Deception in Belief.” In
Perspectives on Self-Deception, ed. B. McLaughlin and A. Rorty. Berkeley: Uni-
versity of California Press, 29–62.
Mele, A. 1982. “Self-Deception, Action, and Will: Comments.” Erkenntnis 18,
159–64.
——— . 1983. “Self-Deception.” Philosophical Quarterly 33, 365–77.
——— . 1987. Irrationality. New York: Oxford University Press.
——— . 1997. “Real Self-Deception.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20, 91–102.
——— . 1999. “Twisted Self-Deception.” Philosophical Psychology 12: 117–37.
——— . 2001. Self-Deception Unmasked. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Nelkin, D. 2002. “Self-Deception, Motivation, and the Desire to Believe.” Pacific
Philosophical Quarterly 83, 384– 406.
Rorty, A. 1988. “The Deceptive Self: Liars, Layers, and Lairs.” In Perspectives
on Self-Deception, ed., B. McLaughlin and A. Rorty. Berkeley: University of
California Press, 11–28.
Scott-Kakures, D. 2002. “At ‘Permanent Risk’: Reasoning and Self-Knowledge in
Self-Deception.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65, 576–603.
Sharpsteen, D., and L. Kirkpatrick. 1997. “Romantic Jealousy and Adult Romantic
Attachment.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 72, 627–40.
Szabados, B. 1985. “The Self, Its Passions, and Self-Deception.” In Self-Deception and
Self-Understanding, ed. M. Martin. Lawrence: University of Kansas Press, 143–68.
Trope, Y., and A. Liberman. 1996. “Social Hypothesis Testing: Cognitive and Moti-
vational Mechanisms.” In Social Psychology: Handbook of Basic Principles, ed.
E. Higgins and A. Kruglanski. New York: Guilford Press, 239–70.
Trope, Y., B. Gervey, and N. Liberman. 1997. “Wishful Thinking from a Pragmatic
Hypothesis-Testing Perspective.” In The Mythomanias: The Nature of Deception
and Self-Deception, ed. M. Myslobodsky. Mahwah, N.J.: Erlbaum, 105–31.
Have I Unmasked Self-Deception or Am I Self-Deceived? 277
Index
277
Index 279