Pertemuan 3 Downs and Jones
Pertemuan 3 Downs and Jones
Pertemuan 3 Downs and Jones
INTERNATIONAL LAW
GEORGE W. DOWNS and MICHAEL A. JONES*
Abstract
Increasingly skeptical about the efficiency and effectiveness of formal multilateral
enforcement mechanisms, a growing number of international relations theorists and
international lawyers have begun to argue that states’ reputational concerns are ac-
tually the principal mechanism for maintaining a high level of treaty compliance.
This essay argues that there are a number of empirical and theoretical reasons for
believing that the actual effects of reputation are both weaker and more complicated
than the standard view of reputation suggests. While states have reason to revise
their estimates of a state’s reputation following a defection or pattern of defections,
they have reason to do so only in connection with those agreements that they believe
are (1) affected by the same or similar sources of fluctuating compliance costs and
(2) valued the same or less by the defecting state. Among the implications of this
is that all but the newest states maintain multiple reputations.
I. Introduction
S95
S96 the journal of legal studies
dard argument, a major—if not the major—reason why states keep com-
mitments, even those that produce a lower level of returns than expected, is
because they fear that any evidence of unreliability will damage their current
cooperative relationships and lead other states to reduce their willingness to
enter into future agreements.2 Since the opportunity costs associated with
this forgone cooperation are substantial, the vast majority of states possess
a strong incentive to behave cooperatively.3
There is, however, empirical evidence to suggest that the impact of rep-
utation is either weaker or more complicated than much of the theoretical
literature suggests. While compliance rates are relatively good in general,
they are often considerably lower than one would expect them to be if every
defection had important implications for every current and future agreement.4
This is true even if we allow for the effects of imperfect information. Even
more suspicious is the fact that it is common for a given state to evidence
very different levels of compliance reliability—the building block of repu-
tational inference—in connection with different agreements. It is difficult to
believe that it is efficient for other states to simply ignore this fact and treat
each state as if it possessed only a single reputation.
Certainly, in everyday life, differentiated historical experience often results
2
International legal theorists use reputation to refer to both (1) the extent to which a state
is considered to be an honorable member of the international community and (2) the degree
to which a state reliably upholds its international commitments. This tends to create confusion
because both can, at least in theory, affect a state’s compliance rate, and the first is to some
extent a function of the second. We say “to some extent” because no one has yet produced a
theory that explains how the two are linked. The focus of this paper is the second, rational
choice meaning of the term, which should be important regardless of whether or not states are
sometimes motivated to comply by a fear of international opprobrium. The reliability with
which a state abides by its commitments determines its value as a prospective partner and
what others are willing to commit in return. It is this rational dimension of reputation that is
chiefly of interest to economists and most political scientists.
3
See Keohane, supra note 1. Reputation operates outside the boundaries of formal treaty
law as well. It plays a critical role in determining the effectiveness of both tacit bargaining
and diplomatic exchanges, or what is generally termed “cheap talk” in the literature. See Anne
E. Sartori, The Might of the Pen: A Reputational Theory of Communication in International
Disputes, 56 Int’l Org. 121 (2002). Reputation expectations are also central to William English’s
explanation of why American states agreed to repay their foreign creditors even after these
creditors were prevented from seeking redress in federal courts during the 1840s. See William
B. English, Understanding the Costs of Sovereign Default: American State Debts in the 1840’s,
86 Am. Econ. Rev. 259 (1996).
4
The literature on the compliance rates associated with different areas is considerable. See
Robert E. Hudec, Enforcing International Trade Law: The Evolution of the Modern GATT
Legal System (1993); Thomas O. Bayard & Kimberly Ann Elliott, Reciprocity and Retaliation
in U.S. Trade Policy (1994); Beth A. Simmons, International Law and State Behavior: Com-
mitment and Compliance in International Monetary Affairs, 94 Am. Pol. Sci. Rev. 819 (2000);
Edwin M. Smith, Understanding Dynamic Obligations: Arms Control Agreements, 64 S. Cal.
L. Rev. 1549 (1991); Randolph M. Siverson & Joel King, Attributes of National Alliance
Membership and War Participation, 1815–1965, 24 Am. J. Pol. Sci. 1 (1980); George W.
Downs, Enforcement and the Evolution of Cooperation, 19 Mich. J. Int’l L. 319 (1998); The
Implementation and Effectiveness of International Environmental Commitments: Theory and
Practice (David G. Victor, Kal Raustiala, & Eugene B. Skolnikoff eds. 1998).
reputation and international law S97
5
While both costs and benefits of an agreement can vary stochastically, we will focus on
costs in what follows to keep things as simple as possible.
S98 the journal of legal studies
are most likely to lie at the center of the most valued cooperative relationships.
In multilateral public goods agreements such as those that are prevalent in
the area of environmental regulation or human rights, the reputational con-
sequences of defection depend on the size of the treaty and the relative
importance that states assign to it.
The implications of this theory for the power of reputation to ensure
compliance with international law generally are substantial. Chief among
these is the fact that, except in the case of new states and regimes that are
believed to constitute sharp departures from the historical norm, the repu-
tational implications of noncompliance are narrower and hence smaller than
much of the literature suggests. This means that even in an increasingly
integrated international system, reputational concerns cannot by themselves
begin to ensure a high level of compliance with every international agreement.
At the same time, however, reputational concerns are an important force for
compliance in connection with certain agreements.
6
Drew Fudenberg & Jean Tirole, Game Theory, ch. 9 (1991).
7
Joel Sobel, A Theory of Credibility, 52 Rev. Econ. Stud. 557 (1985).
8
Reinhard Selten, The Chain Store Paradox, 9 Theory & Decision 127 (1978).
reputation and international law S99
who are either potential cooperative partners of the defecting state or partners
in a different agreement that might potentially be affected.9
Keohane was one of the first to distinguish between the reciprocal expec-
tations each possessed about the other’s short-term response to a violation
and expectations about the broader impact that a violation would have via
the response of states outside the agreement. “Regimes rely not only on
decentralized enforcement through retaliation but on government desires to
maintain their reputations.”10 “For reasons of reputation, as well as fear of
retaliation and concerns about the effects of precedents, egoistic governments
may follow the rules and principles of international regimes even when
myopic self-interest counsels them not to.’’11 In the economics literature,
Michihiro Kandori also takes care to distinguish between personal enforce-
ment or the immediate retaliation by the victim and sanctioning behavior of
the wider community in response to information about defection.12
Having settled at least provisionally on a working definition of what con-
stitutes a reputational effect, we can begin to examine the central question
for both international lawyers and international relations theorists alike: How
much more cooperation exists than would otherwise be the case because
states must worry about their reputation? While positions vary somewhat,
the dominant view in the literature is that reputation plays an extremely
important role in promoting compliance.13 According to the traditional theory,
states carry a general reputation for cooperativeness that determines their
attractiveness as a treaty partner both now and in the future. Because a
defection in connection with any agreement will impose reputation costs that
affect all current and future agreements, states are motivated to comply with
their commitments even in circumstances where they would otherwise defect.
Thus, the literature is rife with references to the cost a state will pay for
losing its reputation for reliably maintaining its commitments and being “law
abiding.” Reflecting on what one should make of the exemplary record of
9
Another related reason for treating reputation and reciprocal retaliation separately is to
avoid inference problems that can lead to faulty prescriptions. For example, empirical re-
searchers in the institutionalist tradition regularly conclude that reputation is responsible for
whatever decentralized cooperation they discover. This suggests that cooperation will be best
increased by adopting policies that will increase system transparency on the grounds that
anything that increases the level of community awareness about compliance will operate to
increase the salutary effects of reputation. Yet if this “reputational” effect is due to a reciprocal
response—or expectations about a reciprocal response—such a policy will be ineffective.
10
Keohane, supra note 1, at 108.
11
Id. at 106.
12
Michihiro Kandori, Social Norms and Community Enforcement, 59 Rev. Econ. Stud. 63
(1992).
13
Authors often oscillate in their characterization of reputational effects between what we
will call the traditional view that states possess a single reputation and a more regime-specific
perspective in which states have a different reputation in connection with different regimes.
For this reason, our association of a given author with a given perspective should be taken
only as indicating our interpretation of a specific text.
S100 the journal of legal studies
have an overall average compliance rate, but the other states have no reason
to be preoccupied with it.
A second difficulty with the notion of reputation as a grand strategy is
that it inevitably leads one to ask what strategic interest a state might have
in fashioning a reputation that is less than perfect when the cost of noncom-
pliance is believed to be so high. One possibility is that less-than-perfect
reputations are the product of misperception. An imperfect technology of
treaty oversight leads a treaty partner to wrongly infer that the state has
defected when in reality it has not. While doubtless such mistakes occur, the
likelihood that most suspected defections have really not taken place is small,
in part because both sides should have an incentive to reduce any such costly
mistakes over time. In any event, no one denies that most defections are real
enough. Another possibility is that states are periodically defecting from
agreements as part of some mixed strategy. However, this inefficient even-
tuality also seems unlikely since agreements are painstakingly negotiated.
Some other explanation for periodic defection and imperfect levels of reli-
ability clearly seems needed.21
27
If treaty members know ahead of time that capacity limitations are going to be a persistent
problem, they should revise the agreement for the sake of efficiency. If they know that certain
social or economic conditions will make it impossible for a state to comply with an agreement,
they can describe these conditions in the agreement so that they do not count as ‘‘intentional’’
noncompliance—as they often do in the case of loans and in many broad and far-reaching
agreements. There are limits to the extent to which this can be done, however, and once we
are past those limits we can sensibly talk about shocks that can affect a state’s reliability or
reputation in equilibrium, at least if they are transient.
28
There is a dangerous tendency in the literature to broaden the definition of “unintentional’’
to cover any defection that is remotely associated with a transient event. This can be a problem
because each of the Chayses’s three factors involves an endogenous element that can easily
lead to moral hazard. See Downs, supra note 4, at 331.
29
Another source of indeterminacy with a similar effect springs from endemic rather then
transient uncertainties associated with the cost of compliance. For example, developed states,
much less developing states, do not know exactly how much it will cost to achieve different
levels of compliance with complicated agreements like CITES or the World Trade Organization
(WTO). In this cost-informational sense, the contract that each state makes is necessarily
incomplete. Under these circumstances, it may also be more efficient to embrace a moderate
level of punishment.
reputation and international law S105
in utility by simply raising the penalty for defection. For example, states
could collectively agree to respond to a defection by immediately abrogating
the treaty forever and refusing to renegotiate it—a punishment known ap-
propriately enough as the “grim strategy.’’ Assuming that a state’s discount
rate is not extremely high, the cost that this represents should be sufficient
to offset any transient benefit that a state can get by defecting when it
experienced the kind of shocks described above.
Yet this is not the course that states pursue. On the contrary, the penalties
specified in real-world treaties never resemble anything approaching the dra-
conian proportions of the grim strategy and are characteristically relatively
weak. In the history of international cooperation there are few if any instances
where a state punishes a state that violates an agreement by abrogating the
treaty and refusing to enter into a similar treaty. One might argue that this
is a consequence of the fact that only modest penalties are needed to provide
near-perfect compliance; therefore there is no reason to use the grim strategy.
However, this cannot be the explanation because, as we have already seen,
compliance, while often good, is usually less than perfect in any number of
areas.
Another, more sophisticated, answer to the question of why states do not
use stronger penalties to insure perfect compliance involves a slippery con-
cept called “renegotiation proofness,” which puts a limit on the size of the
punishment that can be used. To understand how it works, assume that a
group of oil-producing states decides to maximize cooperation by collectively
agreeing to punish overproduction on the part of any one state by jointly
abrogating the treaty forever. Some time after the treaty is made, one state
ends up increasing production and violating the treaty because of some un-
expected series of events such as its leader having to raise money quickly
to overcome a rebellion in one of its provinces. The other states respond by
making good on their punishment threat and resume production at the level
that existed before the agreement was signed. After a significant time period
elapses, the president of the state that violated the treaty communicates to
the other states’ leaders that, while she appreciates their mutual pledge to
defect forever in the face of any violation, she can assure them that the period
of unrestricted competition that has ensued has already cost her state more
than it gained by breaking the treaty: “I and my state have already paid the
price of our mistake. To continue producing at the competitive level will
hurt you as well as us and it will accomplish nothing. Let us (renegotiate a)
return to restricted production so that we will all be better off.”
This is the logic of renegotiation proofness. In prospect, whenever it is
believed by the players that a punishment strategy would be vulnerable to
such an offer, it is said not to be renegotiation proof and, as such, is judged
not to be credible. As a practical matter, one can think of renegotiation
proofness as restricting the size of the punishment to the largest value that
S106 the journal of legal studies
30
For more extended discussions of renegotiation proofness, see Dilip J. Abreu, David Pearce,
& Ennio Stacchetti, Optimal Character of Equilibria with Imperfect Monitoring, 39 J. Econ.
Theory, 251 (1986); Jean-Pierre Benoit & Vijay Krishna, Renegotiation in Finitely Repeated
Games, 61 Econometrica 303 (1993); B. Douglas Bernheim, Bezalel Peleg, & Michael D.
Whinston, Coalition-Proof Nash Equilibria I: Concepts, 42 J. Econ. Theory 1 (1987); B. Douglas
Bernheim & Debraj Ray, Collective Dynamic Consistency in Repeated Games, 1 Games &
Econ. Behav. 295 (1989); Joseph Farrell & Eric Maskin, Renegotiation in Repeated Games,
1 Games & Econ. Behav. 327 (1989); David Pearce, Renegotiation-Proof Equilibria: Collective
Rationality and Intertemporal Cooperation (typescript revision of 1987 Cowles Foundation
Discussion Paper No. 855, Yale Univ., Dep’t Econ. 1988); Eric Van Damme, Renegotiation-
Proof Equilibria in Repeated Prisoner’s Dilemma, 47 J. Econ. Theory 206 (1989).
31
Alan O. Sykes, Mandatory Retaliation for Breach of Trade Agreements: Some Thoughts
on the Strategic Design of Section 301, 8 B.U. Int’l L. J. 301 (1990); George W. Downs &
David M. Rocke, Optimal Imperfection? Domestic Uncertainty and Institutions in International
Relations 88–89 (1995).
reputation and international law S107
32
See Susanne Lohmann, Linkage Politics, 41 J. Conflict Resol. 38 (1997), for a discussion
of the circumstances where linkages are possible. Under the best of circumstances, it is ex-
tremely unlikely that these conditions will ever be present in connection with more that a
handful of agreements, and the existence of a stochastic cost structure would reduce the
likelihood still further.
33
Another sort of linkage behavior whereby a defecting state’s reputation is downgraded in
two areas such as trade and human rights following its failure to comply with its agreement
in one area is theoretically possible (see id.). However, the aggregate effect of such linkage is
also likely to be modest. This is partly because it requires a special complementarity in the
utilities that states place on the linked agreements that will rarely be present and partly because
S108 the journal of legal studies
34
Whether the underlying logic of these authors who implicitly treat reputational implications
as being confined to a specific regime is the same as that described here is unclear since they
rarely give the reasons for their position. It is possible that some of them actually embrace
the unitary perspective and only appear to believe in regime-specific reputations in the context
of a given article whose focus is regime specific.
S110 the journal of legal studies
35
Mercer, supra note 20, at 7.
36
Mercer has generated the most elaborate empirical and theoretical critique of the traditional
view of reputation; however, we are trying to explain somewhat different aspects of reputation.
Mercer is interested in the reputation that states assign other states for resolve or “the extent
to which a state will risk war to achieve its objectives” (id. at 2). We are interested in the
reputational judgments states make with respect to the likelihood that other states will honor
their treaty commitments in the future, a broader topic that has relevance to trade and envi-
ronmental cooperation as well as to security commitments. Nevertheless, we agree with Mercer
that states tend to have multiple and contradictory reputations (see id. at 32). The same is true
of his contention that “actors base their predictions on the specifics of the situation or perhaps
the history of a continuing relationship, and not on a state’s aggregate behavior” (id. at 24).
We are not surprised by the fact that “[l]ike their Soviet counterparts, American decision makers
did not seem to infer that behavior in one area results in similar behavior in another area”
(id.). Unlike Mercer, however, we do not see the existence of such behavior as a challenge to
game theory so much as a challenge to the assumption of actor homogeneity that was made
reputation and international law S111
The states that do have to worry about these sorts of commitment failures
are smaller states that believe they are valued the same as the states that
were abandoned. Of course, it is more complicated than this—the cost of
fulfilling the commitment matters as well as the benefit of fulfilling it, and
these costs might vary in such a way as to give the smaller state more or
less confidence. Still, the principle that small states have the most to learn
by paying attention to the noncompliance of their partners in connection to
other relationships seems to be a general one. Because their relationship is
likely to be viewed by the defector as being of the same or less importance,
the chances that they too will be the victim of defection is fairly large. Large
states do not have to worry as much about the noncompliance of a partner
in connection with a third party spreading to them unless the third party is
another large state. Otherwise, there is a reasonable likelihood that the de-
fecting state values their relationship more.
The connection between the value of a relationship and the perceived
opportunity costs associated with a contemplated defection has two effects
on the extent to which reputation sustains international law. The first is
perverse, if unremarkable. The fact that the reputational consequences of
defecting from an important relationship are larger than those of defecting
from a less important relationship means that reputation protects strong states
more than weak states. This is really not so surprising. The reputational
implications of a firm’s violating a contract with its most important client
are greater than they would be if the client were unimportant. However, the
fact that reputation protects most those who require the least protection is
still disconcerting.
The tendency of the magnitude of the reputational implications of a de-
fection to be directly proportionate to the value of a relationship also implies
that the contribution that reputation makes to sustain international law co-
operation is greatest in connection with agreements that states think are the
most beneficial.37 Conversely, it has the least effect in connection with agree-
ments that produce the smallest amount of benefits. This predicts that the
average compliance rate will be somewhat higher in connection with rela-
tively important agreements. It also may help account for why the quality
of the compliance data that are available is so frequently related to the
importance of the agreement.
From a reputational standpoint, the utility of the cooperation that an agree-
ment represents or the opportunity cost of defecting from it is only half the
story. Its reputational consequences are also a function of the extent to which
the stochastic cost function that leads to defection from it is correlated with
those connected with other regimes. While little is known about this, it seems
for convenience in models designed to look at issues differently than those that interest Mercer
or us.
37
This assumes that we are talking about agreements that are affected by the same stochastic
cost function.
S112 the journal of legal studies
likely that trade agreements are quite “central” in this respect, since many
of the shocks that affect trade agreements such as recessions also affect
compliance with agreements in other areas. Security agreements also have
a claim to centrality. Major shocks in that area are likely to affect trade
agreements as well as human rights agreements.38 Defections from environ-
mental agreements, at least at the present time, seem to have more narrow
implications for treaties in other areas, as have human rights treaties. Hence,
their reputational consequences, at least in the rational choice sense, should
be more restricted.39 It follows, ceteris paribus, that reputation promotes
compliance with international law most in trade and security and least in
environmental regulation and human rights. The most important reputational
consequences are those connected with the most important agreements in
these areas.
The disconcerting implication that reputation fosters cooperation more in
connection with large states than with small holds only for treaties that
regulate the exchange of private or club goods where exclusion is possible
such as trade agreements and alliances. If we consider public-goods agree-
ments, the relative importance of states in determining the importance of a
violation recedes into the background because it is no longer possible to
defect against a particular state: any defection affects every state in the
agreement. In this situation the contribution of reputation to promoting com-
pliance and sustaining international law becomes a function of the importance
of the agreement as a whole. The agreements that get the most reputational
help are the agreements that states value the most and whose stochastic cost
component is the most highly correlated with that of other agreements.
Other effects of reputation on compliance with international law are more
marginal, but worth noting. Just as one would expect, new states and states
with new regimes will on average be more sensitive to reputational consid-
eration and hence more apt to comply with international law than the average
state. This is because they have not yet had the opportunity to develop
multiple reputations by signaling consistent variations in their reliability rates
across agreements. However, if the incidence of compliance opportunities is
relatively high, as it is in trade and human rights agreements, it will not take
the newcomer long to establish multiple reputations. In an area like security
where the opportunities to comply with a defensive alliance are sparser,
multiple reputations will take longer to establish, and strategic behavior of
all sorts will flourish longer. This fact might partially account for why rep-
utation is such a popular topic for discussion in security circles and why
there are so many disagreements abut the reputational consequences of a
particular act.
38
Joanne Gowa, Allies, Adversaries, and International Trade (1994).
39
The reputational damage with respect to a state’s social standing in the international
community might of course be as great or greater.
reputation and international law S113
V. Concluding Comments
The claims of this paper that the reputational consequences of most de-
fections affect only a subset of current and future agreements may be inter-
preted as further support for the revisionist claim that reputation is irrelevant.
This is not the case. To say that the power of reputation to enforce compliance
is usually modest is no more a dismissal of reputation than the claim that
many cooperative agreements are relatively shallow is a dismissal of co-
operation. Reputation matters, just not so much as some might like.
Of course, the theory presented here is relatively simple. It is designed
primarily to understand the boundaries of reputational inference and how
they relate to two stylized facts of cooperative life not easily explained by
most conventional theories of reputation: (1) states have different levels of
reliability in connection with different agreements, and (2) there is consid-
erable evidence that states possess multiple or segmented reputations. In-
evitably, many other interesting issues have been ignored or mentioned only
in passing.
One set of such issues is connected with the role of information and the
capacity of states to process it. The model we have described here is very
information intensive. To behave optimally, states not only have to keep track
of the reliability rates connected with different agreements, but they have to
estimate the degree of similarity among them with respect to the values states
assign them and the factors that determine variations in their compliance
costs. Even if we are correct in believing that states pay attention to these
factors, their capacity for making distinctions may not be as refined as ef-
ficiency demands.40
Information-processing issues are particularly important for understanding
the impact of reputation on new states and states that have recently expe-
rienced wholesale changes in their form of government. Although the inter-
national system usually contains only a handful of these states, the impact
of reputation on their fortunes may be far greater than for more established
states. How quickly can these states develop multiple reputations, and what
is the cost of not being able to do so immediately? Where are multiple
reputations likely to first appear? Conversely, what are the reputational im-
plications of the fact that compliance information for many agreements is
extremely poor and often based on self-reporting?
Finally, the question of how reputation affects the fortunes of small and
or developing states demands more attention because it contrasts so sharply
with the picture of reputation leveling the playing field between the weak
40
A more behavioral approach might also prove helpful regarding this issue.
S114 the journal of legal studies
and the strong. Not only does it appear that a defection against such states
tends to have the fewest reputational consequences for the violator, but the
reputational penalties that they pay for their own defections will tend to be
quite large.