Pertemuan 3 Downs and Jones

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 20

REPUTATION, COMPLIANCE, AND

INTERNATIONAL LAW
GEORGE W. DOWNS and MICHAEL A. JONES*

Abstract
Increasingly skeptical about the efficiency and effectiveness of formal multilateral
enforcement mechanisms, a growing number of international relations theorists and
international lawyers have begun to argue that states’ reputational concerns are ac-
tually the principal mechanism for maintaining a high level of treaty compliance.
This essay argues that there are a number of empirical and theoretical reasons for
believing that the actual effects of reputation are both weaker and more complicated
than the standard view of reputation suggests. While states have reason to revise
their estimates of a state’s reputation following a defection or pattern of defections,
they have reason to do so only in connection with those agreements that they believe
are (1) affected by the same or similar sources of fluctuating compliance costs and
(2) valued the same or less by the defecting state. Among the implications of this
is that all but the newest states maintain multiple reputations.

I. Introduction

I nternational relations theorists and international lawyers have long ar-


gued that reputational concerns help ensure that states maintain their agree-
ments. In the past decade, a growing preoccupation with international co-
operation and its analytical underpinnings have combined to increase the
theoretical centrality of reputation. In the wake of works such as those by
Robert Keohane, Robert Axelrod, and Paul Milgrom, Douglass North, and
Barry Weingast, it now stands as the linchpin of the dominant neoliberal
institutionalist theory of decentralized cooperation.1 According to the stan-

* Downs is Professor, Department of Politics, New York University. Jones is Assistant


Professor, Department of Mathematics, Montclair State University, and Visiting Scholar, De-
partment of Politics, New York University. The authors wish to thank David Rocke, Robert
Keohane, Michael Gilligan, Bruce Bueno de Mesquita, Eric Posner, Jack Goldsmith, Alan
Sykes, an anonymous referee, and participants in the conference Rational Choice and Inter-
national Law, University of Chicago Law School, April 2001, for their comments on this essay
and related papers.
1
See Robert O. Keohane, After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political
Economy 105–8 (1984); Robert Axelrod, The Evolution of Cooperation (1984); Paul R. Mil-
grom, Douglass C. North, & Barry R. Weingast, The Role of Institutions in the Revival of
Trade: The Medieval Law Merchant, Private Judges, and Champagne Fairs, 2 Econ. & Pol. 1
(1990).

[Journal of Legal Studies, vol. XXXI (January 2002)]


䉷 2002 by The University of Chicago. All rights reserved. 0047-2530/2002/3101-0013$01.50

S95
S96 the journal of legal studies

dard argument, a major—if not the major—reason why states keep com-
mitments, even those that produce a lower level of returns than expected, is
because they fear that any evidence of unreliability will damage their current
cooperative relationships and lead other states to reduce their willingness to
enter into future agreements.2 Since the opportunity costs associated with
this forgone cooperation are substantial, the vast majority of states possess
a strong incentive to behave cooperatively.3
There is, however, empirical evidence to suggest that the impact of rep-
utation is either weaker or more complicated than much of the theoretical
literature suggests. While compliance rates are relatively good in general,
they are often considerably lower than one would expect them to be if every
defection had important implications for every current and future agreement.4
This is true even if we allow for the effects of imperfect information. Even
more suspicious is the fact that it is common for a given state to evidence
very different levels of compliance reliability—the building block of repu-
tational inference—in connection with different agreements. It is difficult to
believe that it is efficient for other states to simply ignore this fact and treat
each state as if it possessed only a single reputation.
Certainly, in everyday life, differentiated historical experience often results

2
International legal theorists use reputation to refer to both (1) the extent to which a state
is considered to be an honorable member of the international community and (2) the degree
to which a state reliably upholds its international commitments. This tends to create confusion
because both can, at least in theory, affect a state’s compliance rate, and the first is to some
extent a function of the second. We say “to some extent” because no one has yet produced a
theory that explains how the two are linked. The focus of this paper is the second, rational
choice meaning of the term, which should be important regardless of whether or not states are
sometimes motivated to comply by a fear of international opprobrium. The reliability with
which a state abides by its commitments determines its value as a prospective partner and
what others are willing to commit in return. It is this rational dimension of reputation that is
chiefly of interest to economists and most political scientists.
3
See Keohane, supra note 1. Reputation operates outside the boundaries of formal treaty
law as well. It plays a critical role in determining the effectiveness of both tacit bargaining
and diplomatic exchanges, or what is generally termed “cheap talk” in the literature. See Anne
E. Sartori, The Might of the Pen: A Reputational Theory of Communication in International
Disputes, 56 Int’l Org. 121 (2002). Reputation expectations are also central to William English’s
explanation of why American states agreed to repay their foreign creditors even after these
creditors were prevented from seeking redress in federal courts during the 1840s. See William
B. English, Understanding the Costs of Sovereign Default: American State Debts in the 1840’s,
86 Am. Econ. Rev. 259 (1996).
4
The literature on the compliance rates associated with different areas is considerable. See
Robert E. Hudec, Enforcing International Trade Law: The Evolution of the Modern GATT
Legal System (1993); Thomas O. Bayard & Kimberly Ann Elliott, Reciprocity and Retaliation
in U.S. Trade Policy (1994); Beth A. Simmons, International Law and State Behavior: Com-
mitment and Compliance in International Monetary Affairs, 94 Am. Pol. Sci. Rev. 819 (2000);
Edwin M. Smith, Understanding Dynamic Obligations: Arms Control Agreements, 64 S. Cal.
L. Rev. 1549 (1991); Randolph M. Siverson & Joel King, Attributes of National Alliance
Membership and War Participation, 1815–1965, 24 Am. J. Pol. Sci. 1 (1980); George W.
Downs, Enforcement and the Evolution of Cooperation, 19 Mich. J. Int’l L. 319 (1998); The
Implementation and Effectiveness of International Environmental Commitments: Theory and
Practice (David G. Victor, Kal Raustiala, & Eugene B. Skolnikoff eds. 1998).
reputation and international law S97

in individuals and organizations being assigned what are effectively multiple


reputations that operate to limit the reputational consequences of a given
incident. You have hired a teenager to construct a Web site. Although the
teenager claims to be an expert HTML programmer, he has been foiled by
rudimentary problems. If the teenager is not someone you know very well
and who has only just moved into the neighborhood, you might infer that
he is not trustworthy and assign him that reputation. As a consequence, you
might very well dismiss an idea you have been discussing with him earlier
that day whereby you would pay him to take care of your house, car, and
pets when you were in Greece for the months of January and February. If,
however, the teenager is someone whom you have known since he was a
child and who has faithfully carried out work that you have paid him to do
in the past, it is more likely that you will draw the much narrower reputational
inference that he simply knows much less about programming than he thinks
he does. As a consequence, you make a mental note to be extremely cautious
with regard to allowing the teenager to tutor your young daughter in con-
nection with her introductory programming class. However, you do not feel
the need to set aside the caretaking agreement that you two had previously
discussed.
This paper argues that the reputational consequences of a state’s noncom-
pliance with a given treaty are similarly limited by the history of its coop-
erative relationships with the other member states. While states have reason
to revise their estimate of a state’s reputation following a defection or pattern
of defections, they have reason to do so only in connection with agreements
that they believe (1) are affected by the same or similar sources of fluctuating
compliance costs (or benefits) and (2) are valued the same or less by the
defecting state.5 Over time, states develop a number of reputations, often
quite different, in connection with different regimes and even with different
treaties within the same regime.
The surplus value produced by a relationship is important because it offsets
the invariably fluctuating costs of compliance. If a relationship is of little
value to a state and produces only a small surplus, the slightest increase in
compliance costs will lead to defection. A relationship that yields a higher
surplus will not be disrupted by such a minor fluctuation in costs because
compliance still produces a positive net benefit. It follows that, in general,
states (1) will defect from low-net-benefit relationships more frequently than
they will from high-benefit relationships and (2) will defect from low-benefit
relationships whenever they defect from high-benefit relationships but not
vice versa.
This implies that in treaties where the benefits of cooperation are exclud-
able, reputation tends to protect powerful states the most, since large states

5
While both costs and benefits of an agreement can vary stochastically, we will focus on
costs in what follows to keep things as simple as possible.
S98 the journal of legal studies

are most likely to lie at the center of the most valued cooperative relationships.
In multilateral public goods agreements such as those that are prevalent in
the area of environmental regulation or human rights, the reputational con-
sequences of defection depend on the size of the treaty and the relative
importance that states assign to it.
The implications of this theory for the power of reputation to ensure
compliance with international law generally are substantial. Chief among
these is the fact that, except in the case of new states and regimes that are
believed to constitute sharp departures from the historical norm, the repu-
tational implications of noncompliance are narrower and hence smaller than
much of the literature suggests. This means that even in an increasingly
integrated international system, reputational concerns cannot by themselves
begin to ensure a high level of compliance with every international agreement.
At the same time, however, reputational concerns are an important force for
compliance in connection with certain agreements.

II. The Traditional Approach to Reputation


As in game theory generally, a player’s reputation is viewed here as a
summary of its opponents’ current beliefs about the player’s compliance
strategy or set of strategies in connection with various commitments.6 The
higher its opponents’ expectation about how reliably a state will maintain
its commitments, the better the state’s reputation. Joel Sobel is among the
first to explicitly connect reputation and reliability within the context of
cooperation.7 Most earlier papers on reputation equated reputation with the
ability of an incumbent monopolist to deter challenges by smaller firms; these
earlier papers are part of the “chain-store” tradition, referring to the chain-
store paradox of Reinhard Selten.8
Although reciprocal and reputational responses to defection are sometimes
lumped together in the literature, we will distinguish between them in what
follows. The former category refers to retaliation by the “victim” state(s)
immediately following a defection and/or the punishment meted out by the
international organization charged with managing a given agreement. The
latter refers to the negative consequences that follow from states readjusting
their estimates of the defecting state’s expected reliability. This is in keeping
with the common language definition of reputation that focuses primarily on
a future beyond the immediate, on agreements other than the one in which
defection has taken place, and on the response of a community of actors

6
Drew Fudenberg & Jean Tirole, Game Theory, ch. 9 (1991).
7
Joel Sobel, A Theory of Credibility, 52 Rev. Econ. Stud. 557 (1985).
8
Reinhard Selten, The Chain Store Paradox, 9 Theory & Decision 127 (1978).
reputation and international law S99

who are either potential cooperative partners of the defecting state or partners
in a different agreement that might potentially be affected.9
Keohane was one of the first to distinguish between the reciprocal expec-
tations each possessed about the other’s short-term response to a violation
and expectations about the broader impact that a violation would have via
the response of states outside the agreement. “Regimes rely not only on
decentralized enforcement through retaliation but on government desires to
maintain their reputations.”10 “For reasons of reputation, as well as fear of
retaliation and concerns about the effects of precedents, egoistic governments
may follow the rules and principles of international regimes even when
myopic self-interest counsels them not to.’’11 In the economics literature,
Michihiro Kandori also takes care to distinguish between personal enforce-
ment or the immediate retaliation by the victim and sanctioning behavior of
the wider community in response to information about defection.12
Having settled at least provisionally on a working definition of what con-
stitutes a reputational effect, we can begin to examine the central question
for both international lawyers and international relations theorists alike: How
much more cooperation exists than would otherwise be the case because
states must worry about their reputation? While positions vary somewhat,
the dominant view in the literature is that reputation plays an extremely
important role in promoting compliance.13 According to the traditional theory,
states carry a general reputation for cooperativeness that determines their
attractiveness as a treaty partner both now and in the future. Because a
defection in connection with any agreement will impose reputation costs that
affect all current and future agreements, states are motivated to comply with
their commitments even in circumstances where they would otherwise defect.
Thus, the literature is rife with references to the cost a state will pay for
losing its reputation for reliably maintaining its commitments and being “law
abiding.” Reflecting on what one should make of the exemplary record of

9
Another related reason for treating reputation and reciprocal retaliation separately is to
avoid inference problems that can lead to faulty prescriptions. For example, empirical re-
searchers in the institutionalist tradition regularly conclude that reputation is responsible for
whatever decentralized cooperation they discover. This suggests that cooperation will be best
increased by adopting policies that will increase system transparency on the grounds that
anything that increases the level of community awareness about compliance will operate to
increase the salutary effects of reputation. Yet if this “reputational” effect is due to a reciprocal
response—or expectations about a reciprocal response—such a policy will be ineffective.
10
Keohane, supra note 1, at 108.
11
Id. at 106.
12
Michihiro Kandori, Social Norms and Community Enforcement, 59 Rev. Econ. Stud. 63
(1992).
13
Authors often oscillate in their characterization of reputational effects between what we
will call the traditional view that states possess a single reputation and a more regime-specific
perspective in which states have a different reputation in connection with different regimes.
For this reason, our association of a given author with a given perspective should be taken
only as indicating our interpretation of a specific text.
S100 the journal of legal studies

compliance associated with most agreements, Scott Barrett states, “A dam-


aged reputation resulting from noncompliance can make it difficult for a
deviant to enter into future agreements. Even a single deviation carries the
risk of precipitating general erosion in law abidance, to the detriment of all
states.”14 In speaking about the implications of India’s failing to adhere to
the Comprehensive Test Ban after its prominent multidecade campaign for
its passage, Richard Williamson speaks of the “severe costs to the nation’s
reputation and perception as a trustworthy member of the international com-
munity.”15 Andrew Hurrell and Benedict Kingsbury argue that “states gen-
erally comply with international obligations . . . because of their broader
concern with their reputation as reliable partners and their interest in a rule
governed . . . international system.”16 And Richard Parker speculates that
states complied with the International Convention for the Conservation of
Atlantic Tuna Tuna-Dolphin Program even after suspending their formal
participation in order to “preserve their reputation as reliable negotiating
partners.”17
Abram and Antonia Chayes also believe that the power of reputational
concerns to promote compliance is considerable and rivals the deterrent effect
of expectations about reciprocal defection: “But in international organiza-
tions, as in other political settings, specific reciprocity is not the only or even
the most important form of exchange. When a member of an organization
goes back on a commitment, it compromises in some degree its reputation
as a reliable partner and jeopardizes it ability to continue to reap organiza-
tional benefits.”18 Elsewhere, in support of the power of reputation, they
reference Oran Young’s argument that the forces of “social opprobrium” and
“the sense of shame or social disgrace” will work to induce treaty
compliance.19
No detailed justification of the traditional theory of reputation exists in
the literature, so one can only speculate about the rationale for thinking that
states possess a single, unitary reputation for cooperation. This is the as-
sumption that states possess a single reputation for cooperation that char-
acterizes its expected reliability in connection with every agreement to which
it is a party.
14
Scott Barrett, International Cooperation and the International Commons, 10 Duke Envtl.
L. & Pol’y F. 131, 139 (1999).
15
Richard L. Williamson, Jr., Law and the H-Bomb: Strengthening the Nonproliferation
Regime to Impede Advanced Proliferation, 28 Cornell Int’l L. J. 71, 72 (1995).
16
Andrew Hurrell & Benedict Kingsbury, The International Politics of the Environment: An
Introduction, in The International Politics of the Environment 1 (Andrew Hurrell & Benedict
Kingsbury eds. 1992).
17
Richard W. Parker, The Use and Abuse of Trade Leverage to Protect the Global Commons:
What We Can Learn from the Tuna-Dolphin Conflict, 12 Geo. Int’l Envtl. L. Rev. 1, 2 (1999).
18
Abram Chayes & Antonia H. Chayes, The New Sovereignty: Compliance with International
Regulatory Agreements 273 (1995).
19
Id. at 152.
reputation and international law S101

One possible justification is that a state’s general propensity to cooperate


is attributable to some fundamental underlying attribute of the state such as
the ideology of its leadership or its geopolitical position. The very term
“general propensity to comply” seems to imply this. Under this logic, a
defection anywhere has implications everywhere because it constitutes new
evidence about the basic underlying nature of the state. This dispositional
vision of reputation holds some attractions for realists who tend to reify the
state and are attracted to the idea of a national character, but it has several
weaknesses.20 One such weakness is that the idea of an immutable national
character is inconsistent with the rhetoric of calculation that partisans of the
unitary perspective often employ when referring to a state’s realization that
it needs to build a strong reputation.
A more significant weakness of this justification of the unitary-reputation
theory is that it does not help us understand why states have different com-
pliance rates in conjunction with different regimes and often with different
treaties within the same regime. Instead, the character trait perspective gives
us every reason to expect that a general propensity to cooperate should
manifest itself in relatively uniform compliance rates, in the same way that
we expect a person’s general level of honesty to reflect itself uniformly across
all of the dealings in which she is involved.
An alternative justification for embracing the unitary view of reputation
is that it reflects a state’s grand strategy. This is more consistent with the
rhetoric of most unitary theorists than the reputation-as-character explanation,
and it is more consistent with the contention that states generally maintain
a strong reputation for compliance because it is in their interest to do so.
The grand-strategy justification also appears better able than the reputation-
as-character idea to explain why compliance rates vary from regime to regime
or within a regime. It does not seem unreasonable to believe that a state
might have some broad strategic interest in having a higher compliance rate
in one area than in another or even within a regime category.
Unfortunately, the assumption that a state might be interested in main-
taining different reputations in different areas contradicts the premise that
states have a unitary reputation in the first place. Other states are bound to
notice that the state has a higher compliance rate in some areas than in others
and to condition their behavior on the state’s reputation in each area and in
conjunction with each treaty in the same area. If they do not do so, they will
be behaving irrationally. Once this happens, the state can no longer mean-
ingfully be said to have a single reputation in any strategic sense. It possesses
multiple reputations whether it likes it or not. A state will, of course, always
20
Jonathan Mercer contends that a “dispositional reputation” exists that adheres in the basic
character of the actor and is independent of the actor’s underlying utility function and other
aspects of context; see Jonathan Mercer, Reputation and International Politics 6 (1996).
S102 the journal of legal studies

have an overall average compliance rate, but the other states have no reason
to be preoccupied with it.
A second difficulty with the notion of reputation as a grand strategy is
that it inevitably leads one to ask what strategic interest a state might have
in fashioning a reputation that is less than perfect when the cost of noncom-
pliance is believed to be so high. One possibility is that less-than-perfect
reputations are the product of misperception. An imperfect technology of
treaty oversight leads a treaty partner to wrongly infer that the state has
defected when in reality it has not. While doubtless such mistakes occur, the
likelihood that most suspected defections have really not taken place is small,
in part because both sides should have an incentive to reduce any such costly
mistakes over time. In any event, no one denies that most defections are real
enough. Another possibility is that states are periodically defecting from
agreements as part of some mixed strategy. However, this inefficient even-
tuality also seems unlikely since agreements are painstakingly negotiated.
Some other explanation for periodic defection and imperfect levels of reli-
ability clearly seems needed.21

III. The Case for Multiple Reputations


One way to account for the prevalence of imperfect and variable reliability
is to argue that the reputational consequences of defection are usually more
bounded than the unitary theory suggests. If states have learned that the rates
and timing of defections are often only weakly correlated across treaties,
there is no need to readjust their reliability estimate for every treaty whenever
there is a defection from a given agreement. In such a world states effectively
hold not one reputation but many.
To understand why this might be the case, we first need to consider the
roots of imperfect reliability in the context of cooperative relationships—a
topic that has not received much attention. One explanation for this lack of
attention is that international legal theorists and international relations the-
orists have generally been preoccupied with understanding the origins of
cooperation and accounting for the high levels of compliance that generally
characterize most agreements. A second reason is that for the most part both
groups of theorists, to the extent that they have been exposed to formal
models at all, are familiar only with models that predict perfect reliability
in equilibrium.
Outside international law and mainstream international relations, however,
21
A number of authors implicitly abandon the idea of a unitary reputation by using the term
“reputation” in a regime-specific way. However, they characteristically omit any explanation
for their decision. This leaves the reader in doubt as to whether an author has a well-developed
rationale for believing that a state’s defection from a treaty in one area will not have implications
for its reputation in another area or whether she is simply interested in trade and has no interest
in the broader question of where the boundaries of reputation are located.
reputation and international law S103

the puzzle of why many cooperative agreements are punctuated by periodic


defection in equilibrium has drawn some theoretical attention. Sobel, for
example, describes a number of games of incomplete information where the
value of cheating for player 1 varies from round to round.22 Player 2’s
willingness to cooperate with player 1 is a function of the latter’s reliability,
which can be communicated only through a history of actions. Sobel shows
that if player 2 possesses less than complete information about the fluctuation
of player 1’s payoffs, the first player will always have a compliance rate of
less than 100 percent. Player 2’s uncertainty about the first player’s moti-
vations provides the first player with the opportunity to build a good repu-
tation when the value of the stage game is low that she can later benefit by
exploiting when the value of the stage game is high.23
Sobel’s insight lies in showing that variation in the utility of stage games
combined with uncertainty can provide an additional explanation for less
than perfect compliance. The “cashing in” feature is not essential, and most
models that contain stochastic utility changes do without it. This is generally
true in models of loan default, where stochastic utility changes have been
used most frequently. For example, Herschel Grossman and John Van Huyck
construct a game in which a state’s ability to repay a loan is a function of
its income, which is, in turn, partly determined by a stochastic exogenous
component.24 The borrower chooses to maintain a good reputation only if
the expected present value of the utility it derives from validating lender
expectations is at least as large as it would be if it were to repudiate its
debts.
There appears to be good reason to believe that such fluctuations in payoffs
are the rule rather than the exception and that they hold the key to under-
standing why the reliability rates associated with most agreements are less
than perfect and why these rates vary from one agreement to another.25 To
understand the source of these fluctuations, consider the analysis of why
states violate treaties advanced by the Chayeses—who seem generally to
adhere to the unitary theory. They argue that the majority of treaty violations
are not the product of any calculated exploitation but rather are caused by
three factors: (1) the ambiguity and indeterminacy of treaty language,
(2) limitations on the capacity of the parties to carry out their commitments,
and (3) social, economic, and political departures from the expectation em-
bodied in regulatory treaties.26
22
Sobel, supra note 7.
23
Id. at 564.
24
Herschel Grossman & John B. Van Huyck, Sovereign Debt as a Contingent Claim: Ex-
cusable Default, Repudiation, and Reputation, 78 Am. Econ. Rev. 1088 (1988).
25
Engaging Countries: Strengthening Compliance with International Environmental Accords
(Edith Brown Weiss & Harold K. Jacobson eds. 1998).
26
Chayes & Chayes, supra note 18, at 10.
S104 the journal of legal studies

One characteristic that these explanations have in common is that they


will not necessarily have the same impact on every agreement. Treaty am-
biguity and contract ambiguity are obviously contract specific in the sense
that both types of ambiguity vary enormously across agreements. The ca-
pacity limitations of states to deal with agreements also vary a great deal.27
The demands of the Convention on International Trade in Endangered Species
of Wild Fauna and Flora (CITES), for example, pose almost insurmountable
detection problems for a state with as large an area and as much border
traffic as the United States as compared with Switzerland. For many other
agreements, the capacity demands are similar across states. Volatile economic
and social consequences have a similarly diverse effect across agreements.
A mild recession, for example, might have one effect on a state’s propensity
to fulfill its human rights commitments, another on its ability to repay its
loans according to schedule, and still another on its ability to comply with
a pesticide agreement.28
The factors discussed by the Chayeses help us account for why a state
might have different levels of reliability in connection with treaties in two
different regulatory areas.29 However, the same logic also holds for two
different treaties in the same regulatory area. If it is known that two envi-
ronmental treaties contain different amounts of ambiguity, require widely
differing levels of resources to carry out, or vary in their sensitivity to
different political and economic shocks, then a defection in connection with
one of them need not have reputational implications for the other.
The existence of these fluctuations in compliance costs or payoffs provides
states with an incentive to let their reliability rates vary, but it does not
explain why treaties cannot be constructed to overcome this compliance
problem. At least in theory, if the quality of information is good enough,
near-perfect reliability can still be preserved in the face of such fluctuations

27
If treaty members know ahead of time that capacity limitations are going to be a persistent
problem, they should revise the agreement for the sake of efficiency. If they know that certain
social or economic conditions will make it impossible for a state to comply with an agreement,
they can describe these conditions in the agreement so that they do not count as ‘‘intentional’’
noncompliance—as they often do in the case of loans and in many broad and far-reaching
agreements. There are limits to the extent to which this can be done, however, and once we
are past those limits we can sensibly talk about shocks that can affect a state’s reliability or
reputation in equilibrium, at least if they are transient.
28
There is a dangerous tendency in the literature to broaden the definition of “unintentional’’
to cover any defection that is remotely associated with a transient event. This can be a problem
because each of the Chayses’s three factors involves an endogenous element that can easily
lead to moral hazard. See Downs, supra note 4, at 331.
29
Another source of indeterminacy with a similar effect springs from endemic rather then
transient uncertainties associated with the cost of compliance. For example, developed states,
much less developing states, do not know exactly how much it will cost to achieve different
levels of compliance with complicated agreements like CITES or the World Trade Organization
(WTO). In this cost-informational sense, the contract that each state makes is necessarily
incomplete. Under these circumstances, it may also be more efficient to embrace a moderate
level of punishment.
reputation and international law S105

in utility by simply raising the penalty for defection. For example, states
could collectively agree to respond to a defection by immediately abrogating
the treaty forever and refusing to renegotiate it—a punishment known ap-
propriately enough as the “grim strategy.’’ Assuming that a state’s discount
rate is not extremely high, the cost that this represents should be sufficient
to offset any transient benefit that a state can get by defecting when it
experienced the kind of shocks described above.
Yet this is not the course that states pursue. On the contrary, the penalties
specified in real-world treaties never resemble anything approaching the dra-
conian proportions of the grim strategy and are characteristically relatively
weak. In the history of international cooperation there are few if any instances
where a state punishes a state that violates an agreement by abrogating the
treaty and refusing to enter into a similar treaty. One might argue that this
is a consequence of the fact that only modest penalties are needed to provide
near-perfect compliance; therefore there is no reason to use the grim strategy.
However, this cannot be the explanation because, as we have already seen,
compliance, while often good, is usually less than perfect in any number of
areas.
Another, more sophisticated, answer to the question of why states do not
use stronger penalties to insure perfect compliance involves a slippery con-
cept called “renegotiation proofness,” which puts a limit on the size of the
punishment that can be used. To understand how it works, assume that a
group of oil-producing states decides to maximize cooperation by collectively
agreeing to punish overproduction on the part of any one state by jointly
abrogating the treaty forever. Some time after the treaty is made, one state
ends up increasing production and violating the treaty because of some un-
expected series of events such as its leader having to raise money quickly
to overcome a rebellion in one of its provinces. The other states respond by
making good on their punishment threat and resume production at the level
that existed before the agreement was signed. After a significant time period
elapses, the president of the state that violated the treaty communicates to
the other states’ leaders that, while she appreciates their mutual pledge to
defect forever in the face of any violation, she can assure them that the period
of unrestricted competition that has ensued has already cost her state more
than it gained by breaking the treaty: “I and my state have already paid the
price of our mistake. To continue producing at the competitive level will
hurt you as well as us and it will accomplish nothing. Let us (renegotiate a)
return to restricted production so that we will all be better off.”
This is the logic of renegotiation proofness. In prospect, whenever it is
believed by the players that a punishment strategy would be vulnerable to
such an offer, it is said not to be renegotiation proof and, as such, is judged
not to be credible. As a practical matter, one can think of renegotiation
proofness as restricting the size of the punishment to the largest value that
S106 the journal of legal studies

will never simultaneously be in both players’ interest to reduce.30 Unfortu-


nately, the task of formally translating the above description into formal
terms turns out to be more difficult than it might look, and none of the various
versions in the literature is regularly employed.
Fortunately, the existence of stochastic compliance costs suggests an al-
ternative explanation to renegotiation proofness for limiting the magnitude
of the punishment that is both more intuitively attractive and easier to for-
malize. These costs do this by creating a situation where states are collectively
better off with a treaty and an associated punishment regime that allows them
to periodically defect than they are with a treaty that forces them to always
cooperate. A penalty is still needed to prevent the actors from defecting
exploitatively at every opportunity. However, the duration or severity of the
penalty is adjusted so as to optimize the expected benefits of the treaty given
the anticipated fluctuations of the cost and/or benefit structure. As a result,
we have treaties in which states exhibit high but not perfect levels of reli-
ability, and treaty reliability rates differ from one agreement to another be-
cause they are subject to different patterns of transient shocks. For example,
scholars have argued that the weak enforcement norm of the General Agree-
ment on Tariffs and Trade (GATT) was the result of the existence of the sort
of transient and basically exogenous states of the world described above.
Many (if not most) states did not want aggressive enforcement of GATT
because they knew that there would be times when they themselves would
find it advantageous to depart temporarily from a free-trade standard. This
is because the political, if not the economic, benefit of free trade varies with
changes in the state of the economy, particularly changes in unemployment
in sectors that are import competitive. When unemployment is high, the
domestic pressures to apply tariffs become strong, and politicians find that
they are often better off—at least until the economy recovers—responding
to those demands with temporary protectionist policies and pdaying the costs
(both reputational and otherwise) of doing so.31
In theory, states could ignore the existence of the transient shocks and the

30
For more extended discussions of renegotiation proofness, see Dilip J. Abreu, David Pearce,
& Ennio Stacchetti, Optimal Character of Equilibria with Imperfect Monitoring, 39 J. Econ.
Theory, 251 (1986); Jean-Pierre Benoit & Vijay Krishna, Renegotiation in Finitely Repeated
Games, 61 Econometrica 303 (1993); B. Douglas Bernheim, Bezalel Peleg, & Michael D.
Whinston, Coalition-Proof Nash Equilibria I: Concepts, 42 J. Econ. Theory 1 (1987); B. Douglas
Bernheim & Debraj Ray, Collective Dynamic Consistency in Repeated Games, 1 Games &
Econ. Behav. 295 (1989); Joseph Farrell & Eric Maskin, Renegotiation in Repeated Games,
1 Games & Econ. Behav. 327 (1989); David Pearce, Renegotiation-Proof Equilibria: Collective
Rationality and Intertemporal Cooperation (typescript revision of 1987 Cowles Foundation
Discussion Paper No. 855, Yale Univ., Dep’t Econ. 1988); Eric Van Damme, Renegotiation-
Proof Equilibria in Repeated Prisoner’s Dilemma, 47 J. Econ. Theory 206 (1989).
31
Alan O. Sykes, Mandatory Retaliation for Breach of Trade Agreements: Some Thoughts
on the Strategic Design of Section 301, 8 B.U. Int’l L. J. 301 (1990); George W. Downs &
David M. Rocke, Optimal Imperfection? Domestic Uncertainty and Institutions in International
Relations 88–89 (1995).
reputation and international law S107

differences in reliability across treaties and act as if states possessed a single


reputation. However, except in cases where a special complementarity exists
in the utilities the states place on a few of the agreements, it would not be
rational to enact a unitary reputation for the same reason that large reciprocal
punishments fail. That is, it would be more efficient for both states if they
did not presume a single behavior in disparate agreements.32
One might object to this picture of multiple and relatively independent
reputations by pointing to situations where states have responded to non-
compliance in one area by retaliating in another, unrelated area (for example,
sanctions against Iraq for violating the weapons inspection provisions of its
agreement with the United Nations (UN)). However, we would argue that
these generally represent a coercive linkage penalty rather than a true re-
putational penalty. A linkage penalty might appear to be equivalent to a
reputational punishment because it is occurring as a consequence of a pattern
of noncompliance, but it actually is something different. The states that are
punishing the guilty state are not doing so because they anticipate that because
the state has violated a human rights agreement it will be unreliable in
connection with a trade treaty or fail to pay back its loans. Rather, states are
simply trying to coerce the guilty state into changing its behavior in the same
way that they might try to coerce a state into altering its behavior in an area
where there was no treaty (for example, sanctions against South Africa during
the waning years of apartheid).
Another way of seeing this is to consider that if the states inflicting the
linkage penalty were worried about the defecting state’s reliability, they
would defensively reduce their level of cooperation in the area where they
expected that the violator’s next defection would hurt them (the victim state)
the most. When a linkage penalty is involved, the states are offensively
reducing their level of cooperation in the area where it will inflict the most
damage on the violating state. The very rarity and selective nature of these
linkages are testimony to their strategic nature. The United States has peri-
odically threatened to oppose China’s entry into the World Trade Organization
(WTO) because of its human rights record, but it did not threaten simulta-
neously to oppose China’s participation in other environmental or arms agree-
ments, and the vast majority of states did not threaten to do anything at any
time.33

32
See Susanne Lohmann, Linkage Politics, 41 J. Conflict Resol. 38 (1997), for a discussion
of the circumstances where linkages are possible. Under the best of circumstances, it is ex-
tremely unlikely that these conditions will ever be present in connection with more that a
handful of agreements, and the existence of a stochastic cost structure would reduce the
likelihood still further.
33
Another sort of linkage behavior whereby a defecting state’s reputation is downgraded in
two areas such as trade and human rights following its failure to comply with its agreement
in one area is theoretically possible (see id.). However, the aggregate effect of such linkage is
also likely to be modest. This is partly because it requires a special complementarity in the
utilities that states place on the linked agreements that will rarely be present and partly because
S108 the journal of legal studies

In an environment where compliance costs and benefits fluctuate stochas-


tically, the existence of agreements with different values operate to multiply
the number of reputations still further. That states do, in fact, attach different
values to different agreements is obvious enough, but formal models of
reputation rarely reflect this fact because it complicates the mathematics
considerably and often distracts the reader from the point that they are trying
to make. Still, for the purposes of understanding reputation it is worth con-
sidering the implications of the fact that such variation is the rule rather than
the exception. The United States does not assign the same value to the North
Atlantic Treaty Organization (NATO) that it does the South-East Asian Treaty
Organization; nor does it assign the same value to WTO and a bilateral
fishing treaty that it might have with a small state.
In multilateral agreements that regulate goods with relatively few exter-
nalities such as trade agreements, reputation will operate to protect large and
powerful states the most—assuming that relationships with them are most
likely to be highly valued by their treaty partner—and small states the least.
In multilateral agreements that regulate public goods, defection from a given
agreement affects every treaty partner the same, so the relative importance
of states is largely immaterial. What matters in this case is how important
the agreement is to the defecting state. If the agreement produces a high
level of benefits, states will endure an appreciable rise in compliance costs
before they defect—just as they will in connection with a valued relationship
in the case of agreements that regulate private goods. If the agreement pro-
duces only modest benefits, it will take less of an increase in compliance
costs before costs begin to outweigh benefits, making it desirable for the
state to defect.
The efforts of newly established states or new regimes to establish good
reputations will make the compliance rates of international agreements higher
than they might be otherwise, as long as states have an expectation that the
future agreements will, on average, be more valuable than their current ones.
This is a requirement that is likely to be met in most cases because prospective
partners are likely to “test” the reliability of such states in connection with
agreements of relatively modest importance before agreeing to enter into
agreements where defection is very costly.
Yet the impact of this strategizing on the overall level of compliance in
the international system is likely to be quite modest. Such states make up
only a small proportion of the total number of states at any given time, and
their need to strategically “inflate” their reliability rate erodes relatively
quickly. As these states enter more and more agreements and other states
gather reliability information in connection with each successive agreement,
only a very large state or a group of states acting in a coordinated way will have the power
to establish a linkage that changes another state’s behavior in a dramatic way. Under the best
circumstances, the ability to establish an effective linkage will be negatively related to the size
and power of the target state.
reputation and international law S109

new regimes will be able to develop segmented or multiple reputations like


other states at a modest cost.

IV. The Significance of Reputation for International Law


If our characterization of how reputation operates is correct, the reputa-
tional consequences of a given state’s noncompliance with a particular agree-
ment are real, but they are more narrowly bounded than the traditional theory
predicted. Other states will revise their estimates of its reliability but only
in connection with agreements that they believe (1) are affected by the same
or similar sources of fluctuating costs and (2) are valued the same or less
by the defecting state. The first tends to limit the reputational consequences
of even sharp decreases in compliance with a given treaty to other treaties
in the same area. This prediction is in keeping with the already existing
tendency of a substantial minority of scholars to confine their discussion of
reputational consequences to their impact on a specific regime.34 It helps
explain why, despite the prevalence of the unitary reputation assumption,
examples of a state’s defection from an agreement in one area (for example,
environment) jeopardizing its reputation in every other area (for example,
trade and security) are virtually nonexistent in the literature. More important,
it helps account for why states often have widely divergent reputations in
different areas.
This is not to deny that it can be a useful rhetorical convenience or an
effective political strategy to speak of a state as if it had a single reputa-
tion—especially when the context is understood, for example, during a dis-
cussion of human rights—but it will be descriptively misleading if taken too
seriously. Thus, the United States has one simple reputation for making good
on its financial commitments with workers in the UN Office of the Secretary-
General and another quite different simple reputation with officials of Eu-
ropean states in connection with its financial commitments to NATO. Neither
group is much concerned with characterizing the reliability of the United
States in meeting its financial commitments in general. Those inside the
Office of the Secretary-General are aware of the fact that the United States
has paid its NATO bills, and NATO workers know that the United States is
behind on its UN dues. However, they design their policies in response to
the behavior of the United States in the subset of contexts that is relevant
to them.
The claim that reputational inferences are localized or “segmented” helps
explain why members of the North Atlantic community could have shown

34
Whether the underlying logic of these authors who implicitly treat reputational implications
as being confined to a specific regime is the same as that described here is unclear since they
rarely give the reasons for their position. It is possible that some of them actually embrace
the unitary perspective and only appear to believe in regime-specific reputations in the context
of a given article whose focus is regime specific.
S110 the journal of legal studies

solidarity in dealing with Slobodan Milosevic’s Yugoslavia at the same mo-


ment they were squabbling over the sale of bananas. While there was no
shortage of dispositional-like statements in the United States about European
Union “protectionism’’ and “lack of commitment to multilateralism,’’ such
judgments had few consequences for the ability of the allies to conduct the
war. In this case, both the utility and stochastic elements of the trade and
security treaties were not sufficiently related for reputational consequences
of one treaty to affect the other treaty.
Treaties in the same specific area with similar stochastic costs may still
have few reputational connections if the treaties are valued significantly
differently. In particular, a state’s behavior in connection with a treaty that
it derives little benefit from does not change its reputation in connection with
those that it clearly values much more. This serves to distinguish our position
from that often found in the alliance literature. The latter suggests that states
are prepared to reestimate each other’s reputations at the drop of a hat and
that, as a consequence, a state must be scrupulous about aggressively up-
holding every security commitment that it might have made. For example,
when a small number of Haitian security forces turned away U.S. troops
trying to land at Port-au-Prince as part of a UN mission, a U.S. policy maker
is said to have remarked, “This embarrassment has dealt a blow to American
credibility, one of our most precious assets.”35
While such statements are understandable in the heat of the moment, our
model predicts that whatever the policy maker might have said in frustration,
he did not rush to recommend to his superiors that they immediately call
Germany to reassure officials there that their security umbrella was still intact.
German officials did not need reassurance because it never would have oc-
curred to them that United States valued the two commitments equally. It
follows that from the perspective of our model, the argument that a failure
of NATO in an area like Kosovo or Macedonia will seriously erode NATO’s
credibility in connection with its commitments to Western Europe is wrong
for the same reason.36

35
Mercer, supra note 20, at 7.
36
Mercer has generated the most elaborate empirical and theoretical critique of the traditional
view of reputation; however, we are trying to explain somewhat different aspects of reputation.
Mercer is interested in the reputation that states assign other states for resolve or “the extent
to which a state will risk war to achieve its objectives” (id. at 2). We are interested in the
reputational judgments states make with respect to the likelihood that other states will honor
their treaty commitments in the future, a broader topic that has relevance to trade and envi-
ronmental cooperation as well as to security commitments. Nevertheless, we agree with Mercer
that states tend to have multiple and contradictory reputations (see id. at 32). The same is true
of his contention that “actors base their predictions on the specifics of the situation or perhaps
the history of a continuing relationship, and not on a state’s aggregate behavior” (id. at 24).
We are not surprised by the fact that “[l]ike their Soviet counterparts, American decision makers
did not seem to infer that behavior in one area results in similar behavior in another area”
(id.). Unlike Mercer, however, we do not see the existence of such behavior as a challenge to
game theory so much as a challenge to the assumption of actor homogeneity that was made
reputation and international law S111

The states that do have to worry about these sorts of commitment failures
are smaller states that believe they are valued the same as the states that
were abandoned. Of course, it is more complicated than this—the cost of
fulfilling the commitment matters as well as the benefit of fulfilling it, and
these costs might vary in such a way as to give the smaller state more or
less confidence. Still, the principle that small states have the most to learn
by paying attention to the noncompliance of their partners in connection to
other relationships seems to be a general one. Because their relationship is
likely to be viewed by the defector as being of the same or less importance,
the chances that they too will be the victim of defection is fairly large. Large
states do not have to worry as much about the noncompliance of a partner
in connection with a third party spreading to them unless the third party is
another large state. Otherwise, there is a reasonable likelihood that the de-
fecting state values their relationship more.
The connection between the value of a relationship and the perceived
opportunity costs associated with a contemplated defection has two effects
on the extent to which reputation sustains international law. The first is
perverse, if unremarkable. The fact that the reputational consequences of
defecting from an important relationship are larger than those of defecting
from a less important relationship means that reputation protects strong states
more than weak states. This is really not so surprising. The reputational
implications of a firm’s violating a contract with its most important client
are greater than they would be if the client were unimportant. However, the
fact that reputation protects most those who require the least protection is
still disconcerting.
The tendency of the magnitude of the reputational implications of a de-
fection to be directly proportionate to the value of a relationship also implies
that the contribution that reputation makes to sustain international law co-
operation is greatest in connection with agreements that states think are the
most beneficial.37 Conversely, it has the least effect in connection with agree-
ments that produce the smallest amount of benefits. This predicts that the
average compliance rate will be somewhat higher in connection with rela-
tively important agreements. It also may help account for why the quality
of the compliance data that are available is so frequently related to the
importance of the agreement.
From a reputational standpoint, the utility of the cooperation that an agree-
ment represents or the opportunity cost of defecting from it is only half the
story. Its reputational consequences are also a function of the extent to which
the stochastic cost function that leads to defection from it is correlated with
those connected with other regimes. While little is known about this, it seems
for convenience in models designed to look at issues differently than those that interest Mercer
or us.
37
This assumes that we are talking about agreements that are affected by the same stochastic
cost function.
S112 the journal of legal studies

likely that trade agreements are quite “central” in this respect, since many
of the shocks that affect trade agreements such as recessions also affect
compliance with agreements in other areas. Security agreements also have
a claim to centrality. Major shocks in that area are likely to affect trade
agreements as well as human rights agreements.38 Defections from environ-
mental agreements, at least at the present time, seem to have more narrow
implications for treaties in other areas, as have human rights treaties. Hence,
their reputational consequences, at least in the rational choice sense, should
be more restricted.39 It follows, ceteris paribus, that reputation promotes
compliance with international law most in trade and security and least in
environmental regulation and human rights. The most important reputational
consequences are those connected with the most important agreements in
these areas.
The disconcerting implication that reputation fosters cooperation more in
connection with large states than with small holds only for treaties that
regulate the exchange of private or club goods where exclusion is possible
such as trade agreements and alliances. If we consider public-goods agree-
ments, the relative importance of states in determining the importance of a
violation recedes into the background because it is no longer possible to
defect against a particular state: any defection affects every state in the
agreement. In this situation the contribution of reputation to promoting com-
pliance and sustaining international law becomes a function of the importance
of the agreement as a whole. The agreements that get the most reputational
help are the agreements that states value the most and whose stochastic cost
component is the most highly correlated with that of other agreements.
Other effects of reputation on compliance with international law are more
marginal, but worth noting. Just as one would expect, new states and states
with new regimes will on average be more sensitive to reputational consid-
eration and hence more apt to comply with international law than the average
state. This is because they have not yet had the opportunity to develop
multiple reputations by signaling consistent variations in their reliability rates
across agreements. However, if the incidence of compliance opportunities is
relatively high, as it is in trade and human rights agreements, it will not take
the newcomer long to establish multiple reputations. In an area like security
where the opportunities to comply with a defensive alliance are sparser,
multiple reputations will take longer to establish, and strategic behavior of
all sorts will flourish longer. This fact might partially account for why rep-
utation is such a popular topic for discussion in security circles and why
there are so many disagreements abut the reputational consequences of a
particular act.

38
Joanne Gowa, Allies, Adversaries, and International Trade (1994).
39
The reputational damage with respect to a state’s social standing in the international
community might of course be as great or greater.
reputation and international law S113

V. Concluding Comments
The claims of this paper that the reputational consequences of most de-
fections affect only a subset of current and future agreements may be inter-
preted as further support for the revisionist claim that reputation is irrelevant.
This is not the case. To say that the power of reputation to enforce compliance
is usually modest is no more a dismissal of reputation than the claim that
many cooperative agreements are relatively shallow is a dismissal of co-
operation. Reputation matters, just not so much as some might like.
Of course, the theory presented here is relatively simple. It is designed
primarily to understand the boundaries of reputational inference and how
they relate to two stylized facts of cooperative life not easily explained by
most conventional theories of reputation: (1) states have different levels of
reliability in connection with different agreements, and (2) there is consid-
erable evidence that states possess multiple or segmented reputations. In-
evitably, many other interesting issues have been ignored or mentioned only
in passing.
One set of such issues is connected with the role of information and the
capacity of states to process it. The model we have described here is very
information intensive. To behave optimally, states not only have to keep track
of the reliability rates connected with different agreements, but they have to
estimate the degree of similarity among them with respect to the values states
assign them and the factors that determine variations in their compliance
costs. Even if we are correct in believing that states pay attention to these
factors, their capacity for making distinctions may not be as refined as ef-
ficiency demands.40
Information-processing issues are particularly important for understanding
the impact of reputation on new states and states that have recently expe-
rienced wholesale changes in their form of government. Although the inter-
national system usually contains only a handful of these states, the impact
of reputation on their fortunes may be far greater than for more established
states. How quickly can these states develop multiple reputations, and what
is the cost of not being able to do so immediately? Where are multiple
reputations likely to first appear? Conversely, what are the reputational im-
plications of the fact that compliance information for many agreements is
extremely poor and often based on self-reporting?
Finally, the question of how reputation affects the fortunes of small and
or developing states demands more attention because it contrasts so sharply
with the picture of reputation leveling the playing field between the weak

40
A more behavioral approach might also prove helpful regarding this issue.
S114 the journal of legal studies

and the strong. Not only does it appear that a defection against such states
tends to have the fewest reputational consequences for the violator, but the
reputational penalties that they pay for their own defections will tend to be
quite large.

You might also like