The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas - The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas
The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas - The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas
The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas - The Oxford Handbook of Aquinas
AQUINAS
THE OXFORD HANDBOOK OF
AQUINAS
Edited by
BRIAN DAVIES
AND ELEONORE STUMP
Oxford University Press, Inc., publishes works that further
Oxford University’s objective of excellence
in research, scholarship, and education.
With offices in
Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece
Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore
South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam
www.oup.com
135798642
Printed in the United States of America
on acid-free paper
CONTENTS
Abbreviations
List of Contributors
Introduction
Brian Davies and Eleonore Stump
6. Being
John F. Wippel
8. Causation
Michael Rota
16. Emotions
Peter King
17. Happiness
Brian Davies
31. Incarnation
Michael Gorman
33. Sacraments
Dominic Holtz, O.P.
35. Prayer
Brian Davies
ANDREW PINSENT is Research Director of the Ian Ramsey Centre for Science
and Religion at Oxford University, a member of the Theology Faculty there,
and a Senior Research Fellow at Harris Manchester College. His principal
research interests are in metaphysical problems pertinent to contemporary
science and theology. He is the author of The Second-Person Perspective in
Aquinas’s Ethics: Virtues and Gifts (Routledge, 2012).
AQUINAS
INTRODUCTION
BRIAN DAVIES
ELEONORE STUMP
It was necessary that human beings be instructed by divine revelation even as regards
the things about God that human reason can explore. For the truth about God
investigated by a few on the basis of reason [without relying on revelation] would
emerge for people [only] after a long time and tainted with many mistakes. And yet all
human well-being, which has to do with God, depends on the cognition of that truth.
Therefore, it was necessary for human beings to be instructed about divine matters
through divine revelation so that [the nature of human] well-being might emerge for
people more conveniently and with greater certainty.11
Aquinas is also careful to point out that it is not mere intellectual curiosity or
even a defense of the faith that is served by a rational clarification of the
doctrine of the Trinity. In his view, this application of philosophical theology
—confirming faith by reason, showing that belief in the Trinity is not after all
irrational, exposing the intricate connections between these and other
doctrinal propositions—aids one’s understanding of creation and salvation.
The present volume is intended as a guide to Aquinas’s thinking on almost
all the major topics on which he wrote. In 1993 one of us (Eleonore Stump),
together with Norman Kretzmann († 1998), edited a comparable volume,
which appeared as The Cambridge Companion to Aquinas.18 That well-
received volume, however, consisted of only ten essays, contained
comparatively little on Aquinas’s treatment of wholly theological issues, and
had almost nothing to say about Aquinas’s life and influence. The present
book is much fuller. In addition to documenting Aquinas’s life and work, it
includes contributions that explain the Greek, patristic, Jewish, and Islamic
influences on Aquinas’s thought, and it also contains entries that show the
historical reception and development of Aquinas’s views. There are many
more essays exploring the philosophical and theological topics discussed by
Aquinas.
The book begins with a part devoted to historical background. This part
includes an account of Aquinas’s life and works by Jean-Pierre Torrell,
whose Saint Thomas Aquinas: The Person and His Work is the currently
most authoritative biography of Aquinas.19 It also contains a series of essays
that set Aquinas in his intellectual context. These essays focus on the sources
that are likely to have influenced his thinking, the most prominent of which
(apart from the Bible, of course) were certain Greek philosophers (chiefly
Aristotle), Latin Christian authors, such as Augustine, and Jewish and
Islamic writers, such as Maimonides and Avicenna. The subsequent parts of
the book address topics that Aquinas himself discussed. These include
metaphysics, the existence and nature of God, ethics and action theory,
providence and evil, epistemology, philosophy of mind and human nature,
the nature of language, and an array of topics in philosophical theology,
including Trinity, Incarnation, sacraments, and resurrection, among others.
These parts include more than thirty contributions on topics central to
Aquinas’s own worldview. The final parts of the volume address the
development of Aquinas’s thought and its historical influence.
Although the volume thus aims at being comprehensive, readers familiar
with Aquinas will undoubtedly find that some part of Aquinas’s thought that
strikes them as particularly important is not represented here. Sadly, it is not
possible to do everything in one volume, even a fat one. At any rate, it is
abundantly clear that some compromise is necessary between the ideal plan
of presenting all of Aquinas’s thought and any practicable plan for one book.
We have tried to pick those issues and topics that allow a reader to see
Aquinas’s whole worldview in broad outline and to appropriate in particular
some of its richest and most powerful parts.
Aquinas’s philosophy includes reflection on some basic metaphysical
topics while extending to discussions of what can be known by reason when
it comes to the existence of God.20 He has views to offer on questions such
as “What is it for something to exist?” “How should we distinguish between
things in the world?” “What is it for something to be an individual in the
world?” and “How should we understand causation?” He also has views to
offer on questions such as “Can we know that God exists?” and “Can we give
some account of God’s nature?” Parts II and III of this book try to explain
and comment on what Aquinas has to say by way of answer to such
questions.
Yet Aquinas’s intellectual interests range beyond metaphysics and natural
theology. As the list of topics given above shows, he also had a concern with
many other areas of philosophy as well. Aquinas often insists that moral
philosophy would be redundant if people lack freedom of choice. So Part IV
begins with an account of Aquinas’s views on human freedom and agency,
and it continues with consideration of Aquinas’s approach to happiness, law,
natural law, conscience, virtue and vice, and the theological virtues, among
other things. Part V deals with Aquinas’s theories of human knowledge and
the nature of mind, as well as the relation of reason to faith. Part VI traces
Aquinas’s account of the nature of language and its limits when it comes to
God.
The next part covers topics in philosophical theology. It includes an
account of Aquinas’s views on the problem of evil. Other chapters present
Aquinas’s account of the Trinity, the Incarnation, life after death, prayer, and
the work of the Holy Spirit, among other things. Part VIII focuses on the
progress of Aquinas’s thought and its influence. It includes accounts of the
ways in which Aquinas’s ideas developed over time and the different ways in
which subsequent thinkers have viewed and interpreted Aquinas’s thought.
Finally, any attempt to present the views of a philosopher in an earlier
historical period that is meant to foster reflection on that thinker’s views
needs to be both historically faithful and also philosophically engaged. So the
present book combines both exposition and evaluation insofar as it is
appropriate for any particular contributor to engage in both. It is our hope,
therefore, that this Handbook will prove useful to someone wanting to learn
about Aquinas’s philosophy and theology while also looking for help in
philosophical interaction with it.21
For invaluable assistance in preparing this volume for publication we are
much indebted to Barb Manning, Stephen Chanderbhan, Zita Toth, and
Gideon Jeffrey. We are also grateful to Peter Ohlin of Oxford University
Press for helpful advice and for his patience in waiting for a work that was
longer in the making than we originally expected it to be.
NOTES
1. Summa contra Gentiles, I.2.11; hereinafter SCG.
2. Cf. Summa theologiae, I q.1 a.1 ad 2; hereinafter ST.
3. ST I q.1 a.2.
4. SCG I.1.2.
5. SCG I.1.3.
6. SCG II.4.874.
7. SCG I.1.5.
8. SCG II.4.875.
9. SCG I.1.6.
10. ST I q.1 a.1 ad 2.
11. ST I q.1 a.1.
12. ST I q.2, intro.
13. ST I q.1 a.7.
14. ST I q.1 a.2.
15. Expositio super librum Boethii De trinitate 2.2, ad 7.
16. ST I q.32 a.1.
17. ST I q.32 a.1.
18. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
19. Jean-Pierre Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas: The Person and His Work
(Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 1996).
20. It is often said that Aquinas thinks that he can prove the existence of
God. But he does not. For Aquinas, God’s existence is identical with his
essence, which Aquinas takes to be incomprehensible to us. He does,
however, argue that we might make a philosophical case for “God exists”
being true (on a certain understanding of “God”). For the distinction between
“the existence of God” and “God exists,” see Lubor Velecky, Aquinas’ Five
Arguments in the “Summa Theologiae” 1a 2, 3 (Kampen: Pharos, 1994).
21. Parts of this introduction are revised versions of sections in the entry
“Thomas Aquinas,” by Norman Kretzmann and Eleonore Stump,
Encyclopedia of Philosophy (London: Routledge Press, 1998) and a small
section of the prefatory material taken from Eleonore Stump’s Aquinas
(London and New York: Routledge, 2003).
PART I
HISTORICAL BACKGROUND
CHAPTER 1
The order of the first three books clearly echoes the structure Aquinas had
already found in the Sentences of Lombard, and it prefigures the circular
structure that he sets out in the Summa theologiae: all things come from God
and all things return to God under His guidance. It should be said that this
structure also follows Aquinas’s own logic, as was shown by G. Emery.25
Parallel to the SCG and moving back and forth between the two works,
Aquinas wrote the first part of the Compendium theologiae (1–246: De fide).
This “handbook,” written at the request of his friend Raynald, would be taken
back up in Naples in 1272–73, but would remain unfinished.26
At the same time (1263–65), Aquinas wrote Super Iob, which offers a
lovely example of literal exegesis that is used in the service of doctrinal
reflection on the suffering of the just innocent, which suffering is reconciled
with divine goodness: “The entire intentio of the book is to show by probable
reasons that human affairs are governed by divine providence.”27 This was
also the central subject of Book III of Summa contra Gentiles, which was
written at about the same time; it can be seen that Aquinas knew how to
organize his work.
Many other works of more modest size were written at the same time to
satisfy friendly requests: De emptione et uenditione (1262) is on the morality
of lending with interest; Contra errores Graecorum (1263–64) is a study of
the contested doctrines that were given him by Pope Urban IV. To the very
end of this period in Orvieto (unless they belong to the beginning of his stay
in Rome), we can also attribute De rationibus fidei, Expositio super primam
et secundam Decretalem, and De articulis fidei et ecclesiae sacramentis,
which are brief explications of the Catholic faith written at the request of
various correspondents.28
From amid these various works, the composition of the Office of Corpus
Christi (1264), which was also requested by Pope Urban IV, must be brought
out. Once contested by the Bollandists, its authenticity is accepted today and
it must be noted that this is an important text for understanding its author’s
Eucharistic doctrine. The authenticity of the hymn Adoro Te, also suspected,
is no longer in doubt thanks to the work of R. Wielockx.29 It is, once again,
at the request of Urban IV that Aquinas undertook the Catena aurea, a
commentary on the gospels with the help of excerpts from the Fathers of the
Church (On Matthew was finished in 1264; Mark, Luke, and John were
completed in Rome from 1265 to 1268). This work reveals Aquinas’s
stunning erudition in the Patristics: he is the first in the Occident to use the
complete corpus of the first ecumenical councils.30 Well versed in the Greek
and Latin Fathers (57 Greeks and 22 Latins), he has an affinity for some
authors: Gregory the Great (2,470 uses), John Chrysostom (3,563 uses in the
scriptural commentaries), but above all Augustine whose considerable
influence (some 10,000 citations in the entire works of Aquinas), which grew
over the course of Aquinas’s work (Sentences: 1,518; ST: 2,801), is
particularly clear on the subjects of the divine ideas (a transposition of a
platonic theme), the Trinity, the fittingness of the Incarnation, the nature of
the soul, beatitude, law, grace and sin, and so on.31 Called a “turning point”
by Weisheipl, the Catena aurea served as a source of references for Aquinas
himself over the course of his career and exerted a great influence on the rest
of the history of theology.32
NOTES
1. This brief biography presupposes the others done elsewhere, aside from
William of Tocco. Ystoria sancti Thome de Aquino de Guillaume de Tocco
(1323), ed. Claire le Brun-Gouanvic (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of
Mediaeval Studies, 1996); see also Jean-Pierre Torrell, O.P., Saint Thomas
Aquinas, vol. 1, The Person and His Work, rev. ed. (Washington, D.C.:
Catholic University of America Press, 2005); Jean-Pierre Torrell, O.P., Saint
Thomas Aquinas, vol. 2, Spiritual Master (Washington, D.C.: Catholic
University of America Press, 2003); Simon Tugwell, O.P., Albert and
Thomas: Selected Writings (New York and Mahwah, N.J.: Paulist Press,
1988); and James A. Weisheipl, O.P., Friar Thomas d’Aquino: His Life,
Thought and Works (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday, 1974; 2d ed. with
Corrigenda and Addenda, 1983) for the necessary justifications.
2. Aquinas, Opera omnia, iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita (Roma:
Commissio Leonina, 1882–), I* 1 (1989), 67*–68*; hereinafter cited as
Leonina.
3. Despite the divergent sources and their apologetical embellishments,
the historical reality of this episode cannot be doubted; cf. A. Tilatti, “La
cattura di Tommaso d’Aquino da parte dei parenti,” in M. C. De Matteis, ed.,
Ovidio Capitani: Quaranta anni per la storia medioevale (Bologna: Patron
Editore, 2003), 345–57.
4. Tocco, Ystoria 10:110–11.
5. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:1–17.
6. According to A. Oliva, Les Débuts de l’enseignement de Thomas
d’Aquin et sa conception de la sacra doctrina. Avec l’édition du prologue de
son commentaire des Sentences. (Paris: Vrin, 2006), 207–24, the first biblical
commentaries must be situated in Paris instead of Cologne.
7. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:18–35; Jean-Pierre Torrell, O.P., and
D. Bouthillier, “Quand saint Thomas méditait sur le prophète Isaïe,” Revue
Thomiste 90 (1990): 5–47.
8. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:36–53; cf. Alain de Libera and Cyrille
Michon, ed. and trans., Thomas Aquinas–Dietrich de Freiberg, L’Etre et
l’essence, Le vocabulaire médiéval de l’ontologie; commentary by Alain de
Libera and Cyrille Michon, “Point: Essais” (Paris: Seuil, 1996).
9. M.-M. Dufeil, Guillaume de Saint-Amour et la polémique universitaire
parisienne, 1250–1259 (Paris: Picard, 1972).
10. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:75–95.
11. Cf. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:54–59, 120–21, 198–201, 250–61.
12. Thomas G. Weinandy, OFM Cap., D. A. Keating, and J. P. Yocum,
eds., Aquinas on Scripture: An Introduction to the Biblical Commentaries
(London and New York: T. & T. Clark International, 2005); Gilles Emery,
O.P., “Biblical Exegesis and the Speculative Doctrine of the Trinity in St.
Thomas Aquinas’s Commentary on St. John,” in Gilles Emery, O.P., Trinity
in Aquinas (Ypsilanti, Mich. and Naples, Fla.: Sapientia Press, 2003; 2d ed.,
2006), 271–319; M. Aillet, Lire la Bible avec S. Thomas: Le Passage de la
littera à la res dans la Somme théologique, Studia friburgensia 80 (Fribourg:
Éditions universitaires, 1993).
13. W. G. B. M. Valkenberg, Words of the Living God: Place and Function
of Holy Scripture in the Theology of St. Thomas Aquinas (Leuven: Peeters,
2000), 211–27.
14. B. C. Bazán, “Les Questions disputées, principalement dans les facultés
de théologie,” in B. C. Bazán, G. Fransen, J. F. Wippel, D. Jacquart, Les
Questions disputées et les questions quodlibétiques dans les facultés de
théologie, de droit et de médecine, Typologie des sources du moyen âge
occidental 44–45 (Turnhout: Brepols, 1985), 12–149.
15. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:59–69; S.-T. Bonino, Thomas
d’Aquin: De la vérité Question 2 (La science en Dieu), Introduction,
traduction, et commentaire, Vestigia 17 (Paris: Cerf; Fribourg: Éditions
universitaires, 1996).
16. J. F. Wippel, “Quodlibetal Questions Chiefly in Theology Faculties,” in
Bazán et al., Les Questions disputées, 151–222; J. Hamesse, “Theological
Quaestiones quodlibetales,” in C. Schabel, ed., Theological Quodlibeta in the
Middle Ages: The Thirteenth Century, Brill’s Companion to the Christian
Tradition, I (Leiden-Boston: Brill, 2006), 17–48.
17. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:207–12; cf. Leonard E. Boyle, “The
Quodlibets of St. Thomas and Pastoral Care,” in Leonard E. Boyle, Facing
History: A Different Thomas Aquinas (Louvain-La-Neuve: Federation
Internationale des Instituts d’Etudes Medievales, 2000), 13–35 (also The
Thomist 38 [1974]: 232–56); Kevin White, “The Quodlibeta of Thomas
Aquinas in the Context of His Work,” in C. Schabel, ed., Theological
Quodlibeta in the Middle Ages: The Thirteenth Century (Leiden: Brill, 2006),
49–133.
18. Cf. Jean-Pierre Torrell, O.P., “Philosophie et théologie d’après le
Prologue de Thomas d’Aquin au Super Boetium de Trinitate. Essai d’une
lecture théologique,” Documenti e Studi sulla tradizione filosofica medievale
10 (1999): 299–353.
19. Leonina 50, 6.
20. Leonina 50, 263–64.
21. Cf. Louis Bertrand Geiger, La Participation dans la philosophie de S.
Thomas d’Aquin, 2d ed., Bibliothèque thomiste 23 (Paris: Vrin, 1953);
Cornelio Fabro, La Nozione metafisica di partecipazione secondo S.
Tommaso d’Aquino (Turin: Società editrice internazionale, 2d rev. ed. 1950;
3d ed. 1963); G. Casey, “An Explication of the de Hebdomadibus of
Boethius in the Light of St. Thomas’s Commentary,” The Thomist 51 (1987):
419–34.
22. This is the hypothesis of Weisheipl, Friar Thomas, 165–66. Tugwell,
Albert and Thomas, 221, is in agreement on this point.
23. Cf. R.-A. Gauthier, “Introduction” à Saint Thomas d’Aquin, Somme
contre les Gentils (Paris: Editions universitaires, 1993); this book brings to
light and sensibly modifies the first “Introduction historique” by the same
author and that was published in a translation of Contra Gentiles, by R.
Bernier and M. Corvez (Paris: Lethielleux, 1959), 7–123.
24. Leonina 25/2, 486–88.
25. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:101–16, 415; Gilles Emery, O.P.,
“The Treatise of St. Thomas,” in Trinity in Aquinas, 71–120; there are
excellent introductions and commentaries in the French edition: Thomas
Aquinas, Somme contre les Gentils.
26. Jean-Pierre Torrell, O.P., Thomas d’Aquin: Abrégé de théologie
(Compendium theologiae), Introduction, Texte latin, trad. Française, et
annotations (Paris: Cerf, 2007), 7–34.
27. Cf. Denis Chardonnens, L’Homme sous le regard de la Providence.
Providence de Dieu et condition humaine selon l’Exposition littérale sur le
Livre de Job de Thomas d’Aquin, Bibliothèque thomiste 50 (Paris: Vrin,
1997).
28. Cf. Gilles Emery, O.P., ed. and trans., Thomas d’Aquin, Traités. Les
Raisons de la foi. Les Articles de la foi et les sacrements de l’Église,
Introduction, traduction, et annotation (Paris: Cerf, 1999).
29. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:129–36; R. Wielockx, “Poetry and
Theology in the Adoro Te deuote: Thomas Aquinas on the Eucharist and
Christ’s Uniqueness,” in Kent Emery and Joseph Wawrykow, eds., Christ
among the Medieval Dominicans: Representations of Christ in the Texts and
Images of the Order of Preachers (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre
Dame Press, 1998), 157–74.
30. Cf. M. Morard, “Thomas d’Aquin lecteur des Conciles,” Archivum
Franciscanum Historicum 98 (2005): 213–365.
31. P.-Y. Maillard, La Vision de Dieu chez Thomas d’Aquin: Une lecture
de l’In Ioannem à la lumière de ses sources augustiniennes, Bibliothèque
thomiste 53 (Paris: Vrin, 2001); M. Dauphinais, B. David, and M. Levering,
eds., Aquinas the Augustinian (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of
America Press, 2007).
32. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:126–38; Weisheipl, Friar Thomas,
163–76.
33. Leonard E. Boyle, The Setting of the Summa theologiae of Saint
Thomas, Etienne Gilson Series 5 (Toronto: P.I.M.S., 1982).
34. Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Lectura romana, 1–57.
35. M. M. Mulchahey, “First the Bow is Bent in Study.…” Dominican
Education before 1350, Studies and Texts 132 (Toronto: P.I.M.S., 1998),
278–306.
36. Cf. A. Oliva, “La Questione dell’alia lectura di Tommaso d’Aquino,”
Quaestio 6 (2006): 516–21; Jean-Pierre Torrell, O.P., “Lire saint Thomas
autrement,” in Boyle, Facing History, xxi–xxiv; Torrell, Saint Thomas
Aquinas, 1:45–47 and 413.
37. P. Glorieux, “Pour la chronologie de la Somme,” Mélanges de science
religieuse 2 (1945): 59–98; I. T. Eschmann, “A Catalogue of St. Thomas’
Works,” in E. Gilson, The Christian Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas,
trans. L. K. Shook (New York: Random House, 1956), 386–88; Weisheipl,
Friar Thomas, 221–22.
38. Gauthier, Introduction, 80; cf. 65–67; cf. R. A. Gauthier, ed., L’Ethique
à Nicomaque, II, Introduction (Louvain: Nauwelaerts, 2d ed., 1970), 128–29,
n. 135. The reason for this date is that the ST I-II relies heavily on the
Rhetoric of Aristotle (more than 100 times) according to the translation of
Moerbeke, which Aquinas did not have in hand until the end of 1270.
Gauthier is in agreement with O. Lottin on this, who placed the Prima
Secundae after q.6 of QDM (end 1270).
39. ST III q.90 a.4.
40. With more or less hesitation, many think that Raynald of Piperno could
be the author of the Supplement but others are more reserved (Leonina 12, p.
xvi ff.); Eschmann, A Catalogue, 388.
41. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:50–156; Torrell, Saint Thomas
Aquinas, 2:101–5.
42. For more details on the Secunda Pars, see Stephen J. Pope, ed., The
Ethics of Aquinas (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 2002).
43. Cf. Marie-Dominique Chenu, O.P., Introduction à l’étude de Saint
Thomas d’Aquin, 2d ed. (Montréal and Paris: Institut d’Études Médiévales
and Vrin, 1954), 255–76; Marie-Dominique Chenu, O.P., La Théologie
comme science au XIIIe siècle, 3d ed. (Paris: Vrin, 1957).
44. Super Sent I, Prol., q.1, a.3, sol.1; Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 2:1–
18.
45. Cf. Leonard E. Boyle, “Notes on the Education of the Fratres
communes in the Dominican Order in the Thirteenth Century,” in R. Creytens
and P. Künzle, eds., Xenia medii aevi historiam illustrantia oblata Th.
Käppeli O.P, t. 1, Storia e Letteratura, Raccolta di Studi e Testi 141 (Edizioni
di storia e letteratura, Rome, 1978), 249–67 (reprinted in Leonard E. Boyle,
Pastoral Care, Clerical Education and Canon Law, 1200–1400 [London:
Variorum Reprints, 1981], Etude VI); Boyle, The Setting.
46. Servais Pinckaers, O.P., The Sources of Christian Ethics (Washington,
D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 1995).
47. ST I–II q.3 a.2 ad 3.
48. ST IIIa q.27–59.
49. L. Scheffczyk, “Die Stellung des Thomas von Aquin in der
Entwicklung der Lehre von den Mysteria Vitae Christi,” in M. Gerwing and
G. Ruppert, eds., Renovatio et Reformatio, (Münster: Aschendorff, 1986),
44–70.
50. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 2:125–52. Cf. also Jean-Pierre Torrell,
O.P., Le Christ en ses mystères: La Vie et l’œuvre de Jésus selon saint
Thomas d’Aquin, Jésus et Jésus-Christ 78–79 (Paris: Desclée, 1999), 1:13–
27.
51. For more on the ST, see Jean-Pierre Torrell, O.P., Aquinas’s Summa:
Background, Structure, & Reception, trans. Benedict M. Guevin, O.S.B.
(Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 2005); the ST
continues to inspire numerous studies: D. Berger, Thomas von Aquins
“Summa Theologiae” (Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Gesellschaft, 2004);
Andreas Speer, ed., Thomas von Aquin, Die Summa theologiae:
Werkinterpretationen (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2005); Rik Van
Nieuwenhove and Joseph Wawrykow, eds., The Theology of Thomas
Aquinas (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 2005).
52. Leonina 24/1 and 2; Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:161–64, 427–28.
53. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:127–29, 434.
54. Amid the numerous works in this area must be recalled at least these
few: Vivian Boland, Ideas in God According to Saint Thomas Aquinas:
Sources and Synthesis, Brill Studies in the History of Christian Thought 69
(Leiden and New York: E. J. Brill, 1996); C. D’Ancona Costa, “La Notion de
l’un dans Thomas d’Aquin: Une confrontation des commentaires sur les
Noms divins et sur la Métaphysique,” Recherches de théologie et philosophie
médiévales 64 (1997): 315–51.
55. Thierry-Dominique Humbrecht, O.P., Théologie négative et noms
divins chez saint Thomas d’Aquin, Bibliothèque thomiste 57 (Paris: Vrin,
2005).
56. J. Turbessi, “S. Thomas d’Aquin” in “Denys l’Aréopagite,”
Dictionnaire de spiritualité, ascétique et mystique, ed. Marcel Viller (Paris:
Beauchesne, 1954), 3:349–56; G. O’Daly, “Dionysius Areopagita,”
Theologische Realenzyklopädie, ed. Gerhard Müller (Berlin and New York:
Walter de Gruyter, 1981), 8:772–80; Fran O’Rourke, Pseudo-Dionysius and
the Metaphysics of Aquinas, Studien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des
Mittelalters 32 (Leiden: Brill, 1991).
57. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:167–71.
58. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:171–78.
59. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:182–84; M. M. Dufeil, “Évolution ou
fixité des institutions ecclésiales: Une controverse universitaire. L’édition
critique de trois oeuvres polémiques de saint Thomas d’Aquin,” Revue des
sciences philosophiques et théologiques 55 (1971): 464–79.
60. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:184–87; Torrell, Saint Thomas
Aquinas, 2:227–31. Cf. L. Bianchi, L’Errore di Aristotele: La Polemica
contro l’eternità del mondo nel XIII secolo (Firenze: La nuova Italia, 1984);
T. B. Noone, “The Originality of St. Thomas’s Position on the Philosophers
and Creation,” The Thomist 60 (1996): 275–300; Cyrille Michon, ed.,
Thomas d’Aquin et la controverse sur L’éternité du monde, Traités sur
l’éternité du monde de Bonaventure, Thomas d’Aquin, Peckam, Boèce de
Dacie, Henri de Gand et Guillaume d’Ockam, GF Flammarion 1199 (Paris:
Flammarion, 2004).
61. Cf. SCG II.58; ST I q.76 a.3–4; Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:187–
90; Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 2:252–59.
62. R.-A. Gauthier, “Notes sur les débuts (1225–1240) du premier
“averroïsme,” Revue des sciences philosophiques et théologiques 66 (1982):
327–74; Leonina 45/1, 218*–35*.
63. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:191–96; Alain de Libera, ed., Thomas
d’Aquin, L’Unité de l’intellect contre les averroïstes, suivi des Textes contre
Averroès antérieurs à 1270, Texte latin. Traduction, introduction,
bibliographie, chronologie, notes et index, GF 713 (Paris: Flammarion,
1994); C. Luna, “Quelques précisions chronologiques à propos de la
controverse sur l’unité de l’intellect,” Revue des sciences philosophiques et
théologiques 83 (1999): 649–84.
64. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:197–223.
65. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:197–201. Cf. M. Dauphinais and M.
Levering, eds., Reading John with St. Thomas Aquinas (Washington, D.C.:
Catholic University of America Press, 2005).
66. Jean-Pierre Torrell, O.P., “L’Unité d’être du Christ: Etat de la
question,” in Thomas Aquinas, Le Verbe incarné, t. III: Summa theologiae
IIIa Questions 7–15, New edition with translation and annotations (Paris:
Cerf, 2002), 391–402; Mulchahey, “First the Bow is Bent in Study,” 315–18;
M. H. Deloffre, ed. and trans., Thomas d’Aquin, Question disputée: L’Union
du Verbe incarné (De unione Verbi incarnati) (Paris: Vrin, 2000), 13–27.
67. See also our discussion, in Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:429–30,
on the debated authenticity of two other Disputed Questions, which some
have tried to attribute to Thomas (Utrum anima coniuncta cognoscat seipsam
per essentiam; De immortalitate animae).
68. Table of dates: Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:211.
69. C. D’Ancona Costa, “Saint Thomas lecteur du Liber de Causis: Bilan
des recherches contemporaines concernant le De Causis et analyse de
l’interprétation thomiste,” in C. D’Ancona Costa, Recherches sur le Liber De
Causis, Études de philosophie médiévale 72 (Paris: Vrin, 1995), 229–58.
70. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:224–46.
71. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:250–66.
72. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 1:267–95.
CHAPTER 2
JAMES DOIG
INTRODUCTION
Aquinas’s relation to Aristotle was that of a theologian to a source of
philosophical doctrines and concepts with whose aid he formulated his
theological synthesis of Christian revelation. The value for theology that
Aquinas saw in Aristotelian thought led him to undertake the composition of
“expositions” and sententiae respecting individual works of Aristotle.
Through these compositions, Aquinas offered his readers the possibility of
greater understanding, as well as recognition of the value of that thought for
theology.
Aquinas chose Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics and On Interpretation as the
subjects of what medieval Masters termed “expositions,” that is, studies
proceeding through an explanation focusing on the words of the text being
examined; however, only the exposition on the Posterior Analytics was
completed. As concerns what can be considered the principal works of the
Aristotelian corpus—the Metaphysics, the Physics, the De anima (“On the
Soul”), and the Nicomachean Ethics—Aquinas completed sententiae
(singular: sententia), that is, presentations in summary fashion of the
doctrines he understood Aristotle to propose in each work. While he began
five other sententiae on works of Aristotle, only one was completed, that
treating in succession the two works, “On Sense and the Sensed” and “On
Memory and Remembering.”1
As was true generally of thirteenth-century Masters, Aquinas knew no
Greek but read Aristotle in a variety of Latin translations. While some of
these were made directly from Greek manuscripts, others were based on
Arabic translations several removes from any Greek text. Since the sixth
century, Latin Europe had known Aristotle’s Categories and On
Interpretation in Boethius’s translation, but the remaining parts of the
Organon became available in Latin only by the middle of the twelfth century.
Then too, only in the middle of that same century did Aristotle’s strictly
philosophical works begin to appear in Latin, and even these were at times
only in a partial translation. Moreover, during Aquinas’s lifetime one could
not have found consensus on the exact number or identity of the works of
Aristotle. Nor did Aquinas and his contemporaries have adequate historical
information respecting the relation of Plato and Aristotle, not to speak of
Neoplatonism and its effects on the numerous philosophical works that were
being introduced into the Latin world in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries.2
Yet Aquinas’s mastery of the Aristotelian corpus available to him is
evidenced by the “divisions of text” everywhere proposed in his expositions
and sententiae on individual works. By these divisions, he not only proposed
the unity he saw as constituted by the books that together make up a given
Aristotelian work, but he also explained both the flow from chapter to
chapter within each book and the fashion in which Aristotle proceeded from
point to point within each chapter. In his expositions and sententiae on
Aristotle, we encounter Aquinas the teacher intent on explaining both the
doctrine he understood Aristotle to offer and the procedure by which it was
offered. In what follows, it is Aquinas’s interest in the four principle works
of Aristotle’s philosophy and the use of that philosophy in Aquinas’s
theology that is of concern.
NOTES
1. The unfinished sententiae concerned Meteorology, Politics, Heaven
(known to Aquinas as “On Heaven and on the World”), and Generation and
Corruption. Aquinas’s writings on Aristotle are discussed in: Jean-Pierre
Torrell, O.P., Initiation à saint Thomas d’Aquin: Sa personne et son oeuvre
(Fribourg, Suisse/Paris: Éditions universitaire/Cerf, 1993), 498–503. For the
notions of medieval “expositions” and sententiae, see R. A. Gauthier,
“Praefatio,” Sententia libri Ethicorum, in Sancti Thomae de Aquino Opera
Omnia, 47/1 (Rome: Sancta Sabina, 1969), 244*–45*; R. A. Gauthier, “Le
Cours sur l’Ethica nova d’un maitres es arts de Paris (1235–1240),” Archives
d’histoire doctrinale et litteraire du moyen age 43 (1975): 76–77.
2. On the influx of translations of Greek, Jewish, and Arabic works into
Latin during the twelfth–thirteenth centuries, see Frederick Copleston, A
History of Philosophy (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday, 1985), 3:205–11;
Marie-Therese D’Alverny, La Transmission des textes philosophiques et
scientifiques au Moyen Age, ed. C. Burnett (Aldershot: Variorum, 1994), chs.
2–3. For the Latin translations of Aristotle’s works, see the various volumes
of Aristoteles Latinus, ed. L. Minio-Paluello (Paris: Brouwer, 1965–1995).
3. Aquinas, Sententia Libri De Anima, Leonina, vol. 45-I (Roma:
Commissio Leonina, 1984), 72–73, l. 366–92; 88–89, l. 70–131; 207, l. 358–
83. Hereinafter cited as In DA.
4. In DA, 88–89, l. 43–131.
5. The remote source of this view is: Pseudo-Augustinus, De spiritu et
anima, in Patrologia Latina (Paris: J. P. Migne, 1857), 40: col. 781
(hereinafter cited as PL). Influential was the assertion that the intellective
soul is more properly “perfection” of the body, rather than its form:
Avicenna, Liber de anima seu sixtus de naturalibus, in S. Van Riet, ed., G.
Verbeke, intro., Avicenna Latinus, 2 vols. (Vol. I, Louvain/Leiden:
Peeters/Brill, 1968; Vol. 2, Louvain/Leiden: Éditions Orientalistes/Brill,
1972), 1:16, l. 87–21, l. 48. Later proponents of the soul as subsistent
spiritual form included: Alexander of Hales, Glossa in quatuor libros
Sententiarum Petri Lombardi (Quaracchi: Collegium S. Bonaventura, 1952),
2:145, l. 16–146, l. 3; Jean de La Rochelle, Summa de anima, ed. J. S.
Bougerol (Paris: J. Vrin, 1995), 80, l. 1–2; William of Auvergne, Tractatus
de anima, in Guilielmi Alverni Opera Omnia, Vol. 2 (Paris, 1674); reprinted:
Frankfurt am Main: Minerva GMBH, 1963), fol. 67, col. A; Bonaventure,
Commentaria in quatuor libros Sententiarum, in Opera omnia (Quaracchi:
Collegium S. Bonaventurae, 1885), 1–4: responsio, 414b–415a; ad 5, 415b;
Peter of Spain, Scientia libri De anima, ed. M. A. Alonso, 2d ed. (Barcelona:
Flors, 1961), 17, l. 18–31; 20, l. 10–16; 304, l. 17–18. A witness to the ideas
current at the time Aquinas left Paris (1259) dates from ca. 1260, although
probably not known to him: Anonymous, Questiones in tres libros De anima,
in Ein anonymer Aristoteleskommentar des XIII. Jarhunderts, ed. J.
Vennebusch (Paderborn: F. Schöningh, 1963), 116, l. 22–117, l. 33.
6. Dominicus Gundisalvus, “The Treatise De anima of Dominicus
Gundissalinus,” ed. J. T. Muchkle, intro. E. Gilson, Mediaeval Studies 2
(1940): 58, l. 28–31. Johannes Blund, Tractatus de anima, ed. D. A. Callus
and R. W. Hunt (London: Oxford University Press, 1970), 90, l. 28–91, l. 5.
Alexander of Hales, Summa theologiae (Quaracchi: Collegium S.
Bonaventurae, 1928), solutio, 399a–b. Pseudo-Peter of Spain, Expositio libri
De anima, published as: Pedro Hispano. Obras Filosóficas, Vol. 3, ed. M.
Alonso (Madrid: Instituto Luis Vives, 1954), 328, l. 32–329, l. 6. Jean de La
Rochelle, Summa de anima, 67, l. 75–82; 70, l. 67–69 and 75–77.
Bonaventure, Opera omnia, responsio 414b–15a; ad 6, 415b–16a.
Anonymous, Questiones, 455, l. 262–456, l. 276.
7. The source of this doctrine appears to be had in Avicebron, Fons vitae,
ed. C. Baeumker, in Beiträge zur Geschichte der Philosophie des
Mittelalters, Bd. 1, H. 2–4 (Münster, 1892), 211–27. Proponents included the
following: Alexander of Hales, Summa theologiae, ad 1–7, 422b; Peter of
Spain, Commentarium in De anima, ed. M. A. Alonso, in Obras Filosóficas,
n. 2 (Madrid, 1944), 656, l. 9–30; Anonymous, Magister Artium, Lectura in
librum De anima a quodam discipulo reportata (Ms. Roma Naz. V. E. 828),
ed. R. A. Gauthier (Grottoferrata: Collegium S. Bonaventurae, 1985), 155, l.
212–256, l. 233; 214, l. 311–315, l. 326; 219, l. 442–44. Somewhat similar to
the doctrine of a plurality of forms is the notion of the intellect as a separated
substance whose union with the sensitive soul results in a composed form
that as such is the act of the human body: Anonymous, Questiones, 142, l.
70–76; 176, l. 118–28.
8. Bonaventure, Opera omnia, responsio, 86a; ad 1, 90a. Bonaventure,
Opera omnia, obj. 3, 122a.
9. Avicenna, Liber de anima, 36, l. 49–37, l. 68. Gundisalvus, “The
Treatise De anima,” 37, l. 17–32. Jean de La Rochelle, Summa de anima, 51,
l. 27–41. William of Auvergne, Tractatus de anima, fol. 82, col. B – fol. 83,
col. A. Peter of Spain, Commentarium in De anima, 650, l. 3–24.
10. Gundisalvus, “The Treatise De anima,” 42, l. 11–15. Blund, Tractatus
de anima, 5, l. 23–26, l. 3; 7, l. 1–13. Alexander of Hales, Summa theologiae,
385–86. Jean de La Rochelle, Summa de anima, 385b–386a. Anonymous,
Questiones, 163, l. 51–59; 176, l. 131–32, dated ca. 1260, the year following
Aquinas’s departure from Paris, illustrates the currency of this view of
Aristotle’s definition of the soul.
11. In DA, 79, l. 106–21; 85, l. 155–74.
12. This is implied in these texts: In DA, 74, l. 36–75, l. 44; 76, l. 141–50;
86, l. 239–57.
13. In DA, 222–23, l. 202–20.
14. In DA, 207, l. 372–83.
15. In DA, 216, l. 65–86.
16. Although Aquinas devotes a few paragraphs to the rejection of the
interpretation of the agent and possible intellects attributed to Averroës, both
the failure to mention the latter’s name and the brevity of the discussion also
indicate that Aquinas’s goal is to present Aristotle’s views in as
straightforward a way as possible. See In DA, 220, l. 89–221, l. 166.
17. ST I, prologus.
18. ST I q.75–88.
19. The twenty-some “corrections” range from the mild: In octo libros
Physicorum Aristotelis expositio, ed. M. Maggiolo, (Turin: Marietti, 1954),
no. 8: “His [i.e., Averroës’s] exposition is inappropriate because as a whole it
does not have one goal and because the Philosopher does not intend to show”
to the harsh: In Phy, no. 966: “The argument Averroes has proposed is
completely frivolous,” and in no. 1083: “What the Commentator says is
evidently false.” Hereinafter cited as In Phy.
20. In Phy, no. 145.
21. In Phy, no. 285.
22. In Phy, nos. 150 and 152–53.
23. Place and the vacuum: In Phy, 201–70, lect. 1–14; time: 273–312, lect.
15–23.
24. In Phy, nos. 885–86 and 891–94.
25. In Phy, nos. 972 and 1083.
26. In Phy, nos. 1004–5, 1081–84, and 1168.
27. In Phy, nos. 974–90.
28. Sententia Libri Ethicorum, Leonina, vol. 47 (Roma: Commissio
Leonina, 1969), 4–5, l. 50–54, and 99–109. Hereinafter cited as In NE. For
moral virtue in general, see: In NE, Bk. II, cc. 1–11; for the principles of
virtuous activity, such as voluntary action and choice, see: Bk. III, cc. 1–13;
for individual moral virtues, see: Bk. IV, c. 14–V, c. 17; for intellectual
virtues, see: Bk. VI, cc. 1–11.
29. In NE, 582–83, l. 1–15; and 583, l. 71–78.
30. In NE, 597, l. 1–29.
31. In NE, 14, l. 1–6; 31–32, l. 60–76; and 32–33, l. 136–217.
32. In NE, 60, l. 215–22; and 595, l. 141–44.
33. Averroës, Commentarium in Ethicorum, in Moralem totam
philosophiam complectentes cum Averrois Cordubensis in Moralia
Nicomachia expositione, Vol. 3 of Aristotelis Stagiritae Libri (Venice:
Juncta, 1562–1574; reprint Frankfurt am Main: Minerva G.m.b.H., 1962),
fol. 8vH-I and fol. 9vG-H. Albertus Magnus, Super Ethica commentum et
quaestiones, ed. W. Kübel, in Opera omnia, T. XIV, P. I–II (Cologne:
Aschendorff, 1968–72 and 1987), 75, l. 72–76, l. 4; 714, l. 27–31; 746, l. 5–
16. For a more complete statement of interpretations of the Nicomachean
Ethics current at this time, see James C. Doig, Aquinas’s Philosophical
Commentary on the Ethics (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2001), 8–24.
34. A detailed study showing the In Meta to be Aquinas’s proposal of the
structure Aristotle intended for the Metaphysics is had in: Gabriele Galluzzo,
“Aquinas on the Structure of Aristotle’s Metaphysics,” Documenti e studi
sulla tradizione medievale 15 (2004): 353–86.
35. In duodecim libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelis expositio, ed. M. R.
Cathala & M. Spiazzi, (Turin: Marietti, 1950), nos. 1, 35, and 51. Hereinafter
cited as In Meta.
36. In Meta, no. 534.
37. In Meta, nos. 1147–51.
38. In Meta, nos. 1245–47.
39. In Meta, nos. 1276–79.
40. In Meta, Bk. XII, lect. 5–9.
41. In Meta, nos. 2611–14.
42. In Meta, nos. 556–58.
43. In Meta, nos. 295 and 1164.
44. In Meta, nos. 2496–99.
45. De anima, II, 1, 412a8–9. The Latin translation used by Aquinas is
found in: In DA, 67. Aquinas’s interpretation is had in: In DA, nos. 100–17.
46. e.g., see: ST I q.76 a.1 ad 5; a.2 ad 2; QDP, q.6 a.6 ad 8.
47. The passage in question is Meta., II, 1, 993b26–30. The translations are
found in Aristoteles latinus 1970–95: (Vol. 25/1–1a, 37, l. 7–11 Vetustissima
trans.; 120, l. 3–7 Vetus trans.); (Vol. 25/2, 37, l. 6–10 Media trans.); (Vol.
3/2, 44, l. 29–34 Moerbecana trans.). The Latin text of Aristotle given in In
Meta, 84, while not a critical edition, is very close to the Moerbecana, which
makes Aquinas’s point more clearly than the other three.
48. In Meta, nos. 2614–16. The difference between Aquinas’s approach to
Aristotle’s position in the In Meta and the QDP illustrates the care with
which Aquinas interprets Aristotle when that interpretation is his goal; see
QDP, q.3 a.16, obj. 23 and ad 23.
49. In Meta, nos. 1287–89. That the metaphysical proof is more
demonstrative, see In Phy, no. 107. A related discussion adding detail is had
in QDP, q.9 a.1, resp.
50. James C. Doig, Aquinas on Metaphysics: A historico-doctrinal Study of
the Commentary on the Metaphysics (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1972), chs. 4–5.
51. ST I q.1 a.2. See In Meta, nos. 391–92, 1147–51, and 2249–51.
52. ST I q.2 a.2. See In libros Posteriorum analyticorum, in In Aristotelis
libros Peri Hermeneias et Posteriorum analyticorum expositio, ed. R. M.
Spiazzi, (Turin: Marietti, 1955), nos. 195–97. Hereinafter cited as In PA.
53. ST I q.2 a.3, where Aquinas cites Metaphysics II as asserting first, that
the most true beings are the greatest beings and then, that the greatest reality
included within a genus is the cause of all others within that genus. For his
interpretation of the passage at issue, see In Meta, nos. 292–98. An additional
indication that Aquinas saw the fourth proof as Aristotelian and not Platonic
is had in ST I, q.6 a.4.—Two or three years prior to ST I, Aquinas offered
what is essentially the fourth proof; see QDP, q.3 a.5, cor.
54. Note, e.g., the investigation of predication in In Meta, Bk. V, lect. 1–
22.
55. ST I q.13 a.1 ad 2.
56. ST I q.28 a.2.
57. ST I q.76 a.3 ad 2.
CHAPTER 3
ALEXANDER FIDORA
FINAL REMARKS
Introductory surveys of Aquinas’s thought, if they ever deal with what he
inherited from the Latin-Christian tradition, tend to point out that research on
this topic is still at its very beginning and that in the near future important
results are expected.27 Curiously enough, even though time has passed by,
they keep reiterating this.
In fact the problem one is facing with regard to Aquinas’s Latin-Christian
sources is not an isolated one, but has very much to do with the general
approach to twelfth- and thirteenth-century philosophy. Historiography has
characterized this period as an intellectual revolution brought about by the
introduction of “new” texts and doctrines, from both Greek and Arabic
philosophy, and it is therefore no surprise that these new materials feature
large in the accounts of twelfth- and thirteenth-century philosophy. There can
be no question that the reception of ancient Greek as well as Arabic
philosophy is a distinctive hallmark of this epoch of Latin-Christian thought.
Yet, as I have said, it is precisely in order to obtain an adequate interpretation
of this phenomenon that one has to draw attention to the way in which the
tradition of Latin-Christian philosophy and theology itself is received and
transformed during these years, taking, as it does, an active part—and not
just being a passive background—in some of the most salient intellectual
developments of the time.
Far from being played off against a traditional—and supposedly
conservative—background, the via Thomae is part of a much broader trend in
Latin-Christian thought that has been described as the process of occidental
rationalization. As I have tried to show, it is from this tradition that Aquinas
takes many of his fundamental philosophical and theological motives and
intuitions, which were to assume a leading role in his reception of Greek and
Arabic philosophy, and which concern the theories of human knowledge and
science, together with some of the key concepts of ontology and
metaphysics, as well as the idea of theology as a science.
NOTES
1. Many introductions and presentations of Aquinas, when coming to
discuss his sources, start off directly with Aristotelian and Neoplatonic texts.
And even more well-balanced accounts tend to put his Latin-Christian bases
in second place. Cf., for instance, Tommaso d’Aquino nella storia del
pensiero I: Le fonti del pensiero di S. Tommaso (Atti del congresso
internazionale Tommaso d’Aquino nel suo settimo centenario) (Naples:
Edizioni Domenicane Italiane, 1975), where the chapters on Aquinas’s Latin-
Christian sources are placed right at the end of the volume.
2. For which, see the chapters “Aquinas and Aristotle” by James Doig,
“Aquinas, Plato, and Neoplatonism” by Wayne Hankey, and “Aquinas and
Jewish and Islamic Authors” by David Burrell in this volume.
3. Before this, as a baccalaureus biblicus at Paris, Aquinas had already
written a series of Bible commentaries, i.e., on Isaiah (1251/2), Jeremiah
(1251/2), Lamentations (1251/2), and the Psalms (1252/3 or later). These
biblical commentaries, interesting as they are, still await a thorough
appraisal. Recently Eleonore Stump has drawn attention to the
(philosophical) significance of some of them: Eleonore Stump, Aquinas
(New York: Routledge, 2003), especially 455–78 (Chapter 16: “Providence
and Suffering”). Cf. also Thomas G. Weinandy et al., Aquinas on Scripture:
An Introduction to the Biblical Commentaries (London and New York: T. &
T. Clark International, 2005).
4. See, among others, the accurate account in Marie-Dominique Chenu,
Introduction à l’étude de Saint Thomas d’Aquin, 2d ed. (Montréal/Paris:
Institut d’Études Médiévales/Vrin, 1954), 44–51.
5. For Aquinas’s gnoseological position and his criticism directed at
Augustine, cf. ST I-II q.109 a.1. In ST I q.79 a.4, the question seems to
address both Augustine and Avicenna.
6. See the classical study by Étienne Gilson, “Pourquoi Saint Thomas a
critiqué Saint Augustin,” Archives d’histoire doctrinale et littéraire du
Moyen Âge 1 (1926): 1–127.
7. See Maurice De Wulf, “L’Augustinisme ‘avicennisant’,” Revue
néoscolastique de philosophie 33 (1931): 11–39.
8. Steven Marrone, The Light of Thy Countenance: Science and
Knowledge of God in the Thirteenth Century, 2 vols. (Leiden: Brill, 2001),
here 1:2.
9. Chenu, Introduction à l’étude de Saint Thomas d’Aquin, 47.
10. For Aquinas’s place with regard to this twelfth-century tradition, see
Gillian R. Evans, “The Discussions of the Scientific Status of Theology in
the Second Half of the Twelfth Century,” in Matthias Lutz-Bachmann,
Alexander Fidora, and Andreas Niederberger, eds., Metaphysics in the
Twelfth Century: On the Relationship among Philosophy, Science and
Theology (Turnhout: Brepols, 2004), 161–83.
11. The work is available in an excellent English translation: Thomas
Aquinas, Faith, Reason and Theology, trans. by Armand Maurer (Toronto:
Pontificial Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1987) (= In BDT, q.1–4) and
Thomas Aquinas, The Division and Methods of the Sciences, 4th rev. ed.,
trans. by Armand Maurer (Toronto: Pontificial Institute of Mediaeval
Studies, 1986) (= In BDT, q.5–6).
12. Cf., for instance, Matthias Lutz-Bachmann, “Die Einteilung der
Wissenschaften des Thomas von Aquin. Ein Beitrag zur Rekonstruktion der
Epistemologie in Quaestio 5, Artikel 1 des Kommentars von Thomas zum
Trinitätstraktat des Boethius,” in Rainer Berndt and Matthias Lutz-
Bachmann, eds., “Scientia” und “Disciplina”: Wissenstheorie und
Wissenschaftspraxis im 12. und 13. Jahrhundert (Berlin: Akademie Verlag,
2002), 235–47.
13. Cf. In BDT, q.5, a.4, resp. On this topic, cf. Pasquale Porro’s essay
“Metafisica e teologia nella divisione delle scienze speculative del Super
Boetium De Trinitate” in his edition of Thomas Aquinas, Commenti a
Boezio, ed. and Italian trans. by Pasquale Porro (Milan: Bompiani, 2007),
467–526. See also the introduction to the Latin-German edition of Thomas
Aquinas, Kommentar zum Trinitätstraktat des Boethius II, ed. and German
trans. by Peter Hoffmann (Freiburg i. Br.: Herder, 2007), 7–42.
14. 1259 is the traditional dating of the work, insofar as it is seen as a
follow-up to the commentary on De Trinitate. Yet, on the grounds of some
formal coincidences with Aquinas’s later commentaries on pseudo-Dionysius
and Aristotle, the editors of the Leonina suggest dating its redaction to a later
period. On the other hand, some scholars have claimed that the work, like the
commentary on De Trinitate, remained a fragment; but there is hardly any
evidence for such a hypothesis.
15. See, for instance, Ralph McInerny, Boethius and Aquinas (Washington,
D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 1990), p. xiv: “Boethius taught
what Thomas said he taught.” Against this categorical claim, see Andreas
Speer, “The Hidden Heritage: Boethian Metaphysics and its Medieval
Tradition,” in Pasquale Porro, ed., Metaphysica—sapientia—scientia divina
(= Quaestio 5) (Turnhout: Brepols, 2005), 161–79, here 166f.: “This
completely a-historical construction … overlooks the fact that Thomas, in
discovering the underlying idea of the Boethian metaphysics, dismissed it
fundamentally.”
16. It is worth noting that Aquinas was also indebted to Boethius on other
subjects, such as divine eternity and knowledge as well as the concept of
persona.
17. McInerny, Boethius and Aquinas, 253.
18. On Boethius and his relevance for the reception of Aristotle in the
twelfth century, see Alexander Fidora, Die Wissenschaftstheorie des
Dominicus Gundissalinus: Voraussetzungen und Konsequenzen des zweiten
Anfangs der aristotelischen Philosophie im 12. Jahrhundert (Berlin:
Akademie Verlag, 2004), esp. 89–95.
19. See, among others, Matthew R. Cosgrove, “Thomas Aquinas on
Anselm’s Argument,” The Review of Metaphysics 27 (1974): 513–30.
20. Cf. Clemens Vansteenkiste, “S. Bernardo nell’opera di San Tommaso,”
Rassegna di letteratura tomistica 10 (1978): 35–47.
21. See Ralph J. Masiello, “Reason and Faith in Richard of St. Victor and
St. Thomas,” The New Scholasticism 48 (1974): 233–42.
22. Cf. Beryl Smalley, “William of Auvergne, John of La Rochelle and St.
Thomas Aquinas on the Old Law,” in St. Thomas Aquinas, 1274–1974:
Commemorative Studies, foreword by Étienne Gilson, 2 vols. (Toronto:
Pontificial Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1974), 2:11–71.
23. See the study by Amato Masnovo, Da Guglielmo d’Auvergne a S.
Tommaso d’Aquino, 3 vols. (Milan: Società Editrice Vita e Pensiero, 1930–
45).
24. Both can be considered important prefigurations of some of Aquinas’s
concerns with regard to theology. See, respectively, Rudolf Thomas, “Die
Präfiguration thomistischen Denkens bei Petrus Abaelardus,” in Tommaso
d’Aquino nella storia del pensiero I: Le fonti del pensiero di S. Tommaso
(Atti del congresso internazionale Tommaso d’Aquino nel suo settimo
centenario) (Naples: Edizioni Domenicane Italiane, 1975), 392–98, and
Rainer Berndt, “La Théologie comme système du monde: Sur l’évolution des
sommes théologiques de Hugues de Saint-Victor à Saint Thomas d’Aquin,”
Revue des sciences philosophiques et théologiques 78/4 (1994): 555–72.
25. See Ludwig Jeßberger, Das Abhängigkeitsverhältnis des hl. Thomas
von Aquin von Albertus Magnus und Bonaventura im dritten Buche des
“Sentenzenkommentars” (Würzburg: Ph.D. thesis, 1936).
26. Cf. Super Sent I.1, d.2, q.1, pr. On this innovative rearrangement and its
consequences, see Chenu, Introduction à l’étude de Saint Thomas d’Aquin,
226–37 and 258–65. In addition, see Elisabeth Reinhardt and Josep-Ignasi
Saranyana, “La configuración de la ciencia teológica: De Hugo de San Víctor
a Tomás de Aquino,” Veritas 43/3 (1998): 549–62.
27. Cf., for instance, Fernand Van Steenberghen, La Philosophie au XIIIe
siècle (Louvain/Paris: Publ. Univ. Louvain/Béatrice-Nauwelaerts, 1966),
335.
CHAPTER 4
WAYNE J. HANKEY
The difference between these two positions stems from this, that some, in order to seek
the truth about the nature of things, proceeded from intelligible reasons, and this was the
particular characteristic of the Platonists. Some, however, proceeded from sensible
things, and this was the particular characteristic of the philosophy of Aristotle, as
Simplicius says in his commentary Upon the Categories.14
Because the most perfect unity is found in the highest summit of things, God, and
because with each reality so much the more it is one, so much the greater is its power
and dignity, it follows that, to the extent that things be further away from the First
Principle, so much greater is the diversity and variety found in them. Therefore it is
necessary that the process of emanation from God be united within this Principle itself,
and be multiplied according to the lowliness of things, where it comes to its end.37
According to his own account, in the Summa theologiae Aquinas was finally
able to give sacred teaching the order in which its proper structure would be
intelligible. Thus, in order to get a glimpse at how pervasive Neoplatonism is
in Aquinas, we may suitably conclude with some remarks on how, not only
the Summa theologiae as a whole, but also particular treatises within it,
describe the Neoplatonic structure of remaining, going out, and return by
which all things except the One revert upon their principle.38
The first circle within the Prima Pars (ST I q.3–11) is constructed when,
beginning with simplicity, we arrive back at unity, by way of the going out of
the existence of God into all things. The circles succeeding it return to the
principle by way of more and more differentiated processions. We have a
unification of the Platonic dialectic of the one and the many with Aristotle’s
logic of activity as entelecheia in a Neoplatonic hierarchy.39 Moreover, the
Neoplatonic figures determine content, as well as form.
For example, a Proclean conception, that incorporeal substances have
complete return upon themselves, enables the Summa’s progress from the
circle described by simple being returning to itself as unity to the questions
on the divine activities of knowing, loving, and power. Creation for Aquinas
requires three emanations of two kinds. First, there are the internal
emanations or processions within the divine essence, which produce real
distinctions and relations within the Principle. The two emanations of the
eternal Word and Holy Spirit are necessary and natural. Thomas invokes
Avicenna on behalf of this necessity in God and has in mind a principle,
frequent among the Neoplatonized Arabic Peripatetics, “from a simple one
nothing except a unity can come.”40 Equality as a characteristic is especially
appropriated to the Word as the first emanation from the Father who is the
principle of the Trinitarian processions. Thus, Aquinas writes, once more in a
Neoplatonic mode:
The first thing which proceeds from unity is equality and then multiplicity proceeds.
Therefore, from the Father, to whom, according to Augustine, unity is proper, the Son
processes, to whom equality is appropriate, and then the creature comes forth to which
inequality belongs.41
The multiplication of equals is the origin of the other kind of emanation, that
of “all being from the universal being.”42 Throughout his writing, the
emanations of divine Persons are the cause and reason of all subsequent
emanations.43 The characteristics of the procession of creatures are contrary
to those within the divine essence, but determined by them. This procession
is voluntary because the divine being is necessarily willing. A figure, by
which the Neoplatonists reconciled Plato and Aristotle, the idea of
motionless motion as characterizing the activity of the perfect, enables
Aquinas to call God “living.” A structure, taken from Proclus via Dionysius
and the Liber, provides the framework for the consideration of all spiritual
substances from the soul to the divine; they have essence, power, and act.44
God is unknown to us in this present life, but not, as with Proclus, in
principle. However, reason understands its own ignorance. By a combination
of two Neoplatonic structures: (1) the relation between the grade of a
substance in the hierarchy and its way of knowing, with (2) the systematic
analogy between the ways of knowing and the grades of being, Aquinas
develops his doctrine of analogy to prevent all our judgments about God
being false. The correction of the mode of our knowing of God, by
comparing it to the mode of his being, requires that we are simultaneously
looking at reality in a human way, and regarding our place in the cosmos
from the divine perspective. This capacity to look at ourselves from beyond
ourselves is consequent on our participation in the higher knowing of
separate substances, a characteristically Neoplatonic reworking of a
reconciled Aristotle and Plato.45 This participation is as much a fact about the
psychological and ontological structure of the cosmos—and thus about the
constitution of our nature and how it functions within its hierarchically
situated place—as it is something vouchsafed by revelation. In fact, the top-
down movement of knowing, which Aquinas reserves for revelation in
contradistinction from the upward movement of philosophy, belongs to the
Neoplatonic correction of Aristotle.46
NOTES
1. See Wayne John Hankey, “Aquinas and the Platonists,” in Stephen
Gersh and Martin Hoenen, eds., The Platonic Tradition in the Middle Ages:
A Doxographic Approach (Berlin and New York: de Gruyter, 2002), 279–
324.
2. Wayne John Hankey, “Participatio divini luminis, Aquinas’ Doctrine of
the Agent Intellect: Our Capacity for Contemplation,” Dionysius 22 (2004):
165 and Larry Michael Harrington, ed., A Thirteenth-Century Textbook of
Mystical Theology at the University of Paris (Paris, Leuven, and Dudley:
Peeters, 2004).
3. Super Sent I.2, d.14, q.1, a.2 and Diu. nom., proemium. Translations are
mine.
4. See on Arabic and earlier translations of the Corpus, Alexander Treiger,
“The Arabic Version of Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite’s Mystical
Theology, Chapter 1: Introduction, Critical Edition, and Translation,” Le
Muséon 120: 3–4 (2007): 365–93.
5. Alain de Libera, La Querelle des universaux: De Platon à la fin du
Moyen Age (Paris: Des travaux, 1996), 117.
6. See Houston Smit, “Aquinas’s Abstractionism,” Medieval Philosophy
and Theology 10 (2001): 85–118 and Hankey, “Participatio divini luminis.”
7. QDSC 10, ad 8.
8. SCG 2, 74; ST I q.84 a.4; see Dag Nikolaus Hasse, Avicenna’s De
Anima in the Latin West: The Formation of a Peripatetic Philosophy of the
Soul, 1160–1300 (London/Turin: The Warburg Institute/Nino Aragno, 2000),
72.
9. QDSC 10, ad 8; QDV 16, 3; ST I q.79 a.5; see “Simplicius,” On Aristotle
on the Soul 3.1–5, trans. Henry Blumenthal (London: Duckworth, 2000), vii,
8, 220, and Wayne John Hankey, “Why Philosophy Abides for Aquinas,”
The Heythrop Journal 42:3 (2001): 338.
10. e.g. In DC 3, 2.
11. See Wayne John Hankey, “Thomas’ Neoplatonic Histories: His
Following of Simplicius,” Dionysius 20 (2002): 153–78.
12. Robert John Henle, Saint Thomas and Platonism: A Study of the Plato
and Platonici Texts in the Writings of Saint Thomas (The Hague: Martinus
Nijhoff, 1956), 447.
13. In DC 1, 22; In DA 8, 38; In Meta 3, 11; In Phy 1, 15.
14. QDSC 3.
15. DSS 1.
16. QDSC 10, ad 8.
17. DSS 1.
18. ST I q.2 a.2 s.c.
19. QDV 10, 12; see QDV 14, 9 and ad 9.
20. ST I q.84 a.2.
21. Ibid.
22. Super Sent I.1, d.38, q.1, a.2; see In BDT, Expositio Capituli Secundi
and Wayne John Hankey, “Aquinas, Pseudo-Denys, Proclus and Isaiah
VI.6,” Archives d’histoire doctrinale et littéraire du Moyen Âge 64 (1997):
87–90.
23. DSS 1.
24. DSS 4.
25. In CA, prop. 19.
26. In CA, prop. 10 and prop. 13.
27. In CA, prop. 3; on the ambiguity of Dionysius, see Diu. nom. 5, 1.
28. In CA, prop. 6; see Wayne John Hankey, “Self and Cosmos in
Becoming Deiform: Neoplatonic Paradigms for Reform by Self-Knowledge
from Augustine to Aquinas” in Christopher Bellitto and Louis Hamilton,
eds., Reforming the Church before Modernity: Patterns, Problems and
Approaches (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2005), 49–50 and Jean-Marc Narbonne,
Hénologie, ontologie et Ereignis (Plotin-Proclus-Heidegger) (Paris: Les
Belles Lettres, 2001), 41–70, 222–44.
29. DSS 2.
30. Simplicius, Commentaire sur les Catégories d’Aristote, Traduction de
Guillaume de Moerbeke, ed. Adrien Pattin, vol. 1 (Louvain: Publications
universitaires de Louvain, 1971), prologus, 8.
31. DSS 2.
32. Ibid.
33. Ibid.
34. QDM 16, 1.
35. SCG 2, 92.
36. DSS 4.
37. SCG 4, 1, prooemium.
38. See ST I q.2, prologue and Wayne John Hankey, God in Himself:
Aquinas’ Doctrine of God as Expounded in the Summa Theologiae (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1987), passim.
39. Wayne John Hankey, “Theoria versus Poesis: Neoplatonism and
Trinitarian Difference in Aquinas,” Modern Theology 15 (1999): 397–408.
40. QDP 2, 4 and ST I q.41 a.2; see Wayne John Hankey, “Ab uno simplici
non est nisi unum: The Place of Natural and Necessary Emanation in
Aquinas’ Doctrine of Creation,” in Michael Treschow, Willemien Otten, and
Walter Hannam, eds., Divine Creation in Ancient, Medieval, and Early
Modern Thought (Leiden: Brill, 2007), 328–31.
41. ST I q.47 a.2 ad 2.
42. ST I q.45 a.4 ad 1.
43. Gilles Emery, La Trinité Créatrice: Trinité et création dans les
commentaires aux Sentences de Thomas d’Aquin et de ses précurseurs Albert
le Grand et Bonaventure (Paris: Vrin, 1995), 280.
44. ST I q.75 prologus.
45. DSS 4, see Hankey, God in Himself, 165.
46. Proclus, Elements of Theology, 2d ed., ed. Eric Robertson Dodds
(Oxford: Clarendon, 1963), 198–99.
CHAPTER 5
MOSES MAIMONIDES
Moses Maimonides (1135–1204) lived all of his life in the Islamicate, that is
the linguistic and cultural world of Islam, coming eventually to serve as court
physician for Saladin in Foster, the modern Cairo. He composed works of
philosophy in Judaeo-Arabic (that is, Arabic with Hebrew orthography), the
most significant of which is the Guide of the Perplexed, addressed to his
student, Joseph. It was quickly translated into Hebrew, coming to Aquinas’s
attention in Latin translation. Aquinas’s citations of this work show that he
sensed an affinity with “Rabbi Moses,” engaging his work in a spirit of
shared inquiry, notably around the issue of free creation and that of “naming
God,” another place where revelation and reason intersect. As for creation,
medieval discussions tended to focus on the eternity of the world versus its
beginning in time, reflecting a religious concern that divided Jewish,
Christian, and Muslim thinkers sharply from their pagan predecessors.
Aristotle had maintained the eternity of the world because he had no way of
conceiving it as a whole but could only presume it as a given—as the context
for whatever else might be said or thought. When Plotinus would take the
next step to insist on origination, the presumption of everlasting origination
held. Indeed, the contrary assertion—that it had been created in the moment
when time thus began—would require access to a perspective beyond the
world. Affirming creation required faith in a revelation, and revelation
presupposed one revealing. As Maimonides put it: “as for us, the matter is
clear …: that all things exist in virtue of a purpose and not of necessity, and
that He who purposed them may change them.”7 Necessary emanation from
the One (as Maimonides understood Plotinus, refracted through al-Farabi)
does not count as creation, for on that picture the First is not clearly distinct
from the ensuing series, so the Oneness of God is jeopardized. Aquinas will
accept Maimonides’ contention that we cannot demonstrate from such a
purposeful dependence clearly “in favor of the world’s having been produced
in time,”8 yet the presumption in favor of an eternal world had also been
shown to be undemonstrable, leaving Torah believers free to accept creation
de novo, as well as ex nihilo.
The philosophical discussion, however, has only begun. Avicenna had
tried to reconcile Qur’anic assertions about creation with a pre-existent (and
eternal) matter because he could see no other place to locate the possibility
that what came to be would come to be. (Aquinas distinguished real
possibility from merely conceptual non-repugnance, located within the mind
of the maker.) Yet a clear conception of creatio ex nihilo would similarly
founder on identifying the proper effect of the creator, since analogies with
human making inevitably demanded something be presupposed. Maimonides
did not even attempt this articulation, though his endorsing practical knowing
as a useful way of intimating to ourselves the divine knowing that utterly
escapes us9 offers Aquinas a leading analogy of artisan to artifact. Similarly,
Avicenna’s distinguishing existence from the essence of created things will
allow Aquinas to identify “esse as the proper effect of the first cause,”10 once
he had painstakingly refined Avicenna’s distinction, as we have seen, as well
as carefully distinguished practical from speculative knowing. As
Maimonides notes, “a great disparity exists between the knowledge an
artificer has of the thing he has made and the knowledge someone else has of
the artifact in question.”11 The latter form of knowledge corresponds to our
way of knowing “the things from which we acquire the knowledge [we have]
of them,” whereas “the things in question follow upon [God’s] knowledge,”
as the artifact an artisan. The analogy is hardly a novel one; creating is
usually proposed as a making or modeling. Besides Genesis 2, we are also
reminded of Jeremiah: “as clay is in the potter’s hand, so you are in mine,
House of Israel” (Jer. 18:6). What makes it a bold comparison, however, is to
think of God so related to all there is as artisan to artifact. For the knowledge
involved is too inarticulate to satisfy the philosopher in us, while the
relationship of clay to potter is too passive and mute to meet the demands for
independent agency that we associate with freedom.
So Aquinas will need to specify what it is that can properly be said to
come forth from God, as the shape of the pot does from the potter’s hands.
Maimonides’ context evoked a parallel concern: “to explain to you … that
what exists indicates to us of necessity that it does exist in virtue of the
purpose of One who purposed it,”12 yet how can one safeguard the integrity
of created natures while acknowledging the creator’s sovereignty? Aquinas
refines the distinction introduced by Avicenna at the heart of all created
being to identify the effect proper to God’s creative action: the very existence
of things. Avicenna’s distinction of essence from existence was well known
to Maimonides; he in fact invokes it to characterize God as the One whose
“existence is identical with His essence and His true reality”—unlike
everything else where “existence is an accident attaching to what exists.”13
But as his literal adherence to the language of Avicenna suggests,
Maimonides had not yet seen how one might characterize this “accident” as a
constitutive principle of created being.
That was to be Aquinas’s signal achievement, elaborated early on and
used, as we have seen, to characterize the uniqueness of God (in a passage
reminiscent of Maimonides), as well as in his treatment of creation. So for
Aquinas, “everything … is potential when compared to existence,” so much
so that we must acknowledge that “existence is more intimately and
profoundly interior to things than anything else.”14 Indeed, that is how the
creator is present to each created thing “according to the manner in which it
has its existence”15 because “esse (existence) is the proper effect of the first
and most universal cause.”16 Since the fact that something exists is not a
feature of a thing—not an accident, as Avicenna’s unfortunate choice of
words suggested—we need not fear to identify it as an effect proper to
divinity, for there will be no way for us to pick it out as we can find traces of
ordinary causes. The situation is paradoxical, not unlike a Zen koan: that
which is most actual in each thing—what makes it exist—escapes our notice
because it cannot be isolated as a feature of the thing. In that sense, then, we
cannot talk about it, for what we call features of things are precisely those
things we can say about them. On reflection, however, that should not
surprise us, since the fact that something exists is not customarily listed
among its characteristics. It must, then, be a special sort of fact, which is
exactly Aquinas’s point in singling out esse as “the actuality of every form or
nature” that exists.
By recasting Avicenna’s distinction as he has, Aquinas is able to offer a
coherent characterization of the act of creation without pretending to have
described it. That is appropriate, moreover, since the relation of the One who
is source of all to all that originates from it will not be susceptible of
description, since it is not a relation within the world. Existence [esse],
understood as actuality, becomes the vehicle for articulating God’s
transcendence, as well as what links created things with their creator. It
should now be clear how central a role this account of creation plays in the
development of Aquinas’s thought. We have seen how it offered him a
philosophical basis for confidently asserting a transcendent referent for
analogous terms: “whatever is said both of God and creatures is said in virtue
of the order that creatures have to God as their source and cause.”17 Although
such terms will “signify what God is … imperfectly,”18 that is to be
expected, since they are not being used to signify an object in the world but
the source of all. What is remarkable, then, is not that we cannot speak
adequately of divinity, but that we can use our language to speak truthfully of
God at all.19
So Maimonides’ concern that the demands of philosophical discourse
does not undermine the uniqueness and transcendence of God is Aquinas’s as
well; he has simply discovered a way of enriching that discourse to the point
where philosophy can serve our confession of faith in the One while
exploiting hidden resources in our ordinary human language to highlight his
distinctive way of characterizing that divine activity. For his part,
Maimonides was clearly working without a developed notion of analogical
discourse, which led to his celebrated “agnosticism” regarding our
knowledge of God. Against the background of a Muslim controversy
regarding how we might responsibly apply ninety-nine names to the one
God, Maimonides had to insist that nothing could be said accidentally of the
One without compromising the primary confession of the community’s faith:
“the Lord, our God, is One.”
Aquinas develops his own position in explicit opposition to
Maimonides,20 suggesting some disparity in the thought world each
inhabited. For a century or more of preoccupation in the West with the
diverse uses of language in the Scriptures had prepared the ground for the
fruitful ways in which Aquinas would develop Aristotle’s rather cryptic
remarks on “analogy,” whereas the Islamic philosophers with whom
Maimonides (and his friend Joseph) were conversant had been engaged on a
more architectonic enterprise, while the rabbis in Moses’ own tradition had
been content to remind themselves how frequently “the Torah speaks in the
language of men.” Yet a systematic grappling with religious language
demands greater sophistication for the semantics structuring our use of terms
attributing perfections to God.
Aquinas called upon and expanded key distinctions already articulated in
the “speculative grammar” developed during the century preceding him.
Recent studies on analogy in Aquinas have made us attend to the way his
treatment follows the contours of our linguistic capacities. So, by way of
offering a constructive alternative to Maimonides’ radical agnosticism,
Aquinas insists:
Words are used of God and creatures in an analogical way, that is in accordance with a
certain order between them.… In this way some words are used neither univocally nor
purely equivocally of God and creatures, but analogically, for we cannot speak of God at
all except in the language we use of creatures, and so whatever is said both of God and
creatures is said in virtue of the order that creatures have to God as their source and
cause in which all perfections of things pre-exist transcendently.21
NOTES
1. Richard Walzer, Greek into Arabic: Essays in Islamic Philosophy
(Columbia: University of South Carolina Press, 1962).
2. Richard Walzer, Al-Farabi on the Perfect State (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1985).
3. Avicenna, The Metaphysics of Healing, trans. Michael Marmura
(Provo, Utah: Brigham Young University Press, 2005); Robert Wisnovsky,
Avicenna’s Metaphysics in Context (London: Duckworth, 2003).
4. ST I q.3 a.4: “God is God’s own existing.”
5. David Burrell, Knowing the Unknowable God: Ibn Sina, Maimonides,
Aquinas (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1986).
6. ST I q.45 a.3: “creation is in creatures as a relation.”
7. Maimonides, The Guide of the Perplexed, trans. Shlomo Pines
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1963), 2.19.
8. Ibid. 2.21.
9. Ibid. 3.21.
10. ST I q.45 a.5.
11. Guide, 3.21.
12. Guide, 2.19.
13. Guide, 1.57.
14. ST I q.8 a.1.
15. ST I q.8 a.1.
16. ST I q.45 a.5.
17. ST I q.13 a.5.
18. ST I q.13 a.4.
19. ST I q.13 a.12.
20. ST I q.13 a.2.
21. ST I q.13 a.5.
22. Ibid.
23. ST I q.13 a.4.
24. Ibid.
PART II
BEING
JOHN F. WIPPEL
ACCORDING to Aquinas the word “being” (ens) signifies “that which is” or
“that which exists.”1 This complexity within the notion of being implies that
one does not grasp it by the process of abstraction alone—the intellect’s first
operation whereby it understands what something is without affirming or
denying anything of it. While he acknowledges that this intellectual operation
suffices for one to grasp the quidditative aspect of being (“that which”),
Aquinas appeals to the intellect’s second operation (whereby one affirms or
denies by composing or dividing), often referred to as judgment, to account
for one’s grasp of the existential aspect of being and thus to complete one’s
understanding of being as that which is. As he explains, while the intellect’s
first operation is directed to the nature (essence) of a thing, its second
operation is directed to a thing’s existence (esse).2
NOTES
1. See ST I-II q.26 a.4: “being (ens) in the absolute sense is that which has
existence (esse).” Sancti Thomae de Aquino Opera Omnia (Rome: Leon. ed.,
1882), v. 6, p. 190 = Leon. 6.190; Expositio libri Boetii De hebdomadibus [In
BDH], lec. 2: “so we can say that being (ens), or that which is, is insofar as it
participates in the act of existing” (Leon. 50.271:57–59); line 97: “But that
which is, or being.…” (translations of Aquinas throughout are mine).
2. See In BDT, q.5, a.3 (Leon. 50.147:89–105). Also see Super Sent I,
d.19, q.5, a.1, ad 7 (Mandonnet ed., vol. 1, 489); d.38, q.1, a.3, 903. Étienne
Gilson has emphasized Aquinas’s appeal to judgment to account for the
intellect’s grasp of being as existing, especially in his Being and Some
Philosophers (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1952), c.6.
For my interpretation of this and for references to some who reject this
reading of Aquinas, see John Wippel, The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas
Aquinas: From Finite Being to Uncreated Being (Washington, D.C.: Catholic
University of America Press, 2000), 24–30.
3. In BDT, q.5, a.1 (Leon. 50.138:141–55).
4. Ibid., lines 155–60. Also see q.5, a.4 (Leon. 50.154:186–99), and lines
160–61 on the subject of metaphysics as being insofar as it is being. For
reference to this as being in general (ens commune), see In Meta, Prooemium
(Turin and Rome: Marietti, 1950), 2.
5. In BDT, q.5, a.3 (Leon. 50.148:161–69; 149:156–258, 270–74, 276–
79). A correct understanding of Aquinas’s teaching on “séparation” finally
became possible when a correct text of the key passages was finally
published, beginning with a fundamental article by Louis-B. Geiger,
“Abstraction et séparation d’après s. Thomas In De Trinitate q.5, a.3,” Revue
des sciences philosophiques et théologiques 31 (1947): 3–40, followed by an
excellent critical edition by Bruno Decker, (1955, 2d ed., 1959), and finally
the Leonine ed. (1992). On “separation,” see Wippel, Metaphysical Thought
of Thomas Aquinas, 45–51 and 51–62, on the dispute among Thomistic
scholars concerning whether it presupposes prior knowledge of the existence
of some separate substance.
6. Liber de philosophia prima sive scientia divina I–IV, ed. S. Van Riet
(Louvain/Leiden: Peeters/Brill, 1977), I, c.1, 4–6; c.2, 9–13.
7. In Phy I, com. 83, in his Opera omnia (Venice: 1562–74), v. 4, fol.
47rb-vb; In Meta VI, com. 2–3, v. 8, fols. 146rb–147ra. For this in Avicenna,
Averroës, and many medieval thinkers, see Albert Zimmermann, Ontologie
oder Metaphysik? Die Diskussion über den Gegenstand der Metaphysik im
13. und 14. Jahrhundert (Leuven: Peeters, 1998).
8. See In BDT, q.5, a.4 (Leon. 50.153:80–87, 154:157–201). Also see In
Meta, Prooemium, 1–2, on ens commune as the subject. For his exclusion of
God from esse commune (which is coextensive with ens commune), see Div.
nom. V, lec. 2, ed. C. Pera (Turin and Rome: Marietti, 1950), 245, n. 660.
See Zimmermann, Ontologie oder Metaphysik, 216–23.
9. See QDV, q.1, a.1 (Leon. 22.1.5:106–111); In Meta I, lec. 9, 41, n. 138,
and n. 139, where he accuses Parmenides of having viewed being as if it
were univocal, like the nature of a genus.
10. QDV, q.1, a.1 (Leon. 22.1.5:124–61). On all of these, see Jan A.
Aertsen, Medieval Philosophy and the Transcendentals: The Case of Thomas
Aquinas (Leiden, New York, and Cologne: Brill Academic Publishers, 1996).
11. QDV, q.1, a.1 (Leon. 22.1.5:114–23).
12. See In Meta V, lec. 9, 238, n. 890: “Wherefore it is necessary that being
be restricted to diverse genera in accord with diverse modes of predicating,
which modes follow upon diverse modes of existing.” See pp. 238–39, nn.
891–92 for his derivation of the ten predicaments. For a slightly different
derivation, see In Phy III, ed. P. M. Maggiòlo (Turin and Rome: Marietti,
1953), lec. 5, 158–59, nn. 322–23. On these derivations, see Wippel,
Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas, 210–28.
13. For references to substance as existing per se, see In Meta IV, lec. 1,
152, n. 539; In Meta V, lec. 10, 903; QDP, q.9, a.1, ed. M. Pession (Turin
and Rome: Marietti, 1953), 226; QDV q.1, a.1 (Leon. 22.1.5:119–23). For
Aquinas’s rejection of being per se as the definition of substance and defense
of his alternative, see Super Sent IV, d.12, q.1, a.1, ql.1, ad 2 (Moos ed.), v.
4, 499; SCG I, c.25 (Ed. Leonina manualis, Rome, 1934), 27; QDP, q.9, a.1,
ad 4 (194); ST I q.3 a.5, ad 1 (Leon. 4.44). On accidents, see Super Sent IV
(ibid.); Quodl 9, q.3, a.1, ad 2 (Leon. 25.1.99:78–90). For discussion, see
Wippel, Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas, 228–37.
14. On this distinction, see Wippel, Metaphysical Thought of Thomas
Aquinas, 31–35.
15. QDP, q.7, a.2, ad 9, 192; ST I q.3 a.4 (Leon. 4.42).
16. See Super Sent I, d.8, q.5, a.1 (Mandonnet ed.), v. 1, 226. For
discussion and other texts, see Wippel, Metaphysical Thought of Thomas
Aquinas, 170–76.
17. DEE, c.4 (Leon. 43.375:1–376:93, esp. lines 90–93).
18. Ibid., lines 94–103.
19. Leon. 43.376:103–377:126.
20. Ibid., 377:127–53. The proper interpretation of Aquinas’s
argumentation in De ente, c.4, has been much disputed by various scholars.
For the reading offered here, see Wippel, Metaphysical Thought of Thomas
Aquinas, 137–50. For other interpretations, see there nn. 11 (with references
to a series of discussions between Joseph Owens and myself), 13, 14 (esp. the
references to Cornelio Fabro and Scott MacDonald), 15. Also now see David
Twetten, “Really Distinguishing Essence from Existence,” in Peter A.
Kwasniewski, ed., Wisdom’s Apprentice: Thomistic Essays in Honor of
Lawrence Dewan, O.P. (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America
Press, 2007), 40–84.
21. Ed. Leon. man., p. 145, the first three arguments. On these and other
arguments of this type, see Wippel, Metaphysical Thought of Thomas
Aquinas, 151–57.
22. See ibid. 161–70 for texts and discussion.
23. Much credit for the rediscovery of this long neglected doctrine in
Aquinas must be given to Cornelio Fabro, La nozione metafisica di
partecipazione secondo S. Tommaso d’Aquino, 2d rev. ed. (Turin: Società
editrice internazionale, 1950); L.-B. Geiger, La Participation dans la
philosophie de S. Thomas d’Aquin, 2d ed. (Paris: J. Vrin, 1953). Also see
more recently Rudi te Velde, Participation and Substantiality in Thomas
Aquinas (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1995); Wippel, Metaphysical Thought of
Thomas Aquinas, 94–131.
24. Leon. 50.271.70–73.
25. Leon. 50.271:77–85.
26. Ibid., lines 85–102.
27. Leon. 50.272:180–85; 272:204–73:205; 273:249–58.
28. See Quodl 12, q.4, a.1 (Leon. 25.2.404:16–25), on participating by
likeness in the First Act, which is subsisting existence (esse); In BDH, lec. 2
(Leon. 50:273:240–43), on participating in existence in general (esse
commune); Super Sent I, d.29, q.5, a.2 (Mandonnet ed., v. 1, 491), on a
creature’s participating in its own created esse.
CHAPTER 7
JEFFREY E. BROWER
FEW notions are more central to Aquinas’s thought than those of matter and
form. Although he invokes these notions in a number of different contexts,
and puts them to a number of different uses, he always assumes that in their
primary or basic sense they are correlative both with each other and with the
notion of a “hylomorphic compound”—that is, a compound of matter (hyle)
and form (morphe). Thus, matter is an entity that can have form, form is an
entity that can be had by matter, and a hylomorphic compound is an entity
that exists when the potentiality of some matter to have form is actualized.1
What is more, Aquinas assumes that the matter of a hylomorphic compound
explains certain of its general characteristics, whereas its form explains
certain of its more specific characteristics. Thus, the matter of a bronze statue
explains the fact that it is bronze, whereas its form explains the fact that it is
a statue. Again, the matter of a human being explains the fact that it is a
material object, whereas its form explains the specific type of material object
it is (namely, human).
My aim in this chapter is to provide a systematic introduction to
Aquinas’s primary or basic notions of matter and form. To accomplish this
aim, I focus on the two main theoretical contexts in which he deploys them—
namely, his theory of change and his theory of individuation. In both
contexts, as we shall see, Aquinas appeals to matter and form to account for
relations of sameness and difference holding between distinct individuals.
Change in General
A change C occurs if and only if
(i) there is some matter, M, which exists from some time t1 to some
later time t2;
(ii) there exist some distinct forms, F-ness and G-ness;
(iii) M has F-ness at t1 (thereby composing a hylomorphic compound,
which is F) and M has G-ness at t2 (thereby composing a distinct
hylomorphic compound, which is G).
Substantial Change
A substantial change Cs occurs if and only if
(i) there is some (prime) matter, M, which exists from some time t1 to
some later time t2;
(ii) there exist some distinct (substantial) forms, F-ness and G-ness;
(iii) M has F-ness at t1 (thereby composing a substance, which is F)
and M has G-ness at t2 (thereby composing a distinct substance,
which is G);
(iv) M itself does not go from being F to being G at these times.
Accidental Change
An accidental change Ca occurs if and only if
(i) there is some matter (or substance), M, which exists from some
time t1 to some later time t2;
(ii) there exist some distinct (accidental) forms, F-ness and G-ness;
(iii) M has F-ness at t1 (thereby composing an accidental compound,
which is F) and M has G-ness at t2 (thereby composing a distinct
accidental compound, which is G);
(iv*) M itself does go from being F to being G at these times.
If the term “matter” is used in its proper and common sense, it is impossible for there to
be matter in spiritual substances…. But if the terms “matter” and “form” are used for
any two things which are related as potentiality to actuality, then there can be no
objection (unless it is a mere verbal dispute) to saying that spiritual substances have both
matter and form.8
Principle of Principle of
Context
Sameness Difference
Over Time Matter Form
(Difference of
(In Change) (Sameness of Subject)
Characterization)
At a Time Form Matter
(Outside of (Sameness of
(Difference of Subject)
Change) Characterization)
In the remainder of this chapter, I want to take a closer look at the roles
that Aquinas assigns to matter and form outside the context of change, since
these are essentially connected with his theory of individuation.25 Once again
my strategy will be to proceed by way of example.
Let us return, therefore, to Romulus and Remus and consider them at
some time at which they both exist.26 Like all material objects, Aquinas
thinks of these twins as ultimately composed of prime matter and substantial
form. Insofar as they belong to the same kind, they are material objects
sharing a common nature or form; and insofar as they are distinct members
of this kind, they differ with respect to their prime matter.
So far I have been speaking as if relations of sameness and difference
could always be understood in terms of strict identity. This is useful
heuristically because it makes intuitive Aquinas’s suggestion that matter
must be a principle of individuation in some sense. If Romulus and Remus
literally share one and the same substantial form, then they must differ with
respect to their prime matter, since Aquinas thinks this is the only other type
of entity of which they are ultimately composed. Despite the heuristic value
of this way of speaking, we will eventually see that it too involves an
oversimplification.
Although Aquinas thinks that prime matter plays an essential role in
individuation, he is often at pains to emphasize that it not prime matter as
such that plays this role. Nor is it hard to see why. Since Romulus and Remus
are alike not only in their possession of a common substantial form (namely,
humanity) but also in their possession of prime matter, it cannot be prime
matter as such that individuates them.27 On the contrary, it must be that each
possesses his own distinct prime matter—and likewise for any distinct
material objects belonging to the same natural kind. Aquinas himself often
puts the point by saying that the principle of individuation must be
understood as designated (rather than undesignated) matter. And for reasons
I will now try to explain, he identifies designated matter with matter under
determinate dimensions.28
Recall that prime matter is that which explains a material object’s capacity
to “fill its place” or “have extension in three dimensions”—a type of
nonindividual stuff, on my interpretation, which cannot exist apart from some
larger compound or other. Even so, Aquinas thinks, if we want to explain the
precise dimensions of a material object such as Romulus, or the exact size of
the place he fills, we cannot appeal to his prime matter alone. On the
contrary, we must also appeal to certain of his accidents or quantities. To put
the point another way: although Romulus will fill some region or other solely
in virtue of having prime matter, and his distinct prime matter may well put
some restrictions on the size of this region, his precise extension cannot be
determined apart from certain of his accidental or quantitative properties—
what Aquinas calls his “determinate dimensions” (dimensiones determinatae
vel terminatae) or “dimensive quantities” (quantitates dimensivae). And,
obviously, since Romulus himself cannot exist without some dimensions or
other, the same will be true of his prime matter.29
Now if we add to all this that the determinate dimensions of a substance
are the only means by which its prime matter can be picked out or
designated, we can see why Aquinas would say that the matter associated
with a particular substance—that is, its designated matter—is to be
understood in terms of matter under determinate dimensions. For the sake of
clarity, let us illustrate this as follows for the particular case of Romulus (this
time setting matter and form side-by-side, and using a solid line to indicate
their relation to one other and a dotted line to indicate their relation to the
larger compounds of which they are a part):
As this diagram is intended to show, in the particular case of Romulus we
have some distinct prime matter (namely, prime matter1) combining with a
substantial form (namely, humanity) to make Romulus, and then Romulus
himself combining with another form (namely, the determinate dimensions
by which his prime matter can be designated, which we can abbreviate “D1”)
to make what I have called (for lack of a better term) “D1-Romulus”—that is,
an accidental compound consisting of Romulus having a particular extension.
In light of the foregoing, we can see why Aquinas describes prime matter
as the primary principle of individuation, even though he reserves a role for a
certain type of accident to play here as well. For prime matter, he thinks, is
what ultimately explains there being distinct material objects belonging to the
same kind. Still, prime matter cannot exist without some determinate
dimensions or other, and hence the latter are required for prime matter to play
its role, even they do not themselves account for the distinction in question.
QUANTITY, INDIVIDUALITY, AND THE
INDIVIDUATION OF FORMS
If individuation, for Aquinas, involved nothing more than explaining the
distinction of material objects, we could perhaps leave our discussion here.
But, in fact, this is not the case. To see why, consider Romulus and Remus
again and note that they are not merely distinct entities, but distinct
individuals. The qualification is important because, as we have seen, there
are entities (e.g., Romulus’s and Remus’s respective prime matter) which are
distinct but nonindividual. But, then, how are we to account for the
individuality (as opposed to distinction) of Romulus and Remus? Obviously,
we cannot account for it in terms of their prime matter, since as we have just
noted, it is nonindividual. But neither can we account for it in terms of their
substantial form, since this is something they share in common. But if we
cannot account for Romulus’s and Remus’s individuality either in terms of
their (nonindividual) prime matter or in terms of their (common) substantial
form, how can we account for it?
This question highlights a further aspect of Aquinas’s views about
individuation in which determinate dimensions have a more direct role to
play. What accounts for the distinction of material objects, Aquinas thinks, is
their prime matter, which can only exist under some determinate dimensions
or other. But what accounts for the individuality of material objects is the
particular determinate dimensions under which their prime matter exists. For
unlike prime matter, Aquinas says, such dimensions are not only individual,
but individual in and of themselves.30
Now as the discussion of determinate dimensions makes clear, at least
some of the forms of material objects are individual. But what about their
other forms? As it turns out, Aquinas thinks that all the forms of all material
objects, whether substantial or accidental, are individual.31 Unlike
determinate dimensions, however, he thinks these other forms must be
individuated. That is to say, instead of being individual in and of themselves,
they must get their individuality from their relation to something else. And
here, as in the case of material objects themselves, we can distinguish two
aspects of their individuation. Thus, compare the substantial form of
Romulus with that of Remus. These are, Aquinas thinks, distinct individuals
of the same type, humanity. What accounts for their distinction is the distinct
prime matter with which they are associated, whereas what accounts for their
individuality is the determinate dimensions with which they are associated.
And likewise for each of Romulus’s and Remus’s other forms, as well as
those of material objects generally.
We can now see why I said earlier that, despite the fact that Romulus and
Remus “share a common form,” this cannot be understood in terms of strict
identity. Romulus’s humanity is a distinct individual from Remus’s
humanity. Even so, we can also see why Aquinas wants to insist that
Romulus and Remus nonetheless share something in common. For although
Romulus’s humanity is distinct from Remus’s, it is not intrinsically distinct
from it (or for that matter, from anyone else’s humanity). Nor is it
intrinsically individual or unique to Romulus. To make the point vivid,
suppose we had a metaphysical microscope that allowed us to see all and
only what is intrinsic to a given entity; and suppose that we used this device
to inspect Romulus’s and Remus’s humanities.32 We would not be able to tell
the difference between them. In each case it would be clear that we have a
form or property of humanity before us. But if we wanted to see whose it
was, or its distinction from others, we would have to “zoom out” in such a
way as to include its associated prime matter and determinate dimensions. As
this makes clear, when Aquinas speaks of forms as “common” to many, he is
calling attention not to their numerical sameness but rather to their intrinsic
sameness.33
From what we’ve seen so far, it might appear that although all the forms
of material objects are individual, only certain of them are individuated by
other things—namely, all those besides determinate dimensions. For
determinate dimensions, as we’ve seen, have a kind of individuation in
themselves, which just appears to mean that their individuality, and hence
their distinction both among themselves and from other things, is intrinsic to
them. Even so, Aquinas insists, the forms of material objects are always
individuated by their subjects: their substantial forms are individuated by
their prime matter, and their accidents are individuated by their substances.
Nor does he allow any exceptions for determinate dimensions.34
We can, I think, make sense of Aquinas’s views here, as well as fill out
his account of individuation generally, by noting that there is a further
question we can ask about distinct individuals belonging to the same kind—
namely, what accounts for their identity?35 For even though determinate
dimensions are intrinsically individual, and hence intrinsically distinct from
other things, they cannot exist apart from the particular substances in which
they inhere. That is to say, despite their intrinsic individuality and
distinctness, there is still a sense in which they must be individuated, since
their identity is bound up with other things—namely, the substances of which
they are the accidents.
We can illustrate this further type of individuation, as well as contrast it
with the other types we have already seen, if we return one last time to our
example of Romulus and focus on his relationship to his prime matter and
determinate dimensions:
As this diagram makes clear, Romulus depends for his distinction (from
other material objects) on his prime matter, whereas he depends for his
individuality on his determinate dimensions. But Romulus also depends for
his identity on his prime matter, which is just to say he cannot exist apart
from it.36 In the same way, Romulus’s determinate dimensions depend on
him: since they cannot exist apart from Romulus in particular, their identity
is bound up with him.37 Indeed, given the dependence of Romulus on his
prime matter, there is a sense in which the identity of his determinate
dimensions is ultimately bound up with his prime matter as well.
In short, we can see that there are really three different aspects of
Aquinas’s views about individuation, corresponding to three different
questions we can ask about individuals belonging to the same kind:
In order to answer the first and third questions, Aquinas thinks, we must
appeal to prime matter. But in order to answer the second question, we must
appeal to one of the things that prime matter cannot exist without: namely,
determinate dimensions. In light of Aquinas’s answers to these questions, we
can see why in certain contexts he speaks of matter as the primary principle
of individuation and dimensive quantity as a secondary principle.38
CONCLUSION
This completes our examination of the two main contexts in which Aquinas
develops his notions of matter and form—his theory of change and his theory
of individuation. In each case, as we have seen, Aquinas invokes matter and
form to account for certain relations of sameness and difference holding
between distinct individuals. In each case, moreover, he is able to do so
because he thinks of matter and form as distinct entities that both serve as
constituents of larger wholes (namely, hylomorphic compounds) and explain
certain of their general and specific characteristics.
There is much more that could be said about Aquinas’s understanding of
matter and form, especially in other contexts such as theology or logic. But
we have already seen enough, I think, to appreciate the essential aspects of
these notions in their primary or basic sense, and hence to have a basis for
understanding the further uses to which Aquinas puts them.39
NOTES
1. I use the term “entity” throughout to refer to beings in the broadest
possible sense—that is, to anything that exists or has being in any sense.
2. Unless otherwise indicated, the discussion below is based primarily on
Aquinas’s discussion in the first two chapters of DPN, though in most cases
parallel passages can be found in In Phy, his other main discussion of
change. All translations are mine.
3. Strictly speaking, these remarks apply only to Aquinas’s account of
intrinsic changes in things. Ultimately, I think Aquinas wants to explain all
change in terms of these, but in what follows I shall ignore complications
arising from extrinsic (or mere Cambridge) changes.
4. Cf., e.g., ST I q.45 a.2 ad 2: “It is part of the nature of change (de
ratione mutationis) that it involves the same thing (idem) being different now
from the way it was before…. By contrast, in the case of creation, where the
entire substance of things is produced [ex nihilo], it cannot be said that we
have the same thing being different now from the way it was before—except
according to a certain way of thinking.”
5. When Aquinas wants to speak of change in the broadest possible sense
(motus, mutatio), he always does so in terms of generation (generatio) and
corruption (corruptio). Following Aristotle, however, he also uses these latter
notions in a narrower sense to apply only to substantial change, and thus to
contrast with accidental change (more on the distinction between substantial
and accidental change below). But even here, he sees a close connection
between the different senses of the terms. As he says in DPN, c.1: “In an
unqualified sense, generation and corruption are found only in the category
of substance. But in the other categories they are found in a qualified sense.”
For Aquinas’s discussion of how these different senses of generation and
corruption connect with Aristotle’s texts, cf. In Phy, bk.3, lec.2 and In Meta,
bk.1, lec.12.
6. Cf. In DA, bk.2, c.1, n.5, for an especially clear example of this
identification outside of DPN.
7. Cf. Robert Pasnau, Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2002), 131–40.
8. QDSC, a.1.
9. Cf. the references in note 5.
10. Given the controversy surrounding Aquinas’s embryology, it should
perhaps be emphasized that this pretense is adopted solely for the sake of
simplicity and is not intended to reflect a stance on any substantive
metaphysical or interpretive issues. For introduction to the relevant issues
and controversy, cf. the exchange between Robert Pasnau and John Haldane
and Patrick Lee in Philosophy 78 (2003): 255–78, 521–31, 532–40.
11. For the sake of precision, let us call any individual that is not a property
a “particular.” It is often taken for granted nowadays that all particulars,
whether bare or otherwise, are substances. But during the medieval period,
the precise relationship between particularity and substantiality was a
disputed question.
12. In what follows, I shall use the term “humanity” to refer to the
substantial form of a human being, both because it serves to highlight the
parallel between our human and statue examples and because Aquinas says
that this is the form that locates human beings within their natural kind (cf.
DEE, c.4). It should be noted, however, that Aquinas himself often reserves
the term “humanity” (humanitas) for the natural kind or essence itself (cf.
DEE, cc.2–3), which as we will see below includes not only substantial form
but also prime matter.
13. In the case of humanity, Aquinas puts the point this way: “When a
human comes to be, we can truly say not only that it was previously not
human, but also that it previously was not (full stop)” (In Phy, bk.1, lec.12,
n.10).
14. Cf., e.g., DEE, c.5.
15. In addition to DPN, cc.1–2, cf. ST I q.7 a.2 ad 3; QDV, q.8, a.6; and
SCG I, c.17. Cf. also Super Sent 4, d.12, q.1, a.1, sol. 3, ad 3, where Aquinas
insists that part of what it is to be an individual is to be a being in actuality.
16. Cf., e.g., Ned Markosian, “Simples, Stuff, and Simple People,” Monist
87 (2004): 405–28.
17. This is not to say that prime matter or stuff cannot be characterized at
all. Obviously it can be—it is, after all, prime matter or stuff, nonindividual,
existent, identical-to-itself, etc. The point is just that not all characterization
is to be explained in terms of forms or properties. On the contrary, Aquinas
thinks that in many cases the fact that an entity can be characterized in a
certain way is to be explained by the entity itself (rather than by some distinct
property the entity possesses). Cf., e.g., the discussion of divine simplicity in
ST I q.3.
18. For a taxonomy of different possible interpretations of Aquinas’s
account, as well as references to the literature, see John D. Kronen, Sandra
Mennsen, and Thomas D. Sullivan, “The Problem of the Continuant:
Aquinas and Suarez on Prime Matter and Substantial Generation,” The
Review of Metaphysics 53 (2000): 863–85. (If I understand these authors
correctly, my interpretation is version of the position they label “Gamma.”)
Cf. also the reference to Pasnau in note 7 for an example of an antirealist
interpretation of Aquinas’s prime matter.
19. Cf. In Meta, bk.7, lec.2.
20. Cf. esp. Quodl 3, q.1, a.1. For further passages and discussion of the
historical context, cf. John Wippel, The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas
Aquinas: From Finite Being to Uncreated Being (Washington, D.C.: Catholic
University of America Press, 2000), esp. 312–27.
21. Indeed, as the prime-matter-as-stuff interpretation helps us to see,
Aquinas’s distinction between substance and accidental compound is really
distinction between two different types of particulars. Substances are primary
or basic particulars (insofar as they do not include within themselves any
other particulars playing the role of matter), whereas accidental compounds
are secondary or derived particulars (insofar as they do include within
themselves particulars playing the role of matter).
22. Cf. ST I q.3 a.1 obj.1; q.52, a.1–2; and In BDT, q.4, a.3.
23. Cf., e.g., In Meta, bk.7, lec.16, where he mentions simple living things
(such as certain worms) that can be cut in half to form two new living things.
24. The problem of “explaining sameness of characterization” is, of course,
just the traditional problem of universals. Aquinas’s appeal to form,
therefore, is part of his solution to this problem. More on this below.
25. Indeed, it is because of matter’s role here that he speaks of it as “the
principle of individuation” (principium individuationis) and it is because of
form’s role here that he speaks of it as belonging to a thing’s “essence”
(essentia) or “common nature” (natura communis). Cf., e.g., ST I q.3 a.2;
q.75 a.4; q.76 a.2.
26. For reasons that will emerge, Aquinas thinks of prime matter (or stuff)
as the primary principle of individuation. In what follows, therefore, I will
focus on the example involving the twin human beings rather than that
involving the multiple spheres.
27. As this consideration makes clear, the nature or essence of human
beings includes not only substantial form but also prime matter. It is because
Aquinas is willing to extend the term “form” to the whole essence of a thing
that he famously distinguishes “the form of the whole” (forma totius), which
is the essence, from the “the form of the part” (forma partis), which is the
substantial form. Cf. DEE, c.2 and In Meta, bk.7, lec.9.
28. Aquinas’s views about individuation seem to have changed over time.
In his earliest writings, he identifies the principle of individuation with matter
under determinate dimensions (cf. Super Sent 1, d.23, q.1, a.1 and DEE, c.2).
Later, he suggests that it should be identified with matter under indeterminate
(rather than determinate) dimensions (cf. Super Sent 4, d.12, q.1, a.1–2 and
In BDT, q.4, a.2). By the end of his career, however, he appears to have
returned once again to the determinate-dimensions view (cf. esp. QDA, q.9
and In DA 2, c.12). There is considerable controversy over whether these
different ways of talking correspond to different stages of development.
Since I cannot enter into such controversies here, in what follows I shall
simply focus on what I take to be Aquinas’s most plausible views. For a
helpful introduction to the relevant texts and controversies, cf. Wippel,
Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas, 351–75.
29. It is important to emphasize that the type of dependence involved here
is a sort of generic existential dependence. For despite the fact that both
Romulus and his prime matter depend for their existence on some
determinate dimensions or other, there are no particular dimensions on which
each either depends for its existence. We might put the point by saying that,
although each depends for its existence on determinate dimensions, neither
depends for its “identity” on them (since for any such dimensions, they can
exist without them).
30. In accordance with this aspect of individuation Aquinas says:
“dimensive quantity has in itself a kind of individuation” (ST III q.77 a.2).
Cf. also In BDT, q.4, a.3; Quodl 7, q.4, a.3; and SCG 4, c.65.
31. Cf., e.g., DEE, c.3. With respect to the problem of universals, therefore,
Aquinas is what would nowadays be called a “trope theorist.”
32. My talk here of inspecting forms “under a metaphysical microscope” is
intended to be the contemporary analogue of Aquinas’s talk of the “absolute
consideration” of forms. Cf. DEE, c.3.
33. For further discussion, along with relevant texts, cf. Jeffrey E. Brower
and Susan Brower-Toland, “Aquinas on Mental Representation: Concepts
and Intentionality,” Philosophical Review 117 (2008): 193–243, esp. section
2.1.
34. Cf. In BDT, q.4, a.2; ST I q.29 a.1 and II-II q.24 a.5 ad 1.
35. Cf. note 29 above.
36. Actually, it would be better to speak of the dependence here in terms of
origins. Strictly speaking, Aquinas thinks, Romulus depends on his prime
matter only for his origin or initial existence (since the prime matter of which
Romulus is composed of can and does change over time). Cf. In BDT, q.4,
a.2.
37. Here again it would be better to speak of Romulus’s determinate
dimensions as dependent on Romulus only for their origin or initial existence
(since Aquinas thinks that, on analogy with the Eucharist, God can preserve
Romulus’s determinate dimensions without Romulus, once they have come
into existence). Cf. Quodl 7, q.4, a.3.
38. Cf. Super Sent 4, d.12, q.1, a.1, sol.3, ad 3.
39. An earlier version of this text was presented at the 2008 Cornell
Summer Colloquium in Medieval Philosophy. I am grateful to the audience
on that occasion, as well as to Michael Bergmann, Susan Brower-Toland,
Timothy Pawl, Michael Rea, Michael Rota, Thomas Sullivan, and the editors
of this volume, for helpful discussion, comments, and criticism. I am also
grateful to the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation for a grant, which
supported the initial research for this text.
CHAPTER 8
CAUSATION
MICHAEL ROTA
THE sense of Aquinas’s term “causa” is broader than the English “cause.”
Following Aristotle, Aquinas distinguished four types of causes: “Now the
genus of ‘cause’ is fourfold, namely, final, formal, efficient, and material.
…”1 As a general rule, a material cause is that which something is made up
of (its matter), and a formal cause of a thing is a form of that thing. This
chapter will focus on efficient causation, with some discussion of final
causation as well.
Apart from his brief, early work On the Principles of Nature and some
relatively short sections of his commentaries on Aristotle’s Physics and
Metaphysics, Aquinas wrote nothing that could be considered a systematic
treatise on causation. His understanding of causation must therefore be
gleaned from comments scattered throughout his works. When those
scattered comments are brought together and analyzed, we find a complex
and multifaceted theory. A good place to begin is with a paradigm instance of
ordinary efficient causation: the production of a statue.
On Aquinas’s Aristotelian account of change, any change involves (i)
something that persists throughout the change (the subject of the change), (ii)
something that accounts for the fact that the subject is actually configured or
characterized as it in fact is at the end of the change (the form), and (iii) the
lack of that form at the beginning of the change (the privation). Any subject
of a change can be referred to as “matter,” for Aquinas, so we can also refer
to the subject of change as the matter of the change.
When, for instance, an irregularly shaped lump of bronze is formed into a
statue, the bronze is the matter of the change, the distinctive shape of the
finished statue is the form of the change, and the lack of that shape at the
beginning is the privation.2 Now, while distinguishing these three factors can
help us specify the nature of this change, they cannot by themselves explain
why the change has occurred. As experience tells us, bronze does not make
itself into a statue. It is in this context, the explanation of change, that
Aquinas introduces the notion of an efficient cause in On the Principles of
Nature:
But these [three factors] are not sufficient for generation.3 For what is in potency is not
able to reduce itself to actuality; just as bronze, which is potentially a statue, does not
make itself [into] a statue. But there needs to be something operating, which draws forth
the form of a statue from potency to actuality.… Therefore, it must be that, besides
matter and form, there is some principle which acts, and this is said to be the maker
[efficiens], or the mover, or the agent, or that from which the beginning of motion
comes.4
Upon reading this passage, one would be inclined to think that, for Aquinas,
the efficient cause of the statue in our example is the sculptor, end of story.
Aquinas would indeed say that the sculptor is an efficient cause of the
statue,5 but he also holds that the art of the sculptor is an efficient cause of
the statue.6 As it turns out, the notion of an efficient cause is used
analogically, in Aquinas, and the term “efficient cause” has a broad, manifold
application. To get a full picture of Aquinas’s views here, we need to turn to
his account of transitive action, which is, roughly, action on something. This
will involve a discussion of the following concepts: agent, patient, power,
inclination (or tendency), end, action, and passion.
POWERS
Given the view that the agent produces a change in the patient, we can next
ask how the agent produces that change. While a sculptor has many
properties or features, only some of them are called into play when the
sculptor makes a statue. The sculptor’s power to move his hands is clearly
salient here in a way that his ability to sing middle C is not. He performs the
action of sculpting through the use of his power to move his hands (among
other powers), but not through the use of his power to sing. Aquinas
generalizes this way of thinking, and holds that any action of any agent
occurs through the use of some particular power: “In any action there are two
things to consider, namely the suppositum acting, and the power by which it
acts, just as fire heats by heat.”13 Why posit the existence of powers? Perhaps
the idea is just this: if a thing performs some sort of action, then it is
reasonable, at least in many cases,14 to think that there must be some real,
positive feature of the thing that enables it to perform that sort of action. If a
species of bird appears to use the earth’s magnetic field to navigate, for
example, then it is reasonable to think that members of that species have
some sort of faculty for detecting magnetic fields. An active power is a
feature of some thing that we posit to account for the fact that that thing is
able to perform some action.15 Aquinas thinks of active powers as real
(though not necessarily physical) components of a thing that enable it to act
in certain ways. A passive power is something we posit to account for the
fact that a thing is capable of being acted upon in a certain way, that is, to
account for the fact that a thing is capable of undergoing a certain sort of
passion.16
As is indicated by the last quotation above, Aquinas thinks of heat as a
power. Other examples are the powers of nutrition and growth (in all living
things), the powers of sensation and movement (in animals), and the powers
of intellect and will (in human beings). Aquinas also thinks of productive arts
like the art of building and the art of medicine as powers.17 Aquinas holds
that an art—the art of building, say—is a feature of a person’s mind.18 To say
that a person possesses the art of building is to say that that person has a
certain cognitive feature. And because the possession of that feature enables
him or her to perform a certain sort of action (building), that feature counts as
a power.
TRANSMUTATION
To return to our example: the sculptor (the agent), on account of his
inclinations and through the use of various powers, brings about a change in
the bronze (the patient), so as to give it a new accidental form (its distinctive
shape). This is an example of what Aquinas calls “transmutation.” In any
case of transmutation, an agent,31 on account of its powers and inclinations,
produces a change in some already existing patient. This change might
terminate in the patient’s possession of a new accidental form, or it might
terminate in the existence of a new substance.
CAUSAL RELATA
Because contemporary philosophers almost always use the word “causation”
to refer to a relation,32 it is natural to ask what the terms of the relation of
efficient causation are, according to Aquinas. In our example, what exactly is
the efficient cause and what is the effect? As briefly indicated above,
Aquinas uses the concepts of efficient cause and effect quite broadly,
applying both notions to items from many different ontological categories.
Aquinas applies the notion of an efficient cause to substances,33 to powers,34
to acts of will (and thus to inclinations),35 and to processes or activities.36
When Aquinas says that “passion is the effect of the agent in the patient,”37
he is applying the notion of an effect to a change, which is an event.
(Likewise when he speaks of an action as something that is “produced” by
the agent.38) And because the change that an agent produces terminates in a
new accident (in cases of accidental change) or a new substance (in cases of
substantial change), Aquinas sometimes speaks of accidents39 and
substances40 as the effects of transmuting causes. Further, in cases of
transmutation, for a new accident to be produced is just for some substance
(or substances) to be given a new accidental form, and for a new substance to
be produced is just for some prime matter to be given a new substantial form.
Accordingly, Aquinas can speak of forms (whether accidental or substantial)
as the effects of transmuting causes.41 Thus, rather than thinking that, for
Aquinas, the relation of efficient causation in our example is a relation
existing between the sculptor and the bronze, we should keep in mind
Aquinas’s fuller story: the sculptor brings about a change in the bronze, via
his powers and inclinations (and various tools too, no doubt), and by so doing
produces a statue and a new accidental form.
NOTES
1. ST II-II q.27 a.3. For the Latin texts of Aquinas I have used S. Thomae
de Aquino, Opera omnia, ed. Enrique Alarcon,
<http://www.corpusthomisticum.org/iopera.xhtml>. Translations are my
own.
2. A word about prime matter: Aquinas recognizes several different uses
of the term “matter” (materia). (See DPN, chs. 1–2, and ST I-II q.55 a.4.) For
my purposes here it is only necessary to distinguish two such uses,
corresponding to the two types of change, accidental and substantial. In an
accidental change, the matter of the change is a substance (or an aggregate of
substances) and the form acquired in the course of the change is an accident.
When Socrates loses his tan and becomes pale, Socrates (a substance)
acquires paleness (an accident). The example of a lump of bronze being
formed into a statue is also an example of an accidental change, since bronze
is a substance in its own right that persists through the change, receiving in
the process only a new shape (which is an accident).
In case of substantial change, by contrast, the matter of the change is not
an independently existing substance (or an aggregate of such substances), but
is rather what Aquinas calls materia prima (“prime matter” or “primary
matter”). Matter such as bronze is a subject of form (e.g., this bronze is the
subject of a particular shape), but bronze is itself something that has a
matter–form structure. Aquinas holds that any material substance is
composed of two metaphysical parts or constituents: substantial form and
prime matter. As a first approximation: the substantial form of a material
substance S is that constituent of S that accounts for the fact that S is the kind
of substance it is, and not a substance of some other kind made out of the
same prime matter, while the prime matter of S is that constituent of S that
persists, and begins to be the matter of some new substance, when S passes
away. Prime matter is matter that is not itself composed of form and matter.
According to Aquinas, prime matter can be separated from form in
thought, but it can never be so separated in reality, because prime matter can
never exist on its own, without having some form or another. For more on
prime matter, see DPN 2; In Phy I.13.118; In Meta VII.2.1285–1296, and
VIII.1.1689.
3. Here by “generation” Aquinas intends to include both generation
simpliciter (substantial change) and generation secundum quid (accidental
change). See DPN 1.4, and In Meta I.12.199.
4. DPN 3.15.
5. In Meta V.2.773.
6. In Phy II.5.182.
7. ST I q.82 a.4.
8. ST II-II q.58 a.2.
9. A sentence from the entry on “act” in Webster’s New Collegiate
Dictionary (Springfield, Mass.: Merriam, 1956).
10. For more on Aquinas’s theory of substance, see Brown 2005, ch. 3, and
the chapter on Being in this volume.
11. See In Phy III.5.
12. ST I-II q.26 a.2.
13. ST I q.36 a.3 ad 1. Here, the term “suppositum” refers to the substance
that acts.
14. I say “at least in many cases” because there may be cases where a thing
performs an action of a certain sort, such that it would not necessarily be
reasonable to infer the existence of a single positive feature that enables the
thing to perform actions of that sort. Human beings occasionally hiccup;
should we infer that humans possess a power of hiccupping? Not necessarily,
because a hiccup might just be the accidental result of several distinct powers
functioning (or misfunctioning) together. Be that as it may, what is crucial to
Aquinas’s view is only the claim that, at least in many cases, it is reasonable
to infer the existence of powers.
15. See ST I q.25 a.1; QDP 7.9c; and SCG IV. 77.
16. On the ontology of passive powers, see In Meta V.14.963.
17. In Meta IX.3.1796 and In Meta V.14.955.
18. See In Meta VII.6.1407.
19. By “act of will” I mean to translate Aquinas’s “actus voluntatis,” which
is a generic term that covers at least six different acts of which the will is the
subject: enjoyment (fruitio), intention (intentio), volition (voluntas), choice
(electio), consent (consensus), and use (usus). See ST I-II, q.11–16.
20. ST I-II q.1 a.2; DPN 3.16; SCG III.2; In Phy II.13–14.
21. DPN 3.16 and QDV, q.22, a.1, ad 2.
22. See DPN 3.16; SCG III.16 [3]; and In Phy II.10.240.
23. ST I-II q.1 a.2.
24. Fire always heats, but a stone does not always fall (e.g., if it is held up
by something). Does this mean that a stone sometimes has an inclination to
fall, and sometimes lacks such an inclination? No. Aquinas’s theory seems to
be this: A stone that is located anywhere but at the center of the Earth always
has an inclination to fall. (Indeed, maybe it would be best to characterize the
stone’s inclination as an inclination to move to and rest in its proper place,
which is the center of the Earth.) Now, a stone falls only in certain
circumstances not because it sometimes has the inclination to fall and
sometimes does not have that inclination, but rather because its always-
present inclination to fall is sometimes impeded, and sometimes not. If
something is in the way of the stone and the center of the Earth, then the
stone’s inclination to fall may not be able to issue forth in actual movement.
25. ST I q.87 a.4: “An act of the will is nothing other than a certain
inclination following upon an understood form, just as a natural appetite is an
inclination following upon a natural form.” See also ST I-II q.6 a.4; ST I-II
q.15 a.1; QDV, q.22, a.12c; and QDC, q.1c.
26. Aquinas customarily speaks as if power and inclination are distinct
(see, e.g., ST I q.106 a.2 and ST I q.80 a.1 ad 3). It is easy enough to see why
we should think there is such a distinction in the case of voluntary
inclinations, but in cases of natural inclination it is less clear. Why think that
the substance fire has two ontologically distinct features, one of which is its
active power to heat and one of which is its inclination to heat? Some of
Aquinas’s comments (e.g. at ST II-II q.27 a.4) suggest that he thinks of an
inclination as the actualization of an active power. If so, then there is always
at least a conceptual distinction between a thing’s powers and its inclinations.
Perhaps Aquinas could hold, however, that in cases where an active power is
always actualized (as with fire, which is always inclined to heat anything in
its proximity), there exists just one actual feature, which grounds the truth of
both the claims that “this agent has power P” and “this agent has inclination
I.”
27. In Phy III.5.318.
28. In Phy III.5.
29. In Phy III.5.318.
30. The reader might be puzzled by the fact that, for Aquinas, “the action
of teaching” refers to a change in the learner, and not to a change or process
in the teacher. To motivate Aquinas’s use of language here, imagine that a
teacher is writing at a blackboard and verbally explaining some argument.
Now suppose that there is in fact no one else present in the room. There is a
sense in which we would deny that the teacher is engaged in the action of
teaching. The action of teaching (in this sense) actually occurs only when
some learner is undergoing a certain type of cognitive change. This is the
sense of “action of teaching” that Aquinas is using when he holds that the
action of teaching and the passion of learning are one motion taking place in
the learner.
31. Or, a number of agents working together.
32. The word may also be used to refer to an action, as in “The production
of one thing by another is one type of causation.”
33. In Meta V.3.780.
34. ST I q.82 a.4; In Meta VII.6; DPN 5.26.
35. QDV, q.28, a.8, ad 7: “Consent is the efficient cause of marriage.”
36. See In Meta V.2.771, where Aquinas asserts that the (ancient medical)
processes of reducing and purging can be called causes from which motion
comes, i.e., efficient causes.
37. ST I-II q.26 a.2.
38. SCG III.70 [5].
39. See ST I-II q.75 a.4 (evil dispositions and habits, which are accidents,
are efficiently caused by acts of sin).
40. e.g., at In Meta V.2.765 Aquinas takes up Aristotle’s characterization
of the father as “the cause of the child,” in which case the child (a substance)
is being thought of as an effect.
41. QDM, q.5, a.5, ad 16: “the form itself is an effect of the agent.” See
also De aeternitate mundi.
42. Diu. nom. 4.5: “For these three things seem to belong to the notion of
an efficient cause: to give being, to move, and to conserve.” On creation, see
ST I q.45. On conservation, see ST I q.104, a.1–2.
43. The sense of “action” at issue here is that of transitive action, as
opposed to immanent action. A transitive action is, roughly, an action on
something. This is to be contrasted with an action in the sense of the
actualization of a potency of the agent, which actualization remains within
the agent. When Feynman understands the fundamental theorem of calculus,
for instance, Feynman is the subject of an action of understanding, which is
an action remaining within him. Aquinas discusses the distinction between
actions passing over into exterior things and actions remaining within the
agent in several texts, including SCG II.1; ST I q.18 a.3 ad 1; ST I q.23 a.2 ad
1; ST I q.54 a.1 ad 3; ST I q.85 a.2; and In Meta IX.8.1862–1865. This
distinction has been referred to by later thinkers as the distinction between (i)
transitive (or transient or transeunt) action and (ii) immanent action.
44. In Meta V.2.775. See also QDV, q.28, a.8c.
45. Thus, Aquinas uses agens causa (acting cause) and efficiens causa
(efficient cause) as synonyms (compare ST II-II q.27 a.3 and SCG III.10 [5]).
46. Super Sent 1.29.1.1c. See also Super Sent 3.11.1.1, ad 5.
47. In Meta V.1.751.
48. QDV, q.22, a.2c. The meaning of the second clause in this sentence is
that a final cause has the influence it has by being the object of some
inclination.
49. In this way, the statement that an efficient cause influences by acting is
not like the statement that one gets a promotion by doing good work, but is
like the statement that a cyclist exercises by cycling. It is not as if the cyclist
does one thing (cycle), which in turn allows him to do a second thing
(exercise). Rather, his cycling is his exercising.
50. See ST I-II q.85 a.5; QDM, q.1, a.3c; In Meta V.3.789.
51. SCG III.69 [28].
52. See, e.g., Cartwright 1989, Ellis 2001, Ellis 2002, and Molnar 2003. I
am grateful to Jeffrey Brower, Brian Davies, Colleen McCluskey, Kent
Staley, and Eleonore Stump for their helpful comments on what I have
written here.
CHAPTER 9
TIMOTHY PAWL
INTRODUCTION
The Five Ways are five proofs or demonstrations that Aquinas offers near the
beginning of his Summa theologiae to establish the existence of God.1
Although the Five Ways compose only a miniscule portion of Aquinas’s
Summa—less than 775 words, or nearly one word for every fourth page in a
standard edition of the work—one would be hard-pressed to find another part
of Aquinas’s corpus that has been commented on as much as the Five Ways.
Yet despite their minute size and the gigantic secondary literature on them
throughout the centuries, whether Aquinas succeeds—and even what it is that
Aquinas is attempting to do or how he intends to do it—is still debated.
Some scholars think that Aquinas’s Five Ways are meant to demonstrate
the existence of the particularly Christian God. But if one considers that
Aquinas follows the article containing the Five Ways with an article
questioning whether God has a body2 and then later with articles questioning
whether God is perfect, good, infinite, immutable, eternal, and even whether
there is just one God, one sees that Aquinas does not take himself to have
already shown that the God of the Christian creeds exists.3 Others treat
Aquinas’s Five Ways as attempts to demonstrate the existence of something
omniscient, omnipotent, and wholly good.4 The text does not bear this
interpretation. In fact, Aquinas explicitly argues that God has each of these
attributes at different points later in the Treatise on God (in the case of God’s
power, over twenty questions later).5 Aquinas is attempting to demonstrate
something much weaker here as a first step in arguing for a being with the
traditional divine attributes; namely, that there is something or other that
moves things but is unmoved, and that there is something or other that causes
but is uncaused, and so on.6
One also finds authors treating the Five Ways as if they are the summit of
Aquinas’s careful thought about demonstrations for the existence of God and
intended by Aquinas as the last word when it comes to what can be said
when arguing that God exists.7 But this was not his intent.8 He had
previously written something considerably longer and more detailed on the
argument from motion in the Summa contra Gentiles, and he had already
discussed the other ways, or arguments very similar to them, elsewhere.9 Had
his intent been to produce carefully crafted, full-fledged arguments with the
aim of convincing agnostics or atheists of the existence of God, he would
have used the arguments he had already worked out in careful detail. Since
the Five Ways are not his most in-depth, carefully crafted arguments for
God’s existence, finding them wanting, if one does find them wanting, does
not entail that Aquinas never successfully argued for the existence of God.
To judge on that topic, one must look to the SCG and elsewhere, as careful
commentators, both sympathetic to Aquinas and not, have done.10 The
Summa was written as a theological textbook for students just beginning their
theological training. In fact, there is a case to be made that it was written for
the formation of priests who were not going on into academia, “young and
run-of-the-mill Dominicans.”11 If one of our contemporaries had produced a
detailed and careful defense of a particular position, we would not judge the
merit of her arguments for that position based on what she says about it in an
introductory text she has also authored. Rather, we go to the more detailed
work. Our policy should be the same when it comes to Aquinas.
Nevertheless, the focus of this chapter is exclusively the Five Ways,
which are without a doubt Aquinas’s most well-known arguments for the
existence of God.12 Here I will analyze the Five Ways and discuss what I
take to be the most important points raised in the secondary literature.13
Aquinas calls his First Way the most manifest of the Five Ways.14 He
argues:15
(1) There exist some things that are moved.
(2) For anything that is moved, it is moved by something not identical
with it.
(3) A series of movers does not regress infinitely.
(4) Therefore there must be a first unmoved mover.
(5) This first unmoved mover all people understand to be God.16
There are multiple debates concerning the exact meaning of “motion” in the
First Way. One debate is over whether Aquinas uses “is moved” (movetur) in
a passive or intransitive sense. Does he mean in (2), for instance, that
anything that is in motion (intransitive) is moved by another, or that anything
that is moved by something (passive) is moved by another?17 Following
Scott MacDonald and John Wippel, I read the verb in the passive sense.18
Another question concerns the scope of motion discussed in the First Way.
Aquinas is not discussing solely metaphysical motion because he is talking
about changes that are “plain to the senses,” such as wood heating up (or of
the movement of heavenly bodies, which is his example in SCG I.13 where
he discusses this argument).19 Such changes are prime exemplars of physical
change.20 Considering physical motion, Aquinas is not discussing only local
motion, since one of his own examples of motion in this text is that of fire
heating up wood, and that sort of motion is not local motion.21 It seems most
reasonable then to think that he means the three accidental types of
Aristotelian change: local motion, qualitative change, and quantitative
change.
Allowing for the scope of “motion” to extend beyond local motion
provides an easy response to an objection that the First Way has faced. Some
argue that the First Way is unsound due to its dependence on an obsolete
Aristotelian physics. For instance, I. M. Bochenski writes, “Since ‘movetur’
is to be understood as ‘is in spatial motion’, the claims made in the proof rest
substantially on Aristotelian physics. But since such views are no longer
defensible, the prima via is not valid.”22 If the scope of “motion” in the First
Way extends beyond local motion, this objection, if apt, would only show
that the scope of “motion” would need to be reined in so as not to include
local motion; it would not show that the First Way fails.23
Concerning justification for the premises of the First Way, Aquinas takes
(1) to be “certain, and plain to the senses.” Some things are moved locally,
qualitatively, or quantitatively: people move about, tan and sunburn, bulk up
and thin out.
Aquinas offers arguments for premises (2) and (3). He argues as follows
for (2):
One thing to note about this argument is that it does not address the epistemic
possibility—that is, possibility for all we know—of something going from
being potentially F to being actually F without the aid of any mover
whatsoever.26
Premise (2.4) needs justification. If the appropriate state of actuality were
simply being actually F, then it would be easy to see why one would think
that something could not be both potentially F and actually in an appropriate
state of actuality to make something else actually F. But the appropriate state
of actuality need not be being F, since God brings things to states of being
without sharing those states of being—God makes material things without
being material, or hot things without being hot.27 Here commentators point to
being actually F or virtually F as the appropriate state of actuality, where
something is virtually F when that thing is not F, but is such that it can cause
things to be F.28 But now one wonders why it is that something cannot be
virtually F and potentially F, as (2.4) implies. Perhaps Aquinas would
maintain that the only way something can be virtually F is if it cannot be
potentially F. But now we need an argument for that claim.29
Aquinas’s argument for (3) is as follows:
(3.1) Secondary movers move things in virtue of their being moved by a
first mover.
(3.2) Thus, if there is no first mover, then there are no secondary movers.
(3.3) If it is the case that a series of movers regresses infinitely, then there
is no first mover.
(3.4) But there are secondary movers.
(3) Thus, it is not the case that a series of movers regresses infinitely.30
Premises (3.2) and (3.4) seem to prove, by themselves, the conclusion of the
First Way, namely, that there is a first mover. They also seem to prove the
existence of an unmoved mover, since, if the mover were to be moved, it
would not be first. It seems as if Aquinas could simply give (3.2) and (3.4) as
an argument for a first mover rather than giving the whole First Way.
To elucidate (3.1), Aquinas provides an example of a stick causing
something to move in virtue of the stick being moved by a hand. This leads
one to think that Aquinas is discussing something more than just a mere
series of movers. Instead it seems that the series must be ordered such that
the members all move at the same time and the later members in the series
move in virtue of the motion of the earlier members. I will take up the issue
of such ordered series in the discussion of the Second Way.
One thing to note about the main deduction from (1)–(3) to (4) is that,
while Aquinas intends the argument to conclude that there is something
wholly unmoved, it seems that at most the argument can conclude that there
must be some mover at the beginning of any particular series of movers.31 It
could be that each series has a first mover, but each of those movers is an
intermediate member of some other series of movers. If that is possible, then
one can affirm (1)–(3) and deny (4), that there is anything wholly unmoved
—unmoved in all ways whatsoever.32
Peter Geach provides an interpretation of the First Way (and all Five
Ways) in which, rather than focusing his argument on individual causal
chains, Aquinas is “treating the whole world as a great big object” and then
asking what accounts for the motion of this great big object.33 If Geach were
right, pointing out that the first mover of any particular series might also be
an intermediate mover of another series, as I have done in the previous
paragraph, is irrelevant to the First Way, since Aquinas would be trying to
show that all motion, taken together, needs a first, unmoved mover, and not
that one can trace a chain of a certain type of motion back to a first, unmoved
mover. Thus, if this lumping together interpretation is correct, one could not
affirm (1)–(3) and deny (4) in the way I have presented in the preceding
paragraph. This strategy is not without costs, however. One major problem
with Geach’s interpretation of the First Way is that the text does not seem to
bear it out. There is no evidence in the First Way that Aquinas meant to lump
together the entire world as, for instance, the thing that is moved in (2), or as
a secondary mover, as the sub proof for (3) discusses.
(8.1) In any case of ordered efficient causes, the first is the cause of the
intermediate cause or causes, and the intermediate is the cause of the
ultimate effect.
(8.2) If a cause is removed, then its effects are removed.
(8.3) Thus, if there were not a first cause with regard to efficient causes,
there would be no intermediate causes or ultimate effects.
(8.4) But if efficient causes were to proceed infinitely, then there would
not be a first cause with respect to efficient causes.
(8.5) Thus, there would not be any intermediate causes or ultimate effects.
(8.6) But there are intermediate causes and ultimate effects.
(8) Therefore, it is not possible for an ordered series of efficient causes to
continue infinitely.
One worry about this argument is that premise (8.2) refers to “removing”
(remota; removetur) a cause. It seems as if the removing in mind is the
taking away of what is already there. So if it were the case that you removed
what was there, counterfactually plucking away something upstream in the
causal ordering, then you would not have what followed from it. But (8.3)
and (8.4) make no mention of removing. It may well be that if one were to
remove the first cause in an order of efficient causes, then the effects would
not follow, but it is less clear that if there just is not a first cause at all, as
(8.3) has it, not even one to be removed, then there cannot be any
intermediate causes or ultimate effects. The series of causes could be infinite,
and such a series would have no first cause. Of course, Aquinas denies the
possibility of an infinitely regressing ordered series—that is precisely what
he is arguing for here: (8). But he cannot use (8) to support (8.2), a premise
in the argument for (8).
As with the First Way, the inference from (6)–(9) to (10) does not seem to
yield a particularly impressive being. It is difficult to find among sensible
things an order of generative causes or an order of conserving causes. The
only pertinent sort of efficient causation remaining is that of the moving
cause. But then the Second Way seems to collapse into the First Way, though
perhaps as an argument that starts from movers moving things rather than
things being moved.
(11) Some things are such that they are able to be or not to be.
(12) It is not possible that everything be such that it is able to be or not to
be.
(13) Therefore, there must exist something that is necessary.
(14) For anything that is necessary, it either has its necessity from
something else or it does not.
(15) It is impossible for the objects that have their necessity from
something else to proceed infinitely.
(16) Therefore, one must posit something that has its necessity from itself,
which is the cause of the necessity of other things.
(17) This everyone calls God.44
Aquinas provides justification in the text for premises (11), (12), and (15).
In defense of (11) he points out that some things are able to be generated
or corrupted. This is indicative of his understanding of possible being and
necessary being in this argument. Necessary things, at least in this argument,
are things that cannot cease to exist by corruption (e.g., decomposition).
Non-necessary things are those that can cease to be through corruption.
Likewise, necessary beings cannot be generated by composition, while non-
necessary beings can be generated through composition.45 On this
understanding of necessity, human souls, since they are incorruptible, are
necessary beings.46 But they are not necessary in the sense that they cannot
not be, as the term “necessary” is often used today and as Aquinas himself
sometimes used the term.47
The proof for premise (12) is where the majority of the secondary
literature on the Third Way focuses. In defense of (12), Aquinas argues:
(18) There are things that are more or less good, more or less true, more or
less noble, and so on.
(19) But things are called more or less F insofar as they are closer or
further from that which is maximally F.
(20) Thus, there is something maximally good, maximally true, and
maximally noble.
(21) That which is maximally true is maximally being (or most fully
being).
(22) Therefore, there is something which is maximally being (or most fully
being).
(23) Anything that is maximally F is the cause of all things that are F.
(24) Thus, there is something that is the cause of all beings, their goodness,
and each and every of their perfections.
(25) This we call God.
The Fifth Way, and final way, is from the governance of things:64
(26) There are some things that lack cognition yet act for ends.
(27) Anything that lacks cognition does not act for an end unless it is
directed by something that is cognizant and intelligent.65
(28) Thus, there is something intelligent by which all natural things are
ordered to their ends.
(29) This thing we call God.66
(26.1) Some things that lack cognition always or frequently act in the same
way to bring about that which is best.67
(26.2) If some things that lack cognition always or frequently act in the
same way to bring about that which is best, then they act for an end,
and this not by chance but by design.
(26) Thus, there are some things that lack cognition yet act for ends.
The example for (27) is that of an archer shooting an arrow. Just as the archer
directs the flight of an arrow, so the designer directs the actions of the
noncognizant beings that act for an end.
There is one main problem facing both (27) and (26.2). Darwinism
provides an account of how it could be that something acts for an end, and
does so always or for the most part, but does not act for an end as a result of
the design of an intelligent agent. Darwinism grows (evolves?) another horn
onto the head of the old dilemma: design or chance. It could be that
nonintelligent things act for ends as a result of selective evolution (though
that is not to say that there is something, evolution, which selects for the sake
of evolving things, as if it were acting for an end).
This may just push the argument back, though. Rather than focusing on
things that we see around us, like tomato plants, a proponent of this argument
could focus his or her argument on things that did not evolve yet still act
always or for the most part for an end. For instance, electrons act always or
for the most part to attract positively charged particles. This action, however,
was not selected for by means of an evolutionary process. So the objection
from Darwinism, while narrowing the scope of the examples Aquinas could
give, does not vitiate the argument.
But (27) and (26.2) still stand in need of a positive defense. Even if
electrons do not attract positively charged particles because of an
evolutionary process, why could it not be that they do so without design and
not by chance? It seems epistemically possible that it just be a brute fact that
electrons attract positively charged particles. They do so by nature, and that
nature was not designed by a designer. If that were the case, then the Fifth
Way would be unsound.
CONCLUSION
In this paper I have presented the Five Ways and discussed some of the most
common criticisms of them in the secondary literature. I have provided
citations in the notes for readers looking for additional reading on these
issues.
NOTES
I thank Gary Atkison, Brian Davies, Matthews Grant, Robert Gressis,
Mathew Lu, Rachel Lu, Faith Glavey Pawl, Michael Rota, Jon Stoltz,
Eleonore Stump, and Chris Toner for helpful comments on this chapter.
1. ST I q.2 a.3.
2. ST I q.3 a.1.
3. Aquinas writes that believers ought not try to prove the tenets of
Christian belief that are beyond the scope of reason, an example of which is
that God is triune, since such proofs will fall short and lead unbelievers to
scoff at believers (see SCG I 9, para 2). Aquinas writes this shortly before
going on to provide a detailed argument that is quite similar to the First Way.
It would be absurd for Aquinas to claim that one ought not try to prove the
existence of a triune God—the God of the Christian creeds—in one stroke
and go on, in the next, to attempt such a proof.
4. See Elliott Sober, Core Questions in Philosophy (New York:
Macmillan Library Reference, 1991), Lectures 4 and 5, pp. 36–56. To see
similar treatment at a popular and polemical level, see Richard Dawkins, The
God Delusion (New York: Bantam Press, 2006), 77–79. John Wilcox thinks
something similar. Wilcox seems to think that each of Aquinas’s Five Ways
is an attempt to prove the existence of a simple, infinite entity. See John
Wilcox, “The Five Ways and the Oneness of God,” The Thomist 62 (1998):
245–68.
5. Aquinas argues that God is supremely and essentially good in ST I q.6,
that God is omniscient in ST I q.14, and that God is omnipotent in ST I q.25.
6. Bochenski writes, for instance, “he is using the word ‘deus’ in a very
general and vague sense; it designates Pagan gods as well as the one God of
the great religions and of philosophers. Hence ‘deus’ ought to be interpreted
as a general term rather than a description” (Joseph M. Bochenski, “The Five
Ways,” in Adolfo García de la Sienra, ed., The Rationality of Theism
[Atlanta, Ga.: Rodopi, 2000], 61–92; 67). See also Herman Reith, The
Metaphysics of St. Thomas Aquinas (Milwaukee, Wis.: Bruce, 1958), 177–
78; Timothy McDermott, Summa Theologiae, vol. 2, Existence and Nature of
God:1a. 2–11 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), Appendix 4:
The Meaning of the Word “God”; David Twetten, “Clearing a ‘Way’ for
Aquinas: How the Proof from Motion Concludes to God,” Proceedings of the
American Catholic Philosophical Association 70 (1997): 259–78, 264–67;
Richard Cartwright, “The Second Way,” Medieval Philosophy and Theology
5 (1996): 189–204; 190–91 for a discussion of Aquinas’s intended
conclusion to the Second Way; Brian Davies, “Aquinas’s Third Way,” New
Blackfriars 82 (2001): 450–66; 463 for a discussion of Aquinas’s
demonstrative aim in the Third Way; John Wippel, The Metaphysical
Thought of Thomas Aquinas (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of
America Press, 2000), 461.
7. Again, see Dawkins, God Delusion, 77–79 and Sober, Core Questions,
36–56.
8. See Fergus Kerr, “Theology in Philosophy: Revisiting the Five Ways,”
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 50 (2001): 115–30; 128 and
Bochenski, “The Five Ways,” 68.
9. For an excellent discussion of Aquinas’s arguments for God’s
existence, see Jules Baisnee, “St. Thomas Aquinas’s Proofs of the Existence
of God Presented in Their Chronological Order,” in John K. Ryan, ed.,
Philosophical Studies in Honor of the Very Reverend Ignatius Smith, O.P.
(Westminster, Md.: The Newman Press, 1952), 29–64.
10. See, for instance, Anthony Kenny, The Five Ways: Saint Thomas
Aquinas’ Proofs of God’s Existence (London: Routledge & K. Paul, 1969);
Norman Kretzmann, The Metaphysics of Theism: Aquinas’s Natural
Theology in Summa contra Gentiles I (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997), ch. 2;
Wippel, Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas, Part III.
11. See Leonard Boyle, “The Setting of the Summa Theologiae,” in Brian
Davies, ed., Aquinas’s Summa Theologiae: Critical Essays (Lanham, Md.:
Rowan & Littlefield Publishers, 2006), 1–25; the quotation is from page 12.
12. There are many general points about the Five Ways that deserve
attention but would push this chapter well beyond its size constraints. So, for
instance, questions often asked about why five ways, why these ways, and
why this ordering of the ways, are left aside. A reader interested in these
questions should consult Bochenski, “The Five Ways,” 67–68; Leo Elders,
The Philosophical Theology of St. Thomas Aquinas (Leiden: E. J. Brill,
1990), 86–89; Kenny, The Five Ways, 36–39; Reith, Metaphysics of St.
Thomas Aquinas, 176–78; William Young, “From Describing to Naming
God: Correlating the Five Ways with Aquinas’ Doctrine of the Trinity,” New
Blackfriars 85 (2004): 527–41; John Zeis, “The Epistemic Passage of the
Five Ways,” Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical
Association 68 (1994): 73–84.
13. Considering secondary literature on the whole of the Five Ways, any
serious student of the arguments should look to Kenny, The Five Ways and
Wippel, Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas. Two other useful
discussions of the whole of the Five Ways are: Elders, Philosophical
Theology of St. Thomas Aquinas, and C. F. J. Martin, Thomas Aquinas: God
and Explanations (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1997), the latter
being not only helpful but also quite humorous. For an in-depth analysis of
the logic of the Five Ways, one could do no better than Bochenski, “The Five
Ways.” For a thorough list of parallel passages and some discussion, see
Baisnee, “St. Thomas Aquinas’s Proofs.”
14. All translations are my own. I have been aided in my translations by
consulting Alfred Freddoso’s unpublished translation of the Summa,
available at <http://www.nd.edu/~afreddos/summa-translation/TOC.htm>.
15. Baisnee, “St. Thomas Aquinas’s Proofs,” 62–64, provides the
following parallel passages to the First Way, noting that it is the second most
common argument for the existence of God found in Aquinas’s corpus: SCG
I, 13; CT, c.3; In Phy VII, l.2; In Phy VIII, l.1–3, 7–13, 21–23; In Meta XII,
l.5–10. Baisnee also cites Super Johan Prologue, though I do not find the
argument from motion in that text.
16. For a discussion of the logic of the First Way, see Jan Salamucha, “The
Proof ‘Ex Motu’ for the Existence of God: Logical Analysis of St. Thomas’
Arguments,” New Scholasticism 32 (1958): 334–72, as well as Bochenski,
“The Five Ways.”
17. Some thinkers, like Kenny, accuse Aquinas of moving illicitly from the
intransitive use of “move” to the transitive usage. See Kenny, The Five Ways,
8–9; 18–19; 24, for the charge, and for a response to the charge, see Scott
MacDonald, “Aquinas’s Parasitic Cosmological Argument,” Medieval
Philosophy and Theology 1 (1991): 119–55, 121–24, especially footnote 6.
See also Wippel, Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas, 414–15.
18. See MacDonald, “Aquinas’s Parasitic Cosmological Argument,” 121–
24, and Wippel, Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas, 414–15. One
should note here that a common objection against the passive reading of
movetur is misguided. The common objection is that if Aquinas meant
movetur in the passive sense, then his claim that whatever is moved is moved
by something is trivially true. However, this is not Aquinas’s claim in the
First Way. He does not claim that whatever is moved is moved by something,
he claims that whatever is moved is moved by something else. The exclusion
of self-motion removes the triviality from Aquinas’s claim, as MacDonald
and Wippel both note.
19. Kenny raises this point as well, Kenny, The Five Ways, 9–11. For a
defense of a metaphysical interpretation of the argument and discussion of
the existential and physical readings of the First Way, see Twetten, “Clearing
a ‘Way’ for Aquinas,” 260–64; 267–71, and John F. X. Knasas, “Ad Mentem
Thomae: Does Natural Philosophy Prove God?” Proceedings of the
American Catholic Philosophical Association 61 (1987): 209–19.
20. See Wippel, Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas, 446–47. It
seems reasonable to hold, along with Wippel, that while Aquinas’s examples
clearly show that he has physical motion in mind in the argument, the
principles he appeals to and arguments he provides for those principles
would justify an extension to more than just mere physical motion or change.
21. Contra Bochenski, “The Five Ways,” 74.
22. Ibid. See also Kenny, The Five Ways, 15–17; 28–31.
23. To see a defense of the compatibility of Aristotelian physics with
Newtonian mechanics, see William Wallace, “Newtonian Antinomies
Against the ‘Prima Via’.” Thomist: A Speculative Quarterly Review 19
(1956): 151–92. This reining in is also suggested by MacDonald, “Aquinas’s
Parasitic Cosmological Argument,” 136–38.
24. The language of being “in an appropriate state of” actuality is not in the
ST. Rather, there it merely says that the mover must be in actuality, then
gives an example of fire, which is actually hot, bringing wood from being
potentially hot to being actually hot. But being in actuality alone is not
enough to bring a being from potentially F to being actually F. The mover
must be in an appropriate state of actuality to do such a thing; hence the
addition to the premise.
25. Aquinas provides two additional proofs for (2) in the discussion of
arguments from motion in the SCG I, 13. For helpful discussions of these
arguments, see Kenny, The Five Ways, 11–23; Etienne Gilson, The Christian
Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre
Dame Press, 1994), 60–61, and Wippel, Metaphysical Thought of Thomas
Aquinas, 415–21. Macdonald, “Aquinas’s Parasitic Cosmological
Argument,” 129–30, formalizes this argument.
26. MacDonald, “Aquinas’s Parasitic Cosmological Argument,” 130–33,
points out that Aquinas does not address this possibility and suggests that he
tacitly assumes a modest principle of sufficient reason.
27. Aquinas calls God an analogical cause. See ST I q.13 a.5 ad 1; SCG I,
33; QDV I, q.4, a.6, resp; QDV II, q.11, a.3, ad 4. For more on God and
analogical causation, see Timothy McDermott, Summa Theologiae, vol. 3,
Knowing and Naming God:1a. 12–13 (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2006), Appendix 2: Causes.
28. Sometimes one finds being virtually F referred to as being “eminently”
F. This sort of causation is sometimes referred to as “equivocal causation.”
29. To see discussions of what it is to be virtually F, see MacDonald,
“Aquinas’s Parasitic Cosmological Argument,” 133–35, and Linwood Urban,
“Understanding St. Thomas’s Fourth Way,” History of Philosophy Quarterly
1:3 (1984): 281–95; esp. 285–87.
30. As with (2), Aquinas provides two additional proofs for (3) in the SCG
I, 13. Again, see Kenny, The Five Ways, 23–27; Gilson, Christian
Philosophy, 61–63; and Wippel, Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas,
421–25.
31. It might be, as Kenny says, that there is an unmoved mover with
respect to qualitative change, and another with respect to local motion. In
fact, it could be that the first qualitative changer heats up the first local
mover, and the first local mover moves the qualitative changer around. In
that case, there is no unqualifiedly unmoved mover, but each series of
movers has a mover that is not moved in that series. See Kenny, The Five
Ways, 23.
32. Cf. Kenny, The Five Ways, 33, who provides a poignant quotation from
Suarez to the same effect; MacDonald, “Aquinas’s Parasitic Cosmological
Argument,” 148–49.
33. G. E. M. Anscombe, and Peter Geach, Three Philosophers (Oxford:
Basil Blackwell, 1961), 112. This interpretation is well known in the
discussion of the Five Ways.
34. For a helpful discussion of Aquinas on efficient causation, see Michael
Rota’s contribution to this volume. See also Rosemary Lauer, “The Notion of
Efficient Cause in the Secunda Via,” The Thomist 38 (1974): 754–67.
35. Baisnee, “St. Thomas Aquinas’s Proofs,” 62–64, provides only one
parallel passage to the Second Way: SCG I, 13.
36. I have inserted the “an ordered series of” into this premise, though the
original text does not include the restriction. I include it because, as the first
step in the forthcoming proof for (8) makes clear, as does (6), Aquinas is
discussing an ordered series of efficient causes.
37. For a discussion of the logical form of the Second Way, see Bochenski,
“The Five Ways,” 75–77, and Cartwright, “The Second Way,” 92–94. Here
and in the following three ways I number the conclusions differently, since
the “this” in each conclusion points to the thing named in the proceeding step
of the argument in question. For instance, the “this” in the Second Way refers
to the first efficient cause and not the first mover of the First Way. Also, it is
an open question whether the first mover must be the first efficient cause, the
cause of necessity in things, the maximally good thing, and the orderer of the
universe.
38. As Aquinas says in this oft-quoted passage ST I q.46 a.2 obj. 7 and ad
7. Also see the parallel passage in the SCG II, ch. 38, para. 13, and
McQueen’s discussion of that passage, Donald McQueen, “What is Aquinas’
Second Way?” History of Philosophy Quarterly 11:1 (1994): 23–35; 28–29.
39. For helpful discussions of Aquinas on ordered series, see Cartwright,
“The Second Way,” 196–200; Elders, Philosophical Theology of St. Thomas
Aquinas, 93; and Wippel, Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas, 461.
For a seminal work on God and simultaneity, see Eleonore Stump and
Norman Kretzmann, “Eternity,” Journal of Philosophy 78 (1981): 429–58.
For a recent discussion of God and simultaneity, see Eleonore Stump,
Aquinas (London and New York: Routledge, 2003), ch. 4, “God’s Eternity.”
The reader may substitute “perform their causal work at no temporal distance
from one another” for “perform their causal work simultaneously” if she
finds atemporal simultaneity problematic.
40. Compare this claim with the thought of Gilson, Owens, and Rowe, who
think that the Second Way concludes to a bestower of existence. See Gilson,
Christian Philosophy, 67; Joseph Owens, “Aquinas and the Five Ways,” The
Monist 58 (1974): 16–35, reprinted in St. Thomas Aquinas on the Existence
of God: Collected Papers of Joseph Owens, ed. John Catan (Albany: State
University of New York Press, 1980), 132–42, 135, and William Rowe, The
Philosophy of Religion: An Introduction (Belmont, Calif.: Wadsworth, 1993),
17.
41. Such a series would require A to stand in the conserving relation to B,
and B to conserve C in virtue of the causal power of A. Compare this with
Cartwright, who claims that the Second Way concludes to a conserver of
existence. See Cartwright, “The Second Way,” 202. Conservation seems to
have only two relata for each series: God and the thing being conserved. But
an ordered series, as understood by Aquinas (and Cartwright) requires at least
three relata. See also Lauer, “The Notion of Efficient Cause.”
42. ST I q.44 a.1; ST I q.10 a.4. Cf. Kenny, The Five Ways, 40.
43. Baisnee, “St. Thomas Aquinas’s Proofs,” 62–64, provides the
following parallel passages to the Third Way: SCG I, 15–16 and SCG II, 15.
Baisnee also cites Diu. nom. V, l.1 as a parallel text, but I do not find the
argument from possibility and necessity in that text.
44. For a discussion of the logic of the Third Way, see Bochenski, “The
Five Ways,” 77–81; Mauricio Beuchot, “Saint Thomas’ Third Way:
Possibility and Necessity, Essence and Existence” in Adolfo García de la
Sienra, ed., The Rationality of Theism (Atlanta, Ga.: Rodopi, 2000), 93–108;
Martin De Nys, “If Everything Can Not-Be There Would Be Nothing:
Another Look at the Third Way,” The Review of Metaphysics 56 (2002): 99–
122; 101.
45. One should note that non-necessary things, at least for Aquinas, can
begin existing without being generated and cease existing without being
corrupted, if God creates them ex nihilo or ceases to uphold them in
existence.
46. ST I q.75 a.6.
47. Aquinas did use the term “necessary” in this way as well. And, in fact,
he used the term “possible,” in some cases, such that anything that is
necessary is also possible. See, for instance, SCG 3b, ch. 86. For discussions
of Aquinas’s different understandings of “necessity,” see: Patterson Brown,
“St. Thomas’ Doctrine of Necessary Being,” in Anthony Kenny, ed.,
Aquinas: A Collection of Critical Essays (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of
Notre Dame Press, 1976), 157–74; S. Knuuttila, “The ‘Statistical’
Interpretation of Modality in Averroes and Thomas Aquinas,” Ajatus 37
(1978): 79–98; S. Knuuttila, Modalities in Medieval Philosophy (New York:
Routledge, 1993); J. J. MacIntosh, “Aquinas on Necessity,” American
Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 72 (1998): 371–404; Timothy Pawl, “A
Thomistic Account of Truthmakers for Modal Truths” (Ph.D. thesis, Saint
Louis University, 2008), ch. 4.
48. Cf. Michael Augros, “Aquinas’s Tertia Via,” Angelicum 83 (2006):
767–92; 773.
49. For further discussion, including attempts to answer this question, see
Augros, “Aquinas’s Tertia Via,” 775–79; Beuchot, “Saint Thomas’ Third
Way,” 101–102; Davies, “Aquinas’s Third Way,” 456–58.
50. Others have called this dubious step a fallacy of composition, since it
appears that Aquinas is arguing that since each thing does not exist at some
time, the whole composed of all those things also must not exist at some
time. See De Nys, “If Everything Can Not-Be,” for a helpful discussion of
the considerations here. For one influential presentation of the charge, see
Kenny, The Five Ways, 56.
51. See David Conway, “Possibility and Infinite Time: A Logical Paradox
in St. Thomas’ Third Way,” International Philosophical Quarterly 14:2
(1974): 201–209.
52. The reader should note that De Nys is not making the (false) claim that
if each part of a proposition has its truth-value contingently, then the whole
proposition does as well. Consider any contingently true proposition, P. Both
P and ~P have their truth-values contingently. Their disjunction, however,
does not have its truth-value contingently. See De Nys, “If Everything Can
Not-Be,” 114–18.
53. See De Nys, “If Everything Can Not-Be,” Section III. Section II of the
same article provides a helpful, critical discussion of the responses of Gilson,
Edwards, and Owens to the quantifier shift charge. See also Beuchot, “Saint
Thomas’ Third Way,” 102–4; Davies, “Aquinas’s Third Way,” 458, and
notes 11 and 20; Elders, Philosophical Theology of St. Thomas Aquinas, 104;
and Anscombe and Geach, Three Philosophers, 115.
54. Rowe understands this step as an appeal to a principle of sufficient
reason, not a causal principle. Nevertheless, he claims that the principle
required for this step of the argument might be false. See Rowe, The
Philosophy of Religion, 26–28.
55. See G. E. M. Anscombe, “‘Whatever Has a Beginning of Existence
Must Have a Cause’: Hume’s Argument Exposed,” Analysis 34:5 (1974):
145–51 and the excellent debate on this issue between Quentin Smith and
Thomas Sullivan: Quentin Smith, “The Uncaused Beginning of the
Universe,” Philosophy of Science 55:1 (1988): 39–57; Thomas D. Sullivan,
“Coming to Be Without a Cause,” Philosophy 65 (1990): 261–70; Quentin
Smith, “Can Everything Come to Be Without a Cause?” Dialogue: Canadian
Philosophical Review 33:2 (1994): 313–23; Thomas D. Sullivan, “On the
Alleged Causeless Beginning of the Universe: A Reply to Quentin Smith,”
Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review 33:2 (1994): 325–36.
56. Baisnee, “St. Thomas Aquinas’s Proofs,” 62–64, provides the
following parallel passages to the Fourth Way: Super Sent D.III Divisio
primae partis textus; Super Sent D.I, q.1, a.1–2; SCG I, 13; QDP, q.3, a.5.
57. See Urban, “Understanding St. Thomas’s Fourth Way,” for a helpful
discussion of causation in the Fourth Way. Urban is the commentator who
believes that all three types of causation mentioned are at play in the Fourth
Way.
58. See Urban, “Understanding St. Thomas’s Fourth Way,” 283–84, where
he points to DPN IV 27 and other texts.
59. This is an example of Urban, “Understanding St. Thomas’s Fourth
Way,” 292. Aquinas considered evil a privation and not a thing.
60. The example of a smelliest thing is from Dawkins, God Delusion, 79.
Some commentators, for instance, Wippel, go further and restrict the
argument to transcendental perfections. Wippel writes, “I shall restrict the
argument to transcendental perfections such as goodness and truth”
(Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas, 472). See also Elders,
Philosophical Theology of St. Thomas Aquinas, 111.
61. One might think that the convertibility of being and goodness allows
Aquinas to claim that being hot is a perfection after all. But then limiting the
scope of (19) to perfections would not be useful in removing difficult
examples from the range of (19), since the convertibility move would also be
applicable to being aromatic, for instance. At least one commentator claims
that Aquinas did not intend being hot as an instance of (19). Instead, the
heating claim “is only a comparison and not an instance” (Elders,
Philosophical Theology of St. Thomas Aquinas, 111). But, if that were true,
and it might be, it surely is a poor example to offer for (19).
62. Wippel, Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas, 472. For a
discussion of different ways of understanding the beginning moves of the
argument, (18) to (20), especially (19), see Joseph Bobik, “Aquinas’s Fourth
Way and the Approximating Relation,” Thomist 51 (1987): 17–36.
63. See Wippel’s helpful two part article: John Wippel, “Truth in Thomas
Aquinas,” Review of Metaphysics 43:2 (1989): 295–326; John Wippel,
“Truth in Thomas Aquinas,” Review of Metaphysics 43:3 (1990): 543–67.
64. Baisnee, “St. Thomas Aquinas’s Proofs,” 62–64, provides the
following parallel passages to the Fifth Way, noting that it is the most
common argument for the existence of God found in Aquinas’s corpus:
Super Sent, d.I, q.1, a.1; QDV, q.5, a.2; SCG I, 13; SCG I, 44; QDP, q.3, a.6;
In Meta XII, l.12; Super Johan, Prologue; Super Symbolum Apostolorum, a.1.
Baisnee also lists SCG II, 43 as a parallel text, but I do not find the argument
from the governance of things in that text.
65. Elders, Philosophical Theology of St. Thomas Aquinas, 123, discusses a
potential justification for this premise.
66. For a discussion of the logic of the Fifth Way, see Bochenski, “The
Five Ways,” 84–85.
67. For a discussion of this premise, see Elders, Philosophical Theology of
St. Thomas Aquinas, 121–22.
PART III
GOD’S SIMPLICITY
ELEONORE STUMP
INTRODUCTION
The doctrine of divine simplicity is perhaps the most difficult and
controversial piece of medieval philosophical theology but also one of the
most important.1 It derives from the conviction that God is a being whose
existence is an absolutely perfect being, self-explanatory, completely actual.2
Aquinas was among the most influential expositors and defenders of this
doctrine, and the doctrine is central to his philosophy and theology. It is not
possible to do justice to this doctrine in short space; here I will only sketch its
basic outlines.3
The doctrine of simplicity, as Aquinas understands it, can be summarized
in three claims. The first distinguishes God from material objects:4
(1) It is impossible that God have any spatial or temporal parts that could
be distinguished from one another as here rather than there or as now
rather than then.
The second claims that the standard distinction between an entity’s essential
and intrinsic accidental properties cannot apply to God:5
And the third rules out the possibility of components of any kind in the
essence that is the divine nature. Even when it has been recognized that all
God’s intrinsic properties must be essential to him, it must be acknowledged
as well that
For this reason, God is his own essence or nature.6 For all things other than
God, there is a difference between what they are and that they are, between
their essence and their existence; but on the doctrine of simplicity the essence
that is God is not different from God’s existence. Therefore, unlike all other
entities, God is his own being.
There is a large literature attempting to explain and evaluate these claims,
and it is not possible in this brief essay to explore the controversies at issue in
this literature. Here I will just outline the heart of the doctrine by focusing on
Aquinas’s connection between God’s simplicity and the quid est or essence
of God.
When we know with regard to something that it is, we still need to ask about its mode of
being (quomodo sit), in order to know with regard to it what it is (quid sit). But because
we are not able to know with regard to God what he is, but [rather] what he is not, we
cannot consider with regard to God what the mode of being is but rather what the mode
of being is not.… it can be shown with regard to God what the mode of being is not by
removing from him those things not appropriate to him, such as composition and motion
and other things of this sort.
This passage and others like it have sometimes been cited as evidence for an
interpretation of Aquinas as committed to the via negativa in a radical way.
So, for example, in presenting Aquinas’s position on human knowledge of
God, David Burrell says,
That God’s nature, otherwise utterly unknown, must be affirmed simply to be, gives a
warrant of sorts for taking to-be as an act.8
Claims such as this can give the impression that, for Aquinas, because of
God’s simplicity, it is not possible for human beings to have any positive
knowledge of God. On this interpretation of Aquinas’s views, Aquinas
maintains that because God is simple, human beings can know what God is
not, but they cannot know anything of what God is.10
But caution is warranted here. It is true that Aquinas explains divine
simplicity in terms of what God is not—not a body, not composed of matter
and form, and so on. On the other hand, however, in the course of showing
what God is not, Aquinas relies heavily on positive claims about God. So, for
example, he argues that God is not a body on the basis of these claims among
others: God is the first mover; God is pure actuality; God is the first being;
God is the most noble of beings. In arguing that God is not composed of
matter and form, Aquinas in fact makes a huge, substantial, positive
metaphysical claim about the nature of God. He says,
a form which is not able to be received in matter but is subsistent by itself (per se
subsistens) is individuated in virtue of the fact that it cannot be received in something
else. And God is a form of this sort.11
the understanding of a negation is always based on some affirmation. And this is clear
from the fact that every negation is proved by an affirmation. For this reason, unless the
human intellect knew something affirmatively about God, it would be unable to deny
anything of God.
For all these reasons, it is a mistake to read the prologue to ST I q.3 as
implying a radical agnosticism with regard to knowledge of God.
The problem in interpreting Aquinas’s remarks in the prologue correctly
has to do with the expression “quid est” in the claim that we do not know of
God what he is (quid est).12 The expression quid est is a technical term of
medieval logic. For example, Peter of Spain, the author of a standard
scholastic logic text, gives the traditional medieval formula for a genus as
“that which is predicated of many things differing in species in respect of
what they are (in eo quod quid est).” The same phrase in a slightly different
definition captures the notion of species. The quid est of something therefore
has to do with the genus or species of that thing, or more generally, with the
kind of thing it is. So if one cannot know something’s quid est, one cannot
know what kind of thing it is.
It is helpful to see in this connection that one can know a great deal about
something even if one does not know (or cannot know) what kind of thing it
is. According to quantum physics, we do not know what kind of thing light
is. The best we can do is sometimes to think of light as a wave and
sometimes to think of it as a particle, although we certainly understand that
nothing can be at the same time both a wave and a particle. And yet we have
a great deal of positive knowledge about light, notwithstanding our inability
to know what kind of thing light is.
This view [that God is identical to esse] is subject to a difficulty both obvious and
overwhelming. No property could have created the world; no property could be
omniscient, or, indeed, know anything at all.19
And Plantinga summarizes the problem in a way that is especially apt for my
purposes here. He says,
If God is a property, then he isn’t a person …20
QUANTUM METAPHYSICS
It is worth noticing, however, that on this interpretation, represented by both
defenders and detractors of the doctrine, we do in fact know the quid est of
God, at least to some limited extent. That is because, on this interpretation,
we know that God is esse; and we know something about the quid est of esse,
as Aquinas’s own discussion of it in his commentary on Boethius’s De
hebdomadibus shows, where he gives a detailed characterization of the
nature of esse. So, if the doctrine of simplicity has to be interpreted as
claiming that God is only esse and nothing more, then, on Aquinas’s own
views, we would actually know a reasonable amount about the quid est of
God. But, as we saw, Aquinas is insistent that we are unable to know the quid
est of God because of God’s simplicity. And so the implication that we do
know a reasonable amount about the quid est of God should be a warning
sign about this interpretation.
In my view, the problem with this interpretation is not that it identifies
God with esse. The problem is that it rejects the notion of God as id quod est.
This rejection looks sensible, especially given Aquinas’s care to distinguish
esse from id quod est; but, in fact, it is not true to Aquinas’s position.
In his commentary on Boethius’s De hebdomadibus, Aquinas begins his
discussion of esse and id quod est by saying,
We signify one thing by “esse” and another thing by “‘id quod est,’” just as we signify
one thing by “running” (“currere”) and another thing by “a runner” (“currens”). For
“running” and “esse” signify in the abstract, just as “whiteness” also does; but “id quod
est,” that is, “an entity,” and “a runner,” signify in the concrete, just as “a white thing”
also does.22
it is evident on the basis of what has been presented that in composite things esse and id
quod est differ as regards the things themselves (realiter).23 … And so [Boethius] says
that in every composite thing, esse is one thing, and the composite thing itself [the thing
as id quod est] is another.24
But, having worked so hard to distinguish between esse and id quod est in
this way, Aquinas then goes on immediately to say something that is on the
face of it quite surprising. He says,
In simple things, [however,] esse itself and id quod est must be one and the same as
regards the things themselves (realiter).25
And, after giving an argument that there cannot be more than one thing that
is both esse and also id quod est, Aquinas sums up his position by saying,
With regard to what God himself is (secundum rem), God himself is neither universal
nor particular.28
For this reason, we have to exercise care in the way we frame our claims
about God. It is acceptable to say that God is esse, provided that we
understand that this claim does not rule out the equally true claim that God is
id quod est, an entity, a concrete particular.
Aquinas puts the point this way:
Those material creatures that are whole and subsistent are composite. But the form in
them is not some complete subsisting thing. Rather, the form is that by means of which
some thing is. For this reason, all the names imposed by us to signify some complete
subsisting thing signify in the concrete, as is appropriate for composite things. But those
names that are imposed to signify simple forms signify something not as subsisting but
rather as that by means of which something is, as for example “whiteness” signifies that
by means of which something is white. Therefore because God is both simple and
subsistent, we attribute to God both abstract names—to signify God’s simplicity—and
concrete names—to signify God’s completeness and concreteness. Nonetheless, each
kind of name falls short of God’s mode [of being], just as our intellect does not know
God as he is, in this life.29
We can gain insight into Aquinas’s position here by considering that there
are scriptural texts claiming that God is loving and scriptural texts claiming
that God is love.30 It seems, however, that these claims cannot be true
together. If they were, it would have to be true that love is loving. But love is
abstract and universal. And, as Plantinga objects, an abstract universal is not
a person; it is not the sort of thing that can be loving. So it seems just a
category mistake to attribute loving to love. On Aquinas’s understanding of
the doctrine of simplicity, however, we can make sense of both these
scriptural claims. Because God is simple and we do not comprehend his quid
est, the best we can do is to adopt quantum metaphysics. Sometimes we have
to characterize God with abstract terms—and so we say that God is love—
and sometimes we have to characterize him with concrete terms—and so we
say that God is loving.
Consequently, it turns out that, in one sense, Plantinga is after all in
agreement with Aquinas. Each of them thinks that God must be characterized
as an id quod est, a concrete entity. The difference between them lies
precisely in the quantum metaphysics mandated by the doctrine of simplicity.
For Aquinas, it is right to describe God as an id quod est, capable of creating,
loving, and acting—but only with the proviso that it is also right to think of
God as being esse.
CONCLUSION
On the doctrine of eternity, God is outside time.31 Some scholars have taken
that doctrine to imply that God cannot act, since (on their view) all action
presupposes temporal duration or temporal location; or they have supposed
that God’s mode of existence is that of a frozen point, as it were, without
duration of any kind, since (on their view) all duration is persistence through
time. In effect, such an interpretation takes the doctrine of eternity to imply a
metaphysical smallness about an eternal God by comparison with temporal
creatures. But, on Aquinas’s view, an eternal God is able to act at any and
every point in time, and his mode of existence is broad enough to encompass
all of time within it.32 From Aquinas’s point of view, the doctrine of eternity
implies a metaphysical greatness about God, above the status of any creatures
in time.
There is an analogous conceptual move to be made as regards
interpretations of the doctrine of simplicity. On the doctrine of simplicity,
God is without parts of any kind whatsoever; there is no composition in God.
Some scholars have taken the doctrine to imply that God is identical only to
esse,33 giving rise to the complaint voiced by Plantinga that a simple God
cannot act as persons do, or to the equally worrisome objection that
everything about God is absolutely necessary, since there are no accidents in
God. In effect, such an interpretation takes the doctrine of simplicity to make
God metaphysically more limited than concrete things such as composite
human beings, who can act and who can do otherwise than they do.
But this is to get the doctrine upside down. The doctrine of simplicity
implies that at the ultimate metaphysical foundation of all reality there is
esse. But it also implies that this esse, without losing any of its characteristics
as esse, is something subsistent and concrete, with more ability to act and
with more freedom in its acts than any concrete composite entity has. Trying
to summarize this idea, Aquinas says,
although God is esse only [and not something composite, as material creatures are], …
nonetheless God has all the perfections which are in all the genera [of created things].…
And this is because all these perfections come together in him in accordance with his
simple esse. By way of analogy, if someone could bring about the functioning of all
qualities by means of one quality, he would have [in effect] all the qualities in that one
quality. In just this way, God has all the perfections in his esse.34
The difficulty of thinking one’s way up the ladder of being can leave one
with the impression that the immutable, impassible, eternal, simple God of
Thomistic philosophical theology is frozen, static, inert, unresponsive, and
incapable of action. But Aquinas’s notion of God is exactly the opposite. If it
were not so subject to misinterpretation, one might well say that for Aquinas
God is maximally dynamic, and not static at all. On Aquinas’s views, there is
more ability to act—one might say, more action—on the part of a God with
the classical divine attributes than there could be on the part of a composite
entity acting in time.35 That is why Aquinas can say that in the esse that is
God there are all the perfections of all the genera of created things—
including responsiveness and action, which are perfections of any id quod est
with mind and will.36
On this way of understanding divine simplicity, when the esse that is God
acts, its action is not an accident in it. This is not because esse is an inert
universal that is the same in all possible worlds. Rather, it is because this esse
is more metaphysically one than any composite thing could be. When it acts,
it acts just as esse, and its acting remains within its character as esse. That is,
the acts engaged in by the esse that is also an id quod est are not added on to
esse as something additional to esse. In acting, the esse that is God remains
esse; it does not become esse plus the property of acting. The esse that is the
ultimate foundation of reality can do more than created, composite things
without ceasing to be esse only. That is why, in the power and the richness
that is esse, God can also do otherwise than he does without ceasing thereby
to be esse.
In our sense of the term, then, there is contingency in God. As Aquinas
himself is at pains to point out, Christians are committed to the claim that
God can do otherwise than he does. Creation is a free and not a necessitated
act on God’s part.37 But it is still not the case that there are accidents in God.
For composite things, contingency (in our sense of the term) comes with
composition of subject and accident; but not for God.
For this reason, it is also the case that a simple God can be responsive to
things in time. A simple God cannot do anything after something happens in
time, but a simple God can certainly act because of something that happens
in time. That is because, if something in time had been otherwise, a simple
God might have acted otherwise than he did. To say this is clearly not to say
that God decides what to do after something happens in time or that God can
change in time. To say this is only to claim that God can do otherwise than
he does, as Aquinas explicitly claims.38 As long as a simple God can do what
he does because of what happens in time, God can be responsive to things in
time.
To try to explain the doctrine of simplicity in this way is not to provide an
argument for the truth or even the compatibility of its claims. It is just to try
to contribute to insight into this most challenging part of Thomistic
philosophical theology. If, contra Aquinas, we could grasp the quid est of
something that is both esse and id quod est, we might understand exactly how
to explain what kind of thing can be described in all these ways. But, as it is,
on Aquinas’s views, we do not comprehend God’s quid est; and so we are
limited to the kind of quantum metaphysics sketched here.39
NOTES
1. This doctrine has also been the subject of a voluminous literature. The
most sustained and sophisticated attack on Aquinas’s position can be found
in Christopher Hughes, A Complex Theory of a Simple God (Ithaca, N.Y.:
Cornell University Press, 1989). Hughes’s attack, however, seems to me
based on misunderstandings of crucial elements of Aquinas’s metaphysics, as
reviewers have pointed out (see, e.g., David B. Burrell, “Review of
Christopher Hughes, On a Complex Theory of a Simple God,” Journal of
Religion, 72:1 [Jan 1992]: 120–21), and so I will not consider it here.
2. The derivation of divine simplicity from such considerations is apparent
in Aquinas’s QDP 7.1, as Mark D. Jordan has pointed out in his article “The
Names of God and the Being of Names” in Alfred J. Freddoso, ed., The
Existence and Nature of God (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame
Press, 1983), 161–90; see esp. 176–79.
3. For more extended discussion, see the chapter on simplicity in my
Aquinas (London: Routledge, 2003). For sympathetic treatments published
since then, see, e.g., Jeffrey Brower, “Making Sense of Divine Simplicity,”
Faith and Philosophy 25 (2008): 3–30: Brian Leftow, “Divine Simplicity,”
Faith and Philosophy 23 (2006): 365–80; and Brian Davies, “Simplicity,” in
Chad Meister and Charles Taliaferro, eds., The Cambridge Companion to
Christian Philosophical Theology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2009). For recent book-length treatment, see Peter Weigel, Aquinas on
Simplicity: An Investigation into the Foundations of His Philosophical
Theology (Frankfurt: Peter Lang, 2008).
4. ST I q.3 a.1–2; cf. also ST I q.9 a.1 and q. 10 a.1.
5. ST I q.3 a.6.
6. ST I q.3 a.3.
7. ST I q.3.
8. David Burrell, Aquinas: God and Action (Notre Dame, Ind.: University
of Notre Dame Press, 1979), 139. See also 60–61. “We cannot speak of God
at all … [on Aquinas’s theory of divine simplicity] unless it be under the
rubric of ‘the first cause of all.’ Yet such a cause leaves no proper traces
since its modus operandi cannot conform to the ordinary patterns whereby
effect resembles cause.… In the measure, then, that our language embodies a
subject/predicate, genus/species grammar … no description can succeed in
identifying a trace of divinity.”
9. Leo Elders, The Philosophical Theology of St. Thomas Aquinas (Leiden:
E. J. Brill, 1990), 143.
10. For discussion of this position in the secondary literature, see the
chapter on simplicity in my Aquinas (London: Routledge, 2003).
11. ST I q.3 a.3 ad 3.
12. See, in this connection, particularly SCG I.14.
13. In this connection, cf. also De ente et essentia, c.3. Cf. also the chapter
on being by John Wippel in this volume.
14. In BDH. II.22.
15. In BDH. II.24.
16. There is a complication in this regard that I can only touch on in this
brief essay. The esse at issue here must be distinguished from esse that is
common to all things in existence. (In this respect, see especially De ente et
essentia, c.5.) This common esse is a mental abstraction and so is a universal
in the sense of the term usual for Aquinas, who takes universals to exist only
in the mind. What distinguishes the esse that is God from the common esse is
that the divine esse precludes combination with anything else, whereas the
common esse is open to combination with form and matter. Even with this
distinction between common and divine esse, however, divine esse
considered just as esse is not concrete or particular. It does not follow that
God is a universal for Aquinas, or that for Aquinas there is one universal that
exists outside the mind, namely, God. As the rest of this essay makes clear,
the heart of Aquinas’s position is that we cannot know the quid est of God.
The best we can do is to alternate between language that identifies God with
what is universal—“God is love”—and language that identifies God with a
concrete particular—“God is loving.”
17. Cf., e.g., Leo Elders, The Philosophical Theology of St. Thomas
Aquinas (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1990), 22; “For St. Thomas God is never ‘an
object,’ for God is far above our understanding.”
18. Cf., e.g., David Burrell, Knowing the Unknowable God (Notre Dame,
Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1986); and, more recently, “Act of
Creation with Its Theological Consequences,” in Thomas Weinandy, Daniel
Keating, and John Yocum, eds., Aquinas on Doctrine (London and New
York: T & T Clark, 2004).
19. Alvin Plantinga, Does God Have a Nature? (Milwaukee, Wis.:
Marquette University Press, 1980), 47.
20. Ibid.
21. As he does, e.g., with regard to God’s interactions with Job; see his
prologue to his Expositio super Job.
22. In BDH., 22.
23. The qualifier “realiter” is needed here because in the preceding
discussion Aquinas has examined the distinction between esse and id quod
est considered as concepts. Once that conceptual distinction has been
established, he moves next to show that the conceptual distinction is
exemplified by all composite things, but that it does not apply to the one
thing which is entirely simple, namely, God.
24. In BDH., 32.
25. In BDH., 33. Cf. also, e.g., SCG I, c.38.
26. In BDH., 35.
27. For an excellent discussion of Aquinas’s theory of modality and its
connection to God’s nature, see Timothy Pawl, “A Thomistic Account of
Truthmakers for Modal Truths” (Ph.D. thesis, Saint Louis University, 2008).
28. ST I q.13 a.9 ad 2.
29. ST I q.13 a.1 ad 2. Cf. also SCG I, c.30.
30. For an example of the first, see 1 John 4:10; and for an example of the
second, see 1 John 4:8.
31. For defense of this claim, see the chapter on eternity in my Aquinas; for
a contrasting view, see the chapter on eternity by Brian Leftow in this
volume.
32. For explanation and defense of these claims, see the chapter on eternity
in my Aquinas.
33. That is, not to common esse but to the esse that is God; for the
distinction see note 16.
34. De ente et essentia, c.6.
35. God’s actuality or act of being is an important implication of the
doctrine of divine simplicity, but a detailed exploration of this issue has to be
left to one side in this brief essay.
36. In this connection, it is hard to resist calling attention to the case of
light again. When Newton first discovered that white light contained within it
all the richness of the other colors of light, there was considerable opposition
to his finding. The opposition supposed that the simplicity of white light
excluded the other colors, whose richness was thought to be somehow
tarnishing of the pure whiteness of white light. Goethe, who was among the
opposition, summed up this sort of attitude by saying that white light is “the
simplest most undivided most homogenous being that we know.” I am
indebted to Andrew Pinsent for the point and the historical information.
37. For a discussion of this point and the relevant Thomistic texts, see the
chapter on simplicity in my Aquinas.
38. For a more detailed discussion of this point, see the chapter on
simplicity in my Aquinas.
39. I owe a debt of gratitude to Theodore Vitali, C.P., whose relentless
questioning of my previous presentation of the doctrine of simplicity led me
to want to examine the topic again. And I have learned a great deal from the
seminar presentations on divine simplicity given by John Foley, S.J. His
seminar presentations led me to rethink the doctrine in the way I have
outlined it here. I am also grateful to him for trenchant criticism of an earlier
draft, which caused me to rework one central part of this essay. I am grateful
as well to David Burrell, Tim Pawl, Andrew Pinsent, and especially Brian
Davies for helpful comments on an earlier draft.
CHAPTER 11
GOD’S GOODNESS
LUDGER HONNEFELDER
INTRODUCTION
That “good,” “goodness,” or “being good” has to be predicated of God has
been clear in philosophy and theology at least since Dionysius Pseudo-
Areopagita’s De divinis nominibus.1 It became a traditional part of medieval
philosophical theology because it was demanded in the Jewish and Christian
context by several biblical texts. But the mode of this predication is not self-
evident: Is God—as the Platonists say2—primarily “good” or “goodness
itself” and therefore the cause of the “goodness” of all other things? Or can
God only be called “good” because “good” is—as Aristotle seems to say3—a
common predicate that must be predicated of God, as well as of everything
else that exists? What does “good” even mean? Is it interchangeable with
“being,” so that something is “good” insofar as it has “being”? How is
“good” related to “being,” and what does “good” add to “being”?
Since Philip the Chancellor inaugurated the debate, the medieval doctrine
of the transcendentals4 (i.e., the transcategorical predicates) had developed as
a wide-ranging discussion. The following questions, in particular, were hotly
disputed: Which predicate deserves epistemological and/or ontological
priority? In what sense can “goodness” be predicated of God? And how
should the relation of God’s goodness to the goodness of all other beings be
understood?
The locus classicus that requires Aquinas to deal with these questions is
the first part of his Summa theologiae. Given that “sacred doctrine,” as he
establishes in ST I q.1, must be the science whose subject is God, it must deal
first with God’s nature. This task can be accomplished only by determining
which predicates characterize God: existence/being, simplicity, perfection,
goodness, and so on.
The order Aquinas follows in ST I q.2–6 is not arbitrary. Because God is
not the natural object of any of our cognitive powers, neither God’s existence
nor essence can be presupposed as naturally known, but must instead be
demonstrated. “In this life,” as he explains in ST I q.13 a.1, “we cannot see
God in his essence, but rather we cognize him through creatures under the
aspect of a cause, abstracting from creatures the mode of excellence.”5
If in general God is not naturally known in his essence, God’s “goodness”
in particular is not self-evident, but must be demonstrated on the basis of a
number of premises. Demonstrating God’s goodness is possible only if we
grant that God is a being (as shown in ST I q.2), whose nature is simple and
perfect (as shown in q.3 and q.4), and that the predicate “good” is common
(as shown in q.5).6 On this background, it can be argued in ST I q.6 that God
need not be the precise adequate subject of goodness (a.1), but that God must
be the “highest good” (a.2), and this must be in virtue of God’s nature (a.3).
Thus, no other being can be considered as “good” except by participation in
divine goodness (a.4).
The ST is not the only and not the first place where Aquinas treats God’s
goodness. Already in QDV, q.21 he deals with God’s goodness as the “first
goodness” on which goodness in general depends. The approach in QDV,
q.21 is different than that in ST and has as its background the commentaries
that Aquinas devoted to Boethius’s De hebdomadibus and to Dionysius’s De
divinis nominibus. In SCG it is the treatment of God’s nature in the first book
that requires Aquinas to consider God’s goodness (ch. 37 –41). Since the
doctrine of God’s goodness in ST is the last and the decisive treatment, we
should start with a short explanation of this version of Aquinas’s position,
adding occasional observations on the earlier parallel texts.
NOTES
1. Cf. Dionysius Pseudo-Areopagita, De divinis nominibus, c.4. My
thanks to Rega Wood (Stanford) for her help with the above; thanks, too, to
Jennifer Ottman for her assistance with matters of English style.
2. Cf. ibid.; Boethius, De hebdomadibus.
3. Cf. Aristotle, Ethica Nicomachea l.1, c.4 (1096 a 19 –29).
4. Cf. Philip the Chancellor, Summa de bono.
5. ST I q.13 a.1; cf. Eleonore Stump, Aquinas (London: Routledge, 2003),
93 ff.
6. Cf. Jan A. Aertsen, Medieval Philosophy and the Transcendentals: The
Case of Thomas Aquinas (Leiden, New York, and Köln: E. J. Brill, 1996);
id., “Good as Transcendental and the Transcendence of the Good,” in Scott
MacDonald, ed., Being and Goodness: The Concept of the Good in
Metaphysics and Philosophical Theology (Ithaca, N.Y. and London: Cornell
University Press, 1991), 56 –73; Rudi te Velde, “The Concept of the Good
according to Thomas Aquinas,” in Wouter Goris, ed., Die Metaphysik und
das Gute: Aufsätze zu ihrem Verhältnis in Antike und Mittelalter (Leuven:
Peeters, 1999), 81–103; Scott MacDonald, “The Metaphysics of Goodness
and the Doctrine of the Transcendentals,” in Scott MacDonald, ed., Being
and Goodness: The Concept of the Good in Metaphysics and Philosophical
Theology (Ithaca, N.Y. and London: Cornell University Press, 1991), 31–55
7. Aertsen, Medieval Philosophy and the Transcendentals, 300; te Velde,
“The Concept of the Good.”
8. Cf. In NE I l.1; see Aertsen, Medieval Philosophy and the
Transcendentals, 299 f.
9. Cf. ST I q.5 a.5.
10. QDV q.21, a.1.
11. Ibid.
12. Cf. te Velde, “The Concept of the Good.”
13. Cf. Aertsen, “Good as Transcendental.”
14. Aristotle, Physics l.2, c.7 (193 a 26 f.), l.2 (193 b 8 ff.).
15. Cf. Louis-Bertrand Geiger, La participation dans la philosophie de S.
Thomas d’Aquin, 2d ed. (Paris: Vrin, 1953), 63–73
16. MacDonald, “The Metaphysics of Goodness,” 37, calls it the Agency
Account.
17. Scott MacDonald, “The Relation between Being and Goodness,” in
Scott MacDonald, ed., Being and Goodness: The Concept of the Good in
Metaphysics and Philosophical Theology (Ithaca, N.Y. and London: Cornell
University Press, 1991).
18. Cf. Wolfgang Kluxen, “Thomas von Aquin: Das Seiende und seine
Prinzipien,” in Josef Speck, ed., Grundprobleme der großen Philosophen
(Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Rupprecht, 1972), 174–214
19. See the contribution of John F. Wippel in this volume.
20. ST I q.4 a.1–2; cf. Leo J. Elders, The Philosophical Theology of St.
Thomas Aquinas (Leiden, New York, København, and Köln: E. J. Brill,
1990), 163
21. SCG l.1, c.41, referring to Aristotle, Met. l.2, c.1
22. Cf., e.g., ST I q.44 a.1: ipsum esse per se subsistens.
23. Cf. Ralph McInerny, “Saint Thomas on De hebdomadibus,” in Scott
MacDonald, ed., Being and Goodness: The Concept of the Good in
Metaphysics and Philosophical Theology (Ithaca, N.Y. and London: Cornell
University Press, 1991), 74–97
24. Therefore, Aertsen, Medieval Philosophy and the Transcendentals,
317, states that according to Aquinas “good” is both in the category of
substantial being and in the category of accidental being. Cf. Aertsen, “Good
as Transcendental.”
25. Cf. Albertus Magnus, Summa theologiae, tr.6, q.28, sol. (ed. Siedler,
Ed. Colon. t.34, 1 p.214); MacDonald, “The Metaphysics of Goodness.”
26. QDV q.21 a.1 ad 1.
27. ST I q.5 a.2 ad 1.
28. ST I q.5 a.2 ad 1.
29. ST I q.13 a.1 ad 2.
30. Cf. ST I q.6 a.4; In NE l.1, c.6.
31. ST I q.4 a.3.
32. Cf. Aertsen, “Good as Transcendental.”
33. Aertsen, Medieval Philosophy and the Transcendentals, 302, speaks of
the “attractive and the productive side of goodness”; te Velde, “The Concept
of the Good,” distinguishes between “good in itself” and “good for itself.”
34. See note 25
CHAPTER 12
GOD’S KNOWLEDGE
Aquinas presents God’s knowledge (1) as a divine perfection and (2) as
divine ideas. In addition, there is the special question of (3) God’s knowledge
of future contingent events such as creaturely free choices. Each topic
deserves its own consideration.
(1) For any event x, if God knows that x will occur in the future, then
necessarily (God knows that x will occur).
(2) For any event x, if God knows x will occur in the future, then God
knows (x will necessarily occur).
Statement (1), Aquinas thinks, is true. Statement (2), Aquinas thinks, is false.
Statement (1), however, is not enough to arrive at the conclusion that for any
event x, God knows (x will necessarily be). So much can be understood as a
matter of logic alone. But grasping Aquinas’s answer to the question of
future contingents is more than a matter of seeing through formal fallacies.
A good deal turns on the order in which Aquinas goes about speaking of
God’s knowledge. First, God knows himself. Second, God knows creatures.
But within the second moment, when speaking of God’s knowledge of
creatures, Aquinas seems to be sensitive to a certain complexity. Creatures
are both one and many, but in different respects. Creatures are one whole (the
whole of creation), and many individuals (this or that singular creature).
When speaking of God’s knowledge of creatures, Aquinas first thinks of God
as seeing creatures as a whole and secondarily thinks of God as seeing
creatures as one part or another, one individual or another. All at once, in the
eternal glance at himself, God sees the whole of creation.
When God sees in himself the whole of creation, he comprehends it. He
knows everything that could be known about it. He sees all the parts and so
all the properties of all the parts. So when God comprehends the whole of
creation, God sees the actuality, modality, causality, and morality (if
applicable) of any and every entity or event within the whole. For example,
God sees that Mt. Vesuvius erupts at t, that Mt. Vesuvius might not have
erupted at t, that a certain set of factors caused the eruption, and so on.
Similarly, God also sees at once all the free choices rational creatures make
and all the properties of those choices. In his comprehension of the whole,
God sees concerning any free choice that the person will choose something,
what the person will choose, why the person chooses it (i.e., sees the person’s
liberum arbitrium produce the action), whether the individual could choose
otherwise, and whether that ability or inability to choose otherwise is morally
relevant in the circumstances. In other words, in one glance at himself God
comprehends the whole panoply of individual creaturely free choices and
comprehends each choice as an essentially free contingent act. Such
comprehension of our choices, although it is prior to our choices, does not
predetermine our choices. Rather, God’s prior comprehension of them is a
comprehension of them as essentially free contingent acts. God’s
comprehension of those acts entails no necessity in them except the necessity
of being what God comprehends them to be, that is, essentially free
contingent acts.18
In recent years, there has been new and intense debate amongst
philosophers about what views of time, modality, eternity, knowledge, and
free will Aquinas is committed to given his views on God’s knowledge.19
GOD’S WILL
Aquinas’s account of God’s will touches upon four related topics: (1) God’s
will as a divine perfection, (2) God’s willing of creatures, (3) God’s love and
joy, and (4) God’s justice and mercy. Each topic deserves its own treatment.
And so in our own minds we have three different senses of the term “to will.”
Because of the three senses of “to will,” the issue of God’s will is really
several questions of whether God wills, what God wills, and in what senses
God wills which things. In response to these questions, Aquinas makes three
main points. First, in God there is no will in the sense that God lacks
something and wants it. Second, in God there is will in the sense of
possessing or resting in something good, namely, God possessing and resting
in himself as highest good. Finally, in God there is will in the sense of giving
something, namely, God gives being to creatures. Each of these points
deserves individual attention.
(1) God does not will things in the sense of hungering for a perceived
good that he does not have. For having such a hunger would consist of being
in a state of (passive) potentiality with respect to the perceived good, and in
God there is no (passive) potentiality. It would also amount, on Aquinas’s
physics, of needing to be moved by another, and God is not moved by
another.20 So in God there is no will as lacking something. There could only
be will as possessing and will as giving.
(2) In God there is will as possessing something that one perceives as
good. In God there is will as “loving and delighting in what he possesses.”21
In this sense, God wills himself. Sometimes Aquinas says that God loves and
delights in himself, and sometimes Aquinas says God possesses and rests in
himself. Stated whichever way, Aquinas has in mind his account of God’s
goodness and self-knowledge.
On Aquinas’s account of God’s goodness, God is good, the highest good,
essentially good, completely good, pre-containing every actual and possible
creaturely perfection, and so lacking in no good whatsoever. Indeed, God is
goodness itself.22 Further, on Aquinas’s account of God’s knowledge, God
knows himself completely and so knows himself as goodness. But for
Aquinas, to know goodness as goodness is already to love it.23 So God loves
what he is and is what he loves. He rests and delights in being himself. To be
God is what God loves to be or to do as a pure end in itself. Furthermore,
God cannot be or do otherwise. It is absolutely necessary for him to love
himself and delight in himself just for being God.24 In that sense, God “wills
himself to be”25 and “necessarily wills himself to be.”26 Furthermore, given
the divine simplicity, God’s willing of himself is God.27 Just as when treating
God’s knowledge, Aquinas begins with the claim that God knows himself,
and on that basis accounts for God’s knowledge of other things, so when
treating of God’s will Aquinas begins with the claim that God wills himself
and on that basis accounts for God’s willing other things. So, after treating of
God’s willing himself, Aquinas turns to God’s willing of creatures.
(3) In God there is will as giving. God wills things other than himself in
the sense that he communicates “as far as possible to the others the good
possessed.”28 God gives to other things a share in his own goodness, which is
being (esse). As parents will a share in their wealth to their children, so God
wills a share in his wealth (esse) to his creatures.29 To be clear, the share of
wealth that children receive from their parents differs in many ways from the
share in esse that creatures receive from God. But the analogy affords some
understanding of the sense in which one can say that God wills created
things. God wills them in the sense that God gives them being.
Aquinas often repeats that God wills creatures as a means to an end. What
Aquinas means is that God gives esse to creatures as his way of being God or
as his way of loving and delighting in being himself. For “the things that we
love for their own sake we want to be multiplied as much as possible. And
God wills and loves his essence for its own sake.”30 Therefore, God wills the
multiplication of esse, that is, God gives a share in esse to other things. And
to give a share in esse to other things is God’s way of being God.
Furthermore, God need not have willed (given being to) things other than
himself as his way of being God. He could have and would have been God,
been goodness itself, known goodness itself, loved goodness itself, possessed
goodness itself, and enjoyed goodness itself, and lacked nothing, simply by
being himself—even if he had never given being to anything other than
himself. So it is not absolutely necessary that God will (give being to) other
things.31 But God in fact wills to be himself in this way: by giving a share in
his esse to creatures. What is the modal status of that fact? From the point of
view of merely logical possibility, that God wills creatures is contingent. But
from the point of view of “conditional necessity,” that God wills creatures is
necessary. For God is immutable in every respect. Therefore, his will toward
creatures could not have come into being in God and could not cease to be in
God. Rather, God’s act of willing creatures simply is God.32 Given that God
in fact wills creatures, God cannot do or be otherwise. In that sense, God’s
willing of creatures is necessary.
Aquinas claims that there is love and joy in God.38 The claim is difficult
since in human beings love and joy are passions, and Aquinas wants to say
that there are no passions in God.39 For passions, on Aquinas’s view, are
essentially changes in the physical organs of animals who are responding to
what is perceived through the senses. And no such thing can occur in God
who is immutable and immaterial. But Aquinas distinguishes the passions of
love and joy from the “simple operations” of love and joy, and here he finds
a way to say there is love and joy in God.40 The simple operations of love
and joy are acts of intellect and will as spiritual powers. This spiritual love
and spiritual joy are found in God, but like all other divine perfections this
spiritual love and joy exist in God in a higher and more eminent way than in
creatures.
In creatures, to love something is to respond to some preceding goodness
found in it. The goodness already present in things, being apprehended,
moves our wills to love them. But God’s will is not moved in any respect. So
God’s love is not his response to the preceding goodness found in things.
Rather, God’s love is the cause of whatever goodness there is to be found in
them. This counts as love because “to love anything is nothing else than to
will good to that thing”41 and God wills the good of being (esse) to things.42
In that sense, God loves everything. For God, to will creatures is to give them
being, and to give them being is to give them something good, and to give
them something good is to love them.
Does God love himself? Aquinas says God wills himself to himself and
for himself.43 For he is goodness itself. And being what he wills to himself
and for himself, he is joyful. For joy is a “certain resting of the will in its
object.”44 And “God is at rest in himself, as containing all abundance in
himself.”45
God also rejoices in his creatures. For “each thing takes joy in its like as in
something agreeable,” and creatures are like God in being and in goodness
(albeit as inadequate imitations).46
NOTES
1. ST I q.13. a.2. and a.16 both speak about perfections being “more
eminent” in God than in creatures.
2. ST I q.12 a.4..
3. ST I q.12 a.13 ad 1.
4. Aquinas treats of God’s knowledge elsewhere than the Summa
theologiae, but I am focusing on the ST treatment, since it is the most mature
thought of Aquinas.
5. I use “know” and “understand” synonymously throughout this article,
for knowledge in God corresponds most to what understanding in Aquinas’s
sense of the term denotes.
6. But to be God is to be gazing in a higher and more eminent sense of
“gazing” than what we find in creaturely gazing.
7. ST I q.14 a.5 and a.7 ad 2.
8. ST I q.14 a.7 ad 2.
9. ST I q.14 a.9..
10. ST I q.14 a.13.
11. ST I q.14 a.6.
12. ST I q.15 a.2.
13. ST I q.14 a.8 resp. and ad 1; q.19 a.11 ad 1.
14. Gregory T. Doolan, Aquinas on the Divine Ideas as Exemplar Causes
(Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University Press of America, 2008); Vivian
Boland, Ideas in God According to Saint Thomas Aquinas (New York: E. J.
Brill, 1996); John Wippel, Thomas Aquinas on the Divine Ideas, The Etienne
Gilson Series, no.16 (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies,
1993); John Lee Farthing, “The Problem of Divine Exemplarity in St.
Thomas,” The Thomist 49 (1985): 183–222.
15. James Ross, “Aquinas’ Exemplarism; Aquinas’ Voluntarism,”
American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 64 (1990): 171–98; Armand A.
Maurer, “James Ross on the Divine Ideas: A Reply,” American Catholic
Philosophical Quarterly 65 (1991): 213–20; Lawrence Dewan, “St. Thomas,
James Ross, and Exemplarism: A Reply,” American Catholic Philosophical
Quarterly 65 (1991): 221–34; James Ross, “Response to Maurer and
Dewan,” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 65 (1991): 235–43;
Eleonore Stump and Norman Kretzmann, “God’s Knowledge and Its Causal
Effects,” in Thomas Senor, ed., The Rationality of Belief and the Plurality of
Faith (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1995), 94–124; Brian Shanley,
“Divine Causation and Human Freedom in Aquinas,” American Catholic
Philosophical Quarterly 72 (1998): 99–122.
16. ST I q.14 a.13 obj.3.
17. For a study of necessity de dicto and de re, and also a discussion of
how the distinction applies to God’s knowledge of creaturely properties, see
Alvin Plantinga, The Nature of Necessity (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1974), 9
ff.
18. ST I q.14 a.13.
19. A. Kenny, “Divine Foreknowledge and Human Freedom,” in A.
Kenny, ed., Aquinas: A Collection of Critical Essays (London: MacMillan,
1969), 255–70; Eleonore Stump and Norman Kretzmann, “Eternity,” Journal
of Philosophy 78 (1981): 429–51; William Lane Craig, The Problem of
Divine Foreknowledge and Future Contingents from Aristotle to Suarez
(Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1988), 99–126; William Lane Craig, “Aquinas on God’s
Knowledge of Future Contingents,” The Thomist 54:1 (January 1990): 33–
79; Brian Shanley, “Eternal Knowledge of the Temporal in Aquinas,”
American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 71:2 (Spring 1997): 197–224;
“Eternity and God’s Knowledge: A Reply to Shanley,” American Catholic
Philosophical Quarterly 72:3 (Summer 1998): 439–45; Theodore J.
Kondoleon, “God’s Knowledge of Future Contingent Singulars: A Reply,”
The Thomist 56:1 (January 1992): 117–39; David Burrell, “God’s Knowledge
of Future Contingents: A Reply to William Lane Craig,” The Thomist 58:2
(April 1994): 317–22; “Eternity, Awareness, and Action” Faith and
Philosophy 9 (1992): 463–82; Eleonore Stump, “God’s Knowledge,” in
Aquinas (London: Routledge, 2003), 159–87; Harm Goris, “Divine
Foreknowledge, Providence, Predestination, and Human Freedom,” in Rik
van Nieuwenhove and Joseph Wawrykow, eds., The Theology of Thomas
Aquinas (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 2005), 99–122;
Harm Goris, Free Creatures of An Eternal God (Nijmegen: Stichting
Thomasfonds, 1996).
20. ST I q.19 a.1 ad 2 and 3.
21. ST I q.19 a.1 ad 2.
22. SCG I, c.38.
23. SCG I, c.72, n.2: “Since the understood good is the proper object of the
will, the understood good is as such willed.”
24. ST I q.19 a.3; SCG I, c.80.
25. SCG I, c.75, n.2.
26. SCG I, c.80, n.3.
27. ST I q.19 a.1.
28. ST I q.19 a.2.
29. This analogy is not found in Aquinas.
30. SCG I, c.75, n.3.
31. For contemporary discussion of this point, see Norman Kretzmann, The
Metaphysics of Theism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997), 217–25; John
Wippel, “Norman Kretzmann on Aquinas’s Attribution of Will and of
Freedom to Create to God,” Religious Studies 39 (2003): 287–98; John
Wippel, “Thomas Aquinas on God’s Freedom to Create or Not,” in
Metaphysical Themes in Thomas Aquinas II (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic
University Press of America, 2007), 218–39.
32. ST I q.19 a.1 ad 1.
33. ST I q.19 a.7.
34. ST I q.19 a.6 ad 1.
35. ST I q.19 a.6 ad 1.
36. ST I q.19 a.9.
37. ST I q.19 a.10 ad 3.
38. On God’s love and joy, see Kretzmann, The Metaphysics of Theism,
226 ff; Brian Davies, The Thought of Thomas Aquinas (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1992), 149 ff.
39. SCG I, c.89.
40. SCG I, c.90, n.2.
41. ST I q.20 a.2.
42. ST I q.5 a.1.
43. ST I q.20 a.1 ad 3.
44. SCG I, c.90, n.3.
45. SCG I, c.90, n.3.
46. SCG I, c.90, n.6.
47. On God’s justice and mercy, see Davies, The Thought of Thomas
Aquinas, 152–57.
48. ST I q.21 a.1 ad 3.
49. ST I q.21 a.3.
50. SCG II, c.29.
CHAPTER 13
BRIAN LEFTOW
THE claim that God is impassible can assert that God has no passions, no
negative emotions or no emotions, or that God is not causally passive—not
caused to have any attribute. I discuss these claims in this order, then turn to
immutability.
For Aquinas, God has no passions.1 Having passions, he holds, requires
having a body, senses, and more generally “passive potency” (of which more
anon); God has none of these.2 Leaving “passive potency” aside, we might
jib at this: if I were a disembodied soul, I might well care passionately about
philosophy. But the truth is that “passion” in this context is for Aquinas a
technical term, so defined as to apply only to mental states appropriately
involved with physical states.3 We use “passionate” in a loose sense allied to
“intense.” That God has no passions, in Aquinas’s sense, would not rule out
his being intellectually passionate in our sense.
God’s perfection, Aquinas thinks, rules out his having negative emotions,
such as sorrow, fear, envy, or anger.4 Aquinas’s arguments on these scores
are likely to leave us unsatisfied. Sorrow, he tells us, is about evil we have;
since evil cannot befall God, God cannot sorrow.5 But what of sorrow over
evil befalling creatures God loves? And if we love another sufficiently, evil
befalling that other is or entails evil befalling us: it is a tragedy for a husband
if his beloved wife is crippled, and not necessarily for self-regarding reasons.
Again, surely evil befell God the Son in the Crucifixion, and he seemed in
the Garden to sorrow over it in advance, and even to fear it. It is not clear that
a Christology should even want to deny this, nor that orthodox Christology
can. The fear is a mental state generated in Christ’s human nature, but that
does not stop the state from belonging to the Son, else there are two mental
subjects, two persons, in the incarnate Christ, which is the heresy of
Nestorianism.
Again, Aquinas takes it from Aristotle that anger supposes sorrow over
injury done and entails an appetite for another’s evil for the sake of revenge.6
On this account, he thinks, God cannot be angry both because he cannot
sorrow and because he cannot be injured. But Christ was God and was angry
at times, and again, the anger had to belong to the Son. Further, anger can
issue in a desire for just punishment. Just punishment is not a form of
revenge; further, one who imposes just punishment imposes evil but only
because he/she intends a good, for the community and even for the one
punished. Again, one can be angry over injuries others suffer. Finally,
Aquinas classes envy as a passion in his technical sense, and so ruled out
merely by lack of a body, yet he grants that the Devil was envious.7
Turning now to emotions more generally, Aquinas is willing to say that
God loves.8 But he so parses this that it is not altogether clear that it counts
as what we would call an emotion. As it exists in God, love involves only
intellect and will. It is not a passion, or caused by its object, for reasons we
see shortly; while love in us involves a response to valued qualities we find
in others, God’s love causes those valued qualities ex nihilo.9 Aquinas’s
account of love is entirely in functional terms: it is the first act of the will,
wills the good for the beloved and moves the lover toward union with the
beloved.10 One could be pardoned the thought that on Aquinas’s account,
love is something God does, not something God feels. But surely an emotion,
whatever else it involves, is something one feels. Norman Kretzmann
suggests that the best term for what Aquinas has in mind here is “attitude,”
and having an attitude is not a matter of feeling at all.11 Yet “attitude” is not
quite right either because attitudes are dispositions. Aquinas’s God has none,
and he repeatedly calls joy, delight, and love “operations,” things the divine
will does.12 If anything like feeling comes into Aquinas’s account of God’s
emotional states, it is when he ascribes joy and delight to God.13 But here the
arguments again leave one worried. Aquinas writes, for instance, that since
our understanding is delightful when perfect, God’s, which is perfect, will be
all the more delightful.14 Well, maybe. Why should we think that God will
resemble us in this way? Nothing else in Aquinas’s story about God
encourages us to ascribe any particular affective tone to his inner life.
CAUSAL IMPASSIVITY
The emotional side of impassibility is for Aquinas a minor detail in the
doctrine of God. On the other hand, God’s causal impassivity is a
consequence of a fundamental, far-reaching claim that Aquinas makes about
God: he has no “passive potency.”15 Passive potencies are best thought of as
potentials to acquire attributes. A passive potency is an ability to “move”
(change), or rather be moved,16 with respect to having an attribute. For
Aquinas, “motion” is as such the actualization of a (passive) potency.17 And
any item that passes from potency to act has the potency (i.e., potentially has
the attribute) temporally before it has the actuality (i.e., actually has the
attribute).18 This being so, passive potencies are potentials to become,19 to
come to have some attribute. So lack of passive potencies is the root of God’s
intrinsic immutability. We see below that Aquinas thinks that this entails
divine timelessness. Aquinas’s commitment to immutability and timelessness
conditions a great deal else he says about God. So then does his denial of
divine passive potencies.
Again, whatever passes from passive potency to actuality is for Aquinas
caused to do so.20 So Thomist passive potencies are also liabilities to be
caused. And so something with no passive potencies is causally impassive:
nothing can cause it to have any attribute. The claim that God is causally
impassive plays a large role in Aquinas’s accounts of God’s knowledge (God
cannot be caused to know anything, and so his knowledge cannot literally be
observational) and providence (while God responds to us, we do not cause
Him to do so). Our first question, then, must be why Aquinas thinks God
lacks passive potency. I then pass to immutability and atemporality.
AQUINAS ON IMMUTABILITY
If God has no passive potencies, again, there is nothing he can become. So
God cannot change intrinsically.24 Intrinsic changes are changes like
reddening, growing, or forgetting, which (roughly) occur entirely within the
changing item. For Aristotelians there is also genuine change from place to
place, but this is not intrinsic and (Aquinas thinks) gets ruled out not because
God is immutable but because he is omnipresent: wherever God might be
said to move to, he is already.25
Changes are extrinsic just if they are not intrinsic. Very roughly, for
Aquinas, A changes extrinsically just when a new predicate becomes
applicable to A owing entirely to an intrinsic change in something wholly
distinct from A, as when I become shorter than Joe only because Joe grows.
Aquinas is explicit that God can change extrinsically.26 When Moses comes
to exist, God becomes the Lord of Moses. Moses’ coming to exist and God’s
thus becoming his Lord does not involve any intrinsic change in God; all that
happens here is that a new title comes to apply to God. Further, even if this
did rest on acquiring a new real relational property, this would not realize a
potency of God, Aquinas thinks. For the realizing of a potency involves
“motion,” and Aquinas accepts from Aristotle that there is no “motion” in the
category of relation.27 Rather, new relations arise without having been in
process of change, due to motion in another category.28
For Aquinas as for most other medieval Aristotelians, intrinsic properties
fall into three categories: substance, quality, and quantity.29 Aristotelians see
change with respect to substance—the kind a thing belongs to—as
impossible; Aristotelians see kinds as essential properties. Thus, for Aquinas,
the doctrine of divine immutability (DDI) rules out only change in quality
(e.g., color, intelligence) or quantity (size, shape). For Aquinas, some things
acquire real inhering relational properties by being changed in these
categories: when I grow, I acquire a real relational property of being equal in
height to others of my new height. But because God cannot be changed in
these categories, he cannot acquire a new inhering relational property. God
can only be spoken of in new ways by relational predicates.
We can distinguish a weak and a strong DDI:
ETERNALITY
Aquinas adopts Boethius’s definition of eternity, “the all-at-once and perfect
possession of interminable life.”34 In his Sentence commentary,35 Aquinas
says that the definition’s basic thought is that to be eternal is to have being
without limits.
As Aquinas explains it, God’s life does not stretch through all time. This
is ruled out by its containing no temporal parts—any life lived through time
is lived through one hour, then another, and so has one hour-long part, then
another. Nor does God’s life occupy part of time: this is ruled out by its
having no beginning or end. Nor does it last just an instant. So Aquinas must
see God’s existence as atemporal.43 One might object to this that Aquinas
also says eternity “includes all times”44 and that God “always”45 exists.46
The first, though, brings to mind Anselm’s thesis that an atemporal God has
present to Him in eternity, in an atemporal way, all times insofar as they are
present, which Aquinas appears to endorse in ST I q.14 a.13.47 To image the
relation of eternity to time, Aquinas adopts from Boethius the simile of an
eternal being as a point in the center of a circle, co-existent with every point
on the circumference though not located on it.48 This simile is naturally
cashed out in terms of Anselm’s picture. “Includes all times” does not, then,
have to be read as suggesting existence at all times, and the circle simile in
fact points another way, since center-points do not exist at every point on
their circumferences. The use of “always exists,” moreover, is at best
ambiguous: it could mean no more than that if God is atemporal, at every
time, it is true that he timelessly exists, just as at every point on a
circumference, it is true that the center exists—across from it.
Rory Fox suggests that Aquinas does not hold either that God is timeless
or that he is everlasting.49 Fox points out that Aquinas is willing in the case
of angels, which are not temporal, to say that when they have effects in time,
their actions are in time,50 adding “and so they could be said to be existing, in
effect, in time.”51 Fox thinks Aquinas should say the same of God, who also
has temporal effects.52 Fox adds that Aquinas is happy to say that God exists
in place in virtue of sustaining all things in all places and suggests that
Aquinas should concede in parallel that God exists in time (in some way) in
virtue of sustaining all things in all times.53 But Fox’s point about the angels
takes a step too far. It is a standard part of Aristotelian theories of causation
that the action of a cause takes place in its effect: the action of the fire occurs
in the water, when the fire causes the water to heat up. It does not follow that
the fire exists where the water is; in fact this would be impossible, to an
Aristotelian. To say that an angel’s action exists in time is to say no more
than what we would mean by saying that its effect is in time. Thus, there is
for Aquinas just no move to be made from an angel’s action occurring in our
time to the angel’s literally existing in our time. In fact, in discussing angelic
motion, Aquinas holds that moving angels exist in their own kind of time,
one discrete rather than continuous, rather than claiming that they exist in our
time, even though they move through places we share with them.54 This is in
part because their motion just consists in their actions’ being at different
places at different times.55
Fox’s other argument, about presence in space and time, should resonate
particularly for those who believe we live in a four-dimensional universe, one
not of space in time but of spacetime, a single entity of which “space” and
“time” denote abstracted aspects. For if this is true, then in any sense in
which God is in space, he is also in time. But Aquinas did not think he lived
in such a universe. And the sense in which Aquinas says God exists in place
is too weak to support a claim that God is in any sense intrinsically other than
a-spatial, or literally located in space. For all Aquinas means by this is that all
things are subject to God’s power and that God directly knows all things and
causes all things to be.56 His knowing them hardly places him literally where
they are. His causing effects in them, again, places his action but not God
himself in space. Thus, there is no basis here for any jibbing about whether
Aquinas’s God is atemporal.
Aquinas takes it without argument that even a God he thinks atemporal has a
now. Perhaps this is because God is conscious, and a “now of experience”
seems conceptually inseparable from having experience at all. Aquinas says
that we apprehend God’s “standing now.” We do so, I think, by
apprehending that God is immutable; it is because immutability leads us to
see that God’s now “stands” rather than “flows” that it leads us to conclude
that God is atemporal. The connection between these things runs via
Aquinas’s account of time.
Aquinas believes that the temporal now “flows”—that time really,
objectively passes.64 One question we can ask believers in a flowing now is
why it flows: what “powers” the passage of time. Some see time’s passage as
a process unto itself, primitive, not further explained.65 Aquinas disagrees.
For Aquinas, our time is the time of material things, whose time is the
number of local motion, change of place.66 (I explain “the number of”
shortly.) For Aquinas, angels have their own sort of time, which is the
number of succession—change—in their mental operations.67 Our time for
Aquinas is an accident of the “first motion,” the revolution of the outer
Aristotelian heavenly sphere.68 Now for Aquinas, their subjects make
accidents exist.69 So Aquinas’s claim is that the motion of the outermost
sphere makes our time exist. He is so firm on this, in fact, that he holds that if
there were many Aristotelian universes, each with its own outermost sphere,
each would therefore have its own time: there would be many distinct
temporal series.70 Since for time to exist is for it to “flow”71—time for
Aquinas is generated by the flow of the now72—for Aquinas, the outermost
sphere’s motion makes time pass: what makes our time “flow” is the first
motion.
To see what’s behind this, note that Aquinas accepts Aristotle’s definition
of time as “the number of motion.”73 As Aquinas understands this, it means
that time is the countable or measurable aspect of motion. Aquinas thinks of
the day as a natural first unit of time.74 A day, which is a stretch of time, just
is the time taken by one revolution of the sun around the earth (as Aquinas
thought): a particular motion occurs in its very definition, as that in which the
property of being a day long inheres per se. If the day is the first unit, we do
not measure it: there is no other, prior unit available to measure it with.
Instead we just count days, by counting the times the sun reappears at the
same point in the sky, having completed one revolution. Given this standard
unit, we can measure other lengths of time, and so other time-units are
definable as parts or multiples of this one. The first motion provides the day,
a natural unit by which all other time-stretches, and so all other motions, are
to be measured: it provides the “standard meter” of motion.75
Now there are two ways to parse Aquinas’s view:
On (b) the motion of the outermost sphere makes time pass—in fact is
time’s passing. For on (b), for time to pass is for (say) a new day to begin,
and for a day to begin just is for a new cycle of the motion whose duration is
a day to begin. Time in a strong sense reduces to motion, and as we see
shortly, the Aristotelian first motion is causally as well as chronologically
basic. On (a), we might wonder whether the sphere’s motion really makes
time pass. For we might wonder whether, if the sun stopped revolving but
other motions continued, time would not after all continue to pass,
“powered” by other motion, which might eventually add up to the duration of
a day even without the sun. But in the cosmology Aquinas adopted from
Aristotle, the outermost sphere’s motion is what causes all else to move. If it
stopped moving, all else would, and Aquinas is explicit that in this case the
time of material things would cease.76 (There might still be angelic time.) So
given Aquinas’s Aristotelian cosmology, even on (a), the outermost sphere
powers time’s passage.
Still, Aquinas is careful to make a distinction. To Aquinas, time is of its
nature the number of the first motion, whatever that motion be. Aquinas
thinks that time is only accidentally, contingently the number of the motion
of the outermost heaven. Aquinas has biblical reasons to take seriously the
hypothesis that the outermost heaven did not begin to move at the instant of
creation. He notes that if this is so, there was time between Creation and its
beginning to move. But he adds that this time would have been the number of
whatever “first motion” then existed: “if there were another first motion, that
motion would be the measure of time, because everything is measured by the
first in its genus.”77 Thus Aquinas’s view is in fact detachable from
Aristotle’s natural science. His basic thoughts are that for nature to contain
our sort of time, there must be in the material world a clock-process to
provide a natural first unit, and that time’s passage depends on and perhaps
reduces to some physical process that powers its passage.
Still, in Aquinas’s eyes, de facto, Aristotle’s natural clock-process also
causes all else to move. For Aquinas, time is in other motions in material
nature insofar as they are all ultimately caused by the first motion of which
time is an accident:78 there is quite generally a way causes exist “in” their
effects. Moreover, Aquinas is willing to say that time is in things at rest79
insofar as they are subject to the causation of the outermost sphere, but just
happen then not to be moving. When we see that God cannot move, then, we
see that a moving now is not in Him. The outermost sphere cannot cause God
to move. Further, there is nothing else to “power” a “flow” of the now in
God’s case, unlike the angels’—and so we see that his now must stand still.
Aquinas’s thought, then, is this. A thing is in time only if it can take part
in the flow of a now. Only things that can change can take part in the flow.
For things that can change either “power” a time-flow by their changes or get
caught up in one in virtue of being able to change. God cannot change. So
when we “apprehend” this, we see that God must be atemporal. But
Aquinas’s condition for taking part in a time-flow is debatable. Why not say
instead that just given that time flows, God’s life is timed by it—that its
passage measures the length of his life even if he cannot change?
This brings us to Aquinas’s main SCG argument that God is eternal:
Only things that are moved are measured by time, for time is “the number of motion.”
But God is wholly without motion … so He is not measured by time. So … He does not
have being after non-being, nor … non-being after being, nor can any succession be
found in His being, because these cannot be understood without time. Therefore He
lacks beginning and end, having His being all at once: in which consists the nature of
eternity.80
Aquinas’s “are moved” must be read with care. Aquinas accepts that things
at rest but able to move count as temporal.81 He adds that what cannot move
is therefore not in time.82 So it is a safe bet that his argument is really
That the argument moves by way of being measured by time suggests that
it might address our lingering worry with the ST argument. Part of statement
(2) is God’s inability to move spatially, for Aquinas holds that (our sort of)
time follows upon change of place, so much so that only things in some way
in place are “measured” by (our sort of) time.83 (Aquinas considers our time
the number of local motion.84) Statement (2) also asserts Aquinas’s DDI: for
Aquinas, if God had a succession of mental operations, this would place Him
in the angels’ sort of time. But we may wonder why time so construed
measures only motions (and rest periods of movable things). Aquinas takes it
from Aristotle85 (and not implausibly) that standards for measurement must
share a kind with the items they measure.86 To measure, we establish
congruence between all or part of the item to be measured and a standard
unit. Thus, the standard must be of a sort to be congruent with the item to be
measured—it must be of its kind, so that we can lay the standard unit
alongside the measured item (literally in the case of some lengths, in other
cases figuratively). Thus, lengths can only be measured by lengths, not by
hues or pitches. If the standard for measuring time is or necessarily inheres in
a motion, Aquinas seems to think, we can only “lay that standard alongside
of” another motion: other things are measured by time only insofar as they
have motion, or can have it.87
This argument rests on sound general points—that measurement depends
on standard units and that standard units must be of the right sort to measure
what they measure. But things fall into not just kinds, but superkinds. So we
might ask why a standard unit, which is a motion, must share with what it
measures its most specific kind, motion. Why not instead a more general
kind, like change (thus bringing angels into ordinary time), event, or state?
The last, and perhaps even the next to last, might bring an immutable or even
a Boethian-eternal being into time. I suggest, then, that Aquinas has more
work to do if he is to produce a convincing argument for divine timelessness.
NOTES
1. SCG I, 89.
2. Ibid.
3. ST I-II q.23, passim.
4. SCG I, 89.
5. ST I q.20 a.1 ad 2.
6. Ibid. and SCG I, 89.
7. ST I q.63 a.2.
8. SCG I, 90–91.
9. ST I q.20 a.2.
10. SCG I, 91; ST I q.20 a.1.
11. Norman Kretzmann, The Metaphysics of Theism (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1997), 231.
12. Loci cit.
13. SCG I, 90.
14. Ibid.
15. So, e.g., QDP 1, 1.
16. CT I, 9.
17. SCG I, 16.
18. ST I q.3 a.1; CT I, 9.
19. Thus given an independent argument for immutability, one can also
argue from immutability to lack of passive potency, as Aquinas does in SCG
I, 16.
20. ST I q.2 a.3.
21. E.g. ST I q.2 a.3.
22. CT I, 9.
23. See, e.g., SCG I, 16; QDP 7, 1; ST I q.3 a.1.
24. ST I q.9 a.1.
25. ST I q.9 a.2; q.51 a.3 ad 3.
26. See, e.g., ST I q.13 a.7.
27. Aristotle, Physics V 2, 225b11, and Aquinas, In Phy, V, nos. 666–67.
28. Aquinas, loc. cit.
29. Many medievals classed relational properties as intrinsic too, but they
meant by this only that they involved real inhering “forms.” They did not
mean to call relations intrinsic in the sense this term bears in contemporary
discussion.
30. ST q.25 a.4. For a full discussion of this, see my “Aquinas, Divine
Simplicity and Divine Freedom,” in Kevin Timpe, ed., Metaphysics and God
(London: Routledge, forthcoming).
31. SCG I, 15; CT I, 5.
32. ST I q.45 a.2 ad 2 and q.46 a.3.
33. ST I q.104 a.3.
34. ST I q.10 a.1; CT I, 8.
35. Super Sent, I, d.8, q.2, a.1, corpus.
36. Rory Fox would explain this by saying that Aquinas and other
thirteenth-century thinkers deployed concepts of “non-extensional, non-
temporal types of duratio” (Rory Fox, Time and Eternity in Mid-Thirteenth
Century Thought [Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006], 37) and
sometimes used “duratio” simply to express actual existence (ibid. 36). That
they thought in terms of non-temporal duration is clear from their treatments
of angelic aeviternity, but that they thought in terms of non-extended duration
is at least in Aquinas’s case rather less clear. Fox offers as his main proof-
text for this in Aquinas’s case Super Sent 19, 2, 1, which I translate from the
text he provides (37 n. 36) as “duration attends everything according as it is
in act; a thing is said to endure for as long as it is in act, and not when it is in
potency.” The “as long as” (tamdiu … quamdiu) undermines the claim that
there is nothing extensional here.
37. Super Sent, I, d.8, q.2, a.1, ad 6.
38. Even such apparently anti-extensional texts as In Phy, VIII, l. 2, no.
990 can be read thus.
39. E.g., ST I q.10 a.5.
40. ST I q.10 a.4.
41. ST I q.10 a.1 ad 6.
42. ST I q.10 a.1 ad 5.
43. We see below that Aquinas actually has more than one kind of time in
play in his thinking, but this does not affect the present conclusion.
44. ST I q.10 a.2 ad 4.
45. e.g., CT I, 7.
46. For which reasons Brian Davies holds that Aquinas’s God is temporal
(The Thought of Thomas Aquinas [Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992],
108).
47. Obviously much would have to be said to make sense of this. For one
account, see my Time and Eternity (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press,
1991), 183–245.
48. SCG I, 66.
49. Fox, Time and Eternity, 328.
50. SCG III, 61.
51. Fox, Time and Eternity, 320.
52. Ibid. 324.
53. Ibid.
54. ST I q.63 a.7 ad 4.
55. ST I q.53 a.1.
56. ST I q.8 a.3.
57. SCG I, 15.
58. CT I, 7.
59. Ibid.
60. CT I, 8. This bit of the reasoning recurs in SCG I, 15.
61. In Phy, IV, l. 20, no. 609.
62. ST I q.13 a.7.
63. ST I q.10 a.2, resp. and ad 2.
64. He is also a presentist: he believes that in time, only the present exists
(ST I q.47 a.1 ad 3; In Phy, IV, l. 32, no. 629).
65. So, prominently, Richard Taylor on “absolute becoming” (see, e.g., his
Metaphysics, 4th ed. [Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1992], 82–83).
66. In Phy, IV, l. 18, no. 587.
67. For texts and discussion, see J. MacIntosh, “St. Thomas on Angelic
Time and Motion,” The Thomist 59 (1995): 547–75.
68. ST I q.10 a.6; Super Sent II, d.2, q.1, a.2.
69. So, e.g., De ente et essentia, c.6.
70. Super Sent, I, d.37, q.4, a.3.
71. SCG III, 61.
72. In Phy, IV, l. 18, nos. 585–86; Super Sent, I, d.37, q.4, a.3.
73. e.g., SCG I, 15.
74. In Phy, IV, l. 23, no. 634.
75. Super Sent, II, d.2, q.1, a.2, ad 1.
76. QDP 5, 5, ad 11.
77. ST I q.66 a.4 ad 3.
78. In Phy, IV, l. 17, no. 574.
79. QDP 5, 5, ad 10; In Phy, IV, l. 20, no. 608.
80. S. Thomae Aquinatis Summa Contra Gentiles (Turin: Marietti, 1909),
1:15, p. 15, my translation. SCG is a bit puzzling; along with this occur two
arguments that seem to conclude that God is everlasting and two whose
conclusions seem indifferent between being everlasting and being atemporal.
81. QDP 5, 5, ad 10. For Aristotle, see Physics IV, 11, 221b7–14.
82. QDP 5, 5, ad 10.
83. SCG II, 96.
84. In Phy, IV, l. 18, no. 587.
85. Metaphysics, bk. 10, 1053a24 ff.
86. In Phy, IV, l. 20, no. 601. This implies that items of different genus
must have different measures, a point Aquinas applies in a related context in
Super Sent, II, d. 2, q. 2, a. 1c.
87. QDP 5, 5, ad 10; In Phy, IV, l. 20, no. 602. I am unsure that Aquinas
and Aristotle are really entitled to the claim that time measures the duration
of rest, but I cannot pursue this here.
CHAPTER 14
GOD’S OMNIPOTENCE
BRIAN LEFTOW
THE doctrine that God is omnipotent takes its rise from scriptural texts:
These texts concern two linked topics. One is how much power God has to
put behind actions: enough that nothing is too hard, enough to do whatever
he pleases. Let us call this “how strong God is.” The other is the range of
action in which he can use this power, that is, how much God can do: “all
things.” Christian accounts of omnipotence prior to Aquinas focused mainly
on how much power God has.1 In contemporaries like Bonaventure, talk of
range became a bit more prominent but was still only one note among many.
Aquinas offers a pure range definition of omnipotence, in which the strength
notion is absent. Scotus and Ockham followed Aquinas. So has almost every
account of omnipotence since. The move can fairly be called one of
Aquinas’s most enduring contributions to philosophical theology.
a. God needs no help from anything else to produce his effects—it is not
limited by dependence on another;
b. nor does what might receive his effects limit his power, as no recipient
is necessary;
c. nor does any intrinsic limitation in his being limit his effects;
d. the number of his effects is unlimited—no matter how many he has had,
there can always be more; and
e. its intensity is unlimited—no matter how intense his action, it can
always be more intense.2
Statement (a) implies a strength point, since one way something can need
help is by being not strong enough to produce what it tries to. Statement (b)
implies the same one, since one way something can help in producing an
effect is by being what receives an agent’s power. Aquinas’s thought about
(c) seems to be this: as I have the being of a man, I can produce only a man’s
effects. God has no such limitation because his being is not received into a
particular nature distinct from itself, but is instead identical with his nature
and himself. Statement (d) involves range, but also strength, since we
measure strength by what it can effect. Statement (e) is clearly a strength
notion.
The infinity of God’s strength, Aquinas suggests, is the cause, not the very
nature, of his omnipotence.3 Since Aquinas’s doctrine of divine simplicity
rules out taking him to mean that infinite strength is one attribute and
omnipotence is a second distinct attribute that supervenes on it, his point is
that we can explain the range of God’s power by its infinity. His ST
explanation focuses on (c):
To every active power corresponds a possible being as its proper object, according to the
nature of that act in which the active power is founded, as the power to heat is referred
to the being able to be heated as its proper object. The divine being, on which the nature
of the divine power is founded, is unlimited being, not limited to some genus of being …
whence whatever can be is contained under those possible beings in respect of which
God is called omnipotent.4
Hot things, qua hot, can heat heatable things; by analogy unreceived,
unlimited being, being-itself, can cause to be be-able things—absolutely
possible things.
More than an argument by analogy can be had by way of (d). Strength
could be limited in its effect by needing help, a receiver, and so on, or by
lack of knowledge and other intrinsic restrictions. If none of these apply,
whatever one is strong enough to bring about, one can bring about, given
only suitable opportunity. How much is God strong enough to bring about?
Consider the field of all that is in any way possible. No matter what of this
we begin by saying God is strong enough to bring about, if there is more left
of it, then per (d), God is able to bring about still more, given opportunity.
The infinity of (d) thus pushes the range of God’s power outward till it
finally coincides with the range of the possible.
TO A DEFINITION
That this is God’s range of effects hardly implies that being omnipotent
consists solely of having this range of effects. But neither Scripture nor
Creed define omnipotence, and so Aquinas, like all others, is free to offer
what account he will. Aquinas gives his account this way:
whatever things … do not imply a contradiction are contained among those possible
things with respect to which God is called omnipotent … God is called omnipotent
because He can do all absolutely possible things.5
But this is not right. SCG II, 25 lists many things we can do but God cannot
—alter his own being, move, change, fail, tire, forget, be defeated, repent, be
angry, sorrow. God cannot do these because God by his nature cannot have
“passive potencies,” abilities to be changed. For Aquinas, God necessarily
wills himself to be, be good, be happy, and so cannot produce the contrary
volitions, though we can. Again, God cannot will evil.8 So the “can do”
formulation, in terms of tasks or powers, is not perspicuous for what Aquinas
has in mind. Perhaps Aquinas would say that for God to do these things
would be to bring about a contradiction, that a being with no passive
potencies acts in ways that entail having passive potencies, or a necessarily
good being does evil, or a necessarily happy being is not happy.
The first part of the quoted text (“God is omnipotent”) might suggest that
for Aquinas,
2. God is omnipotent = df. God can bring about all states of affairs not
involving contradictions.
But this is not quite right either. SCG II, 25 adds that God cannot act contrary
to the nature of being or of made being: his power is to make beings, and any
power can produce only what its nature encodes—the power to heat produces
heat, and the power to produce beings produces made beings. So what cannot
be a made being, or a being, cannot be produced, and so God cannot produce
it. Contrary to being made are making God (who is uncreated), making
something equal to God (since it is better to be underived than derived), or
making a thing God did not make and preserve. The “being made” addition
suggests that Aquinas’s definition of omnipotence is really:
3. God is omnipotent = df. God can bring about all states of affairs
producible without a contradiction following.
His examples also suggest that Aquinas is really concerned with what we
would call broad metaphysical impossibility, which he takes to be
coextensive with that whose contradictory implies a contradiction. The
twentieth century has made this claim of coextension controversial.
Statement (3) does not say by whom these states of affairs are producible; it
commits Aquinas to God’s being able to produce anything anyone else can
produce. This creates at least one obvious worry: I can produce my free
actions, but how can God? What is necessarily so is possibly so. And it is not
obvious that the necessary cannot be produced without a contradiction
following. So it might seem that Aquinas’s definition implies that God can
produce necessary states of affairs, that is, that 2 + 2 = 4. But Aquinas does
not mean this. “Possible” was sometimes used for “contingent” in Aquinas’s
day, and he undoubtedly means to restrict omnipotence to range over the
contingent: for him, God himself is the truthmaker for all necessary truths,
and so God could produce the necessary just if he could produce himself.9
Thus, for Aquinas, the necessary falls under the nonproducible. Aquinas does
not need a separate clause to rule it out.
Still, even (3) does not quite capture Aquinas’s intent. Surprisingly,
though he thinks God is outside time, Aquinas wants to relativize
omnipotence to times, and hold that what an omnipotent being can bring
about varies with what time it is. There are things God is too late to bring
about, for example, that the Germans won World War II. It is absolutely
possible that they have done so. But for Aquinas, it is now impossible that
anyone, even God, bring it about. Aquinas thinks that what is producible
without a contradiction following changes as time passes, as I will explain
shortly. This does not imply that God’s power changes intrinsically. Rather,
at some times certain things are absolutely possible, and later they are not
because their contradictories are past.10 With this in view, Aquinas’s real
account of omnipotence is that
4. God is omnipotent at t = df. God can bring about all states of affairs
producible at t without a contradiction following.
WHY NONCONTRADICTION?
Statement (4) prompts us to ask why Aquinas “limits” omnipotence to what
does not entail a contradiction. Descartes, after all, is at least reputed to have
seen this as not power enough for God. One argument in Aquinas takes its
rise from the claim that contradictory states of affairs are literally
inconceivable, even by God.11 If God cannot conceive them, God cannot will
to make them obtain: what cannot be grasped by the intellect cannot be
willed, since the will is of the understood good.12 And what God cannot will,
he cannot produce, since he can do nothing save by willing it.
Let us ask, then, why Aquinas thinks contradictions cannot be conceived
to be true. Aquinas writes in his Sentence commentary that “what is being
and not-being, neither is being nor not-being.”13 He expands the thought a bit
in de Potentia: a contradiction not only cannot have the nature of being, but
cannot even have the nature of nonbeing, because “being removes non-being
and non-being removes being.”14 If this is true, it is impossible to picture
what would be so were a contradiction true. Picturing that P or that ¬P is the
case does not picture both being true at once. Superimposing a mental picture
of a P-world on one of a ¬P-world would not give one a grip on a P and ¬P
world either, as Aquinas sees it. For in his eyes, a P and ¬P world could not
be even determinately both. We now distinguish negation and denial.
Negation is a feature of the content of a proposition—the feature which
makes the difference between P and ¬P. Denial is something we do with or
to propositions, removing what they say from our picture of the world.
Aquinas seems to run the two together. He seems to think of someone who
says “not P” not as asserting that ¬P but as denying that P, expressing a
mental operation of removal. So in Aquinas’s eyes, to conceive a
contradiction, one would have not to superimpose a mental picture of a P-
world on one of a ¬P-world, but simultaneously to add P to and subtract P
from one’s world picture. What it is to add and subtract makes it the case that
there is no such thing as the product of such an intellectual operation. So we
can see why Aquinas writes in ST that a contradiction does not count as a
“word”—a possible product of intellectual conception.15 As he sees it, a
contradictory sentence just does not express anything definite for an intellect
to grasp.
But this leads to a deeper line of thought. For if this is so, a contradictory
sentence does not really express any state of affairs, even a contradictory one.
To Aquinas, this is not because of some limitation of language or mind. It is
because to construct a contradictory state of affairs, one would have to at
once posit and remove the same state of affairs. There is no state of affairs
that is the being posited and removed of some state of affairs. And so a
contradiction cannot be true because there is no state of affairs whose being
actual would make it true. A contradictory state of affairs cannot be possible
because there is no state of affairs there to bear the modality of possibility.
Of course, given this line of reasoning, Aquinas could as easily say that a
contradictory state of affairs cannot be impossible: that too is a modality. But
what is straightforwardly impossible is that a contradictory sentence
standardly interpreted express something true, there being nothing there for it
to express when so interpreted, or something the mind can grasp.16
On this line of thought, God cannot will that a contradiction be true, in the
end, because contradictory sentences are just a sort of nonsense: they express
no proposition to will to be true. But the suggestion that this somehow limits
God is worth resisting. If there just is not such a thing as a contradictory state
of affairs, a God who cannot bring about contradictory states of affairs may
nonetheless literally be able to bring about every state of affairs there is. This
will be so if every absolute impossibility involves a contradiction. Aquinas
asserts this in QDP 1, 3: they all “imply affirmation and negation to be at
once.”17 If this is right, then for Aquinas, again, there is nothing beyond
God’s power, to be the place it cannot go.
Aquinas’s line of thought generates a subordinate metaphysical account of
why God can produce only noncontradictory states of affairs. It is a fact
about causation, Aquinas thinks, that every agent produces effects that are
somehow like itself.18 God’s nature is his existence, and existence itself: God
is esse-ipsum. Thus, all of God’s possible effects must resemble him at least
in being beings. Contradictory states of affairs cannot be beings, for reasons
we have seen. So they cannot be like God in even this way. So they cannot be
divine products.19 This account depends on the fact about causation and
Aquinas’s distinctive understanding of negation. I do not recall a text in
which Aquinas explains either further. The fact about causation could have
its roots in God’s own nature. Perhaps it is a primitive fact about God’s
nature that he can produce only his like. And perhaps it is another that
nothing other than himself can exist unless he produces it. Perhaps this
determines what other agents can be. For God can only produce his like, and
while this is obviously compatible with producing things unlike him in many
ways, perhaps this is one way in which his effects must be very like him:
perhaps it is a primitive fact about God’s power that he can produce only
things that (like him) can produce only their like. So as there cannot be
anything God has not produced, there cannot be an agent not thus
constrained, and so what “began” as a fact about God’s nature ends up a
general theorem about the nature of causality.
NOTES
1. For a survey, see my “Omnipotence,” in Thomas Flint and Michael
Rea, eds., The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, forthcoming).
2. QDP 1, 2.
3. QDP 1, 7.
4. ST I q.25 a.3, 174a21–34.
5. ST I q.25 a.3, 174a12–20, 42–45. Cf. QDP 1, 7.
6. ST I q.25 a.3.
7. Among others, Daniel Hill so reads him (Daniel Hill, Divinity and
Maximal Greatness [London: Routledge, 2005], 131).
8. SCG I, 95.
9. For an account of this, see my “Aquinas on God and Modal Truth,”
Modern Schoolman 82:3 (2005): 171–200.
10. ST I q.25 a.4 ad 2. Geach suggests that the account of q.25 a.3 is
inconsistent with allowing that God’s power varies over time (Peter Geach,
Providence and Evil [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977], 19). In
Aquinas’s eyes, at least, it is not, because what is producible changes with
time.
11. QDP 1, 3, ad 1 opp.; ST I q.25 a.3; Quodl V, q.2, a.3.
12. SCG I, 84.
13. Super Sent I, d.42, q.2, a.2, p. 991.
14. QDP 1, 3, p. 9. So also SCG II, 25. Yet he also says in SCG II, 22 that
things which imply a contradiction include nonbeing in their ratio. Perhaps
Aquinas has one account of things that are contradictions and another of
things that are not themselves self-contradictory but imply contradictions.
15. ST I q.25 a.3.
16. The qualification “standardly interpreted” allows for this sort of silly
counterexample: if I decided to use the sentence “P and not P” to express the
claim that I am a philosopher, it would express something true.
17. QDP 1, 3, p. 9.
18. Ibid.
19. QDP 1, 3; SCG I, 84.
20. QDP 1, 3, ad 9; ST I q.25 a.4.
21. QDP 1, 6, ad 1 and ST I q.25 a.3 ad 2.
22. ST I q.25 a.3 ad 2.
23. Contra Eric Funkhouser, “On Privileging God’s Moral Goodness,”
Faith and Philosophy 23 (2006): 412.
PART IV
THOMAS WILLIAMS
Since every thing desires (appetat) its own perfection, what someone desires as an
ultimate end is what he desires qua perfecting and completing him.… For that reason, an
ultimate end must so fulfill a person’s whole desire that nothing more is left for him to
desire; and that cannot be so if something additional is required for him to be perfect.
And that is why desire cannot aim at two [distinct] things as if each were its perfect
good.3
This single ultimate end can be an aggregate of goods that the agent regards
as collectively constituting his perfection; the arguments of a.5 do not
commit Aquinas to understanding the ultimate end as a unitary good.
This ultimate end, whether unitary or aggregate, must be (Aquinas argues)
the ultimate explanation for all of a given person’s actions. For whatever the
agent desires, she desires sub ratione boni: under the notion or aspect of the
good. Now if something is not desired as the complete, all-inclusive good
(that is, the ultimate good), it must be desired as aiming at or leading to the
complete, all-inclusive good. The “as” does not mean that an agent will
always be thinking of the ultimate end in every action she performs, any
more than someone on a journey must be consciously thinking about her
destination in order to be truly said to be aiming at that destination. But the
desire for the ultimate end is what explains every other desire. The ultimate
end is the first mover of desire, and secondary movers—that is, any desirable
objects other than the ultimate end—move desire only in virtue of their
relation to the ultimate end, whether the agent is thinking explicitly about
that relation or not. As Aquinas puts it, “the power of the first intention,
which is of the ultimate end, remains in any desire of any object whatever,
even if one is not actually thinking of the ultimate end.”4
Finally, Aquinas argues that this ultimate explanation for all actions is the
same for every human being. All human beings have the same ultimate end,
for all human beings desire their own perfection, though different people will
have different ideas about what perfection consists in. So Aquinas says that
all human beings have the same ultimate end as far as the intelligible formula
for the ultimate end goes (secundum rationem ultimi finis), but not in terms
of the object that people think is aptly described by that formula (secundum
id in quo finis ultimi ratio invenitur).
To summarize: Aquinas argues in the first question of ST I-II that (a) all
human actions are performed for the sake of an end; (b) any given human
action has one and only one ultimate end; (c) this one ultimate end is the
same for all of a given human being’s actions; and indeed (d) all human
beings have the same ultimate end. Interpreters of Aquinas have disagreed
about how to construe each of these claims, but the most widely divergent
readings concern (b) and (c). The most obvious way of taking (b) and (c) is
as descriptive claims about the psychology of human actions. But when taken
as descriptive claims, (b) and (c) strike many interpreters as flatly
indefensible. We may take Jean Porter’s objection as representative:
Not many of us have the self-possession, or the fanaticism, to shape our whole lives
around devotion to some one object, cause, or ideal. And even those few of us who do
cannot be said literally to direct all our actions toward one end. Even the most dedicated
individuals indulge in an ice-cream cone or a joke once in a while.… Let me say at once
that if Aquinas does indeed claim that each person always directs all her actions and
activities toward some one goal or idea, then I do not see how that claim could be
defended.5
In light of such reservations about (b) and (c) taken as descriptive claims,
some interpreters argue that what Aquinas sets forth in the opening question
of I-II is normative rather than descriptive: his claims “state criteria of fully
rational action, and the arguments for them draw attention to what is required
by the concept of rational action,”6 as Scott MacDonald puts it. On this
interpretation Aquinas is not denying that human beings sometimes act
without having a single ultimate end in view, but instead saying that such
actions are not fully rational and therefore not fully human. As Porter,
another defender of the normative reading, says, this analysis “leaves room to
admit that some behaviors which do not meet this ideal can still be said to be
rational, and hence truly human actions, albeit in a derivative sense.”7
A third interpretation is possible, according to which Aquinas’s claims in
the opening question of I-II are neither descriptive nor normative, but
explanatory. That is, Aquinas is analyzing the metaphysical preconditions for
human action. His arguments for a single ultimate end are akin to his
arguments for a single unmoved mover or uncaused cause; they are at bottom
neither psychological descriptions nor conceptual analysis, but quia
arguments intended to trace the phenomena of human action to their ultimate
explanation in a good that awakens desire, and thereby initiates action, in its
own right and not in the power of any other good. The natural desire for
perfection explains why we desire anything at all. Since every human being
has this desire, every human action is ultimately to be explained with
reference to one and the same ultimate end—though, owing to the
variabilities of human reason, different people will seek their fulfillment in
different objects or states.
On Aquinas’s view, the will cannot, by any innate capacity, direct the intellect’s
attention, keep the intellect from issuing judgments about what one ought to do, or keep
itself from willing what the intellect has determined one ought to will. Nor can it select
one from among a variety of alternatives unless the intellect has first settled on that one
as the alternative to be pursued. Which, if any, of a set of objects the will wills, and
whether it wills anything at all, depends not on any voluntaristic capacity of the will, but
on how the intellect judges the object in question.18
In the process that leads to action, the intellect is not in the business of
making judgments of the form “Here’s an ice-cream cone: take it or leave it
—or look around for something else” and then leaving it up to the will to
make the choice. The intellect offers a verdict: a iudicium or sententia. And
the will, being nothing more than the appetitive arm of the intellectual soul,
elects in accordance with the intellect’s judgment. As in a one-party
totalitarian state, by the time there’s an election, there’s only one name on the
ballot.
for those effects that he willed to be necessary, he provided necessary causes; and for
those effects that he willed to be contingent, he ordained causes that act contingently,
which is to say, causes that can fall short [of producing an effect]. It is in accordance
with this characteristic of their causes that effects are called either necessary or
contingent, even though they are all dependent on the divine will as their first cause.…
God’s will cannot fail, but nevertheless not all its effects are necessary; some are
contingent.25
God’s activity as first cause does not override the characteristic manner of
acting that belongs to the natures he created. He moves natural causes in such
a way that their effects are natural, and he moves voluntary causes in such a
way that their effects are voluntary: “He acts in each thing in accordance
with its distinctive character.”26
NOTES
1. ST I-II q.1 a.1. All translations are my own.
2. Eleonore Stump, Aquinas (London and New York: Routledge, 2003),
278.
3. ST I-II q.1 a.5. One might well think that the argument as a whole is
question-begging, since the claim that “what one desires as an ultimate end is
what he desires qua perfecting and completing him” follows from the claim
that “every thing desires its own perfection” only if we interpret the latter as
meaning something like “every thing desires only its own perfection”—but
on that interpretation, the argument already presupposes the very unity of
desire that it purports to establish. For further analysis of Aquinas’s
arguments in the opening questions of ST I-II, see Peter F. Ryan, “Must the
Acting Person Have a Single Ultimate End?” Gregorianum 82 (2001): 325–
56.
4. ST I-II q.1 a.6 ad 3.
5. Jean Porter, The Recovery of Virtue: The Relevance of Aquinas for
Christian Ethics (Louisville: Westminster/John Knox Press, 1990), 72–73.
6. Scott MacDonald, “Ultimate Ends in Practical Reasoning: Aquinas’s
Aristotelian Moral Psychology and Anscombe’s Fallacy,” Philosophical
Review 100 (1991): 31–66, at 40. Peter F. Ryan, “A Single Ultimate End
Only for ‘Fully Rational’ Agents? A Critique of Scott MacDonald’s
Interpretation of Aquinas,” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 75
(2001): 433–38, argues that Aquinas is neither making empirical claims nor
analyzing the concept of fully rational action, but “trying to articulate a
necessary condition for human action as such, a condition that he thinks
follows from just what a human act is” (438). Ryan emphasizes, however,
that Aquinas’s view is empirically falsified if there are any cases of human
action that do not meet the necessary condition, and he argues in “Must the
Acting Person Have a Single Ultimate End?” that there are such cases.
7. Porter, Recovery of Virtue, 73.
8. Aquinas denies that voluntas is in general a necessary consequence of
the intellectual apprehension of something as an end. I take up the issue of
necessity and contingency in human action in the last section.
9. For an incisive explanation of the problems with translating electio as
“choice,” see Stump, Aquinas, 288–89.
10. This is what Aquinas calls “perfect fruitio,” as opposed to the
“imperfect fruitio” that one can have regarding an end that is “possessed only
in intention.” See ST I-II q.11 a.4.
11. Or rather, it sets out one possible, and fairly mainstream, reading of the
Treatise on Human Acts. For a sampling of the variety of interpretations in
recent scholarship, see Thomas Gilby, trans. and ed., Summa theologiae, vol.
17 (Cambridge: Blackfriars, 1970), Appendix 1; Alan Donagan, “Thomas
Aquinas on Human Action,” in Norman Kretzmann, Anthony Kenny, and
Jan Pinborg, eds., The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 642–54; Ralph McInerny,
Aquinas on Human Action: A Theory of Practice (Washington, D.C.: The
Catholic University of America Press, 1992), ch. 3; Daniel Westberg, Right
Practical Reason: Aristotle, Action, and Prudence in Aquinas (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1994), Part III; Stephen L. Brock, Action and Conduct:
Thomas Aquinas and the Theory of Action (Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 1998);
Stump, Aquinas, 287–94.
12. ST I-II q.15 a.3 ad 3.
13. ST I-II q.14 a.4, especially ad 1.
14. ST II-II q.156 a.1.
15. Donagan, “Thomas Aquinas on Human Action,” 654.
16. Stump, Aquinas, 278.
17. For interpretations that find some degree of voluntarism in Aquinas,
see, e.g., David Gallagher, “Free Choice and Free Judgment in Thomas
Aquinas,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 76 (1994): 247–77;
Eleonore Stump and Norman Kretzmann, “Absolute Simplicity,” Faith and
Philosophy 2 (1985): 353–82; John Finnis, “Object and Intention in Moral
Judgments according to Aquinas,” The Thomist 55 (1991): 1–27; Bonnie
Kent, Virtues of the Will: The Transformation of Ethics in the Late Thirteenth
Century (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press,
1995).
18. Jeffrey Hause, “Thomas Aquinas and the Voluntarists,” Medieval
Philosophy and Theology 6 (1997): 167–82, at 168. See also Scott
MacDonald, “Aquinas’s Libertarian Account of Free Choice,” Revue
Internationale de Philosophie 2 (1998): 309–28.
19. See Gallagher, “Free Choice and Free Judgment in Thomas Aquinas,”
for an argument of this kind, and Hause, “Thomas Aquinas and the
Voluntarists,” for a rebuttal.
20. Scott MacDonald, “Aquinas’s Libertarian Account of Free Choice,”
Revue Internationale de Philosophie 2 (1998): 309–28 defends this sort of
reading of Aquinas.
21. Peter van Inwagen, Metaphysics, 2d ed. (Boulder, Colo.: Westview
Press, 2002), 203.
22. Note that in QDM 6, ad 10, Aquinas says that the will’s not being
necessitated with respect to specification by any incomplete good is just like
the intellect’s not being necessitated with respect to specification by any
contingent truth. No one takes it that Aquinas is denying determinism with
respect to any particular intellectual act in which someone affirms a
contingent truth. Why then should any take it that Aquinas is denying
determinism with respect to any particular volitional act in which someone
elects a partial good?
23. Eleonore Stump, “Aquinas’s Account of Freedom: Intellect and Will,”
The Monist 80 (1997): 591–94 and Aquinas, 299–306, argues for this
understanding of Aquinas’s views.
24. QDP, q.3, a.7. Cf. SCG 3, c.66–67, 70.
25. In Peri herm. 1, lec. 14.
26. ST I q.83 a.1 ad 3.
CHAPTER 16
EMOTIONS
PETER KING
Since the body is altered due to an operation of the soul in the case of emotion, it must
be the sort of power that is joined to a bodily organ and whose function it is to alter the
body. Hence emotion is not in the intellective part [of the soul], which does not pertain
to the actualization of some bodily organ. Nor again is it in sensitive apprehension, since
from sense-apprehension there follows movement in the body only through the
mediation of the appetitive power, which is the immediate moving cause.8
An animal must seek out or avoid some things not merely because they are suitable or
unsuitable to the senses, but according to certain other uses and advantages or
disadvantages. For example, a sheep seeing an approaching wolf runs away—not due to
its unsightly colour or shape, but as if it were a natural enemy. Likewise, a bird collects
straw not because it is pleasing to sense but because it is useful for building a nest. Thus
it is necessary for an animal to perceive intentiones of this sort, which the exterior senses
do not perceive. There must be some distinct principle … the proper sense and the
common sense are appointed for the reception of sensible forms, but the estimative
power (uis aestimatiua) is appointed for apprehending intentiones, which are not
received through sensing.13
The object of the animal’s cognitive act, be it the wolf for the sheep or the
straw for the bird, is also perceived under some intentio or other: the sheep
perceives the wolf as a natural enemy, the bird perceives the straw as useful
in the construction of a nest.14 These are not perceptible properties. The
wolf’s dangerousness is not perceived the way its “unsightly color” is. Yet
the emphasis Aquinas puts on intentiones not being perceptible properties—
to the extent of postulating a distinct psychological faculty to perceive them
at all—is misleading. After all, no dispositional property is strictly speaking
perceptible: rationality, ferociousness, fragility, and the like are not apparent
to the exterior senses alone. (Neither is the wolfhood of the wolf, or in
general the substance of anything.) No wonder that friendliness or hatred are
not perceptible.15 Yet far more important for Aquinas’s purposes is his
recognition that intentiones are what we should call today evaluative
response-dependent concepts. The sheep regards the wolf as a threat, and the
bird regards straw as useful, because of the kind of thing each is. The sheep
does not regard straw as useful, since it does not build nests of straw; the bird
does not regard the wolf as a threat (or as much of one), since it can easily fly
away. At bottom this is a built-in capacity: “animals perceive these sorts of
intentiones only through a kind of natural instinct,”16 though it may be
modified through conditioning and habituation, as when the family watchdog
learns that strangers are the only proper targets of its anger, or, in the case of
human beings, through the exercise of higher faculties (as we shall see
shortly). For now let us take the point that such evaluative response-
dependent concepts occur after acts of simple cognition.
Aquinas offers a few examples of intentiones: the sheep perceives the
wolf as inimical, the bird perceives the straw as useful, or vaguely
“advantages and disadvantages.” Now it might be thought that these are a
motley collection as varied as the nature of evaluation itself (“evaluation”
being the root meaning of aestimatio). But there is a general way to describe
intentiones as such, that is, a way to characterize anything that is to count as
an intentio at all, much the way that for anything to count as visible it must
have color.17 It is sensible good or evil, where “sensible” refers to the
subject’s perception of its object as good or as evil.18 Hence, an intentio must
present some thing to its subject as a good or as an evil in some fashion.
When the sheep perceives the approaching wolf, it may evaluate the wolf as a
danger—that is, as an imminent evil—which is hard to avoid.19 The initial
simple cognition of the wolf is augmented with this evaluative response-
dependent cognition, each cognition arguably caused by the wolf, or more
exactly by the wolf given the natures of the wolf and the sheep.
So much for the cognitive side of things. At this point there is a hand-off
to the sensitive appetite: “the lower appetitive power does not naturally tend
to anything until after that thing has been presented to it under the aspect of
its proper object,”20 since in the case of animals “the sensitive appetite is apt
to be moved by the estimative power, as when a sheep esteems a wolf as
inimical and is then afraid.”21 The sensitive appetite, as a passive power, is
reduced from potency to act when it “inherits” objectual content from the
evaluative response-dependent concept (which is the actualization of the
estimative power). That is to say, the sheep has an act of the sensitive
appetite directed at the wolf, which is presented to the sensitive appetite as a
hard-to-avoid imminent evil. This “proper object” therefore has a double
causal role. On the one hand, it reduces the sensitive appetite from potency to
act and is thereby an efficient cause of the resulting act. On the other hand, it
makes the resulting act be the kind of act it is and is thereby its formal cause.
For the resulting act of the sensitive appetite is the emotion of fear when it is
caused by the formal object the wolf as a hard-to-avoid imminent evil, with
the appropriate associated somatic responses. If an object were presented as a
hard-to-attain imminent good, say, the way the sheep might appear to the
wolf, the act of the wolf’s sensitive appetite would be hope.
Emotions are therefore objectual, since the sensitive appetite is the passive
recipient of the causal and formal agency of the external principle, the wolf
in the case of the fearful sheep.
Aquinas is therefore a cognitivist about emotion, since cognitive acts are
not only causal preconditions of emotion, but contribute their formal causes
as well. The emotion is not the feeling alone: it literally would not be the
emotion it is without the formal object it has, and there would be no emotion
at all in the absence of a formal object. This is not to say that there cannot be
“objectless” states of the sort that are so important to contemporary
philosophy, such as angst, dread, or boredom, but that they are not to be
understood as emotions: they are rather akin to moods, somatic states that
influence psychological states.22 Despite being a cognitivist, however,
Aquinas is also an externalist. For the pair of cognitive acts do not in
themselves have motivational force: they act as efficient and final causes of
the acts of the sensitive appetite, which do motivate the agent, but even the
evaluative judgment implicit in the response-dependent conception of
something as a good or an evil does not cause responsive action directly.
The point is important, because the causal link between cognition and
appetite is more complicated in the case of human beings. Even in the case of
animals such as sheep, the “natural tendency” or “instinct” to respond
emotionally in a certain way can be tempered and perhaps even changed by
conditioning and habituation. The extent to which this is possible depends on
the type of animal, and perhaps even on the particular animal. Kittens and
puppies raised together often remain quite friendly with one another as cats
and dogs, though they respond in more traditional ways to unknown dogs and
cats; sheep, on the other hand, might never learn to be tolerant of wolves, no
matter how tame. The strength of the causal linkage in each animal, and its
susceptibility to conditioning and to habituation, make all the difference, and
these are matters for empirical investigation.
Human beings have higher cognitive faculties, and, in consequence, a
more complex and sophisticated emotional life. For one thing, instead of an
estimative power, humans have a general “cogitative power,” which is
sometimes called “particular reason” on the grounds that it combines
individual or particular intentiones.23 Aquinas says little about human
cogitative power, and nothing about what it is to “combine” intentiones. Nor
do the details really matter. What does matter to Aquinas is that thinking and
reasoning affect the evaluative response-dependent concepts that trigger the
sensitive appetite, and that human “cogitative power” is involved in the
process.
We can now turn to the second of the two questions posed at the start of
this section, namely the extent to which cognition can influence and control
emotions.24 We have already seen that some nonhuman animals are
susceptible to conditioning. And, like other animals, humans have some
instinctual emotional responses (fear of falling) and some habituated
responses (pleasure at the sight of a loved one). But human beings, unlike
animals, have an extensive and rich set of conceptual resources that can be
deployed even at the level of mere conditioning: the botanist’s instant delight
at recognizing an unknown species; the anger that follows upon a perceived
slight in a complex but thoroughly assimilated code of honor; and so on.25
Nor is it merely a matter of human beings having a larger conceptual
apparatus; human beings are much less tied to their present circumstances,
being better able to imagine things in other places and at other times, and in
addition are able to conceptualize the world in a universal, rather than merely
a particular, way. They can hope for a happier afterlife, become angry at the
memory of a rebuke, love wisdom, hate spiders, be saddened at the loss of
the sculptures of Phidias—all beyond the capacity of animals.
Aquinas mentions two ways in which human emotion is “cognitively
penetrable,” that is, capable of being consciously affected by changes in
belief or thought after the quasi-instinctual initial response of the sensitive
appetite.26 For although an emotional response “is not completely in our
power since it precedes the judgment of reason, it is in our power to some
extent.”27 First, we can imaginatively present one and the same thing in
different lights, via the imagination, and thereby trigger different emotional
responses.28 The divorced spouse can think of the former partner with love or
hatred, depending on which past situations and events are recalled or
imagined. Likewise, the imagination can provoke emotional responses by the
force of what it imagines. Aquinas offers the example of a believer who
reflects on punishment in the afterlife: “imagining the fire burning and the
worm gnawing and the like, there follows the emotion of fear in his sensitive
appetite.”29 Since deliberate imagination of this sort is in the agent’s
conscious control, it is clear that some emotions are indirectly subject to the
control of reason—though it is a bit like controlling digestion by being able
to pick and choose what one eats.
Second, Aquinas notes that the intellect can influence emotion: “anyone
can experience for himself that by applying some universal considerations,
anger or fear or the like can then be mitigated or even stirred up.”30
Reminding oneself of general truths can affect the understanding of a
particular situation. Grief over the death of a friend can be mitigated by
thinking of the general truth that we all die; confidence can increase by the
thought that only the brave deserve the fair; and so on. Here Aquinas is
somewhat hamstrung by his view that the intellect is the realm of the
universal, whereas sense is the realm of the particular; if we allow him to
relax his strict insistence on this dividing principle, then there are all sorts of
ways in which intellectual cognition can (attempt to) influence one’s
emotions: thinking about the stringent air-safety regulations in place in order
to curb one’s fear of flying, for example, or thinking about how even lesser
lights have been awarded the Nobel Prize in order to boost one’s hopes. The
factor in common in all these cases is that the emotional responses seem to
follow (when they follow at all) merely upon having the thoughts.
Such techniques do not always lead to success. For the emotions do not
always submit to the dictates of reason or imagination; they are unruly and
may resist their commands.31 Yet strictly speaking, it is not the role of reason
to “command” at all. That is the province not of cognition, but of the
intellective appetite, that is, the will.
Aquinas argues that emotion is the province of the sensitive rather than
the intellective appetite on the grounds that the latter, like the intellect itself,
has a purely nonphysical operation.32 Yet just as in the case of cognition, the
presence of higher intellective faculties allows human beings to influence
their emotions in ways that are not open to animals, though not to dictate
them; we cannot simply choose not to have an emotional response, though
we can have some effect on what that response might be. Aquinas describes
three ways in which this can happen.
First, the sensitive appetite is subordinate to the will, and this
subordination affects the kinds of emotions that accompany volition:
In the case of powers that are connected and ordered to one another, it happens that an
intense movement in one of them (and especially in the higher one) overflows into the
other. Accordingly, when the movement of the will is directed to something through
choice, even the [emotions] follow this movement of the will.33
Concupiscible Irascible
Passions Passions
[simple Hope-
Love-Hate
tendency] Despair
Desire- Confidence-
[movement]
Aversion Fear
Joy-Sorrow [repose] Anger
CONCLUSION
The last section might well lead one to wonder about Aquinas’s theoretical
aims, if he is neither giving us quite an empirical theory founded on
observation nor a taxonomic genera-species classificatory scheme. There is
much to say about the sense in which Aquinas offers us a theory of emotion,
but perhaps the best way to approach the issue is to see how his theory is
related to contemporary theories of emotion.
We have already seen that Aquinas is a cognitivist (of sorts) about
emotion, a finding that puts him with the majority of philosophical treatments
of emotion in the last fifty years. But the discussion in the first section gives
us an even closer comparison. Given the role played in the psychological
economy by sensitive cognition, on the one side, and by sensitive appetite, on
the other side, it is clear that Aquinas’s account of the emotions is in many
ways like contemporary “perception theories” of emotion.44 Such perception-
theories diverge from standard cognitivist accounts in taking the evaluative
element crucial to emotion to be not a judgment, with all the cognitive
apparatus judgments draw in their train, but rather a perception, or something
very like a perception. From the safety of the sidewalk, I might perceive the
onrushing traffic as a threat even though I know that I am quite safe where I
am; if the evaluative judgment that I am in danger were a requisite part of the
emotion of fear, then it seems hard to explain my fear in the face of my
knowledge of my safety. Perceptions, however, need not be reasoned, though
perhaps permeable to reason; they can be had by nonintellectual subjects,
such as babies and dogs, who we want to say experience genuine if primitive
emotions; and they can deploy concepts without requiring their articulation—
the sheep may regard the wolf as dangerous without having the concept of
danger at all.
Aquinas’s account of the emotions is in many ways close to such
perception theories. Indeed, Aquinas exploits the structural parallel between
perception and emotion frequently, and, as with perceptions, he holds that the
most fundamental way to understand emotions is to see them as modes of
engagement with the world. Again, Aquinas holds that the cognitive
penetrability of emotion derives from the susceptibility of perception to being
affected by changes in beliefs and thoughts. The rich array of psychological
faculties that Aquinas sketches, with the complex interplay among cognitive
and affective components, offers a congenial background for the
contemporary cognitive scientist accustomed to working with mental
modules and their transference of information via representations. If Aquinas
draws a sharper line between perceptual and intellectual cognition than most
theorists are comfortable with today, that is a small drawback for being
centuries ahead of his time. The taxonomic structure he proposes might then
be taken as a first attempt to isolate the natural kinds of emotion as an
affective phenomenon. In short, we could preserve his insights and his
general approach to the emotions, and perhaps even the general taxonomy,
but leave behind some of its more medieval features, such as the appeal to
the Aristotelian theory of motion, or the necessarily immaterial character of
intellectual functions. But a remarkable amount of Aquinas’s analysis bears
worthwhile comparison to contemporary theories, as well as being a stunning
intellectual accomplishment in its own right.
NOTES
1. I adopt the dating of these works given in Jean-Pierre Torrell, O.P., ed.
and trans., Thomas Aquinas, Le Verbe incarné, vol. 3, Summa theologiae IIIa
Questions 7–15 (Paris: Cerf, 2002).
2. Respectively, amor and odium, desiderium and fuga, gaudium and
tristitia; spes and desperatio, audacia and timor, and ira. Aquinas adopts this
list and much of the structure that supports it from Jean de la Rochelle
(Summa de anima), by way of his mentor Albert the Great: see Simo
Knuutila, Emotions in Ancient and Medieval Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2004) and Peter King, “Emotions in Medieval Thought,” in
Peter Goldie, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Emotion (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2010), 167–87.
3. QDV, q.26, a.2 and ST I-II q.22 a.1.
4. See Peter King, “Aquinas on the Passions,” in Scott MacDonald and
Eleonore Stump, eds., Aquinas’s Moral Theory (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell
University Press, 1998), 101–132; Robert Miner, Thomas Aquinas on the
Passions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009), ch. 2.3, and the
discussion in §4.
5. See ST I-II q.44 a.1: “In the case of the emotions, the formal aspect is
the motion of the appetitive potency and the material element is a
physiological change, where the one is proportionate to the other.”
6. Aquinas takes this direction of influence from the soul to the body as a
mark of emotion, which he calls by the name of “animal emotion” (passio
animalis) in QDV, q.26, a.2.
7. A corollary of Aquinas’s insistence that physiological changes are
essential to emotion is that nonphysical beings, such as angels and God,
strictly speaking do not have emotions. See Miner, Thomas Aquinas on the
Passions, ch. 2.2 and the references therein, as well as Peter King,
“Dispassionate Passions,” in Martin Pickave and Lisa Shapiro, eds., Reason
and Emotion in Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2011).
8. All translations are my own. Latin texts are cited from their respective
editions, with the punctuation as given (not always respected in the
translations).
9. ST I-II q.22 a.3. Aquinas offers two further arguments for the view that
emotions do not belong to the will: the will is a free active power whereas
emotions are not, and the will tends to a universal object whereas the
emotions tend to a particular object (QDV, q.25, a.1).
10. ST I-II q.22 a.2. This is Aquinas’s preferred proof when he has to give a
brief account of why the emotions are appetitive: see, e.g., Diu. nom. 2.4
§191 or In NE, 2.5 §291.
11. See Diana Cates, Aquinas on the Emotions: A Religious-Ethical Inquiry
(Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 2009), ch. 4.
12. See Shawn Floyd, “Aquinas on Emotion: A Response to Some Recent
Interpretations,” History of Philosophy Quarterly 15 (1998): 161–75; Patrick
Gorevan, “Aquinas and Emotional Theory Today: Mind–Body, Cognitivism,
and Connaturality,” Acta Philosophica 9 (2000): 141–51; and Thomas Ryan,
“Revisiting Affective Knowledge and Connaturality in Aquinas,”
Theological Studies 66 (2005): 49–68.
13. ST I q.78 a.4. See also Super Sent 3 d.26, q.1, a.2, §25, where much the
same account is given. Miner, Thomas Aquinas on the Passions, ch. 3.3,
discusses the estimative and memorative powers in Aquinas with regard to
the emotions.
14. It is unclear whether this cognitive act is distinct from the initial
perception of the wolf—perhaps the sheep’s “concept” of a wolf has
dangerousness built into it—but it is enough for our purposes that it is
logically distinct.
15. These are the examples that Aquinas mentions in Super Sent 3, d.26,
q.1, a.2, §25.
16. Ibid. The “natural instinct” may be nothing more complicated than the
way the animal is wetwired: whenever a wolf-form occurs in sensitive
cognition, the adrenal glands begin pumping, heart rate increases, and so on.
17. This is the medieval notion of the “proper object” or the “primary
object”—the terminology was fluid—of a cognitive potency, in this case of
the estimative power.
18. The terminology is not perspicuous, since the intentio, which must be a
form of sensible good or evil, is, as Aquinas has remarked, not a perceptible
feature of the object. The key point to keep in mind is that “sensible” here
refers to the particular that is grasped in its presentation as a good or an evil.
19. As we shall see in more detail in §3, the formal object of the irascible
emotions is sensible good or evil that is difficult.
20. QDV, q.25, a.4, ad 4.
21. ST I q.81 a.3.
22. Moods were often thought to be completely explained in purely
physiological terms, having to do with the relative balance among the four
bodily humors. Acts of the vegetative soul in the higher animals, such as
sexual arousal or hunger, were also thought to be objectless and hence not
emotions—a view in keeping with their contemporary classification as drives
or urges. Aquinas points out that male impotence effectively demonstrates
the difference between mere bodily arousal and sexual desire, a form of the
emotion of desire (concupiscentia) and an altogether different thing.
23. ST I q.78 a.4 and q.81 a.3.
24. See Claudia Murphy, “Aquinas on Our Responsibility for Our
Emotions,” Medieval Philosophy and Theology 8 (1999): 163–205; and
Elisabeth Uffenheimer-Lippens, “Rationalized Passions and Passionate
Rationality: Thomas Aquinas on the Relation between Reason and the
Passions,” Review of Metaphysics 56 (2003): 525–58.
25. Aquinas notes that the irascible emotions, in virtue of having a more
complex formal object, are thereby “closer to reason” and more susceptible
to its influence. He takes this point from Aristotle, In NE 7.6 (1149a25–b3):
see for instance Super Sent 3, d.26, q.1, a.2, §28 and QDV, q.25, a.6.
26. Of course, humans can condition themselves over time through a
variety of techniques: training, education, brainwashing, self-hypnosis,
repetitive practice, and so on. But here we are concerned with Aquinas’s
focus on the ways in which someone can attempt to affect his or her
emotional responses directly.
27. QDV, q.25, a.5.
28. QDV, q.25, a.4.
29. QDV, q.26, a.3, ad 13. See Umberto Galeazzi, “Le passioni secondo
Tommaso d’Aquino: De veritate q. 26,” Aquinas 47 (2004): 547–70.
30. ST I q.81 a.3.
31. ST I-II q.17 a.7. See also ST I q.81 a.3 ad 2. The allusion is to Aristotle,
Pol. 1.2 (1254b2–5), in which the rational part of the soul is said to control
the irrational part “with a political and royal rule” rather than a tyrannical
rule.
32. QDV, q.26, a.3 and ST I-II q.22 a.3.
33. QDV, q.25, a.4. See also ST I-II q.24 a.4 ad 1.
34. Aquinas takes this point from Aristotle, In NE 2.5 (1105b25–29).
35. QDV, q.25, a.5, ad 5.
36. QDV, q.25, a.4.
37. The following discussion is derived from Super Sent 3, d.26, q.1, a.2;
QDV, q.25, a.2; and ST I-II q.81 a.2.
38. There seems to have been some development in Aquinas’s conception
of how the emotions are structured and organized. The account given here
mostly follows the mature analysis given in ST I-II q.23 a.2–4. This is
Aquinas’s major advance over Jean de la Rochelle, who had organized
emotions into their conjugate pairs, but who did not offer any principles
underlying their organization.
39. This last point illustrates a logical and causal truth for Aquinas, namely
that the irascible emotions begin from and finally terminate in the
concupiscible emotions (ST I-II q.25 a.1–2).
40. ST I-II q.26–48.
41. ST I-II q.29 a.4.
42. ST I-II q.38 a.3.
43. There have recently been several studies of Aquinas’s views about
particular emotions: Marcos Manzanedo, “El deseo y la aversión según Santo
Tomás,” Studium 27 (1987): 189–233; Marcos Manzanedo, “Efectos y
propriedades de la delectación,” Studium 29 (1989): 107–39; Marcos
Manzanedo, “El dolor y sus causas,” Studium 31 (1991): 63–97; Marcos
Manzanedo, “La audacia según Santo Tomás,” Studium 34 (1994): 437–53;
Mark Drost, “In the Realm of the Senses: St. Thomas Aquinas on Sensory
Love, Desire, and Delight,” The Thomist 59 (1995): 47–58; Stephen
Loughlin, “Tristitia et dolor: Does Aquinas Have a Robust Understanding of
Depression?” Nova et Vetera 3 (2005): 761–83; Keith Green, “Aquinas on
Attachment, Envy, and Hatred in the Summa theologiae,” Journal of
Religious Ethics 35 (2007): 403–28; the need for such careful studies of
particular emotions is the central theme of Miner, Thomas Aquinas on the
Passions.
44. See, e.g., Robert C. Roberts, Emotions: An Essay in Aid of Moral
Psychology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).
CHAPTER 17
HAPPINESS
BRIAN DAVIES
For man to rest content with any created good is not possible, for he can be happy only
with complete good which satisfies his desire altogether: he would not have reached his
ultimate end were there something still remaining to be desired. The object of the will,
that is the human appetite, is the Good without reserve, just as the object of the mind is
the True without reserve. Clearly, then, nothing can satisfy man’s will except such
goodness, which is found, not in anything created, but in God alone. Everything created
is a derivative good.23
NOTES
1. We all know the athlete’s slogan “No pain, no gain.” But think also of
people who would speak of themselves as finding happiness in living lives
that many would find distasteful in the extreme (members of certain rather
austere religious orders: Carthusians or Cistercians, for example).
2. For a useful introduction to theories of happiness, see Steven M. Cahn
and Christine Vitrano, eds., Happiness: Classic and Contemporary Readings
in Philosophy (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008). See
also Elizabeth Telfer, Happiness (London and Basingstoke: Macmillan Press,
1980).
3. Cf. ST I-II q.1 a.1.
4. I say “not always” in this sentence since, I presume, we can talk about
mental activity (such as following an argument or envying someone) without
thinking of overtly physical processes (like going for a walk or mending a
washing machine). Aquinas in various places distinguishes between
“immanent” and “transient” action. Here he is (surely rightly) thinking that
there is a big difference between, for example, my admiring you and my
trying to kiss you.
5. I say “all things being equal” since, of course, practical reasoning,
unlike theoretical reasoning, can be affected by the addition of extra
premises. A formally valid argument is not vitiated by the addition of extra
premises. But a piece of practical reason might be. Thus, for example, the
reasonableness of my getting on a certain plane from Paris to New York
might be deeply affected by learning that this particular plane has certain
critical parts missing from it. Cf. Anthony Kenny, Will, Freedom, and Power
(Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1975), ch. 5.
6. My impression is that Aquinas thinks that we could be aiming for
happiness even should it be the case that what appeals to us is masochism.
7. I have heard it said that Aquinas denies that nonhuman animals enjoy
happiness. In fact, though, he often ascribes pleasure to nonhuman animals.
Cf. ST I-II q.31 a.1 or I-II q.4 a.2. He knows very well that animals can be
thought of as happy in some sense. What he denies is that their happiness,
when they have it, is something gained by them as an intellectual goal
pursued and understood by them as such. And he thinks that this is so
because he takes nonhuman animals not to have what he means by
“intellect”.
8. It might be said that Arthur Schopenhauer was someone who
disbelieved in the existence of happiness. In The World as Will and
Representation (1818), he pessimistically seems to claim that, given the
nature of our will or desire, it is impossible for anyone to be genuinely
happy.
9. The phrase “ghost in a machine” is, perhaps, best known from Gilbert
Ryle’s use of it in his highly influential anti-Cartesian book The Concept of
Mind (London: Hutchinson, 1949).
10. In “Analytical Philosophy and the Spirituality of Man,” Elizabeth
Anscombe interestingly observes how Descartes (a “ghost in the machine”
thinker when it comes to people) internalizes sensations so as to make them
nonbodily occurrences on the dubious ground that he can doubt that he has a
body but not that he hears, sees, and so on. See Elizabeth Anscombe, Human
Life, Action and Ethics (Exeter: Imprint Academic, 2005), 5. By contrast,
Aquinas (surely with more sense on his side than Descartes) takes hearing,
seeing, and so on (understood, of course, in nonmetaphorical senses) as
inextricably bodily. The “darkness” of the Middle Ages did not seem to
prevent Aquinas from recognizing that, speaking literally, you need ears to
hear, eyes to see, and a nose to smell. I presume that he would think along
the same lines today were he to know of rare nonhuman animals (of the kind
who amaze us as we view the numerous television programs about them)
whose engagement with the world does not depend on them having human
organs or anything that look remotely like them.
11. Herbert McCabe, On Aquinas (London and New York: Continuum,
2008). One might rightly accuse me (and McCabe) of here presenting a
conclusion of Aquinas in somewhat anachronistic terms (ones which take
Aquinas to be thinking of understanding chiefly on the model of talking). But
I think that this is actually a helpful way of getting his main point about
understanding across to contemporary readers especially since both Aquinas
and Wittgenstein are concerned that we should not misread linguistic life by
assimilating it to sensations or to events in the brain. For an example of
Aquinas precisely speaking in his own voice and terminology, see ST I q.75
a.2. Here his argument for human understanding being immaterial runs: “It is
obvious that man’s understanding enables him to know the nature of all
bodily things. But what can in this way take in things must have nothing of
their natures of their own, for the form that was in it by nature would obstruct
the knowledge of anything else.… Accordingly, if the intellectual principle
had in it the physical nature of any bodily thing, it would be unable to know
all bodies. Each of them has its own determinate nature. Impossible,
therefore, that the principle of understanding be something bodily.” I quote
from vol. 11 of the Blackfriars edition of ST (London and New York: Eyre
and Spottiswoode, 1970).
12. Cf. ST II-II q.146 a.1.
13. I should note that, speaking purely as a philosopher, Aquinas
concentrates on the classical cardinal virtues, the possession of which he
takes (as did Aristotle) to be vital when it comes to human happiness in this
life. But, speaking more theologically, Aquinas believes in what he calls
“theological virtues,” which he believes to be critically important when it
comes to ultimate human happiness. More on this matter (as on other issues
on which I touch above) can be found in some other contributions to the
present volume.
14. With this thought in mind, readers might be interested in consulting
Herbert McCabe, The Good Life: Ethics and the Pursuit of Happiness
(London and New York: Continuum, 2005).
15. Aquinas thinks that everyone naturally desires beatitude whether they
realize it or not. That is because he holds that whatever enjoyment I might
achieve by X, Y, or Z, such enjoyment is but a getting hold of something
good, not of being in a state in which nothing is left for me to want. As long
as there remains something we lack but can add to our happiness then, thinks
Aquinas (reasonably as it seems to me, though not, perhaps, to some non-
theistic millionaires), we have not achieved perfect happiness (beatitudo) and
are always looking for more.
16. See note 5 above.
17. SCG III, 26.
18. I quote from the New Revised Standard Version of the New Testament.
19. Aquinas’s account of the beatific vision is a complicated one and I do
not think that this is the place to try to explain what it amounts to in detail.
Perhaps, though, I ought at least to note (a) that he obviously does not equate
it with looking at God as one might look at a physical object, and (b) that he
basically thinks that it involves us sharing, at least to a limited degree, in the
life and being of God. For a general study of the concept of the vision of
God, see Kenneth Kirk, The Vision of God: The Christian Doctrine of the
Summum Bonum (New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1966). For a discussion of
Aquinas on the beatific vision written with an eye on what St Albert the
Great says on the topic, see Jeffrey Hergan, St. Albert the Great’s Theory of
the Beatific Vision (New York: Peter Lang, 2002). Kirk deals with Aquinas
on pp. 379–94 of his volume. Hergan does so in his ch. 5.
20. I should note that ultimate human happiness (however much they might
desire it) is not, for Aquinas, something that people can achieve by their
natural human abilities or powers. For him, beatitude (the “beatific vision”)
is a gift of God. Cf. ST I-II q.5 a.5. But then, of course, one also has to
remember that, for Aquinas, everything created is a gift of God.
21. See also SCG III, chapters 26–33.
22. I should note that in his discussion of what happiness does not consist
in Aquinas’s questions and answers very much resemble what we find in bk
3 of Boethius’s The Consolation of Philosophy. Aquinas’s discussion of
happiness is surely heavily indebted to that of Boethius.
23. ST I-II q.2 a.8. I quote from vol. 16 of the Blackfriars edition of the ST
(London and New York: Eyre and Spottiswoode, 1969).
24. For two recent, detailed, and interesting books on Aquinas and
happiness, see (1) Denis Bradley, Aquinas on the Twofold Human Good:
Reason and Happiness in Aquinas’s Moral Science (Washington, D.C.:
Catholic University of America Press, 1997), and (2) Stephen Wang, Aquinas
and Sartre on Freedom, Personal Identity, and the Possibility of Happiness
(Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 2009). See also
the entry on “Happiness” by Georg Wielad in Stephen Pope, ed., The Ethics
of Aquinas (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 2002). I should
add that for critical comments on earlier versions of this contribution to the
present volume I am much indebted to Christopher Arroyo, Michael Baur,
Gyula Klima, Turner Nevitt, and Giorgio Pini.
CHAPTER 18
MICHAEL BAUR
IN his often-quoted definition, Aquinas tells us that law is “nothing other than
an ordering of reason for the common good from one who has care of the
community, and promulgated.”1 For Aquinas, law is essentially an ordering
of reason, and not of will, since law is a rule and measure of acts; the first
principle of action is the end; and it belongs to reason to direct things to an
end.2 Aquinas acknowledges that law would have no motive force, and thus
no power to cause or prohibit action, if it were not for the will.3 But without
the ordering of reason, the will’s motive force would be without aim or
direction. For “to command is essentially an act of reason”4 and “to order is
the proper act of reason.”5 Aquinas’s account of law as an ordering of reason
for the common good of a community depends on his mereology (i.e., his
theory of parthood relations, including the relations of parts to parts and parts
to wholes), and so a fuller exploration of his account of law might well begin
with an examination of parts, wholes, and the common good in his thought.
therefore, if a man’s will wills a thing to be, according as it appears to be good, his will
is good: and the will of another man, who wills that thing not to be, according as it
appears evil, is also good. Thus a judge has a good will, in willing a thief to be put to
death, because this is just: while the will of another—e.g., the thief’s wife or son, who
wishes him not to be put to death, inasmuch as killing is a natural evil—is also good.31
each part naturally loves the common good of the whole more than it loves its own
particular good. This is evidenced by its operation, since the principle inclination of each
part is towards common action conducive to the good of the whole. It may also be seen
in civic virtues whereby sometimes the citizens suffer damage even to their own
property and persons for the sake of the common good.32
On Aquinas’s account, citizens are generally willing to bear their fair share
of a political community’s tax burden, since for the most part they recognize
that their shared shouldering of the tax burden is essential for the
achievement of a common good or goods that could not otherwise be
attained.
Of course, it might be objected that: (a) individual citizens would not pay
their taxes if they were not reasonably confident that others would do so as
well; (b) individual citizens are confident that others will pay their taxes,
since the law has established certain mechanisms to punish those who do not
pay their taxes; and therefore (c) individual citizens are induced to pay their
taxes only because of a generalized threat of punishment and not because
they love the common good more than they love their own particular goods.
Aquinas would be able to acknowledge that (a) and (b) may both be true,
while nevertheless denying that (c) follows. Indeed, on Aquinas’s account,
the attempt to argue from (a) and (b) to (c) commits the error of mistaking
the effect (the establishment of some mechanism for punishment) for the
cause (lawfulness). That is to say, (a) and (b) can be taken to support not (c),
but rather the conclusion that (d) individual citizens generally recognize that
as citizens they share a common end whose importance is sufficiently
weighty to justify the establishment of certain mechanisms for coercing those
who do not willingly contribute their fair share toward the attainment of this
common end. If individual citizens did not willingly and for the most part
shoulder their fair share of the overall tax burden, then the very notion of
lawfulness would cease to apply. For if tax monies essential to sustaining the
common good had to be coercively wrested from a majority of the citizens,
then the community would have to expend large sums of its wealth simply in
order to enforce the tax code. But there is a point at which the costs of
enforcing the tax code would exceed the gains to be had through such
enforcement, in which case the very effort at enforcement would cannibalize
itself. Just as an excessive amount of cancer will eventually destroy the body
(and thus destroy the cancer itself), and an excessive amount of counterfeit
will eventually destroy a currency (and thus destroy the counterfeit itself), so
too excessive costs in enforcement will eventually destroy the common good
for which such enforcement exists, and thus undermine the whole point of
enforcement itself. On Aquinas’s account, lawfulness is compatible with the
need to compel compliance in some instances, but incompatible with the
need to compel compliance in most instances.33
NOTES
1. ST I–II q.90 a.4.
2. ST I–II q.90 a.1.
3. ST I–II q.17 a.1.
4. Ibid.
5. ST I–II q.17 a.2; see also SCG III, 78; In NE I, lec.1.
6. ST II–II q.58 a.5.
7. ST II–II q.64 a.2.
8. ST I–II q.17 a.4.
9. SCG III, 94; SCG II, 39; QDP, q.3, a.16, ad 1; In Meta XII, lec.12,
n.2637.
10. SCG III, 94; see also SCG II, 44–45; and Super Sent, bk.1, d.44, q.1,
a.2, ad 6.
11. SCG III, 69.
12. See also QDV, q.11, a.1; QDV, q.5, a.8, ad 12; Super Sent, bk.2, d.1,
q.1, a.5.
13. In NE I, lec.1, n.1.
14. In Meta XII, lec.12, n.2627.
15. Ibid.
16. QDV, q.5, a.3; see also In Meta XII, lec.12, n.2630.
17. In Meta V, lec.3, n.782; ST I q.5, a.2, ad 1.
18. QDV, q.7, a.6, ad 7.
19. ST I q.39 a.4 ad 3; also In Meta VII, lect.13, n.6; QDP, q.7, a.4, ad 1.
20. ST I–II q.90 a.2 ad 2.
21. ST I–II q.19 a.10; ST I–II q.109 a.3; ST II–II q.26 a.3; SCG III, 17.
22. In Meta XII, lec.12, n.1303.
23. In NE IX, lec.6, n.1839.
24. In NE VIII, lec.12, n.1724.
25. SCG III, 18.
26. QDV, q.5, a.3.
27. In Meta V, lec.21, n.1108.
28. QDP, q.7, a.1.
29. ST II–II q.58 a.7 ad 2.
30. ST I q.93 a.2 ad 3.
31. ST I–II q.19 a.10.
32. ST II–II q.26 a.3; see also ST I q.60 a.5.
33. I am indebted to the work of Herbert McCabe for this insight, and for
the examples used in illustrating it. See Herbert McCabe, Faith Within
Reason, ed. Brian Davies (New York: Continuum, 2007), 52–53; and Herbert
McCabe, God and Evil in the Theology of St. Thomas Aquinas, ed. Brian
Davies (New York: Continuum, 2010), 36–39. See also Aristotle, Physics, II,
199a34–b33; and Aquinas, Commentary on Aristotle’s Physics, II, lec.12–14.
34. This dimension of Aquinas’s account should make clear that his
understanding of law does not stand in tension with, but is in fact closely
allied with, a deep appreciation of the role of the virtues in human action.
35. ST I–II q.93 a.5; see also ST I q.103 a.1 ad 3.
36. See Michael Bright, Intelligence in Animals (New York: Reader’s
Digest Association, Ltd., 1997), 74–75.
37. ST I–II q.91 a.6.
38. ST I–II q.91 a.1; see also ST I–II q.93 a.3; ST I–II q.93 a.4–6.
39. ST I–II q.93 a.4.
40. ST I–II q.93 a.5.
41. ST I–II q.91 a.4–5.
42. ST I q.22 a.2 ad 2; ST I q.48 a.2; ST I q.49 a.1–2; SCG III, 71.
43. Thus for Aquinas, not only is it the case that eternal law (like every
other instance of law) is incompatible with the existence of coerced
compliance in most instances. Eternal law is incompatible with any kind of
coerced compliance whatsoever; for apart from the creative, legislative
causality of God (which is the same as his eternal law), there simply is no
created being or created act that is there to be coerced (ST I q.103 a.1 ad 3;
ST I q.105 a.4; ST I q.105 a.4).
44. ST I q.103 a.1.
45. ST I q.44 a.4.
46. ST I q.47 a.1.
47. See also In Meta XII, lec.12, n.2627–2629.
48. ST I–II q.90 a.1 ad 1; ST I–II q.91 a.2; see also ST I–II q.93 a.6; and ST
I q.103 a.1 ad 1.
49. ST I–II q.91 a.2 ad 1.
50. ST I–II q.91 a.2.
51. Ibid.
52. ST I–II q.93 a.5; see also SCG III, 114.
53. ST I–II q.96 a.4; see also Augustine, De Libero Arbitrio, I, 5. Literally
translated, the statement reads: “What will not have been just, does not
appear to be law” (“Non videtur esse lex, quae justa non fuerit”).
54. See ST I–II q.94 a.2.
55. Ibid.
56. ST I–II q.79 a.2.
57. ST I q.82 a.4.
58. See QDM, q.6.
59. See ST I q.79 a.3; ST I q.86 a.1.
60. ST I–II q.2 a.8; ST I–II q.17 a.1 ad 2; ST I q.105 a.4; SCG III, 10.
61. ST I–II q.10 a.2.
62. Along these lines, Aquinas observes that it belongs to the perfection of
the liberty of the will to be able to choose between opposite things while
keeping the order of the end in view; but it is a defect of the liberty of the
will for it to choose anything while turning away from the order of the end.
Thus, speaking of the beatified angels, Aquinas tells us: “there is greater
liberty of will in the angels who cannot sin, than there is in ourselves who
can sin.” (ST I q.62 a.8 ad 3.)
63. See ST I–II q.94 a.2.
64. See ST I q.59 a.1; ST I q.63 a.4; QDV, q.21, a.1–2 and q.22, a.1.
65. Holding that the naturalness of certain inclinations dictates the
choiceworthiness of certain actions is, as Josiah Royce suggests, similar to
holding that our being subject to the law of gravitation dictates “that we all
ought to sit down.” See Josiah Royce, The Religious Aspect of Philosophy: A
Critique of the Basis of Conduct and of Faith (Boston: Houghton, Mifflin,
and Co., 1885), 80.
66. ST I–II q.94 a.2.
67. ST I q.60 a.5.
68. ST II–II q.69 a.4.
69. ST II–II q.69 a.4 ad 1; see also ST I–II q.94 a.2 ad 2.
70. ST II–II q.110 a.1.
71. ST I–II q.17 a.2.
72. QDV, q.5, a.3; see also QDV, q.5, a.1, ad 9; ST I q.11 a.3; In Meta XII,
lec.12, n.2630.
73. ST I q.19 a.9; see also QDM, q.1, a.3.
74. In NE I, lec.6, n.76.
75. ST I–II q.90 a.2.
76. ST II–II q.10 a.11; see Augustine’s De Ordine, II, 4.
77. See ST I q.22 a.2 ad 2; ST I q.48 a.2; ST I q.49 a.1–2; SCG III, 71. In a
similar vein, Aquinas holds that a judge may sometimes be obligated to
pronounce a sentence that he personally knows to be an unjust one. The
reason for this is that the judge, insofar as he exercises public authority, is
obligated to render judgments on behalf of the community and for the sake of
the community’s common good; accordingly, the judge may legitimately
render judgments based only on knowledge acquired by him as a public
authority, and not based on knowledge acquired by him as a private
individual (i.e., outside the scope of an appropriate public, judicial process).
If the judge in a capital case privately knows that a defendant is innocent, but
is unable to remove himself from the case and is unable to bring his privately
acquired knowledge to light through some appropriate judicial proceeding,
then the judge does no wrong in sentencing the innocent defendant to death
(see ST II–II q.64 a.6 ad 3; ST II–II q.67 a.2; ST II–II q.96 a.6).
CHAPTER 19
TOBIAS HOFFMANN
There could not be any stability and certainty in the things that depend on principles, if
the principles were not firmly established.… Accordingly, so that rectitude in human
actions may be possible, there must be a permanent principle that has an unchanging
rectitude, and by which criterion all human deeds are examined. This permanent
principle must resist all evil and assent to every good. And this is synderesis, the task of
which is to rebuke evil, and to incline to the good. Therefore we concede that there
cannot be any sin in it.4
Aquinas rejects the view of the anonymous author, and he would in part
contradict Bonaventure as well. For Aquinas, the distinction of generally
good, evil, and indifferent acts does not have any bearing on when erring
conscience binds and when it does not. Regardless of whether my action is
objectively good, evil, or indifferent, conscience binds, for it is by means of
conscience that an action is proposed to me as good, bad, or indifferent.
Aquinas gives two examples: if on account of erring conscience I consider it
evil to abstain from fornication, and I want to abstain from it, then I want
something evil, although in truth it is not evil, but only misapprehended as
evil. Likewise, if because of erring conscience I think that believing in Christ
is evil, then choosing to believe in Christ, I choose it as something evil,
although for Aquinas, believing in Christ is really something good. Since
conscience presents the action to me as good or bad, Aquinas considers it
immoral to act contrary to erring conscience.27 Conscience should in fact not
be seen as a rival to God’s law, but rather as the herald of God’s law. It binds
not on its own account, but on account of the divine precept. Aquinas
provides an apt illustration of this point:
Suppose that a ruling by a king would reach the people only through some inferior
leader, and suppose that he says that this ruling comes from the king, although this is not
true. What this leader says would then be obligatory qua ruling by the king, and those
who disrespect it would deserve punishment.28
NOTES
I wish to thank the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation for supporting me
during my work on this text.
JEAN PORTER
NOTES
1. ST I-II q.6 intro.
2. ST I-II q.49 intro. The translation of habitus as “habit,” while common,
is misleading, because the English word implies mindless or stereotypical
behavior, whereas for Aquinas a true virtue is precisely not mindless. On the
contrary, it is a disposition formed through, and continually informed by,
rational reflection. Nor would it be quite accurate to translate the term as
“disposition,” since a habitus is only one example of such. I have therefore
simply left the term untranslated throughout.
3. ST I-II q.90 a.1. This and all subsequent translations are my own.
4. Most notably, see Ralph McInerny, Ethica Thomistica: The Moral
Philosophy of Thomas Aquinas (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of
America Press, 1982/1997).
5. The best account of the development of virtue ethics in the medieval
period remains the essays collected in Odon Lottin, Psychologie et morale
aux XII et XIII siecles, vol. 3, parts 1 and 2 (Paris: Louvain, 1949). On
Abelard and Peter Lombard, see Lottin, Psychologie et morale, 3/1:100–104;
for a more detailed account of Abelard’s theory of virtue, see John
Marenbon, The Philosophy of Peter Abelard (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1997), 282–87.
6. As Cary Nederman points out, key ideas from Aristotelian ethics were
in general circulation for at least 150 years before the full text of the
Nicomachean Ethics became available in Latin; see “Aristotelianism and the
Origins of ‘Political Science’ in the Twelfth Century,” Journal of the History
of Ideas 52 (1991): 179–94, 180–81. This does not mean, however, that
scholastic theories of virtue were identical to Aristotle’s own theory. They
were not—the scholastics, including Aquinas himself, do not follow the
outline of Aristotle’s account of the virtues in the Nicomachean Ethics (as
Andrew Pinsent rightly points out in his chapter in this volume), and by the
same token, they press beyond what Aristotle himself explicitly says about
the metaphysical underpinnings of virtue theory. We may fairly regard
Aquinas’s theory of the virtues as Aristotelian, therefore, without claiming
that it simply repeats Aristotle’s own view, or denying that it incorporates
many other classical and theological voices, as well as Aristotle’s own.
7. ST I-II q.55 a.4, quoting Super Sent II 27.5.
8. ST I-II q.55 a.1.
9. ST I-II q.49 a.4.
10. ST I-II q.56 a.3; I-II q.57 a.1; I-II q.58 a.3.
11. ST I-II q.58 a.1.
12. On virtues as perfections of faculties, see, e.g., ST I-II q.55 a.3 and I-II
q.56 a.1; on virtue as a perfection of the agent, see ST I-II q.4 a.7 in tandem
with I-II q.3 a.2. I argue for this interpretation in more detail in Nature as
Reason: A Thomistic Theory of the Natural Law (Grand Rapids, Mich.:
Eerdmans, 2005), 163–203.
13. For further details, including further textual references, see Robert
Pasnau’s illuminating discussion of the metaphysics of actuality in Thomas
Aquinas on Human Nature: A Philosophical Study of Summa theologiae Ia
75–89 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 143–51; in addition,
see Porter, Nature as Reason, 158–63.
14. ST I-II q.61 a.4.
15. ST I-II q.59 a.2; I-II q.60 a.3–5; cf. De virtutibus in communi, a.12,
which sets forth the relation of the virtues to the different faculties of the soul
in more detail.
16. ST I-II q.58 a.2.
17. ST I-II q.59 a.5.
18. ST I-II q.56 a.6; I-II q.60 a.2; II-II q.24 a.1; II-II q.58 a.4.
19. ST I q.60 a.5; cf. ST I-II q.109 a.3.
20. ST I-II q.60 a.1.
21. ST I-II q.65 a.1.
22. ST I-II q.65 a.1.
23. ST I-II q.65 a.2.
24. ST I-II q.4 a.7 and I-II q.5 a.5; cf. QDVCom a.10.
25. ST I-II q.62 a.1 and I-II q.110 a.3.
26. ST I-II q.62 a.1.
27. ST I-II q.110 a.3; with reference to the gifts in particular, I-II q.68 a.1,
2.
28. ST I-II q.68 a.1.
29. ST I-II q.68 a.1.
30. Isa. 11:2–3; in this paragraph, I follow ST I-II q.68 a.1 except where
otherwise noted.
31. See ST I-II q.68 a.4
32. ST I-II q.68 a.8.
33. For this reason, I would not say (as Andrew Pinsent suggests in his
chapter) that Aquinas’s account of the gifts of the Holy Spirit reflects a
fundamental break with the Aristotelian orientation of his overall theory of
virtue, that is to say, with his analysis of the virtues as perfections directed
toward the ultimate flourishing of the rational creature. It should also be
noted that in this question, Aquinas once again affirms that the acquired
virtues are adequate to attain the connatural end of the human person, and
that at least some individuals throughout history have in fact fully attained
and practiced the (acquired) cardinal virtues without the aid of supernatural
grace (ST I-II q.68 a.2). At the same time, I would agree with Pinsent that
Aquinas’s incorporation of the Gifts and Fruits of the Holy Spirit takes him
well beyond the parameters of Aristotle’s own outline and extends the scope
of an Aristotelian construal of the virtues as perfections beyond anything that
Aristotle’s classical followers would have been likely to envision.
34. ST I-II q.68 a.2.
35. ST I-II q.63 a.3, 4.
36. ST II-II q.147 a.1 ad 2.
37. ST II-II q.104 a.6; II-II q.141 a.6 ad 1.
38. e.g., see ST I q.60 a.5.
39. QDVCom a.9; ST I-II q.61 a.5.
40. ST I-II q.110 a.3.
41. ST I-II q.114 a.2.
42. ST I-II q.63 a.3, especially ad 2; I-II q.65 a.3.
43. ST II-II q.58 a.7, 8.
44. Ibid.
45. Ibid.; II-II q.61 a.1.
46. ST II-II q.47 a.11.
47. ST I-II q.71 a.1, 3.
48. ST I-II q.71 a.1.
49. ST I-II q.71 a.3.
50. ST I-II q.71 a.4.
51. ST I-II q.64 a.1.
52. ST I-II q.64 a.2.
53. Ibid.; also see ST I-II q.56 a.6; II-II q.58 a.10.
54. ST I-II q.64 a.4
55. See, for e.g., Daniel Mark Nelson, The Priority of Prudence: Virtue
and Natural Law in Aquinas and Its Implications for Modern Ethics
(University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1992), and more
recently, John Bowlin, Contingency and Fortune in Aquinas’ Ethics
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 97–137.
56. ST I-II q.54 a.2, 3.
57. See, e.g., ST II-II q.27 a.1.
58. The relevant texts are ST II-II q.16, 22, 44, 56, 122, 140, and 170; cf.
ST II-II q.108 a.2.
59. De malo, q.2, a.1; sins are said specifically to be opposed to one or
more virtues at q.2, a.6.
CHAPTER 21
PRACTICAL REASONING
AQUINAS thinks that practical reason is distinct but not entirely insulated from
speculative reason. Although his description of practical reasoning applies to
a variety of human activities, his greatest focus is on the practical reasoning
that is involved in human action. Although practical reasoning resembles the
speculative in its use of a kind of syllogism, its connection with particular
affairs precisely as contingent gives it a special character.
JOSEPH WAWRYKOW
FAITH
In discussing each of the theological virtues, Aquinas will consider the act or
acts made possible by the virtue, the gift or gifts that perfect the possessor of
that virtue and so make her more open to the promptings of the Holy Spirit to
act out of that virtue and so in a way pleasing to God, the vices opposed to
the virtue, and the pertinent precepts.8 In what follows on each of the
theological virtues, I concentrate on the virtue with its act(s), with some
attention to the opposing vices.
Believing, the internal act of faith, is to think with assent.9 It is an act of
the intellect, commanded by the will. By faith, one is related to God as First
Truth. The First Truth is both the formal object and, in an extended sense, the
material object of faith. God reveals the truths held by theological faith, and
it is on God’s authority that one assents to these truths. And, these truths
involve beatitude: God reveals that God is the beatifying end of human
beings, and what God has done, in Christ, to make possible reaching that end.
With the tradition, in defining the virtue of faith, Aquinas is content with the
words of Hebrews 11:1: “faith is the substance of things to be hoped for, the
certainty of things that appear not.”10 One does not see God in this life and so
the object of faith does not of itself bring a person to affirm it; faith, not
knowledge, is characteristic of the journey, in this life. But, on God’s
authority, one can believe that God is the beatifying end of the person and
that the way to this end is through Jesus Christ; and since God does not lie,
there is a certainty to faith (the “assurance” of things that appear not). The
word “substance” in the definition is taken in a distinctive sense, to indicate
that, by faith, there is an anticipation of heaven. There is, to be sure, a
distance between now and what lies in the future. But, by faith, there is a first
taste of heaven and an ordering to heaven, a thinking appropriate to life in
this world by which the “substance” of heaven is possessed and which
promotes the attaining of heaven. To reach an end, one must be aware of the
end and the means to it; and this is provided in faith.
With the tradition, Aquinas thinks there are three aspects of the internal
act of faith.11 He adopts a formulation that nuances the relation of the person
to God by faith: credere Deo; credere Deum; credere in Deum. By the first
part of the formula is indicated God as the formal object of the act of faith.
By the second is indicated the material object of faith. On the basis of God
revealing and the authority of God (credere Deo), one affirms basic truths
involved in salvation, that God is the beatifying end of the human journey,
that God is triune, and the like (credere Deum). The first two parts of the
formula deal with the intellect, which is perfected by the habit of faith. The
final part of the formula turns to will, which commands the act of the
intellect. In the faith that justifies, that puts one right before God, credere in
Deum bespeaks the virtue of charity, which directs human acts to God as the
ultimate end. Charity quickens the act of faith, and makes it worthy before
God.
In his fullest depiction of the act of faith, Aquinas will also note the place
of grace. The object of faith lies beyond reason, and the object is not known
directly. Since it is unseen, the object of faith is not sufficient to move the
intellect to affirm it. The act of the intellect must be commanded by the will,
and the will need not command the act of faith. That the will commands this
act is due to grace, to God moving the will to command the act of faith.12
Faith, then, has a twofold dependence on God’s gracious will: for the
infusion of the virtue in the first place, and for the act of the virtue.13
WHAT FAITH AFFIRMS
What is the content of the faith? Have all believers, whenever they have
lived, been bound to hold, explicitly, the same truths? Aquinas’s position, in
brief, is that in essence the truth of the faith has always been the same, but
that it has come to finer expression over time. What was virtually contained
in the faith, objectively taken, has been made explicit, been more finely
articulated.14 Aquinas here is invoking his notion of the articles of faith (the
truths necessary for salvation, which are revealed by God, cannot be
demonstrated by human reason and are to be held by faith),15 as well as his
basic epistemology. The act of faith terminates in a reality;16 by faith one is
related to God as First Truth. This is confirmed by the wording of the creed,
which contains the articles (“I believe in God almighty,” for example, not “I
believe that God is almighty,” etc.).17 But, what is known is in the knower
according to the mode of the knower;18 and so although God is simple, since
humans know by analysis and synthesis, certain propositions are formed
about the God affirmed in faith, as well as about things in relation to God as
these are ordered to human salvation. An article corresponds to the way in
which God is unseen; and an article can cover much. There is one sort of
difficulty posed by the dying of God. Another sort of difficulty is posed by
the resurrection of the dead Word incarnate. And so these fall under different
articles of the faith. But, that the Word incarnate suffered and was buried
evinces the same difficulty as his dying; and so they are summarized under
that same article.19
The articles have increased over time; the faith of believers, in terms of
the content, has become nuanced, although virtually identical with that held
by their predecessors. Aquinas finds in Scripture an apt statement of the faith
that all believers have held, whenever they have lived. As Hebrews 11:6
states, “He that comes to God must believe that He is, and that He rewards
those that seek God.”20 By the first part is meant all that pertains to the God
who is the beatifying end of human existence; by the second, addressing
God’s providence, is indicated that God saves and does so in keeping with
human constitution and need. Over time, as God reveals more about God and
the way to God, what was virtual has become explicit; and at present all
believers are required to hold, explicitly, a series of truths about God and
about Christ, the way to God as end.
These beliefs, now in their fully articulated form, are stated in the creed,
which falls into articles of two sorts: those that have to do with the mystery
of the triune God who is end, and those that have to do with the mystery of
Christ, with what God has dispensed in time to make the attainment of God
as end possible.21 There are seven articles, by Aquinas’s counting, under
each of these main categories. With regards to the majesty of God, three
things are proposed for belief: the unity of the Godhead, the trinity of
persons, and the works proper to the Godhead. There are three articles on the
trinity of persons, one for each of the persons. There are three articles too for
the works of God, one dealing with the order of nature (God as creator),
another on the order of grace, affirming the sanctification of people, the third
on the order of glory, affirming the resurrection of the dead and life
everlasting. As for Christ’s human nature, its seven articles treat of his
conception, his virginal birth, his passion, death and burial, his descent into
hell, his resurrection, his ascension, and his coming to judge.22
Again, revelation has been progressive, as has articulation. Earlier
believers had a less articulated faith. In describing earlier faith, Aquinas
makes use of a fundamental division of the history of the race, theologically
construed.23 Thus, prior to the Fall, humans did affirm God as beatifying end,
and affirmed Christ; but, lacking a foreknowledge of their own sin, they did
not believe that the Christ to come would have to meet the problem of sin,
through his suffering and dying and being raised. They believed only with a
view to the coming of beatitude, and so believed in Incarnation, as tailored to
making available the elevating grace needed to attain God as end. After the
Fall, the need for the suffering, dying, and raising of the incarnate Word
came to expression, and so believers affirmed not only Incarnation, but the
Passion and Resurrection as well. With the coming of Christ, and the
performance of his saving work, what was believed as future has occurred
and is held, now, in faith as accomplished. Faith holds that, in Jesus Christ,
God has taken decisive action to overcome sin and make possible the
attainment of eternal life as intended by God.
Aquinas nuances this “historical” account of the making explicit of the
content of faith by working in some reflections on degrees of explicitness,
especially in terms of the believers who lived under the Old Law, rendered in
the Old Testament. Aquinas distinguishes between the learned and the rest of
the people of God.24 The faith of the leaders was more explicit: they
explicitly believed in the Christ to come, who would suffer and die for sins.
They knew that their ritual and sacrificial actions, while valuable in
themselves for expressing right relation to God, also foretold Christ, and so
would find their completion in Christ. The simple, however, lacked this
further understanding of ritual and practice. And so their faith in the Christ to
come was more implicit, expressed under the figure of these rituals and
practices. As for the present time—that is, after Christ—Aquinas too knows
of a kind of distinction between explicit and implicit faith among believers,
although this plays out differently now. All, whatever their state, are held to
explicit faith about God and Christ as expressed in the creed, which
summarizes the articles of faith. But, the faith of the leaders must be more
advanced, more nuanced, more acquainted with the surrounding details; the
faith of the people in the articles as stated in the creed suffices, although they
are to be prone to accept whatever else attends belief in, say, the death of
Christ as reported in Scripture.
Human beings are involved in God’s revealing and the process of
articulation. The truths needed for salvation are revealed in Scripture, and
God reveals these truths to the human authors of Scripture and does so in
such a way that they cannot be mistaken. They pass on these truths to others
as God intends.25 And church leaders articulate the faith through their
participation in councils. It pertains to a council to determine, in the face of
heretical challenge, on a matter of importance to the faith, that is, to further
articulate the faith. This the council does in dependence on Scripture,
determining the correct interpretation, in terms of major matters of faith, of
Scripture. A council, according to Aquinas, is called by the pope, to whom it
also belongs to confirm and publish conciliar articulations. These
articulations of the faith constitute the rule of faith, itself reflective of God’s
revelation, which is the measure of true faith.26 In both revelation and
articulation, the human role is real, albeit secondary. It is God who reveals
the truths necessary for salvation; and the Holy Spirit guides the deliberations
and determinations of the councils. Humans act instrumentally. In his
discussion of faith, Aquinas can mention one other human, whose
contribution, however, is the most important: Christ, the Word incarnate.
What is to be held by faith, on the basis of God’s authority, might also be
designated the “doctrine of Christ,”27 for it is Christ, the God become human,
the one to whom the Old Testament has been pointing, who provides the
definitive and final revelation of God’s saving truth. There is a considerable
gap between this human and the others involved in revelation and
articulation. Christ is the Word of God become human, and the second divine
person is the bearer, the subject, of the human nature of Christ; the human
nature stands to the divinity as a conjoined instrument. The others involved
in revelation and articulation are not, obviously, God, and act as separated
animated instruments of God. Their authority then can only be participated,
derived from the God who acts through them. In referring to Christ’s
doctrine, Aquinas is anticipating the fuller, much more expansive treatment
of Christ as teacher in the third part of the Summa;28 that later treatment itself
builds on, as does the discussion of faith in the Secunda Secundae, the
opening question of the Summa, on sacred doctrine.29
HOPE
CHARITY
The treatise on charity is the lengthiest of those in the Summa on the
theological virtues, consisting of two more questions (24) than the other two
treatises combined (16 questions on faith, 6 on hope).46 The treatise on
charity is divided into four main segments: a consideration of the virtue
itself, including an in-depth analysis of its object; the principal act of the
virtue, love, accompanied by its effects; the vice opposed to love, hatred, as
well as the vices opposed to the effects of charity; and, questions on the
precepts, gift of the Holy Spirit, wisdom, that perfects charity, and the vice
opposed to wisdom, folly.
That Aquinas offers an analysis of charity in such detail and complexity is
most fitting for more than one reason. Scripture makes much of charity, as
does the subsequent Christian tradition, and the treatise aims at gathering up
and synthesizing these various comments. Charity stands at the heart of the
medieval Christian version of the journey to God as end and will be
manifested in all acts that lead to the God who beatifies. And, as Aquinas
puts it in one of the articles of the treatise,47 charity, simply put, is the
greatest of all the virtues, standing first, in terms of perfection, not only in
comparison with the acquired virtues but also in terms of the other
theological virtues. The acquired virtues have their particular goods,
proportioned to the human as human. The other theological virtues relate the
person to God, as to one who offers what the person needs to attain God as
end, whether knowledge of the end and the way to the end, or the help
required to reach eternal life. Charity unites in will the lover and the beloved:
God is loved as God should be, for God’s own sake and as God is.
Charity is friendship.48 For friendship, several criteria must be met: that
one wills the good of another, the well-being of that other; that the willing of
good be mutual; that there be a community between the two on which charity
is based. All of this holds for friendship between God and those endowed
with the virtue of charity. The community is that of beatitude. Beatitude
pertains to God as God; God wills to share this beatitude with human beings
and wills that in love; God’s love is causal, and so the virtue of charity is
infused in the soul as the created effect of God’s love. On the basis of that
causal love, human beings have the possibility of attaining to God as
beatifying end. The love is mutual. First God loves, and on the basis of that
love, with the further aid of grace, the recipient of God’s love loves in return,
out of the virtue of charity; and this person shows that love in acts of love,
elicited by the will, and of acts of will, shaped by charity, that command
other acts of the person (see, e.g., on faith, above, and on charity as form,
below). God in love wills the person to share in beatitude, and the person
loves God, and loves God as God deserves to be loved, as truly and fully
good. The friendship, then, is that that pertains to the virtuous:49 it holds
between God, who is fully good, and those whom God makes good, by
God’s loving gifts.
OBJECTS OF CHARITY
God is the principal object of the love of charity. Aquinas asserts other
objects of charity, all ordered to God as principal object. He adopts the list of
four objects of charity offered by Augustine, in the first book of the De
doctrina, in parsing the twofold command, to love God above all things, and
the neighbor as oneself.50 Thus, the person who has received the virtue of
charity will love by that charity God, the neighbor, oneself, and one’s body.
God is loved as the absolute good, who is the beatifying end of the human
person. God is loved for God’s own sake. One loves the neighbor, and
oneself, in charity, as participating in beatitude. One loves the neighbor as
made by and for God as end; so too one loves oneself. In this sense, one
loves the neighbor and oneself as in God, as ordered to God as beatifying
end. The body is loved in charity also in terms of beatitude. In the beatific
vision, the soul will be fulfilled in knowing and loving God directly. There
will be an overflow to the body, which in this life had been involved in the
actions sought by God of those who will attain God as end, from soul: and so
in the vision, through this overflow, the body will be clarified, made subtle
and agile.
With the tradition, Aquinas thinks of the possibility of progress in charity,
of degrees of charity that can be plotted along the journey of a life, which, if
successful, finds its term in heaven.51 There are different pursuits that
characterize the three degrees of charity: beginning, progress, and perfection.
At first a person will be chiefly occupied with avoiding sin and resisting his
concupiscence, which works against charity. In beginners, charity has to be
fostered and fed, so as not to be destroyed. Eventually, as one increases in
proficiency, the person’s chief pursuit is to aim at progress in good. And,
finally, the perfect will aim at union with and enjoyment of God; these desire
to be dissolved and to be with Christ. Can, however, charity be truly perfect
in this life?52 There is a perfection in charity that is reserved to the next life,
when the person who is in God’s presence is in act ever and wholly borne
toward God. Such an unfailing actual loving of God is not possible in the
present life; because of human weakness it is not possible actually to think
always of God and so be moved actually at all times to love of God. But,
there is a kind of perfection that is possible in the present life, when the
person makes an earnest endeavor to give his time to divine things, while
scorning other things except as the needs of life in the world demand. Such
however is not common to all who have charity. What will be found in
others, who fall short of that perfection (as in the members of religious orders
who have given themselves wholly over to the single-minded pursuit of
God), is a giving of the heart over wholly to God habitually, that is, by
neither thinking nor desiring anything contrary to the love of God.
Does the love of charity extend to others, to, say, the sinner, or to the
enemy? Jesus, after all, tells his followers to love the enemy,53 who,
however, seems missing from the list of objects of charity adopted by
Aquinas from Augustine. That a person is a sinner means that she is at odds
with God; and so at first glance would not appear to belong to God and so be
subject to the love of charity. And, the enemy can similarly be viewed as at
odds with God, having done something that is destructive of community with
God and with those who belong to God. Sin, of course, is an impediment to
the attaining of God; and charity is incompatible with mortal sin. But, even in
terms of the sinner and the enemy, one can posit a connection to God, which
is the basis for a community of them with God and with those called to love
in charity. For, while not now in correct relationship to God, a human being
is potentially in that relationship, and will be in that relationship if sin is
rejected and the person turns to God. And, given that potentiality, the sinner
and the enemy can be said to belong to God, and so too are subject to charity.
One will, as Jesus asks, love the enemy, although not as enemy, and will love
the sinner, but not the sin; one loves the sinner or the enemy, for God’s sake.
Aquinas thinks of an order among the objects of charity.54 God is the
principal object and is to be loved above all things and for God’s sake. The
neighbor and oneself are to be loved as called to beatitude, as belonging to a
fellowship that God has initiated and sustains. But, another human will be
loved more, in accordance with a greater reason, or better, more reasons, to
love that one in comparison to another object of love. The basic idea is that
community or fellowship with some is deeper than with others. In addition to
the fellowship established with all other humans, as made by and for God,
who have been the recipients of God’s special love, which is causal of their
own charity, a person can have additional bonds with others and so be related
to them more closely. Aquinas can mention in this regard the bonds of
country or city, as well as those of family, all of which can strengthen the
links among people. A person will love a relative more than someone to
whom he is not related. And, the union with relatives is more stable than
those with others, which may come into existence or pass away (e.g., as civic
needs and responsibilities come to be but might find an end; the union of
kinship abides).55
Even among relatives, Aquinas can posit a greater or lesser love. Should a
parent be loved more than a child?56 The better something is and the more
akin to God it is, the more it is to be loved; and so in this sense, a parent, who
is one’s principle (and so like God, the principle of all), should be loved more
than one’s child. From another perspective, however, one can say that the
child is to be loved the more, for the parent is more closely connected to the
child, and so the child is better known and so more loved, than the other way
around. Aquinas will offer various observations to support this contention.
Thus, for example, parents love their children as being part of themselves; so
the child is loved as the parent loves himself. And, parents know better that
this one is their child; there can be, it appears, some doubt about one’s own
parents. And, parents love their children right from the start and so longer
than a child loves a parent; apparently there is a lag, in coming to love a
parent, for a child (who must mature to be capable of expressing love).
Aquinas can also inquire about a child loving her parents: whom should be
loved more, the mother or the father?57 Both are principles, and so both have
a likeness to God. Should they then be loved equally? Here, trading on his
Aristotelian biology, Aquinas opts for the father: the father is the active, the
mother, the passive, principle of the child; and so the father, as more alike to
God, deserves more love. (This is an argument in need of revision, in light of
a more updated account of conception.) And, finally along these lines, who is
to be loved more by a man, his wife or his parents?58 Again, Aquinas will
show why each are deserving of love: the parents, as the principle, and so the
affinity with God; the wife, to whom the man is united as one, for she is
closer to him and is loved by him as he loves himself, in relation to God.
Depending on the perspective from which one is answering the question,
then, one will answer that one or the other is to be loved the more.
CONNECTION
Aquinas asserts the connection of the virtues, with an eye to underscoring the
importance of charity.73 In terms of the theological virtues, asserting their
connection is to repeat the claim about charity as the form of the virtues.
Faith and hope find their completion in charity, for charity relates them to
God as beatifying end. Without charity so orienting, the other theological
virtues are imperfect and not conducive to eternal life. Charity in this sense
employs these other virtues, in exercising its role as form of the virtues, and
disposes them well. These other virtues with their acts provide the matter for
the activity of charity. It perfects these virtues and makes their acts better: by
charity, one believes well, hopes well, for this believing and hoping leads to
God as beatifying end. The connection goes, as well, in the other direction.
Here, Aquinas echoes his teaching about the order of generation of these
virtues: first faith, then hope, then charity. One loves only on the basis of
knowing what is to be loved and having a confidence that what is to be loved
can be attained. Remove faith and hope, and there is no charity.
Aquinas asserts an additional connection of virtues, of charity with the
infused moral virtues, which are infused with the theological virtues at the
term of the process of conversion.74 The infused moral virtues make possible
moral acts that are pleasing to God and lead to eternal life; they are not to be
reduced to the acquired moral virtues, gained through acts of a kind and
ordered to the person’s natural end. The infused moral virtues are, as are the
theological virtues, simply infused, given by God as gift, in accordance with
God’s will for a person. As with that with the other theological virtues, the
connection of charity with the infused moral virtues can be thought of as
going in both directions. Charity is their form, moving and directing them to
God as beatifying end, making them better, well done. And, charity too is
dependent on them: the infused moral virtues are the principles of good
moral acts that lead to God as end; charity works through them to bring a
person to God; take them away and charity has nothing to act on.
LOSS OF VIRTUE
In describing increase in the theological virtues, Aquinas can gesture in a
relatively straightforward way to what is the case for the acquired virtues.
Those increase by acts of that kind; those acts incline the possessor of the
acquired virtue the more to acts of that kind. So too for the virtues of faith,
hope, charity, which increase by acts of faith, hope, charity, as aided by God.
There is no parallel, however, in the losing of the virtues. Language of
“decrease” is appropriate to an analysis of the acquired virtues. That decrease
will be due to lack of use of that virtue or infrequent use of it. By inactivity,
there can be an erosion of that inclination to such act, to the point that the
habit disappears. A single act will not destroy such virtue, which had been
acquired and built up by acts of that kind. In his lengthy discussion of the
loss of charity, however, Aquinas disallows talk of “decrease.” Failing to act
out of that virtue, or acting only infrequently out of it, may be inadvisable, as
rendering the will prone to fall from charity. But such inactivity does not
forfeit charity. Rather, the virtue of charity is lost only by sin, mortal sin, and
is destroyed by a single mortal sin.75
Charity involves fellowship between humans and God, due to the divine
initiative. On the basis of God’s loving, there is a mutual love between
humans and God. One loves God above all things and loves others in relation
to God. A mortal sin destroys this community. In sinning mortally, one acts
against the love of God and of neighbor; in this there is a loss of the virtue
that makes charitable acting possible. It may be that charity will be restored,
but that will not be due to the efforts of a person to regain it. The restoration
of charity, as in its first giving, is due to God’s initiative, in accordance with
God’s saving will for that person. It may be that there will be no return of
that person who has lost charity to fellowship with God.
Aquinas can adopt a different image to account for the destructive effect
of mortal sinning. God always offers God’s love to the possessor of the virtue
of charity. The appropriate response is that person’s own loving. Sometimes,
however, a person will refuse that response, instead opting to put an obstacle
to God’s offered love. No longer in relationship to the source of spiritual life,
the virtue of charity thus dies.76 That mortal sin is possible is due to the
human will. The virtue of charity inclines its possessor to the act of charity. It
does not necessitate such acting. By the will, the one endowed with charity
may decide to act in a way that is counter to charity; the virtue then is lost.
Mortal sin also destroys the infused moral virtues that accompany charity
in its initial infusion. Those virtues are dependent on charity for their proper
ordering and for their good expression. Once charity is destroyed, so too are
the infused moral virtues.77 They will be regained, if they are, only when and
if God restores, by God’s free giving, charity to a person. But, the loss of
charity does not mean the loss of the habit of faith or of that of hope.78 The
mortal sin that destroys charity does not destroy either of the others. What is
removed by that sin is the form that perfects them. Aquinas refers frequently
to “formed faith” and “unformed faith”; and there is a formed and an
unformed hope as well.79 The form of charity disposes well the believer, the
one who hopes, to the God who is the beatifying end; the loss of charity
means that belief and hope are no longer related to that God in a way that is
savingly conducive. Whether formed or unformed, however, the habit of
faith remains; it is no longer virtuous, a full virtue. But, it is still faith. The
same is true of hope, whether formed or unformed. Both are, and remain
(with or without charity), a gift of God. There can, then, be a move from
formed faith to unformed faith; that is due to mortal sin, to the instability of
the will and the failure to act out of the charity that binds one to God as
beatifying end. There may be a move from unformed faith to formed. But,
that is up to God, to the God who gives God’s gifts to whom God wills. As
long as charity is absent, the act of faith will not justify before God. In terms
of the threefold credere: when the act of faith issues from the virtue of faith,
as shaped by charity, all three aspects are found. One believes God, believes
correctly about God, believes in a way that expresses love of God and so
brings one closer to that God as end. When charity no longer forms faith, one
will still believe God and on the basis of God as first truth; one will not
believe unto God, believe in a way that expresses love, bespeaks a correct
orientation to God. As for hope, since charity is missing, the one who hopes
will not do the moral good that is meritorious before God, and so will not
hope in a way that facilitates the end to which one aspires. To destroy the
habit of faith, or of hope, a vicious act is required, an act of a vice that is
proportioned to that habit. Hence, faith is destroyed by unbelief, hope by acts
of despair or of presumption.
DURATION
Will the theological virtues remain in heaven?80 Guided by the Apostle Paul
(1 Corinthians 13:8, 10–12), Aquinas denies the virtues of faith and of hope
to the beatified. These virtues, suited to the present life, will not be needed in
heaven. At the core of each of these virtues is a fundamental imperfection,
when viewed in comparison with the heavenly state. “Now we see in a glass
darkly, then we will see face to face.” In the entry into heaven, belief will
yield to vision, which is a superior form of knowing. And, hope has to do
with a future good. When that good is no longer future, but present, the need
for hope is removed. The one who had hoped, which sustained her in the
journey to God in the confidence of God’s aid, now comprehends, clings,
directly, to the God who is her end. Of the theological virtues, only charity
will remain in heaven. By charity, people are united in will to God. In
heaven, that union is consummated; charity remains, but in its fullest form, as
the person wills God in the immediate presence of God, who loves in return.
In his Christology, Aquinas adds nuance to this account of duration. Did
Christ have the theological virtues during his earthly sojourn?81 On initial
reflection, one might think that he did; for, he had the fullness of grace, and
the theological virtues are infused with habitual grace. However, Aquinas
believed that Christ enjoyed the beatific vision from the first moment of his
conception. And so, what holds of those in heaven, holds of Christ. He had
the virtue of charity, and in its fullness (and so in his every human action
related his acts to God as end), but lacked the virtues of faith, of hope, as
unnecessary, to one who is blessed. Yet in that same question on the grace
and virtues of Christ, Aquinas adds that while Jesus did not need these
virtues, he still had what was perfect or complete in them.82 What Aquinas
means becomes clearer from the parallel discussion in the disputed question
on hope. As in the ST, Aquinas thinks there of a twofold object of hope: God
as future good, and God in God’s aiding, by which the one who hopes can
attain to God as end. Aquinas then links language of imperfection, and, of
completion or perfection, to the two objects of hope. With regards to the
principal object of hope, there is imperfection, because that object is in the
future, not presently held. But, with regards to divine help, hope is a
tendency of someone perfect, for human perfection consists in holding on to
God.83 And so, Aquinas explicitly states later in the same article, with
regards to the completeness of the virtue of hope, Christ possessed hope
utterly in this sense, since he held utterly on to God’s help.84 Aquinas adds
that the same is true of the virtue of faith, which too has a completion or
perfection in addition to its fundamental imperfection. Faith is imperfect in
that one does not yet see what one believes, but perfect in that it holds on to
the witness of the first truth.85 Through this discussion of Christ, Aquinas has
nicely indicated for both hope and faith a fundamental continuity between the
present state and heaven, while remaining faithful to Paul’s point.
SOURCES
That the discussion of the theological virtues takes as its point of departure
what Scripture proclaims about faith, hope, and charity, and that the
scriptural witness frames the analysis, is patent enough. Without Scripture,
Aquinas would be unable to discuss these properly Christian things. In
reflecting on these virtues, Aquinas has been aided by the intervening
Christian theological tradition. He is not, obviously, the first theologian to
write about faith and the others, or to think of these virtues as theological;
there is the weighty precedent of such as Augustine and Gregory the Great,
themselves following after the Apostle Paul on these virtues. Post-scriptural
Christian theologians can also provide stimulus to fruitful interpretation in
particular ways. Aquinas’s understanding of faith as intellectual assent stands
in close dependence on Augustine;86 he owes Augustine as well for the
parsing of the act of faith in terms of the threefold credere;87 and, Augustine
too had defined virtue in a useful way, emphasizing in that definition what is
pertinent to these particular virtues (that is, the grace of God, working these
virtues in their recipient).88 That definition was conveyed to Aquinas through
its quotation in the Lombard’s Sentences. The Lombard could in his own way
further Aquinas’s analysis of the theological virtues. The Lombard’s
identification of charity with the Holy Spirit lies behind Aquinas’s insistence,
to the contrary, that charity is something created in the soul, infused by God
to make possible acts pleasing to God.89 The person is not, as the Lombard’s
straightforward identification would suggest, simply moved by the Spirit;
that person has an endowment, itself owed to God’s initiative, that makes the
person capable of acts on the supernatural order. It is the person who loves,
with the help of the Holy Spirit. The Lombard too helped Aquinas to clarify
an important point when it comes to hope. Does one hope on the basis of
grace and merits?90 Rather, Aquinas insists, one hopes for God and in God,
not in one’s own accomplishments. And yet hope does not exclude merit.
God seeks the graced behavior of those who will reach God as end. And so,
if that is what the Lombard meant, one can allow a place to merits in the
realization of one’s hope. And, Aquinas is the beneficiary of what he has
read in non-Christian sources, not least in Aristotle. The questions on these
virtues are replete with references to the Ethics, whether for a definition of
habit and virtue, or for an account of the faith, of the hope, of the love, with
which Aristotle was familiar. Christian faith is like, but unlike, the faith that
the philosopher knew; so too for Christian hope and for Christian charity.
Those comments could be useful, then, to put these virtues, unknown to
Aristotle, in their proper relief.
NOTES
1. In the Summa theologiae, Aquinas discusses the theological virtues at I-
II q.62, and in some of the articles in questions that closely follow (q.64 a.4;
q.65 a.2–5; q.66 a.6; q.67 a.3–6). The discrete discussions of the theological
virtues are found at the beginning of the Secunda Secundae: II-II q.1–16, for
faith; q.17–22, for hope; and, q.23–46, for charity. Aquinas returns to the
theological virtues in his Christology: III q.7 a.3–4, 9. Some of his
Quaestiones disputatae are devoted to theological virtues: de caritate (in
thirteen articles), de correctione fraterna (in two articles), and de spe (in four
articles). For all of the disputed questions on the virtues in English
translation, see Thomas Aquinas Disputed Questions on the Virtues, ed. E. M.
Atkins and Thomas Williams, trans. E. M. Atkins (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2005).
2. This is argued at length of charity at ST II-II q.23 a.2.
3. For the following paragraphs in the text, see ST I-II q.62 a.1.
4. On the increase of charity, see ST II-II q.24 a.4–7.
5. See ST I-II q.62 a.4; there, reference is made as well to the order of
perfection, examined later in the text.
6. See, e.g., ST I-II q.62 a.3 s.c.
7. For the precepts of faith, see ST II-II q.16; for hope, II-II q.22; for
charity, II-II q.44.
8. In treating each of the theological virtues, Aquinas is flexible in the
actual order of discussion. Thus, in discussing faith, in looking at faith itself,
he considers its object, act, and only then the virtue, and then turns to the
gifts, the vices, and the precepts. In discussing hope, he considers hope itself
and its subject, then its gift, and then the opposing vices, and finally the
precepts. For the order of the discussion of charity, see below in the text,
under “Charity.”
9. ST II-II q.2 a.1. For scholarly discussions of Aquinas on faith: Benoit
Duroux, La Psychologie de la foi chez S. Thomas d’Aquin (Tournai: Desclée
de Brouwer, 1963); Tad W. Guzie, “The Act of Faith according to St.
Thomas: A Study in Theological Methodology,” The Thomist 29 (1965):
239–80; Daniel Bourgeois, “‘Inchoatio vitae eternae’: La Dimension
eschatologique de la vertu théologale de foi chez saint Thomas d’Aquin,”
Sapienza 27 (1974): 272–314; Stephen F. Brown, “The Theological Virtue of
Faith (IIa IIae, qq.1–16),” in Stephen J. Pope, ed., The Ethics of Aquinas
(Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 2002), 221–31.
10. ST II-II q.4 a.1.
11. ST II-II q.2 a.2.
12. ST II-II q.6 a.1.
13. James 2:19 refers to the believing of the demons. For Aquinas, that
belief is not due to a gift of God. And, it does not involve assenting to the
actual truths revealed by God and conveyed through the church. Rather, it is
based on evident signs: in seeing those signs, the demons recognize that what
is taught is from God. That is the basis, and extent, of their believing. That is
how they have read the signs, and so they have opted for a faith. But, that
faith is vague, and certainly is not salvific. They are not thereby correctly
related to God, nor less hostile to God and those who love God. See ST II-II
q.5 a.2. For the denial that such faith is even unformed faith (discussed later
in the text), see ad 2.
14. ST II-II q.1 a.7, 16.
15. ST I q.1 a.1.
16. ST II-II q.1 a.2 ad 2.
17. ST II-II q.1 a.2 obj. 2 and ad 2.
18. ST II-II q.1 a.2.
19. ST II-II q.1 a.6.
20. The verse from Hebrews is quoted at ST II-II q.1 a.7.
21. ST II-II q.1 a.8.
22. In that same article, Aquinas notes that others think that six, not seven,
articles fall under each main heading, the Godhead, and, the humanity of
Christ.
23. ST II-II q.2 a.7.
24. Ibid.
25. See ST I q.1 a.8 ad 2, and in the same question, a.9 ad 2. For Scripture
as the locus of God’s revealing of saving truth, see too ST II-II q.1 a.9 ad 2.
26. On this work of the council and the pope, see ST II-II q.1 a.9–10. For
the guiding work of the Holy Spirit, see II-II q.1 a.9, s.c.
27. See ST II-II q.11 a.1.
28. ST III q.42.
29. ST I q.1.
30. See ST II-II q.4 a.3–5.
31. For the denial that unformed faith is a “virtue,” see ST II-II q.4 a.5, and
I-II q.65 a.4.
32. ST II-II q.4 a.4.
33. ST II-II q.10.
34. ST II-II q.10 a.1–2.
35. ST II-II q.3.
36. ST II-II q.13.
37. ST II-II q.11.
38. ST II-II q.5 a.3.
39. For this description of the object of hope, see, e.g., ST II-II q.17 a.1.
For scholarly discussions of hope in Aquinas: C.-A. Bernard, Théologie de
l’espérance selon Saint Thomas d’Aquin (Paris: Vrin, 1961); G. M. Conlon,
“The Certitude of Hope,” The Thomist 10 (1947): 76–119, 226–52; V. De
Couesnongle, “Le ‘Dieu de l’espérance’ de saint Thomas Aquinas,” Studia
Theologica Varsaviensis 12 (1974): 103–20; Romanus Cessario, “The
Theological Virtue of Hope (IIa IIae, qq. 17–22),” in Stephen J. Pope, ed.,
The Ethics of Aquinas (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press,
2002), 232–43.
40. For the language of principal and secondary, see ST II-II q.17 a.4.
41. For despair, see ST II-II q.20; for presumption, II-II q.21.
42. ST II-II q.20 a.2.
43. ST II-II q.21 a.1.
44. See too ST II-II q.21 a.2.
45. See S. Pfürtner, Luther and Aquinas on Salvation, trans. E. Quinn (New
York: Sheed and Ward, 1964); see as well Joseph Wawrykow, God’s Grace
and Human Action: “Merit” in the Theology of Thomas Aquinas (Notre
Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1995), 247–59.
46. For scholarly discussions of charity in Aquinas: A. J. Falanga, Charity:
The Form of the Virtues according to Saint Thomas (Washington, D.C.:
Catholic University of America Press, 1948); J. Aumann, “Thomistic
Evaluation of Love and Charity,” Angelicum 55 (1978): 534–56; P. Wadell,
The Primacy of Love: An Introduction to the Ethics of Thomas Aquinas (New
York: Paulist Press, 1992); G. Mansini, “Similitudo, Communicatio, and the
Friendship of Charity in Aquinas,” in Thomistica, Recherches de théologie
ancienne et médiévale, Supplement 1 (Leuven, 1995), 1–26; E.
Schockenhoff, “The Theological Virtue of Charity (IIa IIae, qq.23–46),” in
Stephen J. Pope, ed., The Ethics of Aquinas (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown
University Press, 2002), 244–58; M. Sherwin, By Knowledge and by Love:
Charity and Knowledge in the Moral Theology of St. Thomas Aquinas
(Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 2004).
47. ST II-II q.23 a.6; see too I-II q.66 a.6. In this assessment, Aquinas is
echoing Paul, I Corinthians 13:13.
48. ST II-II q.23 a.1.
49. On the kinds of friendship, see ST II-II q.23 1 obj. 3 and ad 3.
50. ST II-II q.25 a.12.
51. ST II-II q.24 a.9.
52. ST II-II q.24 a.8.
53. Matthew 5:44 is quoted at ST II-II q.25 a.8 s.c.
54. ST II-II q.26.
55. ST II-II q.26 a.8.
56. ST II-II q.26 a.9.
57. ST II-II q.26 a.10.
58. ST II-II q.26 a.11.
59. ST II-II q.27.
60. ST II-II q.28.
61. ST II-II q.29.
62. ST II-II q.30.
63. ST II-II q.31.
64. ST II-II q.32.
65. ST II-II q.33.
66. ST II-II q.34.
67. ST II-II q.35 for sloth; q.36 for envy.
68. ST II-II q.37–42.
69. ST II-II q.43.
70. See, e.g., ST I-II q.62 a.4; II-II q.4 a.3; II-II q.23 a.8.
71. For charity as form, mother, and root, see, e.g., ST I-II q.62 a.4, as well
as II-II q.23 a.8.
72. On the need for charity for perfect virtue, see, e.g., ST II-II q.23 a.7,
and I-II q.65 a.4.
73. ST I-II q.65.
74. For the following, see ST I-II q.65 a.2–3.
75. See ST II-II q.24 a.10–12.
76. ST II-II q.24 a.12.
77. ST I-II q.65 a.2.
78. ST I-II q.65 a.4.
79. For a reference to a “formed hope,” see, e.g., ST II-II q.17 a.8 ad 3; in
the background here is the understanding of the order of perfection that holds
for the theological virtues, as discussed in ST I-II q.62 a.4.
80. ST I-II q.67 a.3–6.
81. ST III q.7 a.3, did Christ have faith; a.4, did he have hope?
82. ST III q.7 a.9 ad 1.
83. QD de spe, a.1, ad 4; trans. Atkins, p.222.
84. QD de spe, a.1, ad 12; trans. Atkins, p.225.
85. QD de spe, a.1, ad 4; trans. Atkins, p.222. See as well de spe, a.4, ad
14; Atkins, p.239.
86. See ST II-II q.2 a.1 s.c., where Aquinas notes that this is Augustine’s
definition in de praedestinatione sanctorum.
87. See ST II-II q.2 a.2 s.c.
88. See ST I-II q.55 a.4.
89. For the Lombard’s identification, see Super Sent Bk. I, d.XVII. For
Aquinas’s discussion, see ST II-II q.23 a.2. On this and other points on which
thirteenth-century scholastics questioned the Lombard, see E. Synan,
“Brother Thomas, the Master, and the Masters,” in St Thomas Aquinas 1274–
1974 Commemorative Studies, vol. 2 (Toronto: PIMS, 1974), 219–42.
90. Aquinas refers at ST II-II q.17 a.1 obj. 2 to a saying in the third book of
the Sentences (d.26) that appears to make merits, as well as grace, the object
of hope.
PART V
HUMAN KNOWLEDGE
MARTIN PICKAVÉ
SCIENTIA AS KNOWLEDGE
As I noted earlier, it is far from clear which expression in Aquinas’s
philosophical vocabulary corresponds to what we would usually refer to as
knowledge. But despite the reservations mentioned above, it can be argued
that Aquinas’s scientia is equivalent to what we call knowledge. When we
describe knowledge in the broadest possible terms, we usually compare it to
belief or opinion and say that knowledge possesses something that sets it
apart from mere belief or opinion. The task of the epistemologist is to capture
what exactly knowledge has that belief lacks. Aquinas similarly compares
scientia with belief (and faith) with the aim of determining how they differ
from one another. What would be the point of such a comparison, if scientia
were for Aquinas right from the start only a very restricted and highly special
sort of cognition, such as a specific scientific understanding? It is obvious
that belief and faith are different from that in many ways. But isn’t there
space in between for another cognitive attitude, the comparison with which is
more elucidating for the case of belief and faith than the comparison with a
strange and highly specific form of cognition?
One way to distinguish scientia from belief or opinion (opinio) and faith
(fides) is presumably with respect to the objects to which these different
cognitive attitudes are directed. However, Aquinas frequently opts for
another way. In his commentary on the Posterior Analytics, for example, he
distinguishes them by focusing on the subject that has such attitudes. From
the subject’s point of view, scientia and belief and faith are similar insofar as
they all incline their subjects to only one of a pair of contrary propositions, as
opposed to, for instance, mere suspicion (suspicio), where reason is not
completely inclined to one or the other. But they differ insofar as belief and
faith are “with fear of the opposite” (cum formidine alterius).30 In other texts,
Aquinas puts the comparison somewhat differently. There mere belief is
characterized by the fear of the opposite, whereas in both scientia and faith
such fear is absent.31 The apparent contradiction disappears if we keep in
mind that in the first text, Aquinas talks about belief and fear merely insofar
as these are cognitive states brought about by the intellect itself. It is true that
faith involves a firm commitment to what is believed, but such a commitment
“without fear of the opposite” is not brought about by the intellect itself, but
by other factors such as the will and grace.32 If, however, we simply focus on
the overall degree of conviction involved in the three states, not regarding the
source of the conviction, scientia and faith are more similar to each other
than to belief.
All this shows that for Aquinas scientia is inseparably linked with
certainty (certitudo).33 According to Aquinas, I cannot be said to have
scientia of something if I am in doubt about it. The notion of certainty also
explains why Aquinas is so prone to restrict scientia to a clearly defined class
of objects. In another passage in his commentary on the Posterior Analytics,
he provides some sort of definition of what it means to know (scire). The
definition also explains why scientia is necessarily about what is true and
involves a grasp of the causes of that which is known:
One might wonder whether this definition is complete; to give just one
example, it does not mention, as Aquinas insists elsewhere, that scientia is
always of something universal. But however this may be, together with
Aquinas’s remarks on certainty and the absence of “fear of the opposite,” the
definition illustrates that, for Aquinas, a series of conditions, both internal
and external from the point of view of the knowing person, have to be met
for there to be scientia. In this way Aquinas combines elements of externalist
and internalist epistemologies. If knowing is supposed to be a perfect form of
cognizing, it cannot consist simply in a mental state that is founded on more
basic beliefs and characterized by a high degree of conviction; people in such
a state could, at least in principle, be entirely wrong. Scientia also requires
that the reasons on the basis of which we are convinced of the truth of
something be adequate. Aquinas’s remarks on certainty make it especially
clear that he takes the certainty involved in scientia not only to be subjective
certainty, but a certainty which precludes the very possibility of scientia
being objectively uncertain. This leads Aquinas to restrict knowledge or
scientia to necessary objects. On the other hand, it is not enough for scientia
that someone have a true belief, including a grasp of the causes of what he
believes to be the case, and that the true belief be about something that could
not be otherwise. If such a person lacks subjective certainty and is “with fear
of the opposite,” one cannot, according to Aquinas, attribute scientia to her
either. Moreover, due to it being a perfect form of cognizing, scientia also
involves for Aquinas what Jaakko Hintikka has called the KK-thesis: a
knower in the sense of someone having scientia also knows that she knows.35
Aquinas’s definition of scire and scientia looks like a definition of
knowing and knowledge. From a modern perspective his definition is
admittedly strange. But there is no reason to assume that Aquinas talks about
something other than knowledge rather than that his views on knowledge
differ from ours in interesting ways. If we start with the idea that Aquinas’s
scientia is something completely different from our idea of knowledge, we
deprive ourselves of the possibility of recognizing how different Aquinas’s
take on (what we call) knowledge is. It is true that ultimately Aquinas’s
characterization of knowledge does not apply to many instances of what we
would call knowledge, for instance, knowledge of contingent facts. This,
however, is not because Aquinas restricts his understanding of knowledge
right away to necessary facts, but because only in grasping necessary facts
can we finally attain real and absolute certainty and thus perfect cognition.
When Aquinas insists, for example, that we do not have knowledge of
contingent facts, this does not mean he is denying that we can cognize
contingent facts or that we can have true cognition of contingent facts. It just
means that Aquinas does not think that our cognition of contingent facts
qualifies as knowledge in the strict sense because such cognition lacks the
high degree of certainty that he considers as required for knowledge.
But where there is perfection, there are things that fall short of perfection.
By insisting that knowledge is perfect cognition, Aquinas turns knowledge in
the strict sense into an ideal. Yet the various cognitive states that fall short of
that ideal are not necessarily discounted as mere beliefs. In the passage
quoted above, Aquinas insists that perfect cognition requires cognition of the
causes; in other words, knowledge as perfect cognition is explanatory. But
Aquinas admits that we sometimes know that something is the case not
because we know its immediate causes, but because we know certain other
facts from which the truth of what we know follows; for instance, when we
know about the existence of a cause through the existence of its effects. In
those cases we can be said to have knowledge in an extended and qualified
sense, and we possess more than just belief. This is just one example; there
are many other ways in which true cognition can fall short of knowledge
proper, but where Aquinas is happy to talk about knowledge (scientia) in a
qualified sense.36
In different contexts, Aquinas emphasizes different aspects of what I take
to be his overall account of what it means to know. The absence of “fear of
the opposite” was, as we have seen, a key criterion for distinguishing
knowledge from faith and mere belief. When Aquinas explains what causes
the cognizing agent not to be uncertain and in “fear of the opposite,” he
usually points to the grasp of principles, “for knowledge [scientia] possesses
certainty, which results from the understanding of principles.”37 This leads to
the question of how understanding of principles leads to certainty, a question
Aquinas usually answers by providing a foundationalist account of
knowledge. Foundationalism distinguishes between basic and nonbasic
beliefs, where nonbasic beliefs are accepted (and known), directly or
indirectly, on the basis of basic beliefs. Aquinas undeniably endorses
foundationalism when he declares that scientia “proceeds from propositions
which are true, first, and immediate, i.e., from propositions which are not
demonstrated by something intermediate but which are evident by
themselves.”38 Such basic beliefs are for Aquinas either self-evident
principles, such as the principle of noncontradiction, or beliefs that we
immediately accept on the basis of sense perception. The point of the theory
of demonstrative syllogisms, as we find it in Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics
(and in Aquinas’s commentary), is thus to explain how nonbasic beliefs are
accepted on the basis of basic beliefs.39
It is very common among interpreters to classify Aquinas’s
epistemological views as a whole as a sort of foundationalism.40 This
tendency is understandable in light of what he says about how we acquire
certainty in knowledge and if we turn to his commentary on Aristotle’s
Posterior Analytics as a point of reference for his epistemology. Recently,
however, some commentators have argued that the picture of Aquinas as a
foundationalist is flawed and that he should rather be thought of as defending
“an externalism with reliabilist elements.”41 From what has been said above,
it should be clear that I do not consider Aquinas an epistemological
internalist committed to a purely foundationalist view of knowledge, but I
also do not want to downplay the undeniably foundationalist aspects of his
epistemology. If what has been said is correct, foundationalism only
describes some elements of Aquinas’s account of knowledge, namely how
we acquire (subjective) certainty and also how we understand something
through its causes; these are the elements that he examines in his
commentary on the Posterior Analytics.42 But there are other elements, of a
more externalist sort, that also have to be in place for something to count as
knowledge. A fair appreciation of Aquinas’s epistemology will have to do
justice to both tendencies.43
It is easy to imagine someone resisting my reading of Aquinas’s account
of scientia as an account of knowledge. Take the example of the principles of
scientia: given Aquinas’s definition it would follow from my identification
of scientia with knowledge not only that we have no scientia of those
principles but also that we do not know them; a very strange result indeed.
But the objection is less problematic than it seems. Although we do not have
proper scientia or knowledge of these principles, we can still be said to know
them in some qualified sense,44 for our cognitive grasp of the principles is
somewhat similar to knowledge proper. Consider as an example the self-
evident principle that the whole is greater than its part. We grasp this
principle presumably without “fear of the opposite” and although we do not
grasp it by means of an inference, that is, by means of an inferential
justification, we still perceive its truth by perceiving the self-evident
relationship between the various terms making up the principle, that is, we
accept it by means of a noninferential justification.
This response, however, invites a new problem: it now seems as if
Aquinas ranks scientia higher than the simple acts of understanding on which
scientia is based, for scientia is the paradigmatic case of knowledge and
knowledge of principles is knowledge only in a qualified sense. And why
after all is only scientia perfect cognition and not the much simpler intuitive
act by which we grasp the principles? An answer to these problems will have
to point to some facts about the nature of the human mind. Human beings are
rational beings and this means that the typical mode of operation of our
intellective capacities is discursive reasoning. Unlike higher-level intellectual
creatures (i.e., angels), we do not understand everything intuitively; in
understanding we typically move “from one thing to another” (ab uno in
aliud).45 From this perspective, scientia seems to be the mode of
understanding most appropriate to human beings, because in scientia too we
move from one thing to another, from the understanding of the causes and
principles to the understanding of the conclusion.
NOTES
1. For the problems in mapping Aquinas’s epistemic categories onto ours,
see Eleonore Stump, Aquinas (London: Routledge, 2003), 217–43; John I.
Jenkins, Knowledge and Faith in Thomas Aquinas (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1997), 15–17; Scott MacDonald, “Theory of Knowledge,”
in Norman Kretzmann and Eleonore Stump, eds., The Cambridge
Companion to Aquinas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993),
160–95.
2. Aquinas talks about false cognition (cognitio falsa) in ST I q.17 a.3; ST
I-II q.2 a.3 ad 3; and In DA, lib.3, lect.12.
3. In PA, lib.1, lect.44; ST I-II q.57; QDVCom a.7. For Aristotle’s account
of the five so-called intellectual virtues, see Nicomachean Ethics, bk VI.
4. See, for instance, Myles F. Burnyeat, “Aristotle on Understanding
Knowledge,” in Enrico Berti, ed., Aristotle on Science: The “Posterior
Analytics,” Proceedings of the Eighth Symposium Aristotelicum (Padua:
Editrice Antenore, 1981), 97–139.
5. Thomas of York engages with skeptical arguments in his Sapientiale,
bk VI, c.24; for an edition of this text, see John P. E. Scully, Reality and
Truth in Thomas of York (Ph.D. diss., University of Toronto, 1960), vol. 2,
338–60. Siger’s discussion of skepticism is examined in Antoine Côté, “Siger
and the Skeptic,” Review of Metaphysics 60 (2006): 305–25. For more on
medieval discussions of skepticism, see Dominik Perler, Zweifel und
Gewissheit: Skeptische Debatten im Mittelalter (Frankfurt a.M.:
Klostermann, 2006); Henrik Lagerlund, ed., Rethinking the History of
Skepticism: The Missing Medieval Background (Leiden: Brill, 2010).
6. For the first, see ST I q.84 a.1; for the second, see, for instance, QDP,
q.7, q.10, ad 5; QDV, q.1, a.2. Parts of bk IV of Aristotle’s Metaphysics,
namely the discussion of the principle of noncontradiction, were often read
by medieval authors as Aristotle’s response to skepticism. In this sense it is
possible to read the relevant parts of Aquinas’s commentary on the
Metaphysics as also engaging in such a response.
7. See, for instance, ST I q.91 a.3; ST I q.93 a.2, a.4, and a.6.
8. See Aristotle, Politics, 1253a9; Parts of Animals, 658a8; Progression of
Animals, 704b15.
9. Metaphysics, 980a21. For the importance this statement has for
Aquinas, see Jan A. Aertsen, “Aquinas and the Human Desire for
Knowledge,” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 79 (2005): 411–30.
10. See, for instance, SCG, lib.3, cap.48: “Impossibile est naturale
desiderium esse inane; natura enim nihil facit frustra. Esset autem inane
desiderium naturae si nunquam posset impleri.”
11. See, for instance, SCG, lib.2, cap.60: “Sed homo habet propriam
operationem supra alia animalia, scilicet intelligere et ratiocinari, quae est
operatio hominis inquantum est homo, ut Aristoteles dicit in I Ethicorum.”
See Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, I 7.
12. A more exhaustive examination of Aquinas’s account of the reliability
of our cognitive capacities can be found in Norman Kretzmann, “Infallibility,
Error, and Ignorance,” in Richard Bosley and Martin Tweedale, eds.,
Aristotle and His Medieval Interpreters (Calgary: University of Calgary
Press, 1991), 159–94.
13. For more details on Aquinas’s cognitive psychology, see Stump,
Aquinas, 244–76; Robert Pasnau, Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002).
14. For Aquinas’s account of sensory cognition and the sensory powers,
see ST I q.78 a.3 and a.4; In DA, lib.2, lect.13–24 and lib.3, lect.1–6; QDA,
a.13.
15. ST I q.75 a.2; translation by Robert Pasnau, Thomas Aquinas: The
Treatise on Human Nature: Summa Theologiae 1a 75–89 (Indianapolis:
Hackett, 2002), 5.
16. ST I q.75 a.2; QDA, a.1 and a.2; In DA, lib.3, lect.7; ST I q.84 a.2; ST I
q.86 a.2 ad 4.
17. ST I q.84 a.7.
18. In BDT, q.1, a.2.
19. QDV, q.2, a.3, obj.19 and ad 19.
20. See, for instance, In BDT, q.1, a.3.
21. ST I q.79 a.3; ST I q.54 a.4; QDA, a.4; SCG, lib.2, cap.77; In DA, lib.3,
lect.10. Despite its name, the agent intellect is not the power in and by which
thinking actually takes place in human beings. Aquinas calls the thinking
power the possible intellect, but for sake of brevity I will refer to this power
simply as the intellect.
22. Not surprisingly, Aquinas associates innate cognition with Plato. In
addition to the two arguments mentioned in the following, Aquinas
sometimes also argues against a specific aspect of Plato’s version of innate
cognition, namely the idea that the soul exists (and understands) before it is
joined with the body: see, for instance, QDV, q.10, a.6; QDV, q.18, a.7.
23. QDV, q.10, a.6; QDV, q.19, a.1; ST I q.84 a.3; QDA, q.15.
24. QDV, q.10, a.6; QDV, q.19, a.1; ST I q.84 a.3; QDA, q.15.
25. QDV, q.10, a.6; QDV, q.11, a.1; QDA, q.15.
26. See, for instance, QDV, q.10, a.6, ad 6; QDV, q.11, a.1, ad 5.
27. He also says so explicitly in In PA, lib.2, lect.20. See also Horst Seidl,
“Über die Erkenntnis erster, allgemeiner Prinzipien nach Thomas von
Aquin,” in Albert Zimmermann, ed., Thomas von Aquin: Werk und Wirkung
im Licht neuerer Forschungen, Miscellanea Mediaevalia 19 (Berlin: De
Gruyter, 1988), 103–16.
28. QDV, q.11, a.1. Some interpreters, however, interpret Aquinas’s
account of cognition in more innativist terms. For a recent example of this
tendency, see Houston Smit, “Aquinas’s Abstractionism,” Medieval
Philosophy and Theology 10 (2001): 85–118.
29. ST I-II q.109 a.1; In BDT, q.1, a.1. See also Etienne Gilson, “Pourquoi
saint Thomas a critiqué saint Augustin,” Archives d’histoire doctrinale et
littéraire du Moyen Age 1 (1926/27): 5–127.
30. In PA, lib.1, lect.1. Aquinas takes the expression cum formidine alterius
from Avicenna and uses it frequently in his writings: see, for instance, In
BDT, q.3, a.1; Super Sent III, d.17, q. un., a.2, qc.1; Super Sent III, d.23, q.2,
a.2, qc.1; QDV, q.14, a.1; In DA, lib.1, lect.4; ST II-II q.2 a.1. Where the
Latin translation has cum formidine, the Arabic text rather suggests a
translation as cum possibilitate; see Avicenna, Liber de anima, tract. V, cap.
1, ed. S. Van Riet (Louvain/Leiden: Editions Orientalistes/Brill, 1968), 79,
including the editor’s note. I thank Deborah Black for pointing this out to me.
A rendering as “with the possibility of the opposite” (cum possibilitate
alterius) suggests a less subjective understanding of the cognitive states in
question.
31. For instance, in ST I-II q.67 a.3.
32. See ST II-II q.1 a.4 and q.2 a.1.
33. See also SCG, lib.3, cap.39.
34. In PA, lib.1, lect.4; see Aristotle, Metaphysics, 993b28–31. Aquinas’s
definition is based on Posterior Analytics, 71b9–12, but it is interesting to see
what Aquinas adds to Aristotle’s words: by saying that knowing is perfectly
cognizing Aquinas explains why knowing involves grasp of the causes, and
by bringing certainty into the picture he explains why we only know what is
necessary. The notion of certainty is in general absent from Aristotle’s
epistemology and was introduced into medieval epistemology via the Arabic
philosophers. For more on this see Robert Pasnau, “Science and Certainty,”
in Robert Pasnau and Christina Van Dyke, eds., The Cambridge History of
Medieval Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 357–
68.
35. QDV, q.10, a.10 ad 5. For Aquinas and the KK-thesis see Christopher J.
Martin, “Self-Knowledge and Cognitive Ascent: Thomas Aquinas and Peter
Olivi on the KK-Thesis,” in Henrik Lagerlund, ed., Forming the Mind:
Essays on the Internal Senses and the Mind/Body Problem from Avicenna to
the Medical Enlightenment (Dordrecht: Springer, 2007), 93–108.
36. For a very good discussion of some of these points, see MacDonald,
“Theory of Knowledge,” 174–80. Aquinas mentions some of the “improper”
modes of knowing in In PA, lib.1, lect.4.
37. ST I-II q.67 a.3.
38. In PA, lib.1, lect.4.
39. For a very detailed account of Aquinas’s foundationalism, see
MacDonald, “Theory of Knowledge.”
40. See, for instance, MacDonald, “Theory of Knowledge.”
41. Stump, Aquinas, 235. Jenkins, Knowledge and Faith, and Kretzmann,
“Infallibility, Error, and Ignorance,” endorse a similar view.
42. In the prologue to his commentary on the Posterior Analytics (In PA,
lib.1, lect.1), Aquinas remarks on the title of Aristotle’s work. He notes that
the expression “Analytics” means the same as “resolution” (resolutio) and
explains that both the Prior and Posterior Analytics have to do with the
analysis or resolution of judgments; for only in this way can we achieve
certainty in our judgments. From this it is clear that Aquinas considers the
Posterior Analytics as dealing with how the knowing subject acquires
certainty.
43. For a very different attempt to harmonize the externalist and internalist
elements of Aquinas’s epistemology, see Thomas S. Hibbs, “Aquinas, Virtue,
and Recent Epistemology,” Review of Metaphysics 52 (1999): 573–94. Hibbs
sees similarities between Aquinas and modern proponents of virtue
epistemology.
Since I have emphasized the notion of certainty (certitudo) for Aquinas’s
account of knowledge, I should add a note of caution. For it is not entirely
clear what Aquinas means by certitudo. It obviously means more than what
we normally call certainty, for it captures more than just, say, the total
absence of doubt. Certitudo also requires that something cannot be otherwise.
And when Aquinas compares different areas of knowledge, he remarks that
some, like arithmetic, are more certain than others (see, for instance, In PA,
lib.1, lect.41). What I have said about Aquinas’s account of knowledge as a
whole seems also to apply to one of the key notions of this account: in order
for something to be certain (certum), a series of conditions have to be met,
some of which are internal to the knower, and some of which are external.
44. In PA, lib.1, lect.4.
45. QDV, q.15, a.1; ST I q.79 a.8; In PA, lib.1, lect.1.
46. ST I q.3; In BDT, q.1, a.2; In BDT, q.6, a.3. For a discussion of the
corresponding article of the condemnation, i.e., article 215, see Roland
Hissette, Enquête sur les 219 articles condamnés à Paris le 7 mars 1277
(Louvain: Publications universitaires, 1977), 32–34.
47. In BDT, q.6, a.3. For a thorough discussion of the various texts in
which Aquinas develops his view of the impossibility of quidditative
knowledge of God (in this life), see John F. Wippel, The Metaphysical
Thought of Thomas Aquinas (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of
America Press, 2000), 501–75.
48. Our knowledge of the existence of God is, of course, knowledge only
in a qualified sense. For we have such knowledge not through the causes of
God’s existence (there are none), but only a posteriori, from God’s effects.
49. See In BDT, q.6, a.3.
50. QDP, q.7, a.5, ad 6.
51. Super Sent I, d.3, q.1, a.4; In BDT, q.1, a.4; QDV, q.10, a.13; ST I q.32
a.1.
52. For theology as a non-paradigmatic scientia, see Jenkins, Knowledge
and Faith.
53. Expositio in Symbolum Apostolorum, proem.
54. Quodl VIII, q.2, a.2: “Intellectus cognoscit ipsam naturam et
substantiam rei.” See also ST I q.17 a.3; ST I q.58 a.5; ST I q.85 a.6; Super
Sent III, d.35, q.2, a.2, qc. 1.
55. QDV, q.1, a.12: “Dicendum quod nomen intellectus sumitur ex hoc
quod intima rei cognoscit; est enim intelligere quasi intus legere: sensus enim
et imaginatio sola accidentia exteriora cognoscunt; solus autem intellectus ad
interiora et essentiam rei pertingit.” For the following see also Philip
Reynolds, “Properties, Causality, and Epistemic Optimism in Thomas
Aquinas,” Recherches de théologie et philosophie médiévales 68 (2010):
270–309.
56. See Aurélien Robert, Penser la substance: étude d’une question
médiévale (XIIIe–XIVe siècles) (Paris: Vrin, forthcoming).
57. See the passages in nn. 54 and 55 above.
58. See, for instance, ST I q.85 a.6; In DA, lib.3, lect.11. For more
discussion of this theory see Jenkins, Knowledge and Faith, 101–17, and
Kretzmann, “Infallibility, Error, and Ignorance,” 181–94.
CHAPTER 24
TOBIAS HOFFMANN
Considering the intellectual virtues individually will bring out more clearly
how Aquinas understands the distinctive characteristics of the five
intellectual virtues, and in particular of prudence, which is the intellectual
virtue that is most easily misconstrued.
Wisdom
Aquinas’s understanding of wisdom is rooted mainly in Aristotle’s
Metaphysics, where Aristotle provides a more elaborate account of wisdom
than in his Nicomachean Ethics. For Aristotle, wisdom concerns knowledge
of the highest causes and the ability to judge and order subordinate things by
these standards.8 Aquinas understands this idea both in a comparative and in
an absolute sense. Comparatively, those are called wiser who are more
knowledgeable about things of a higher order, by which knowledge they can
evaluate things of a lower order; thus, the architect is wiser than the
bricklayer. In the absolute sense, those are wise who have knowledge of the
highest cause of the entire universe, which is God. Wisdom as an intellectual
virtue concerns God as he is knowable by natural human reason, that is, as he
is investigated in the science of metaphysics. In the supernatural order,
wisdom can be either identified with “sacred doctrine” (that is, with theology
as the science of God that is based upon divine revelation) or with wisdom as
a gift of the Holy Spirit (that is, a connatural familiarity with divine matters,
by which one is able to evaluate and order things according to a divine
standard).9
Because of the eminence of the object of wisdom, that is, God, Aquinas
considers wisdom the highest intellectual virtue. Wisdom provides one with
the criteria by which to judge and order all the other intellectual virtues.
Wisdom moreover has an ethical dimension in that it contemplates God, the
object of “felicity” (felicitas, Aquinas’s word for philosophical happiness, as
opposed to beatitudo, which is supernatural happiness). Thus, Aquinas says
that wisdom is even more closely related to happiness than prudence. This
reflects his view that the “contemplative life” (that is, living a concern for
knowledge of the truth) is superior to the “active life” (that is, the practice of
the moral virtues).10
Science
Aristotle’s and Aquinas’s understanding of science is quite different from
today’s use of the term. As an intellectual virtue, science is a “demonstrative
habit,”11 namely, a habit whereby one possesses knowledge acquired by
means of demonstration. Aquinas’s most developed account of science is
found in his commentary on the Posterior Analytics, where he follows
Aristotle closely. Since he uses this same account in his theological works as
the basis for his discussion of theology as a science, we should assume that
his comments on Aristotle’s text here reflect his own view and not only his
understanding of Aristotle. According to this account, the domain of a
specific science is defined by its “subject,” which is confined to a single
genus. For example, the subject of arithmetic is number, and the subject of
geometry is spatial magnitude. Certain derivative facts about the subject of a
science are demonstrated; for example, it is demonstrated in geometry that
the interior angles of any triangle are equal to two right angles. According to
the Posterior Analytics, there are a number of conditions for demonstrative
scientific knowledge, which Aristotle for the most part does not address in
his brief account in the Nicomachean Ethics.12 There he emphasizes merely
that science concerns necessary things, that is, things which cannot be
otherwise than they are. Thus, science is distinguished by its object from
prudence and art, which concern contingent matters that are done through
human agency.
Understanding
Whereas science is knowledge obtained through demonstration,
understanding is knowledge that is obtained nondiscursively of a proposition
which is “known through itself” (per se notum), that is, knowable thanks to
the terms of the proposition.13 It may seem that knowledge of what is known
through itself is no accomplishment, and thus one may wonder why it has the
character of an intellectual virtue. Yet such propositions are not necessarily
known instantly and without effort. According to Aquinas, not all that is per
se notum is clear to everyone. Aquinas distinguishes between that which is
“per se notum to all,” because everybody easily grasps the terms of the
proposition (such as “whole” and “part” in “the whole is larger than its
part”), and what is “per se notum only to the knowledgeable,” that is, to those
who understand a proposition consisting of less obvious terms (as in the
statement that an angel does not occupy a specific space). The common
English translation of “per se notum” as “self-evident” does not take this
important nuance into account.14
Art
The intellectual virtue of art refers to what the medievals called the
mechanical arts. It is distinct from the so-called liberal arts (Grammar,
Rhetoric, Logic, Arithmetic, Geometry, Music, and Astronomy). For
Aquinas, the liberal arts are speculative habits like the theoretical sciences;
they merely have a resemblance to the mechanical arts in that they involve
such activities as counting and measuring.15 Art as an intellectual virtue is
what we would call the knowledge or the professional competence of a
craftsman. Thus, a cabinetmaker uses his or her art to produce a good piece
of furniture. Using Aristotle’s formula, Aquinas defines art as right reason
about things to be made.16 Thus, at first sight, art is very similar to prudence,
which Aquinas and (less explicitly) Aristotle define as right reason about
things to be done.17 What art and prudence have in common is that they are
habits of practical reason, whereas wisdom, science, and understanding are
habits of speculative reason. Yet from the ethical perspective, art and
prudence differ significantly, even as production and action differ in a crucial
respect. As Aquinas explains with reference to Aristotle’s Metaphysics,
production is an activity that passes into a thing outside of the individual,
such as to build or to saw. Action, in contrast, is an activity that remains
within the individual, such as to see, to think, and to wish.18 In other words,
products are distinct from their producers, while actions are inseparable from
their agents. This implies that the work of art is judged solely according to
the quality of the product and not according to the good will of the craftsman.
The work of prudence, by contrast, is not merely assessed according to the
results of action, but above all, whether it is done for the right reason and
with the appropriate disposition of the will.19 Art thus exemplifies what is
characteristic of all the intellectual virtues apart from prudence: they provide
the ability to carry on intellectual activities, but they do not affect the will of
the individual. In order for craftsmen to make good use of their competence,
they need the moral virtue of justice that inclines them to work in the fitting
manner.20
Aristotle’s and Aquinas’s emphasis on the difference between action and
production, or between art and prudence, indicates how far removed their
ethics is from utilitarianism, for which this distinction is morally irrelevant.
In utilitarianism, what counts are the results of an activity, not the mindset
with which it was done.
Prudence
To lead a good life and thus to attain the properly human good means to act
in an excellent and thoughtful manner in the various domains and the
particular circumstances of life: in other words, it means to act virtuously.
None of the previously discussed intellectual virtues can sufficiently provide
the knowledge that would effectively allow us to live virtuously. For one
thing, the knowledge obtained through understanding of the first practical
principles and through moral science is too abstract to guide us in particular
situations. Moreover, such general knowledge is often too weak to withstand
the interference by desires or fears that make it ineffective. Socrates’ claim
that it is sufficient to know what is best in order to act accordingly is
contradicted by the facts: weakness of will, that is, acting contrary to one’s
better judgment, is a common human phenomenon. Not just any knowledge,
but only prudence guarantees that we judge correctly what specific situations
require and that we act accordingly.
For a better understanding of Aquinas’s notion of prudence, we must first
see what it is not. In English and in the Romance languages, prudence
connotes above all the ability to avoid dangers; in German, Klugheit evokes
astuteness, which is why Kant qualifies shrewd selfish behavior as prudent
and dissociates prudence from virtue.21 In contrast, for Aquinas, who follows
Aristotle on this point, a prudent person experiences perfect harmony
between correct practical knowledge, upright desire, and action. Furthermore,
for Aquinas as for Aristotle, prudence does not concern limited purposes, but
rather what is relevant for the good life as a whole.22 For this reason,
Aquinas in one place calls it “wisdom in human affairs.”23 Yet prudence is
not only practical wisdom, for it is not mainly about practical considerations.
Rather, the main task of prudence is to apply general practical knowledge to
a specific deed.24 The passage from correct general practical considerations
to a concrete action that embodies these considerations, which is the work of
prudence, is anything but trivial. It requires experience, acumen, foresight,
circumspection, caution, and other characteristics that enhance the cognitive
capacity of prudence.25 Moreover, it requires the support of well-ordered
desire. In prudence, cognitive and appetitive qualities are unified in such a
way that the practical knowledge of what is best is fully internalized. No one
can replace us in our decision-making. Even when we consult the advice of
other prudent persons, or when we act in accordance with a good law, we
must appropriate the criteria that prudent people or good legislators are
offering us.26
In order to appreciate the nature of prudence and its preconditions, we
must briefly look at Aquinas’s account of the stages of human action. When a
sick person is serious about wanting to become healthy, he intends to take
specific measures. Unless these measures are immediately apparent, he
deliberates about them, such as whether he needs to see a doctor and which
doctor would be best. Having concluded that the first step toward health is to
visit a particular doctor, he actually goes to see her. Thus, the basic steps in
the process of his action are intention of an end to be attained by some
means, deliberation about which means are suitable and which are not,
decision to employ the most suitable means, and execution of the required
action(s). In Aquinas’s account, each of these stages has a cognitive and a
volitional dimension, which interpenetrate each other and which are
inseparable.27
The practice of the moral virtues involves analogous considerations about
means and end. A soldier who intends to act bravely has to deliberate
whether a given situation requires him to move toward the enemy or away
from him. What in one situation might be considered as brave could on a
different occasion turn out to be reckless or cowardly. No routine and no
general policy can replace the brave soldier’s reflection about which steps are
concretely involved in acting bravely and in avoiding cowardice and
recklessness. It is the task of prudence to establish the mean of virtue in the
ever-changing circumstances of human life, by employing the appropriate
means to a virtuous end.28
Prudence guides the stages of human action from the good intention to the
actual performance of the deed in concert with three subordinate intellectual
virtues. The ability to make good practical deliberations is due to euboulia,
while the aptitude to make the correct practical judgment is owing to synesis
(in ordinary matters) and gnome (in matters where ordinary guidelines must
be overruled). Even more crucial than these steps, which as such could even
remain theoretical considerations about action, is the application of the
decision to a concrete action. Thus, the proper act of prudence, according to
Aquinas, is to “command” (praecipere, imperare) oneself to put the decision
into practice.29
Failure is possible at each of the stages of human action. For example, one
can fail with regard to the end by seeking an evil end (cunning) or by seeking
a good end in a selfish manner without concern for the common good.30 Or
one may fail with respect to deliberation, or the practical judgment that
informs the decision or execution; each of these deficiencies constitutes a
special kind of imprudence.31 The moral virtues are crucial to avoid these
shortcomings. Above all, the pursuit of good ends is the work of moral
virtues, for they make it “connatural” to judge correctly about which specific
ends are truly worth pursuing; thus for a just person, the idea of stealing or
cheating has no appeal. The moral virtues furthermore temper the passions
(such as excessive fear or intemperate desire) that might interfere with
practical deliberation, the attainment of the practical judgment, or the
“command” by which the decision is carried out.32
For Aquinas (as for Aristotle), the interconnection between prudence and
the moral virtues implies that all genuine virtues are connected in such a way
that one can only possess all moral virtues together with prudence, or none.
This claim is not as implausible as it might appear at first sight. If one
possesses a “virtue” independently of other virtues, it is only an
approximation of virtue, not a true virtue. Moreover, prudence is a single
intellectual habit that is required for each genuine moral virtue. For Aquinas,
it is not the case that each moral virtue is perfected by its own prudence.
Nothing could better illustrate the peculiaritiy of Aquinas’s notion of
prudence: as an indivisible principle of moral virtue, prudence informs all
human action in view of the comprehensive human good. Any specific vice
corrupts right reason in general, thereby destroying prudence not only with
regard to the virtue in question, but also all the others. Thus, intemperance
would sooner or later lead to injustice, as is clear in the case of adultery. In
contrast, the other intellectual virtues can be instantiated separately, for they
do not originate in a single principle. Thus, a good geometrician might be
bad at metaphysics, or a good cabinetmaker might be a bad car mechanic.33
Later authors, such as Duns Scotus and William of Ockham, rejected
Aquinas’s view, arguing that each moral virtue has its own distinct
prudence.34 Thus, prudence lost its eminent character as the intellectual
virtue that concerns life as a whole. It became a habit that is instrumental to
limited goals.
Aquinas admits, however, that prudence has some important limitations
with respect to the moral life. For instance, while prudence allows one to find
the means by which the moral virtues are implemented, it does not discover
the ends to which these are ordered. Aquinas attributes this task to
understanding, by which we grasp the first principles not only of speculative
reason, but also of practical reason, such as “no evil is to be done” or “no one
is to be harmed.” Aquinas treats understanding of the first practical principles
as synonymous with synderesis, the habit of the first principles of practical
reason, which belong to the natural law. Like judgments of conscience, so
also prudential decisions presuppose insight into the principles of natural
law. In a manner that is foreign to Aristotle, Aquinas thus links prudence to
the natural law.35
A further limitation of prudence, for Aquinas, lies in the fact that the
ultimate end of human life consists in friendship with God. Charity, a
supernatural habit infused by God, makes it possible to attain this
supernatural end. Together with charity, other virtues are divinely infused,
including infused prudence, which essentially differs from naturally acquired
prudence. Infused prudence informs the infused moral virtues that in turn
order the various aspects of life to God.36 Yet even infused prudence is
insufficient to guide decision-making in view of the ultimate end, for infused
prudence or infused euboulia is limited to deliberations about things one can
understand. In order to make the right decisions regarding things that are
beyond human understanding, one needs the gift of counsel.37
NOTES
I wish to thank the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation for supporting me
during my work on this article.
HOW does Aquinas conceive of the relation between reason and faith? In
order to answer this question I will first briefly summarize Aquinas’s account
of faith. Then I will identify and assess the different ways in which Aquinas
believes that faith and reason are related.
In Aquinas’s view the object of faith is God as the first truth2 and the last end
of human longing.3 Thus, the object of faith is related to both, intellect (truth)
and rational appetite (last end). How intellect and rational appetite (will) are
related can be made understandable in the following way. In order to pursue
an end one needs some cognition4 of the end. One needs to grasp what the
end consists in, that it is available and how one can attain it.5 Human beings
naturally long for happiness as their last end. But they do not naturally know
what happiness consists in and whether it is available. True cognition of this
is offered by God’s revealing himself to human beings as the fulfillment of
their life.
Aquinas sharpens this characterization of the proper object of faith in two
ways: first, by taking into account the special conditions of the human
cognizer in this life. Human beings cognize things, even simple things like
God, in a propositional way.6 Via the propositions believed, they get into
contact with the things.7 Second, Aquinas sharpens the account of the object
of faith from an epistemological point of view. What can be demonstrated
about God does not—strictly speaking—belong to the object of faith. Only
those truths belong to the object of faith that are believed on God’s
authority.8 Aquinas calls such truths “credibles.” Putting the things said
together, I suggest the following definition of a credible proposition:
A proposition p is a credible proposition (short: pc) if and only if
(i) p is true;
(ii) p is revealed by God;
(iii) p is assented to because p is revealed by God;
(iv) p presents truths about God and created things insofar as they are
necessary and sufficient for orienting the life of human beings toward
their last end.
The Interior and the Exterior Act of Assenting to the Object of Faith
The interior act of faith is a human person’s act of assenting to pc. Aquinas
explores the kind of the act involved by doing two things: first, he tries to
situate the kind of assent involved in the act of faith by comparing it to other
acts of assent to propositions.9 Regarding the firmness of assent, the act of
faith is similar to insight and science. Regarding the way the assent is
brought about, the act of faith is rather similar to opinion and conjecture.
Their objects do not by themselves sufficiently move the intellect to assent to
them. One does not see that they are true. An act of will is required. In
Aquinas’s words: “The act of believing [credere] itself is an act of the
intellect assenting to the divine truth at the command of the will that is
moved by God through grace.”10 Thus, the act of faith is a cognition action.11
Second, Aquinas distinguishes three aspects of the one interior act of faith
with the aid of the traditional formula to believe that God (credere Deum), to
believe God (credere Deo), to believe in God (credere in Deum).12
(i) The first part of the formula focuses on what is believed, on the
content of faith; in short: S assents that pc.
(ii) The second part focuses on the reason for assenting. A person assents
that pc on God’s say-so: because God reveals—directly or mediated
through other persons—that pc. This part of the formula captures the
trust aspect of the act of faith. Putting (i) and (ii) together, one could
say: S believes God that pc.13
(iii) The third part of the formula focuses on the relation of the object of
faith to the will, the rational appetite of the believer. The propositions
of faith represent the good believers are lovingly longing for as the
fulfillment of their life. This part of the formula captures the
existential aspect of the act of faith. What one believes matters heavily
for the orientation of one’s life as a whole.
With “faith” can be meant the exterior act of faith, that is: the speech act
of confessing to believe the Christian content.
What Human Beings Cognize by the Virtue of Faith is Above but not
Against Reason
In the context of epistemology Aquinas usually means with “reason”—ratio
—in its wide sense capacities and acts of natural human cognition. Natural
human cognition starts by sense perception and, through processes of
abstraction, ends up by grasping the essences of things. In a narrower sense,
“reason” means cognitive acts of drawing conclusions from premises or
finding premises for conclusions.
Aquinas claims that human beings are not able to cognize pc by such acts
of reason. Nevertheless, he insists that what human beings cognize by natural
reason and what they cognize by faith is consistent with each other. He says:
“Although the truth of Christian faith exceeds the capacity of human reason,
nevertheless what reason is naturally endowed with cannot be contrary to that
truth.”19 This optimistic claim follows from the conviction that God is the
origin of both human nature and revelation.
And in this way sacred doctrine is a science because it proceeds from principles known
by the light of a higher science, namely, the science of God and the blessed. Hence, just
as music believes the principles taught it by the arithmetician, so sacred doctrine
believes the principles revealed to it by God.22
This is a congenial solution. For now Aquinas has both: theology is a science
in the Aristotelian sense, and nevertheless, the principles of this science are
the articles that Christians accept in faith. These principles cannot be
demonstrated by human beings. But they can be defended. Thus, Aquinas
claims, that one should be able to show that these principles of faith are not
impossible, that they do not contradict what is self-evident or demonstrable,
that defeaters can be defeated, that one can draw conclusions from the
principles in a deductive way.23
These are rationality requirements that Aquinas thinks theologians should
be able to fulfill. But surely he did not think that normal Christians have to
do all this theological work in order to be rational believers. Thus, the
question arises as to the rationality of faith itself.
The reason why the will is inclined to assent to what it does not see is because God says
it, just as a human being concerning things he does not see believes the testimony of a
good man who sees what he himself does not see.24
That God exists and other like things, that can be known about God by natural reason, as
it is said, are not articles of faith, but preambles to the articles. For faith presupposes
natural cognition, just as grace nature, and perfection something that can be perfected.30
In another passage Aquinas gives the impression that the act of faith
includes having credibility arguments. To the objection that accuses believers
of being gullible he responds:
The believer has sufficient evidence for believing, for he is induced by the authority of
the divine doctrine confirmed by miracles, and, what is more, by the inward instinct of
the inviting God: hence he does not believe lightly. He has not, however, sufficient
evidence for scientific knowledge, hence the ground for the merit is not lost.31
To be sure, Aquinas does not think that the evidence by miracles is sufficient
for assenting, “for of those who see the same miracle, or who hear the same
sermon, some believe, and some do not.”32 Nevertheless, miracles
confirming the authority of divine doctrine seem to play an evidential role.
On the other hand, there are also passages indicating that Aquinas holds
that arguments for the existence of God and credibility are not necessary for
rational assent to the propositions of faith. First, he insists that it is possible
and safer to believe on faith even the propositions about God that can
naturally be known.33 Second, he comments on the passage of the gospel
according to John 4, where the woman comes to believe in Jesus as the
Messiah. The woman tells the people of her village about Jesus. At the end
the people of the village come to believe in Jesus and they say to the
woman:34 “We no longer believe because of your word; for we have heard
for ourselves, and we know that this is truly the saviour of the world.”
Aquinas comments:
Faith is proper if one obeys the truth not because of something else but because of the
truth itself. And thus [the evangelist] says that they say to the women, that “we now
believe” the truth [veritati] “not because of your speech” but because of the truth itself.
For three things lead us to the faith of Christ: first, natural reason […]; second the
testimonies of the Law and the Prophets […]; third, the sermon of the Apostles and
others. But when somebody, who is guided by this, believes, then one can say that he
does believe because of none of them: not because of natural reason, not because of the
testimonies of the Law, not because of the sermon of others, but alone because of the
truth itself; Gen 15.6: Abraham believed God, and this was credited to him as
righteousness.35
The first question that arises is whether this passage can be reconciled with
the others. I think the passages can be reconciled by interpreting the
presuppositions as preparatory for faith. But they would not themselves be
part of faith. They would be neither necessary nor sufficient for the
rationality of the assent to the propositions of faith. Some believers could
quote such arguments when asked. But they would not believe because of
these arguments.
The second question is whether faith that is independent of such
arguments or reasons can be rational. For Aquinas, faith is a habit of belief
formation, which is together with hope and charity infused by God, designed
to get the truth in order to find orientation in one’s life toward the last end
one is longing for: beatitude. Faith is a cognitive habit sui generis that cannot
be reduced to other habits of belief formation like intellect, science, or
wisdom. This view of faith can be and has been interpreted as a version of
epistemological externalism.36 One’s assent to the propositions of faith is
epistemically justified by being the outcome of the cognitive habit called
faith. Moreover, there are passages that suggest that such beliefs are basic:
first, Aquinas compares them with principles. Principles are basic, not
inferred, not believed on the evidential basis of other beliefs. Second, when
Aquinas deals with the gifts of the Holy Spirit that belong to faith, namely
insight and science, he stresses the nondiscursive character of both these
gifts.37
However, I said above that believing God that pc presupposes some other
beliefs that cannot themselves be part of pc, for example, God exists, what
God communicates is pc. These propositions can be inferentially justified.
But if Aquinas thinks that even such propositions can be believed on faith, he
must have in mind a different, wider, meaning of “faith,” perhaps in the sense
of taking something to be true without arguments. One suggestion to
understand this would be the following: if my mother tells me something I
do, of course, not believe her that she exists and that she is communicating
something to me. But I do not believe these propositions on evidential
grounds either. I just believe them in the basic way. Similarly, if somebody
experiences that God speaks to him, he does not believe God that God exists
and that God is communicating something to him. But he need not believe
these propositions on evidential grounds either. They could be believed in the
basic way.
It is rational to believe in the existence of the complete good that attracts
the will
The second aspect of reason can be found in the role the will plays in
assenting to the propositions of faith. Aquinas writes:
CONCLUSION
Thomas Aquinas thinks that faith is a virtue. Anthony Kenny, however,
writes
that faith is not, as theologians have claimed, a virtue, but a vice, unless a number of
conditions can be fulfilled. One of them is that the existence of God can be rationally
justified outside faith. Secondly, whatever are the historical events which are pointed to
as constituting the divine revelation must be independently established as historically
certain with the degree of commitment which one can have in the pieces of historical
knowledge of the kind I have mentioned.42
Aquinas does not deny that both kinds of arguments can be produced. He
seems however to deny that a Christian must have such arguments in order to
believe rationally and meritoriously. The virtue of faith alone is necessary
and sufficient. Is he right? If faith is a God-given habit, designed to get the
truth in matters of God, our last end and the way to achieve it, then the belief
resulting from such a habit is justified indeed. If a person’s will is heightened
by the grace of God and, through being attracted by the supreme good
presented in the propositions of faith, influences the intellect to assent, then
such assent is justified indeed. The question is: Does the Christian need some
justification for the belief that the antecedents are true? In a world without
doubts regarding the reliability of faith and without irritations regarding the
truth of its output, I think, the answer is: probably not. But we do not live in
such a world. In our world where people have very different religious beliefs,
I think, some arguments are required: not only in order to defeat the defeaters
of one’s belief but also in order to sustain belief in the antecedent. Thus, I
think that pure epistemological externalism concerning the justification of
religious beliefs is not satisfying. This, however, does not mean that every
Christian must be intellectually trained. I would like to bring in the old idea
of the division of epistemic labor. In other areas, for example, in physics,
biology, astronomy, lay people are justified in holding particular beliefs
without being in a position to understand the details and to know what speaks
in favor of them. They are justified by relying on the experts who are in a
position to know the details and the evidence. Similarly, simple religious
believers are justified in holding their religious belief without being in a
position to understand the details and to have arguments and defeaters
against defeaters. They are justified by relying on the experts who do have
some arguments. Thus, Aquinas might be right when he claims at the
beginning of the Summa Theologiae that sacred doctrine in the sense of
theology is necessary—even if he intends his argument there to answer a
quite different problem.43
NOTES
1. Aquinas mentions this distinction in ST I–II q.55 a.1 ad 1. Moreover, he
construes his treatise on the virtue of faith according to this distinction.
2. ST II-II q.1 a.1.
3. ST II-II q.1 a.8: “Those things belong per se to faith the vision of which
we shall enjoy in eternal life and by which we are lead to eternal life”; ST II-
II q.2 a.2: “For the first truth refers to will insofar as it has the aspect of an
end”; ST II-II q.2 a.5: “One must therefore say that the object of faith per se
is that by which a human being is made happy.”
4. “Cognition” is the translation of the Latin word cognitio, which is the
broadest concept under which all cognitive acts (understanding, knowledge,
opinion, conjecture, etc.) can be subsumed. In this sense I will also use the
rather unfamiliar words “cognizer” and “to cognize.”
5. ST I q.1 a.1: “But the end must first be cognized by human beings who
are to direct their intentions and actions to the end.” See also ST I-II q.6 a.2.
6. ST II-II q.1 a.2: Aquinas here says that on the part of the believer the
object of faith is “aliquid complexum per modum enuntiabilis,” something
complex by way of a proposition. Note that “enuntiatio” is the translation of
the Greek “apophansis,” Aristotle’s central term in Peri hermeneias. What is
meant by this term is that kind of speech that has the property of being either
true or false.
7. In ST II-II q.1 a.2 ad 2, Aquinas deals with the problem that in the creed
we say “I believe in God almighty” and not “I believe that God is almighty.”
Thus, the objection runs, the object of faith is the thing itself—God—not a
proposition. Aquinas solves the objection by saying that the act of the
believer does not terminate in a proposition but in the thing. By forming
propositions, we cognize the things.
8. ST II-II q.1 a.1: “For the faith of which we are speaking does not assent
to anything, except because it is revealed by God. Hence faith proceeds from
the divine truth itself like a middle term.”
9. ST II-II q.1 a.4; ST II-II q.2 a.1; ST II-II q.4 a.1; QDV, q.14, a.1; In Heb,
c.12, l.1.
10. ST II-II q.2 a.9. See also ST II-II q.1 a.4 and ST II-II q.2 a.1 ad 3. This
translation, as well as all the other translations from Aquinas in this article, is
my own.
11. Thus, Aquinas is committed to a version of cognitive voluntarism.
Whether cognitive voluntarism is tenable is a much disputed issue that I
cannot deal with here properly. In my view Aquinas does not hold an
extreme cognitive voluntarism but a modest form of it. In Aquinas’s view,
first, one has voluntary control over belief formation only vis à vis some
classes of cognitive objects. Second, having voluntary control over belief
formation does not require that one has no evidence whatsoever for the truth
of the target proposition. Who forms an opinion or a suspicion is not without
evidence. Third, habits that we acquire voluntarily over a long period of time
play a role. They influence the way we choose and ponder arguments pro and
con; they influence how compelling arguments appear to us. For a detailed
discussion, see Claudia Eisen Murphy, “Aquinas on Voluntary Belief,”
American Philosophical Quarterly 74:4 (2000): 569–97; Bruno
Niederbacher, Glaube als Tugend bei Thomas von Aquin:
Erkenntistheoretische und religionsphilosophische Interpretationen
(Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 2003), 60–66; Eleonore Stump, Aquinas (London
and New York: Routledge, 2003), 342–49.
12. ST II-II q.2 a.2.
13. Aquinas is aware that revelation comes to most people via mediators
such as parents, preachers of faith, etc. Nevertheless, he thinks that the true
believer believes human beings insofar as God is speaking through them. See
Super Sent III, d.23, q.2, a.2, qc.2, ad 3: “The believer believes a human
being not insofar he is a human being but insofar as God speaks in him.”
14. ST II-II q.4 a.1.
15. ST I-II q.62 a.1.
16. ST II-II q.4 a.3.
17. Cf. QDV, q.14, a.2, ad 10; QDV, q.14, a.7; ST I-II q.65 a.4.
18. Super Sent III, d.23, q.2, a.2, qc.2, ad 4.
19. SCG 1, 7.
20. Super Sent I, Prologus, q.1, a.3, qc.2, ad 2.
21. In ST II-II q.1 a.4 ad 2 and ad 3, Aquinas mentions ways in which the
believer can be said to “see.” But these ways are not meant in the strict sense
of insight into the truth of the propositions of faith but rather in the sense of
seeing that the propositions of faith ought to be believed.
22. ST I q.1 a.2. The subalternation-idea is also to be found in some
editions of Super Sent I, Prologus, q.1, a.3, qc.2. For text-critical details, see
Johannes Beumer, “Ein nichtauthentischer Text im Prolog zum
Sentenzenkommentar des hl. Thomas von Aquin (q.1.a.3.sol.2),” Scholastik
33 (1958): 247–52; Marie-Dominique Chenu, La Théologie comme science
au XIIIe siècle, 3d ed. (Paris: Vrin, 1957); Bruno Niederbacher,
“Erläuterungen des Prologs zum Sentenzenkommentar des Thomas von
Aquin,” in Bruno Niederbacher and Gerhard Leibold, eds., Theologie als
Wissenschaft im Mittelalter: Texte, Übersetzungen, Kommentare (Münster:
Aschendorff, 2006), 277.
23. I collect these rationality-requirements from: Super Sent I, Prologus,
q.1, a.3, qc.2, ad 2; ST I q.1 a.8.
24. Super Sent III, d.23, q.2, a.2, qc.2. Cf. ST II-II q.2 a.2.
25. QDV, q.14, a.2, ad 9.
26. See ST I q.1 a.8 ad 2. For a precise analysis, see Niederbacher, Glaube
als Tugend bei Thomas von Aquin, 67–81.
27. ST II-II q.2 a.4; ST II-II q.4 a.8 ad 2.
28. See SCG 3, 38.
29. SCG 1, 6.
30. ST I q.2 a.2 ad 1.
31. ST II-II q.2 a.9 ad 3; see also ST II-II q.2 a.1 ad 1; ST II-II q.1 a.4 ad 2.
32. ST II-II q.6 a.1.
33. ST II-II q.2 a.4; ST I q.2 a.2 ad 1.
34. In Aquinas’s view, and according to the tradition, the woman
symbolizes human reason. See ST II-II q.2 a.10. Cf. William of Auxerre,
Summa aurea, liber 1, prologus.
35. In John, c.4, l.5. Cf. ST II-II q.27 a.3 ad 2.
36. John I. Jenkins, Knowledge and Faith in Thomas Aquinas (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1997) has developed an interpretation along
externalist lines, as well as Alvin Plantinga, “Warranted Christian Belief: The
Aquinas/Calvin Model,” in Godehard Brüntrup and Ronald C. Tacelli, eds.,
The Rationality of Theism (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1999),
125–43; and Alvin Plantinga, Warranted Christian Belief (New York:
Oxford University Press, 2000). See also James R. Brent, “The Epistemic
Status of Christian Beliefs in Thomas Aquinas” (Ph.D. diss., Saint Louis
University, 2008).
37. See ST II-II q.8 a.1; ST II-II q.8 a.5 ad 3; ST II-II q.9 a.1 ad 1. These
gifts of the Holy Spirit are not to be confused with the intellectual virtues of
the same name.
38. QDV, q.14, a.1.
39. See ST I-II q.62 a.3.
40. Cf. ST II-II q.45 a.2. For details of this interpretation, see Niederbacher,
Glaube als Tugend bei Thomas von Aquin, 137–41, and Brent, “The
Epistemic Status of Christian Beliefs in Thomas Aquinas,” ch. 5.
41. This line of argument is developed in detail by Eleonore Stump, “Faith
and Goodness,” in Godfrey Vesey, ed., The Philosophy in Christianity
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 167–91.
42. Anthony Kenny, What is Faith? Essays in the Philosophy of Religion
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992), 57.
43. ST I q.1 a.1.
CHAPTER 26
ROBERT PASNAU
BIOLOGICAL OR THEOLOGICAL
A theory of human nature must consider from the start whether it sees human
beings in fundamentally biological terms, as animals like other animals, or
else in fundamentally supernatural terms, as creatures of God who are like
God in some special way, and so importantly unlike other animals. Many of
the perennial philosophical disputes have proved so intractable in part
because their adherents divide along these lines. The friends of materialism,
seeing human beings as just a particularly complex example of the sort of
complex organic structure found everywhere on Earth, suppose that we are
ultimately constituted out of just the same material from which squirrels and
rabbits are made. The friends of dualism, instead, think that such a story can
hardly do justice to what is special about human nature. Likewise, the friends
of a libertarian, robustly nondeterministic conception of free will see
something special in human spontaneity and moral responsibility. To their
opponents, human beings operate on the same principles, albeit more
complex, as do squid and plankton.
These and other such disputes need not divide along religious lines. One
may oppose naturalism without embracing a supernatural theistic
perspective; one might, for instance, think it simply a matter of fact that
human beings are fundamentally unlike other biological organisms, but yet
not suppose we are made that way by any higher power. Conversely, the
theist may think it part of the divine plan to have made human beings as
nothing more than the most complex of biological organisms, constituted out
of the same stuff and constrained by the same laws. So although the choice I
have described between two perspectives—biological and naturalistic versus
theological and supernatural—captures an important fault line that runs
through the debate over human nature, it by no means determines all of one’s
subsequent philosophical choices.
The philosophy of Thomas Aquinas exemplifies the sorts of tensions that
arise from these two perspectives. For while the overall orientation of
Aquinas’s work is, of course, profoundly theistic, he nevertheless harbors a
certain sympathy for a naturalistic, biological understanding of human
nature. In some cases, as in his account of the human intellect, the
supernaturalist slant clearly wins out. In other cases, as in his conception of
human beings as a soul–body union, it is equally clear that biological
considerations are paramount. In still other cases, as for instance his views on
free will, it is very difficult to say which line of thought holds sway, and the
preference of interpreters for one reading or another seems largely governed
by their own predilections.
The traditional way of making this point about Aquinas is to describe him
as mediating between the theological teachings of the Church and the
philosophical writings of Aristotle. Historically, this is an apt place to begin
thinking about Aquinas’s philosophy, because there is no doubt that the
central philosophical challenge Aquinas faced over the course of his career
was to find a place for the newly recovered work of Aristotle within the
overriding framework of Christian belief.1 To find a place for Aristotle,
however, means finding a place for a conception of human nature that is
decidedly biological in its overall orientation. This is clear from the
fundamental Aristotelian text on human nature, the De anima, which as it
happens was the subject of the first and most careful of Aquinas’s many
Aristotelian commentaries. For us, the notion of a soul (anima) has become
firmly associated with a supernatural perspective on human nature. But for
Aristotle the term “soul” has not the slightest of nonnaturalistic implications.
On the contrary, a soul is something that all living things possess, from
human beings down to the simplest of life forms, and indeed the De anima is
not so much a study of human nature as it is the foundational treatise in
Aristotle’s long sequence of biological works.
The project of reconciling Aristotle and Christianity, however, important
as it is to understanding Aquinas’s historical situation, does not fit the
natural–supernatural distinction as neatly as one might expect. For even if the
Aristotelian notion of soul is fundamentally biological, the De anima
nevertheless seems to treat the capacity for thought—the intellect—as quite a
special feature of human nature and, indeed, as “immortal and eternal.”2 As
we will see, these few brief, notoriously obscure remarks supply a
bridgehead from Aristotle’s naturalistic biology to Christian soteriology.
There is movement in the other direction as well. For even while there are
tendencies in Christian thought toward treating the body in Platonic fashion,
as a temporary prison of the soul, there is also the doctrine of the
resurrection, according to which the separation of body and soul at death is a
temporary state of affairs, to be remedied by the body’s ultimate restoration,
for all of eternity, at the time of the Final Judgment. As we will see, Aquinas
understands the resurrection as pointing toward the fundamentally biological
character of human nature, in the sense that human beings are, essentially,
not just souls but incarnate souls. Although it is certainly the case that
Aquinas regards the most important human attributes—our intellectual and
volitional powers—as arising from the side of the soul rather than body, he is
nevertheless adamant that a full understanding of human nature requires
understanding our bodily nature as well. God did create purely spiritual
beings, the angels, who are nothing more than disembodied minds, but that is
not what we are. We are, essentially, mind–body composites. So to
understand human nature, one must study not just our mental capacities,
intellect and will, but also the human body. Hence, the task is partly
biological, but not wholly so.
IOP: “The intellectual principle, which we call mind or intellect, has an operation of its
own, in which the body has no share.”11
Before turning to the arguments for IOP, we should be clear about what it
entails. By itself, clearly, IOP does not show that the “intellectual principle”
(the soul that is ultimately responsible for intellectual cognition) is immortal.
Moreover, IOP does not even show that the soul has the possibility of
existing apart from the body. To get those further results, Aquinas argues,
first, that a thing’s manner of operation tracks its manner of existence, so that
whether or not a thing can operate apart from other things shows whether or
not it can exist apart from other things. This shows, as Aquinas thinks of it,
that the human soul is a substance, because to be a substance just is to be the
sort of thing that can exist without inhering in something else.12 Of course,
not all substances are incorruptible, so to get the further result that the human
soul will naturally continue to exist even apart from its body, Aquinas further
argues that whereas form–matter composites are always corruptible,
substances that are pure forms are by nature such that, once created, it is
impossible for them naturally to cease to exist.13
The supplementary principles just mentioned are perhaps just as doubtful
as is IOP itself, but even so it seems right to keep our focus on that
fundamental premise. For if Aquinas can establish that the human soul has an
operation of its own, independent of the body, then he will have dealt a fatal
blow to the sort of reductive materialism that, then as now, looms as the main
adversary to a view like Aquinas’s. For we would then know that “human
soul” is not just a convenient catchphrase for whatever it is that explains
human life, but that it in fact picks out an independent causal principle within
us, irreducible to any material description. Admittedly, that alone does not
show that the soul can exist apart from the body, but it takes the decisive first
step.
It is necessary to say that the principle of intellectual operation, which we call the soul
of a human being, is a nonbodily and subsistent principle. [1] For it is clear that through
the intellect a human being can cognize the natures of all bodies. [2a] But that which can
cognize certain things must have none of those things in its own nature, because that
which exists in it naturally would impede its cognition of other things. In this way we
see that a sick person’s tongue, infected with a jaundiced and bitter humor, cannot
perceive anything sweet; rather, all things seem bitter to that person. Therefore if the
intellectual principle were to contain within itself the nature of any body, it could not
cognize all bodies. But every body has some determinate nature. Therefore [3a] it is
impossible for the intellectual principle to be a body. [3b] It is likewise impossible for it
to operate through a bodily organ, because [2b] the determinate nature even of that
bodily organ would prevent the cognition of all bodies. Analogously, a determinate color
not just in the pupil, but even in a glass vase, makes liquid poured into that vase seem to
be of the same color. [IOP] Therefore this intellectual principle, which is called mind or
intellect, has an operation of its own that the body does not share in.14
What drives this argument is the idea that the intellect displays a startling
plasticity in its cognitive range. Our other cognitive capacities—sight,
hearing, and so on—are each rigidly limited to a certain domain, that of
color, sound, and so forth. But the intellect, according to the first premise of
the argument, can think about anything (or at any rate anything in the
material realm, which is as strong a claim as Aquinas takes himself to need).
The second premise of the argument then asserts that such plasticity would
be impossible if the intellect either (a) were a body or (b) were to operate
through a body. From these two premises, the subconclusions of (3a) and
(3b) immediately follow, and they together yield IOP.
It hardly needs saying that this falls short of being a demonstrative proof.
Although the logical form of the argument is valid, none of the premises are
self-evident in the way they would have to be to carry complete conviction. It
is not perfectly clear, for instance, that the intellect can “cognize the natures
of all bodies.” Even more doubtful is the second premise (2a, 2b). Although
the comparisons to taste and sight point toward the kind of point Aquinas
wishes to make, these are merely illustrative examples, and hardly show that
the intellect, if it relied on the brain, would similarly be limited in the scope
of what it could grasp.
Still, there is undoubtedly something suggestive about the argument. For it
really is a remarkable feature of the mind that it can range so widely—in a
seemingly unlimited fashion—over the whole of the world around us, readily
grasping entirely new concepts of all kinds. Such plasticity is strikingly
different, Aquinas thinks, not just from what one finds in the case of the
senses, which are so obviously tied down to a single sort of object, but also
from what we observe of the higher-level cognitive abilities of other animals,
which Aquinas regards as similarly bound to a certain predetermined range
of objects. Swallows make judgments of a certain sort about nests, and bees
about honeycombs,15 but they have no capacity to expand beyond their
limited horizons. The bee could not form the idea of opening a retail outlet to
market its product. And once one gets squarely in focus this remarkable
feature of the human mind, it can begin to seem at least worth taking
seriously the idea that our soul is not just a larger, more complex version of
what swallows and bees have, but that it is something qualitatively different.
What exactly that difference might be is again not a claim that Aquinas can
establish decisively, but his suggestion is that the soul acts independently of
the material conditions that lock other souls into a narrow framework of
operation.
A second line of argument for IOP rests on the intellect’s capacity to form
universal concepts. Aquinas’s overarching cognitive theory rests on the
empiricist principle that all information arises from the senses.16 At the
sensory level, however, that information is always represented as here and
now—a particular sensible quality in the world at a particular place and time.
The intellect represents information differently, in abstraction from any such
particular conditions, and Aquinas takes such facts to form the basis of an
argument for IOP:
Everything that gets added to something after its complete existence gets added to it
accidentally, since it lies outside its essence. But every substantial form yields a
complete being in the genus of substance, since it yields an actual, particular being.
Therefore whatever gets added to a thing after its first substantial form gets added to it
accidentally. So, since a nutritive soul is a substantial form, inasmuch as living is
predicated substantially both of human beings and of other animals, it would follow that
a [further] sensory soul would get added accidentally, and likewise for a [further]
intellective soul. And thus neither “animal” nor “human being” would signify a thing
that is unconditionally one, nor would these terms signify any genus or species in the
category of substance.31
The advocate of a plurality of substantial forms thus loses any ability to treat
human beings and other animals as substances. The body would be a
substance, in virtue of the first substantial form that inheres in it, but any
further form added after that point could not possibly perform the role of a
substantial form, because that role is already taken. Accordingly, for a living
thing to possess a rational soul would be like a tree’s taking on a new color—
the additional feature would be a mere accidental addition, and rational
animal would no more pick out a distinct category of substance than does
maple-tree-with-orange-leaves. The cost of failing to explain the substantial
unity of a human being, then, is quite dire: human beings fail to be
substances at all, which is to say that they fail to count as entities in any
proper sense.
The key to the argument is Aquinas’s robust conception of substantial
forms as causal principles. In effect, Aquinas is advancing a physical, proto-
scientific hypothesis about what distinguishes substances from
nonsubstances. This is exactly what one should expect from Aquinas’s
commitment to a biological approach to human nature. Human beings are
material substances like other substances, which is to say that we have a
unifying intrinsic principle like other substances, explained not by a priori
metaphysical considerations, but by the substantial form’s concrete causal
role within substances. If we were to decide that human beings, and perhaps
living things in general, lack any such organizing principle, then we would
have to conclude that human beings, viewed as mind–body composites, are
not substances at all. Either that, or we would have to formulate an entirely
new theory of substance.
Inasmuch as the human soul has an operation transcending matter, its existence is
elevated above the body and does not depend on it. But inasmuch as it is naturally suited
to acquire its immaterial cognition from a material cognition, it is clear that the
fulfillment of its species can occur only when united to a body.35
The senses, relying on the familiar bodily organs of the eyes, ears, and so on,
acquire information about the world, and the mind works on that information,
abstracting it to form the sorts of universal concepts described earlier.
Aquinas does not think that the intellect must have such sensory information
in order to operate, but this, as he puts it here, is how the intellect is
“naturally suited” (nata) to operate.
More interesting than this familiar empiricism is Aquinas’s insistence on
the intellect’s need to “turn toward phantasms” every time we think. The
term “phantasm” is Aquinas’s general label for sensory information as it gets
processed in the four inner senses listed earlier. For other animals, this is
where the highest level of cognitive processing occurs. The inner senses are
important in human beings, too, not just in their own right but also because
these images (visual, auditory, etc.) get put at the service of intellectual
cognition. They are not just the data by which we initially form abstract
thoughts; beyond that, they crucially accompany all of our ongoing thoughts,
so that when the intellect is thinking about, for instance, the nature of a
triangle, or the nature of a camel, the inner senses are at the same time
framing sensory images of triangles or camels. (When one tries to think
about things one has never perceived, one may form images that are likely to
be a close approximation. When one tries to think about imperceptible things,
like the human soul or an angel, still one forms images, but to little
advantage, which is precisely why it is so hard for us to think about such
things.) Thus, as with the initial gathering of information through the senses,
“turning toward phantasms is, for the soul, its natural mode of thinking.”36 In
this process, the intellect and the senses run in tandem, with the result that
what does the thinking is not the intellect alone or the senses alone, but the
human being as a whole, using all of its cognitive faculties.37
These remarks threaten to bring us around in a circle, back to the idea that
using the senses is simply the soul’s nature. What we sought, instead, was an
account of why it is its nature. Aquinas’s view is that the mind not only
naturally does work in tandem with the senses, but that it works best that
way. This point is made with particular vividness in his discussions of how
the soul will operate for the period of time between its death and the
resurrection of the body, at the Final Judgment. Apart from the body, the soul
will operate as the angels do, by directly grasping intelligible truths conveyed
to it by other intellectual substances. (The idea seems to be that our souls
will, during this time, communicate telepathically with the angels, and
perhaps with other separated souls.) One might suppose that this mode of
thought will be better than our earthly mode, thereby making the eventual
resurrection of the body undesirable. Not so, according to Aquinas, because
although this mode of cognition is better for the angels, it is not better for us.
Just as people who are less intelligent need many concrete examples to bring
them to an understanding of something abstract, so our minds are such that
we work best through the senses: “in order for human souls to be able to have
a complete and distinctive cognition of things, they are constituted by nature
so as to be united to bodies; in this way they acquire a distinct cognition of
sensible things from the things themselves.”38
Again, and now at a deeper level, we can see the essentially biological
orientation of Aquinas’s thinking about human nature, even in a highly
theological context. The soul will exist apart from the body and will during
this time communicate with the angels. But it is not our nature to exist that
way, and reflection on our cognitive processes shows why it is not. Even
though the mind itself does not use the body when it thinks, nevertheless our
minds work best when attached to a body. We are, essentially, rational
animals.
NOTES
1. See James Doig’s contribution to this volume.
2. Aristotle, De anima. III.5, 430a23.
3. The Treatise on Human Nature was written ca. 1267. At roughly the
same time, Aquinas composed his more detailed Disputed Question on the
Soul (QDA), and his commentary on Aristotle’s De anima (In DA). Readers
interested in exploring Aquinas’s views should begin with the Treatise,
which contains the most concise and elementary account, and then look to
QDA for a more developed statement, and to In DA for a fuller understanding
of the Aristotelian background. Also particularly important is the treatment in
SCG II.56–90 dating from the early 1260s. My translation of the Treatise
(Hackett, 2002) contains extensive notes intended for non-experts.
4. ST I q.75 a.1; cf. De anima II.1, 412a28.
5. DPN 2 (Leonine lines 112–18; Marietti §349).
6. De substantiis separatis 1 (Leonine lines 1–5; Marietti §43).
7. This debate over the status of Aristotelian hylomorphism obviously
runs too deep and wide to be pursued here. The main task of my
Metaphysical Themes 1274–1671 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2011) is to
assess the rise and fall of hylomorphic metaphysics in the years from
Aquinas to Descartes and Locke.
8. The paradox of a stuff, matter, that is intrinsically characterless is one
of the principal difficulties of the hylomorphic approach, and is handled very
differently by different scholastic authors. For Aquinas’s approach, see
Jeffrey Brower’s contribution to this volume and also, for an extensive
textual analysis, John F. Wippel, The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas
Aquinas: From Finite Being to Uncreated Being (Washington, D.C.: Catholic
University of America Press, 2000).
9. Supernaturally, Aquinas thinks it is possible for any form to exist apart
from matter, a doctrine that looms largest in discussions of the Eucharist.
Hereafter, however, I will generally ignore such absolute, supernatural
possibilities. When I speak without qualification of what is possible or
necessary, the modality at issue will generally be natural or physical, rather
than metaphysical or logical.
10. SCG II.51.
11. ST I q.75 a.2.
12. Aquinas often couches this thesis regarding the human soul as the
thesis that the human soul is “subsistent” (e.g., ST I q.75 a.2; QDA 1). This is
his label for the precise characteristic of substances that they are the sorts of
beings that can exist without inhering in other things (see my discussion in
Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature §2.2). To understand scholastic theories
of substance, such as Aquinas’s, it is important to frame the theory more
precisely than is usually done. The theory does not require that substances be
(naturally) capable of existing apart from everything else. That criterion
immediately admits of obvious counterexamples. Rather, the theory requires
that substances be able to exist without inhering in any subject. This rules out
all accidental forms, which (naturally) require a subject, and rules out all
substantial forms other than the human soul, since they require matter for
their operation, and so cannot exist apart from matter. (This last inference
again presupposes a connection between operating and existing. For that
principle, see, e.g., ST I q.75 a.3: “all things have existence and operation in a
similar way.”) The subsistence criterion does not rule out accidental unities
such as a heap of stones. A heap is not a substance, however, because it is not
a being at all, and so is not even a candidate for the subsistence criterion,
which applies only to things or beings. A heap is not a being because it lacks
a substantial form, for reasons that will be clearer below.
13. For this stage of the argument, going from IOP to immortality, see, e.g.,
ST I q.75 a.6 and QDA 14.
14. ST I q.75 a.2. For another version of this argument, see In DA III.7
(Leonine lines 131–59; Marietti §680), which elaborates on a sketch along
these lines that Aristotle had put forth at De anima III.4, 429a18–24.
15. For these examples, see QDV 24.1c. The focus there is on free will, but
Aquinas takes the distinctive character of human freedom to be the direct
result of our greater cognitive capacities. For discussion of this issue, see
Thomas Williams’s chapter in this volume.
16. Aquinas only once utters the famous principle often associated with his
name—“nihil est in intellectu quod non sit prius in sensu”—and he does so
only as an initial objection to his position (QDV 2.3 obj. 19). In his response
to that objection he signals, however, that he accepts the principle, reworded
as the thesis that “what exists in our intellect must first have existed in the
senses” (QDV 2.3 ad 19). Does this make Aquinas an empiricist? As the later
history of philosophy demonstrates, one’s commitment to empiricism must
be judged not so much by abstract principles such as this, but by the rigor
with which they are applied.
17. ST I q.75 a.5.
18. For Aquinas’s theory of individuation, see again Jeffrey Brower’s
contribution to this volume.
19. On Aquinas’s theory of mental representation, see Claude Panaccio,
“Aquinas on Intellectual Representation,” in D. Perler, ed., Ancient and
Medieval Theories of Intentionality (Leiden: Brill, 2001), 185–201, as well as
Jeffrey Brower and Susan Brower-Toland, “Aquinas on Mental
Representation,” Philosophical Review 117 (2008): 193–243.
20. ST I q.50 a.3.
21. For the place of human beings in the larger context of intellectual
substances, including the angels, see SCG II.46–55, as well as Disputed
Question on Spiritual Creatures and the treatise De substantiis separatis.
22. The first article of Aquinas’s Disputed Question on the Soul takes up
this issue in careful detail, asking whether the human soul can be both a form
and a hoc aliquid, a particular thing, which he goes on to explain as
tantamount to the soul’s being a subsistent entity. For a thorough discussion
of Aquinas’s views in this area, see Bernardo Carlos Bazán, “The Human
Soul: Form and Substance? Thomas Aquinas’ Critique of Eclectic
Aristotelianism,” Archives d’histoire doctrinale et littéraire du Moyen Age
64 (1997): 95–126. For a more general evaluation of Aquinas’s position as a
version of dualism, see Eleonore Stump, Aquinas (London: Routledge,
2003), ch. 6.
23. ST I q.77 a.6.
24. For a brief overview of this division, see ST I q.78 a.1. For a fuller
account of many of the details, see In DA. I discuss all of these powers at
some length in Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature, chs. 5–10. For a recent
summary of the broader medieval background regarding the soul’s powers,
see Dag Nikolaus Hasse, “The Soul’s Faculties,” in R. Pasnau, ed., The
Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2010), 305–19.
25. DUI ch. 3 (Leonine lines 378–81; Marietti §233).
26. On the status of artifacts for Aquinas, see, recently, Michael Rota,
“Substance and Artifact in Thomas Aquinas,” History of Philosophy
Quarterly 21 (2004): 241–59. It is unclear whether Aquinas wants to
recognize aggregates of nonliving substances—e.g., a pool of water or a
stone—as a substance over and above the minimal-sized water and stone
particles that make up the aggregate. I argue that he does not in Thomas
Aquinas on Human Nature, ch. 3.
27. This is “essence” in the strict Aristotelian sense of what defines the
thing, rather than in the weaker modern sense of merely being necessary. A
thing has many necessary properties, but one defining essence. Strictly
speaking, for Aquinas, the essence is not simply the substantial form, but
rather the substantial form together with the common matter (see ST I q.29
a.2 ad 3; I q.75 a.4), a detail that helps safeguard the essentially bodily aspect
of human beings.
28. E.g., ST I q.76 a.4.
29. ST I q.7 a.3. I discuss Aquinas’s theory of substantial form in more
detail, in its broader historical context into the seventeenth century, in “Form,
Substance, and Mechanism,” Philosophical Review 113 (2004): 31–88. For a
still broader and more detailed look at scholastic views in this domain,
focusing on the later Middle Ages, see my Metaphysical Themes, chs. 24–26.
30. For views prior to Aquinas, see Anton C. Pegis, St. Thomas and the
Problem of the Soul in the Thirteenth Century (Toronto: Pontifical Institute
of Mediaeval Studies, 1934), and Richard Dales, The Problem of the Rational
Soul in the Thirteenth Century (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1995). For the later
debate, see Marilyn Adams, William Ockham (Notre Dame, Ind.: University
of Notre Dame Press, 1987), ch. 15; Richard Cross, The Physics of Duns
Scotus: The Scientific Context of a Theological Vision (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1998), ch. 4; Pasnau, Metaphysical Themes, ch. 25.
31. SCG II.58.6.
32. In I Cor 15.2.924.
33. An important further detail here is that, for Aquinas, a particular soul
can be joined only to a body of exactly the right sort—my soul needs my
body, or at any rate a body just exactly like it, and could not be joined to
anyone else’s body. “Just as specifically the same matter is needed for
specifically the same form, so numerically the same matter is needed for
numerically the same form. For just as a cow’s soul cannot be the soul of a
horse’s body, so one cow’s soul cannot be another cow’s soul. Therefore,
since numerically the same rational soul remains, it must be united again at
the resurrection with numerically the same body” (CT I.153 [Marietti §305]).
For further discussion of these issues, from a somewhat different perspective,
see Eleonore Stump’s chapter in this volume on “Resurrection and the
Separated Soul.” I myself discuss these issues further in Thomas Aquinas on
Human Nature, ch. 12.
34. Even the punishment of Original Sin is simply the abrogation of a gift
given to Adam and Eve; our punishment is having to live in our natural state,
infirm and unwise (see ST I q.100 a.1). On grace, see the chapter in the
present volume by Andrew Pinsent.
35. QDA 1c.
36. ST I q.89 a.1.
37. On the need for phantasms, see ST I q.84 a.7 and In DMR 2. I discuss
this doctrine in detail in Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature, §9.4.
38. ST I q.89 a.1.
PART VI
THEORY OF LANGUAGE
CHAPTER 27
THEORY OF LANGUAGE
GYULA KLIMA
Now the discussion concerns utterances that are meaningful on account of human
agreement. Thus, by the phrase “affections of the soul” [passiones animae] we must
understand the concepts of understanding [intellectus conceptiones], which nouns, verbs
and expressions immediately signify, according to Aristotle’s position. They cannot
immediately signify things, as is clear from their mode of signification; for the noun
“man” signifies human nature in abstraction from the singulars. Therefore, it cannot
immediately signify a singular human, whence the Platonics posited that it should
signify the separate Idea of Man. However, since this does not subsist in the abstract in
reality according to Aristotle’s position, but is only in the intellect, it was necessary for
him to say that utterances immediately signify the concepts of the intellect and by their
mediation the things.5
The ratio of every single thing is what its name signifies, as the ratio of a stone is what
its name signifies. But names are the signs of intellectual conceptions, whence the ratio
of any single thing signified by a name is the conception of the intellect that the name
signifies. And this conception of the intellect is in the intellect as in its subject, but it is
in the thing thought of as in that which is represented: for the conceptions of the intellect
are certain similitudes of the things thought of. But if the conception of the intellect were
not assimilated to the thing, then the conception would be false of that thing; for
example, if the intellect would think something that is not a stone to be a stone. So the
ratio of the stone is in the intellect as in its subject, but it is in the stone as in that which
causes truth in the conception of the intellect thinking the stone to be such and such.6
Thus, the ratio, indeed, the same ratio, is both in the intellect, as the
conception of the intellect, and in the object, as in what is conceived by that
conception. This conception is said to be similar to the object precisely on
account of embodying (or should I say, encoding?), the same ratio that is in
the object. And it is precisely the presence of the same ratio in the object that
renders the conception of the intellect true of the object.
In another passage, in connection with the question of how the attributes
we predicate of God may apply to Him, Aquinas explains in more detail in
what sense we can say that the ratio is in the thing:
we should know that a ratio, as taken here, is nothing else, but what the intellect
apprehends from the signification of some name, and this in the case of those things that
have definition is the definition of the thing itself, in accordance with what the
Philosopher says: “the ratio signified by the name is the definition.”7 But some things
that are not defined are [also] said to have a ratio in this way, e.g., things such as
quantity or quality, which are not defined because they are most general genera.
Nevertheless, the ratio of quality is what is signified by the name of quality; and it is
that from which quality has it that it is quality. Thus, it makes no difference whether
those things that are said to have a ratio have a definition. And so it is clear that the ratio
of wisdom predicated of God is what is conceived of in the signification of this name,
even if divine wisdom itself cannot be defined. Nevertheless, the name “ratio” does not
signify this conception itself, because that is signified by the name of wisdom, or by
some other name of the thing, but it signifies the intention of this conception, just as the
name “definition” and other names of second imposition do. And thus the second point,
namely, the one concerning how the ratio is said to be in the thing, is also clear. For this
does not mean that the intention itself which is signified by the name “ratio” would be
in the thing, nor even that the conception to which this intention applies would be in the
thing outside the soul, for it is in the soul as in its subject; but it is said to be in the thing
insofar as there is something in the thing outside the soul that corresponds to the
conception of the soul, as what is signified [corresponds] to the sign.8
So, the ratio that is immediately signified by the name of some sort of thing
is an inherent act of the human mind considered precisely with regard to its
information content,9 that is, a concept, whereby the mind conceives of the
sort of thing in question. This relation of immediate signification, as we have
seen, is established by an act of imposition. But when we impose words to
signify, we normally do not impose them to talk about our concepts, but to
talk about the things we conceive, unless of course we are imposing names
on concepts by which we conceive of concepts. The utterance imposed on
our concept by which we conceive of human beings, say, “man” in English
or “homo” in Latin, is not used to talk about this concept, but rather to talk
about what we conceive by this concept. But, of course, we can form
concepts by which we conceive of concepts, and thus the name imposed on
such a concept is used to talk about these concepts. Such a name, in fact, is
the name “ratio,” which, as Aquinas indicates in the passage above,
(immediately) signifies an intention, namely a concept whereby we conceive
of other concepts (by which, in turn, we may conceive external things). An
intention or concept of this sort, therefore, is usually referred to in the
medieval logical literature as a second intention (i.e., an intention by which
we conceive first intentions), and its name a name of second imposition. But,
again, just as a name of first imposition is not used to talk about the concept
on which it is imposed, but about the things conceived by that concept, so a
name of second imposition is not used to talk about the second intention on
which it is imposed, but about the first intentions conceived by this second
intention. Thus, although imposition (of any order) primarily establishes the
relation of immediate signification between an utterance and a concept,
because of the naturally representative nature of the concept itself, this also
establishes the relation of conventional ultimate signification, on account of
which the word signifies not the concept, but rather the object of the concept,
namely, whatever it is that is conceived by this concept.
Therefore, Aquinas’s conception is by no means susceptible to
Wittgensteinian objections to a “private language.” On Aquinas’s and his
contemporaries’ conception, our concepts are in fact very public entities. Our
concepts form the natural representational system of the human mind, which
is therefore common to all human beings, and which we express by each and
every meaningful utterance we make, using these utterances to refer, not to
some hidden, private mental events, but whatever we conceive by these
“mental events,” the commonly accessible objects of our thought.10
Now what is such an object of thought, what is it that is conceived by a
concept? Clearly, the answer depends on the kind of concept we are talking
about. So far, we have only considered concepts that provide the signification
of so-called categorematic terms, i.e., terms that can be the subject or
predicate of a proposition.11 And even among these, we have only considered
simple, universal terms, as opposed to complex terms and singular terms,
respectively. Aquinas and his contemporaries were, of course, very much
aware of the variety of semantic functions of various parts of speech, which,
in line with the common doctrine of imposition and signification, they would
all primarily attribute to the different semantic functions of the concepts on
which these parts of speech are imposed.
Aquinas wrote at a time when influential textbooks on logic devoted
thoroughgoing, subtle discussions to the issue of the signification of
syncategorematic terms, that is, parts of speech we nowadays would refer to
as those expressing logical connectives. Of course, none of these authors held
that by these concepts we conceive of, and so by the corresponding terms we
signify, things in the way we do by categorematic concepts. (Just what would
be the thing we conceive by the concepts expressed by the words “no,”
“and,” or “every”?) Therefore, they rather analyzed the ways in which
constructing these terms together with categorematic terms modifies the
semantic functions of the latter.12 Aquinas, not being a logician but a
theologian, did not devote separate attention to syncategorematic terms per
se. However, he did deal in great detail with one syncategorematic term in
particular, or rather a term that has both syncategorematic and categorematic
functions, namely, the verb “est” [“is”] and its cognates, such as its infinitive
form “esse” [“to be”] or its participle “ens” [“being”].
The reason why [Aristotle] says that the verb “is” co-signifies composition is that it does
not principally signify composition, but secondarily; for it primarily signifies what
occurs to the mind in the way of actuality absolutely: for “is,” uttered absolutely,
signifies being in act, and hence it signifies as a verb. But since actuality, which the verb
“is” principally signifies, is in general the actuality of every form, whether it is a
substantial or an accidental actuality, this is why when we want to signify any form or
act to actually inhere [inesse] in a subject, we signify this by means of the verb “is,”
either absolutely [simpliciter] or with some qualification [secundum quid].14
Existence itself [ipsum esse] is not signified as the subject of existence, just as [the act
of] running [currere] is not signified as the subject of running, therefore, just as we
cannot say that [the act of] running itself runs, so we cannot say that existence itself is.
But just as that-which-is is signified as the subject of existence, so that-which-runs is
signified as the subject of running. Therefore, just as we can say of that which runs, or
the runner, that it runs, insofar as it is subjected to running, so we can say of a being
[ens], or that which is, that it is, insofar as it participates in the act of existing
[inquantum participat actum essendi].21
(1) x is F
(2) x is-with-respect-to-its-F-ness
(3) The F-ness of x is
(4) x is-(actual)-with-respect-to-a-thing-that-is-F,
which is true just in case x is an F, that is, if x is identical with a thing that is
F, namely, itself, provided it is F (for if the thing is not F, then it is clearly
not identical with any thing that is an F). So, in this sense the qualified sense
of “is” clearly expresses the actual identity of x with itself under the
designation of being an F.26
Indeed, we can also explain along the same lines why the enuntiabile
signified by the whole proposition has to be signified to be a being by the
copula in the same sense, as Aquinas claims, in which it would signify the
being of a privation or any other being of reason. For the primary semantic
value of the predicate F is neither its suppositum (a thing that is actually F),
nor its ultimate significate (the thing’s individualized F-ness), but its
immediate significate, namely, F-ness in general, as it is conceived by the
abstractive mind forming the abstract concept expressed by the term F.27 So,
what the proposition as a whole signifies, namely, that x is F, is actual in the
same sense in which we can say that
(5) x is-(actual)-with-respect-to-F-ness-(in-general).
Here the qualified predicate obviously has to express the actuality of the
subject with respect to a being of reason, given that the qualification itself
refers to something that is the direct object of reason, namely, the nature of
the thing conceived in abstraction from its individuating conditions.
To be sure, Aquinas never spells out the idea expressed in the
propositional schemata listed here in exactly such terms. However, his
several remarks made in various contexts about the primary and secondary
senses of being relating to each other as unqualified (simpliciter) and
qualified (secundum quid), as well as his remarks about how the different
semantic values of the same term added to the copula may provide different
qualifications on its primary sense (thereby determining different secondary
senses of the verb), may well justify the connections expressed by the
foregoing propositional schemata.
Indeed, further justification may be gleaned from the fact that once we
realize these connections, it is easy to see how Aquinas’s claims about the
analogical predication of being of substances, especially of God and His
creatures can also receive a consistent interpretation in the same framework.
(7) x is S
(8) x is-with-respect-to-its-S-ness.
A created spiritual substance has to contain two [principles], one of which is related to
the other as potency to act. And this is clear from the following. It is obvious that the
first being, which is God, is infinite act, namely, having in Himself the whole plenitude
of being not contracted to the nature of some genus or species. Therefore, it is necessary
that His being itself should not be an act of being that is, as it were, put into a nature
which is not its own being, for in this way it would be confined to that nature. Hence, we
say that God is His own being. But this cannot be said about anything else; just as it is
impossible to think that there should be several separate whitenesses, but if whiteness
were separate from any subject and recipient, then it would be only one, so it is
impossible that there should be a subsistent act of being, except only one. Therefore,
everything else after the first being, since it is not its own being, has being received in
something, by which its being is contracted; and thus in any created being the nature of
the thing that participates being is other than the act of being itself that is participated.29
Thus, since according to Aquinas we gain our primary concept of being from
created substances, we need to understand divine being by analogically
“stretching” our mundane concept. We first need to grasp the analogy
between the being of created substances and accidents, thereby understanding
that accidents exist in a diminished sense relative to substance. Then we can
grasp the analogy between the being of created substances and God, whereby
we understand that just as accidental being is diminished relative to
substantial being on account of the limitation imposed on the accident’s act
of being by its nature, so creaturely being is diminished relative to divine
being on account of the limitation imposed on a creaturely act of being by a
creaturely nature. Thus, the primary significate of the term “being” in the
ontological order has to be divine being. But this is cognized by us only
secondarily, on the basis of a primary concept we first acquire from
creaturely being.32 To be sure, if we gained our primary concept of being
directly from God, that is, if the primum cognitum of our minds were divine
being, and not created being in general, then we could understand created
being directly as a sort of diminished being, delimited and specified by the
limited nature it realizes, and then the cognitive order would match the
ontological order. However, since our mind is first confronted with the being
of created substances, it has to arrive at the cognition of divine being in this
more circuitous way, at least in accordance with Aquinas’s doctrine. But
pursuing the implications of this observation would already lead our
discussion into the arcana of late-medieval disputes concerning the primum
cognitum, which would be certainly beyond the scope of this chapter.33
NOTES
1. In fact, in medieval philosophy in general, there was no philosophical
discipline identifiable as “philosophy of language.” This is not to say,
however, that medieval thinkers had no philosophical reflections on language
as the conventional medium of human thought and communication. But these
reflections can be found mostly in works on grammar and logic, or scattered
all over in works in other disciplines, putting these reflections to work in
handling other philosophical, theological, or scientific problems. Aquinas,
being a theologian, never produced a major systematic work on grammar or
logic. He did produce commentaries on Aristotle’s On Interpretation and
Posterior Analytics (Aristotle’s logical works dealing with propositions and
with demonstrations, respectively), and there are some short logical treatises
dubiously attributed to him (on such topics as modal propositions and
fallacies). But one has to piece together his views on language mostly from
scattered remarks in his other, philosophical and theological works, and from
contemporary logical doctrines he knew and used, as something presupposed
in his philosophical and theological discussions.
2. By way of a preliminary description, one may say that a form in general
is a determination of the way something is. Thus, a form of a thing is what
makes the thing actual (i.e., actually existing) either absolutely speaking, if
the form is a substantial form, or in some respect, if the form in question is an
accidental form. See, e.g., De Principiis Naturae, c.1.
3. The allusion in the last clause is to Aristotle’s description of
signification in his On Interpretation (1.6b21–22), which functioned pretty
much as “the standard definition” of meaning for medieval logicians. See
Aquinas, In Peri hermeneias, lib.1, l.5, n.16: “it is a property of a
significative utterance that it generates some understanding in the soul of the
listener” (proprium vocis significativae est quod generet aliquem intellectum
in animo audientis).
4. Translations, unless otherwise indicated, are mine.
5. In Peri hermeneias, lib.1, l.2, n.5.
6. Resp. ad lect. Vercell. de art. 108, q.1. Cf. “The ratio that a name
signifies is the conception of the intellect about the thing signified by the
name” (Ratio enim quam significat nomen, est conceptio intellectus de re
significata per nomen.) ST I q.13 a.4.
7. See, In Meta, lb.4, lc.16, n.733.
8. Super Sent, lib.1, ds.2, q.1, a.3. in corpore.
9. That is to say, a ratio is a mental act considered only insofar as it is a
carrier of some specific sort of information, regardless of just what sort of
entity this carrier of information is, namely, whether it is some brain function
or some purely spiritual modification of an immaterial mind. That is a
completely separate issue. But then, based on this understanding of what a
concept or ratio is, Aquinas will argue that our universal concepts, carrying
just the type of information they do, cannot be the acts of a material organ.
See G. Klima, “Aquinas on the Materiality of the Human Soul and the
Immateriality of the Human Intellect,” Philosophical Investigations 32
(2009): 163–82.
10. For a brief discussion of the medieval conception of a naturally
common, and in this sense “public” mental language, as opposed to the post-
Cartesian conception of “a private” language of ideas, see G. Klima, “Review
of C. Panaccio: Le Discours intérieur de Platon à Guillaume d’Ockham,”
History and Philosophy of Logic 23 (2002): 71–73. Of course, for an
excellent survey and detailed discussion of premodern conceptions of mental
language, one should consult Panaccio’s book reviewed there.
11. For further niceties of the medieval (and later) distinction between
categorematic and syncategorematic terms, see G. Klima,
“Syncategoremata,” in Keith Brown, ed., Elsevier’s Encyclopedia of
Language and Linguistics, 2d ed. (Oxford: Elsevier, 2006), 12:353–56.
12. This is not to say, however, that some of them did not attribute any
representative function to such concepts. In fact, Peter of Spain argued that
syncategorematic concepts exercise their function of modifying the
representative function of categorematic concepts as a result of their own
representative function, representing as they do certain modes of the things
represented by categorematic concepts, as conceived by these categorematic
concepts. Cf. Peter of Spain, Tractatus, called afterwards Summule
Logicales, ed. L. M. De Rijk (Assen: Van Gorcum, 1972), 195 and 212; Peter
of Spain, Syncategoreumata, ed. L. M. De Rijk and trans. J. Spruyt (Leiden:
E. J. Brill, 1992), 106–9.
13. After all, we might introduce just any old symbol to do this linking,
say, the “=” sign, uttered, for instance, as “equals.” So, out of a mere list of
names, such as “Socrates,” “a man,” “Plato,” “a philosopher,” instead of
forming propositions by using the copula (as in “Socrates is a man” or “Plato
is a philosopher”), we might form propositions, such as “Socrates = a man,”
“Plato = a philosopher,” in which there would be not a hint of the idea of
being or existence.
14. In Peri hermeneias, 1.5, n.22.
15. As St. Thomas wrote: “we should say that the thing from which
something is denominated does not always have to be a form according to the
nature of the thing; it is enough if it is signified in the way a form would be
signified, grammatically speaking. For a man is denominated from his
actions or from his clothes, which are not forms in reality” (dicendum est
quod illud a quo aliquid denominatur non oportet quod sit semper forma
secundum rei naturam, sed sufficit quod significetur per modum formae,
grammatice loquendo. Denominatur enim homo ab actione et ab indumento,
et ab aliis huiusmodi, quae realiter non sunt formae) (QDP, q.7, a.10, ad 8).
Cf. also, e.g., Cajetan: “Don’t be misled when you hear that a denominative
comes from a denominating form, and don’t believe on account of the word
‘form’ that the denominating thing has to be a form of the thing that is
denominated; you have to know that by the name ‘form’ in this context we
understand anything from which something is said to be such, whether in
reality it is an accident, or a substance, or matter or form” (Verum ne fallaris
cum audis denominativum a forma denominante oriri, et credas propter
formae vocabulum quod res denominans debet esse forma eius quod
denominatur, scito quod formae nomine in hac materia intelligimus omne
illud a quo aliquid dicitur tale, sive illud sit secundum rem accidens, sive
substantia, sive materia, sive forma) (Cajetan [Thomas de Vio], Scripta
Philosophica: Commentaria in Praedicamenta Aristotelis, ed. M. H. Laurent
[Rome: Angelicum, 1939], 18).
16. Cf. In Meta, lb.6, lc.4; In Meta, lb.5, lc.9, n.895.
17. Cf. G. Nuchelmans, Late Scholastic and Humanist Theories of the
Proposition (Amsterdam: North Holland Publishing Co., 1980), and Theories
of the Proposition: Ancient and Medieval Conceptions of the Bearers of
Truth and Falsity (Amsterdam: North Holland Publishing Co., 1973). D.
Perler, “Late Medieval Ontologies of Facts,” The Monist 77 (1994): 149–69.
18. For this interpretation, clearly reflecting Aquinas’s doctrine, see
Cajetan, Scripta Philosophica, 87.
19. Cf. Super Sent, lib.3, d.5, q.3, a.3; In Meta, lb.9, lc.11; ST I q.13 a.12;
ST I q.85 a.5 ad 3-um; ST III q.16 a.7 ad 4-um; a.9, ad 3-um.
20. The literature on this doctrine is simply staggering. For an up-to-date
survey of the literature, as well as an eminently accessible account of
Aquinas’s great commentator’s, Cajetan’s interpretation, and further
articulation of Aquinas’s doctrine, see Joshua P. Hochschild, The Semantics
of Analogy: Rereading Cajetan’s De Nominum Analogia (Notre Dame, Ind.:
University of Notre Dame Press, 2010).
21. In De Hebdomadibus, lc.2, n.22.
22. For a more comprehensive treatment of Aquinas’s conception of beings
of reason along these lines, see G. Klima, “The Changing Role of Entia
Rationis in Medieval Philosophy: A Comparative Study with a
Reconstruction,” Synthese 96 (1993): 25–59.
23. For a technical, model-theoretical account of exactly how this
secondary signification of “is” can be compositionally obtained from its
primary signification, see G. Klima, “Aquinas’ Theory of the Copula and the
Analogy of Being,” Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy 5 (2002):
159–76.
24. See G. Klima, “Peter of Spain, the author of the Summulae,” in J.
Gracia and T. Noone, eds., Blackwell’s Companion to Philosophy in the
Middle Ages (Oxford: Blackwell, 2003), 526–31, esp. 529–30.
2. For a brief, up-to-date survey of the medieval theories of supposition,
see Stephen Read, “Medieval Theories: Properties of Terms,” Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2006 edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta,
forthcoming <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2006/entries/medieval-
terms/>.
26. Cf. Super Sent, lib.3, d.5, q.3, a.3 expos. “We have to say that there is a
difference between substantive and adjective names. For substantives signify
not only a form but also the suppositum of a form and can be predicated on
account of both. And when they are predicated on account of the suppositum,
then the predication is said to be predication by identity; and when on
account of the form, then it is said to be predication by denomination or by
information. And the latter is a more appropriate predication, because terms
as predicates are taken formally. Adjectives, however, only signify a form,
and so they can be predicated only by information. Therefore, this is false:
‘the essence is generating’, although this is true: ‘the essence is the Father’.
Thus, when it is said that the Son of God is a man, then the predication is by
information and identity; but when it is said that the divine essence is a man,
then it is by identity, for [the divine essence] is really identical with a
suppositum of man, but not by information, for divine nature is not signified
as a suppositum subsisting in human nature” (Dicendum, quod differentia est
inter nomina substantiva et adjectiva. Substantiva enim significant non
tantum formam, sed etiam suppositum formae, unde possunt praedicari
ratione utriusque; et quando praedicantur ratione suppositi, dicitur
praedicatio per identitatem; quando autem ratione formae, dicitur per
denominationem, sive informationem: et haec est magis propria praedicatio,
quia termini in praedicato tenentur formaliter. Adjectiva autem tantum
significant formam; et ideo non possunt praedicari, nisi per informationem:
unde haec est falsa: essentia est generans; quamvis haec sit vera: essentia
est pater. Cum igitur dicitur, filius Dei est homo, est praedicatio per
informationem et identitatem; cum vero dicitur: essentia divina est homo, est
praedicatio per identitatem, quia est idem secundum rem cum supposito
hominis; non autem per informationem, quia natura divina non significatur
ut suppositum subsistens in humana natura). See also Super Sent., lib.3, d.7,
q.1, a.1, co; ST I q.39 a.6 ad 2; ST I q.13 a.12; Contra errores Graecorum,
pars 1, cap.18 co.
27. See Cajetan’s astute discussion of this issue in Thomas de Vio Caietani
In De Ente et Essentia D. Thomae Aquinatis, Marietti, 1934, Quaestio 7:
Utrum natura absolute sumpta sit illa quae praedicetur de individuis, 100–
101.
28. That an act of existence (a significate of the verb “is” or “exists”) does
not delimit itself is not some arcane metaphysical principle that only “the
initiated” could grasp: in general, a qualification added to a predicate
referring to the significate of the predicate itself is non-diminishing, and so it
can be dropped salva veritate. For example, saying “This sheet of paper is
white with respect to its whiteness (or with respect to its color)” amounts to
the same as saying absolutely “This sheet of paper is white.” By contrast, if
the qualification refers to something else, say, the quantity informed by this
whiteness, as in “This sheet is white with respect to its one side,” then it is
diminishing, for this claim can be true of a sheet that is not totally white but
only on one side, and in that case the qualification cannot be dropped salva
veritate, for of that sheet the absolute predication “This sheet is white” is not
true. For more about the issue of diminishing vs. non-diminishing
qualifications and their relation to analogical predication and the related issue
of the medieval treatment of the fallacy secundum quid et simpliciter, see G.
Klima, “The Semantic Principles Underlying Saint Thomas Aquinas’s
Metaphysics of Being,” Medieval Philosophy and Theology 5 (1996): 87–
141.
29. QDSC, q. un., a.1.
30. It should be noted here, however, that this is not “the criterion” on
account of which “being” ought to be regarded as predicated analogically of
God and creatures. Throughout this chapter, a predicate is regarded as
analogical if and only if it has a primary sense and some secondary sense(s)
somehow related to, and therefore derivable from, the primary sense by
means of some diminishing qualification. This “semantic derivability” need
not reflect at all the actual process of the formation of an analogical concept.
For the finer details of this issue in the context of thirteenth-century logic, see
E. J. Ashworth, “Analogy and Equivocation in Thirteenth-Century Logic:
Aquinas in Context,” Mediaeval Studies, 54 (1991): 94–135, and E. J.
Ashworth, “Medieval Theories of Analogy,” Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Winter 2004 edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2004/entries/analogy-medieval/>.
31. Super Sent, lib.1, d.22, q.1, a.2 co.
32. Cf. “Although in the natural order of cognition God is the first thing to
know, nevertheless, as far as we are concerned, his sensible effects are
known by us earlier” (Quamvis enim secundum naturalem ordinem
cognoscendi Deus sit primum cognitum, tamen quoad nos prius sunt cogniti
effectus sensibiles eius). In De Hebdomadibus, lc.4. Cf. ST I q.88 a.3 resp.
and ad 1.
33. A difficult, but very illuminating discussion of the problem can be
found in the first question of Cajetan’s commentary on Aquinas’s De Ente et
Essentia. See op. cit. Quaestio 1: Utrum ens sit primum cognitum ordine et
via originis, 2–19.
CHAPTER 28
BRIAN DAVIES
REJECTED ANSWERS
When turning to this question, Aquinas notes two responses to it both of
which he takes to be mistaken.
The first holds that all that we say of God should be construed in negative
terms—that, for example, “God is good” should be taken to mean “God is
not bad,” or that “God is living” should be taken to mean “God is not
inanimate.” Aquinas rejects these construals, since, so he argues, people who
say that God is good just do not mean that God is not bad. They mean that
God is actually good in and of himself. And people who say that God is
living are not just saying that God is not inanimate; they are telling us what
God really is (living as opposed to inanimate).
The second response tries to construe talk of God in causal terms and
argues that to say that God is X, Y, or Z is just to say that God causes things
to be X, Y, or Z. In terms of this response, to say, for example, that God is
good is just to say that God causes or accounts for there being good things.
Turning to this response, however, Aquinas argues that it seems to license us
to say what we cannot possibly say when it comes to God. God may cause
what is good, but, as Creator of the universe, as the cause of the esse of
things, God also causes (makes to be) what is bodily. Yet we surely cannot
conclude from this that God is something bodily. And should we suppose
that God is only good because he brings it about that good things exist? If
that were so, then God’s being good would depend on him creating good
things. Yet, Aquinas argues, God does not have to create and, therefore, we
cannot take statements like “God is good” only to mean that God produces
something good in the created universe. In Aquinas’s view, God is good, and
is whatever he is by nature, regardless of what he has brought about
(created/caused to be).
MOVING FORWARD
As he seeks to present his account of what is going on as we talk sensibly of
God, Aquinas notes two ways in which we use words, and he then asks
whether we can think of ourselves as using them in either of these ways as
we start to talk about God. His key terms here are “univocal/univocally” and
“equivocal/equivocally.”
One employs a word univocally, thinks Aquinas, when one uses it to talk
of two or more things and when the word means exactly the same each time
it is used. Suppose I say that Julius Caesar was a man and that Alexander the
Great was a man. According to Aquinas, I would be using “man” here
univocally. Again, suppose that I say that Paris is a city and that London is a
city, or that Paris is highly populated and that London is highly populated.
Aquinas would hold that I am here using “city” and “highly populated”
univocally.
By contrast, however, think of someone saying that they have money in
the bank and that their boat has just run into a bank (i.e., a river bank).
“Bank” used to speak about places in which we keep money, and “bank”
used to refer to what is to be found alongside rivers, is purely equivocal, or
so Aquinas would say. It is a linguistic accident that “bank” is used of things
that bear no resemblance to each other whatsoever (as it is a linguistic
accident that, for example, the word “date” is used to refer to what can be
eaten and to someone whom one might take out for a romantic evening). The
same can be said with an eye on, for example, “pen” as in “I keep my pen in
my pocket” and “I keep my pigs in a pen.”
With these distinctions in mind, Aquinas asks whether words applied both
to God and creatures should be thought of as univocal (meaning exactly the
same) or purely equivocal (having no meaning in common). And he rejects
both alternatives.
Words applied to creatures, he argues, cannot mean exactly the same
when applied to God, since God is not something distinct from his nature.
The reasoning goes roughly like this: (1) To say, for example, that John is
wise is to note that he has various attributes, not that he is these attributes; (2)
To say that God is wise is not to say that he has a collection of attributes
distinct from what he (considered as an individual) is; in God, wisdom is not
something different from God; (3) Clearly, therefore, “wise” in “John is
wise” and “God is wise” does not signify (pick out) exactly the same thing.
As used of John, it signifies an attribute distinct from an individual. As used
of God, it signifies the individual that God is. Or, in Aquinas’s words, and
focusing on the adjective “wise”:
When we say that a man is wise, we signify his wisdom as something distinct from the
other things about him—his essence, for example, his powers, or his existence. But
when we use “wise” when talking about God we do not intend to signify something
distinct from his essence, power or existence.… So it is clear that we do not use “wise”
in the same sense of God and people, and the same goes for all other words. So we
cannot use them univocally of God and creatures.2
On the other hand, Aquinas also wants to say, words applied to creatures
cannot mean something entirely different when applied to God. According to
Aquinas, we have positive reasons (philosophical ones) for saying that God
is, for example, active, powerful, living, and good, reasons based on what we
know of creatures. Yet, so he reasons, this could not be so if words like
“active,” “powerful,” “living,” and “good,” as used to talk about God, have
no meaning in common with our use of these words when we apply them to
creatures. Or as Aquinas again puts it: “Although we never use words in
exactly the same sense of creatures and of God, we are not merely
equivocating when we use the same word … for if this were so we could
never argue from statements about creatures—any such argument would be
invalidated by the Fallacy of equivocation.”3
ANALOGY
Immediately following the above observation, Aquinas writes: “So, we must
say that words are used of God and of creatures in an analogical way.” But
what does he mean here? His basic thought is that, when we apply words
signifying perfections to God (words that we learn in the first place when
taught to speak about creatures), the words in question (a) are truly
applicable to God, and (b) do not mean exactly what they do when used to
talk about creatures.
Note the word “perfections” here. When he says that words are used of
God and creatures in an analogical way Aquinas is not saying that all that we
might say of God is to be construed analogically. He does not, for example,
think that “The Lord is my shepherd” uses “shepherd” analogously.
Analogical predication is, for Aquinas, literal predication (is literally true,
not figuratively or metaphorically true). To say that Smokey is a cat is to say
what is literally true of him. And to say that I am alive is to say what is
literally true of me (as I write now). For Aquinas, though, to say that God is a
shepherd is not to say what is literally true of him, for God is not literally
someone in a field who looks after sheep. But, Aquinas also wants to say, we
can predicate certain terms literally of God if the terms in question do not
have some irreducibly creaturely meaning built into them. “Shepherd” means
something irreducibly creaturely (a shepherd is a human being with a
particular job at a particular time and a particular place). But what of words
like “good,” “living,” “wise,” and “powerful”? Can we use these words (and
similar ones) when speaking of what is not a creature? Aquinas thinks that
we can, and it is from here that his teaching on God and analogy takes off.
A central element in it is the conviction that we can use certain words
without meaning exactly the same thing on various occasions while also not
meaning something entirely different. And the conviction here is a sound
one. Consider, for example: “I love my family,” “I love my job,” and “I love
chicken curry.” Does “love” mean exactly the same in each of these
sentences? Hardly. But neither does it mean something entirely different.
And, notice, there is no problem in supposing that people who utter these
sentences are speaking literally. What we need to note is that love can
(literally) take different forms. Again, consider the sentences “My baby is
strong,” “My horse is strong,” and “The FBI is strong.” These can all be
thought to express literally true propositions. Yet the strength of babies is
hardly equal to the strength of horses, and the strength of the FBI goes well
beyond that of either babies or horses. What we need to note is that strength
(power) can take different forms.
With thoughts like these in mind Aquinas argues that we can use certain
words when talking of God and that we can understand them literally. He
would, however, want to add that we need to recognize how these words do
not mean just what they do when used to talk about creatures. Hence, for
example, he would find no problem in saying that the FBI is powerful and
that God is powerful. But, he would add, God is not a collection of material
individuals, as the FBI is. He would say that God’s power goes well beyond
that of the FBI, while also being comparable to it. Actually, he would say
that God’s power runs to creating the FBI (while not being an attribute that
he has distinct from himself).
Does Aquinas have some rule of thumb for determining what we can and
cannot take God to be? Yes, since he thinks that words signifying perfections
can always be used when talking of God so long as the perfections in
question are not such as to be had only by a creature of God. Being able to
purr is a perfection in the feline world. Perfect cats are purring cats. A cat
who cannot purr is sick or in some way thwarted. Yet Aquinas would not
want to say that God is able to purr. He would, however, say that God is, for
example, good. To call something good is not to categorize it as a creature of
some kind. Things of many different kinds can be thought of as good.
Goodness, we might say, can be had by anything that exists. So, thinks
Aquinas, goodness, considered as a perfection, can be ascribed to God.
Something is good, says Aquinas, insofar as it is desirable. But God is
desirable. So God is good.4
On the other hand, however, when it comes to much talk about God
Aquinas does not have a rule of thumb. Frequently, his line is that we are
justified in speaking of God with some words that we normally use to talk
about creatures just because we have one or another reason to do so. Should
we, for example, say that God is something that acts? Yes, replies Aquinas,
since we have reason to suppose that God has produced something and that
he continues to do so.5 Again, should we say that God is alive? Yes, replies
Aquinas, since we have reason to suppose that God acts of himself and not as
moved by something else.6 In general, Aquinas seeks to show that words X,
Y, or Z can be used when talking truly (and literally) of God by trying to
show that we have reason to use the words in question.
Question 13 of the Prima Pars is instructive when it comes to all of this.
Here Aquinas defends the claim that we can speak of God analogously with
words that we normally use when talking of creatures. But he does not
suggest (as some seem to have taken him to do) that we therefore have a
calculator that allows us mechanically to determine what can and cannot be
truly said of God. Commenting on Aquinas’s view that talk about God uses
words “analogically,” Peter Geach observes: “It would be better to say that it
turns out to be analogical: what happens, on Aquinas’s view, is that we first
call God “wise”; then discover that “the wisdom of God” is a designation of
God himself, whereas the like does not hold of any other being whom we
rightly call “wise”; and thus reflecting upon this, we see that “wise” cannot
be applied to God in the same way as to other beings.”7 With respect to
Prima Pars 13, Geach is exactly right. That question of the Summa
theologiae is best read as what Americans refer to as a “State of the Union
Speech.” In such speeches U.S. presidents tell their country where things
stand now given what has recently happened. In Prima Pars 13 Aquinas is
doing something like that with an eye on what he has written beforehand. He
has argued for the truth of “Deus est” (“God exists”); he has then noted ways
in which God must differ from creatures; then he has argued that certain
words that we use when talking of creatures can, for various reasons, be used
when talking of God; then he notes how these words, though not to be
thought of as used in a purely equivocal sense, are also not to be thought of
as used univocally.
In general, Aquinas’s mature view of “God talk” holds that terms we use
when speaking of creatures can be used to talk truly of God if we have reason
for using them with respect to God. And their sense, when used to talk about
God, is to be gleaned from the reasons we have for using them when talking
of God. So critics of Aquinas on talk about God do not need to worry about a
“theory of analogy.” They simply need to ask themselves if Aquinas delivers
good reasons for saying that God is X, Y, or Z, while also bearing in mind,
and, of course, evaluating, his reasons for denying that God is this, that, or
the other.8 “We cannot,” says Aquinas, “speak of God at all except in the
language we use of creatures.”9 Yet, he thinks, language we use of creatures
can be used to talk literally of God. Why? Because, thinks Aquinas, we have
a variety of reasons to use it in this way. To evaluate the truth of this
conclusion, readers will need to examine Aquinas’s many arguments for the
truth of the many propositions about God which he claims to be literally true.
NOTES
1. Statements (2) and (3) here are what Aquinas has in mind when saying
that God is entirely simple. Aquinas’s doctrine of divine simplicity is
discussed in this volume by Eleonore Stump, so I shall not labor to expound
it in any more detail.
2. ST I q.13 a.5. I should say that in this section of the present volume I
am concentrating on what Aquinas has to say about talking of God in the
Summa theologiae, in which his most mature treatment of the topic is to be
found.
3. ST I q.13 a.5.
4. ST I q.6 a.1.
5. Here, of course, Aquinas’s causal arguments for the truth of “God
exists” (Deus est) are relevant.
6. ST I q.18 a.3.
7. G. E. M. Anscombe and P. T. Geach, Three Philosophers (Blackwell:
Oxford, 1961), 122 f.
8. In Appendix 4 to vol. 3 of the Blackfriars edition of the Summa
Theologiae (London and New York: Eyre and Spottiswoode, 1964), Herbert
McCabe writes, “Too much has been made of St Thomas’s alleged teaching
on analogy. For him, analogy is not a way of getting to know about God, nor
is it a theory of the structure of the universe, it is a comment on our use of
certain words” (106). McCabe seems to me to hit the nail on the head here.
9. ST I q.13 a.5.
PART VII
PHILOSOPHICAL THEOLOGY
CHAPTER 29
ELEONORE STUMP
INTRODUCTION
The problem of evil is raised by the combination of certain traditional theistic
beliefs and the acknowledgement that there is evil in the world. If, as the
major monotheisms claim, there is a perfectly good, omnipotent, omniscient
God who creates and governs the world, how can the world such a God
created and governs have evil in it? In medieval philosophy in the Latin-
speaking west, philosophical discussion of evil is informed by Augustine’s
thought.1 Readers who have some acquaintance with the history of Christian
thought in general and with Augustine in particular may expect Aquinas’s
position as regards the problem of evil to be some version of what is often
understood, mistakenly, as Augustine’s theodicy.2 It will save confusion to
set this mistaken expectation aside at the outset.
Augustine struggled with the question of the metaphysical status of evil;
and his ultimate conclusion, that evil is a privation of being, was shared by
many later medieval philosophers, including Aquinas. “Privation” here is a
technical term of medieval logic and indicates one particular kind of
opposition; its correlative is possession. A privation is the absence of some
characteristic in a thing that naturally possesses that characteristic. So, on
Augustine’s views, evil is not nothing, as he is sometimes believed to have
maintained. Rather, it is a lack or deficiency of some sort of being in
something in which that sort of being is natural. This position of Augustine’s
is an attempt to explain, as it were, the ontology of evil. Nothing about this
ontological position constitutes a solution to the problem of evil, nor did
Augustine or any later medieval philosophers suppose it did.3 Aquinas
himself would certainly not have supposed that anything about the
metaphysical status of evil provided a reason for God’s permitting human
suffering to occur.4
Augustine is also known for his suggestion that the evil permitted by God
contributes to the beauty and goodness of the whole universe, just as a dark
patch may contribute to the lightness and beauty of a painting. Some people
also mistakenly interpret this suggestion on Augustine’s part as an attempt at
theodicy. But taking Augustine’s point in this way is to suppose that, for
Augustine, the answer to the question of why God allows suffering is that
suffering has an aesthetic value for God. The moral repulsiveness of such a
position strikes many people as obvious; it would most certainly have been
obvious to Aquinas.5 Aquinas himself explicitly repudiates the idea that God
would allow the suffering of human persons for any reason other than benefit
to the sufferers. So, for example, Aquinas says,
Whatever happens on earth, even if it is evil, turns out for the good of the whole world.
Because as Augustine says in the Enchiridion, God is so good that he would never
permit any evil if he were not also so powerful that from any evil he could draw out a
good. But the evil does not always turn out for the good of the thing in connection with
which the evil occurs, because although the corruption of one animal turns out for the
good of the whole world—insofar as one animal is generated from the corruption of
another—nonetheless it does not turn out for the good of the animal which is corrupted.
The reason for this is that the good of the whole world is willed by God for its own sake,
and all the parts of the world are ordered to this [end]. The same reasoning appears to
apply with regard to the order of the noblest parts [of the world] with respect to the other
parts, because the evil of the other parts is ordered to the good of the noblest parts. But
what ever happens with regard to the noblest parts is ordered only to the good of those
parts themselves, because care is taken of them for their own sake, and for their sake
care is taken of other things.… But among the best of all the parts of the world are
God’s saints.… He takes care of them in such a way that he does not allow any evil for
them which he does not turn into their good.6
If there is no resurrection of the dead, it follows that there is no good for human beings
other than in this life. And if this is the case, then those people are more miserable who
suffer many evils and tribulations in this life. Therefore, since the apostles and
Christians [generally] suffer more tribulations, it follows that they, who enjoy less of the
goods of this world, would be more miserable than other people.14
What Aquinas goes on to say spells out explicitly the difference between the
commonly accepted worldview of his society and that of the popular culture
of our own. He says,
If there were no resurrection of the dead, people would not think it was a power and a
glory to abandon all that can give pleasure and to bear the pains of death and dishonor;
instead they would think it was stupid.
So, in order to see human suffering as Aquinas does in his theodicy, in order
not to see the acceptance of human suffering or the justification of God’s
allowing such suffering as senseless, it is essential to Aquinas’s theodicy also
to include the doctrine that human beings are capable of everlasting union
with God in the afterlife.
It is also important to recognize that the best thing, the upper limit of
Aquinas’s scale of value for human lives, comes in degrees.15 This may
appear paradoxical, but a moment’s thought will dissipate the appearance. As
regards physical condition, the best state for human beings is to be in peak
physical condition. But human beings will differ greatly in what constitutes
peak physical condition for them. The peak physical condition for a professor
will be considerably less impressive as regards physical condition than the
peak physical condition of a professional athlete. Analogously, on Aquinas’s
views, human beings differ greatly in what constitutes for them the peak
human condition of union with God.16
That is because it is possible to have more or less of a loving relationship
in union with any person. It is possible to have more or less of a loving
relationship in union with God, too. The love and presence of omnipresent
God are fully and equally available to all human beings.17 But there are
differences in the willingness and the capacity to receive God’s love even on
the part of those human beings who are in union with God. Even in heaven,
then, the best thing for human beings, their glory, as Aquinas would call it,
comes in degrees. For this reason, what constitutes the most excellent state
for human beings is itself a degreed state; it is not had equally by all those
who are in that state.
If all the pain a human being suffers is from God [as Aquinas thinks it is], then he ought
to bear it patiently, both because it is from God and because it is ordered toward good;
for pains purge sins, bring evildoers to humility, and stimulate good people to love of
God.21
For a person who does not have faith, whose suffering is involuntary
simpliciter, God is justified in allowing suffering and suffering is defeated
because of the contribution suffering makes to warding off a greater harm for
the sufferer. On the other hand, for a person who is committed to a life of
faith, whose suffering is involuntary only in a certain respect, God is justified
in allowing suffering and suffering is defeated because of the contribution of
suffering to providing a greater good for the sufferer.22 Union with God
features in each of these benefits. The greater harm warded off is the
permanent absence of shared union with God; and the greater good provided
is the increased degree of everlasting shared union with God.
Since it is an extrinsic lower limit on the scale of human flourishing, the
negative value of the permanent absence of union with God outweighs the
negative value of suffering of any kind. And since union with God is the
intrinsic upper limit to human flourishing, the greater good of this union
outweighs the good of the avoiding of suffering. The main question for
Aquinas’s theodicy therefore is not whether the good of the benefit
outweighs the suffering in any given case but rather whether the suffering is
appropriately connected to one or the other of these benefits. Even if we
weigh the relative value of the benefits and the suffering as Aquinas does, the
question arises why Aquinas would suppose that suffering is connected to
these benefits in the way it needs to be for the purposes of theodicy.
Aquinas comments in great detail on the line in Hebrews: “whom the Lord
loves he chastens.”33 He says, for example,
Since pains are a sort of medicine, we should apparently judge correction and medicine
the same way. Now medicine in the taking of it is bitter and loathsome, but its end is
desirable and intensely sweet. So discipline is also. It is hard to bear, but it blossoms into
the best outcome.34
someone’s suffering adversity would not be pleasing to God except for the sake of some
good coming from the adversity. And so although adversity is in itself bitter and gives
rise to sadness, it should nonetheless be agreeable [to us] when we consider its
usefulness, on account of which it is pleasing to God.… For in his reason a person
rejoices over the taking of bitter medicine because of the hope of health, even though in
his senses he is troubled.35
Now it sometimes happens that God hearkens not to a person’s pleas but rather to his
advantage. A doctor does not hearken to the pleas of the sick person who requests that
the bitter medicine be taken away (supposing that the doctor doesn’t take it away
because he knows that it contributes to health); instead he hearkens to [the patient’s]
advantage, because by doing so he produces health, which the sick person wants most of
all. In the same way, God does not remove tribulations from the person stuck in them,
even though he prays earnestly for God to do so, because God knows these tribulations
help him forward to final salvation. And so although God truly does hearken, the person
stuck in afflictions believes that God hasn’t hearkened to him.36
For Aquinas, then, suffering is medicinal for the parts of a person’s psyche in
need of healing.37 For those who are already healed to a certain extent, the
experience of suffering enables them to open in a deeper way to the love of
God, as Aquinas says in the commentary on the Creed. But for those who are
very far from being healed, suffering is medicinal in the sense that, as
Aquinas puts it, it helps the sufferer forward to salvation. For those very
alienated from themselves and from God, suffering contributes to warding
off from the sufferer the worst thing for human beings.
It is plain that the general of an army does not spare [his] more active soldiers dangers or
exertions, but as the plan of battle requires, he sometimes lays them open to greater
dangers and greater exertions. But after the attainment of victory, he bestows greater
honor on the more active soldiers. So also the head of a household assigns greater
exertions to his better servants, but when it is time to reward them, he lavishes greater
gifts on them. And so neither is it characteristic of divine providence that it should
exempt good people more from the adversities and exertions of the present life, but
rather that it reward them more at the end.39
Aquinas’s sense that the inner wholeness of a person renders her more, rather
than less, likely to suffer can be understood in light of his taking suffering as
medicinal. Strenuous medical regimens are saved for the strongest patients,
in the hopes of bringing them to the most robust health and functioning. On
Aquinas’s theodicy, for those people who are psychically healthier, the
benefit that justifies suffering is the connection between suffering and glory.
So, for example, he says,
All the saints who have pleased God have gone through many tribulations by which they
were made the sons of God.40
Many who are alive [in the eschaton] will be tried in the persecution of Antichrist, and
they will surpass in greatness the many who had previously died.41
Elsewhere he puts the point in a more general way. He says,
These and many other passages make it clear that Aquinas thinks there is a
connection between suffering, on the one hand, and glory in shared union
with God, on the other. It is not surprising, then, to find that Aquinas sees a
person’s enduring severe suffering as a sign of the spiritual greatness of the
sufferer.
Aquinas does not lose sight of the fact that any particular involuntarily
endured suffering is real suffering, lamentable, sorrowful, execrable, and to
be avoided or remedied if at all possible. But because Aquinas thinks that the
suffering for those able and willing to receive it as sanctifying contributes to
the best thing for human beings, he also thinks that there is something to
exult in as regards such suffering. So, for example, he says,
It is a sign of the ardent hope which we have on account of Christ that we glory not only
because of [our] hope of the glory to come, but we glory even regarding the evils which
we suffer for it. And so [Paul] says that we not only glory (that is, in our hope of glory),
but we glory even in tribulations, by which we attain to glory.43
the ultimate perfection, by which a person is made perfect inwardly, is joy, which stems
from the presence of what is loved. Whoever has the love of God, however, already has
what he loves, as is said in 1 John 4:16: “whoever abides in the love of God abides in
God, and God abides in him.” And joy wells up from this.46
When [Paul] says “the Lord is near,” he points out the cause of joy, because a person
rejoices at the nearness of his friend.47
Moreover, on Aquinas’s views, the joy that comes from such personal
presence between God and a human person is essential to a religious life of a
believer; and he expects that all persons of faith will have such joy.48 As
Aquinas sees it, without the joy of this relationship, no progress is possible
for anyone in the life of faith.49
Someone might object that suffering interferes with the joy of loving
relations and that Aquinas simply fails to appreciate this point. In response to
such an objection, Aquinas would grant that loving relationship even with the
deity does not prevent or take away suffering.50 On the other hand, however,
Aquinas would reject the objection itself. Aquinas thinks that no sort of
suffering, not even pain, can destroy the good of the loving personal
relationship between God and a human being open to God’s presence.51
[one reason why something is not known is that] it is obscured by being inside
something [else]. The things most obscured in this way are the things hidden in the
[human] heart, which is exceedingly deep and inscrutable.56
NOTES
1. The literature on Augustine’s reflections on goodness is vast; but see,
e.g., Christopher Kirwan, Augustine (London: Routledge, 1989) and G. R.
Evans, Augustine on Evil (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982)
for helpful introductions. For more recent discussion, see Norman Kretzmann
and Eleonore Stump, eds., The Cambridge Companion to Augustine
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001). For a good overview of the
problem in the context of medieval philosophical theology, see Ingolf
Dalferth, Malum: Theologische Hermeneutik des Bösen (Tübingen: Mohr
Siebeck, 2008).
2. For some further discussions of the issues in this section, see my “The
Problem of Evil,” in Robert Pasnau, ed., The Cambridge History of Later
Medieval Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009).
3. For a general discussion of this Augustinian position in later medieval
philosophy, see, e.g., Scott MacDonald, ed., Being and Goodness: The
Concept of the Good in Metaphysics and Philosophical Theology (Ithaca,
N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1991).
4. In this essay, I am limiting consideration not just to human suffering
but in fact to the suffering of normally functioning adult human beings. The
reasons for such a limitation on the description of Aquinas’s theodicy and the
possibility of extrapolating from that theodicy to other cases of suffering not
covered in it are explored in detail in my Wandering in Darkness: Narrative
and the Problem of Suffering (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010).
5. Augustine would also have found such a position unacceptable, in my
view. For a discussion of this issue, see my “The Problem of Evil,” in Robert
Pasnau, ed., The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009). Some parts of this entry are
taken from that essay.
6. In Rom 8.6.
7. In Aquinas’s terms, the point has to be put differently, of course; on the
doctrine of the Trinity, in medieval terms, there is one God in three persons.
But this is a technical sense of “person,” drawn from Boethius’s formulation:
a person is an individual substance of a rational nature. Nonetheless, the
technical sense as it is used in the doctrine of the Trinity is compatible with
the claim that God is a person, in our sense of the word “person.” There is
just one will and one intellect in the triune God, on the orthodox views
Aquinas accepts. Insofar as, in our sense of “person,” something having one
mind and one will is a person, it is true to say that for Aquinas God is a
person. Some readers will also want to object to the claim that for Aquinas
God has a will and a mind, on the grounds that for Aquinas God is simple
and therefore has no parts that can be distinguished from one another as mind
is distinguished from will. But although it is true that Aquinas’s God is
simple, Aquinas himself talks about the intellect and the will of God.
Formulating claims about God in order to bring the doctrine of simplicity to
the fore requires so much clumsiness in locution that Aquinas himself
regularly omits it. For defense of Aquinas’s views on simplicity, see the
relevant chapter in my Aquinas (London: Routledge, 2003).
8. For an explanation of Aquinas’s kind of libertarianism, see the chapter
on free will in my Aquinas.
9. There is more to hell than simply the loss of God’s presence, on
Aquinas’s views, because there is also penalty or punishment; but Aquinas
supposes that the loss of God’s presence is sufficient for hell.
10. For examination of Aquinas’s view that the union of love is possible
only in integration around goodness, see my “Love, By All Accounts,”
Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 80:2
(November 2006): 25–43.
11. For Aquinas’s position on the separated soul, see my entry in this
volume.
12. Because of the connection he accepts between the intellect and the will,
Aquinas thinks that there is no major change of heart possible after a person
has his first experience of the afterlife and sees whatever of God he can see.
For explanation of Aquinas’s moral psychology, see the chapters on freedom
and on wisdom in my Aquinas.
13. Aquinas supposes that there is no traffic between heaven and hell; that
is, no person who was really in heaven ever goes to hell, and no person who
was really in hell ever goes to heaven. (The qualifier “really” is needed to
handle some theological complexities, such as the harrowing of hell, which
are not relevant to the topic of this essay.) It is clear enough why the inability
to lose heaven would be essential to peace and joy in heaven. But it is less
easy to see why a person in hell could not repent and come to heaven. The
reasons Aquinas gives for his view that it is not possible have to do with his
understanding of the conditions needed for changing one’s mind. If he were
wrong on this score, the error would necessitate only a redescription of the
extrinsic lower limit of the scale of value for human flourishing.
14. Aquinas, In I Cor 15.2.
15. It is also the case that, for Aquinas, the extrinsic lower limit on
flourishing comes in degrees. The state of everlasting distance from God is a
degreed state too, on his views. As far as I can see, this part of his worldview
makes no significant difference to the lineaments of his theodicy, and so I am
leaving it out of account here, for the sake of keeping complications to a
minimum. But if in fact someone supposes that this part of Aquinas’s
worldview does make a difference to his theodicy, it can be added in at no
cost except that of complexity. In that case, the lower limit of flourishing
would have to be dealt with in the same way as the upper limit.
16. Cf., e.g., ST I-II q.112 a.4 ad 2, where Aquinas addresses the objection
that there cannot be greater or lesser grace in one person than in another,
either in this life or in heaven. In the reply to that objection, Aquinas makes
clear that there are differences of degree even, as he says, in final glory.
17. For further discussion of Aquinas’s position on God’s grace and its role
in human salvation, see the chapters on faith and on grace and free will in my
Aquinas.
18. Some readers will suppose that by speaking of a morally sufficient
reason for God to allow evil, one attributes moral obligations to God; and
they will resist such attribution. It is important to recognize that this position
is not entailed by a theodicy; a theodicy does not require anyone to posit
moral obligations for God. A morally sufficient reason for God to allow
suffering is only a reason which, by the moral standards of human beings
considering the problem of evil, is sufficient to justify God in our eyes for his
permission of human suffering.
19. In what follows, the discussion is limited to the suffering of fully
functional adult human beings, for the sake of brevity. For a consideration of
the reasons for this limitation and suggestions for ways in which Aquinas’s
basic theodicy as presented here might be extended, see my Wandering in
Darkness.
20. The point of the clumsy phrase “the sufferings of life” is, of course, to
exclude some sorts of partly voluntary suffering, such as the suffering
experienced by athletes or soldiers in the course of their activities as athletes
or soldiers.
21. For an annotated translation of the text, see Nicholas Ayo, The Sermon-
Conferences of St. Thomas Aquinas on the Apostles’ Creed (Notre Dame,
Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988). Although I have preferred to
use my own translation, I found Ayo’s helpful, and for this work I give
citations both to the Latin and to Ayo’s translation. Thomas Aquinas,
Collationes Credo in Deum, sec. III; Ayo, Sermon-Conferences, 40–42.
22. Of course, the same person might at one time not be a person of faith
and at another time might be a person of faith. So the benefit defeating
suffering has to be relativized not only to a person but also to the condition of
that person at a particular time.
23. Strictly speaking, this claim needs to be slightly qualified for reasons
having to do with the Incarnation.
24. Aquinas, Super ad Hebraeos, chap. 12, lect. 2.
25. To say that this is the only obstacle is not to say that a human being can
achieve this union on her own without help from God. But since, on
Aquinas’s views, the apostle Paul is correct in claiming that God desires to
save all human beings, the obstacle to union with God comes only from
human beings.
26. For discussion of these topics, see the relevant chapters in my Aquinas.
27. For the connection between this claim and Aquinas’s theory of the
atonement, see the chapters on faith and on atonement in my Aquinas.
28. For the role of grace in the formation of this act of will, see the chapter
on grace in my Aquinas.
29. For more discussion of justification, see the relevant chapters in my
Aquinas.
30. For a discussion of the sort of cooperation at issue here, see the
chapters on faith and on grace in my Aquinas.
31. For futher discussion of suffering as medicinal in the thought of
Thomas Aquinas, see the chapter on providence and suffering in my Aquinas.
32. There is a translation of this commentary: Commentary on Saint Paul’s
First Letter to the Thessalonians and the Letter to the Philippians by St.
Thomas Aquinas, trans. F. R. Larcher and Michael Duffy (Albany, N.Y.:
Magi Books, 1969). Although I have preferred to use my own translations, I
found the Larcher and Duffy translation helpful. Thomas Aquinas, Super ad
Thessalonicenses I, prologue; Larcher and Duffy, Commentary, 3.
33. Super ad Hebraeos, chap. 12, lect. 1.
34. Super ad Hebraeos, chap. 12, lect. 2.
35. Aquinas, Expositio super Job, chap. 1, sec. 20–21; Thomas Aquinas,
The Literal Exposition on Job: A Scriptural Commentary concerning
Providence, trans. Anthony Damico and Martin Yaffe, The American
Academy of Religion Classics in Religious Studies (Atlanta: Scholars Press,
1989), 89.
36. Aquinas, Expositio super Job, chap. 9, sec. 15–21; Damico and Yaffe,
Literal Exposition on Job, 174.
37. To say that it is medicinal for all sufferers is not to say that all sufferers
are justified and sanctified by it; not all things that are medicinal are
efficacious for cure.
38. Only one of the two metaphors is in the text translated in the Revised
Standard Version, the King James, and the Anchor Bible.
39. Aquinas, Expositio super Job, chap. 7, sec. 1; Damico and Yaffe,
Literal Exposition on Job, 146.
40. Super ad Hebraeos, chap. 12, lect. 2.
41. Aquinas, Super ad Thessalonicenses I, chap. 4, lect. 2; Larcher and
Duffy, Commentary, 39.
42. Aquinas, Super ad Philippenses, chap. 3, lect. 2; Larcher and Duffy,
Commentary, 102.
43. Aquinas, Super ad Romanos, chap. 5, lect. 1.
44. It is clear that there are degrees of such experience. For human beings
in this life, the religious experience of mystics no doubt is an upper bound.
At the lower bound, it is possible to receive something of the consolation of
God’s presence and love without recognizing it as such. The consolation of
love, and its opposites, need not operate at the level of full consciousness.
Perhaps it is possible even for a person who believes of himself that he is
alienated from God or an atheist to receive some kind of consolation from
God’s presence, provided that, contrary to what he believes of himself, he
has not closed God out entirely. There is a poignant description of such a
complicated psychic state in the autobiographical work, Grace Abounding to
the Chief of Sinners, by the seventeenth-century Puritan writer John Bunyan.
So perhaps there are people who believe of themselves that they have no
religious experiences but who are wrong in that claim.
45. The notable exception to this claim has to do with the dark night of the
soul, a complicated religious phenomenon that has to be left aside here.
46. There is an English translation of this work: Commentary on Saint
Paul’s Epistle to the Galatians by St. Thomas Aquinas, trans. F. R. Larcher
and Richard Murphy (Albany, N.Y.: Magi Books, 1966). Although I have
preferred to use my own translations, I found the Larcher and Murphy
translation helpful. Super ad Galatas, chap. 5, lect. 6; Larcher and Murphy,
Commentary, 179–80.
47. Super ad Philippenses, chap. 4, lect. 1; Larcher and Duffy,
Commentary, 113.
48. For Aquinas, joy is one of the fruits of the Holy Spirit, and it is the state
resulting from the gifts of the Holy Spirit that are necessary to salvation. See,
e.g., ST I-II q.70 a.3.
49. Super ad Philippenses, chap. 4, lect. 1; Larcher and Duffy,
Commentary, 112.
50. See, e.g., Aquinas’s interpretation of the suffering of Christ in his
commentary on the Gospel of John.
51. We ourselves share this view when it comes to relationships between
human persons. That is why we do not leave a person in pain to himself. We
suppose that there is some great consolation for him, which even pain cannot
take away, in having someone who loves him near him in his suffering.
52. As pointed out by William Rowe, in his classic formulation of the
argument from evil, it is also possible to rebut the argument from evil
effectively without a theodicy by employing on it what Rowe calls “the G. E.
Moore shift” (William Rowe, “The Problem of Evil and Some Varieties of
Atheism,” American Philosophical Quarterly 16 [1979]; reprinted in Daniel
Howard-Snyder, The Evidential Problem of Evil [Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 1996], 1–11). As Rowe explains it, the G. E. Moore shift
consists in taking as a premiss the negation of the conclusion of an
opponent’s argument and deriving as a conclusion the negation of one of the
premisses in the opponent’s argument. In the case of the argument from evil,
the G. E. Moore shift is a matter of taking as a premiss the existence of God
and concluding that there is a morally sufficient reason for God to allow evil.
This response to the argument from evil depends on some support for the
premiss that God exists, support which is not effectively undercut by the
problem of evil itself. The G. E. Moore shift has not received much attention
by contemporary philosophers because they suppose that support for the
premiss that God exists would have to come from arguments for the
existence of God, and few people now have much confidence that such
arguments can be adequately defended. So, e.g., Peter van Inwagen says that
a response of this sort to the argument from evil is “unappealing, at least if
‘reasons’ [for preferring the claim that God exists to the rival claim of
atheism] is taken to mean ‘arguments for the existence of God’ in the
traditional or philosophy-of-religion-text sense. Whatever the individual
merits or defects of those arguments, none of them but the ‘moral argument’
(and perhaps the ontological argument) purports to prove the existence of a
morally perfect being. And neither the moral argument nor the ontological
argument has many defenders these days” (Peter van Inwagen, “The Problem
of Evil, the Problem of Air, and the Problem of Silence,” in Daniel Howard-
Snyder, ed., The Evidential Argument from Evil [Bloomington: Indiana
University Press: 1996], 154). Even if none of the arguments for the
existence of God is successful, however, it might still be the case that for any
particular individual belief in God is rooted in religious experience or is in
some other way a properly basic belief. In that case, the G. E. Moore shift
would be an adequate response to the argument from evil for such a person.
On the other hand, even if it were successful, the G. E. Moore shift would not
obviate the usefulness of a theodicy, because a theodicy contributes an
explanation of evil, as the G. E. Moore shift does not.
53. Skeptical theism comes in different varieties, some considerably
different from or more complicated than the short description in the text here
indicates. For a good introduction to the varieties of skeptical theism and
objections to them, see Paul Draper, “The Skeptical Theist,” in Daniel
Howard-Snyder, ed., The Evidential Argument from Evil (Bloomington:
Indiana University Press, 1996), 175–92.
54. See, e.g., William Alston, “The Inductive Argument from Evil and the
Human Cognitive Condition”; Stephen Wykstra, “Rowe’s Noseeum
Arguments from Evil”; Peter van Inwagen, “The Problem of Evil, the
Problem of Air, and the Problem of Silence”; Paul Draper, “The Skeptical
Theist”; and Peter van Inwagen, “Reflections on the Chapters by Draper,
Russell, and Gale,” in Daniel Howard-Snyder, ed., The Evidential Argument
from Evil (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1996), 97–125, 126–50,
151–74, 175–92, 219–43, respectively.
55. Aquinas would agree with skeptical theism that a limited human mind
cannot comprehend the infinite mind of God. But Aquinas accepts the idea
that God can communicate his purposes to human beings through revelation.
So even if skeptical theism is right about what unaided human intellects can
understand, Aquinas would suppose that human intellects are not always
unaided.
56. Super ad Hebraeos, chap. 4, lect. 2.
57. I say “specific” in this context because, of course, Aquinas’s theodicy
provides a general answer which applies in an abstract way to every case of
human suffering.
58. I am grateful to Brian Davies for helpful comments on an earlier draft.
CHAPTER 30
THE TRINITY
GILLES EMERY
AQUINAS places the Trinity at the heart of the Christian faith: “The Christian
faith chiefly consists in confessing the holy Trinity.”1 The revelation of the
Trinity is thus of central importance: “To know the divine persons was
necessary for us for two reasons. First, in order to have a right view of the
creation of things … The other and principal reason is so that we may have
the right view of salvation of mankind, accomplished by the Son who
became flesh and by the gift of the Holy Spirit.”2 Faith in Christ intrinsically
implies faith in the Trinity.3 Final beatitude consists in the vision of the Holy
Trinity, and, “moreover, what brings us to beatitude is the mission of the
divine persons.”4 Aquinas’s account of Christian faith is Trinitarian in
nature.5 “The vision of the Father (visio Patris) is the end of all our desires
and actions.”6
NOTES
1. De rationibus fidei, c.1.
2. ST I q.32 a.1 ad 3. Translations of the ST are taken, with some
modifications, from: St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, ed. Thomas
Gilby and T. C. O’Brien, 60 vols. (London: Eyre and Spottiswoode; New
York: McGraw-Hill, 1964–73). Other translations are mine.
3. ST I-II q.2 a.8.
4. ST I-II q.2 a.8 ad 3; cf. Super Sent I, dist.1, q.2, a.2.
5. Jean-Pierre Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, vol. 2, Spiritual Master,
trans. Robert Royal (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America
Press, 2003), 23–224: “A Trinitarian Spirituality.” Most of the elements
outlined in the present contribution are developed at greater length (with a
bibliography) in Gilles Emery, The Trinitarian Theology of Saint Thomas
Aquinas, trans. Francesca Murphy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).
6. Aquinas, Super Johan, c.14, lect.3.
7. ST I q.32 a.1.
8. Hans Christian Schmidbaur, Personarum Trinitas: Die trinitarische
Gotteslehre des heiligen Thomas von Aquin (St. Ottilien: EOS Verlag, 1995).
9. Bonaventure, Super Sent I, dist.2, a.1, q.2; Opera omnia, vol. 1
(Quaracchi: Ed. Collegii S. Bonaventurae, 1882), 53–54. See Gilles Emery,
Trinity in Aquinas, 2d ed. (Naples, Fla.: Sapientia Press, 2006), 16–23.
10. Aquinas, Super Sent I, dist.2, q.1, a.4; cf. ST I q.32 a.1.
11. ST II-II q.1 a.5 ad 2.
12. QDP, q.9, a.5.
13. Gilles Emery, Trinity, Church, and the Human Person: Thomistic
Essays (Naples, Fla.: Sapientia Press, 2007), 1–72.
14. ST I q.32 a.1 obj. 2; QDP, q.9, a.5.
15. ST I q.2 prol.; cf. CT I, c.2.
16. ST I q.28 a.4.
17. Super Sent I, dist.13, q.1, a.1.
18. ST I q.27 a.5.
19. ST I q.27 a.1–4.
20. ST I q.28.
21. ST I q.29 a.4.
22. ST I q.39 a.1 ad 1.
23. QDP, q.8, a.2, ad 1.
24. Albert, Super Dionysium de divinis nominibus, c.2, §25–26; Opera
omnia (Cologne edition), vol. 37/1, ed. Paulus Simon (Münster: Aschendorff,
1972), 60. See also Albert, Super Sent I, dist.28, a.4; Opera omnia (Paris
edition), vol. 26, ed. Auguste Borgnet (Paris: Vivès, 1893), 59–61.
25. Bonaventure, Super Sent I, dist.26, a.1, q.3; Opera omnia, 1:456–58.
26. ST I q.40 a.2.
27. ST I q.40 a.3.
28. ST I q.33 a.3.
29. Bonaventure, Super Sent I, dist.27, pars 1, a.1, q.2, sol. and ad 3;
dist.28, a.1, q.2; dist.28, dubium 1; Opera omnia, 1:469–72, 499–500, and
504.
30. ST I q.33 a.4.
31. SCG I, c.53; QDP, q.8, a.1; Super Johan, c.1, lect.1.
32. SCG IV, c.11; ST I q.34 a.1–2.
33. ST I q.34 a.3.
34. In Rom, c.8, lect.6; ST III q.23. a.3.
35. ST I q.36–38.
36. ST I q.37 a.1–2; SCG IV, c.19.
37. ST I q.36 a.1.
38. ST I q.37 a.1; I-II q.28 a.2 resp. and ad 1.
39. ST I q.38 a.2.
40. ST I q.38 a.1.
41. SCG IV, c.20–22.
42. ST I q.37 a.2 ad 3.
43. ST I q.37 a.2.
44. ST I q.32 a.1; q.45 a.6.
45. ST I q.39 a.7–8.
46. Super Johan, c.1, lect.2; ST I q.39 a.8.
47. Emery, Trinity, Church, and the Human Person, 115–53.
48. ST I q.43; Super Sent I, dist.14–16.
49. ST I q.43 a.3.
50. Super Sent I, dist.14, q.2, a.1, quaestiunc.2; cf. ST I q.43 a.3 resp. and
ad 1.
51. ST I q.43 a.5 ad 2; Super Sent I, dist.15, q.4, a.1; In Rom, c.5, lect.1.
52. ST I q.93 a.5 and a.7–8.
53. QDV, q.10, a.7.
54. In II Cor, c.3, lect.3.
55. ST I q.43 a.7; cf. In Rom, c.1, lect.3.
56. See, for instance, Timothy L. Smith, Thomas Aquinas’ Trinitarian
Theology: A Study in Theological Method (Washington, D.C.: Catholic
University of America Press, 2003).
57. See, for instance, Matthew Levering, Scripture and Metaphysics:
Aquinas and the Renewal of Trinitarian Theology (Oxford: Blackwell, 2004);
Gilles Emery, “Theologia and Dispensatio: The Centrality of the Divine
Missions in St. Thomas’s Trinitarian Theology,” The Thomist 74 (2010):
515–61; Guillermo A. Juárez, Dios Trinidad en todas las creaturas y en los
santos: Estudio histórico-sistemático de la doctrina del Comentario a las
Sentencias de Santo Tomás de Aquino sobre la omnipresencia y la
inhabitación (Córdoba, Argentina: Ediciones del Copista, 2008). On the
person of the Father, see John Baptist Ku, “St. Thomas Aquinas’s Treatment
of the Name ‘Father’ in ST I, q. 33, a. 2,” Nova et Vetera 9 (2011): 433–78.
—I owe a special thanks to John Baptist Ku, O. P. who translated the present
chapter from French into English.
CHAPTER 31
INCARNATION
MICHAEL GORMAN
INTRODUCTION
According to Christian belief, Jesus Christ is a divine person who became
“incarnate,” that is, who became human. A key event in the second act of the
drama of creation and redemption, the incarnation could not have failed to
interest Aquinas, and he discusses it in a number of places. A proper
understanding of what he thought about it is thus part of any complete
understanding of his work. It is, furthermore, a window into his ideas on a
variety of other topics: God, human nature, language, substance, and so on.
Finally, it forces us to come to grips with what is at stake in acknowledging
that Aquinas was not only a philosopher but a theologian as well.
A DIFFICULT ISSUE
So far I have simply laid out some of the many claims that Aquinas makes
about the incarnation, without much attempt to indicate where difficulties
arise or how Aquinas might address them. In the remainder of this article, I
will focus by way of example on one difficult topic. The goal, besides
exploring more of Aquinas’s views, will be to provide an example of how
Thomas uses and adapts philosophical ideas in carrying out his Christological
investigations.
Let us begin by briefly stepping back from Christ’s humanity and talking
instead about Socrates’. Socrates’ human nature is a principle in virtue of
which he exists in a certain way, as an entity of a certain sort—namely, as a
human being.18 But it is not only for being an entity of a certain sort that he
is dependent on having a human nature—he is also dependent on having a
human nature for the simple fact that he exists at all, as an individual
substance or supposit of any sort.19 In other words, he depends on his human
nature not only for being such-and-such a sort of thing but also for what
Aquinas would call his “simple” or “absolute” existence. Without his
humanity, Socrates would not only fail to be human, he would fail to be
anything at all—he would simply not exist.20 Let us say henceforth that
Socrates’ human nature is not only a “humanizing” nature but also a
“supposit-supporting” nature.
Now is what is true of Socrates’ human nature true of every instance of
human nature? If we were to say “yes,” implying that Christ’s human nature
too is not only humanizing but also supposit-supporting, then we would run
into problems. Given that there is only one supposit in Christ and that this
supposit is the second person of the Trinity, we would be committed to
saying that Christ’s human nature is supposit-supporting for a divine
supposit, that is, that a divine supposit depends for its absolute existence on
being human. Obviously, Aquinas is not going to take this route.
So it seems necessary to answer “no,” that is, to say that there can be a
human nature that is humanizing but not supposit-supporting. And in fact this
is just what Aquinas holds: “On the basis of his human nature, the Son of
God does not exist absolutely … but only as a human being.”21 The person or
supposit of the Son of God is not supported by Christ’s human nature. His
humanity is a principle in virtue of which he is human, as well as divine, but
not a principle in virtue of which he exists as opposed to not existing at all.
Indeed, there is no supposit or person that depends for its absolute existence
on Christ’s humanity.
It might sound wrong to say that Christ’s humanity does not account for
the absolute existence of any supposit or person. Saying so seems to imply
that his human nature is somehow lacking in metaphysical dignity. Worse, it
might seem to imply a sheer impossibility, namely, that something could be a
human nature and yet not be that on which the absolute existence of a person
depends.22
Concerning the dignity of Christ’s human nature, Aquinas says that “it is
more dignified for something to exist in something else that is of greater
dignity than for it to exist through itself.”23 To forgo a lower role (being
responsible for the existence of a supposit) for the sake of a higher one (being
a constituent of a divine–human supposit) is no loss—in fact, it is gain.
Concerning the second and deeper worry, that is, the worry about whether
it is even possible for there to be a human nature that is humanizing but not
supposit-supporting, Aquinas clearly thinks that it is possible, so long as the
nature exists in some pre-existing supposit (it could not exist in no supposit
at all). His idea seems to be that it is not a necessary condition of something’s
being a human nature that it actually be a principle upon which a supposit
depends for its absolute existence—what is necessary is only that it be the
sort of reality to which it is natural to have a supposit thus dependent upon it.
This is still true of Christ’s human nature, even though it is not supposit-
supporting in actual fact.
The same point can be made from the complementary perspective, that of
the supposit rather than that of the nature. Everything that possesses a human
nature must have absolute existence as a supposit, that is, every human being
must be a supposit. But from this it does not follow that everything that
possesses a human nature must have absolute existence as a supposit in virtue
of possessing that nature. It might, as in Christ’s case, have it in virtue of
possessing some other nature. Before the Son became human, he was already
subsistent, already a supposit, and therefore becoming subsistent was not
possible for him. Christ’s human nature was given no opportunity to be
supposit-supporting; from the very first it existed only as a constituent of a
supposit that was, so to speak, already supported. But, of course, that does
not mean that Christ’s human nature does nothing—before the incarnation,
the Son was not human, and Christ’s human nature serves for him precisely
as a humanizing principle, a principle in virtue of which he is not only divine
but human as well. Although in the incarnation the Son does not come to be a
supposit or person, he does come to be human, to be corporeal and animate in
a fully and properly human way.
To say that there can be a human nature that is humanizing but not
supposit-supporting is certainly to deviate from the usual way of thinking.
Such a deviation might be looked upon as a valuable insight, or it might be
looked upon as a desperate ad hoc maneuver. Whether one thinks of it as
desperate or not depends, in large part, on whether one thinks it rational to
adopt Aquinas’s faith-based point of view in the first place. As for its being
ad hoc, however, there is a sense in which Aquinas would gladly agree: he is
explicit about the fact that the incarnation is a unique case, and so in a sense
an ad hoc solution is just what one should expect.24 As noted at the outset,
theology in Aquinas’s understanding must not only employ philosophical
notions but modify them when necessary.25
NOTES
1. Quodl 4, q.9, a.3, response.
2. See, e.g., ST I q.12 a.12–13.
3. For “essence” and other synonyms of “nature,” see, e.g., DEE, c.1.
4. See, e.g., Super Sent 3, d.5, q.1, a.2; SCG 4, c.35; QDP, q.9, a.1,
response; QDV, a.1; ST III q.2 a.1.
5. For helpful remarks on some of Aquinas’s views here, see Matthew J.
Kelly (1976), “‘Subject,’ ‘Substance,’ and ‘Accident’ in St. Thomas,” New
Scholasticism 50 (1976): 232–36. For a partial attempt to recapture the same
sort of approach in a contemporary framework, see Michael Gorman, “The
Essential and the Accidental,” Ratio 18 (2005): 276–89.
6. That last claim would need to be qualified in light of Aquinas’s
understanding of transubstantiation, but such concerns lie beyond the scope
of this chapter.
7. See Super Sent 3, d.5, q.1, a.3; Super Sent 3, d.6, q.1, a.1, qa.1,
response; QDP, q.9, a.1–2; DUI, a.1–2; ST I q.29 a.1–2; ST III q.2 a.2–3.
Lafont has laid stress on the fact that for Aquinas the divine persons are
subsisting relations (e.g., ST I q.28 a.2), and he thinks that the Boethian
notion of person as rational substance is not always adequate for
Christological purposes. The particular problems that Lafont is concerned
with are not at issue here, however, so the point will not be pursued further.
See Ghislain Lafont, Peut-on connaître Dieu en Jésus Christ? (Paris: Cerf,
1969), 107–57. For further complications, see John Wippel, The
Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas (Washington, D.C.: Catholic
University of America Press, 2000), 228–37.
8. ST III q.2 a.1–3; see also SCG 4, c.41; QDVUI, a.1–2.
9. A good discussion of Aquinas on Christ’s human nature from just this
perspective can be found in Marilyn McCord Adams, What Sort of Human
Nature? Medieval Philosophy and the Systematics of Christology
(Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1999), 49–68.
10. For an overview of Christ’s human knowledge, see ST III q.9. For
details on Christ’s possession of the beatific vision, see ST III q.10; for
details on his infused knowledge, see ST III q.11; for details on his acquired
knowledge, see ST III q.12.
11. See ST III q.9 a.2.
12. See ST III q.18–19.
13. ST III q.14 a.1; for more on Christ’s bodily defects, see the whole of ST
III q.14.
14. ST III q.15 a.4; for more on Christ’s sinlessness, see ST III q.15 a.1–2;
for physical pain, see ST III q.15 a.5; for sorrow, see ST III q.15, a.6.
15. For a sustained reflection on some of the linguistic issues concerning
the incarnation, and on the metaphysical issues that lie behind them, see
Henk J. M. Schoot, Christ the “Name” of God: Thomas Aquinas on Naming
Christ (Leuven: Peeters, 1993).
16. ST III q.19 a.1 ad 5; see also ST III q.18 a.1 ad 2.
17. See ST III q.16.
18. See, e.g., DEE, c.1.
19. See, e.g., QDVUI, a.4.
20. Here it is worth comparing Socrates’ humanity with one of his
accidental forms: in virtue of his whiteness, Socrates is the sort of thing that
is white, but he does not depend on his whiteness for his absolute existence
(cf. QDVUI, a.4).
21. “Non enim ex natura humana habet Filius Dei quod sit simpliciter …
sed solum quod sit homo” (ST III q.3 a.1 ad 3), my translation. See also
Super Sent 3, d.6, q.1, a.1, qa.4, ad 1. QDVUI, a.1, ad 15, as it appears in the
Marietti edition, seems to undermine or even contradict the idea that Christ is
humanized by his human nature, but the text of that edition is flawed there:
see Michael Gorman, “Christ as Composite according to Aquinas,” Traditio
55 (2000): 143–57, at 150 n.12. For a few more relevant passages, not all of
them easy to interpret, see Super Sent 3, d.10, q.1, a.2, qa.1, ad 1–2; Super
Sent 3, d.10, q.1, a.2, qa.2, ad 1; Super Sent 3, d.12, q.1, a.1, ad 2; ST III q.2
a.2 ad 2; ST III q.2 a.3 ad 3; ST III q.16 a.6 ad 1; ST III, q.16 a.12 resp. and
ad 1.
22. Here it is worth mentioning a distinct but related problem. According to
Aquinas’s canonical way of speaking, a human nature is but one principle of
a human being, and human beings are not identical to their natures. From this
perspective it makes sense to consider the possibility that Christ’s human
nature is unique inasmuch as it fails to support a human supposit, but it does
not make sense to consider the possibility that Christ’s human nature is
unique inasmuch as it fails to be a human supposit—such is true of every
human nature. But there is another way of using the expression “human
nature,” also found in Aquinas, in accordance with which it might indeed
make sense to say that ordinary human natures are human persons but that
Christ’s human nature, uniquely, is not. If we did say that, then we would
face the analogous difficulty of explaining how it could be true at all, and
how it could be true without Christ’s human nature being inadequate in some
way. For discussion, see, e.g., Othmar Schweizer, Person und Hypostatische
Union bei Thomas von Aquin (Freiburg [Schweiz]: Universitätsverlag, 1957);
Michael Gorman, “Uses of the Person–Nature Distinction in Thomas’s
Christology,” Recherches de théologie et philosophie médiévales 67 (2000):
58–79; Richard Cross, The Metaphysics of the Hypostatic Union (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2002), 246–56; Eleonore Stump, Aquinas (London
and New York: Routledge, 2003), 409–10. Although I do not think that
Aquinas’s views on this problem have yet received a fully adequate
interpretation, I do think it safe to say that the right path is the one laid out by
Schweizer and Stump.
23. “Dignius autem est alicui quod existat in aliquo se digniori, quam quod
existat per se” (ST III q.2 a.2 ad 2), my translation.
24. For example, in QDVUI, a.3, response, Aquinas notes that in the case
of the Trinity there is one nature with three supposits, and in the case of the
incarnation two natures with only one supposit, but that in every other case,
the correspondence between natures and supposits is one-to-one. See also ST
III q.2 a.6 ad 1, where Aquinas quotes John Damascene to the effect that the
incarnation is not wholly like anything else.
25. I would like to thank Anne-Marie Gorman and Thomas Weinandy for
helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper.
CHAPTER 32
INTRODUCTION
How we have been saved in Christ is undoubtedly one of the most central
questions for any Christian theologian, and it is not any different with
Aquinas.1 In recent years Aquinas’s soteriology has not enjoyed the same
attention as his theology of the Trinity, or his virtue ethics. Nevertheless, in
my view Aquinas’s soteriology deserves more consideration, not only
because it is a fairly sophisticated one, central to all his theological
endeavors, but also because it differs rather considerably in inspiration,
presuppositions, and issues it addresses from those of modern-day
theologians. It is exactly because of these differences (which often evoke
criticism) that it can begin to challenge us at a more fundamental level.
Theologians of a liberal mindset, for instance, may want to question a
soteriology that (allegedly) attributes saving significance to the innocent
suffering of Jesus of Nazareth. It has been argued that the Anselmic theory of
satisfaction that Aquinas adopts (with modifications) comes dangerously
close to turning God into a vindictive, punitive God who needs a bloody
sacrifice before he becomes reconciled with this sinful world. The theory of
satisfaction, so it is further alleged, is legalistic, transactional, more indebted
to feudal categories than to the Scriptures, and effectively glorifies innocent
suffering, instead of providing us with resources to challenge it. In this vein
E. Schillebeeckx has famously argued that we have been saved “despite the
Cross.”2 He writes, “Many existing theories of our redemption through Jesus
Christ deprive Jesus, his message and career of their subversive power, and
even worse, sacralize violence to be a reality within God. God is said to call
for a bloody sacrifice which stills or calms his sense of justice.”3 I will argue
that Aquinas is very much aware of the concerns that Schillebeeckx raises
and is perfectly capable of dealing with them.4 Moreover, I am in little doubt
that Aquinas would be ill at ease with the disturbingly unscriptural stance
that is implied in Schillebeeckx’s disparagement of the Cross as the central
event in Christian salvation.
Other theologians, such as J. Moltmann, have developed an influential and
popular theology of suffering that does pay attention to the Cross as the
supreme saving event but rather than interpreting it in terms of a salvation
from evil it is interpreted in terms of a salvation from suffering: in the Cross
God suffers and dies for us, and this is the only viable theodicy that can meet
the challenges of the atheist critique.5 Now Aquinas is perfectly happy to
state that God suffers and dies for us on the Cross in the humanity of the
incarnate Word—but unlike Moltmann he explicitly rejects the view that this
suffering and death can be attributed to the divinity: “The Lord of glory is
said to be crucified, not as the Lord of glory, but as a man capable of
suffering.”6 This traditional view, which Aquinas represents here, does not
go far enough for Moltmann who criticizes it (erroneously in my view) on
the grounds that this emphasis upon the impassibility of God is due to the
influence of Aristotelian philosophy (the unmoved mover). Now Moltmann’s
theopaschite theology has, in turn, come in for a sharp critique from a
number of thinkers who argue that a suffering God may perhaps give us
some psychological solace—we are not alone in our suffering—but from a
mature religious point of view it will not do: if even God is subject to
suffering and in need of salvation there is no hope left. That is not to say that
the issue of suffering is not relevant to Aquinas; but he approaches it by
focusing our attention on the God-man, the Word-become-human, as I hope
to show in this contribution, and not on the intratrinitarian life, as Moltmann
does.7
In what follows I will outline Aquinas’s soteriology by examining the
following themes: the saving significance of the Passion of Christ, the Body
of Christ, and the role of the Eucharist. Given the systemic nature of
Aquinas’s theological enterprise, these themes are deeply interwoven with
one another.
If God had decided to restore man solely by an act of His will and power, the order of
divine justice would not have been observed. Justice demands satisfaction for sin. But
God cannot render satisfaction, just as he cannot merit. Such a service pertains to one
who is subject to another. Thus God was not in a position to satisfy for the sin of the
whole of human nature; and a mere man was unable to do so.… Hence divine Wisdom
judged it fitting that God should become man, so that thus one and the same person
would be able both to restore man and to offer satisfaction.19
While the onus was on humanity to restore the relationship with God, we
could not do so, infected as we are by sin. Therefore, it was necessary that
somebody who was both human and divine (and thus sinless) would restore
this relationship (i.e., make satisfaction). I would like to make a number of
comments.
First, it is a gross misreading to understand “making satisfaction” in terms
of retribution and punishment. Aquinas repeatedly points out that there are
two major differences between punishment and making satisfaction. The first
difference is that punishment is inflicted upon the sinner against his will,
while making satisfaction is something we freely undertake to restore a
broken relationship with somebody: grieving for the offence we committed
we are anxious to become reconciled with, or make satisfaction to, our
friend.20 Hence, for Aquinas, as for Anselm, satisfaction excludes
punishment. Incidentally, the language of friendship Aquinas uses here
suggests a personalist rather than a judicial or legalistic paradigm for
understanding salvation. This is further confirmed by the link between the
satisfaction Christ makes on the Cross, and the sacrament of penance.21
Given the fact that penance is described as “a spiritual healing of a sort”22 or
as “a spiritual medicine”23 and that sin is called “a sickness of the soul”
(infirmitas animae),24 it is clear that “making satisfaction” too should be
understood in medicinal terms. It comes therefore as no surprise to find that
Aquinas describes Christ as a doctor.25 These metaphors reveal, of course, a
world of difference: whereas a judge punishes, a doctor heals.
The second major difference between punishment and making satisfaction
is that one person can make satisfaction for another if the two are united in
charity.26 By drawing on the Pauline notion of the Church as the mystical
Body of Christ,27 Aquinas argues that Christ’s saving activity benefits all the
faithful. I will come back to this important point in the next section.
Some readers might perhaps be wondering whether Aquinas’s soteriology
is not excessively subjectivist: has the Cross actually made an objective
difference in the world? Undoubtedly, Aquinas puts a very strong emphasis
upon our need to somehow “appropriate” the saving work of Christ: Christ’s
Passion, which is a kind of universal cause of merit and of the forgiveness of
sins, still needs to be applied to each individual for the cleansing of personal
sins.28 Similarly, as a doctor prepares a medicine, we still need to apply it
through faith, love, and the sacraments of the Church.29 However, although
there is undoubtedly a strong personalist or subjectivist element to Aquinas’s
soteriology, this should not be taken to imply that the saving work of Christ
has nothing to do with the restoration of justice in “objective” terms. The
order of the world, as created by God, was distorted by sin. This needs to be
rectified, and if it had not been for Christ’s saving work this distortion and
alienation would have been perpetuated indefinitely (an alienation that would
involve, according to Aquinas, the punishments of hell). In that sense there is
something “objectively” changed in the world in that the disorder that sin has
caused is being rectified through the redeeming and meritorious work of
Christ. Sin cannot have the last word: it needs to be cancelled out by the
overarching mercy of God.
This restoration of the order of justice in the world should not be taken to
mean, as is sometimes alleged, that God somehow subjects his mercy to his
justice in the redemptive work of Christ. In agreement with Anselm, Aquinas
argues that in the divine self-gift that is the life and death of Christ the divine
mercy and justice are in perfect harmony with one another.30 Also, when I
speak of an “objective” dimension of Aquinas’s soteriology, I mean that
something is changed in the world—not in God. Aquinas, like other medieval
theologians before him, rejects the view that God is somehow “changed” by
the life and death of Christ:31 the Cross is the expression and manifestation of
God’s love, not the cause of it.32
But some readers might still share Schillebeeckx’s reservations: is it
appropriate to attribute saving significance to the suffering of an innocent
man? Should we not see the Cross for what it is: a horrible crime inflicted
upon a defenceless victim, rather than the way in which God reconciles the
world? Aquinas, however, argues that this is a false dilemma. Given his
understanding of providential care and divine causality, which implies that
God is such a powerful efficacious Cause that he can attain his goals by
genuinely contingent events,33 Aquinas suggests that it is not incoherent to
state that the slaying of Christ was a most grievous sin, and yet in accordance
—on a more transcendent level, if you like—with God’s providential plan.34
Of course, God could have forgiven us without Christ’s saving work, but
this would have been less “fitting.”35 Examining the reasons why this is the
case reveals a lot about how much Aquinas values human dignity and the
reciprocity of the relationship between humanity and God: if we had simply
been forgiven by a divine fiat, we would not have been allowed to
participate, through Christ and in union with him (as members of his Body),
in the restoration of our relationship with God (i.e., making satisfaction).36
But what exactly is the source of merit in Christ’s saving work? It is not
his sufferings as such but rather what these sufferings reveal: his obedience
and love. Thus, not the sufferings per se but the willingness with which
Christ took them upon himself are a source of merit that can be shared with
all the faithful.37 The emphasis upon the voluntary nature of Christ’s saving
activity allows Aquinas to state in ST that making satisfaction needs to be
understood in terms of a gift of self by Christ (Christus autem satisfecit …
dando … seipsum).38 This is an important observation for two reasons: first,
because, again, it dispels the specter of a revengeful God and instead reveals
a self-giving God;39 second, because this teaches us something about the way
we should approach our own afflictions: we should refrain from attributing
any intrinsic value to them as such; rather, if borne with obedience and love,
they can become an occasion for us to become more Christ-like. I will come
back to this in the next section.
In summary, Aquinas adopts the notion of making satisfaction to explain
how Christ, as the God-man, restores a broken relationship between
humanity and God: while the onus to restore the relationship was on
humanity (as we were the guilty party), only God, as the sinless source of all
merit, could make satisfaction for the whole human race.40 As I tried to make
clear, this theory should not be construed in legalistic or penal terms. Nor
should it be construed in terms of substitution. To explain why this is the
case we need to examine in more detail the theme of our participation in
Christ’s redemptive work as members of his Body.
For since He is our head, then, by the Passion which he endured from love and
obedience, He delivered us as his members from our sins, as by the price of his Passion:
in the same way as if a man by the good industry of his hands were to redeem himself
from a sin committed with his feet. For, just as the natural body is one, though made up
of diverse members, so the whole Church, Christ’s mystic body (mysticum corpus
Christi), is reckoned as one person with its head, which is Christ.42
This does not simply mean that Christ is in union with us; it also means
that we are in union with Christ. Thus, it is not just the case that Christ
suffers for us; but also: our own sufferings can be seen as a sharing in those
of Christ. Commenting on John 20:21, Aquinas writes: “He [= Christ] says
As the Father has sent me, so too I sent you, which means: as the Father who
loves me has sent me in the world to suffer the Passion for the salvation of
the faithful … so too I love you, and I send you to endure tribulations for my
sake.”43 The view that our own sufferings are a way of becoming more
Christ-like was a prominent theme amongst the early Church Fathers.
Augustine, for instance, had put it at the heart of his Exposition on the
Psalms and had actually stated in this work44 that the risen Christ himself
continues to suffer in the members of his Body, the Church.45 Aquinas does
not make such a radical statement, and it is revealing that he hardly ever
refers to the crucial text, Colossians 1:24, which at first sight seems to
suggest that the sufferings of Christ are somehow deficient and need to be
completed in the faithful.46 Thus, although he does not go as far as stating
that the risen Christ continues to suffer in his members, Aquinas does adopt
the notion that our sufferings can be interpreted as a means of growing in
conformity with Christ. In SCG, for instance, when dealing with the
objection that it seems odd to claim that Christ saved us while death and
other penalties are still with us,47 he writes that the afflictions that remain
allow us to achieve conformity to Christ as members to the head:
It was both fitting and useful to have the penalty remain even when the fault was taken
away. First, indeed, to achieve conformity of the faithful to Christ as members to the
head; hence, just as Christ bore many sufferings, and thus arrived at the glory of
immortality, it was also becoming to his faithful first to undergo sufferings and so to
arrive at immortality, bearing in themselves, so to say, the marks of the passion of
Christ, in order to achieve likeness to his glory. So the Apostle says: “Heirs, indeed of
God, and joint-heirs with Christ: yet so, if we suffer with him, that we might also be
glorified with him” (Rom 8:17).48
Thus, Christ does not take away our afflictions here and now. Rather, we
should regard our continuing afflictions as a way of sharing in his saving
work, as a way of becoming more Christ-like.49 Although Aquinas does not
share the view that the risen Christ continues to suffer in the members of his
Body, he does make room for the notion that Christ’s saving work continues
for all eternity. He does so by developing the idea of Christ’s eternal
priesthood and by pointing out the significance of the sacramental
economy.50
because this sacrament is that of the Passion of our Lord, it contains within itself the
suffering of Christ; therefore, all the beneficiary effects of the Passion of our Lord reside
plentifully in this sacrament. This sacrament is nothing else but the Passion of our Lord
that is communicated to us.… The destruction of death that Christ has effected by his
death and the renewal of life that he effected through his resurrection are also the effects
of this sacrament.67
Commenting on John 6:54, Aquinas states that through the Eucharistic food
we become Christ-like; it is the Eucharistic food that transforms us into
Christ, makes us members of his Body, deifies us, and inebriates us with the
divinity.68 Because the Word resides in this sacrament according to his
divinity and his humanity, it is the cause of our spiritual and bodily
resurrection.69
CONCLUSION
This is a balanced and beautiful soteriology, utterly faithful to the biblical
witness; it does justice to the reality of sin, the need to tackle the disorder it
causes, and the overwhelming mercy of God. Given the sacramental
understanding of Christ, it is Aquinas’s view that every aspect of Christ’s
life, death, and resurrection has saving meaning. The salvation that Christ
effected, particularly through his redeeming death, continues to reside in the
sacraments, especially in the Lord’s Supper, through which the Church is
established as one Body. This notion of the Church as the Body of Christ is
pivotal in everything that Aquinas has to say about how we appropriate the
salvation Christ accomplished. This suggests the organic unity of Aquinas’s
“theory” of Christ’s saving activity, and his sacramentology. But perhaps we
should not call Aquinas’s soteriology a “theory” of salvation, for it is much
more than that. It offers us spiritual guidance as to how we should live and
die in Christ.
NOTES
1. I developed some of the ideas in this chapter elsewhere, such as in
“‘Bearing the Marks of Christ’s Passion’—Aquinas’ Soteriology,” in Rik
Van Nieuwenhove and Joseph Wawrykow, eds., The Theology of Thomas
Aquinas (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 2005), 277–
302; and Rik Van Nieuwenhove, “St Anselm and St Thomas Aquinas on
‘Satisfaction’: Or How Catholic and Protestant Understandings of the Cross
Differ,” Angelicum 80 (2003): 159–76.
2. Edward Schillebeeckx, Christ: The Christian Experience in the Modern
World (London: SCM, 1980), 729.
3. Edward Schillebeeckx, The Church: The Human Story of God (London:
SCM, 1990), 125.
4. For instance, in SCG IV, 53.16, we find the objection that it seems
“impious and cruel to command an innocent to be led to death, especially on
behalf of the impious who are worthy of death. But the man Christ Jesus was
innocent. Therefore it would have been impious if at the command of God
the Father He had undergone death.” In Saint Thomas Aquinas, Summa
contra Gentiles, Book Four: Salvation, trans. Charles O’Neil (Notre Dame,
Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1975), 226. For a reply, see SCG IV,
55.18–19; ST III q.47 a.3 ad 1 and III q. 47 a.4 ad 2.
5. See Jürgen Moltmann, The Crucified God (London: SCM, 1976), esp.
ch. 6.
6. All translations from ST are from the Benzinger edition, St Thomas
Aquinas, Summa Theologica, trans. Fathers of the English Dominican
Province (Westminster, Md.: Christian Classics, 1981). ST III q.46 a.12 ad 1.
7. For an excellent critique of Moltmann’s theology, see Thomas
Weinandy, Does God Suffer? (Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 2000).
8. CT I, 227–28.
9. We do not find the expression in either the SCG or ST.
10. See ST III q.19 a.1.
11. I deliberately write that every aspect of Christ’s life has sacramental
“meaning and power” because for Aquinas causation and signification are
not opposed but mutually enrich one another. This is important to keep in
mind as some recent critics (such as L.-M. Chauvet) have artificially played
out a supposedly more “existentialist” signification against a supposedly
more “metaphysical” causation, preferring the first to the second.
Unfortunately, this runs the risk of reducing God’s sacramental power to our
understanding or experience of it. For a more in-depth discussion of this
issue, see Liam Walsh’s searching contribution on the “Sacraments” in Rik
Van Nieuwenhove and Joseph Wawrykow, eds., The Theology of Thomas
Aquinas (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 2005), 326–64,
esp. 329–30.
12. In Rom 4:25, no. 380. My translation from the Marietti edition.
13. ST III q.48 a.6; see also ST III q.49 a.1.
14. ST III q.66 a.2.
15. In Rom 6:11, no. 491.
16. Within the confines of this contribution I cannot develop Aquinas’s
theology of the resurrection. For this, see Van Nieuwenhove, “‘Bearing the
Marks of Christ’s Passion,’” esp. 294–95.
17. In ST III q.48, Aquinas describes how the Passion of Christ effects our
salvation by way of merit, by way of making satisfaction, by way of
sacrifice, and by way of redemption.
18. I have dealt with this in Van Nieuwenhove, “St Anselm and St Thomas
Aquinas on ‘Satisfaction,’” 169–70.
19. CT I, 200, in The Light of Faith: The Compendium of Theology, trans.
by C. Vollert (Manchester: Sophia Institute Press, 1993), 229–30. See also
SCG IV, 54.9 and ST III q.48 a.2.
20. Cf. ST III q.85 a.3 ad 3 and ST III q.84 a.5 ad 2. Some editions (such as
the Editio Altera Romana, 1894) have “et quod amico homo studeat
satisfacere”; others have “et quod amico homo reconciliari studeat.”
21. Cf. SCG IV, 72.14. The sacrament of penance consists of three
elements: confession, contrition, and making satisfaction (see SCG IV, 72). It
is only the element of making satisfaction (satisfactio) that applies to Christ’s
redemptive activity through the union with his members (see ST III q.48 a.2
ad 1).
22. SCG IV, 72.1.
23. ST III q.84 a.10 ad 5.
24. ST I-II q.88 a.1.
25. In ST III q.49 a.1 ad 3.
26. SCG III, 158, 7 and ST III q.48 a.2 ad 1.
27. ST III q.49 a.1; III q.48 a.2 ad 1.
28. ST III q.49 a.1 ad 4.
29. Cf. ST III q.49 a.1 ad 3; ST III q.49 a.3 ad 1.
30. ST III q.46 a.1 ad 3.
31. Cf. ST III q.1 a.1 ad 1.
32. ST III q.49 a.4 ad 2.
33. Cf. ST I q.19 a.8; SCG III, 72.
34. Cf. ST III q.47 a.4 ad 2; ST III q.47 a.3 ad 1.
35. Cf. ST III q.46 a.1 and a.3.
36. Cf. SCG IV, 54.8.
37. See ST III q.48 a.1; SCG IV, 55, 25–26.
38. ST III q.48 a.4.
39. Cf. In Rom 5:8–9, no. 399.
40. SCG IV, 54, 9.
41. ST III q.48 a.2 ad 1; see also ST III q.8 a.1 and a.3.
42. In ST III q.49 a.1.
43. Super Johan, no. 2527, my trans.
44. Augustine, Expos. on the Psalms, 62, 2.
45. See Ennerationes in Psalmos 62, 2, in Exposition on the Psalms, vol. 3,
trans. Maria Boulding (New York: New City Press, 2001), 230–31: “This
solidarity [between the Head and the Body] meant that when Christ suffered,
we suffered in him; and it follows that now that he has ascended into heaven,
and is seated at the right hand, he still undergoes in the person of his Church
whatever it may suffer amid the troubles of this world.” See Rik Van
Nieuwenhove, “The Christian Response to Suffering, and the Significance of
the Model of the Church as Body of Christ,” Angelicum 82 (2005): 605ff.
46. He refers to the text only twice outside the Commentary on Colossians
itself (no. 61), namely in ST III q.48 a.5 obj. 3 and in In I Cor 1:13, no. 32. In
each case he points out that the Passion of Christ is the sole cause of our
salvation and that the sufferings of the saints do not have any redemptive but
only an exemplary value.
47. SCG IV, 55.28.
48. Summa contra Gentiles, trans. by O’Neil, 245.
49. Cf. ST III q.49 a.3 ad 3; ST III q.79 a.2 ad 1; ST I-II q.85 a.5 ad 2; ST III
q.56 a.1 ad 1; In Rom 8:17, no. 651.
50. “Sacramental economy” refers to the communication (esp. through the
sacraments) of the fruits of Christ’s paschal mystery into our world.
51. Cf. ST III q.48 a.3.
52. Cf. ST III q.83 a.1; but also ST III q.63 a.6 ad 1.
53. ST III q.22 a.2; III q.48 a.3 obj. 2; III q.60 a.1; II-II q.81 a.7 ad 2.
54. Cf. In Rom 12:1–2, nos. 957–67; ST II-II q.85 a.2; ST II-II q.85 a.3 ad
2; Lectura super Epistolam Pauli ad Ephesos 5:2, no. 270.
55. ST III q.73 a.5 ad 2.
56. ST III q.83 a.1.
57. ST III q.22 a.2.
58. Sacerdos [priest] is derived from sacra dans, to give sacred things, as
Aquinas explains in ST III q.22 a.1.
59. ST III q.22 a.1. Christ’s priesthood fulfils the priesthood of the OT in its
threefold aspect, namely as offerings for sins, peace offerings, and burnt
offerings (ST III q.22 a.2). For an illuminating discussion as to how Christ
fulfils the hopes of Israel, see Matthew Levering, Christ’s Fulfillment of
Torah and Temple: Salvation according to Aquinas (Notre Dame, Ind.:
University of Notre Dame, 2002).
60. For instance, in ST III q.22 a.1, we find that Christ in his role as priest
is the mediator who “offers up the people’s prayers to God, and, in a manner,
makes satisfaction to God for their sins” (et pro eorum peccatis Deo
aliqualiter satisfacit). Similarly, ST III q.22 a.3.
61. ST III q.82 a.1 ad 2.
62. See the brilliant contribution by Gilles Emery, “Le Sacerdoce spirituel
des fidèles chez Saint Thomas d’Aquin,” Revue Thomiste 99 (1999): 211–43.
63. ST III q.22 a.5.
64. ST III q.54 a.4.
65. ST III q.73 a.4.
66. Aquinas states that the sacrifice that is offered every day in the Church
is not distinct from that which Christ himself offered, but is a
commemoration (commemoratio) of it (ST III q.22 a.3 ad 2). It is clear from
his stance on the Real Presence of Christ in the Eucharistic Bread and Wine
that “commemoration” should not be misunderstood in terms of mere
remembrance.
67. Super Johan, no. 963. My translation. A similar view can be found in
ST III q.73 a.5 ad 2: “The Eucharist is the perfect sacrament of our Lord’s
Passion, as containing Christ crucified.”
68. Super Johan, no. 972.
69. Super Johan, no. 972–73.
CHAPTER 33
SACRAMENTS
IT is an ancient, and some would say original, conviction of the Church that
the redemption won in the deeds, sufferings, and glorification of Jesus Christ
is communicated to the Christian faithful in the enacting of certain ritual
practices understood in some sense to have been instituted by Jesus Christ
himself. Said differently, the universal tradition of the Church has attributed
to what have been called the sacraments or mysteries the role in Christian life
of making manifest and effective here and now the universal salvation
effected by the Word made flesh. Thomas Aquinas is no different in this
regard, nor does he intend to be. He recognizes as sacraments instituted by
Christ those rites so recognized by the Latin Church in the thirteenth century:
above all Baptism and Eucharist, but also Confirmation, Penance, Extreme
Unction, Order, and Matrimony.
SACRAMENTS AS WORSHIP
Aquinas understands worship, and not simply the internal love shown in
mind and will of a rational creature to its Creator but also the use of material
objects, words, and bodily gestures, to be a natural obligation of all human
beings.1 As a matter of justice, creatures must honor their Creator, even as
children must honor their parents and citizens their city and must also do so
in ways proper to their nature.2 Furthermore, to succeed at its task, any
human religion must include means of designating those who are able to
perform the rites, those who may benefit from them, as well as a means to
restore to right relationship those who have been rendered unfit for worship,
whether unfit to minister or to receive the blessings of ministry.3 That is,
worship, for Aquinas, while at heart directed to God, nonetheless requires the
constitution of a people rightly ordered to one another and to God. As with
many other features of the natural law, the specifics of such natural worship
are not, on Aquinas’s view, necessary, and there are many ways by which a
human creature might rightly devise rites, prayers, festivals, and sacrifices to
fulfill the natural obligation of worship.
However, the worship that derives from a human response to the natural
law will necessarily fall short of its goal. In part, this is because of the effects
of sin on human knowledge and desire. Being subject to the corruption of sin,
knowledge of God is dimmed and the authentic desire to be rightly related to
God is bent, and thus human persons will misconceive not only God’s nature
but also the kind of worship pleasing to him. This false worship will in turn
orient the worshippers either to nothing at all or to some other being
unworthy of divine worship. Moreover, even the best rites of natural worship
will fail to bring the believer to God precisely because, as natural activities,
they are insufficient for their end, which is supernatural. This, Aquinas holds,
is the reason God both revealed the rites of the Tabernacle and Temple for
the Old Covenant and the sacraments of faith for the New. Since the worship
of God found in the Old and New Covenant directs the believer to God as to
a supernatural end, an end that exceeds all unaided human efforts both to
know fully and to achieve, no natural worship originating from human
ingenuity will as such succeed.4 In addition, for such worship to be not
merely rightly oriented but also succeed in accomplishing what it promises,
that is to draw the worshipper into the mystery of the divine interpersonal
communion that is God himself, it must be in important ways an act of God
himself, since only a divine act is proportionate to a divine end. It is uniquely
that worship of God offered by the God-man, the Word Incarnate, Jesus
Christ, through all of his theandric acts and experiences, but most especially
in his death on the Cross,5 that succeeds at being worship in spirit and in
truth, the reasonable or spiritual worship of the New Covenant. Indeed, it is
only insofar as the worship of the Church is the worship of Christ himself,
the acts of his body of which he is the head, and only insofar as the prayer of
the Church is the prayer of the Holy Spirit, that the rites of the Church are
acceptable as true worship and effective for directing and bringing the
believer to eternal life.
SACRAMENTS AS SIGNS
Aquinas is rightly credited with asserting that the sacraments are better
understood as signs than as causes, and that even as causes, they have their
effect by means of their signifying.6 Of course, to see the sacraments as signs
is nothing new of itself. The earliest discussions of the Christian sacraments
distinguished between what was seen and touched, the words spoken and the
rites performed, on the one hand, and the sacred reality imparted, on the other
hand. In Aquinas’s day, the distinction between sign (sacramentum) and
reality (res) was well established. Moreover, the response in the eleventh
century to the sacramental teachings of Berengar of Tours and subsequent
developments in the twelfth century equipped Aquinas with a threefold way
of discussing the sacraments.7 In every sacrament, there is something that is
only a sign, the dynamic ritual action by members of the faithful rightly
constituted as recipients and dispensers of God’s grace in the Church
(sacramentum tantum), that which is both sign and signified reality, the
healing and sanctifying work of Christ applied to the recipient here and now
(res et sacramentum), and that which is only a signified reality, that ultimate
possession of the reality, inaugurated and experienced in part through the
sacrament, but of which the effect here and now is only a foretaste and a
pledge (res tantum).
The purpose of this analysis of the sacraments is meant to do justice to the
fullness of the sacramental teaching that Aquinas has inherited from the early
centuries of the Church. Aquinas, like other Christians, holds that there is
more to Baptism, for example, than getting someone wet, more to Eucharist
than what appears to the eye and taste as bread and wine, more to penance
than comforting words and admirable or ascetical deeds, and yet that these
ritual actions disclose important features of that reality which they impart.
Yet, while early and Medieval Christians asserted that these human rites had
divine effects, they also accepted that the effect, the reality associated with
each did not always obtain. Not everyone baptized in fact remains dead to
sin. Not all who share in the Eucharist maintain that union of charity in
which the Body of Christ consists, and so on. By the twelfth century in the
Latin West, the threefold schema of sacramental language was thus a means
of upholding all three aspects of this common and ancient wisdom, that not
all the sacraments promise is true here and now, nor perhaps even in the
future, but that no sacrament rightly enacted goes without a real effect.
At the same time, the signification that is true of the sacraments is true
also of other ritual activity that does not pretend to have a direct spiritual,
which is to say supernatural, effect. There is, in other words, a broader way
to speak of sacraments, namely as signs of sacred realities. Taken at its
broadest, it might be possible to claim that everything created, insofar as it is
what it is, insofar as it participates in some way in God’s perfection, is a sign
of a sacred thing, namely, of God’s own being. Aquinas, however, is not
inclined to use the term “sacrament” in this way.8 Similarly, while Aquinas
takes the worship of God to be a natural obligation of human beings as
rational animals, he does not generally speak of the rites of human religion in
general as sacraments. He is, however, willing to speak of the sacraments of
the Old Law, including not only the ceremonies, festivals, and sacrifices but
also those rites that constitute the community of Israel as sacred, as set apart
for worship of the Lord, especially circumcision and the anointing of priests.
While Aquinas asserts that these sacraments of the Old Law signified sacred
realities, and specifically that they presignified the reality of the saving work
of the Incarnate Word,9 Aquinas held that they did not effect what they
signified. It was the faith of the people of Israel in the redemption signified
by these rites, not the rites themselves, which Aquinas takes to be the basis of
the salvation of those who believed in the true God before the coming of
Jesus Christ.10 Still, while this distinguishes the sacraments of the Old
Covenant from those of the New, it also admits a continuity between them.11
Curiously, while Aquinas has a high view of the rites of the Old Law, and
indeed devotes a fair number of questions in his Summa theologiae to the
very topic, he holds celebration of these same rites now, and indeed in any
time since the promulgation of the Gospel by the apostles, to be sinful. Why
should this be so? On Aquinas’s view, ritual activity, ritual signification, is
fundamentally communicative: it “says” something.12 Moreover, it does so in
a “tensed” way. The grammar of rites includes, on Aquinas’s view, a past,
present, and future.13 According to Aquinas, the rites of the Old Law are all
in the future tense. They speak, admittedly in shadow and figured ways, of
the future coming of the Lord. While one could have “said” that the Lord will
come in the flesh and will suffer and die prior to the Incarnation of the Word
and the life, death, resurrection, and glorification of the Son of God, after
these events, such rites will no longer be true.
Since the sacraments, the signification of enacting the rites themselves,
depend on this kind of contextual meaning, and since the sacraments are
effective only insofar as they succeed in signification, some recent
theologians have wondered whether the seven sacraments recognized by
Thomas Aquinas might not be too deeply enmeshed in the cultural
framework of the classical Mediterranean and the inheritor cultures of the
Greco-Roman world, that is, the culture of Europe and the European
Diaspora.14 Can a Eucharist with wheat bread and wine of the grape have an
effect if the signification of wheat and grape wine is altogether different from
its meaning in Europe, say in sub-Saharan Africa or East Asia? Might not a
different cultural framework require a different, even radically different, kind
of signification, in both matter and ritual word and act (i.e., form) to succeed
in signifying meaningfully?
Aquinas is not unaware that one might imagine both different matter and
different form, particularly different words, to enact the sacraments. In
certain respects, Aquinas is willing to admit a range of signification. Any
wine of the grape, for example, will do.15 Any kind of wheaten bread,
leavened or unleavened, will succeed for the celebration of the Eucharist.16
Any water will do for Baptism,17 whether in a small pool or a running
stream, a lake or the ocean. Likewise, Aquinas is aware that the ritual actions
that surround the sacrament admit to a wide variety, even change. The words
that are used in the sacraments, while not infinitely plastic, likewise may be
subject to legitimate variety and change. Aquinas is keenly aware of the ways
in which the ritual words used by Orthodox Christians in the East differ from
those used by Latin Christians in the West, and he admits that, while the
Latin forms are simply speaking better, the “Greek” (i.e., Orthodox) ritual
forms are no less valid, no less true in their signification.18 Even errors in
speech do not, for Aquinas, necessarily vitiate the signification that is
important for the sacraments to be effective. So long as the intended meaning
of the words is not altogether lost by the error, the signification is
preserved.19
Nonetheless, Aquinas rejects any radical departure from the matter or the
ritual forms accepted by the Church. He notes, for example, that while
Eucharist with barley loaves or a lamb rather than bread of wheat may have a
kind of logic, no rite so celebrated would be a true sacrament. Similarly, to
baptize in the name of the Father who creates, the Son who redeems, and the
Spirit who sanctifies, would be valid and effective, while to baptize in the
name of the Mother, the Daughter, and the Spirit would not.20 What permits
the variety in some sense, but does not allow change in another? Aquinas
recognizes that objects and ritual actions are ambiguous as signs. They
generally require words to locate the meaning that they have here and now.
Moreover, on Aquinas’s view, the signification in the sacraments is located
not principally in the culture in which the sacraments are celebrated, but in
the historical particularities of the earthly life of the Incarnate Word. This
means that the critical question is not, for example, what wheat and wine of
the grape “mean” semantically in Osaka, but whether sake and rice cakes
adequately signify in the way Jesus Christ intended when he instituted the
Eucharist at the Last Supper. The question for Baptism is not whether “Son”
and “Father” have the same signification in North America in the early
twenty-first century that they had in the first in Palestine, but why, in God’s
providence, his Son was Incarnate in first-century Palestine and chose to
reveal himself as the Son of the Father.
SACRAMENTS AS CAUSES
While Aquinas is rightly credited, especially in his later works, with a refined
and enriched conception of the sacraments as signs, it would be a mistake to
overlook the crucial ways that Aquinas wanted to safeguard understanding
the sacraments as true causes of grace. At first glance, one can see why
several of Aquinas’s precursors, and some of his contemporaries as well,
were anxious about the claim that the sacraments cause what they signify.
The sacraments are signs of supernatural effects, of the various participations
in the healing of sin and more importantly of the perfection, the completion
of the human person through a sharing in the life of the Incarnate Word,
Jesus Christ. However, since this is a divine effect, it is difficult to see how
the act of a creature could produce it. Indeed, some of Aquinas’s
contemporaries argued just that, namely, that the sacraments are only signs of
what God does independently of them.21 They are, so they claimed, like a
lead coin that a king has decreed to have commercial value. One can truly
buy things with the coin, not because the coin has value in itself, but merely
by the power of the royal decree. These theologians conceived the
sacraments then as occasions of grace, that God promised to produce certain
effects of grace concurrently with the sacraments, of which the sacraments
were however only the signs.
Others, including Aquinas himself in his early career, were dissatisfied
with this approach. The sacraments, he argued, really produce some effect.
Why? Fundamentally, the early Aquinas and others were convinced from the
language of the Scriptures as understood through the heritage of the Fathers
of the Church that the sacraments did something. Seeing the occasionalist
explanation as a denial of any causality for the sacraments, they rejected it as
unfaithful to the received Tradition. Nonetheless, there remained the problem
of associating a supernatural effect with a natural, and thus finite and
disproportionate, cause. Aquinas’s early solution was to assert that the
sacraments indeed had an effect, but only so as to dispose the recipient to
receive the grace of the sacrament, which grace God imparts directly, without
mediation.22 Since this disposing effect was understood to be proportionate
to the sacraments as finite signs, it was seen as a way to assert, on the one
hand, that the sacraments were indeed efficient signs and, on the other hand,
that it was God, and not created activities, who imparted to believers the gift
of eternal life. Ultimately, Aquinas will abandon this disposing view of the
effect of the sacraments for a more robust claim that the sacraments in fact,
without nuance, impart the grace that they signify, but that in doing so they
do not violate the claim that a finite, physical cause cannot, of itself, produce
a divine, spiritual effect.23 This shift is possible through an appeal to the
notion of instrumental causality, itself enriched not only by an engagement
with the Christological writings of the Christian East, especially John of
Damascus, but also in general of a more comprehensive sense of the
relationship between God’s primary causality and secondary causes in the
created world.
It is also worth noting that, fundamentally, Aquinas’s incentive to hold his
position arises from his conviction that the sacraments are received in faith as
handed on from Jesus Christ, who instituted them, and passed them on to the
apostles, who themselves handed them on to their successors, and through
them to the Church throughout the ages. The sacraments are, for Aquinas, a
theological datum, part of the revelation given in Christ. They are neither the
product of human ingenuity nor can they be derived from prior principles.
There is no more foundational category, “sacramentality,” that can be used to
then discover or produce some new set or ordering of the sacraments of faith
other than the seven sacraments received from Christ by the Church.24
Aquinas does consider the hypothetical possibility, for example, that Christ
might have authorized the apostles to produce new sacraments, or
sacramental effects, in their own name rather than his.25 Likewise, he
accounts for the number of sacraments and what they do on the basis of
anthropology (in light of the origin, growth, maintenance, and restoration of
human beings both as individuals and as social animals) and the virtues
(moral and theological).26 However, in both of these cases, Aquinas is keen
to demonstrate the convenientia, the fittingness of the sacraments as they
have been received. They have an order and a reason to them, but only in the
way that all of the works of God are characterized by wisdom. One could no
more invent a new sacrament on Aquinas’s view than write a new inspired
book of Scripture. One could no more restructure the sacramental system
than one could rewrite the events of Christ’s life.
A more recent worry about Aquinas’s presentation of the sacraments
responds to his understanding of the sacraments as causes. Specifically, the
worry has taken the form of a Heideggerian critique of metaphysics and
“ontotheology,” especially in the work of Chauvet.27 Chauvet, following
Heidegger, worries about the project of seeking a single foundation for all
instances of being, for some indeterminate and unspecified being shared by
all, and then identifying this ground of being with God. As a result, so the
critique goes, while, on the one hand, the richness of individual things as
primary is lost to the vagueness of foundational “being,” so also God is
misrepresented as knowable, as sharing the same kind of being as any other
thing, albeit maximally. God thus becomes the subject of human rational
projects, as opposed to being the One encountered in the world but as always
escaping the capacity of the world to anticipate or categorize. As related to
classic sacramental thought exemplified in Thomas Aquinas, this
ontotheological project is accused of depersonalizing and objectifying the
sacraments, making what should be understood as the creative, self-
producing power of ritual words in an encounter with God who escapes all
human anticipations into a mechanistic scheme of “grace” in which the
actions of God, being capable of categorization in the sphere of being, are
safely known, deprived of mystery.
This is not the place to provide a full response to Chauvet’s critique, much
less to Heidegger’s critique of ontotheology, as they relate to Thomas
Aquinas.28 However, it may be helpful to consider Chauvet’s worry that
Aquinas’s account depersonalizes the sacraments, subordinating them to a
productionist scheme of impersonal objects. On the face of it, the worry does
not seem altogether unfounded. After all, Aquinas does admit that the
sacraments are causes of grace. Even granting that they cause by signing or
through their signification, they are nonetheless causes. Indeed, because they
produce the effects of grace in the recipient, they are efficient causes, and
because they produce their saving effects not of their own materiality or their
intentional ritual use (i.e., their form) but by God’s use of them to produce an
effect properly divine, they are instrumental causes.
Now, efficient causality is not generally how we conceive of the
interaction of persons as persons. The loving encounter between persons is,
one might insist, precisely opposed to producing an effect in the other
directly, as opposed to moving the other by loving example through a kind of
exemplar or final causality. Similarly, if the minister in the ritual enacting of
the sacrament is understood to act as an instrument, and Aquinas’s preferred
analogy for instrumental causality is the saw in the hand of a carpenter,29 we
might rightly worry here that not only the recipient of the sacrament, but also
the minister, is reduced to something inert, an object on which God effects a
change rather than a person invited into the encounter with mystery.
Given these unhappy implications, why would Aquinas assert that
sacraments are instrumental causes? Fundamentally, Aquinas is committed to
the claim that the sacraments are not human acts pointing to God, but divine
acts, God applying the work of salvation effected by the deeds and
experiences of the Incarnate Word to the faithful in the Church, which is
itself the body of the Incarnate Word. They are, in other words, not merely
interpersonal, but in crucial ways intrapersonal, the realization in each of the
members of the body what is fully realized in the head, Jesus Christ, by
means materially and numerically different from the acta et passa Christi,
but which communicate the same power and person those theandric activities
accomplished in the earthly ministry of the Incarnate Word.30
Even so, how should instrumentality not undermine the very personal
reality Aquinas seeks to uphold? The answer lies in the richness Aquinas sees
in the notion of instrumental causality, a richness he has expanded well
beyond its brief discussion in Aristotle, even as Aquinas’s sacramental
thought as a whole enriches and expands the whole understanding of
causality itself.31 The most excellent and pertinent case of instrumental
causality is, for Aquinas, the human nature assumed by the Son of God in the
Incarnation. In this most intimate of all unions, more than even the union of a
hand with its body, the Word of God employs the human nature, an animate,
rational nature, as his own, such that even the simplest of human acts or
experiences of the Incarnate Word is theandric, the human act or experience
of God. Because this fully rational human nature is the human nature of a
divine person, all of the human activity of Jesus Christ is therefore of infinite
value, overflowing with divine charity and sufficient for the salvation of the
whole human race, even if this is all the more evident and effected in those
deeds most clearly enacted out of love for the human race, most especially
his death on the Cross. Thus, in the economy of salvation, all of God’s saving
work is accomplished through the instrumentality of the humanity of the
Incarnate Word and the joining of believers to that saving instrumentality
through the Spirit ordinarily through the instrumentality of the sacraments.
So, in highlighting the instrumentality both of the minister and recipient of
the sacraments, Aquinas is committed neither to a project of
depersonalization nor to the mechanization of the work of grace. The notion
of sacramental character, far from a theological curiosity to distinguish
sacraments that cannot be repeated in the same individual from those that
can, serves to account for how both the reception of the sacraments and their
administration is not merely a human act occasioning or preparing for a
divine act, but a real knowing and loving participation in the personal,
theandric, saving work of the Incarnate Word.32 Indeed, this is why Aquinas
insists that the sacraments do effect what they sign, that they are efficient
causes. To know and love as we ought, to know and love as Christ knows
and loves, to breathe with the same breath that is the Holy Spirit, to be in
other words divinized, is not traceable, reducible, or derivable from any
created nature. No account of semiotics and the power of signs, nor any kind
of formal or final causality alone, can speak meaningfully of what it means
for a created agent to be drawn into the life of the Trinity through the saving
work of the Son of God made flesh. In the end, whatever ways it may also be
the work of the believer, it must necessarily be principally the work of God.
For Aquinas, in line with the historical consensus of Christendom, while
the sacraments share much not only with human religious ceremonies in
general and the offices and sacrifices of the Old Testament in particular,
these sacraments take their origin, institution, meaning, and effect directly
from Jesus Christ in his earthly ministry and as handed on to the Apostles
and their successors. That is, while the sacraments may be said to be
ecclesial (to be sacramenta ecclesiae) insofar as they both constitute the
Church as such and are, especially in the Eucharist, the fundamental activity
of the Church, for Aquinas they are essentially dominical in nature. The
sacraments flow from God’s freedom, from the divine will and plan to draw
his elect to himself by the saving work of the Incarnate Word and the sending
forth of the Holy Spirit. Thus, like any other part of the economy of
salvation, and especially the mysteries of the Incarnation to which they are
intimately linked, the sacraments cannot be deduced by reason, reduced to a
set of principles, or produced by human ingenuity.33 They are irreducibly the
works of Jesus Christ, to be contemplated and explored for deeper
understanding, to be sure, but like all else in the divine economy, explored
not for necessity, but for their fittingness (convenientia) with the eternal
wisdom made manifest in God’s work of salvation in Jesus Christ.
NOTES
1. SCG 3, q.119; ST II-II q.85 a.1.
2. ST II-II q.81 a.2.
3. ST I-II q.102 a.5.
4. ST I-II q.99 a.3.
5. ST III q.48 a.3.
6. ST III q.60 a.1; John P. Yocum, “Sacraments in Aquinas,” in Thomas
Weinandy, Daniel Keating, and John Yocum, eds., Aquinas on Doctrine: A
Critical Introduction (London and New York: T & T Clark International,
2004), 160–64.
7. Edward J. Kilmartin, The Eucharist in the West (Collegeville, Minn.:
Liturgical Press, 1998), 97–102, 120ff.
8. ST III q.60 a.2 ad 1.
9. ST I-II q.102 a.2.
10. ST III q. 62 a. 6.
11. ST I-II q.107 a.1.
12. Yocum, “Sacraments in Aquinas,” 165–68.
13. ST II-II q.93 a.1.
14. See Phillip Tovey, Inculturation of Christian Worship: Exploring the
Eucharist (Aldershot and Burlington, Vt.: Ashgate Publishing, 2004), 33–55.
15. ST III q.74 a.5 ad 3.
16. ST III q.74 a.4.
17. ST III q.66 a.4.
18. ST III q.60 a.8; ST III q.66 a.5 ad 1.
19. ST III q.60 a.7 ad 3.
20. ST III q.60 a.7 ad 3; ST III q.60 a.8.
21. ST III q.62 a.1.
22. Super Sent 4, d.1, q.1, a.4, qc.1, co.
23. ST III q.62 a.1.
24. In all his works, Aquinas only uses the word sacramentalitas once,
Super Sent 4, d.31, q.1, a.2, ad 7. Here he seeks to distinguish different
understandings of marriage. While marriage is a sacrament, it is also a form
of life arising from human nature (officium naturae), and so it can be
understood in this latter way, and not only in terms of its signification of,
among other things, inseparability.
25. ST III q.64 a.4.
26. ST III q.65 a.1.
27. Louis-Marie Chauvet, Symbole et sacrement: Une relecture
sacramentelle de l’existence chrétienne (Paris: Les Éditions du Cerf, 1988).
See also Kenan B. Osborne, Christian Sacraments in a Postmodern World: A
Theology for the Third Millennium (New York and Mahwah, N.J.: Paulist
Press, 1999).
28. For a recent critique of Chauvet’s engagement with Aquinas, see
Bernard Blankenhorn, “The Instrumental Causality of the Sacraments:
Thomas Aquinas and Louis-Marie Chauvet,” Nova et Vetera 4:2 (2006):
255–94.
29. ST III q.62 a.1.
30. ST III q.8.
31. Mark D. Jordan, Rewritten Theology: Aquinas after His Readers
(Malden, Mass. and Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 2006), 163–68.
32. ST III q.63 a.2.
33. ST III q.64 a.2 ad 3.
CHAPTER 34
ELEONORE STUMP
If Aquinas’ view is to be spelled out coherently, it must be done.… [in terms of intrinsic
properties of the soul]. What did happen to a soul in the past, namely that it was united
to a certain body, and will happen to it in future cannot make it the soul it is now. That
must be something internal to it now. Religious believers who believe that humans can
exist without their bodies, even if only temporarily, must hold that. So too must any
believer who holds that there is life after death, even if souls do not exist separately from
bodies.9
everything has its being and its individuation from the same source.… Therefore, as the
being of the soul is from God as from an active principle … so also the individuation of
the soul, even if it has a certain relationship to the body, does not perish when the body
perishes.10
One reason for his holding this position is that there is continuity of cognitive
and conative faculties, with their dispositions and occurrent conditions,
between an embodied person such as Socrates and his subsisting separated
soul. For example, the separated soul of Socrates has the memories of
Socrates rather than those of Plato.11 As far as that goes, all the intellectual
faculties, including the rational will, of Socrates are preserved in his
separated soul. But what is contained in these faculties of the separated soul
of Socrates, including the habits of the will, as well as the mind’s memories
and knowledge, will be different from those in the faculties of the separated
soul of Plato. And so there are these intrinsic differences between the
separated souls of Socrates and Plato: the things known, willed, and
remembered by the separated soul of Socrates are different from those
known, willed, and remembered by the separated soul of Plato.
Consequently, on Aquinas’s view, there are intrinsic characteristics that
differentiate one separated soul from another.
When the soul is separated from the body, it receives its reward or punishment
immediately for those things which it did in the body.… In the providence of God,
rewards and punishments are due to rational creatures. Since when they are separated
from the body, they are immediately capable both of glory and of punishment, they
immediately receive one or the other; and neither the reward of the good nor the
punishment of the bad is put off until the souls take up their bodies again.18
But if the soul of Socrates is not Socrates, then what justice is there in
assigning to the separated soul either the reward or the punishment merited
by Socrates, who is not the soul? Furthermore, at the resurrection Socrates
will exist again; and the separated soul-which-is-not-Socrates will cease to
exist, since the separated soul will then cease to exist as a separate subsisting
thing. But why should the separated soul-which-is-not-Socrates lose its bliss
when Socrates is resurrected?
The views implied by the position that a human being fails to exist in the
period between bodily death and bodily resurrection are theological
gibberish, and they are contradicted in multiple places by explicit claims on
Aquinas’s part. So, for example, about the nature of the separated soul’s
bliss, Aquinas says that
souls immediately after their separation from the body become unchangeable as regards
the will.… [B]eatitude, which consists in the vision of God, is everlasting.… But it is
not possible for a soul to be blessed if its will did not have rectitude.… And so it must be
that the rectitude of the will in the blessed soul is everlasting.19
This text and many others like it make plain the unacceptability of the
interpretation that assigns to Aquinas the view that a human being ceases to
exist at death and that a separated soul is not the same human being as the
person whose soul it is. That interpretation has to attribute to Aquinas views
that make his theological position bizarre and that he explicitly denied in one
place or another. It is abundantly clear therefore that for Aquinas the
existence of the separated soul is sufficient for the existence of the human
being whose soul it is.
But, then, we need to ask, how can Aquinas also hold that a human being
is a material composite? It seems as if, for Aquinas, either a human being is
identical to his soul, in which case a human being is not a material
composite, or else a human being is a material composite, in which case he is
not identical to his soul. How is it possible for a human being to be a material
composite and yet to continue to exist in the absence of his body?
The consistency of Aquinas’s position is manifest if we give proper
weight to the distinction between constitution and identity in his thought. A
human person is not identical to his soul; rather, a human person is identical
to an individual substance in the species rational animal. A particular of that
sort is normally, naturally, composed of form and matter configured into a
human body. Because constitution is not identity for Aquinas, however, a
particular can exist with less than the normal, natural complement of
constituents. It can, for example, exist when it is constituted only by one of
its main metaphysical parts, namely, the soul. And so although a person is
not identical to his soul, the existence of the soul is sufficient for the
existence of a person. Once we are clear about Aquinas’s distinction between
constitution and identity, we can see that a rejection of the Platonic position
that a human being is identical to a soul is not equivalent to the acceptance of
the position that a human being cannot exist without a body.
NOTES
1. For further discussion of the metaphysical issues raised here and in
subsequent sections in connection with Aquinas’s theory of forms, see the
chapter on Aquinas’s theory of things in my Aquinas (London: Routledge,
2003).
2. In DA II.11.226.
3. QDA un.9.
4. In BDT 2.4.2; cf. also ST I q.119 a.1 and QDP 9.1.
5. Perhaps the most detailed exposition of this view of his is in his In BDT
2.4.2.
6. In BDT 2.4.2. Aquinas does not always describe his position on this
score in the same way, and the variation in terminology suggests to some
scholars either a development in his thought or a series of changes of mind.
The issue is complicated, and so I am leaving it to one side here. For the
discussion of the scholarly controversy, see John Wippel, The Metaphysical
Thought of Thomas Aquinas: From Finite Being to Uncreated Being
(Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 2000), 357–73.
7. But see also Jeffrey Brower’s contribution to this volume.
8. Cf., e.g., ST III q.3 a.7 ad 1, where Aquinas says that a substantial form
is multiplied in accordance with the division of matter.
9. Richard Swinburne, “Soul, Nature and Immortality of the,” in
Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (London: Routledge, 1999).
10. QDA un.1 ad 2.
11. In fact, for Aquinas, there are two memory capacities, one which is
dependent on the senses and phantasia, and one which is dependent on the
intellect. The second is the memory at issue here. For further discussion of
Aquinas’s views of human cognitive capacities, see the chapter on the
mechanisms of cognition in my Aquinas (London: Routledge, 2003).
12. See, e.g., In Metaphysica VII.17.1672–1674. There Aquinas says that
in cases in which the composite is one thing, the composite is not identical
with its components; rather the composite is something over and above its
components. For interesting contemporary arguments against the reduction of
wholes to their parts, see Mark Johnston, “Constitution is Not Identity,” Mind
101 (1992): 89–105, and Lynne Rudder Baker, “Why Constitution is Not
Identity,” Journal of Philosophy 94 (1997): 599–621. For an excellent
discussion of the constitution relation, see Lynne Rudder Baker, “Unity
Without Identity: A New Look at Material Constitution,” Midwest Studies in
Philosophy 23 (1999): 144–65. Cf. also Lynne Rudder Baker, Persons and
Bodies: A Constitution View (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2000).
13. In Metaphysica VII.17.1673–1674.
14. For more defense of this position, see my “Resurrection, Reassembly,
and Reconstitution: Aquinas on the Soul,” in Bruno Niederberger and
Edmund Runggaldier, eds., Die menschliche Seele: Brauchen wir den
Dualismus? (Frankfurt a. M.: Ontos Verlag, 2006).
15. I am grateful to Brian Leftow for calling this passage to my attention.
16. In I Cor, ch. 15, l.2.
17. So, e.g., Peter van Inwagen says, “Aquinas.… sees the human person as
essentially a composite of a human soul and a human body. According to the
‘composite’ theory, a person cannot exist without a body: to exist is for one’s
soul (always numerically the same) to animate some human body or other.
(In the interval between one’s death and one’s receiving a new body at the
time of the general resurrection, one’s soul exists and thinks and has
experiences, but one does not, strictly speaking, exist)” (Peter van Inwagen,
“Resurrection,” in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy [London:
Routledge, 1999]). Robert Pasnau also argues that for Aquinas a separated
soul is not a human being and therefore that a human being ceases to exist at
death, on Aquinas’s position. As one example supporting this interpretation,
Pasnau cites a passage from Aquinas’s Sentence commentary in which
Aquinas is discussing the separated soul of Abraham. In that place, as Pasnau
rightly points out, “Aquinas remarks … that ‘Abraham’s soul is not, strictly
speaking, Abraham himself’” (the passage is cited by Pasnau as Super Sent
IV 43.1.1.1 ad 2). Pasnau claims that Aquinas “insists on this point precisely
so as to argue that bodily resurrection is necessary for human immortality.
Hence [Aquinas] immediately concludes: ‘So Abraham’s soul’s having life
would not suffice for Abraham’s being alive.’” In Pasnau’s view, this
passage shows that Aquinas cannot have supposed that “the persistence of
the soul ‘is sufficient for the existence’ of the human being.” Rather, in
Pasnau’s view, the passage makes plain that Aquinas “would deny that a
human soul could constitute a human being.” See Robert Pasnau’s review of
my Aquinas in Mind 114 (2005): 203–6.
18. SCG IV.91.
19. SCG IV.92.
20. The phrase is Van Inwagen’s; see Van Inwagen, “Resurrection.”
21. I am grateful to Brian Davies for helpful comments on an earlier draft
of this paper.
CHAPTER 35
PRAYER
BRIAN DAVIES
God’s will is to be thought of as existing outside the realm of existents (extra ordinem
entium existens), as a cause from which pours forth everything that exists in all its
various forms. Now what can be and what must be are variants of being, so that it is
from God’s will itself that things derive whether they must be or may or may not be and
the distinction of the two according to the nature of their immediate causes. For he
prepares causes that must cause for those effects that he wills must be, and causes that
might cause but might fail to cause for those effects that he wills might or might not be.
And it is because of the nature of their causes that some effects are said to be effects that
must be and others effects that need not be, although all depend on God’s will as
primary cause, a cause which transcends this distinction between must and might not.6
In other words, Aquinas thinks that God’s omni-causality does not act as a
rival to the causality of creatures, since it actually empowers this or makes it
to exist.
With this thought in mind, Aquinas draws the conclusion that God is
omnipotent. Unlike some authors, by “God is omnipotent” Aquinas does not
mean that we can stick the expression “God can …” before any expression
signifying any logically possible feat. He does not mean that God is
omnipotent, since, for example, God can ride a bicycle, or fly to Germany, or
sin. Aquinas’s account of omnipotence is tied to his notion of God as
bringing it about that things have esse. His rule is: if it can be thought
(without contradiction) to be, then God can make it to be. And this rule takes
us to the notion of petitionary prayer. For people who pray want it to be the
case that certain things, states, or processes come to be. And, so one might
ask, if Aquinas is right on the topic of God as Creator, then is it not
reasonable for such people to ask God to bring it about that these things,
states, or processes actually do come to be?7
OBJECTIONS TO PRAYER
But is it? Not according to many people. Some of these would object to the
notion of petitionary prayer on the ground that there is no God to pray to,
and, if that is so, then petitionary prayer is obviously misguided. More
commonly, however, critics of petitionary prayer argue that there is
something unreasonable about engaging in it because of what God is
commonly taken to be. God is said to be good and omniscient. In that case,
however, would he not know what we want or need without us telling him,
and would he not provide for us without being asked? And does it not,
therefore, follow that prayer is redundant? Given God’s goodness and
omniscience, many have suggested that this is exactly what it is. Others have
held that petitionary prayer makes no sense given the traditional claim that
God is immutable. If God is immutable, so it has been argued, then he
changelessly wills what he wills from eternity and nothing that we can do or
say can make any difference when it comes to what God wills.
These objections to petitionary prayer, though often voiced today, are
ancient ones. You can find them documented in, for example, chapter 3 of
Origen’s De Oratione (written around a.d. 233).11 And Aquinas is aware of
them. As they emerge in his formulation:
Prayer seems to be needed to give information about what we want to the person we are
asking for something. But, as it says [Matthew 6:32] “Your Father knows that you need
all these things” … Prayer is a way in which we change the mind of the person to whom
we are praying, so that he will do what is being asked of him. But God’s mind cannot be
changed or deflected.… It is more generous to give something without waiting to be
asked than it is to give something to someone who asks for it.… But God is extremely
generous. So it is apparently not appropriate that we should pray to God.12
Yet Aquinas rejects these objections. And his basic response to them is:
Divine providence does not merely arrange what effects are to occur; it also arranges the
causes of these effects and the relationships between them. And among other causes,
some things are caused by human acts. So human beings have to do certain things, not
so as to change God’s plans by their acts, but in order to bring about certain effects by
their acts, according to the pattern planned by God.… We do not pray in order to change
God’s plans, but in order to obtain by our prayers those things which God planned to
bring about by means of prayers.13
You shall, I hope, see how this response of Aquinas fits in with what I
reported above concerning his take on God as Creator. But let me try to spell
things out a bit.
Given what he says of God in general, Aquinas clearly cannot think of
prayer as having a causal effect on God. In his way of thinking, the source of
the esse of creatures cannot be modified by a creature. So Aquinas does not
think of prayer in magical terms—as a way of manipulating God.
Consequently, he does not think of it as informing God or as changing him in
any way. But he still thinks of prayer as a significant activity, since, so he
believes (and regardless of how good or generous God is), it matters that we
should recognize God for what he is and turn to him for what we need. “We
do not,” he observes, “have to present our prayers to God in order to disclose
to him our needs and desires, but in order to make ourselves realize that we
need to have recourse to his help in these matters.”14
What, then, of the causality of prayer? Evidently, Aquinas cannot say that
my praying causes God to do something in the sense that, say, my tossing a
salad causes its ingredients to become covered in dressing. And yet, so
Aquinas would presumably add, my responding to a request from you is not
caused in this sense either. Aquinas holds that people have freedom of choice
(liberum arbitrium) and, so he would say, a good example of this being
exercised would be someone giving people something for which they ask. Of
course, I might give you what you ask for because you coerce me (because
you force some money out of my hand, say). For Aquinas, though, I would
not really be giving or acting here. I would be operating under duress. On his
account, people freely responding to requests are not being caused by the
requests or the petitioners in the way in which a salad gets caused to be
dressed by one tossing it.
One might, of course, reply that, even if we accept this point, prayer, on
Aquinas’s account cannot really make any difference. The argument might
go like this: If Fred asks John for some money, and if John gives him some,
Fred’s asking might be thought to have made a difference in that John might
not have given Fred money had he not asked for it. If Aquinas is right,
however, God is immutable. So he brings about what he has decreed from
eternity to bring about. What room is there in this picture for a prayer making
any difference at all? And if prayer makes no difference, why bother with it?
To understand Aquinas’s position with respect to this argument, it is
important to note that he genuinely believes that creatures have causal
powers. He thinks, for example, that we actually do digest food, or hit tennis
balls, or build houses. His claim that God acts in every operation is not meant
to deny that creatures genuinely act. It is meant to put the causal activity of
creatures into a deeper context—that of God as Creator. For Aquinas, in
causing the esse of all creatures, God is also empowering their creaturely
causality. And with this thought in mind, Aquinas insists that, for example,
when I act it is true both that I act and that I act only as God is bringing it
about that I do so.
Now consider the case of someone deciding, for example, to build a
house. And imagine this person reasoning thus: “Well, it’s actually pointless
for me to get started since, if Aquinas is right in what he says about God, I
can’t make any difference. If God has from eternity decreed that the house
shall be built, then it will get built and I can spare myself some effort.” This
argument, of course, clearly rests on the assumption that creatures are not
genuine causal agents and that God is an omnipotent puppet master, an
assumption that Aquinas denies. He would say that, as God in his providence
has arranged things, houses do not get built unless people get on with
building them. He would, indeed, agree that whether people build houses,
and whether or not houses come to exist, depend on God’s changeless will as
the Maker of all things. But he would not take this to mean that people do not
make a difference when it comes to what happens.
That said, we can return to the notion of prayer making a difference. In
Aquinas’s view (if I understand his teaching on miracles correctly), God
could have brought it about that the British Houses of Parliament came to be
by the direct action of God and of nothing else. Yet what in fact happened, so
Aquinas would say, is that God brought them about by the action of people.
By the same token, so Aquinas thinks, God could bring it about that, say, I
recover from an illness without anyone praying that I do so. Yet, Aquinas
also thinks, what might in fact come to pass is that God brings it about that I
recover as having been prayed for—that my improved state of health is an
answer to someone’s concern for me and not just a mere matter of getting
better. “God,” says Aquinas, “gives us many things out of sheer generosity,
without being asked. The reason why he wants to give us some things in
response to our petition is that it is profitable for us to acquire a certain
confidence in running to him and to recognize that he is the source of all that
is good for us.”15
NOTES
1. For some history of the term “prayer” in Christian circles, see Michel
Dupuy, “Oraison,” in Dictionnaire de Spiritualité, vol. 11 (Paris: Beauchesne
Editions, 1982).
2. Bonaventure, quoted in Super Sent IV, d.15, p.2, a.1, q.4.
3. Simon Tugwell, O.P., Albert and Thomas: Selected Writings (New
York and Mahwah, N.J.: Paulist Press, 1988), 275. See also Simon Tugwell,
O.P., “Prayer, Humpty Dumpty and Thomas Aquinas,” in Brian Davies, ed.,
Language, Meaning and God (London: Geoffrey Chapman, 1987).
4. ST II-II q.83.
5. In Super Sent IV, d.15, q.1, a.4, Aquinas seems prepared to take
seriously the suggestion that “prayer” is to be used in more than one sense.
By the time he writes on prayer in the ST, however, his focus is entirely on
prayer as petition. Texts in which Aquinas deals with oratio include: Super
Sent IV, d.15, q.4; QDV, q.6, a.6; SCG, III, 95–96; In 1 Cor 14:13–15.
Reliable translations of these texts, and other texts by Aquinas on prayer, can
be found in Tugwell, Albert and Thomas, 363–523.
6. In Peri herm, 1:14. I quote from Timothy McDermott, ed., Aquinas:
Selected Philosophical Writings (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993),
282f.
7. In ST II-II q.83 a.4, Aquinas argues that it is appropriate to address
prayer to the saints and angels, but only insofar as we ask them to join their
prayers to ours. “We address prayer to the angels and the saints,” he says,
“not because we want them to let God know what we want, but because we
want our petitions to be successful through their intercession and merits.”
8. This is the main point made in ST II-II q.83 a.1.
9. So Aquinas denies that nonrational creatures pray. Cf. ST II-II q.83
a.10.
10. What if I want all babies born within the next twenty-four hours to be
murdered by gangsters? Then, Aquinas would say, I would have no business
asking for this from God, since he is the highest good (the source of all
creaturely goods) and can hardly be called upon to produce what is obviously
evil. That said, however, Aquinas’s position is that if you want it, and if God
can provide it, it makes sense to ask him for it.
11. For a translation of this text, see Origen, On Prayer, trans. E. G. Jay
(London: S.P.C.K., 1954).
12. ST II-II q.83 a.2. I quote from Tugwell, Albert and Thomas, 479–80.
13. ST II-II q.83 a.2. Tugwell, Albert and Thomas, 481.
14. ST II-II q.83 a.2 ad 1. Tugwell, Albert and Thomas, 481.
15. ST II-II q.83 a.2 ad 3. Tugwell, Albert and Thomas, 481.
16. ST II-II q.83 a.3. In ST II-II q.83 a.15, Aquinas goes on to note that
prayer is an expression of humility, faith, and devotion, and is, therefore,
meritorious (meaning that it brings us closer to God).
17. ST II-II q.83 a.7. In ST II-II q.83 a.4, Aquinas goes on to say that we
should pray for our enemies.
18. ST II-II q.83 a.5.
19. ST II-II q.83 a.6.
20. Curiously, Aquinas does not note the obvious point that it might be
logically impossible for God to grant what everyone prays for since different
people might (and do) pray for things that are mutually exclusive (e.g., “a
fine day for my garden party” and “rain for my crops”). Perhaps he does not
note the point since it is, indeed, obvious.
21. ST II-II q.83 a.15.
CHAPTER 36
ANDREW PINSENT
INTRODUCTION
Recent scholarship has suggested the need to reconsider the validity of an
Aristotelian reading of Aquinas’s virtue ethics. The recognition that there are
certain differences between the virtues described by Aristotle and Aquinas is
not, of course, anything new. Even a cursory examination of Aquinas’s vast
treatise on the virtues in Summa theologiae1 reveals many perfective
qualities, such as humility, which Aristotle never mentions. Nevertheless, the
general approach of much Thomistic scholarship has been to view Aquinas’s
treatise as following an Aristotelian framework with certain extrinsic
additions. The cardinal virtues in Aquinas’s treatise have long been treated,
in particular, in more or less the same way as their homonymous counterparts
in the Nicomachean Ethics.
The principal motivation for doubting the continued validity of this
approach is a growing recognition of the differences between Aristotle and
Aquinas regarding what is meant by “virtue” in the proper sense.2 Aquinas
does recognize that we can acquire virtues in the Aristotelian manner by
repeated good actions; he calls such virtues acquired virtues. Aquinas also
claims, however, that proper or perfect virtues are not acquired, but infused
in us by God.3 These infused virtues include counterparts of many of the
acquired moral and intellectual virtues. So, for example, as well as acquired
justice, there is infused justice, which is the proper sense of the virtue of
justice. Similarly, besides acquired prudence, there is infused prudence,
which is the proper sense of the virtue of prudence, and so on.4
While defining the relationship between the acquired and the infused
virtues has proved difficult, it is clear that acquired and infused virtues are
distinct in several important ways. First, Aquinas argues that only the infused
virtues are perfect and deserve to be called “virtues” simply.5 Second,
acquired and infused virtues differ in species, distinguished, according to
Aquinas, by their proper objects and the kinds of flourishing to which they
are directed.6 Third, as Jean Porter has noted, all human beings have the
capacity to receive infused virtues, even those, such as children, who lack the
intellectual training required for Aristotelian virtues.7 Fourth, as Porter and
Bonnie Kent have observed, an infused virtue, unlike an acquired virtue, can
be present with a previously acquired contrary disposition.8 Fifth, Aquinas
claims that infused virtues are connected together, unlike specific acquired
tendencies to do good actions.9 Sixth, as Jeffrey Hause argues, the difference
between acquired and infused virtues cannot be reduced to a proportional
change in the good established by reason, such as greater asceticism, since
such a change does not require a different virtue.10 Seventh, even if a person
possesses all the acquired virtues, if he lacks the infused virtues he cannot
enter heaven.11
Besides these important distinctions, the structure of ST II-II q.1–170
provides additional evidence of a non-Aristotelian approach to virtue ethics.
It should occasion some wonder that, despite having the greatest respect for
Aristotle and a detailed knowledge of the structure of the Nicomachean
Ethics,12 Aquinas organized his own treatise on the virtues in such a different
way from that of Aristotle. Furthermore, the difference in Aquinas’s
approach is not just that he has added novel virtues, like the theological
virtues and humility, hallowed by Christian tradition. Even his articles on the
Greek cardinal virtues of prudence, justice, courage, and temperance,
interleave these virtues with other attributes that are not virtues at all and
which lack any Aristotelian counterpart.
Consider, for instance, the virtue of courage. Following his treatise on
courage as a virtue,13 Aquinas appends a further question describing an
entirely new quality, the Gift (donum) of Courage.14 Although this Gift of
Courage is infused, Aquinas claims that a Gift is a different kind of quality
from an infused virtue.15 Even the addition of the Gift of Courage is not the
end of the story, though, because Aquinas claims that this Gift is linked to a
further attribute, a Beatitude (beatitudo) called “Hungering and thirsting for
justice.”16 This Beatitude is in turn associated with two final and distinct
attributes, the Fruits (fructus) of Patience and Long-suffering.17 So Aquinas
appends a network with one Gift, one Beatitude, and two Fruits to the virtue
of courage. Similar networks can be found for the other cardinal and
theological virtues, giving the impression of an intricate and even “organic”
structure different from that of the Nicomachean Ethics.18
This non-Aristotelian structure implies that the cardinal virtues Aquinas
examines in ST IIaIIae are not the acquired versions of these virtues, even if
they exhibit many parallels with the acquired virtues and even though
Aquinas often cites Aristotle. ST II-II q.47 a.14 clarifies, in fact, that the
prudence being examined is infused prudence, and there are similar
clarifications for the other cardinal virtues.19 If, then, the cardinal virtues in
ST II-II q.1–170 are infused rather than acquired, a further inference follows.
To grasp what Aquinas means by an infused virtue, it is also important to
study what he means by a Gift, a Beatitude, and a Fruit. These attributes
appear to be interconnected with the virtues, both in ST IIaIIae and according
to a claim Aquinas makes when he introduces the genus of virtue in ST
IaIIae: “We must speak in the first place of the good habitus, which are
virtues, and of other matters connected with them, namely the Gifts,
Beatitudes and Fruits.”20
In this chapter I focus on the first and last of these three kinds of attributes
that Aquinas appends to the virtues: the Gifts and the Fruits of the Holy
Spirit. As I shall show, Aquinas claims that the Gifts are, in fact, essential
and connected to the virtues, while Fruits feature as the terminating attributes
of the entire network. Given these pivotal roles, understanding the Gifts and
Fruits is, therefore, an important step toward grasping Aquinas’s virtue ethics
as a whole.
THE GIFTS
What is a Gift of the Holy Spirit, and how do Gifts relate to virtues and other
perfecting attributes? There are seven Gifts, which Aquinas appends to
various theological and cardinal virtues in ST IIaIIae. The cognitive Gifts are
Understanding (Intellectus) and Knowledge (Scientia), which are appended
to the virtue of faith, Wisdom (Sapientia), appended to the virtue of caritas,21
and Counsel (Consilium), appended to the virtue of prudence. The appetitive
Gifts are Fear (Timor), appended to the virtue of hope, Piety (Pietas),
appended to the virtue of justice, and Courage (Fortitudo), appended to the
homonymous virtue of courage.22 Aquinas also examines the genus of Gift in
ST I-II q.68, immediately following his treatise on the genus of virtue, ST I-II
q.55–67.
ST I-II q.68 a.2 claims that the Gifts are essential to salvation, an explicit
confirmation that they are not adventitious in Aquinas’s account of human
flourishing. ST I-II q.68 a.8 adds that, while the theological virtues are more
excellent than the Gifts, the Gifts are more excellent than the moral and
intellectual virtues, thereby taking precedence over any of the qualities
described in the Nicomachean Ethics.23 Aquinas even claims, in ST II-II q.19
a.9 ad 4, that the Gifts are the origins or foundations (principia) of the
intellectual and moral virtues.
The function of the Gifts is, however, more difficult to grasp than the fact
of their importance. ST I-II q.68 a.4 states that the Gifts extend to all those
things to which the virtues, both intellectual and moral, extend. Yet if the
work of the Gifts parallels that of the virtues, why are the Gifts necessary?
Aquinas’s response is a principle set out in ST I-II q.68 a.1:
Now it is manifest that human virtues perfect man according as it is natural for him to be
moved by his reason in his interior and exterior actions. It is fitting, therefore, for there
to exist in man higher perfections, whereby he is disposed to be moved by God in a
divine way. These perfections are called Gifts, not only because they are infused by
God, but also because by them man is disposed to be made readily moveable by divine
inspiration.24
In this passage, Aquinas claims that what is specific about a Gift is not that it
is infused, since perfect virtues are also infused, but that, by means of a Gift,
we are disposed to be moved by God. What, however, does being “moved”
by God mean in this context? Aquinas clarifies elsewhere that such
movement is not coercive.25 Furthermore, it can be inferred that what is
given by means of the Gifts is not reducible to some propositional description
of the world, a description that could, in principle, be communicated in some
other way.26 In what, then, does Gift-based movement consist?
A partial answer to this question can be inferred from the notion of a
“participated likeness” (participativa similitudo), a phrase that Aquinas uses
when describing the Gift of Knowledge. Aquinas claims that the Gift of
Knowledge enables a “participated likeness” of God’s knowledge,
knowledge that is absolute and simple rather than discursive, as for the
homonymous intellectual virtue.27 A similar notion of participation can be
found in Aquinas’s descriptions of the other Gifts. By the Gift of Piety, we
are moved to regard other persons as God regards them, namely as potential
or actual children, and thereby our brothers and sisters.28 By the Gift of
Courage, we regard present dangers and potential future dangers with the
kind of confidence with which God regards such difficulties.29 By the Gift of
Fear, we regard ourselves as God regards us, as adopted children with whom
God desires to be united, and so shrink from the loss of our own good from
God’s perspective.30 By the Gift of Counsel, we are “directed as though
counseled by God,” implying that we take on God’s stance toward possible
courses of action.31 By the Gift of Understanding, we grasp what is proposed
to us by God.32 Finally, by the Gift of Wisdom, we are enabled to judge
aright about divine things on account of a “connaturality” with them.33 In all
these cases, the movement enabled by the Gifts can be characterized as a
sharing or appropriation of God’s stance toward some object.
Such appropriations of God’s stance cannot, however, be reduced to mere
imitations, as Aquinas shows, for example, in his description of the Gift of
Wisdom: “Wisdom as a Gift is more excellent than wisdom as an intellectual
virtue, since it attains to God more intimately by a kind of union of the soul
with him (unio animae ad ipsum).”34 The idea of a union or oneness of the
soul with God in this passage is reflected in other texts about the Gifts,
especially Aquinas’s claim that whoever has caritas, which unites us to God,
has all the Gifts, none of which can be possessed without caritas.35 So Gift-
based movement is not a mere imitation of God’s stance but implies a union
of the soul with God, a union based on caritas.
Aquinas’s descriptions of Gift-based movement therefore express two
main principles. First, he describes a situation in which a person’s stance
toward some object involves a participation in God’s stance toward the same
object. Second, Gift-based movement involves what Aquinas describes as a
union or oneness of the soul with God. Expressed in these terms, Aquinas’s
descriptions of the operation of the Gifts seem analogous to the phenomenon
of joint attention, the subject of a new field of experimental psychology and
philosophy.36 While the precise definition of joint attention remains a matter
of some debate, the phenomenon has at least the following basic
characteristics. First, joint attention takes place in a person-person-object
situation in which both persons share a stance toward the object that is the
focus of their attention. In the context of parent–child interactions, activities
manifesting joint attention can include, for example, referential use of eye
contact, offering and giving objects to others, pointing at objects and
following others’ points. Second, joint attention involves sharing an
awareness of the sharing of focus with the other person,37 an experience
commonly described as a “meeting of minds.” Both these characteristics of
joint attention with another person have clear parallels with Aquinas’s
descriptions of Gift-based movement.
So a description of the Gifts seems clear and the phenomenon of joint
attention may provide an analogy for their operation. Nevertheless, to show
the function of the Gifts does not, in itself, explain their importance. Why,
exactly, are the Gifts so essential to Aquinas’s conception of human
flourishing? If joint attention is a correct analogy for Gift-based movement,
then it may be possible to answer this question by examining the role of joint
attention in interactions between human persons. In particular, by examining
what happens when joint attention between persons is inhibited, it may be
possible to highlight what is so important about joint attention for human
relationships, and, in turn, what is important about Gift-based movement
with regard to one’s relationship with God.
As it turns out, there is a condition that is characterized by lack of
engagement in joint attention with other human persons. This condition is
autism, the characteristics of which have been both an incentive and a means
to investigate joint attention in recent years. In the following passage, Peter
Hobson, a professor of developmental psychopathology, describes the
outcome of an experiment designed to highlight how autistic children interact
with other persons:
In two respects, then, the children with autism were not moved to adopt the orientation
of the person they were watching. They did not adopt the style with which the
experimenter executed the actions, nor did they identify with him and copy his self-
orientated actions so that these actions became orientated towards themselves. On the
other hand, they were perfectly able to perceive and copy the strategies by which he
achieved the goals in each demonstration. So they were able to learn something from
watching what the experimenter did.… Yet what they learned seemed to be available
from their position as a kind of detached observer of actions and goals. They were not
“moved.”38
The experiment described in this passage showed that autistic children were
perfectly capable of recognizing other persons and following instructions
given by another person.39 Furthermore, they were also able to imitate the
actions and goals of another. What the children with autism did not do,
however, was to appropriate another person’s psychological orientation or to
“identify” with the other person.40 Indeed, in the passage above, Hobson
articulates what is missing from autistic behavior by the same language that
Aquinas uses to describe the Gifts: the children with autism were not
“moved.”
So joint attention provides a possible analogy for Gift-based movement,
and autism provides a corresponding analogy for a person’s condition, in
relationship to God, when the person lacks the Gifts. Now the analogy of
autism with a lack of the Gifts does not imply that the condition of autism
precludes possession of the Gifts. On the contrary, unlike the acquired
virtues, Aquinas is clear that anyone can possess the infused virtues and
Gifts.41 Nevertheless, the analogy between the condition of autism and the
absence of the Gifts gives some indication of why the Gifts are important.
Furthermore, there is another intriguing characteristic of autism that sheds
light on the role of the Gifts in relationship to God. As Leo Kanner noted in
his original description of the syndrome, and many subsequent studies have
confirmed, children with autism often refer to themselves as “you” and the
person they are speaking with as “I.”42 For example, the question, “How are
you?” might elicit the response, “You are fine.” Such instances of pronoun
reversal are not, however, common to children with other kinds of retarded
learning conditions, such as Down Syndrome.43 The fact that those with
autism find it especially hard to grasp the rules for second-personal pronouns
suggests that those with autism have difficulties relating to others in a
specifically second-personal sense. Indeed, if the capacity to engage in joint
attention is inhibited, as in the case of autism, it is hard to see how an
intuitive grasp of the “I”–“you” relationship can be acquired easily in human
development.44
The connection between joint attention and the second person therefore
implies a further way of showing why the Gifts are important for Aquinas’s
understanding of human flourishing. If joint attention enables a second-
personal relationship to other human persons, the Gifts, by analogy, enable a
specifically second-personal relationship with God. If, therefore, virtues can
be classified as first-personal habitus, by which a person is moved easily by
his or her own reason, the Gifts, by contrast, are the second-personal habitus,
by which a person is moved by God in a manner analogous to joint attention.
Such a conclusion is consistent with the intrinsic connection that Aquinas
makes between the Gifts and caritas, given that Aquinas describes caritas as
friendship with God and friendship implies the ability to relate to one’s friend
in a second-personal way.45
THE FRUITS
Aquinas introduces the Fruits by means of a material analogy. Using the
example of a plant, Aquinas observes that a material fruit is “the product of a
plant when it comes to perfection, and has a certain sweetness.”46 These
qualities also characterize the ethical attribute that he calls a “Fruit”: “The
notion of Fruit implies two things: first that it should come last; second, that
it should calm the appetite with a certain sweetness and delight … that which
is last simply, and in which one delights as in the last end, is properly called a
Fruit; and this it is that one is properly said to enjoy.”47 Consistent with the
notion of a Fruit coming last, Aquinas generally assigns the Fruits of each
virtue last in the ST II-II q.1–170, after the appended Gifts and Beatitudes.
Aquinas also examines the genus of Fruit in ST I-II q.70, after examining the
genus of Gift and Beatitude.
What, however, does Aquinas understand by the term “Fruit”? According
to ST I-II q.70 a.3, the Fruits of Caritas, Joy (Gaudium), Peace (Pax),
Patience (Patientia), and Long-suffering (Longanimitas) pertain to the good
ordering of the mind. The Fruits of Goodness (Bonitas), Benignity
(Benignitas), Meekness (Mansuetudo), and Faith (Fides) pertain to one’s
neighbor. The Fruits of Modesty (Modestia), Continency (Continentia), and
Chastity (Castitas) pertain to the body. The twelve Fruits therefore extend to
many, and perhaps all, of the same things to which the virtues and the Gifts
extend. Why, therefore, is there yet another set of attributes, distinct from the
virtues and the Gifts?
The mystery of the Fruits is deepened by Aquinas’s claim that they are not
habitus in the manner of Gifts or virtues.48 On the contrary, Aquinas
describes the Fruits variously as actus or operationes or opera of the virtues
and as the last and congruous products of the Gifts.49 The implication is that
a Fruit is some kind of actualization or manifestation of the virtues and Gifts.
Some of the Fruits, such as Caritas, have homonymous counterparts among
the virtues, whereas others, such as Joy and Peace, are unique to the category
of Fruit. How, then, is the attribute of Fruit to be understood?
Aquinas implies an answer to this question in his description of the Fruit
of Peace, which he classifies as an actus of caritas:
Peace implies a twofold union.… The first is the result of one’s own appetites being
ordered toward one thing; while the other results from one’s own appetite being united
with the appetite of another: and each of these unions is effected by caritas … hence it is
reckoned a sign of friendship if people “make choice of the same things” (Ethic. ix, 4),
and Tully says (De Amicitia) that friends like and dislike the same things.50
In the article cited above, Aquinas highlights the interpersonal aspect of the
Fruit of Peace and its connection with friendship, observing that Peace
implies a harmony between two persons, an alignment in which one chooses
the same things as one’s friend and with one’s friend.51 Aquinas also
describes other Fruits in interpersonal terms: he associates Joy with the
experience of God abiding in a person, and the Fruit of Caritas with both a
union of affections and a union of persons.52
These interpersonal descriptions are consistent with Aquinas’s claim that
the Fruits are the last and congruous products of the Gifts. Since, as argued
previously, the Gifts are second-personal habitus, one would expect the
Fruits, as actus of these Gifts, to have a second-personal aspect as well.
Nevertheless, in Aquinas’s network of perfecting attributes, not all actus of
the Gifts are Fruits. The actus of Counsel, for example, are not Fruits, but
only means for bringing about Fruits.53 Furthermore, the Fruits are also
consequent upon the Beatitudes, as Aquinas states in ST II-II q.139 a.2,54
implying some intermediate step between Gift-based actus in general and the
special class of actus that are Fruits. By what measure, then, are the Fruits
perfect or complete compared to Gift-based actus in general?
Some poetic inspiration to help answer this question may be found in a
scene from Dante’s Paradiso, during which Dante the traveler encounters the
soul of Aquinas in heaven,
The idea of “stars,” that is, souls in paradise, revealing their interpersonal
union to Dante by the image of a perfect dance, suggests that it is important
to examine not only what it means to be moved by another person, but the
manner in which such movements are perfected. Orchestras, choirs, or
dancers, for example, do not always harmonize very well and can experience
discords, mistimings, and mistakes. When their joint operation becomes
second nature, however, with the participants being near-perfectly attuned to
one another, there is often a sudden, disproportionate improvement in the
objective quality of the activity. Subjectively, musicians or dancers may also
experience the pleasurable exhilaration of “flying along,” accompanied by
the sense of being “one” with the other persons. This harmonized operation
appears similar to the phenomenon of resonance in physics, when two
systems engage in close to perfect joint operation with disproportionate ease
and intensity.56 In the case of the joint operation of two persons, when
activities in union with the other person have become second nature, the
phenomenon could be described as an interpersonal resonance.
Can the Fruits be regarded as resonances? A resonance is a perfected joint
operation, matching the description of the Fruits as actus that are also
perfections, the terminating attributes of the entire network of Gifts, virtues,
and Beatitudes. An interpersonal resonance also needs at least two persons,
matching the inference that the Fruits, based on the Gifts, are intrinsically
second-personal. A resonance in joint human activity, such as musicians
playing in perfect harmony, is also pleasurable, matching Aquinas’s material
analogy of a Fruit as having “sweetness.” Finally, a resonance indicates that
some aspect of a second person is sealed or imprinted on oneself, knowledge
which is no longer mediated but immediate.57 Within the context of a piece
of music, for example, the musicians can be said to know one another
perfectly and immediately, analogous to the way in which Aquinas associates
the Fruits with having an immediate experience of God being with oneself or
even abiding in oneself.58 I therefore conclude that the Fruits, as Aquinas
describes them, can be characterized as resonances.
CONCLUSIONS
To grasp what Aquinas means by an infused or perfect virtue, it is also
important to study what he means by a Gift, a Beatitude, and a Fruit. Aquinas
claims that the seven Gifts are necessary for true human flourishing and
appends these to the theological and cardinal virtues. The twelve Fruits, by
way of the Beatitudes, are the terminating attributes of the “organic” network
of ST II-II q.1–170.
The essential characteristic of the Gifts is that they enable a person to be
“moved” by God in a second-personal manner. In other words, the Gifts
enable us to share in God’s stance toward something, in union with God in an
“I”–“You” relationship. To lack the Gifts does not preclude all knowledge of
God or interaction with God, but it is analogous to being autistic with respect
to God, so that second-personal interaction with God is inhibited. The Fruits
are the perfect actus of the Gifts and virtues. These actus also have a second-
personal basis, according to the descriptions Aquinas gives of certain Fruits
and insofar as they conclude a network of attributes in which the Gifts play a
foundational role. Those actus that are Fruits may be characterized as
interpersonal resonances, in which a person’s activity is aligned and united
perfectly with God in a harmonized manner.
It seems, therefore, that Aquinas regards infused virtue ethics as
intrinsically second-personal, both in terms of the foundations of the virtues,
in which the Gifts play an essential role, and the Fruits or interpersonal
resonances to which all perfective attributes are ordered.59
NOTES
1. ST II-II q.1–170.
2. In answering the question of how to define virtue, ST I-II q.55 a.4,
Aquinas defends the definition, “Virtue is a good quality of the mind, by
which we live righteously, of which no one can make bad use, which God
works in us, without us.” Mark Jordan has drawn attention to the fact that this
definition of virtue, the only one Aquinas sets out to defend explicitly, is
drawn from Peter Lombard’s Sentences rather than from Aristotle. This
choice is an early indication in the ST of Aquinas’s non-Aristotelian
approach to virtue in the proper or perfect sense. See Mark Jordan,
“Theology and Philosophy,” in Norman Kretzmann and Eleonore Stump,
eds., The Cambridge Companion to Aquinas (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1993), 237–41.
3. According to Aquinas, only the acquired virtues are caused in an
Aristotelian manner, that is, by repeated good actions, whereas infused
virtues, that is, virtues in the proper sense, are caused by the action of God.
See, e.g., QDVCom a.2, ad 18, in which Aquinas claims that, just as acquired
virtues are increased and fostered by the same sort of acts that caused them,
so the infused virtues are increased by the action of God, by whom they are
caused.
4. Aquinas differentiates acquired and infused justice in ST I-II q.100 a.12,
claiming that only the latter is true justice. In ST I-II q.47 a.14, he
distinguishes acquired and infused prudence. In ST I-II q.63 a.4, he describes
acquired and infused temperance as distinct species of temperance. Acquired
and infused courage are mentioned as distinct virtues in QDVCom a.10, ad
10. John Inglis, “Aquinas’s Replication of the Acquired Moral Virtues,”
Journal of Religious Ethics 27:1 (1999): 3–27, has drawn attention to
Aquinas’s introduction of infused counterparts of the acquired moral virtues
and to the need for greater study of the impact of infused virtues on
Aquinas’s ethics as a whole. Robert C. Miner, “Non-Aristotelian Prudence in
the Prima Secundae,” The Thomist 64:3 (2000): 401–22, has examined
prudence in ST I-II and argued that Aquinas’s descriptions differ strikingly
from Aristotelian phronêsis. Most of the intellectual virtues are, however,
replicated as Gifts rather than virtues (ST II-II q.8, 9, 45), a point made by
Eleonore Stump, “Wisdom: Will, Belief, and Moral Goodness,” in Scott
Charles MacDonald and Eleonore Stump, eds., Aquinas’s Moral Theory:
Essays in Honor of Norman Kretzmann (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University
Press, 1999), 48.
5. ST I-II q.65 a.2: “It is therefore clear from what has been said that only
the infused virtues are perfect, and deserve to be called virtues simply: since
they direct a person well to the ultimate end. But the other virtues, those,
namely, that are acquired, are virtues in a restricted sense, but not simply: for
they direct a person well in respect of the last end in some particular genus of
action, but not in respect of the last end simply.” Aquinas is clear, therefore,
that only the infused virtues are virtues properly speaking. This clarification
further suggests that, when Aquinas refers to a virtue without qualification,
he is referring to an infused rather than an acquired virtue.
6. In ST I-II q.63 a.4, Aquinas claims that acquired and infused virtues
differ in species, both in relation to their proper objects and to their
respective ends, “those infused moral virtues, whereby persons behave well
in respect of their being ‘fellow-citizens with the saints, and of the household
of God,’ differ from the acquired virtues, whereby a person behaves well in
respect of human affairs.” Aquinas makes a similar distinction in ST I-II q.65
a.2: “It is possible by means of human works to acquire moral virtues, in so
far as they produce good works that are directed to an end not surpassing the
natural power of man: and when they are acquired thus, they can be without
caritas, even as they were in many of the Gentiles. But in so far as they
produce good works in proportion to a supernatural last end, thus they have
the character of virtue, truly and perfectly; and cannot be acquired by human
acts, but are infused by God.”
7. Jean Porter, “The Subversion of Virtue: Acquired and Infused Virtues
in the ‘Summa theologiae,’” Annual of the Society of Christian Ethics (1992),
34. Citing ST II-II q.47 a.14, Porter points out that infused prudence is
present, according to Aquinas, in all who have grace, even those who cannot
exercise independent thought and judgment. She concludes that the infused
virtues function in a way that is significantly different from the way in which
the acquired virtues function, “so much so that they can be described as
virtues only in a carefully qualified sense” (ibid. 20).
8. Ibid. 30; Bonnie Kent, “Does Virtue Make It Easy to be Good? The
Problematic Case of St. Paul,” in Bernardo C. Bazán, Eduardo Andújar, and
Leonard G. Sbrocchi, eds., Les Philosophies morales et politiques au Moyen
Âge: Actes du IXe Congrès International de Philosophie Médiévale, Ottawa,
17–22 Août 1992 (Ottawa: Legas, 1995), 728. The article from which these
observations are taken is ST I-II q.65 a.3 ad 2: “Sometimes the habitus of
moral virtue experience difficulty in their works, by reason of certain
ordinary dispositions remaining from previous acts. This difficulty does not
occur in respect of acquired moral virtue: because the repeated acts by which
they are acquired, remove also the contrary dispositions.” See also ibid. ad 3:
“Certain saints are said not to have certain virtues, in so far as they
experience difficulty in the acts of those virtues, for the reason stated;
although they have the habitus of all the virtues.”
9. Jordan, “Theology and Philosophy,” 240, points out that Aquinas’s view
of the unity of the virtues is nuanced. If an acquired moral virtue is regarded
simply as an acquired tendency to carry out a particular kind of good action,
then such virtues are not connected, “since we find men who, by natural
temperament or by being accustomed, are prompt in doing deeds of
liberality, but are not prompt in doing deeds of chastity” (ST I-II q.65 a.1).
Infused virtues, on the other hand, are infused together with caritas and
connected on account of caritas (ST I-II q.65 a.3).
10. Jeffrey Hause, “Aquinas on the Function of Moral Virtue,” American
Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 81:1 (2007): 16. Hause’s argument is
important because Aquinas’s example of infused temperance (ST I-II q.63
a.4) seems to suggest that the difference between acquired and infused
temperance is simply that the latter is more ascetic, promoting fasting rather
than moderate consumption. From this example, it might be thought that the
infused virtues are proportionally harder or more demanding versions of the
acquired virtues. This is the understanding implied by Réginald Garrigou-
Lagrange, who exemplifies the neo-Thomist school of the first half of the
twentieth century. Garrigou-Lagrange conflates the definitions of the
acquired and infused versions of the cardinal virtues, holding that the same
definition holds proportionally for both categories. See Réginald Garrigou-
Lagrange, La Synthèse Thomiste, Bibliothèque française de philosophie
(Paris: Desclée de Brouwer, 1946), 529, 530, 532, and 536. Hause, however,
argues that such an approach cannot be correct. Acquired temperance could
also be constituted in a mean that pursues fasting and chastising. Infused and
acquired virtues must be different in kind and not merely in degree.
11. Acquired virtues imply moral and intellectual maturity, yet once a
person has achieved such maturity, she will tend, among other things, to
deliberate about herself. If this deliberation leads her to direct herself to her
due end, she will, by means of grace, receive the remission of original sin,
together with caritas and the infused virtues (ST I-II q.89 a.6). If, however, a
person does not direct himself to the due end, and as far as he is capable of
discretion at that particular age, “he will sin mortally, for through not doing
that which is in his power to do” (ST I-II q.89 a.6) and if unrepentant, he will
end in hell (ST I-II q.89 a.6; QDM, q.7, a.10, ad 10). Similarly, if he accepts
grace, and subsequently rejects it by mortal sin, he will again forfeit the
infused virtues, without necessarily losing the acquired virtues. Once again,
if he persists in mortal sin without repentance, he will end in hell. So to be in
a state of possessing only the acquired virtues is of no true benefit to the
moral agent. Indeed, to possess acquired virtues without infused virtues may
even be a sign of the rejection of grace arising from some conscious decision,
arguably a worse state than one in which a person lacks the maturity to
choose.
12. Evidence for Aquinas’s detailed appropriation of the Nicomachean
Ethics can be seen in his analysis of the structure of Aristotle’s work.
Aquinas subdivides the text into a complex nested structure with some fifteen
hundred functionally distinct parts. For an English translation of his
commentary, see St Thomas Aquinas, Commentary on Aristotle’s
Nicomachean Ethics, trans. C. I. Litzinger (Notre Dame, Ind.: Dumb Ox
Books, 1993).
13. ST II-II q.123–38.
14. Aquinas introduces the Gift of Courage in ST II-II q.139 a.1, at the
conclusion of his treatment of the virtue of courage. Since Courage and
certain other attributes have homonymous counterparts among the virtues in
Aquinas’s network, I capitalize references to the Gifts, Beatitudes, and Fruits
in this chapter to distinguish them from the virtues.
15. Aquinas devotes ST I-II q.68 a.1; q.69 a.1; and q.70 a.2 to arguments
that the virtues, Gifts, Beatitudes, and Fruits are distinct kinds of attributes
from one another.
16. Aquinas argues that courage is about difficult things and, since it is
difficult to do virtuous deeds with an insatiable desire, which may be
signified by “hunger and thirst for justice,” this Beatitude is properly
assigned to the virtue of courage (ST II-II q.139 a.2), as well as to the virtue
of justice (ST II-II q.121 a.2).
17. ST II-II q.139 a.2 ad 3.
18. Aquinas’s network is described as an “organic unity” in Servais
Pinckaers, Morality: The Catholic View (South Bend, Ind.: St. Augustine’s
Press, 2001), 87. By contrast, most commentators on the non-Aristotelian
aspects of Aquinas’s network of attributes have tended to concentrate on the
Gifts, paying little attention to the virtue-Gift-Beatitude-Fruit network as an
organic whole. The pattern of this approach was set in the seventeenth
century in a classic work by John of St. Thomas. As its title implies, John of
St. Thomas concentrates almost exclusively on the Gifts, devoting ten out of
eleven chapters to commentaries on their general or particular operations.
While he makes occasional references to the Beatitudes and Fruits in these
chapters, it is only in chapter 9 that he considers the Beatitudes as a distinct
group of qualities and it is only in the last two paragraphs that he mentions
the Fruits. For an English translation of this work, see John of St. Thomas,
The Gifts of the Holy Ghost, trans. Dominic Hughes, O.P. (New York: Sheed
& Ward, 1951).
19. In much of the ST II-II q.1–170, Aquinas does not state explicitly
whether he is describing an acquired or an infused virtue. Nevertheless, ST I-
II q.65 a.2 makes clear that “virtue” taken simply means infused virtue.
Furthermore, in ST II-II q.47 a.14, Aquinas shows that the prudence he is
examining is infused prudence, since it is infused along with grace and
caritas, in contrast to acquired prudence, the acquisition of which is “caused
by acts” and which demands “experience and time.” In ST II-II q.123, he
argues that the principal act of courage is martyrdom, involving the virtues of
faith and caritas, underlining that this is the infused rather than the acquired
virtue of courage. In ST II-II q.141 a.1 ad 2, he refers to the temperance that
he is describing, that is, the perfect sense, as not acquired through
habituation, implying that “temperance” taken simply means infused
temperance. In the case of justice, the many theological concepts Aquinas
annexes to justice, such as the act of prayer (ST II-II q.83), provide
corroborating evidence that he is examining an infused rather than an
acquired virtue. So unless Aquinas explicitly states otherwise, the cardinal
virtues of ST II-II q.1–170 appear to be the infused rather than acquired
versions of these virtues.
20. ST I-II q.55 prol. I am grateful to Fr Kevin Flannery, S.J. for the
opportunity to discuss the most appropriate way of expressing certain ideas
in Aquinas’s texts. In this passage, the term habitus is sometimes translated
as “habit” or as “disposition,” but both words are slightly misleading for the
senses in which Aquinas uses the word habitus. I have therefore left the term
untranslated.
21. The word caritas is sometimes translated as “love” or “charity.” Since,
in Aquinas’s work, caritas denotes the unique love pertaining to divine
friendship (ST II-II q.23 a.1), I have left the word untranslated.
22. The questions devoted to the specific Gifts are ST II-II q.8
(Understanding), q.9 (Knowledge), q.19 (Fear), q.45 (Wisdom), q.52
(Counsel), q.121 (Piety), and q.139 (Courage).
23. Whether Aquinas is referring to acquired or infused virtues, his claim
that the Gifts take precedence over the moral and intellectual virtues means
that the Gifts take precedence over any of the qualities described in the
Nicomachean Ethics.
24. ST I-II q.68 a.1. Descriptions of the Gifts as enabling us to be moved by
God can also be found in ST I-II q.68 a.4; II-II q.52 a.1; q.52 a.3; III q.7 a.5.
25. Aquinas argues in ST I-II q.10 a.4 that the will is not moved of
necessity by God. In whatever manner, therefore, God does cause our acts of
will (and this is a point of some debate), it is generally acknowledged that,
according to Aquinas, God’s action on the will is “not coercive” (cf. Brian J.
Shanley, “Divine Causation and Human Freedom in Aquinas,” American
Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 72:1 [1998]: 113).
26. In ST II-II q.8 a.5, Aquinas refers to the Holy Spirit enlightening the
mind without the Gifts, in regard to truths that are preambles of faith.
Nevertheless, he also states that such enlightenment, no matter how
extensive, is no substitute for movement by means of the Gift of
Understanding. He confirms this point in ST II-II q.9 a.3 ad 3, in which he
says that not everyone who understands, has the Gift of Understanding, but
only the one who understands from a habitus of grace (cf. ST II-II q.9 a.3 ad
3 on Knowledge). So what is communicated by means of the Gifts cannot be
reduced to propositions, since propositions could, in principle, be
communicated in some other way besides the Gifts.
27. ST II-II q.9 a.1 ad 1. Note that none of the cognitive Gifts are
deliberative, despite the fact that three of them share names with intellectual
virtues that pertain to discursive reasoning. The operations of the cognitive
Gifts are, therefore, consistent with understanding them as enabling
participation in God’s absolute, “simple” cognition.
28. In ST II-II q.121 a.1, Aquinas describes the Gift of Piety as moving us
to have a filial affection toward God, and, as a consequence, to pay
veneration and service to all people on account of their relationship to God.
29. ST II-II q.139 a.1. The Gift of Courage could be said to “cement” the
virtue of courage, because the virtue adequate for current difficulties might
still be feared inadequate for hypothetical future difficulties. The Gift,
however, enables a sharing in God’s standpoint, a confidence that any future
challenge can also be overcome with divine assistance.
30. In ST II-II q.19 a.9, Aquinas describes the Gift of Fear as moving us to
revere God and avoid separating ourselves from him. This Gift enables “filial
fear,” the kind of fear a child has to disappoint a father whom he loves, not
the fear of loss or pain for oneself, which is “servile fear” (ST II-II q.19 a.5).
So the Gift of Fear disposes one to shrink from separation from God, not
from the point of view of one’s own good as desired by oneself, but from the
point of view of one’s own good as desired by God with whom one is united
by caritas.
31. ST II-II q.52 a.1 ad 1.
32. ST II-II q.8 a.4. The relational aspect of the Gift of Understanding is a
point of distinction between the Gift and the homonymous virtue.
33. ST II-II q.45 a.2.
34. ST II-II q.45 a.3.
35. ST I-II q.68 a.5.
36. Naomi Eilan, “Joint Attention, Communication, and Mind,” in Naomi
Eilan et al., eds., Joint Attention: Communication and Other Minds: Issues in
Philosophy and Psychology (New York: Oxford University Press, 2005), 1.
37. Peter Hobson, “What Puts Jointness into Joint Attention?” in Eilan et
al., eds., Joint Attention, 185. Hobson is a professor of developmental
psychopathology who has developed experiments to study joint attention and
autism.
38. Ibid. 200.
39. An autistic child is, therefore, able to respond to another person in
Darwall’s sense of the “second-person standpoint,” that is, “the perspective
that you and I take up when we make and acknowledge claims on one
another’s conduct and will.” See Stephen Darwall, The Second-Person
Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability (Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press, 2006). For an introduction to the main ideas and
examples from everyday life, see pp. 3–38. Douglas Lavin has provided a
helpful review and critique of Darwall’s thesis for the Notre Dame
Philosophical Review, January 2008.
40. Such findings are consistent with other symptoms of autism in young
children, such as a failure to follow the gaze of an adult toward an object,
failing, in other words, to appropriate and track a second person’s stance.
41. Cf. ST II-II q.47 a.14 ad 3.
42. Leo Kanner, “Autistic Disturbances of Affective Contact,” Nervous
Child 2:220 (1943); reprinted in Acta Paedopsychiatrica 35:4 (1968): 100–
36.
43. For a comparison of pronoun reversal in autistic and Down syndrome
children, see, e.g., Helen Tager-Flusberg, “Dissociations in Form and
Function in the Acquisition of Language by Autistic Children: Studies of
Atypical Children,” in Helen Tager-Flusberg, ed., Constraints on Language
Acquisition (Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum, 1994), 184.
44. Johannes Roessler, “Joint Attention and the Problem of Other Minds,”
in Eilan et al., eds., Joint Attention, 247.
45. ST II-II q.23 a.1; see also, e.g., QDC, q.2, a.4, ad 11; q.2 a.8, ad 16 and
QDM, q.5, a.5. The centrality of friendship with God as a principle of
Aquinas’s work highlights another distinction between the virtue ethics of
Aquinas and that of Aristotle. Although Aristotle suggests the possibility of
attaining a kind of similitude of divine activity, he denies that a human being
can be friends with any god. See Nicomachean Ethics, X, 8, 1159a3–9.
46. ST I-II q.70 a.1.
47. ST I-II q.11 a.3.
48. Aquinas argues, e.g., that certain specific Fruits, such as Joy and Peace,
are operationes and not virtues (ST II-II q.28 a.4; q.29 a.4).
49. In Gal, 5.6. Regarding terminology, Aquinas uses the word actus, e.g.,
when he argues that Joy and Peace are actus of caritas, and when he
describes a Fruit as an actus of virtue rather than a virtue (ST II-II q.28 a.4).
Aquinas uses the word operatio, e.g., when he argues that Counsel has no
assigned Fruit (ST II-II q.52 a.4 ad 3) and when he describes a Fruit as a kind
of perfect operatio (In Gal, 5.6). Sometimes Aquinas will use the term opus,
when, for example, he describes the Fruits as opera of the virtues and of the
Spirit (opera virtutum et spiritus) (In Gal, 5.6). As the usual translations
(such as “act,” “operation,” or “work”) can be misleading when discussing
the Fruits, I have not translated these words, especially as the determination
of the nature of the Fruits is one of the goals of the chapter.
50. ST II-II q.29 a.3.
51. In ST II-II q.29 a.3, Aquinas is principally referring to the alignment
involved in the friendship of two human persons, but caritas also signifies
friendship with God (I-II q.65 a.5), implying that the Peace involved in the
love of God is also a kind of alignment.
52. ST II-II q.28 a.1; ST II-II q.27 a.2.
53. In ST I-II q.52 a.4, Aquinas assigns no Fruits to the Gift of Counsel,
even though Counsel helps direct or bring about the actions of other Fruits,
such as Goodness and Benignity. Counsel is, therefore, an instance of a Gift
for which the corresponding actus are not Fruits.
54. In the case of Peace, e.g., the Beatitude of Peacemaking precedes the
Fruit of Peace (ST II-II q.45 a.6).
55. Dante Alighieri, The Divine Comedy, trans. Henry Wadsworth
Longfellow (Boston, 1867), Paradiso, Canto XIII, 19–21.
56. When a playground swing, e.g., is given a periodic push at a certain
frequency, the natural frequency of the swing, it is very easy to make the
swing go higher. In the terminology of the physical sciences, the two
systems, the swing and the person pushing, are said to be in resonance.
57. The notion of resonance and habitus matching is also hinted at by
Aquinas’s description of the Fruit of Benignity. Aquinas twice explains that
“Benignity” means “good fire” (bonus ignis), one by which a person “melts”
to relieve the needs of others (ST I-II q.70 a.3; In Gal, 5.6). Given that a
“good fire” is also one of the most common symbols of the Holy Spirit,
Aquinas seems to imply that the person becomes like God in the manner in
which she loves others.
58. ST II-II q.29 a.3; ST I-II q.65 a.5.
59. I am most grateful to Eleonore Stump and Brian Davies for reviewing
earlier drafts of this chapter. I also thank Theodore Vitali for encouraging me
to pursue research in this field. I explore these issues in more detail in a
forthcoming book, The Second-Person Perspective in Aquinas’s Ethics:
Virtues and Gifts (Routledge, 2012).
PART VIII
GIORGIO PINI
It is a clear sign of the subtle intelligence and certain judgment of this admirable and
memorable teacher, brother Thomas Aquinas, that, after he became a master of theology,
when teaching or writing, he did not change the original views and arguments he had
endorsed as a bachelor, except in a few cases. By contrast, we modern authors, as suits
people of uncertain and doubtful judgment, change the views we once endorsed any time
an objection is raised against them, no matter how weak.1
It is not sure whether Giles of Rome actually uttered these words. But the
claim attributed to him is fairly accurate. Even though Aquinas’s teaching
stretched over a period of twenty years, his thought is remarkably consistent.
Indeed, some events may have caused him to refine his opinions on a few
topics. For example, his direct confrontation with Averroës’s followers
around 1270 may have induced him to reconsider a few issues in his theory
of the soul and cognitive psychology.2 And it has been suggested that his
increasingly critical attitude toward Maimonides may have resulted in a more
nuanced endorsement of negative theology.3 Furthermore, Aquinas’s
relatively late exposure to some important theological and philosophical
writings left a mark in the development of his thought. For example, in 1268
William of Moerbeke’s translation of Proclus’s Elements of Theology
(Elementatio theologica) gave new impetus to Aquinas’s understanding of
Neoplatonism.4 Also, Aquinas’s exposure to the proceedings of ancient
ecumenical councils at the papal court in 1261–65, and more specifically the
proceedings of the Council of Chalcedon, is likely to have influenced the
development of his views on Christ.5 As a final example, Aquinas’s reading
in the 1260s of two of Augustine’s late writings, On the Predestination of the
Saints (De praedestinatione sanctorum) and On the Gift of Perseverance (De
dono perseverantiae), probably played a key role in the development of his
views on grace and merit.6 With the possible exception of the last case,
however, none of these events and readings resulted in a major shift in
Aquinas’s thought.
Accordingly, it is not surprising that Aquinas has often been presented as
a monolithic figure, whose system leaped fully formed from his head. The
very possibility of development has sometimes been rejected as an attempt to
diminish the perfection of Aquinas’s achievement. This attitude may have
been fostered by the understandable and deeply entrenched tendency to
regard the Summa theologiae as the standard or even the only place to look
for Aquinas’s opinion about any given topic. It is quite clear, however, that it
would be unfair, to say the least, to dismiss such masterpieces as his
commentary on the Sentences and the questions De veritate as merely
youthful works—not to speak of the Summa contra Gentiles, the Aristotelian
commentaries and the later disputed questions, most notably De Potentia and
De malo. Once these and other writings are taken into account, it is difficult
to escape the conclusion that Aquinas’s thought did develop and that he did
change his mind about a number of topics. What is more, the view of
Aquinas’s unhesitatingly embracing a certain opinion at the beginning of his
career and sticking to it in all his writings does not fit with what can be
gathered from the autograph of two of his works, namely the third book of
his commentary on the Sentences and the Summa contra Gentiles. As
emerges from the study of those portions of these works that are still extant
in his handwriting, in many cases Aquinas revised and rewrote up to four
times what he had originally written.7 Many of these revisions cannot be
dismissed as merely cosmetic improvements. Rather, they allow us to get a
glimpse at Aquinas’s hesitations and developments about some key topics in
his thought.
Aquinas himself explicitly claimed to have changed opinion about at least
three issues, namely, Christ’s acquired knowledge, the effects of the
Empyrean Heaven on other bodies, and the healing effects of circumcision
before Christ’s incarnation.8 But several other instances have long been
known to both Aquinas’s adversaries and followers and have been
investigated by modern interpreters.
The most remarkable and still most useful tool to investigate the
development of Aquinas’s thinking is the list compiled by some members of
the Dominican order around 1280 to indicate several topics about which
Aquinas changed his mind between writing his early commentary on the
Sentences to drafting his later works. To the original 32 topics listed in 1280,
some more were added in the following years to arrive at a total of 80 topics
about which Aquinas held a “better opinion” in the Summa than in the
Sentences.9
I will not here give an exhaustive treatment of all or even the most
important topics about which Aquinas changed his mind. Rather, I intend to
document the evolution of Aquinas’s thought by focusing on four cases and
merely mentioning a few other shifts in Aquinas’s views. Most of the cases I
will take into consideration have both a theological and a philosophical side.
The two criteria I have followed in my selection are, first, that the evidence
for Aquinas’s change of mind is textually solid and generally undisputed
among modern interpreters and, second, that the topics addressed are
particularly significant from a philosophical and/or a theological point of
view.
MENTAL WORDS
An important and particularly well-documented development in Aquinas’s
thought concerns the notion of mental word.25
This shift has both a theological and a philosophical side to it. With regard
to the theological side, in his commentary on the Sentences Aquinas held that
the term “word” can be said both personally and essentially of the Trinity. In
the first sense, the term “word” refers exclusively to the second person of the
Trinity. In the second sense, the term “word” refers to the divine essence. It
is this second sense that is controversial. Aquinas illustrated this point by a
parallelism with human intellectual cognition. According to Aquinas’s earlier
position, there are only two items involved in human intellectual cognition in
addition to the object of thought. First, there is an intelligible species that
makes the intellect actual with regard to the cognition of a certain object and
provides the content of thought. Second, there is the act of thinking itself,
that is, the activity that the intellect carries out once it has been actualized by
the intelligible species. For example, suppose that I am thinking about what a
horse is (i.e., the essence of horses). According to Aquinas’s account in the
Sentences, this intellectual activity can be analyzed into the presence of the
intelligible species that my intellect abstracts from sensory images of horses,
on the one hand, and, on the other hand, my intellect’s act of thinking about
what a horse is. Since these are the only two elements into which thinking
can be broken down, when we apply the term “word” to the activity of
human cognition we may be referring to either the intelligible species or the
act of thinking (Aquinas leaves this option open). As far as God’s intellectual
activity is concerned, however, there is neither an intelligible species nor an
act of thinking distinct from the divine essence itself, due to God’s
simplicity. As a consequence, when applied to God, if the term “word” is
taken to refer to God’s intellectual activity, that term is said essentially of
God, that is, it refers to the entire divine essence and not only to the second
person of the Trinity, since God’s intellectual activity is identical with his
essence.26
Some years afterwards, however, Aquinas became dissatisfied with this
view both theologically and philosophically. The process through which he
reached his mature position was particularly tortured. Some elements of a
new solution can already be found in De veritate, q.4, a.2. But Aquinas’s
mature view emerged only after he drafted a key chapter of the Summa
contra Gentiles no fewer than three times between 1259 and 1264–65.27 By
the time he completes the fourth book of the Summa contra Gentiles, the
questions De Potentia, the first part of the Summa theologiae and the
commentary on St. John’s Gospel, the contours of Aquinas’s definitive
position are clear.28 From a theological point of view, Aquinas rejects the
view that the term “word” can be said of the entire divine essence. Rather,
there is only one sense of the term “word,” and that is the personal sense by
which that term refers only to the second person of the Trinity.29 From a
philosophical point of view, Aquinas rejects the view that the process of
human cognition can be analyzed into only two elements, that is, the
intelligible species and the act of thinking. He now adds a third factor,
namely, a concept (conceptio) produced by the act of thinking. Thus, when I
think about what a horse is, in addition to the object I am thinking about,
there is, first, an intelligible species abstracted from sensory images of
horses; second, there is my intellect’s act of thinking; and finally, there is
also a concept produced by my act of thinking. It is this concept that is called
a “mental word.” To think about something is to produce a concept of that
thing.30
The difference between Aquinas’s first and second account of the process
of intellectual cognition can also be expressed in the following terms. Both in
his earlier and in his later account, Aquinas held that acts of thinking are
what he called “immanent actions,” that is, actions that do not produce
effects distinct from the agents that perform those actions. In that respect,
thinking is different from actions such as building, which produces houses,
and heating, which results in something’s becoming hot. So far, Aquinas did
not change his mind. But whereas in his earlier account he held that thinking
is an action that does not produce anything at all, in his later account he
claims that thinking is an action that produces a result distinct from the
process of thinking, that is, a concept or inner word. That concept or inner
word, however, does not get outside the intellect. As a consequence, Aquinas
can still claim that thinking is an immanent action, but the reason is not that
the act of thinking produces nothing, as he had previously claimed, but that
its product remains within the intellect.
Possibly the most significant philosophical outcome of Aquinas’s new
position on mental words is that he can now introduce a more stringent
parallelism between acts of thinking and natural actions. In both cases, an
agent produces something. Just as the act of building produces a house, so
the act of thinking produces a concept. When considered as a productive act,
an act of thinking can be compared more easily to natural actions such as
heating and cooling and thus be interpreted within the framework of natural
philosophy.31
ANALOGY
Some modern interpreters have called attention to a significant development
in Aquinas’s treatment of analogy and the relation of likeness holding
between creatures and God.32 How can we account for our predicating of
God terms such as “being,” “good,” “wise,” and so on? Aquinas’s answer
was that we can do so because, in some respect, creatures are like God. All
along his career, Aquinas’s constant effort was to account for the relationship
of likeness linking the created world to God while at the same time
contending that there is no common feature shared by both God and
creatures. Because there is a similitude between creatures and God, it is
possible to attribute to God some terms that are ordinarily attributed to
creatures (such as “being,” “good,” “wise,” and the like). Because there is no
common feature between God and creatures, however, these terms do not
have exactly the same meaning when applied to God and when applied to
creatures.33
Granted that Aquinas always subscribed to these claims, it is possible to
distinguish three stages in his understanding of analogy.34
First, in his commentary on the Sentences, Aquinas distinguished between
two kinds of analogy. The first kind of analogy is grounded on a relationship
between two (or more) things that share the same feature according to
different degrees. The second kind of analogy is grounded on the relationship
holding between two (or more) things of which one imitates the other within
the limits of its own essence even though there is no common feature shared
by both the imitating and the imitated thing. According to Aquinas’s earlier
view, the first kind of analogy holds among all created things, which all share
the same feature (i.e., being), even though some things (i.e., accidents) are
beings only because they inhere in other things (i.e., substances). By contrast,
the second kind of analogy holds between creatures and God. Creatures
imitate God within the limits of their own nature and are therefore like God
in some respect. Notwithstanding this likeness between creatures and God,
however, there is no common feature shared by both God and creatures.
Aquinas assumed as primitive the relation of imitation on which the analogy
between God and creatures is grounded and did not make any attempt to
explain it.35
Second, in his De veritate, Aquinas adopted a unique view. He rejected
the position he had previously endorsed, according to which creatures are
directly related to God by a primitive relation of imitation. By contrast, he
argued that no relation can directly tie creatures and God, because the
distance between creatures and God is infinite, and any relation holding
between two things presupposes that there is a determined, that is,
measurable and finite, distance between them. Thus, to say that creatures and
God are directly related to each other would entail that there is a finite
distance between creatures and God. But if there were a finite distance
between creatures and God, God would be one of the things of this world.
This would just eliminate God’s transcendence. In order to avoid this result,
Aquinas posited a peculiar kind of analogy, which is based not on a relation
holding between two things but between two proportions. Aquinas called the
relation on which this second kind of analogy is based “agreement of
proportionality” (convenientia proportionalitatis) and contrasted it to the
relation holding between two or more things, which he called “agreement of
proportion” (convenientia proportionis). For example, the number six is
related to the number three just as the number four is related to the number
two. Six and three, on the one hand, and four and two, on the other hand, are
related to each other by the relation of “being the double of.” This relation,
however, holds between two proportions. The terms of each proportion are
not directly related to each other. Similarly, sight is related to the body just as
the intellect is related to the soul, and a pilot is related to a ship just as a
prince is related to a city. Sight is in some way similar to the intellect, but
only by virtue of sight’s being related to the body and the intellect’s being
similarly related to the soul. Sight and intellect are not similar to each other
by virtue of any intrinsic property present in either sight or the intellect. The
same holds for a pilot and a prince. Aquinas contended that the analogy
holding between creatures and God is of this kind. For example, God’s
goodness is related to God’s infinite being just as a creature’s goodness is
related to that creature’s finite being. A creature’s goodness, however, is not
directly related to God’s goodness. In this way, Aquinas could give a detailed
analysis of the relation of imitation, which he had previously assumed as
primitive in his commentary on the Sentences. That creatures imitate God
within the limits of their essence only means that the properties of creatures
are related to their being just as God’s attributes are related to his being. This
solution, however, came at a very high cost. Aquinas had to give up the view
that there is any direct relationship holding between creatures and God. As
several commentators have noted, this comes very close to saying that there
is complete equivocity between what we say of creatures and what we say of
God.36
Third and finally, in his most mature works, Aquinas recovers his first
idea that there is a relation holding directly between creatures and God.
Contrary to what he had done in the Sentences, however, he now gives an
analysis of the relation by which each creature is directly linked to God.
Creatures are related to God and imitate God because they are caused by
God. Specifically, Aquinas holds that it is efficient causality that grounds the
relationship of likeness holding between creatures and God. He now
recognizes that the relation of likeness between creatures and God is just a
consequence of the principle according to which every agent produces
something like itself (omne agens agit sibi simile). This principle holds even
when no common feature is shared by the agent and its effect.37 Furthermore,
Aquinas can now give a unified account of the analogy holding among
creatures, on the one hand, and between creatures and God, on the other
hand. With regard to the former sort of analogy, there is no common feature
shared by accidents and substances. Contrary to what he had previously
claimed, Aquinas now thinks that being is not a common feature shared by
created things.38 All the same, accidents are attributed to substances as to
their cause (presumably, their efficient and material cause). Similarly, with
regard to the latter analogy, there is no feature common to both creatures and
God. All the same, creatures are in some way like God because they are
caused by God. As a consequence of this likeness, terms such as “being,”
“good,” “wise,” and the like, can be literally (i.e., nonmetaphorically)
predicated of both creatures and God.
OTHER ISSUES
There are several other issues about which Aquinas’s thought evolved. Here I
will list only a few cases.47
(1) Whether God can communicate the power to create to his creatures. In
his commentary on the Sentences, Aquinas claimed that God can
communicate to creatures the power to create by virtue of his own
causality, that is, as instruments of his action. Aquinas noticed that it is
in this way that some philosophers (e.g., Avicenna) thought that
separated substances create something. Aquinas remarked that this
position is heretical. But at that stage of his career, he did not seem to
have any philosophical objection to it. In his later works, however,
Aquinas rejects the view that creatures can be given the power to create,
even if only as instruments of God’s causality, on the ground that to
create is to give being, and being is God’s proper effect.48
(2) Whether there is a divine idea of prime matter distinct from the idea of
composites of matter and form. In the Sentences, Aquinas claimed that
there is such an idea. In the Summa theologiae, he argues that there is
not.49
(3) Whether pain is located in the senses (and specifically in touch) or in
the soul (and specifically in that part of the soul that Aristotle called
“appetitive,” which is connected with bodily desires). In the Sentences,
Aquinas claimed that pain is located in touch. In the Summa theologiae,
he argues that pain is located in the appetitive soul.50
(4) Whether God can dispense human beings from the commandments
contained in the second tablet (i.e., those commandments that do not
concern our dealings with God but our dealings with other human
beings). In his commentary on the Sentences, Aquinas argued that God
can dispense us from obedience from the commandments contained in
the second tablet. In the Summa theologiae, he argues that this is
impossible.51
(5) Whether Christ’s resurrection is the cause of human salvation. In his
commentary on the Sentences, Aquinas held the traditional view that
Christ’s resurrection plays no causal role in human salvation, for
salvation is caused directly by the divine essence. In the Summa
theologiae, however, he adopts the novel view that Christ’s resurrection
is not only an example but the genuine cause of our own salvation.52
(6) How charity increases when the body is reunited with the soul after
resurrection. In the Sentences, Aquinas held that after resurrection
charity increases both intensively and extensively. In the Summa
theologiae, he claims that after resurrection charity increases only
extensively, not intensively.53
CONCLUSION
As I have said at the beginning of this chapter, Aquinas’s thought is
remarkably consistent. Any suggestion that Aquinas may have changed his
mind about a certain topic should be assessed with extreme care. Sometimes,
this suggestion does not stand the test of an attentive consideration of
Aquinas’s writings. A case in point is Aquinas’s alleged passage from an
intellectualist to a voluntaristic position in his theory of the will. This
hypothesis, once popular among scholars, is most probably one to be
rejected.54 More often than not, however, students of Aquinas (probably
because of a misplaced urge to defend their master) have refused to
contemplate the very possibility that Aquinas ever changed his mind about
any topic whatsoever. This attitude, however, clashes with textual evidence.
As well known already to his contemporaries and first interpreters, Aquinas
did change his mind about a certain number of topics. When taken together,
these changes do not amount to any major turn or reversal in Aquinas’s
thought. Nevertheless, each one of them deserves careful consideration. As
once remarked by Cajetan (possibly the most enthusiastic and influential
among Aquinas’s interpreters), it is not detrimental on Aquinas’s dignity to
have reached his definitive view only step by step, because “it is natural for
the human intellect to be perfected in the course of time.”55
NOTES
1. William of Tocco, Ystoria sancti Thome de Aquino de Guillaume de
Tocco (1323), ed. Claire le Brun-Gouanvic (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of
Mediaeval Studies, 1996), 170. I have adopted the following chronology of
Aquinas’s writings: Scriptum super libros Sententiarum (= Super Sent):
1252–56; Quaestiones disputatae De Veritate (= QDV): 1256–59; Expositio
in librum Boethii De trinitate (= In BDT): 1257–58/59; Summa contra
Gentiles (= SCG): 1259/60–64/65; Quaestiones disputatae De Potentia (=
QDP): 1265–66; Quaestiones de disputata anima (= QDA): 1266–67;
Sententia Libri De anima (= In DA): 1267–68; Quaestio disputata De
spiritualibus creaturis (= QDSC): 1267–68; Summa theologiae (= ST) I:
1265/66–68; I-II: 1271; II-II: 1271–72; III, incomplete: 1272–73;
Quaestiones de quodlibet I–XII (= Quodl) I: 1269; II: 1269; III: 1270; VI:
1270; XII: 1272; Sententia super Metaphysicam (= In Meta): 1270–72;
Quaestio disputata De unione verbi incarnati (= QDUVI): 1272. Unless
otherwise indicated, the translations from Aquinas’s writings are my own.
2. J.-P. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, vol. 1, The Person and His Work,
rev. ed., trans. Robert Royal (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of
America Press, 1996), 191–96.
3. J. F. Wippel, Metaphysical Themes in Thomas Aquinas (Washington,
D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 1984), 229–40; “Thomas
Aquinas on What Philosophers Can Know about God,” American Catholic
Philosophical Quarterly 66 (1992): 279–97, esp. 286–88; The Metaphysical
Thought of Thomas Aquinas: From Finite Being to Uncreated Being
(Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 2000), 540–41.
4. Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 221–22.
5. G. Geenen, “En marge du Concile de Chalcédoine: Les textes du
quatrième Concile dans les oeuvres de S. Thomas,” Angelicum 19 (1952):
43–59; “Doctrinae concilii Chalcedonensis usus et influxus in theologia S.
Thomas Aquinatis,” Divus Thomas (Pl.) 56 (1953): 319–42; D. Ols, Le
cristologie contemporanee e le loro posizioni fondamentali al vaglio della
dottrina di S. Tommaso (Città del Vaticano: Libreria Editrice Vaticana,
1991), 161–62, n. 17.
6. H. Bouillard, Conversion et grace chez S. Thomas d’Aquin: Étude
historique (Paris: Aubier, 1944), 92–122; J. P. Wawrykow, God’s Grace and
Human Action: “Merit” in the Theology of Thomas Aquinas (Notre Dame,
Ind. and London: University of Notre Dame Press, 1995), 266–76.
7. P.-M. Gils, “Textes inédits de S. Thomas: Les Premières Redactions du
Scriptum super Tertio Sententiarum,” Revue des sciences philosophiques et
théologiques 45 (1961): 201–28; 46 (1962): 445–62 and 609–28; “S. Thomas
écrivain,” in Sancti Thomae de Aquino Super Boetii De Trinitate. Expositio
libri Boetii de hebdomadibus, Opera omnia, 50, Commissio Leonina, Rome
and Les Éditions du Cerf (Paris, 1992), 173–209, esp. 191–209.
8. On Christ’s knowledge, ST III q.9 a.4: “And thus, although elsewhere I
wrote differently (quamvis aliter alibi scripserim), it must be said that in
Christ there was acquired knowledge”; and q.12,a.2: “Therefore, if in the
soul of Christ there were no habit of acquired knowledge in addition to the
habit of infused knowledge, as it seems to some and sometime seemed to me
(ut quibusdam videtur, et mihi aliquando visum est).” On the Empyrean
Heaven, Quodl 6, q.11, art. un. [19]: “some think that the Empyrean Heaven
has no influence on the other bodies.… And so at some time it seemed to me
(Et hoc quidem mihi aliquando visum est).” On circumcision, ST III q.62 a.6
ad 3: “And thus others say that circumcision conferred grace also with regard
to a certain positive effect, namely by making human beings worthy of
eternal life, but not so as to repress the concupiscence that makes human
beings prone to sin. And so at one time it seemed to me (Quod aliquando
mihi visum est).” See Ols, Le Cristologie, 160–61; T. Litt, Les Corps célestes
dans l’univers de saint Thomas d’Aquin (Louvain and Paris: Publications
universitaires and Béatrice-Nauwelaerts, 1963), 260, n. 2. I wish to thank
Adriano Oliva and Ruedi Imbach for these indications.
9. R.-A. Gauthier, “Les ‘Articuli in quibus frater Thomas melius in
Summa quam in Scriptis,’” Recherches de théologie ancienne et médievale
19 (1952): 271–326. This list of topics was known as “Articles in which
brother Thomas held a better opinion in his Summa than in his Commentary
on the Sentences” (Articuli in quibus frater Thomas melius in Summa quam
in Scriptis” [= Articuli]). For other concordances and similar documents, see
ibid. 292–93.
10. Super Sent II, d.20, q.2, a.2, ad 3; Super Sent III, d.31, q.2, a.4; QDV,
q.10, a.2, ad 7; q.10, a.8, ad 1; SCG II, 73; ST I q.84 a.7; q.85 a.1; Quodl XII,
q.9, a.1. See R. Pasnau, Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature: A Philosophical
Study of Summa theologiae Ia 75–89 (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2002), 278–95.
11. In what follows, I focus exclusively on the acquisition of simple
concepts such as the concept horse, the concept human being, etc., and on the
acts of understanding and thinking about the real essences that correspond to
those concepts. Aquinas referred to these acts as actus intelligendi or
intellectiones and he used the verb intelligere to indicate the intellect’s
operation of performing those acts. I translate these expressions by “acts of
thinking” and “thinking.” “Acts of understanding” and “understanding” are
also possible translations.
12. QDV, q.10, a.2, ad 4; q.19, ad 1; SCG II, 74; ST I q.79 a.6 ad 3; Quodl
III, q.9, a.1.
13. Articuli, art. 29, in Gauthier, “Les ‘Articuli in quibus,’” 312–13.
14. Super Sent III, d.14, q.1, a.3, qla 5: “Christ’s knowledge never
increased with regard to the kind of cognition he had … nor did it increase
with regard to the number of things He knew, because from the first instant
of His conception He knew all that pertains to such knowledge. But [Christ’s
knowledge] increased with regard to the mode of certitude”; d.18, a.1, ad 5:
“it must be said that Christ did not have any knowledge received from the
senses; rather, He had infused knowledge.” See Ols, Le Cristologie, 154–56;
J.-P. Torrell, Recherches thomasiennes: Études revues et augmentés (Paris:
Vrin, 2000), 202, n. 1.
15. Super Sent III, d.14, q.1, a.3, qla 5, ad 3: “by virtue of the light of the
agent intellect, no new species was received in His possible intellect; rather,
there occurred a new turning back to the species that were already in His
imagination, just as it happens to somebody who already has the habit of
knowledge with regard to what he imagines or sees.”
16. ST III q.9 a.4: “Thus is it necessary to say that in Christ there were
some intelligible species received in the possible intellect by the action of the
agent intellect—which is just to say that in Him there was acquired
knowledge, which some call ‘experiential knowledge’”; q.12 a.2: “Christ is
thought to have acquired knowledge … because of what is fitting to the agent
intellect, so that its action, which is to make things actually intelligible, will
not be useless.” Aquinas started questioning his earlier position already in
QDV, q.20, a.3. See Ols, Le cristologie, 156–59. Of course, the question of
acquired versus infused knowledge only concerns Christ as a human being,
not Christ as God.
17. See above, note 8.
18. Torrell, Recherches thomasiennes, 202. By “knowledge” I refer here to
knowledge of essences. Thus, the point is not whether Christ learned that a.d.
January 20, 30 was a sunny day. Rather, the question is whether Christ
learned what a horse is, what a dog is, and so on. See above, note 11.
19. Super Sent III, d.31, q.2, a.4; Super Sent IV, d.50, q.1, a.1; QDV, q.19,
a.1; SCG II, 80–81; QDA, q.15; ST I q.89 a.1; ST I-II q.67 a.2; Quodl III, q.9,
a.1.
20. Super Sent III, d.31, q.2, a.4: “Therefore, a soul separated from its body
will still retain its nature, but will lose its actual union with a body. And thus
that soul, considered just in its nature, will need no sensory image in order to
consider what it already knew [before being separated from the body].
Rather, it will need sensory images only in order to consider those things that
it must learn for the first time. And thus, [that soul] will be able to consider
those things that it already knew not by using a sensory image, but by virtue
of the habit of knowledge that it acquired previously.… For to say that a soul,
in accordance with what now that soul has in its nature, won’t be able to
think at all without its body, is a claim typical of those who hold that the soul
ceases to exist with the body, because, as is said in the first book of On the
Soul, if none of the soul’s operation can exist without the body, then the soul
itself could not exist without the body, since natural operations follows
nature.”
21. QDV, q.19, a.1: “But when the soul will be separated from the body,
just as it will have its being neither dependent on the body nor existing in the
body, so, too, it will receive an influx of intellectual cognition in such a way
that it will neither be confined to the body, as though it had to be exercised
through the body, nor will it have any ordination to the body at all.
Therefore, when at its creation the soul is infused in the body, the only
intellectual cognition that is given it is ordained to the powers of the body.
Thus, through the agent intellect it can make sensory images that are only
potentially intelligible actually intelligible, and through the possible intellect
it can receive the intelligible species thus abstracted. And this is also the
reason why, as long as it has being united to the body in the state of this life,
it does not know even those things whose species are preserved in it except
by insight into sensory images.… But when it will have its being free of the
body, then it will receive the influx of intellectual cognition in the way in
which angels receive it, without any ordination to the body. Thus, it will
receive species of things from God Himself, and it won’t be necessary to turn
back to any image in order to actually think by virtue of those species or of
those that it acquired previously.” The English translation is taken, with some
modification, from St. Thomas Aquinas, Truth, vol. 2, trans. J. V. McGlynn
(Chicago: Henry Regnery Company, 1953), 390. See also SCG II, 81.
22. ST I q.89 a.1: “Therefore with respect to the mode of existence by
which the soul is united to a body, the appropriate mode of thinking for the
soul is to turn toward the sensory image of bodies, sensory images that exist
within bodily organs. But once it has been separated from its body, the
appropriate mode of thinking for the soul is to turn toward intelligible things
straightaway—just as is appropriate for other separate substances. So turning
toward sensory images is, for the soul, its natural mode of thinking, just as
being united to a body is natural. But being separated from its body is foreign
to the character of its nature, and thinking without turning toward sensory
images is likewise foreign to its nature. So it is united to a body in order to
exist and operate in keeping with its nature.” The English translation is taken,
with a few modifications, from Thomas Aquinas, The Treatise on Human
Nature: Summa Theologiae 1a 75–89, trans. Robert Pasnau (Indianapolis
and Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company, 2002), 205–6.
23. Ibid.: “One need to consider, then, that although thinking by turning
toward higher things is in itself loftier than thinking by turning toward
sensory images, still that first mode of thinking was less perfect considered
as it was possible for the soul.” (Pasnau’s translation with some
modifications.) Aquinas had already anticipated this position in QDA, q.15,
where he had granted that the knowledge obtained by separated souls is not
as good and precise as that obtained by way of sensory images. Contrary to
what he would say in ST, however, in QDA Aquinas still maintained that
separated souls do not need any supernatural help to think without sensory
images. The QDA are thought to precede immediately or be roughly
contemporary to the first part of ST.
24. Possibly connected to the role of sensory images in human cognition is
the question whether it is possible to see God in this life without the light of
glory (lumen gloriae). In QDV, q.10, a.11, Aquinas held that this is possible.
By contrast, in ST II-II q.175 a.3 ad 2, he argued that this is not possible,
because the human intellect can be actualized only by an intelligible species
abstracted from a sensory image; as a consequence, the human intellect
cannot be actualized directly by God, as is the case in the beatific vision,
without being supernaturally predisposed by the light of glory, which
replaces the agent intellect’s act of abstraction. See Articuli, art. 75 in
Gauthier “Les ‘Articuli in quibus,’” 325.
25. H. Paissac, Théologie du Verbe: Saint Augustine et saint Thomas
(Paris: Éditions du Cerf, 1951), 117–218; A. F. von Gunten, “In principio
erat verbum: Une évolution de saint Thomas en théologie trinitaire,” in C.-J.
Pinto de Oliveira, ed., Ordo Sapientiae et Amoris: Hommage au Professeur
Jean-Pierre Torrell OP à l’occasion de son 65e anniversaire (Fribourg,
Suisse: Éditions universitaires, 1993), 119–41; Articuli, art. 8, in Gauthier,
“Les ‘Articuli in quibus,’” 303.
26. Super Sent I, d.27, q.2, a.2, qla 1. In addition to the studies indicated in
the previous note, see J. Chênevert, “Le Verbum dans le Commentaire sur le
Sentences de Saint Thomas d’Aquin,” Sciences ecclésiastiques 13 (1961):
191–233; 359–90. There are two versions of the relevant part of this
question. See von Gunten “In principio erat verbum,” 212–28; A. Oliva, Les
débuts de l’enseignement de Thomas d’Aquin et sa conception de la sacra
doctrina, avec l’édition du prologue de son commentaire des Sentences
(Paris: Vrin, 2006), 123–29.
27. SCG I, 53. The third and definitive version is the one printed in the
editions of the SCG commonly available. The first and second versions are
given in the appendix to vol. 13 of the Leonine edition, 20*–21*. See L.-B.
Geiger, “Les rédactions successives de Contra Gentiles I, 53 d’après
l’autographe,” in Saint Thomas d’Aquin aujourd’hui (Paris: Desclée de
Brouwer, 1963), 221–40.
28. SCG IV, 11; QDP, q.8, a.1; q.9, a.5; ST I q.27 a.1 and a.2; q.28 a.4 ad
1; q.34 a.1; q.85 a.2 ad 3; Super Johan I, 1.
29. According to Roger Marston’s testimony, the position Aquinas held in
the commentary on the Sentences was excommunicated around 1271–72 in
the course of a disputation attended by Aquinas himself. See Roger Marston,
De emanatione aeterna, q.6, in Quaestiones disputatae (Ad Claras Aquas,
1932), 117. For the debate on the theological issue of mental word, see G.
Pini, “Henry of Ghent’s Doctrine of Verbum in Its Theological Context,” in
Henry of Ghent and the Transformation of Scholastic Thought: Studies in
Memory of Jos Decorte (Leuven: Leuven University Press, 1993), 307–26.
30. QDP, q.8, a.1: “And that concept (conceptio) differs from the three
other things I have mentioned. It differs from the thing thought about.… It
differs from the intelligible species.… It also differs from the intellect’s
action, because that concept is considered as the term of the action and as
something produced by it, as it were.… This concept of the intellect is
properly called ‘word’ in us.” On Aquinas’s mature doctrine of mental
words, see C. Panaccio, “From Mental Word to Mental Language,”
Philosophical Topics 20 (1992): 125–47, esp. 126–28; R. Pasnau, Theories of
Cognition in the Later Middle Ages (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1997), 256–71; C. Panaccio, Le Discours intérieur de Platon à
Guillaume d’Ockham (Paris: Éditions du Seuil, 1999), 177–92; Pasnau,
Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature, 327–28; E. Stump, Aquinas (London and
New York: Routledge, 2003), 266–68.
31. G. Pini, “Two Models of Thinking: Thomas Aquinas and John Duns
Scotus,” in G. Klima, ed., Intentionality, Cognition and Representation in the
Middle Ages (New York: Fordham University Press, forthcoming).
32. B. Montagnes, The Doctrine of the Analogy of Being according to
Thomas Aquinas, trans. E. M. Macierowski and P. Vandevelde (Milwaukee:
Marquette University Press, 2004). See also G. P. Klubertanz, St. Thomas
Aquinas on Analogy: A Textual Analysis and Systematic Synthesis (Chicago:
Loyola University Press, 1960).
33. Wippel, The Metaphysical Thought, 543–72.
34. Montagnes, The Doctrine of the Analogy, 65–93.
35. Super Sent prol., q.1, a.2, ad 2; I, d.19, q.5, a.2; d.35, q.1, a.4; d.48, q.1,
a.1; II, d.16, q.1, a.1, ad 3.
36. QDV I, q.2, a.11.
37. On the likeness obtaining between creatures and God: SCG I, 29; ST I
q.4 a.3. Specifically on analogy: SCG I, 32 and 34; QDP, q.7, a.7; ST I q.13
a.5: “So, whatever we say of both God and creatures we say in virtue of the
order that creatures have to God as to their source and cause, in which all the
perfections of things pre-exist most excellently.” The English translation is
from Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, Questions on God, ed. Brian Davies and
Brian Leftow (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 149. On the
principle that every agent produces something like itself, which Aquinas
takes to be entailed by the very nature of causality, see Wippel, The
Metaphysical Thought, 517–18, 558–59.
38. SCG I, 34.
39. Articuli, art. 16 and art. 17, in Gauthier, “Les ‘Articuli in quibus,’”
306–7. On Aquinas’s shift concerning grace, probably due to his increased
familiarity with Augustine’s writings, see Bouillard, Conversion et grace,
92–122; J.-P. Torrell, Nouvelle recherches thomasiennes (Paris: Vrin, 2008),
125, n. 2. See also A. E. McGrath, Iustitia Dei: A History of the Christian
Doctrine of Justification, 3d ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2005), 132–38. For a similar shift concerning merit and the role of
predestination from the Sentences to the Summa theologiae, see Wawrykow,
God’s Grace and Human Action. In general on nature and grace in Aquinas,
see Torrell, Nouvelle recherches thomasiennes, 99–129.
40. Super Sent II, d.28, q.1, a.2: “Others, however, with the intention of
preserving the nature of free will, say that human beings, in keeping with
their natural virtue, have been created in such a way that they can avoid sin;
but as a consequence of sin virtue is so changed that one who is already in a
state of sin cannot avoid sin but falls into another sin unless he is freed by
grace. But because they do not want to appear to say that it is absolutely
impossible not to sin, they add that somebody who is in mortal sin can avoid
this or that particular sin, but not all sins. And the same is true of venial sins.
They also state that somebody who is in a state of mortal sin can avoid
sinning for some time, but not for a long time. This position, however, seems
false in several respects. First, it is false because, just as sin reduces but does
not remove the natural goods, a human being cannot lose what pertains to the
nature of a natural power, even though he can become weak in that respect.
Therefore, since the free choice or avoidance of good or evil pertains to the
nature of free will, the capacity to avoid sin cannot be taken away from a
human being. Rather, it can only be reduced, namely in such a way that one
can avoid only with difficulty that sin that previously he could have avoided
easily.… And it cannot even be said that somebody can avoid sinning for
some time but not for long, because a free will that resists evil becomes much
stronger in resisting evil, not weaker; and so it is much more capable of
avoiding sinning after than before.”
41. QDV I, q.24, a.12.
42. ST I-II q.109 a.8: “But in the state of corrupted nature human beings
need grace to heal their nature in order that they may entirely abstain form
sin.… So, too, before a human being’s reason, wherein is mortal sin, is
restored by justifying grace, that human being can avoid each mortal sin, and
for some time, since it is not necessary that he should always be actually
sinning. But it cannot be that he remains for a long time without mortal sin.
… And thus, just as inordinate movements of the sensitive appetite cannot
help occurring when the lower appetite is not subject to reason, so likewise,
when a human being’s reason is not entirely subject to God, the consequence
is that many disorders occur in the acts themselves of reason. For when a
human being’s heart is not so fixed on God as to be unwilling to be parted
from Him for the sake of finding any good or avoiding any evil, many things
happen for the achieving or avoiding of which a human being strays from
God and breaks His commandments, and thus sins mortally; especially since,
when surprised, a human being acts according to his preconceived end and
his pre-existing habits, as the Philosopher says, although with the
premeditation of his reason a human being may do something outside the
order of his preconceived end and the inclination of his habit. But because a
human being cannot always have this premeditation, it cannot help occurring
that he acts in accordance with his will turned aside form God, unless, by
grace, he is quickly brought back to the due order.” The English translation is
taken, with some modifications, from Basic Writings of Saint Thomas
Aquinas, ed. Anton C. Pegis, vol. 2 (New York: Random House, 1945), 991–
92. Around 1280, Roger Marston, while noticing Aquinas’s development on
this topic, did not hesitate to label Aquinas’s earlier position as Pelagian
(“Istud manifeste est de errore Pelagii”). See Roger Marston, De statu
naturae lapsae, q.2, ad 28, in Quaestiones disputatae, p. 200, as quoted in
Gauthier, “Les ‘Articuli in quibus,’” 277–78, n. 17.
43. Super Sent II, d.28, q.3, a.1: “Therefore, it must be said that somebody
can observe the precepts of the law by free will, with regard to what falls
directly under a precept, and without gratuitously given or sanctifying grace
(sine gratia gratis data vel gratum faciente), as long as grace is taken to
mean some infused habit. But with regard to the lawgiver’s intention, the
precepts of the law cannot be observed in the absence of grace, because the
gift of charity cannot become present in us through our own forces but is
infused by God.”
44. QDV, q.24, a.15, ad 2.
45. ST I-II q.109 a.4: “I answer that there are two ways of fulfilling the
commandments of the Law. The first regards the substance of works, as
when somebody does works of justice, fortitude, and of other virtues. And in
this way a human being in the state of integral nature could fulfill all the
commandments of the Law; or otherwise he would have been unable not to
sin in that state, since to sin is nothing else than to transgress the divine
commandments. But in the state of corrupted nature, a human being cannot
fulfill all the divine commandments without healing grace.” The English
translation is taken, with some modifications, from The Basic Writings of
Saint Thomas Aquinas, 2:985.
46. There seems to be a similar shift in Aquinas’s position concerning the
necessity of grace in order to carry out the commandment of loving God
above everything else (grace is not necessary: Super Sent II, d.28, q.1, a.3;
grace is necessary: ST I-II q.100 a.10), as well as in order to prepare
ourselves to the reception of healing grace (grace is not necessary: Super Sent
II, d.28, a.4; grace is necessary: QDV, q.24, a.15; Quodl I, q.4, a.2; ST I-II
q.109 a.6). See Articuli, art. 18 and art. 39, in Gauthier, “Les ‘Articuli in
quibus,’” 307 and 317, and, on the latter issue, Roger Marston, De statu
naturae lapsae, q.2, ad 11, 195–96, in Quaestiones disputatae, as quoted in
Gauthier, “Les ‘Articuli in quibus,’” 287, n. 39. A close reading of Aquinas’s
text, however, seems to cast some doubts on Aquinas’s shift especially
concerning the latter issue.
47. Sometimes Aquinas hesitated between two views, but it is not possible
to detect a clear evolution in his position. The question whether supposit and
essence are identical in angels is a case in point. In several places, Aquinas
argued that supposit and essence are identical in angels. See Super Sent I,
d.25, q.1, a.1, ad 3; Super Sent II, d.3, q.1, a.2; Super Sent III, d.5, q.1, a.3;
SCG IV, 55; QDP, q.7, a.4; QDP, q.9, a.1; QDA, q.17, ad 10; In DA 3, 2; ST
I q.3 a.3; q.39 a.3 ad 3; QDSC 5, ad 9; In Meta VII, 5 and 11; VIII, 3. In
other places, however, Aquinas claimed that supposit and essence are really
different in any creature, angels included. See Super Sent I, d.5, q.1; d.34,
q.1, a.1; SCG II, 54; Quodl II, q.2, a.2; QDUVI, 1; cf. also ST III q.17 a.1.
See Articuli, art. 36, in Gauthier, “Les ‘Articuli in quibus,’” 316–17; Wippel,
The Metaphysical Thought, 238–53. Similarly, Aquinas’s wavered in his
opinion about the role that determinate or indeterminate dimensions play in
the individuation of material things. See Super Sent II, d.3, q.1, a.4; Super
Sent II, d.30, q.2, a.2; In BDT, q.4, a.2 (the individuating principle is matter
considered under indeterminate dimensions); Super Sent III, d.1, q.2, a.5; In
DA 2, c.12; QDA, q.9 (the individuating principle is matter considered under
determinate dimensions). See Wippel, The Metaphysical Thought, 356–73.
48. Super Sent II, d.1, q.1, a.2; SCG II, 21; QDP, q.3, a.4; ST I q.45 a.5.
See Articuli, art. 12, in Gauthier, “Les ‘Articuli in quibus,’” 305. John of
Naples noticed this development. See Gauthier, “Les ‘Articuli in quibus,’”
287, n. 41.
49. Super Sent I, d.36, q.2, a.3, ad 2; ST I q.15 a.3 ad 3. See Articuli, art.
56, in Gauthier, “Les ‘Articuli in quibus,’” 321.
50. Super Sent III, d.15, q.2, a.3, sol.1; ST I-II q.35 a.1. See Articuli, art.
30, in Gauthier, “Les ‘Articuli in quibus,’” 313–14. Giles of Rome noticed
this development. See Gauthier, “Les ‘Articuli in quibus,’” 278, n. 18.
51. Super Sent I, d.47, q.1, a.4; ST I-II q.100 a.8. See Articuli, art. 10, in
Gauthier, “Les ‘Articuli in quibus,’” 304.
52. Super Sent IV, d.43, q.1, a.2; ST III q.56 a.1 ad 3. Aquinas’s evolution
concerns the notion of instrumental causality and can be documented also in
QDV, q.27, a.4. See Torrell, Recherches thomasiennes, 214–41.
53. Super Sent, IV, d.49, q.1, a.4, sol. 1; ST I-II q.4 a.5 ad 5. See F. Pelster,
“Das Wachstum der Seligkeit nach der Aufestehung, um die Auslegung von
S. Th. I-II, q. 4 a. 5 ad 5,” Scholastik 27 (1952): 561–63; Torrell, Recherches
thomasiennes, 195–96, n. 3.
54. The view that Aquinas changed his mind about the will was first
proposed in O. Lottin, “La date de la Question Disputée De Malo de Saint
Thomas d’Aquin,” Revue d’histoire ecclésiastique 24 (1928): 373–88. It was
then endorsed in many other studies, both by Lottin and other scholars,
including B. Lonergan, “St. Thomas’s Thought on Gratia Operans,”
Theological Studies 2 (1941): 289–324; 3 (1942): 69–88, 375–402, 533–78,
reprinted as Grace and Freedom: Operative Grace in the Thought of Thomas
Aquinas, ed. F. E. Crowe and R. M. Doran (Toronto: University of Toronto
Press, 2000). Serious doubts have been cast on this hypothesis in D.
Westberg, “Did Aquinas Change His Mind about the Will?” The Thomist 58
(1994): 41–60; and esp. P. Eardley, “Thomas Aquinas and Giles of Rome on
the Will,” Review of Metaphysics 56 (2003): 835–62.
55. This remark, which concerns Aquinas’s development on mental words,
is taken from the commentary on the first part of the Summa theologiae by
Thomas de Vio, Cardinal Cajetan, as printed in vol. 4 of the Leonine edition,
368, and quoted in von Gunten, “In principio erat verbum,” 119, n. 2.
I wish to express my gratitude to Adriano Oliva, O.P. (Commissio
Leonina) and Russell Friedman (Katholieke Universiteit Leuven) for their
suggestions and help. I also wish to thank Brian Davies for many useful
comments on a first draft of this paper.
CHAPTER 38
CHRISTOPHER UPHAM
Aquinas appealed, as we have seen, to many friars, monks, university teachers, and
students, to relatively few high ecclesiastics, and, among the laity, to some jurists and
doctors. Popes and princes might not read him themselves but, by 1500 at least,
considered him a necessary part of a great library. He did not, it seems, appeal to the
general intelligent lay person who had not been educated in a university.… Nobles or
rich bourgeois could have acquired the works of Aquinas but they were not interested in
doing so.47
NOTES
1. Summa theologiae I q.42 a.1 ad 1.
2. This is reported by Aidan Nichols in Discovering Aquinas (Grand
Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 2003), 130.
3. Leonard Boyle, “The Summa Confessorum of John of Freiburg,” in
Facing History: A Different Thomas Aquinas (Louvain: La Neuve, 2000),
37–64.
4. Eugenio Garin, History of Italian Philosophy, tran. Giorgio A. Pinton,
vol. 1 (Amsterdam: Rodopi, 2008), 86.
5. The introductions and notes to Esolen’s translation of the Commedia
draw out these connections well. See Dante, Inferno, Purgatory, and
Paradise, tran. Anthony Esolen (New York: Random House Publishing
Group, 2004).
6. Romanus Cessario, O.P., A Short History of Thomism (Washington,
D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 2003), 57.
7. The Eastern Church denies that the Holy Spirit proceeds from the
Father and the Son, and never consented to its presence in the Nicene
symbol. Aquinas’s exposition of the Apostle’s Creed does not evade this
controversy, since he does include a very succinct defense of the Nicene
inclusion.
8. Charles L. Stinger, Humanism and the Church Fathers: Ambrogio
Traversari (1386–1439) and Christian Antiquity in the Italian Renaissance
(Albany, N.Y.: SUNY Press, 1977), 90.
9. Cf. op. cit.: Lending further support to this, Stinger reports that
Planudes also translated Augustine’s De Trinitate.
10. Steven Runciman, The Last Byzantine Renaissance (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1970), 80.
11. J. Gill, “Gennadius II Scholarius, Patriarch of Constantinople,” New
Catholic Encyclopedia, 2d ed., vol. 6 (Detroit: Gale, 2003), 136–37.
12. Ibid.
13. Seymour Feldman, “Maimonides—A Guide for Posterity,” in Kenneth
Seeskin, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Maimonides (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2005), 332–35.
14. Cf. Jean-Pierre Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, vol. 1, The Person and
His Work, tran. Robert Royal (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of
America Press, 1996), 316. Among the texts translated into Hebrew, Torrell
mentions the first part of the De unitate intellectus, extracts from the Summa
theologiae, and the Super de causis.
15. Cf. Nichols, Discovering Aquinas, 130.
16. To be sure, there are certain doctrines almost ubiquitous among
Thomists (here one might mention the real distinction in creatures between
esse and essentia), so that it is not nonsense to speak of Thomism. For an
example of a definition of Thomism based on shared beliefs, see J. A.
Weisheipl, “Thomism,” New Catholic Encyclopedia, 2d ed., vol. 14 (Detroit:
Gale, 2003), 40–52. Cessario’s Short History of Thomism follows
Weisheipl’s formulation.
17. Here, I am taking my cue from Freddoso in his review of Cessario,
accessed online at: <http://www.nd.edu/~afreddos/pubs.htm>.
18. Such a catalogue already exists. Cf. L. A. Kennedy, A Catalogue of
Thomists, 1270–1900 (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press,
1987).
19. Fergus Kerr, After Aquinas: Versions of Thomism (Oxford: Blackwell
Publishing, 2002), 10.
20. His polemic tract Contra errores Graecorum (Against the Errors of the
Greeks) served in his stead, but one can only imagine that Aquinas in person
would have argued his case more persuasively.
21. As quoted by Hans Thijssen, “Condemnation of 1277,” The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta,
accessed online at:
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/condemnation/>.
22. For a helpful guide to these controversies, see Edward Grant, The
Foundations of Modern Science in the Middle Ages: Their Religious,
Institutional, and Intellectual Contexts (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1996), 70–85.
23. A list of these can be found in Gyula Klima, with Fritz Allhoff and
Anand Jayprakash Vaidya, eds., Medieval Philosophy: Essential Readings
with Commentary (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 2007), 180–89.
24. Five pro-Thomist correctories remain to this day: D. A. Callus,
“Correctoria,” New Catholic Encyclopedia, 2d ed., vol. 4 (Detroit: Gale,
2003), 274–78.
25. Simon Tugwell, Albert & Thomas (Mahwah, N.J.: Paulist Press, 1988),
241.
26. J. J. Przezdziecki, “Thomas of Sutton,” New Catholic Encyclopedia, 2d
ed., vol. 14 (Detroit: Gale, 2003), 37.
27. Allan Wolter, “Duns Scotus, John (c. 1266–1308),” Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, ed. Donald Borchert, 2d ed., vol. 3 (Detroit: Macmillan
Reference USA, 2006), 133–45.
28. Eugene Rairweather, “Henry of Ghent (??–1293),” Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, ed. Donald Borchert, 2d ed., vol. 4 (Detroit: Macmillan
Reference USA, 2006), 312–15.
29. James Weisheipl, “Durandus of Saint-Pourçain (c. 1275–1334),”
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Donald Borchert, 2d ed., vol. 3 (Detroit:
Macmillan Reference USA, 2006), 148–49.
30. Roland Teske, “Hervaeus Natalis (c. 1250–323),” Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, ed. Donald Borchert, 2d ed., vol. 4 (Detroit: Macmillan
Reference USA, 2006), 343–44.
31. Isabel Iribarren, Durandus of St Pourcain: A Dominican Theologian in
the Shadow of Aquinas (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005). Two recent
studies of Durandellus are worth attention: Gilles Emery, “La Théologie
trinitaire des Evidentiae contra Durandum de Durandellus,” Revue Thomiste
97:1 (1997): 173–218; M. Lanczowski and R. Wittwer, “Les Evidentiae
contra Durandum de Durandellus,” Revue Thomiste 97:1 (1997): 143–56.
32. James Weisheipl, “John of Paris (c. 1255–1306),” Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, ed. Donald Borchert, 2d ed., vol. 4 (Detroit: Macmillan
Reference USA, 2006), 842.
33. Argued in John’s De Potestate Regia et Papali (On royal and papal
power) of 1302. See John of Paris, On Royal and Papal Power: A
Translation, with Introduction, of De potestate Regia et Papali of John of
Paris, tran. Arthur P. Monahan (New York: Columbia University Press,
1974); or John of Paris, On Royal and Papal Power, tran. J. A. Watt
(Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 2002).
34. Edward Bouverie Pusey, First Letter to the Very Rev. J. H. Newman
(London: Rivingtons, 1869).
35. Scotus defended the immaculate conception in his Lectura in III Sent.,
dist.3, q.1.
36. Aquinas would not be declared officially a “Doctor of the Church” until
1567, under Pope Pius V.
37. According to Iribarren, a specialist on Durandus of St. Pourçain, this
exhibits the authoritative status of Thomism within the Dominican order by
1325, when he penned the Evidentiae contra Durandum, 2 vols., ed. P. T.
Stella, critical edition prepared by M. Lanczkowski and R. Imbach, Corpus
Philosophorum Medii Aevi: Opera Philosophica Mediae Aetatis Selecta
(Tübingen and Basle: A. Francke Verlag, 2003).
38. Martin Grabmann, Mittelalterliches Geistesleben: Abhandlung zur
Geschichte der Scholastik und Mystic, vol. 1 (Munich: Max Hueber, 1926),
421.
39. Ernest Moody, “William of Ockham (c. 1285–1349),” Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, ed. Donald Borchert, 2d ed., vol. 9 (Detroit: Macmillan
Reference USA, 2006), 770–85.
40. C. R. Meyer, “Henry of Gorkum,” New Catholic Encyclopedia, 2d ed.,
vol. 6 (Detroit: Gale, 2003), 753.
41. M. Grabmann, Mittelalterliches Geistesleben, Abhandlungen zur
Geschichte der Scholastik und Mystik, vol. 2, (München, 1936), 443; vol. 3
(1956), 412. Cf. Thomas Franklin O’Meara, Thomas Aquinas Theologian
(Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1997), 158. Cf. also,
Paul van Geest, Harm Goris, and Carlo Leget, eds., Aquinas as Authority: A
Collection of Studies Presented at the Second Conference of the Thomas
Insituut te Utrecht, December 14–16, 2000 (Leuven, Belgium: Peeters
Publishers, 2002), 31.
42. a.k.a. Denys van Leeuwen, of Rijkel/Ryckel, Belgium. For more, see B.
Du Moustier, “Denis the Carthusian,” New Catholic Encyclopedia, 2d ed.,
vol. 4. (Detroit: Gale, 2003), 661–62. For primary sources: “Doctoris
ecstatici Dionysii Cartusiani,” Opera Omnia, 42 vols. (Montreuilsur-Mer:
Tournai Parkminster, 1896–1913, 1935). This is a noncritical, slightly
corrected reissue of the sixteenth-century Cologne edition. Also, see Kent
Emery, Dionysii Cartusiensis Opera selecta: prolegomena Bibliotheca
manuscripta/auctore Kent Emery Jr (Turnholti [Turnhout, Belgium]:
Typographi Brepols, 1991). For secondary sources: Kent Emery, “Twofold
Wisdom and Contemplation in Denys of Ryckel (Dionysius Cartusiensis,
1402–71),” Journal of Medieval and Renaissance Studies, 18 (1988): 99–
134; David C. Steinmetz, Luther in Context (Bloomington, Ind.: Indiana
University Press, 1986); Anselme Stoelen, “Denys the Carthusian,” in James
Walsh, ed., Spirituality through the Centuries (New York: Kenedy & Sons,
1964), 220–32.
43. For details, see Leen Spruit, Species Intelligibilis, vol. 1, Classical
Roots and Medieval Discussions (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1994), 360–68.
44. John Capreolus, Defensiones Theologiae divi Thomae Aquinatis
(Turonibus: Sumptibus Alfred Cattier, 1900).
45. The format of lectures and disputations makes sense in an oral culture,
where books are not available to all students and lengthy, repetitive
arguments offer the surest means to cover all aspects of a question. Print
media, of course, allow for perfect recall without the need for memorization
by repetition.
46. I should acknowledge one glaring exception to the insularity of this
period: Christopher Columbus’s protector, Diego de Deza, was a Dominican
Thomist, and according to the renowned explorer in a letter dated December
21, 1504, “It is he [Diego de Deza] who was the cause of their Majesties’
possessing the Indies.” One Thomist, namely, de Deza, had a vital role in
Columbus’s voyage across the Atlantic, though this can hardly be considered
a direct result of Aquinas’s influence. Quote taken from The Catholic
Historical Review, vol. 1 (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America
Press, 1915), 105. Also, cf. P. Mandonnet, Les Dominicains et la découverte
de l’Amérique (Paris: P. Lethielleux, 1893).
47. J. N. Hillgarth, “Who Read Thomas Aquinas?” in The Gilson Lectures
on Thomas Aquinas (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies,
2008), 46–73. The quote is from page 70.
48. J. F. Hinnebusch, “Crockaert, Peter,” New Catholic Encyclopedia, 2d
ed., vol. 4 (Detroit: Gale, 2003), 374.
49. Felix Alluntis, “Vitoria, Francisco de (1492/1493–1546),”
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Donald Borchert, 2d ed., vol. 9 (Detroit:
Macmillan Reference USA, 2006), 698–99.
50. His most famous lectures were collected in relectiones, and include De
Indis, De Iure Belli, De Potestate Civili among the most important. See
Gregory M. Reichberg, “Francisco De Vitoria, De Indis and De Iure Belli
Relectiones (1557): Philosophy Meets War,” in Jorge J. E. Gracia, ed., The
Classics of Western Philosophy: A Reader’s Guide (Malden, Mass.:
Blackwell Publishing, 2003).
51. Hugo Grotius, The Law of War and Peace, tran. Francis W. Kelsey
(New York: Bobbs-Merrill Company, Inc., 1925).
52. Joshua Hochschild, “Cajetan, Cardinal (1469–1534),” Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, ed. Donald Borchert, 2d ed., vol. 2 (Detroit: Macmillan
Reference USA, 2006), 6–7.
53. Cf. Joshua Hochschild, The Semantics of Analogy: Rereading
Cajetan’s De Nominum Analogia (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre
Dame Press, 2010).
54. For example, consider Desiderius Erasmus, Moriae Encomium (The
Praise of Folly) (London: Hamilton, Adams & Co., 1887), 142–43.
Originally written in 1509: “Do not wonder, therefore, that at public
disputations they bind their heads with so many caps one over another; for
this is to prevent the loss of their brains, which would otherwise break out
from their uneasy confinement. It affords likewise a pleasant scene of
laughter, to listen to these divines in their hotly managed disputations. To see
how proud they are of talking such hard gibberish, and stammering out such
blundering distinctions, as the auditors perhaps may sometimes gape at, but
seldom apprehend. [paragraph] And they take such a liberty in their speaking
of Latin, that they scorn to stick at the exactness of syntax or concord;
pretending it is below the majesty of a divine to talk like a pedagogue, and be
tied to the slavish observance of the rules of grammar. Finally, they take a
vast pride, among other citations, to allege the authority of their respective
master.”
55. Leibniz would edit this work in 1670.
56. Peter de la Ramée (1515–1572) is indicative of this tendency: “Let us
ignore all these Aristotelians and return to Aristotle, the author of such a
noble discipline [i.e., philosophy], and to Cicero, who tries to emulate
Aristotle’s teaching and to imitate him.” As quoted by Erland Sellberg,
“Petrus Ramus,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008
edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta, accessed online at:
<http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ramus/>. Ramée’s popularity seems to have
exceeded his insights.
57. However, some recent scholarship has suggested some occult
influences that Aquinas may have exerted within the via moderna, as
characterized by Gabriel Biel and transmitted to Martin Luther. See van
Geest et al., eds., Aquinas as Authority.
58. For the preparation for justification, compare ST III q.85 a.5 with the
decrees of the Council of Trent, Session VI, chapter 6. For the causes of
justification, compare ST I-II q.112 a.4 and II-II q.24 a.3 with Session VI,
chapter 7.
59. For a more complete, if somewhat apologetic, summary of Thomists
during this period, see Réginald Garrigou-Lagrange, Reality: A Synthesis of
Thomistic Thought, tran. Patrick Cummins (St. Louis: B. Herder, 1958), ch.
3.
60. Thomas Franklin O’Meara, Thomas Aquinas Theologian (Notre Dame,
Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1997), 162.
61. Michael Griffin, “Molina, Luis de (1535–1600),” Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, ed. Donald Borchert, 2d ed., vol. 6 (Detroit: Macmillan
Reference USA, 2006), 321–23.
62. John Mourant, “Suárez, Francisco (1548–1617),” Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, ed. Donald Borchert, 2d ed., vol. 9 (Detroit: Macmillan
Reference USA, 2006), 282–85.
63. Vernon Bourke, “Vasquez, Gabriel (1549–1604),” Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, ed. Donald Borchert, 2d ed., vol. 9 (Detroit: Macmillan
Reference USA, 2006), 649–50.
64. Vernon Bourke, “Báñez, Dominic (1528–1604),” Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, ed. Donald Borchert, 2d ed., vol. 1 (Detroit: Macmillan
Reference USA, 2006), 476.
65. Cf. Aquinas’s commentary on the De Interpretatione, Bk. I, lect.5.
66. Vernon Bourke, “John of St. Thomas (1589–1644),” Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, ed. Donald Borchert, 2d ed., vol. 4 (Detroit: Macmillan
Reference USA, 2006), 843–44.
67. For more on this suggestive possibility, see John N. Deely, Four Ages
of Understanding: The First Postmodern Survey of Philosophy from Ancient
Times to the Turn of the Twenty-first Century (Toronto Studies in Semiotics)
(Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2001), 447–84.
68. Francis Bacon, The Advancement of Learning (Rockville, MD: Serenity
Publishers, 2008), 31. Take the following critical passage: “Surely, like as
many substances in nature, which are solid, do putrefy and corrupt into
worms; so it is the property of good and sound knowledge, to putrefy and
dissolve into a number of subtle, idle, unwholesome, and, as I may term
them, vermiculate questions, which have indeed a kind of quickness, and life
of spirit, but no soundness of matter, or goodness of quality. This kind of
degenerate learning did chiefly reign amongst the schoolmen: who having
sharp and strong wits, and abundance of leisure, and small variety of reading,
(but their wits being shut up in the cells of a few authors, chiefly Aristotle
their dictator, as their persons were shut up in the cells of monasteries and
colleges,) and knowing little history, either of nature or time, did, out of no
great quantity of matter, and infinite agitation of wit, spin out unto us those
laborious webs of learning, which are extant in their books.”
69. Gilson rejects these assumptions as “essentialist,” basing metaphysics
on the abstract notions of the human mind, rather than the transcendent
character of all actual, existent things.
70. James A. Weisheipl, “Thomism,” New Catholic Encyclopedia, 2d ed.,
vol. 14 (Detroit: Gale, 2003), 40–52.
71. René Descartes, The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, vol. 2, tran.
John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1984), 82–83, emphasis mine.
72. Cf. ST I q.2 a.1. Importantly, Aquinas does not think that a nominal
definition of “God,” such as “that than which nothing greater can be
conceived,” or perhaps “the necessary being” is sufficient by itself to prove
that God exists. For Aquinas, these premises only result in a mental
existence, or conception of God. But Aquinas wants to arrive at a mind-
independent reality for God.
73. Cf. Leviathan, Part I, ch. 4, “necessities of definitions.”
74. Cf. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Bk. III, ch. X, §§6–
10.
75. Aeterni Patris, accessed online at:
<http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/leo_xiii/encyclicals/documents/hf_l-
xiii_enc_04081879_aeterni-patris_en.xhtml>.
76. For the contents of this list, see
<http://www.catholicapologetics.info/catholicteaching/philosophy/thomast.htm
77. Studiorum Ducem, accessed online at:
<http://www.ewtn.com/library/ENCYC/P11STUDI.HTM>.
78. On this front, one thinks of the Leonine Commission, which has
worked since 1879 to produce critical editions of the entire body of
Aquinas’s writings. Institutes devoted to all aspects of medieval study have
been formed throughout Europe (e.g., at the University of St Thomas in
Rome, the Thomas-Institut of Cologne, the Grabmann-Institut of Munich, the
Thomas Instituut of Utrecht, and the Thomist Institue of Warsaw, to name
just a few). In North America, I must mention the Pontifical Institute of
Medieval Studies in Toronto, created in 1929 at the suggestion of Gilson.
Journals include the Revue Thomiste, The Modern Schoolman, and The
Thomist. Finally, an excellent resource for any scholar of Aquinas is Roberto
Busa’s electronic index of Aquinas’s works, accessed online at
<http://www.corpusthomisticum.org/>.
79. N. E. Fenton, “Weisheipl, James Athanasius,” New Catholic
Encyclopedia, 2d ed., vol. 14 (Detroit: Gale, 2003), 672–73.
80. W. J. Hill, “Thomism, Transcendental,” New Catholic Encyclopedia,
2d ed., vol. 14 (Detroit: Gale, 2003), 52–57.
81. James Conway, “Maréchal, Joseph (1878–1944),” Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, ed. Donald Borchert, 2d ed., vol. 5 (Detroit: Macmillan
Reference USA, 2006), 707–10.
82. Elizabeth Galbraith, “Rahner, Karl (1904–1984),” Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, ed. Donald Borchert, 2d ed., vol. 8 (Detroit: Macmillan
Reference USA, 2006), 231–34.
83. F. G. Lawrence, “Lonergan, Bernard,” New Catholic Encyclopedia, 2d
ed., vol. 8 (Detroit: Gale, 2003), 772–75.
84. For Rahner, this activity would most poignantly be expressed in terms
of excessus, which Aquinas mentions in his De divinis nominibus expositio,
c.7, lect.4.
85. Joseph Evans, “Maritain, Jacques (1882–973),” Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, ed. Donald Borchert, 2d ed., vol. 5 (Detroit: Macmillan
Reference USA, 2006), 712–17.
86. Robert Miller, “Gilson, Étienne Henry (1884–1978),” Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, ed. Donald Borchert, 2d ed., vol. 4 (Detroit: Macmillan
Reference USA, 2006), 91–93.
87. John F. X. Knasas, Being and Some Twentieth-Century Thomists (New
York: Fordham University Press, 2003).
88. Kerr, After Aquinas.
89. Theologian Karl Rahner seems to have been well aware of this
problem. In 1980, his response when asked to say a few words about his
philosophy was “Ich habe keine Philosophie” (I have no philosophy). See
William V. Dych, Karl Rahner, Outstanding Christian Thinkers series (New
York: Continuum International Publishing Group, 2000).
90. For a sampling of Geach on Aquinas, see Three Philosophers:
Aristotle, Aquinas, Frege (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 1973). Kenny has
many notable works, but for an introduction to his thinking on Aquinas, see
Aquinas on Mind (London: Routledge, 1993); and Aquinas on Being
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002).
91. Anthony Kenny, Aquinas: A Collection of Critical Essays (Notre
Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1976), 1.
CHRONOLOGICAL LIST OF AQUINAS’S
WRITINGS
Works sometimes ascribed to Aquinas may well be texts of which he was not
the author in any sense. What follows is a list of Aquinas’s writings with
respect to which there is not too much scholarly controversy concerning their
authenticity. They are cited by the Latin titles commonly used for them,
together with English translations of these. But note that we cannot always be
sure of the titles that Aquinas gave to his writings (notably, in the case of the
Summa theologiae and the Summa contra Gentiles). Within each category
below, works are cited in roughly chronological order of composition, though
in some cases this order is uncertain. For detailed discussions concerning the
dating of Aquinas’s writings, see Jean-Pierre Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas:
The Person and His Work (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University Press of
America, 1996).
DISPUTED QUESTIONS
Quaestiones disputatae De veritate (Disputed Questions on Truth: c.1256–
1259).
Quaestiones disputatae De potentia (Disputed Questions on the Power [of
God]: c. 1265–1266).
Quaestio disputata De anima (Disputed Question on the Soul: c.1265–1266).
Quaestio disputata De spiritualibus creaturis (Disputed Question on
Spiritual Creatures: c.1267–1268).
Questiones disputatae De Malo (Disputed Questions on Evil: c.1266–1270).
Quaestiones disputatae De virtutibus (Disputed Questions on the Virtues:
c.1271–1272).
Quaestio disputata De unione verbi incarnati (Disputed Question on the
Union of the Incarnate Word: c. 1271–1272).
Quaestiones de quodlibet I–XII (Quodlibetal Questions I–XII [concerning a
very large range of topics]: c.1252–1256 and c.1268–1272).
BIBLICAL COMMENTARIES
Expositio super Isaiam ad litteram (Commentary on Isaiah: c.1248–1254).
Super Ieremiam et Threnos (Commentaries on Jeremiah and Lamentations:
c.1248–1252).
Expositio super Job ad litteram (Commentary on Job/Literal Exposition on
Job: c.1261–1265).
Catena aurea (The Golden Chain: c.1262–1264 [commentary on the Gospels
drawing on quotations from the Church Fathers]).
Lectura super Matthaeum (Commentary on Matthew: c.1269–1270).
Lectura super Ioannem (Commentary on John: c.1270–1272).
Expositio et Lectura super Epistolas Pauli Apostoli (Commentaties on the
Letters of St. Paul: dating very difficult to establish, possibly 1265–
1273).
Postilla super Psalmos (Commentary on the Psalms: c.1273).
COMMENTARIES ON ARISTOTLE
Sententia Libri De anima (Commentary on Aristotle’s On the Soul: 1267–
1268).
Sententia Libri De Sensu et sensato (Commentary on Aristotle’s On Sense
[and On Memory]: c.1268–1269).
Sententia super Physicam (Commentary on Aristotle’s Physics: c.1268–
1269).
Sententia super Meteora (Commentary on Aristotle’s Meteorology: c.1268–
1270).
Sententia Libri Politicorum (Commentary on Aristotle’s Politics: c. 1269–
1272).
Expositio Libri Peri hermeneias (Commentary on Aristotle’s On
Interpretation [De Interpretatione]: c.1270–1271).
Expositio Libri Posteriorum (Commentary on Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics:
c. 1270–1272).
Sententia Libri Ethicorum (Commentary on Aristotle’s Nichomachean
Ethics: 1271–1272).
Sententia super Metaphysicam (Commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics:
c.1270–1272).
Sententia super librum De caelo et mundo (Commentary on Aristotle’s On
the Heavens: c. 1272–1273).
Sententia super libros De generatione et corruptione (Commentary on
Aristotle’s On Generation and Corruption: c.1272–1273).
OTHER COMMENTARIES
Expositio super librum Boethii De trinitate (Commentary on Boethius’s De
Trinitate: c.1257–1259).
Expositio in librum Boethii De hebdomadibus (Commentary on Boethius’s
Hebdomads [actually, Boethius’s third theological tractate]: c. 1257–
1259).
Expositio super Dionysium De divinis nominibus (Commentary on [Pseudo-]
Dionysius’s The Divine Names: c.1261–1268).
Expositio super librum De causis (Commentary on the Book of Causes:
c.1272).
POLEMICAL WRITINGS
Contra impugnantes Dei cultum et religionem (Against those who Impugn the
Cult of God and Religion: 1256).
De perfectione spiritualis vitae (On the Perfection of the Spiritual Life:
1269–1270).
De unitate intellectus contra Averroistas (On the Unicity of the Intellect
Against the Averroists: 1270).
Contra doctrinam retrahentium a religione homines a religionis ingressu
[commonly referred to as Contra retrahentes] (Against the teachings of
those who prevent men entering the religious life: 1271).
De aeterntate mundi (On the Eternity of the World: c.1271).
1. PRIMARY SOURCES
The most authoritative listing of Aquinas’s works in English is I. T.
Eschmann, “A Catalogue of St. Thomas’s Works: Bibliographical
Notes,” in E. Gilson, The Christian Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas
(New York: Random House, 1956). It is supplemented by “A Brief
Catalogue of Authentic Works” in James A. Weisheipl, Friar Thomas
D’Aquino (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1974; republished with
Corrigenda and Addenda, Washington D.C.: Catholic University of
America Press, 1983).
The definitive edition of Aquinas’s writings is currently being published by
the Leonine Commission, established by Pope Leo XIII in 1880, which
has now produced volumes containing Aquinas’s most important
works (Sancti Thomae Aquinatis Doctoris Angelici. Opera Omnia.
Iussu Leonis XIII, Rome: Vatican Polyglot Press, 1882–). Publications
of Aquinas’s writings prior to the Leonine edition include the Parma
edition (Opera Omnia, Parma: Fiaccadori, 1852–73) and the Vivès
edition (Opera Omnia, Paris: Vivès, 1871–82). Most of Aquinas’s
writings have also been published in manual size by the Casa Marietti
(Torino-Rome).
Students of Aquinas should also consult R. Busa, Index Thomisticus
(Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog, 1974–80), which
provides a text of Aquinas’s writings and a useful, if somewhat
unwieldy, way to search for terms used by him.
A substantial amount of Aquinas’s writings still remains untranslated into
English. There are, however, some currently available English editions
of a number of his more important works.
To date, the best English edition of the Summa theologiae (with notes and
commentaries) is the Blackfriars edition (61 vols., Latin and English
with notes and introductions, London: Eyre & Spottiswoode, and New
York: McGraw-Hill Book Company, 1964–80). Unfortunately,
however, this translation is sometimes unreliable. For a more literal
rendering of the text, see St. Thomas Aquinas Summa Theologica
(translated by the Fathers of the English Dominican Province,
originally published by Burns, Oates, and Washbourne in London in
1911 and now available from Christian Classics, Westminster, Md.,
1981). This edition may be found on the Internet at:
<http://www.newadvent.org/summa>. A searchable concordance to it
can be found on the Internet at:
<http://www.intratext.com/IXT/ENG0023/_FA.HTM>. Also worth
consulting is Timothy McDermott (ed.), St Thomas Aquinas, Summa
Theologiae: A Concise Translation (London: Eyre and Spottiswoode,
1989). A Latin concordance of Aquinas’s full corpus can be found at
the Corpus Thomisticum website:
<http://www.corpusthomisticum.org/it/index.age>.
For a reliable translation of the Summa contra Gentiles, see On the Truth of
the Catholic Faith, translated by Anton Pegis, James F. Anderson,
Vernon J. Bourke, and Charles J. O’Neil (New York: Doubleday,
1955–57, reprinted as Summa Contra Gentiles, Notre Dame, Ind. and
London: University of Notre Dame Press, 1975). An annotated
translation of the Summa contra Gentiles (by Joseph Rickaby, with
some abridgements) is available on the Internet at:
<http://www.nd.edu/departments/maritain/etext/gc.xhtml>.
Other English translations of Aquinas’s writings include:
(a) Disputed Questions
Truth (Quaestiones disputatae De veritate), translated by Robert W.
Mulligan, J. V. McGlynn, and R. W. Schmidt (3 vols., Chicago: Henry
Regnery Company, 1952–54).
On the Power of God (Quaestiones disputatae De potentia), translated by the
English Dominican Fathers (3 vols., London: Burns, Oates, and
Washbourne, 1932–34).
The Soul (Quaestio disputata De anima), translated by J. H. Robb
(Milwaukee, Wis.: Marquette University Press, 1984).
On Spiritual Creatures (Quaestio disputata De spiritualibus creaturis),
translated by M. C. Fitzpatrick and J. J. Wellmuth (Milwaukee, Wis.:
Marquette University Press, 1949).
On Evil (Quaestiones disputatae De Malo), translated by Richard Regan
(New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).
Disputed Questions on Virtue (Quaestio disputata De virtutibus in communi
and Quaestio disputata De virtutibus cardinalibus), translated by
Ralph McInerny (South Bend, Ind.: St. Augustine’s Press, 1999).
On Charity (Quaestio disputata De caritate), translated by Lottie H.
Kendzierski (Milwaukee, Wis.: Marquette University Press, 1984).
Quodlibetal Questions 1 and 2, translated by Sandra Edwards (Toronto:
Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1983).
(b) Commentaries on Scripture
The Literal Exposition on Job (Expositio super Job as litteram), translated by
Anthony Damico (Atlanta, Ga.: Scholars Press, 1989).
Commentary on the Gospel of John (Lectura super Ioannem), translated by
James A Weisheipl and F. R. Larcher (2 vols., Albany, N.Y.: Magi
Books, 1980, and Petersham, Mass.: St. Bede’s Publications, 1998).
Commentary on Saint Paul’s First Letter to the Thessalonians and the Letter
to the Philippians, translated by F. R. Larcher and Michael Duffy
(Albany, N.Y.: Magi Books, 1969).
Commentary on Saint Paul’s Epistle to the Ephesians, translated by Matthew
L. Lamb (Albany, N.Y.: Magi Books, 1966).
Commentary on Saint Paul’s Epistle to the Galatians, translated by F. R.
Larcher (Albany, N.Y.: Magi Books, 1966).
(c) Commentaries on Aristotle
A Commentary on Aristotle’s De anima (Sententia Libri De anima),
translated by Robert Pasnau (New Haven, Conn. and London: Yale
University Press, 1999).
Commentary on Aristotle’s Physics (Sententia super Physicam), translated by
R. Blackwell (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1963).
On Interpretation (Expositio Libri Peri hermenias), translated by Jean T.
Oesterle (Milwaukee, Wis.: Marquette University Press, 1962).
Commentary on the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle (Expositio Libri
Posteriorum), translated by F. R. Larcher (Albany, N.Y.: Magi Books,
1970).
Commentary on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics (Sententia Libri Ethicorum),
translated by C. I. Litzinger (2 vols., Notre Dame, Ind.: University of
Notre Dame Press, 1964).
Commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics (Sententia super Metaphysicam),
translated by John P. Rowan (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre
Dame Press, 1995).
(d) Other Commentaries
Saint Thomas Aquinas, Faith, Reason, and Theology. Questions I–IV of his
Commentary on the De Trinitate of Boethius (Expositio super librum
Boethii De trinitate), translated by A. Maurer (Toronto: Pontifical
Institute of Medieval Studies, 1987).
Saint Thomas Aquinas, The Divisions and Methods of the Sciences.
Questions V and VI of his Commentary on the De Trinitate of Boethius
(Expositio super librum Boethii De trinitate), translated by A. Maurer
(Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1986).
Saint Thomas Aquinas, An Exposition of the “On the Hebdomads” of
Boethius, Introduction and translation by Janice L. Schultz and Edward
A. Synan (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press,
2001).
Commentary on the Book of Causes (Expositio super librum De causis),
translated by Vincent A. Guagliardo, Charles R. Hess, and Richard C.
Taylor (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press,
1996).
(e) Other Writings
On Being and Essence (De ente et essentia), translated by Joseph Bobik
(Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1965).
Aquinas on Matter and Form and the Elements (translations of De principiis
naturae and De mixtione elementorum), translated by Joseph Bobik
(Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1998).
On There Being Only One Intellect (De unitate intellectus contra
Averroistas), translated by Ralph McInerny in Aquinas Against the
Averroists (West Lafayette, Ind.: Purdue University Press, 1993).
Compendium of Theology (Compendium theologie), translated by Richard J.
Regan (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2009).
The Sermon Conferences of St. Thomas Aquinas on the Apostle’s Creed
(Collationes in Symbolorum Apostolorum), translated by Nicholas Ayo
(Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988).
Readers might like to note that Thérese Bonin maintains an updated web site
listing currently available English translations of Aquinas at:
<http://www.home.duq.edu/~bonin/thomasbibliography.xhtml>.
The Thomas Institute in Utrecht also lists translations into English of
Aquinas and provides one of the most helpful of internet research sites
for students of Aquinas. It can be found at:
<http://www.thomasinstituut.org/>.
3. BIBLIOGRAPHICAL WORKS
P. Mandonnet and J. Destrez, Bibliographie Thomiste, 2d ed., revised by M.-
D. Chenu (Paris: Vrin, 1960).
Vernon J. Bourke, Thomistic Bibliography: 1920–1940, The Modern
Schoolman, 1921.
Richard Ingardia, Thomas Aquinas: International Bibliography 1977–1990
(Bowling Green, Ohio: Philosophy Documentation Center, 1993).
Terry L. Miethe and Vernon J. Bourke, Thomistic Bibliography, 1940–1978
(Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press, 1980).
The Bulletin Thomiste (1940–65), continued in Rassegna di Letteratura
Tomistica (1966–), receives all Thomistic publications and is a useful
research tool with respect to Thomistic bibliography.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Abelard, Peter, 51
abstraction, 493
accident, substance and, 105, 500
accidental change, 89–92, 112n2, 117
accidental compound, 89, 92, 96, 101n21
accidental form, 386n2
accidental predicate, 380
acquired virtues, 266, 268–70, 295–96. See also specific virtues
cardinal virtues and, 476
infused virtues compared to, 475–76, 483n3, 484nn5–6, 485n19
sin and, 485n11
act and potency, doctrine of, 67–68, 149, 153
action. See also human action
of angels, 179–80
causation and, 108–9
choiceworthiness of, 251, 253n65
generically evil, 259, 259t
generically good, 259, 259t
immanent, 114n43, 235n4, 498
indifferent, 259, 259
law and, 244–47
passion and, 108–9, 420
production and, 279, 331–32, 498
stages of, 333
transient, 235n4
transitive, 114n43
of Trinity, 423–25
virtue as principle of, 266–71
action of human being (actio hominis), 199, 228
active power, 106, 113n26
act of being (actus essendi), 153, 155
act of will, 113n19
actuality
of form, 371
mover in, 128n24
passive potencies and, 175
actus, of Gifts and virtues, 481–83, 488n49
adjective names, 388n26
Adoro Te (Aquinas), 20
affirmative precepts, 281
afterlife, 37
agency, 9–10, 199–207
agent
causation and, 105–8
defined, 105
deliberate imagination by, 216
fire, 105, 108
intellect, 315, 493
structure of human action and, 202–3
ultimate end and, 200
aggregates, 360, 367n26
agnosticism, 70–71, 136–37
agreement of proportionality, agreement of proportion and, 500
Albert the Great, 16, 37, 45, 154–55, 256, 421
almsgiving, 298
analogy
artist–artwork, 160–61
of being, 379–85, 389n30
development of thought about, 499–501
in language, 379–85, 389n30, 394–97
Prima Pars and, 396
psychological, 423
Angelic Doctor (Doctor Angelicus)
in Baroque period, 520–23
Neo-Thomists and, 523–26
renaissance of, 518–20
rise to authority, 515–18
angels
action of, 179–80
cognition of, 365
emotions and, 224n7
prayer to, 474n7
species of, 358
time of, 181–82
anger, 174, 211, 220–21
animal
emotion, 224n6
happiness of, 232, 234, 235n7
participation in, 82
sensory powers of, 314
soul of, 357–58
annihilation, 86
anonymous author, erring conscience and, 259–60
Anscombe, Elizabeth, 277
Anselm of Canterbury, 436–41
appetible object, 248–49
appetite
cognition and, 212–16
goodness and, 149
intellective, 212
practical reason and, 277
rational, 248–49
sensitive, 209–17, 219–20, 222
appetitive powers, 210, 328
appetitive soul, 502–3
Aquinas, Thomas. See also Angelic Doctor; Commentary on the Book of
Sentences; Common Doctor; Quaestiones disputatae de veritate; Summa
contra Gentiles; Summa theologiae
Adoro Te by, 20
on agency, 10, 199–207
Albert the Great and, 16, 37, 45, 154–55, 256, 421
Aristotle’s connection with, 3–4, 16, 22–27, 33–41, 57, 78–79, 93, 108–9,
124, 149, 152, 174, 177, 180–82, 231, 272, 279, 281–82, 325n34, 327,
329–34, 340, 349–51, 373, 420, 437, 475, 485n12, 516–17
Augustine and, 4, 15, 20, 23, 46–48, 50, 56, 192, 251, 279, 296, 303, 401,
442
Averroës and, 15, 26, 35–37, 39, 42n16, 43n19, 67, 78, 491, 514, 517
Avicenna and, 4, 35, 39, 56, 65–70
on being, 77–82
Boethius and, 48–50, 54n16, 78, 81–82, 138–39, 178–79
canonized as saint, 518
Catena aurea by, 20, 24
on causation, 104–11
change theory of, 85–94, 99–100
Commentary on Aristotle’s Ethics by, 279
Compendium theologiae by, 19, 175, 437–39
on conscience, 255–62
Contra doctrinam retrahentium a religione by, 17
Contra impugnantes Dei cultum et religionem by, 17
Contra retrahentes by, 26
De aeternitate mundi by, 26
De ente et essentia by, 17, 80–81, 521
De perfectione spiritualis vitae by, 17, 26
De Potentia by, 24–25, 492, 498
De principiis naturae by, 17, 104–5
De substantiis separatis by, 27, 57–59
De ueritate by, 17–18, 25
De unitate intellectus contra averroistas by, 26
development of thought of, 491–503
Disputed Questions and, 17–18, 24–25, 365n3, 367n22
as Doctor Communis, 511–14
early years, 15–16
eclecticism avoided by, 4
on emotions, 209–23
on evil, 401–12
Expositio libri Boetii De ebdomadibus by, 18
on faith, 337–45
on form, 68, 80, 85–100, 109–10
on freedom, 9–10, 199–207
on God’s eternality, 173–84
on God’s goodness, 147–55, 165, 168–69
on God’s immutability, 173–84, 470–71
on God’s impassibility, 173–84
on God’s knowledge, 158–70
on God’s omnipotence, 187–94
on God’s simplicity, 135–43
on happiness, 37, 227–35
on human knowledge, 311–23
on incarnation, 428–33
individuation theory of, 85, 94–100
influence of, 511–26
influences on, 4, 9, 15–16, 20, 40–41
Islamic authors and, 4, 65–72
Jewish authors and, 4, 65–72, 514
on language, 371–86, 390–97
last years of, 27–28
in Latin-Christian tradition, 45–52
on law, 238–51
Lectura super Epistolam Pauli Apostoli ad Hebraeos by, 443
Lectura super Epistolam Pauli Apostoli ad Romanos by, 438
on matter, 68, 80, 85–100
on mind and human nature, 349–65
in Naples, 15–16, 27–28
Neoplatonism and, 34, 55–62
in Orvieto, 19–21
in Paris, 16–18, 25–27
philosophical theology of, 6–7
Plato and, 55–62, 152–53, 325n22
on practical reasoning, 228, 276–83, 334
on prayer, 467–73
on providence, 401–12
Quaestiones disputatae de malo by, 205, 208n22, 272, 492
in Rome, 20–25
on sacraments, 448–56
on saving work of Christ, 436–44
scale of value of, 402–4
scholastic tradition and, 50–51
Scriptum super libros Sententiarum by, 209
Sententia Libri De anima by, 33–35, 37, 365n3
Sententia Libri Ethicorum by, 36–37
Sententia super Metaphysicam by, 37–39
Sententia super Physicam by, 35–36, 38
On Separate Substances by, 27, 57–59
Super Boetium De Trinitate by, 18, 23
Super De Causis by, 27
synthesis by, 45
Thomists and, 515–26
on Trinity, 8, 25, 418–25
on vices, 265–73, 282
virtues and, 231, 236n13, 252n34, 265–73, 287–304, 327–34
voice of, 236n11
Aristotle. See also Metaphysics; Nicomachean Ethics; Posterior Analytics
act and potency doctrine of, 67–68, 149, 153
Aquinas’s connection with, 3–4, 16, 22–27, 33–41, 57, 78–79, 93, 108–9,
124, 149, 152, 174, 177, 180–82, 231, 272, 279, 281–82, 325n34, 327,
329–34, 340, 349–51, 373, 420, 437, 475, 485n12, 516–17
Augustine and, 46–47
Categories by, 33, 57, 378
Christianity reconciled with, 349
contingency defined by, 67
De anima by, 33–35, 47, 276, 349
Ethics by, 16
On Interpretation by, 33, 376, 386n3
Islamic authors and, 66–67
Organon by, 33–34
Peri Hermeneias by, 469
Physics by, 35–36, 38, 117
Plato correcting, 58–62
revival of, 522, 530n56
semantic triangle of, 373
sententiae on works of, 33–39, 41
Summa theologiae and, 39–40
theology and, 33
on virtues, 266, 273n6, 274n33, 327–34, 475–76, 483n2
on wisdom, 37–39, 329–30
art
Augustine on, 279
defined, 331
as intellectual virtue, 328, 330–32
liberal, 331
mechanical, 331
nature imitated by, 281
as power, 106–7
practical knowledge and, 278
productive, 106
prudence above, 279–80
artifacts, 367n26
artist–artwork analogy, 160–61
atemporal duration, 178
attitude, 174
Augustine
Aquinas and, 4, 15, 20, 23, 46–48, 50, 56, 192, 251, 279, 296, 303, 401,
442
Aristotle and, 46–47
on art, 279
on evil, 401–2
Exposition on the Psalms by, 441
On the Gift of Perseverance by, 492
in Latin-Christian tradition, 46–47
On the Predestination of the Saints by, 492
sin defined by, 260
authority
Angelic Doctor’s rise to, 515–18
epistemic source from, 341
of scripture, 4, 419, 428
autism, 479–80, 483, 487nn39–40
Averroës
Aquinas and, 15, 26, 35–37, 39, 42n16, 43n19, 67, 78, 491, 514, 517
Metaphysics and, 78
aversion, 220–21
Avicenna (Ibn Sina)
Aquinas and, 4, 35, 39, 56, 65–70
contingency defined by, 67
First Philosophy by, 39
al-Shifa by, 66
faith
as acceptance, 428
affirmation by, 290–92
Aquinas’s conception of, 337–45
beatitude and, 343
believing and, 289
charity and, 292–93, 339
about Christ, 291–92
cognitive voluntarism and, 346n11
complete good and, 343–44
connection of, 300
defined, 337
divine testimony and, 341–43
exterior act of, 338–39
formed, 292–93, 301
as Fruit, 481
happiness and, 337–38
interior act of, 338–39
loss of, 301–2
object of, 337–39, 346nn6–7
person of, 405, 414n22
rationality of, 341–44
reason related to, 337–45
revelation and, 418
science dealing with, 317, 340–41
as theological virtue, 287–93, 300–303, 339–40, 343–45
Trinity at heart of, 418
unformed, 292–93, 301
will related to, 340, 343–44
false cognition, 311
false worship, 449
fame, 234
al-Farabi, 65–68
Father, properties and names of, 421–23. See also Trinity
fear, 213–17
confidence and, 220–21
filial, 487n30
Gift of, 477–78, 487n30
of opposite, 317–20
servile, 487n30
felicitas, 231–33
felicity, 330
Fifth Way, 124–25
filial fear, 487n30
filiation, 421
final causation, 111
fire, as agent, 105, 108
First Cause, 206
first-personal habitus, 480
First Philosophy (Avicenna), 39
First Way, 116–20, 175–76
Five Ways
defined, 115–16
Fifth, 124–25
First, 116–20, 175–76
Fourth, 123–24
Second, 119–20, 122, 129n36
Summa contra Gentiles and, 116
Third, 121–22, 180
flourishing, of human beings, 403, 405–7, 412, 413n15
flow, of now, 181–82
Flying Man, 35
forgiveness, 440, 443
form. See also substantial form
accidental, 386n2
actuality of, 371
Aquinas on, 68, 80, 85–100, 109–10
being influenced by, 110–11
bronze statue example of, 85–87, 89, 91, 352
change and, 85–94
charity as form of virtues, 299
defined, 351–52, 386n2
denominating, 387n15
human, 352
of human beings, 352
individualized, 371–72
individuation and, 85–100
inherence of, 377
matter and, 68, 80, 85–100, 112n2, 351, 366n9, 459
soul as, 353, 361–62, 367n22, 458–60
types of, 89–94
formed faith, 292–93, 301
Fourth Way, 123–24
Fox, Rory, 179–80, 185n36
fraternal correction, 298
freedom
agency and, 9–10, 199–207
Aquinas on, 9–10, 199–207
of choice, 163, 166–68, 471–72
cognition and, 366n15
determinism incompatible with, 204–6
hell and, 403
human action and, 204–7
law and, 247–51
necessitation, causation and, 204–7
prayer and, 471–72
friendly love, 221
friendship
charity as, 296
with God, 477–81, 484n9, 488n51
fruitio (enjoyment), 202–3, 208n10
Fruits, of Holy Spirit
as actus, 481–83, 488n49
Beatitudes and, 476–77, 483, 485n18
capitalized, 485n14
defined, 476–77, 480–81
Gifts and, 476–83, 485n18
habitus and, 481
future contingent events, knowledge of, 162–63
Jerome, 255
Jesuits, 522
Jesus. See Christ
Jewish authors. See also Maimonides, Moses
Aquinas and, 4, 65–72, 514
Doctor Communis among, 514
Job, 407
John Damascene, 279, 438
John of Freiburg, 512
John of St. Thomas, 522
joint attention, 478–79
joy
charity and, 298–99
as Fruit, 481
God’s, 168–69
passion, 168
judges, 242, 254n77
judgment, intellect and, 77
justice
acquired, 483n4
distributive, 170
God’s, 169–70
of humanity, 169
hungering and thirsting for, 476, 485n16
infused, 483n4
restoration of order of, 439–40
as virtue, 328
will and, 169–70
justification, 406–7
language, theory of
analogy in, 379–85, 389n30, 394–97
Aquinas on, 371–86, 390–97
concepts in, 372–73
copula in, 376–79, 387n13
enuntiabile in, 378–80
God and, 391–97
imposition in, 372–76
limits of, 390–97
mental content in, 373–74
perfection and, 394–95
predication in, 371–84
ratio in, 373–75, 386n9
rejected answers and, 392–93
signification in, 372–76, 381
tensed, 391
univocal and equivocal use of words in, 393–94
large-scale suffering, 412
Latin-Christian tradition
Aquinas in, 45–52
Augustine in, 46–47
Boethius in, 48–50
law. See also natural law
action and, 244–47
Aquinas on, 238–51
common good and, 238–44, 246, 251, 254n77
compliance with, 244, 253n43
defined, 244
divine, 245, 260, 260t, 501
eternal, 245–51, 253n43
evil and, 250–51
freedom and, 247–51
human, 246–47, 251
judges and, 242, 254n77
moral, 261
nonrational creatures and, 244–47
Old Law, 450
will and, 238, 249–50
lawfulness, 244
learning, teaching and, 108–9, 113n30
Lectura super Epistolam Pauli Apostoli ad Hebraeos (In Heb) (Aquinas),
443
Lectura super Epistolam Pauli Apostoli ad Romanos (In Rom) (Aquinas),
438
legal directives, externally imposed, 247
Leibniz, Gottfried, 523–24
Leonine Commission, 531n78
liberal arts, 331
Liber de causis, 55–59, 62
libertarians, 206, 348
light, 137, 140, 145n36
local motion, 117
Locke, John, 524
logical connectives, 376
logical participation, 82
Lombard, Peter, 16, 45, 51, 191, 266, 303, 519
Long-suffering, as Fruit, 476, 481
Lord’s Supper, 442–44
love
causal, 287
of charity, 296–98
covetous, 221
in creatures, 168
friendly, 221
in God, 168–69, 174
hate and, 220–21, 299
of relatives, 298
self-love, 268
will and, 168–69, 174
Word and, 419–20, 422–23
Luther, Martin, 295, 521
names
adjective, 388n26
divine, 158
substantive, 388n26
of Trinity, 421–23
Naples, Aquinas in, 15–16, 27–28
natural cognition, 316
naturalism, 348
natural law, 246–51, 449
desire and, 250–51
inclinations and, 250
prudence linked to, 334
synderesis connected to, 256
natural philosophy, 210
natural theology, 4–7
natural worship, 449
nature
approach, 153
art imitating, 281
defined, 429–30
of emotions, 210–12
of God, 468–69
humanizing, 432–33
pre-rational, 248
rational, 248
supposit-supporting, 432–33, 434n22
of Trinity, 435n24
necessitation, 204–7
necessity
of coercion, 205–6
conditional, 166
of grace, 501–2
of past, 193
way from, 121–22, 130n37
negative precepts, 281
Neo-Augustinianism, 47
Neoplatonism, 34, 55–62, 491
Neo-Thomists, 523–26
New Covenant, 449, 451
Nicomachean Ethics (Aristotle)
sententia on, 36–37
structure of, 476, 485n12
virtues in, 273n6, 327, 329–30, 475–76
Nizolius, Marius, 522
noncontradiction, 191–93
nondiminishing qualifications, 389n28
nonrational creatures, law and, 244–47
now, flow of, 181–82
nutrition, 210, 359
object
appetible, 248–49
bodies as, 229–30
of charity, 296–98
of faith, 337–39, 346nn6–7
of hope, 294, 302–3
immaterial, 89
proper, 214–15, 224n17
ratio in, 374
of thought, 375
wisdom, 330
observational knowledge, 176
Ockham, William, 334, 518
Old Covenant, 449, 451
Old Law, 450
omnipotence
Aquinas on, 187–94
defined, 188–91
God’s, 187–94
impeccability and, 193–94
noncontradiction and, 191–93
in scriptural texts, 187
sin and, 194
strength and, 187–88
in Summa contra Gentiles, 189–90, 193
in Summa theologiae, 188, 193
omnipresence, 409–10
one-many change, 94
one-one change, 94
On Interpretation (Aristotle), 33, 376, 386n3
On the Gift of Perseverance (De dono perseverantiae) (Augustine), 492
On the Predestination of the Saints (De praedestinatione sanctorum)
(Augustine), 492
ontological participation, 82
operations, 77, 174, 468. See also Independent Operation Premise
operative perfections, 158
opposite, fear of, 317–20
Opuscula Sacra (Theological Treatises) (Boethius), 48, 50
order
of creation, 166
of justice, 439–40
of parts, 239–40
ordered series, 119–20
Order of Preachers, 15–16
ordo disciplinae, 51
Organon (Aristotle), 33–34
Origen of Alexandria, 471
Original Sin, 368n34
origins, dependence and, 102n36
Orvieto, 19–21
outermost heaven, 182
taxes, 243–44
taxonomy, of emotion, 218–22
teaching, learning and, 108–9, 113n30
temperance, 270, 485n10, 485n19
Tempier, Étienne, 516
Tertia Pars, 21–22, 27
testimony, divine, 341–43
theological perspective, in philosophy of mind and human nature, 348–50
theological virtues
charity, 287, 295–303, 343
connection of, 300
defined, 287–89
duration, 302–3
faith, 287–93, 300–303, 339–40, 343–45
God and, 287–304
happiness and, 236n13
hope, 287, 293–95, 300–304, 343
loss of, 300–302
political virtues and, 270–71
in scripture, 288–90, 295
in Secunda Secundae, 289, 292
sources, 303–4
theology. See also philosophical theology
Aristotle and, 33
Boethius and, 48–49
incarnation as problem of, 428–29
metaphysics distinguished from, 49
moral, 23–24
natural, 4–7
in philosophy of mind and human nature, 348–50
revealed, 6–8, 429
as science, 7–8, 50–51
scope and philosophical character of, 3
speculative Trinitarian, 418–19
theoretical reason, 256
theoretical science, 78
theoretical wisdom, 327
things, in semantic triangle, 373
Third Way, 121–22, 180
Thomists, Aquinas and, 515–26
time
of angels, 181–82
defined, 181
motion and, 182–84
timelessness, 180–84
Torrell, Jean-Pierre, 9
transcendentals, doctrine of, 147
transient action, 235n4
transitive action, 114n43
transmutation, 109–10
Treatise on God, 115
Treatise on Human Nature, 350, 352, 354, 365n3
Trinity
Aquinas on, 8, 25, 418–25
Bonaventure on, 418–19, 421–22
contemporary criticism of, 425
creative action of, 423–25
Disputed Questions and, 25
in exposition of speculative Trinitarian theology, 418–19
at heart of Christian faith, 418
id quod est and, 138–39
intellect of, 413n7
knowledge of, 322
nature of, 435n24
persons and, 419–21, 425
processions and, 419–21
proofs of, 126n3
properties and names of, 421–23
relations and, 419–21
sanctifying action of, 423–25
in Summa theologiae, 8, 419
will of, 413n7
Word in, 419–20, 422, 498
truth, science of, 5–6
Tugwell, Simon, 467
zygotehood, 91, 93